0% found this document useful (0 votes)
15 views2 pages

Classical 18

This lecture summary discusses classical mechanics as a category, with physical systems as objects and processes between systems as morphisms. It provides two examples of Poisson maps: (1) the Galilei group acting on phase space, and (2) Hamiltonian flows generated by a Hamiltonian function. The lecture proves that Hamiltonian flows are Poisson maps by showing they preserve Poisson brackets. It concludes that time evolution in classical mechanics gives a Poisson map within the category of classical systems.

Uploaded by

damnation
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
15 views2 pages

Classical 18

This lecture summary discusses classical mechanics as a category, with physical systems as objects and processes between systems as morphisms. It provides two examples of Poisson maps: (1) the Galilei group acting on phase space, and (2) Hamiltonian flows generated by a Hamiltonian function. The lecture proves that Hamiltonian flows are Poisson maps by showing they preserve Poisson brackets. It concludes that time evolution in classical mechanics gives a Poisson map within the category of classical systems.

Uploaded by

damnation
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 2

Classical Mechanics, Lecture 18

March 11, 2008


lecture by John Baez
notes by Alex Hoffnung

1 The Category of Classical Systems


A category is a bunch of things (objects) and processes (morphisms):

• /•

For us, the ‘things’ are physical systems in classical mechanics: Poisson manifolds. The ‘processes’
are certain maps between physical systems: Poisson maps.

Definition 1 Given two Poisson manifolds X and Y , a map φ: X → Y is Poisson if it is smooth


and
φ∗ : C ∞ (Y ) → C ∞ (X)
f 7→ f φ
preserves the Poisson brackets: given f, g ∈ C ∞ (Y )

{φ∗ (f ), φ∗ (g)} = φ∗ {f, g}

In fact, we have seen lots of Poisson maps. Any physical process in classical mechanics gives a
Poisson map.

Example: X = T ∗ (Rn ) is the phase space for a particle in Rn ; the Galilei group G(n + 1) acts on
X:
A: G(n + 1) × X → X
and in fact for each g ∈ G(n + 1) the map A(g): X → X is Poisson!

Example: X is any Poisson manifold, H ∈ C ∞ (X). Then we get a vector field on X and if vH is
integrable we get a flow
φ: R × X → X
(t, x) 7→ φt (x)
with
d
φt (x) = vH (φt (x))
dt
Given this, each map φt : X → X is Poisson!

Check: given F, G ∈ C ∞ (X) we want:

{φ∗t F, φ∗t G} = φ∗t {F, G}

This is true for t = 0 since φ0 : X → X is the identity, hence φ∗0 F = F . So, it is enough to show:

d d
{φ∗ F, φ∗t G} = φ∗t {F, G}
dt t dt
i.e.
d d
{φ∗ F, φ∗t G} (x) = φ∗t {F, G} (x)
dt t dt

1
d ∗ def. of pullback d
φ {F, G} (x) = {F, G} (φt (x))
dt t dt  
chain rule d
= d {F, G} φt (x)
dt
def. of φt
= d {F, G} vH (φt (x))
def. of vH
= vH {F, G} (φt (x))
Jacobi id.
= {H, {F, G}} (φt (x))
= ({{H, F } , G} + {F, {H, G}}) φt (x)

On the other hand:


   
d bilin. of {·,·} gives prod. rule d ∗ d ∗
{φ∗ F, φ∗t G} (x) = ∗ ∗
φ F, φt G + φt F, φt G (x)
dt t dt t dt
= {{H, φ∗t F } , φ∗t G} + {φ∗t F, {H, φ∗t G}} (x)

This agrees with the other side at t = 0.


(Note: H = φ∗t H since energy is conserved.)
So we have:
d ∗ d
φ {F, G} (x) = {φt F, φt G} (x)
∗ ∗
dt t t=0 dt t=0
for all x, so use φs (x) ∈ X:

d ∗ d
φ {F, G} φs (x) = {φt F, φt G} (φs (x))
∗ ∗
dt t dt
t=0 t=0
d
{F, G}φt+s (x) =
dt t=0
d
{F, G}φs (x) =
ds

We would like:
d d ∗
{F, G} φs (x) = {φ F, φ∗s G}
ds ds s
Ugh!

So: we have a category of Poisson manifolds and Poisson maps and time evolution for any Hamilto-
nian is a Poisson map.
Definition 2 A category consists of a collection of objects and for any pair of objects X and
Y a set of morphisms f : X → Y such that given f : X → Y and g: Y → Z we have a morphism
gf : X → Z, such that:
1. (hg)f = h(gf )
2. each X has an identity morphism 1X : X → X such that:
f 1X = f
1X g = g

You might also like