Charles Tart States of Consciousness
Charles Tart States of Consciousness
Charles Tart States of Consciousness
Charles T. Tart
There is a great elegance in starting out from simple ideas, slowly building them up into connected patterns, and
having a complex, interlocking theoretical structure emerge at the end. Following the weaving of such a pattern,
step by step, can be highly stimulating. Unfortunately, it is easy to get bogged down in the details, especially when
the pattern has gaps to be filled in, and to lose track of what the steps are all about and what they are leading
toward. This chapter gives a brief overview of my systems approach to state of consciousness—a brief sketch map
of the whole territory to provide a general orientation before we look at detail maps. I do not define terms much
here or give detailed examples, as these are supplied in later chapters.
Our ordinary state of consciousness is not something natural or given, but a highly complex construction, a
specialized tool for coping with our environment and the people in it, a tool that is useful for doing some things but
not very useful, and even dangerous, for doing other things. As we look at consciousness closely, we see that it can
be analyzed into many parts. Yet these parts function together in a pattern: they form a system. While the
components of consciousness can be studied in isolation, they exist as parts of a complex system, consciousness,
and can be fully understood only when we see this function in the overall system. Similarly, understanding the
complexity of consciousness requires seeing it as a system and understanding the parts. For this reason, I refer to
my approach to states of consciousness as a system approach.
To understand the constructed system we call a state of consciousness, we begin with some theoretical postulates
based on human experience. The first postulate is the existence of a basic awareness. Because some volitional
control of the focus of awareness is possible, we generally refer to it as attention/awareness. We must also
recognize the existence of self-awareness, the awareness of being aware.
Further basic postulates deal with structures, those relatively permanent structures/functions/subsystems of the
mind/brain that act on information to transform it in various ways. Arithmetical skills, for example, constitute a (set
of related) structure(s). The structures of particular interest to us are those that require some amount of
attention/awareness to activate them. Attention/awareness acts as psychological energy in this sense. Most
techniques for controlling the mind are ways of deploying attention/awareness energy and other kinds of energies
so as to activate desired structures (traits, skills, attitudes) and deactivate undesired structures.
Psychological structures have individual characteristics that limit and shape the ways in which they can interact
with one another. Thus the possibilities of any system built of psychological structures are shaped and limited both
by the deployment of attention/awareness and other energies and by the characteristics of the structures comprising
the system. The human biocomputer, in other words, has a large but limited number of possible modes of
functioning.
Because we are creatures with a certain kind of body and nervous system, a large number of human potentials are
in principle available to use. but each of us is born into a particular culture that selects and develops a small number
of these potentials, rejects others, and is ignorant of many. The small number of experiential potentials selected by
our culture, plus some random factors, constitute the structural elements from which our ordinary state of
consciousness is constructed. We are at once the beneficiaries and the victims of our culture's particular selection.
The possibility of tapping and developing latent potentials, which lie outside the cultural norm, by entering an
altered state of consciousness, by temporarily restructuring consciousness, is the basis of the great interest in such
states.
The terms states of consciousness and altered state of consciousness have come to be used too loosely, to mean
whatever is on one's mind at the moment. The new term discrete state of consciousness (d-SoC0 is proposed for
greater precision. A d-SoC is a unique, dynamic pattern or configuration of psychological structures, an active
system of psychological subsystems. Although the component structures/subsystems show some variation within a
d-SoC, the overall pattern, the overall system properties remain recognizably the same. If, as you sit reading, you
think, "I am dreaming," instead of "I am awake," you have changed a small cognitive element in your
consciousness but not affected at all the basic pattern we call your waking state. In spite of subsystem variation and
environmental variation, a d-SoC is stabilized by a number of processes so that it retains its identity and function.
By analogy, an automobile remains an automobile whether on a road or in a garage (environment change), whether
you change the brand of spark plugs or the color of the seat covers (internal variation).
Examples of d-SoCs are the ordinary waking state, nondreaming sleep, dreaming sleep, hypnosis, alcohol
intoxication, marijuana intoxication, and meditative states.
A discrete altered state of consciousness (d-ASC) refers to a d-SoC that is different from some baseline state of
consciousness (b-SoC). Usually the ordinary state is taken as the baseline state. A d-ASC is a new system with
unique properties of its own, a restructuring of consciousness. Altered is intended as a purely descriptive term,
carrying no values.
A d-SoC is stabilized by four kinds of processes: (1) loading stabilization—keeping attention/awareness and
other psychological energies deployed in habitual, desired structures by loading the person's system heavily with
appropriate tasks; (2) negative feedback stabilization—correcting the functioning of erring structures/subsystems
when they deviate too far from the normal range that ensures stability; (3) positive feedback stabilization—
strengthening activity and/or providing rewarding experiences when structure/subsystems are functioning within
desired limits; and (4) limiting stabilization—restricting the range of functioning of structures/subsystems whose
intense operation would destabilize the system.
In terms of current psychological knowledge, ten major subsystems (collections of related structures) that show
important variations over known d-ASCs need to be distinguished: (1) Exteroception—sensing the external
environment; (2) Interoception—sensing what the body is feeling and doing; (3) Input-Processing—automated
selecting and abstracting of sensory input so we perceive only what is "important" by personal and cultural
(consensus reality) standards; (4) Memory; (5) Subconscious—the classical Freudian unconscious plus many other
psychological processes that go on outside our ordinary d-SoC, but that may become directly conscious in various
d-ASCs: (6) Emotions; (7) Evaluation and Decision-Making—our cognitive evaluating skills and habits; (8)
Space/Time Sense—the construction of psychological space and time and the placing of events within it; (9) Sense
of Identity—the quality added to experience the makes it a personal experience instead of just information; and (10)
Motor Output—muscular and glandular outputs to the external world and the body. These subsystems are not
ultimates, but convenient categories to organize current knowledge.
Our current knowledge of human consciousness and d-SoCs is highly fragmented and chaotic. The main purpose
of the systems approach presented here is organizational: it allows us to relate what were formerly disparate bits of
data and supplies numerous methodological consequences for guiding future research. it makes the general
prediction that the number of d-SoCs available to human beings is definitely limited, although we do not yet know
those limits. It further provides a paradigm for making more specific predictions that will sharpen our knowledge
about the structures and subsystems that make up human consciousness.
There are enormously important individual differences in the structure of the d-SoCs. If we map the experiential
space in which two people function, one person may show two discrete, separated clusters of experiential
functioning (two d-SoCs), while the other may show continuous functioning throughout both regions and the
connecting regions of experiential space. The first person must make a special effort to travel from one region of
experiential space (one d-SoC) to the other; the second makes no special effort and does not experience the contrast
of pattern and structure differences associated with the two regions (the two d-SoCs). Thus what is a special state of
consciousness for one person may be an everyday experience for another. Great confusion results if we do not
watch for these differences: unfortunately, many widely used experimental procedures are not sensitive to these
important individual differences.
Induction of a d-ASC involves two basic operations that, if successful, lead to the d-ASC from the b-SoC. First,
we apply disrupting forces to the b-SoC—psychological and/or physiological actions that disrupt the stabilization
processes discussed above either by interfering with them or by withdrawing attention/awareness energy or other
kinds of energies from them. Because a d-SoC is a complex system, with multiple stabilization processes operating
simultaneously, induction may not work. A psychedelic drug, for example, may not produce a d-ASC because
psychological stabilization processes hold the b-SoC stable in spite of the disrupting action of the drug on a
physiological level.
If induction is proceeding successfully, the disrupting forces push various structures/subsystems to their limits of
stable functioning and then beyond, destroying the integrity of the system and disrupting the stability of the b-SoC
as a system. Then, in the second part of the induction process, we apply patterning forces during this transitional,
disorganized period—psychological and/or physiological actions that pattern structures/subsystems into a new
system, the desired d-ASC. The new system, the d-ASC, must develop its own stabilization processes if it is to last.
Deinduction, return to the b-SoC, is the same process as induction. The d-ASC is disrupted, a transitional period
occurs, and the b-SoC is reconstructed by patterning forces. The subject transits back to his customary region of
experiential space.
Psychedelic drugs like marijuana or LSD do not have invariant psychological effects, even though much
misguided research assumes they do. In the present approach, such drugs are disrupting and patterning forces whose
effects occur in combination with other psychological factors, all mediated by the operating d-SoC. Consider the
so-called reverse tolerance effect of marijuana that allows new users to consume very large quantities of the drug
with no feeling of being stoned (in a d-ASC), but later to use much smaller quantities of marijuana to achieve the d-
ASC. This is not paradoxical in the systems approach, even though it is paradoxical in the standard pharmacological
approach. The physiological action of the marijuana is not sufficient to disrupt the ordinary d-SoC until additional
psychological factors disrupt enough of the stabilization processes of the b-SoC to allow transition to the d-ASC.
These additional psychological forces are usually "a little help from my friends," the instructions for deployment of
attention/awareness energy given by experienced users who know what functioning in the d-ASC of marijuana
intoxication is like. These instructions also serve as patterning forces to shape the d-ASC, to teach the new user how
to employ the physiological effects of the drug to form a new system of consciousness.
This book also discusses methodological problems in research from the point of view of the systems approach:
for example, the way in which experiential observations of consciousness and transitions from one d-SoC to
another can be made and the shifts in research strategies that this approach calls for. The systems approach can also
be applied within the ordinary d-SoC to deal with identity states, those rapid shifts in the central core of a person's
identity and concerns that are overlooked for many reasons, and emotional states. Similarly the systems approach
indicates that latent human potential can be developed and used in various d-ASCs, so that learning to shift into the
d-ASC appropriate for dealing with a particular problem is part of psychological growth. At the opposite extreme,
certain kinds of psychopathology, such as multiple personality, can be treat as d-ASCs.
One of the most important consequences of the systems approach is the deduction that we need to develop state-
specific sciences. Insofar as a "normal" d-SoC is a semi-arbitrary way of structuring consciousness, a way that loses
some human potentials while developing others, the sciences we have developed are one-state sciences. They are
limited in important ways. Our ordinary sciences have been very successful in dealing with the physical world, but
not very successful in dealing with particularly human psychological problems. If we apply scientific method to
developing sciences within various d-ASCs, we can evolve sciences based on radically different perceptions, logics,
and communications, and so gain new views complementary to our current ones.
The search for new views, new ways of coping, through the experience of d-ASCs is hardly limited to science. It
is a major basis for our culture's romance with drugs, meditation, Eastern religions, and the like. But infatuation
with a new view, a new d-SoC, tends to make us forget that any d-SoC is a limited construction. There is a price to
be paid for everything we get. It is vital for us to develop sciences of this powerful, life-changing area of d-ASCs if
we are to optimize benefits from the growing use of them and avoid the dangers of ignorant of superstitious
tampering with the basic structure of consciousness.
People use the phrase states of consciousness to describe unusual alterations in the way consciousness functions. In
this chapter we consider some of the experiences people use to judge what states they are in, in order to illustrate
the complexity of experience. We then consider what basic concepts or components we need to make sense out of
this variety of experiences.
I have often begun a lecture on states of consciousness by asking the audience the following question: "Is there
anyone here right now who seriously believes that what you are experiencing, in this room, at this moment, may be
something you are just dreaming? I don't mean picky, philosophical doubts about the ultimate nature of experience
or anything like that. I'm asking whether anyone in any seriously practical way thinks this might be a dream you're
experiencing now, rather than you ordinary state of consciousness?" How do you, dear reader, know that you are
actually reading this book now, rather than just dreaming about it? Think about it before going on.
I have asked this question of many audiences, and I have only occasionally seen a hand go up. No one has stuck
to defending this position. If you take this question to mean, "How do you know you're not dreaming now?" you
probably take a quick internal scan of the content and quality of your experience and find that some specific
elements of it, as well as the overall pattern of your experience, match those qualities you have come to associate
with your ordinary waking consciousness, but do not match the qualities you have come to associate with being in a
dreaming state of consciousness.
I ask this question in order to remind the reader of a basic datum underlying my approach to consciousness—that
a person sometimes scans the pattern of his ongoing experience and classifies it as being one or another state of
consciousness.
Many people make distinctions among only a few states of consciousness, since they experience only a few.
Everyone, for example, probably distinguishes between his ordinary waking state, dreaming, and dreamless sleep.
Some others may distinguish drunkenness as a fourth state of consciousness. Still others who have personally
experimented with altered states may want to distinguish among drug-induced, meditative, and emotion-induced
states.
Without yet attempting to define consciousness or states of consciousness more precisely, suppose we ask people
who have personally experienced many states of consciousness how they make these distinctions. What do they
look for in their experience that alerts them to the fact that they are in a different state of consciousness from their
ordinary one? A few years ago I asked a group of graduate students who had had fairly wide experience with altered
states, "What sorts of things in yourself do you check on if you want to decide what state of consciousness you're in
at a given moment?" Table 2-1 presents a categorization of the kinds of answers they gave, a categorization in terms
of the systems approach I am explaining as we go along. A wide variety of unusual experiences in perceptions of
the world or of oneself, of changes in time, emotion, memory, sense of identity, cognitive processes, perception of
the world, use of the body (motor output), and interaction with the world were mentioned.
If we ignore the categorization of the experiences listed in Table 2-1, we have an illustration of the current state
of knowledge about states of consciousness—that people experience a wide variety of unusual things. While the
experiencers imply that there are meaningful patterns in their experiences that they cluster together as "states," our
current scientific knowledge about how his wide variety of things goes together is poor. to understand people's
experiences in this area more adequately we must develop conceptual frameworks, theoretical tools, that make
sense out of the experiences in some more basic way and that still remain reasonably true to the experiences as
reported.
We can now begin to look at a conceptual framework that I have been developing for several years about the
nature of consciousness, and particularly about the nature of states of consciousness. Although what we loosely call
altered states of consciousness are often vitally important in determining human values and behavior, and although
we are in the midst of a cultural evolution (or decay, depending on your values) in which experiences from altered
states of consciousness play an important part, our scientific knowledge of this area is still sparse. We have a few
relationships, a small-scale theory here and there, but mainly assorted and unrelated observations and ideas. My
systems approach attempts to give an overall picture of this area to guide future research in a useful fashion.
I call this framework for studying consciousness a systems approach because I take the position that
consciousness, as we know it, is not a group of isolated psychological functions but a system—an interacting,
dynamic configuration of psychological components that performs various functions in greatly changing
environments. While knowledge of the nature of the components is useful, to understand fully any system we must
also consider the environments with which it deals and the goals of its functioning. So in trying to understand
human consciousness, we must get the feel of the whole system as it operates in its world, not just study isolated
parts of it.
I emphasize a psychological approach to states of consciousness because that is the approach I know best, and I
believe it is adequate for building a comprehensive science of consciousness. but because the approach deals with
systems, it can be easily translated into behavioral or neurophysiological terms.
Let us now look at the basic elements of this systems approach, the basic postulates about what lies behind the
phenomenal manifestations of experience. In the following chapters we will put these basic elements of awareness,
energy, and structure together into the systems we call states of consciousness.
Attention/awareness can be volitionally directed to some extent. If I ask you to become aware of the sensations in
your left knee now, you can do so. but few would claim anything like total ability to direct attention. If you are
being burned by a flame, it is generally impossible to direct your attention/awareness to something else and not
notice the pain at all, although this can be done by a few people in the ordinary d-SoC and by many more people in
certain states of consciousness. Like the degree of separation of attention/awareness from content, the degree to
which we can volitionally direct our attention/awareness also varies. Sometimes we can easily direct our thoughts
according to a predetermined plan; at other times our minds wander with no regard at all for our plans.
Stimuli and structures attract or capture attention/awareness. When you are walking down the street, the sound
and sight of an accident and a crowd suddenly gathering attract your attention to the incident. This attractive pull of
stimuli and activated structures may outweigh volitional attempts to deploy attention/awareness elsewhere. For
example, you worry over and over about a particular problem and are told that you are wasting energy by going
around in circles and should direct your attention elsewhere. but, in spite of your desire to do so, you may find it
almost impossible.
The ease with which particular kinds of structures and contents capture attention/awareness varies with the state
of consciousness and the personality structure of the individual. For example, things that are highly valued or are
highly threatening capture attention much more easily than things that bore us. Indeed, we can partially define
personality as those structures that habitually capture a person's attention/awareness. In some states of
consciousness, attention/awareness is more forcibly captivated by stimuli than in others.
Attention/awareness constitutes the major energy of the mind, as we usually experience it. Energy is here used in
its most abstract sense—the ability to do work, to make something happen. Attention/awareness is energy (1) in the
sense that structures having no effect on consciousness at a given time can be activated if attended to; (2) in the
sense that structures may draw attention/awareness energy automatically, habitually, as a function of personality
structure, thus keeping a kind of low-level, automated attention in them all the time (these are our long-term
desires, concerns, phobias, blindnesses); and (3) in the sense that attention/awareness energy may inhibit particular
structures from functioning. The selective redistribution of attention/awareness energy to desired ends is a key
aspect of innumerable systems that have been developed to control the mind.
The concept of psychological energy is usually looked upon with disfavor by psychologists because it is difficult
to define clearly. Yet various kinds of psychological energies are direct experiential realities. I am, for example, full
of energy for writing at this moment. When interrupted a minute ago, I resented having to divert this energy from
writing to dealing with a different issue. Last night I was tired; I felt little energy available to do what I wished to
do. Those who prefer to give priority to observations about the body and nervous system in their thinking would tell
me that various chemicals in my bloodstream were responsible for these varied feelings. But "chemicals in my
bloodstream" is a very intellectual, abstract concept to me, while the feelings of energy and of tiredness are direct
experiences for me and most other people. So we must consider psychological energy in order to keep our
theorizing close to experience.
I cannot deal in any detail with psychological energy at this stage of development of the systems approach, for
we know little about it. Clearly, changing the focus of attention (as in trying to sense what is happening in your left
knee) has effects: it starts, stops, and alters psychological processes. Also, attention/awareness is not the only form
of psychological energy. Emotions, for example, constitute a very important kind of energy, different in quality
from simple attention/awareness shifts, but interacting with attention/awareness as an energy. So while this book
deals concept of psychological energy is much more complex and is one of the major areas to be developed in the
future.
Note that the total amount of attention/awareness energy available to a person varies from time to time, but there
may be some fixed upper limit on it for a particular day or other time period. Some days, we simply cannot
concentrate well no matter how much we desire it; other days we seem able to focus clearly, to use lots of attention
to accomplish things. We talk about exhausting our ability to pay attention, and it may be that the total amount of
attention/awareness energy available is fixed for various time periods under ordinary conditions.
Structures
The mind, from which consciousness arises, consists of myriad structures. A psychological structure refers to a
relatively stable organization of component parts that perform one or more related psychological functions.
We infer (from outside) the existence of a particular structure by observing that a certain kind of input
information reliably results in specific transformed output information under typical conditions. For example, we
ask someone, "How much is fourteen divided by seven?" and he answers, "Two." After repeating this process, with
variations, we infer the existence of a special structure or related set of structures we can call arithmetical skills.
Experientially, we infer (from inside) the existence of a particular structure when, given certain classes experienced
input information, we experience certain transformed classes of output/response information. Thus, when I overhear
the question about fourteen divided by seven and observe that some part of me automatically responds with the
correct answer, I infer an arithmetical skills structure as part of my own mind.
We hypothesize that structures generally continue to exist even when they are not active, since they operate again
when appropriate activating information is present. I again know that fourteen divided by seven equals two, even
though I stopped thinking about it for a while.
The emphasis here is on the structure forming something that has a recognizable shape, pattern, function, and
process that endure over time. Ordinarily we are interested in the structure's overall properties as a complete
structure, as a structured system, rather than in the workings of its component parts. Insofar as any structure can be
broken down into substructures and sub-substructures, finer analyses are possible ad infinitum. The arithmetical
skill structure can be broken down into adding, subtracting, multiplying, or dividing substructures. Such
microscopic analyses, however, may not always be relevant to an understanding of the properties of the overall
system, such as the state of consciousness, that one is working with. the most obvious thing that characterizes an
automobile as a system is its ability to move passengers along roads at high speed; a metallurgical analyses of its
spark plugs is not relevant to an understanding of its primary functioning and nature. Our concern, then, is with the
psychological structures that show functions useful to our understanding of consciousness. Such structures can be
given names—sexual needs, social coping mechanisms, language abilities.
Note that some structures may be so complex that we are unable to recognize them as structures. We see only
component parts and never understand how they all work together.
A psychological structure may vary in the intensity and/or the quality of its activity, both overall and in terms of
its component parts, but still retain its basic patterns (gestalt qualities) and so remain recognizably the same. A car
is usefully referred to as a car whether it is moving at five or twenty-five miles an hour, whether it is red or blue,
whether the original spark plugs have been replaced by spark plugs of a different brand. We anticipate an
understanding of a state of consciousness as a system here.
Some structures are essentially permanent. The important aspects of their functioning cannot be modified in any
significant way; they are biological/physiological givens. They are the hardware of our mental system. To use an
analogy from computer programming, they are fixed programs, functions built into the machinery of the nervous
system.
Some structures are mainly or totally given by an individual's particular developmental history; they are created
by, programmed by, learning, conditioning, and enculturation processes that the individual undergoes. This is the
software of the human biocomputer. Because of the immense programmability of human beings, most of the
structures that interest us, that we consider particularly human, are in this software category.
Permanent structures create limits on, and add qualities to, what can be done with programmable structures: the
hardware puts some constraints on what the software can be. The physiological parameters constituting a human
being place some limits on his particular mental experience and his possible range of programming.
Our interest in relatively permanent structures,[3] one that are around long enough for us conveniently to
observe, experience and study. But all the theoretical ideas in this book should be applicable to structures that are
not long-lasting, even though investigation may be more difficult.
Structure, for the outside investigator, are hypothesized explanatory entities based on experiential, behavioral, or
psychological data. They are also hypothesized explanatory concepts for each of us in looking at his own
experience: I know that fourteen divided by two equals seven, but I do not experience the arithmetical skills
structure directly; I only know that when I need that kind of knowledge, it appears and functions. Since I need not
hold on consciously to that knowledge all the time, I readily believe or hypothesize that it is stored in some kind of
structure, someplace "in" my mind.
Although the interaction of one psychological structure with another structure depends on activation of both
structures by attention/awareness energy, this interaction is modified by an important limitation: that individual
structures have various kinds of properties that limit and control their potential range of interaction with one
another. Structures are not equipotent with respect to interacting with one another, but have important individual
characteristics. You cannot see with your ears.
Information is fed into any structure in one or more way and comes out of the structure in one or more ways.[5]
We can say in general that for two structures to interact (1) they must have either a direct connection between them
or some connections mediated by other structures, (2) their input and output information must be in the same code
so information output from one makes sense to the input for the other, (3) the output signals of one structure must
not be so weak that they are below the threshold for reception by the other structure, (4) the output signals of one
structure must not be so strong that they overload the input of the other structure.
Now let us consider ways in which psychological structures may not interact. First two structures may not
interact because there is no direct or mediated connection between them. I have, for example, structures involved in
moving the little finger of my left hand and sensing its motion, and I have structures involved in sensing my body
temperature and telling me whether I have a fever or a chill. Although I am moving my little finger vigorously now,
I can get no sense of having either a fever or a chill from that action. Those two structures seem to be totally
unconnected.
Second, two structures may not interact if the codes of output and input information are incompatible. My body,
for example, has learned to ride a bicycle. While I can sense that knowledge in my body, in the structure that
mediates my experience of riding a bicycle when I actually am doing so, I cannot verbalize it in any adequate way.
The nature of knowledge encoded in that particular structure does not code into the kind of knowledge that
constitutes my verbal structures.
Third, two structures may not interact if the output signal from one is too weak, below the threshold for affecting
another. When I am angry with someone and arguing with him, there may, during the argument, be a still small
voice in me telling me that I am acting foolishly, but I have little awareness of that still small voice, and it cannot
affect the action of the structures involved in feeling angry and arguing.
Fourth, two structures may not interact properly if the output signal from one overloads the other. I may be in
severe pain during a medical procedure, for instance, and I know (another structure tells me) that if I could relax the
pain would be lessened considerably; but the structures involved in relaxing are so overloaded by the intense pain
that they cannot carry out their normal function.
Fifth, two structures may be unable to interact properly if the action of a third structure interferes with them. An
example is a neurotic defense mechanism. Suppose, for instance, your employer constantly humiliates you. Suppose
also that part of your personality structure has a strong respect for authority and a belief in yourself as a very calm
person who is not easily angered. Now your boss is humiliating you, but instead of feeling angry (the natural
consequence of the situation), you are polite and conciliatory, and do not feel the anger. A structure of your
personality has suppressed certain possible interactions between other structures (but there may well be a hidden
price paid for this suppression, like ulcers).
Now consider the case of smoother interaction between structures. Two structures may interact readily and
smoothly with one another to form a composite structure, a system whose properties are additive properties of the
individual structures, as well as gestalt properties unique to the combination. Or, two or more structures may
interact with one another in such a way that the total system alters some of the properties of the individual
structures to various degrees, producing a system with gestalt properties that are not simple additive properties of
the individual structures. Unstable interactions may also occur between two or more structures that compete for
energy, producing an unstable, shifting relationship in the composite system.
All these considerations about the interactional structures apply to both hardware (biologically given) and
software (culturally programmed) structures. For example, two systems may not interact for a lack of connection in
the sense that their basic neural paths, built into the hardware of the human being, do not allow such interaction. Or,
two software structures may not interact for lack of connection because in the enculturation, the programming of
the person, the appropriate connections were simply not created.
All the classical psychological defense mechanisms can be viewed in these system terms as ways of controlling
interaction patterns among perceptions and psychological structures.
Remember that in the real human being many structures usually interact simultaneously, with all the above-
mentioned factors facilitating or inhibiting interaction to various degrees at various points in the total system
formed.
Thus while the interaction of structures is affected by the way attention/awareness energy is deployed, it is also
affected by the properties of individual structures. In computer terms, we are not totally general-purpose computers,
capable of being programmed in just any arbitrary fashion. We are specialized: that is our strength, weakness, and
humanness.
Table 2-1
EXPERIENTIAL CRITERIA FOR DETECTING AN
ALTERED STATE OF CONSCIOUSNESS
EXTEROCEPTION (sensing the external world)
• Alteration in various sensory characteristics of the perceived world—glowing
lights at the edges of things, attenuation or accentuation of visual depth
INTEROCEPTION (sensing the body)
•
Alteration in perceived body image---shape or size changes
• Alteration in detectable physiological parameters---accelerated or retarded heart
rate, respiration rate, muscle tonus, tremor
• Perception of special bodily feelings not normally present---feelings of energy in
the body, generally or specially localized, as in the spine; change in quality of
energy flow in the body, such as intensity, focus vs. diffuseness
INPUT-PROCESSING (seeing meaningful stimuli)
•
Sensory excitement, involvement, sensuality
•
Enhanced or decreased sensory intensity
•
Alterations of dominance-interaction hierarchies of various sensory modalities
• Illusion, hallucination, perception of patterns and things otherwise known to be
unlikely to actually exist in the environment
EMOTIONS
• Alteration in emotional response to stimuli---overreacting, underreacting, not
reacting, reacting in an entirely different way
•
Extreme intensity of emotions
MEMORY
• Changes in continuity of memory over time---either an implicit feeling that
continuity is present or an explicit checking of memory that shows current
experience to be consistent with continuous memories leading up to the present,
with gaps suggesting an altered state
• Details. Checking fine details of perceived environment (external or internal)
against memories of how they should be to detect incongruities
TIME SENSE
•
Unusual feeling of here-and-nowness
•
Feeling of great slowing or speeding of time
•
Feeling of orientation to past and/or future, regardless of relation to present
•
Feeling of archetypal quality to time; atemporal experience
SENSE OF IDENTITY
•
Sense of unusual identity, role
•
Alienation, detachment, perspective on usual identity or identities
EVALUATION AND COGNITIVE PROCESSING
•
Alteration in rate of thought
•
Alteration in quality of thought---sharpness, clarity
•
Alteration of rules of logic (compared with memory of usual rules)
MOTOR OUTPUT
•
Alteration in amount or quality of self-control
• Change in the active body image, the way the body feels when in motion, the
proprioceptive feedback signals that guide actions
•
Restlessness, tremor, partial paralysis
INTERACTION WITH THE ENVIRONMENT*
• Performance of unusual or impossible behaviors---incongruity of consequences
resulting from behavioral outputs, either immediate or longer term
• Change in anticipation of consequences of specific behaviors---either
prebehavioral or learned from observation of consequences
•
Change in voice quality
• Change in feeling of degree of orientation to or contact with immediate
environment
•
Change in involvement with vs. detachment from environment
• Change in communications with others---incongruities or altered patterns,
consensual validation or lack of it
*This category represents the combined functioning of several subsystems.
Foototes
[1] The reader may ask, "How can we study awareness or consciousness when we don't know what it basically
is?" The answer is, "In the same way that physicists studied and still study gravity: they don't know what it is, but
they can study what it does and how it relates to other things."
[2] Something we can only know retrospectively.
[3] I suspect that many of these relatively permanent psychological structures exist not just in the nervous system
but as muscle and connective tissue sets in the body, and can be changed radically by such procedures as structural
integration {54}
[4] We should be careful about a priori definitions that certain structures must be outside awareness. Data from
the rapidly developing science of biofeedback, and traditional data from yoga and other spiritual disciplines, remind
us that many processes long considered totally outside conscious awarenesS can be brought to conscious awareness
with appropriate training.
[5] For complex structures, we should probably also distinguish among (I) inputs and outputs that we can be
consciously aware of with suitable deployment of attention/awareness, (2) inputs and outputs that we cannot be
consciously aware of but that we can make inferences about, and (3) inputs and outputs that are part of feedback
control interconnections between structures, which we cannot be directly aware of. Further, we must allow for
energy exchanges, as well as informational exchanges, between structures.
An almost universal theory in Western scientific circles, sunk to the level of an implicit belief and thus controlling
us effectively, is that awareness is a product of brain functioning. No brain functioning—no awareness, no
consciousness. This is the conservative view of the mind. It is dangerous as an implicit belief for two reasons. First,
many experiences in various altered states of consciousness are inconsistent with this theory, but implicit faith in
the conservative view makes us liable to distort our perception of these phenomena. Second, parapsychological data
suggest that awareness is at least partially outside brain functioning, a condition that leads to very different views of
human nature. The radical view of the mind sees awareness as this something extra and postulates that physical
reality can sometimes be directly affected by our belief systems. We must be openminded about the radical view to
guard against maintaining too narrow and too culturally conditioned a view of the mind.
Although in general speech we tend to use the terms awareness and consciousness to mean basically the same
thing, I use them here with somewhat different meanings. Awareness refers to the basic knowledge that something
is happening, to perceiving or feeling or cognizing in its simplest form. Consciousness generally refers to awareness
in a much more complex way; consciousness is awareness as modulated by the structure of the mind. Mind refers to
the totality of both inferable and potentially experiencable phenomena of which awareness and consciousness are
components. These are not precise definitions because the three key words—awareness, consciousness, and mind—
are not simple things. But they are realities, and we must deal with them whether or not we can give them precise
logical definitions. Since logic is only one product of the total functioning of the mind, it is no wonder that we
cannot arrive at a logical definition of the mind or consciousness or awareness. The part cannot define the whole.
Awareness and consciousness, then, can be seen as parts of a continuum. I would use the word awareness to
describe, for instance, my simple perception of the sound of a bird outside my window as I write. I would use the
word consciousness to indicate the complex of operations that recognizes the sound as a bird call, that identifies the
species of bird, and that takes account of the fact that the sound is coming in through my open window. So
consciousness refers to a rather complex system that includes awareness as one of its basic ingredients, but is more
complex than simple awareness itself.
Few psychologists today would argue with the statement that consciousness is awareness resulting from the
brain's functioning. But if you ask what is the basic nature of awareness, the simple basic behind the more complex
entity consciousness, you meet the common assumption in Western culture generally and scientific culture in
particular that awareness is a "product" of the brain. When psychology was fond of chemical analogies, awareness
was thought of as a sort of "secretion" by the brain.
I believe that seeing consciousness as a function of the brain is sound, but I think that explicitly or implicitly
assuming that awareness is only a function of the brain, as accepted as that theory is, can be a hindrance, for two
reasons.
First, as psychology deals more and more with the phenomena of altered states of consciousness, it will more and
more have to deal with phenomena that do not fit well in a conceptual scheme that says awareness is only a product
of the brain. Experiences of apparently paranormal abilities like telepathy, of feeling that one's mind leaves one's
body, of mystical union with aspects of the universe outside oneself, of supernormal knowledge directly given in
altererd states, fit more comfortably into schemes that do not assume that awareness is only a function of the brain.
I have nothing against competent attempts to fit such phenomena into our dominant Western scientific framework,
but the attempts I have seen so far have been most inadequate and seem to work mainly by ignoring major aspects
of these altered states phenomena. Thus the assumption that awareness is only a function of the brain, especially as
it becomes implicit, tends to distort our view of real phenomena that happen in altered states. We dismiss their
possible reality a priori. We cannot build a science when we start with such a selected view of the data.
The second reason for questioning this assumption is the existence of first-class scientific data to suggest that
awareness may be something other than a product of the brain. I refer to excellent evidence of parapsychological
phenomena like telepathy, evidence that shows that the mind can sometimes function in ways that are "impossible"
in terms of our current, physical view of the world. I review our knowledge of the paranormal in Studies of Psi
{131}. "Impossible" means only that these phenomena are paraconceptual, that our conceptual schemes are
inadequate because they exclude this part of reality. These same conceptual schemes underlie the belief that
awareness is only a product of the brain, and if we question these conceptual schemes we question that assumption.
This book is not the place for detailed argument, but I have discussed the subject at greater length in Transpersonal
Psychologies {128}, which reviews the impact of the spiritual psychologies on the evolving science fo
consciousness.
This view that awareness is only a function of the brain
—the conservative or physicalistic view of the mind—is
diagrammed in Figure 3-1. The brain (and nervous system
and body) are depicted as a structure that has hardware
qualities on the one hand and software qualities on the
other. The hardware qualities are those inherent in the
physical makeup of the brain itself, as dictated by the
physical laws that govern reality. This dictation of
limitation is shown as a one-way arrow from the physical
world to the brain. The software qualities are the
programmable aspects of the brain, the capacities for
recording data and building up perception, evaluation, and
action patterns in accordance with programming instructions given by the culture. The arrows of influence are two-
way here, for even though the programming is largely done by the culture to the individual, occasionally the
individual modifies some aspects of the culture. Awareness is shown as an emergent quality of the brain, and so
awareness is ultimately limited by the hardware and by particular software programs of the brain. Consciousness is
the individual's experience of awareness diffused through a tiny fraction of the structure of the brain and nervous
system.
The radical view of the mind is diagrammed in Figure 3-2. Two changes have been made to incorporate the
radical view. First, awareness is shown as something that comes from outside the structure of the physical brain, as
well as something influenced by the structure of the brain (thus giving consciousness) and the cultural
programming. In religious terms, this is the idea of a soul or life/mind principle that uses (and is used by) the body.
This is a most unpopular idea in scientific circles, but, as I have argued elsewhere {129}, there is enough scientific
evidence that consciousness is capable of temporarily existing in a way that seems independent of the physical body
to warrant giving the idea serious consideration and doing some research on it.
The second change incorporated in the radical view is shown by the two-way arrow from the physical world to
the hardware structure of the brain. The idea, held in many spiritual systems of thought that have dealt with altered
states of consciousness, is that physical reality is not a completely fixed entity, but something that may actually be
shaped in some fundamental manner by the individual's beliefs about it. I am not speaking here simply of
perceptions of reality, but of the actual structure of reality. Pearce {49}, for example, describes an experience as a
youth where he accidentally entered an altered state of consciousness in which he knew he was impervious to pain
or injury. In front of witnesses he ground out the tips of glowing cigarettes on his cheeks, palms, and eyelids. He
felt no pain, and there was no sign of physical injury. The consventional view can easily account for the lack of
pain: by control of the structures involved in sensing pain (nerve tracts and certain brain areas), pain would not be
perceived. But a glowing cigarette tip has a temperature of about 1400F, and his skin should have been severely
burned, despite his state of consciousness. From the radical point of view, his beliefs about reality in the altered
state actually altered the nature of physical reality.
To argue for or against the radical view of the mind would take a book in itself, and this is not the one. (I
recommend Pearce's book and my Studies of Psi {131} for data on paranormal phenomena) I wnat to emphasize
that the radical view of the mind, in various forms, is often reported as an experience from altered state of
consciousness. If we are going to study states of consciousness adequately, we hall have to confront the radical
view, not automatically dismiss it as an illusion or a product of inferior brain frunctioning, but take it as data. I
would personally prefer not to: I do not like the radical view that our belief systems may actually alter the nature of
reality even though I can comfortably accept parapsychological data that show that reality is more complex than our
current physical world-view believes. But we should stay open to that view and make a decision for or against its
probability on scientific grounds, not simply because we have been trained to believe that there is an ultimate,
immutable physical reality. Don Juan put it pithily: "To believe that the world is only as you think it is is stupid"
{10}.
I sympathize with reader who finds himself rejecting the radical view of the mind. I suggest, however, that he
honestly ask himself, "Have I rejected this view as a result of careful and extensive study of the evidence for and
against it, or because I have been trained to do so and rewarded by social approval for doing so?"
4. The Nature of Ordinary Consciousness
A king once decided to give away a part of his wealth by disinterested charity. At the same time he wanted to
watch what happened to it. So he called a baker whom he could trust and told him to bake two loaves of bread. In
the first was to be baked a number of jewels, and in the other, nothing but flour and water.
These were to be given to the most and least pious people whom the baker could find.
The following morning two men presented themselves at the oven. One was dressed as a dervish and seemed
most pious, though he was in reality a mere pretender. The other who said nothing at all, reminded the baker of a
man whom he did not like, by a coincidence of facial resemblance.
The baker gave the bread with jewels in it to the man in the dervish robe, and the ordinary loaf to the second
man.
As soon as he got his loaf the false dervish felt it and weighed it in his hand. He felt the jewels, and to him they
seemed like lumps in the loaf, unblended flour. He weighed the bread in his hand and the weight of the jewels made
it seem to him to be too heavy. He looked at the baker, and realized that he was not a man to trifle with. So he
turned to the second man and said: "Why not exchange your loaf for mine? You look hungry, and his one is larger."
The second man, prepared to accept whatever befell, willfully exchanged loaves.
The king, who was watching through a crack in the bakehouse door, was surprised, but did not realize the relative
merits of the two men.
The false dervish got the ordinary loaf. The king concluded that Fate had intervened to keep the dervish protected
from wealth. The really good man found the jewels and was able to make good use of the. The king could not
interpret this happening.
"I did what I was told to do," said the baker.
"You cannot tamper with Fate," said the king.
"How clever I was!" said the false dervish.
The king, the baker, and the false dervish all had their own views of what reality was. None of them was likely
ever to correct his impression of this particular experience.
Consciousness, then, including perception, feeling, thinking, and
acting, is a semi-arbitrary construction. I emphasize semi-arbitrary
because I make the assumption, common to our culture that there are
some fixed rules governing physical reality whose violation produces
inevitable consequences. If someone walks off the edge of a tall cliff, I
believe he will fall to the bottom and probably be killed, regardless of
his beliefs about cliffs, gravity, or life and death. Thus people in cultures
whose belief systems do not, to a fair degree, match physical reality, are
not likely to survive long enough to argue with us. But once the minimal
degree of coincidence with physical reality necessary to enable physical
survival has been attained, the perception/consciousness of an action in
the complex social reality that then exists may be very arbitrary indeed.
We must face the fact, now amply documented by the scientific
evidence presented in any elementary psychology textbook, that perception can be highly selective. Simple images
of things out there are not clearly projected onto a mental screen, where we simply see them as they are. The act of
perceiving is a highly complex, automated construction. It is a selective category system, a decision-making
system, preprogrammed with criteria of what is important to perceive. It frequently totally ignores things it has not
been preprogrammed to believe are important.
Figure 4-2 shows a person with a set of categories programmed in his mind, a selection of implicit criteria to
recognize things that are "important." When stimulated by one of these things he is preprogrammed to perceive, he
readily responds to it. More precisely, rather than saying he responds to it which implies a good deal of directness in
perception, we might say that it triggers a representation of itself in his mind, and he then responds to that
representation. As long as it is a good representation of the actual stimulus object, he has a fairly accurate
perception. Since he tends to pay more attention to the representations of things he sees than to the things
themselves, however, he may think he perceives a stimulus object
clearly when actually he is perceiving an incorrect representation.
This is where perception begins to be distorted by the perceiver's
training and needs. Eskimos have been trained to distinguish seven
or more kinds of snow. We do not see these different kinds of snow,
even though they exist, for we do not need to make these
distinctions. To us it is all snow. Our one internal representation of
snow is triggered indiscriminately by any kind of actual snow.
Similarly, for the paranoid person who needs to believe that others
are responsible for his troubles, representations of threatening
actions are easily triggered by all sorts of behaviors on the part of
others. A detailed analysis of this is given in Chapter 19.
What happens when we are faced by the unknown, by
things we have not been trained to see? Figure 4-3, using the
same kind of analogy as the previous figure, depicts this. We
may not see the stimulus at all: the information passes right
through the mind without leaving a trace. Or we may see a
distorted representation of the stimulus: some of the few
features it has in common with known stimuli trigger
representations of the known features, and that is what we
perceive. We "sophisticated" Westerners do not believe in
angels. If we actually confronted one, we might not be able to
see it correctly. The triangle in its hands is a familiar figure,
however, so we might perceive the triangle readily. In fact, we
might see little but the triangle—maybe a triangle in the hands of a sweet old lady wearing a white robe.
Don Juan, the Yaqui man of knowledge, puts it quite succinctly: "I think you are only alert about things you
know" {10}.
I mentioned above the curious fact about psychologists, who know about the complexities of perception, almost
never seem to apply this information to their own perceptions. Even though they study the often large and obvious
distortions in other people's perceptions, they maintain an image of themselves as realistic perceivers. Some
psychologists even argue that perception is actually quite realistic. But what does "realistic" mean?
We like to believe that it means perception of the real world, the physical world. But the world we spend most of
our time perceiving is not just any segment of the physical world, but a highly socialized part of the physical world
that has been built into cities, automobiles, television sets. So our perception may indeed be realistic, but it is so
only with respect to a very tailored segment of reality, a consensus reality, a small selection of things we have
agreed are "real" and "important." thus, within our particular cultural framework, we can easily set up what seem to
be excellent scientific experiments that will show that our perceptions are indeed realistic, in the sense that we
agree with each other on these selected items from our consensus reality.
This is a way of saying that our perceptions are highly selective and filtered, that there is a major subsystem of
consciousness, Input-Processing discussed at length later, that filters the outside world for us. If two people have
similar filtering systems, as, for example, if they are from the same culture, they can agree on many things. But
again, as Don Juan says, "I think you are only alert about things you know." If we want to develop a science to
study consciousness, and want that science to go beyond our own cultural limitations, we must begin by
recognizing the limitations and arbitrariness of much of our ordinary state of consciousness.
I have now mentioned several times that we believe certain things imply because we were trained to believe
them. Let us now look at the training process by which our current "normal" or ordinary state of consciousness
came about.
Enculturation
Figure 4-4 illustrates the concept of the spectrum of human potential. By the simple fact of being born human,
having a certain type of body and nervous system, existing in the environmental conditions of the planet earth, a
large (but certainly not infinite) number of potentials are possible for you. Because you are born into a particular
culture, existing at a particular time and place on the surface of the planet, however, only a small (perhaps a very
small) number of these potentials will ever be realized and
become actualities. We can think of a culture[1] as a group
of people who, through various historical processes, have
come to an agreement that certain human potentials they
know of are "good," "holy," "natural," or whatever local
word is used for positively valuing them, and should be
developed. They are defined as the essence of being human.
Other potentials, also known to the culture, are considered
"bad," "evil," "unnatural." The culture actively inhibits the
development of these potentials in its children, not always
successfully. A large number of other human potentials are
simply not known to that particular culture, and while some
of them develop owing to accidental circumstances in a
particular person's life, most do not develop for lack of
stimulation. Some of these potentials remain latent, capable
of being developed if circumstances are right in later life;
others disappear completely through not being developed at
an early, critical stage.
Most of us know how to do arithmetic, speak English,
write a check, drive an automobile, and most of us know
about things, like eating with our hands, which are repellent
to us (naturally or through training?). Not many of us,
though, were trained early in childhood to enter a d-ASC
where we can be, for example, possessed by a friendly spirit
that will teach us songs and dances as is done by some
cultures. Nor were most of us trained to gain control over our dreams and acquire spirit guides in those dreams who
will teach us useful things, as the Senoi of Malaysia are {88 or 115, ch. 9}. Each of us is simultaneously the
beneficiary of his cultural heritage and the victim and slave of his culture's narrowness. What I believe is worse is
that few of us have any realization of this situation. Like almost all people in all cultures at all times, we think our
local culture is the best and other peoples are uncivilized or savages.
Figure 4-4 shows two different cultures making different selections from and inhibitions of the spectrum of
human potential. There is some overlap: all cultures, for example, develop a language of some sort and so use those
particular human potentials. Many potentials are not selected by any culture.
We can change the labels in Figure 4-4 slightly and depict various possible experiences selected in either of two
states of consciousness. Then we have the spectrum of experiential potentials, the possible kinds of experiences or
modes of functioning of human consciousness. The two foci of selection are two states of consciousness. These
may be two "normal" states of consciousness in two different cultures or, as discussed later, two states of
consciousness that exist within a single individual. The fact that certain human potentials can be tapped in state of
consciousness A that cannot be tapped in state of consciousness B is a major factor behind the current interest in
altered states of consciousness.
Figure 4-4, then, indicates that in developing a "normal" state of consciousness, a particular culture selects
certain human potentials and structures them into a functioning system. This is the process of enculturation. It
begins in infancy, possibly even before birth: there has been speculation, for example, that the particular language
sounds that penetrate the walls of the womb from outside before birth may begin shaping the potentials for sound
production in the unborn baby.
Figure 4-5 summarizes the main stages of the enculturation process. The left-hand column represents the degree
to which physical reality shapes the person and the degree to which the person can affect (via ordinary muscular
means) physical reality. The right-hand column indicates the main sources of programming, the psychological
influences on the person. The main stages are infancy, childhood, adolescence, adulthood, and senescence.
Infancy
We tend to think of a newborn infant as a rather passive creature, capable of little mental activity, whose primary
job is simple physical growth. Recent research, on the contrary, suggests that a person's innate learning capacity
may be highest of all in infancy, for the infant has to learn to construct the consensus reality of his culture. This is
an enormous job. The cultural environment, for instance, begins to affect the perceptual biases described in Chapter
8 as the Input-Processing subsystem. Most Westerners, for example, are better at making fine discriminations
between horizontal lines and vertical lines than between lines that are slanted. At first this was thought to result
from the innate hardware properties (racial, genetic) of the eye and nervous system, but recent evidence shows that
it is probably a cultural effect. Cree Indians, who as infants live in teepees where there are many slanted lines, can
discriminate slanted lines as acutely as horizontal and vertical ones{2}. "Civilized" Westerners, on the other hand,
grow up in environments where vertical and horizontal lines predominate. In more ways than we can even begin to
think of, the enculturation process affects perception, and ultimately consciousness, even in infancy.
Note also that the structuring/programming of our consciousness that takes place in early infancy is probably the
most persistent and most implicit of all our programming and learning, for at that time we have no other framework
to compare it with. It is the only thing we have, and it is closely connected with our physical survival and our being
loved and accepted. It gives us a loyalty and a bond to our culture's particular world-view that may be almost
impossible for us to break, but again, one whose limitations we must be aware of if we are really to understand the
workings of our minds. Another Sufi teaching story, "The Bird and the Egg" {58, p. 130}, illustrates the power of
this early programming:
Once upon a time there was bird which did not have the power of flight. Like a chicken, he walked about on the
ground, although he knew that some birds did fly.
It so happened that, through a combination of circumstances, the egg of a flying bird was incubated by this
flightless one.
In due time the chick came forth, still with the potentiality for flight which he had always had, even from the
time he was in the egg.
It spoke to its foster-parent, saying: "When will I fly?" And the landbound bird said: "Persist in your attempts to
fly, just like the others."
For he did not know how to take the fledgling for its lesson in flying: even how to topple it from the nest so that
it might learn.
And it is curious, in a way, that the young bird did not see this. His recognition of the situation was confused by
the fact that he felt gratitude to the bird who had hatched him.
"Without this service," he said to himself, "surely I would still be in the egg?"
And, again, sometimes he said to himself: "Anyone who can hatch me, surely he can teach me to fly. It must be
just a matter of time, or of my own unaided efforts, or of some great wisdom: yes, that is it. Suddenly one day I will
be carried to the next stage by him who has brought me thus far."
Childhood
By the time an ordinary person reaches childhood, he has attained a basic membership in the consensus reality of
his culture. A normal child has a pretty good idea of the dos and don'ts of his culture and behaves in a generally
acceptable fashion. Many of the potentials present at the time of his birth are gone by now, but consensus reality has
been formed from the few that have been cultivated.
One of the main ways in which consciousness is shaped to fit consensus reality is through the medium of
language. The word for an object focuses a child's perception onto a specific thing considered important by the
culture. Social approval for this kind of behavior gives words great power. As a child gradually grows in his
mastery of language, the language structure and its effect on consciousness grow at an exponential rate. The tyranny
of words is one of the most difficult things from which we must try to free ourselves.
A child's basic membership in consensus reality is not complete. The mind of the child can still do many strange
(by adult standards) things. As Pearce {49, p. 56} comments:
The child's mind is autistic, a rich texture of free synthesis, halluncinatory and unlimited. His mind can skip over
syllogisms with ease, in a non-logical, dream-sequence kind of "knight's move" continuum. He nevertheless shows
a strong desire to participate in a world of others. Eventually his willingness for self-modification, necessary to win
rapport with his world, is stronger than his desire for autonomy. Were it not, civilization would not be possible. That
we succeed in moulding him to respond to our criteria shows the innate drive for communion and the flexibility of a
young mind. It doesn't prove an essential and sanctified rightness of our own constructs.
Maturity, or becoming reality adjusted, restricts and diminishes that "knight's move" thinking, and tends to make
pawns of us in the process. The kind of adult logic that results is dependent on the kinds of demands made on the
young mind by parents and society.
It is precisely this kind of childish strangeness that both frustrates us adults when we try to deal with children and
excites our envy when we realize children have a certain freedom we do not have.
Adolescence
Adolescence is a different stage from childhood, not just a continuation of it, because the influx of sexual
energies at puberty allows considerable change in the ordinary consciousness of the child. for most adolescents this
is a time of turmoil (at least in our culture) as they strive to adjust to bodily changes and to learn to satisfy their
sexual needs within the mores of the culture.
For many there is a continuity with childhood, and after a transitional period of being difficult, the adolescent
settles into a pattern of being a grown-up version of the child he was. For others a conversion of some sort occurs:
the sexual and other energies unleashed at puberty become sublimated into a belief system that may be radically
different from what they had as children. If this is traumatic or sudden, or if the belief system is radically at odds
with that of the parents, we notice this conversion. If the sublimation of the energies is into a socially accepted
pattern, we are not as likely to perceive it.
Conversion is a powerful psychological process that we do not understand well. It bears some similarity to the
concept of a discrete state of consciousness (introduced later) but more basically refers to a psychological process
of focusing, of giving great energy to selected structures, that may take place in any state of consciousness.
I do not believe that the conversion process is completely free to go wherever it will. By the time a person has
reached adolescence (or later, if conversion takes place later), many human potentials he possessed at birth are, for
lack of stimulation, simply no longer available. Of the latent potentials that still could be used, cultural selection
and structuring have already made some more likely than others t o be utilized in a conversion. Thus even the rebels
in a society are in many ways not free: the direction that rebellion takes has already been strongly shaped by
enculturation processes.
The adolescent is very much a member of the consensus reality of his culture: his ordinary state of consciousness
is well adapted to fit into, and he has a fair degree of control over his physical environment. For most "ordinary"
adolescents, there are far fewer possibilities for unusual functions of consciousness than there were in childhood.
Adulthood
Adults are full-fledged members of the consensus reality: they both maintain it through their interaction with
their peers and are shaped by it and by parts of it. Adults are, as Don Juan taught, always talking to themselves
about their ordinary things, keeping up a constant pattern of information flow in their minds along familiar routes.
This strengthens and maintains their membership in the consensus reality and their use of their ordinary state of
consciousness as a means for dealing with consensus reality.
Because of the power over physical reality given them by their consensus reality state of consciousness, adults
are the most free; yet, because they are the most thoroughly indoctrinated in consensus reality, they are the most
bound. They receive many rewards for participating in the consensus reality in an acceptable way, and they have an
enormous number of external and internalized prohibitions that keep them from thinking and experiencing in ways
not approved by the consensus reality. The Sufi teaching story, "Bayazid and the Selfish Man" {58 p. 180}, shows
how difficult it is for an adult to free himself from the power of ordinary consciousness and consensus reality, even
when he believes he wants to:
One day a man reproached Bayazid, the great mystic of the ninth century, saying that he had fasted and prayed
and so on for thirty years and not found the joy which Bayazid described. Bayazid told him that he might continue
for three hundred years and still not find it.
"How is that?" asked the would-be illuminate.
"Because your vanity is a barrier to you."
"Tell me the remedy."
"The remedy is one which you cannot take."
"Tell me, nevertheless."
Bayazid said: "You must go to the barber and have your (respectable) beard shaved. Remove all your clothes and
put a girdle around yourself. Fill a nosebag with walnuts and suspend it from your neck. Go to the marketplace and
call out: 'A walnut will I give to any boy who will strike me on the back of neck.' Then continue to the justices'
session so that they may see you."
"But I cannot do that; please tell me something else that would do as well."
"This is the first move, and the only one," said Bayazid, but I had already told you that you would not do it; so
you cannot be cured."
I stress the view that we are prisoners of our ordinary state of consciousness, victims of our consensus reality,
because it is necessary to become aware of this if we are to have any hope of transcending it, of developing a
science of the mind that is not culturally limited. Enormous benefits result from sharing in our consensus reality, but
these benefits must not blind us to the limits of this reality.
Senescence
The final stage in a person's life comes when he is too old to participate actively in the affairs of his culture. His
mid may be so rigid by this time that it can do little but rerun the programs of consensus reality while his abilities
diminish. If he is aware of other possibilities, he may find old age a way of freeing himself from cultural pressures
and begin to explore his mind in a new way. There are cultural traditions, in India, for example, where a person who
has fulfilled his main tasks in life is expected to devote his remaining years to exploring his own mind and
searching out spiritual values. This is difficult to think about in the context of our own culture, however, for we
have so overvalued youth and the active mode of life that we define older people as useless, a defining action that
often affects those older people so that they believe it.
This chapter opened with a drawing showing the naiveté of the view that perception and consciousness are means
of grasping physical reality. It ends with a drawing (Figure 4-6) that shows a truer and more complex view of
perception (and, to some extent, of the consciousness behind it). In the center of the drawing are depicted various
stimuli from others and from the physical world impinging on the individual. These stimuli produce effects that can
be classified as mental, emotional, and bodily. The innermost reaction circle represents clearly conscious
experiences. At this moment, as I write, I hear a pneumatic drill being used to break up the pavement outside my
window. I mentally speculate about the air pressure used to operate such an interesting tool but note that it is
distracting me; I emotionally dislike the disturbance of my writing; the muscles of my face and ears tighten a little,
as if that will reduce the impact of the noxious sound on me.
While the three-part classification of effects provides a simplification, in reality the mental, emotional, and
bodily responses to stimuli interact at both conscious and less than conscious levels. My mind notices the tension
around my ear and interprets that as something wrong, which, as a minor emotional threat, aggravates the
noxiousness of the sound, etc.
Immediately behind fully conscious experiences are easily experienceable phenomena, represented by the second
circle. The mental effect of these phenomena relates to the individual's explicit belief system: I believe that noise is
undesirable, but I am fascinated by the workings of machines. Their emotional effect relates to the things he readily
knows he likes or dislikes: loud noises generally bother me and make me feel intruded upon. Their bodily effect
relates to consciously usable skills and movements: I can relax my facial muscles. These phenomena affect the
individual at a level that is not in the focus of consciousness, but that can be easily made conscious by paying
attention.
These two levels are themselves affected and determined by a more implicit level of functioning, implicit in that
the individual cannot identify its content simply by wanting to and paying attention. Where did I get the idea that
noise is an intrusion? Why am I fascinated by the workings of machines? I do not know. I might be able to find out
by prolonged psychological exploration, but the information is not easily available, even though these things affect
me. Why do I have an immediate emotional dislike of noise? Is there some unconscious reaction behind it? How
have I come to maintain certain muscle sets in my face that are affected by stress in certain ways?
The outer circle in Figure 4-6 represents basic learnings, conditionings, motor patterns, instincts, reflexes,
language categories, and the like, which are so implicit the individual can hardly/ recognize their existence. This is
the level of the hardware, the biological givens, and the basic enculturation processes. The distance of these things
from consciousness makes it extremely difficult for him to discover and compensate for their controlling influences:
they are, in many ways, the basis of himself.
If the stimulus in the middle of Figure 4-6 is a cat, this whole complex machine functions, a machine designed by
our culture. We don't "just" see the cat! Our ordinary state of consciousness is a very complex construction indeed,
yet Figure 4-6 hardly goes into details at all. So much for the naturalness of our ordinary state of consciousness.
Figure 4-6
Footnote
[1] For simplicity here, we will ignore subcultures and conflicts within a culture.
The king, the baker, and the false dervish all had their own views
of what reality was. None of them was likely ever to correct his
impression of this particular experience.
Consciousness, then, including perception, feeling, thinking, and
acting, is a semi-arbitrary construction. I emphasize semi-arbitrary
because I make the assumption, common to our culture that there
are some fixed rules governing physical reality whose violation
produces inevitable consequences. If someone walks off the edge
of a tall cliff, I believe he will fall to the bottom and probably be
killed, regardless of his beliefs about cliffs, gravity, or life and death. Thus people in cultures whose belief systems
do not, to a fair degree, match physical reality, are not likely to survive long enough to argue with us. But once the
minimal degree of coincidence with physical reality necessary to enable physical survival has been attained, the
perception/consciousness of an action in the complex social reality that then exists may be very arbitrary indeed.
We must face the fact, now amply documented by the scientific evidence presented in any elementary
psychology textbook, that perception can be highly selective. Simple images of things out there are not clearly
projected onto a mental screen, where we simply see them as they are. The act of perceiving is a highly complex,
automated construction. It is a selective category system, a decision-making system, preprogrammed with criteria
of what is important to perceive. It frequently totally ignores things it has not been preprogrammed to believe are
important.
Figure 4-2 shows a person with a set of categories programmed in his mind, a selection of implicit criteria to
recognize things that are "important." When stimulated by one of these things he is preprogrammed to perceive, he
readily responds to it. More precisely, rather than saying he responds to it which implies a good deal of directness in
perception, we might say that it triggers a representation of itself in his mind, and he then responds to that
representation. As long as it is a good representation of the actual stimulus object, he has a fairly accurate
perception. Since he tends to pay more attention to the representations of things he sees than to the things
themselves, however, he may think he perceives a stimulus object clearly when actually he is perceiving an
incorrect representation.
This is where perception begins to be distorted by the perceiver's training and needs. Eskimos have been trained
to distinguish seven or more kinds of snow. We do not see these different kinds of snow, even though they exist, for
we do not need to make these distinctions. To us it is all snow. Our one internal representation of snow is triggered
indiscriminately by any kind of actual snow. Similarly, for the paranoid person who needs to believe that others are
responsible for his troubles, representations of threatening actions are easily triggered by all sorts of behaviors on
the part of others. A detailed analysis of this is given in Chapter 19.
What happens when we are faced by the unknown, by things we have not been trained to see? Figure 4-3, using
the same kind of analogy as the previous figure, depicts this. We may not see the stimulus at all: the information
passes right through the mind without leaving a trace. Or we may see a distorted representation of the stimulus:
some of the few features it has in common with known stimuli trigger representations of the known features, and
that is what we perceive. We "sophisticated" Westerners do not believe in angels. If we actually confronted one, we
might not be able to see it correctly. The triangle in its hands is a familiar figure, however, so we might perceive the
triangle readily. In fact, we might see little but the triangle—maybe a triangle in the hands of a sweet old lady
wearing a white robe.
Don Juan, the Yaqui man of knowledge, puts it quite succinctly: "I think you are only alert about things you
know" {10}.
I mentioned above the curious fact about psychologists, who know about the complexities of perception, almost
never seem to apply this information to their own perceptions. Even though they study the often large and obvious
distortions in other people's perceptions, they maintain an image of themselves as realistic perceivers. Some
psychologists even argue that perception is actually quite realistic. But what does "realistic" mean?
We like to believe that it means perception of the real world, the physical world. But the world we spend most of
our time perceiving is not just any segment of the physical world, but a highly socialized part of the physical world
that has been built into cities, automobiles, television sets. So our perception may indeed be realistic, but it is so
only with respect to a very tailored segment of reality, a consensus reality, a small selection of things we have
agreed are "real" and "important." thus, within our particular
cultural framework, we can easily set up what seem to be
excellent scientific experiments that will show that our
perceptions are indeed realistic, in the sense that we agree
with each other on these selected items from our consensus
reality.
This is a way of saying that our perceptions are highly
selective and filtered, that there is a major subsystem of
consciousness, Input-Processing discussed at length later, that
filters the outside world for us. If two people have similar
filtering systems, as, for example, if they are from the same
culture, they can agree on many things. But again, as Don Juan says, "I think you are only alert about things you
know." If we want to develop a science to study consciousness, and want that science to go beyond our own cultural
limitations, we must begin by recognizing the limitations and arbitrariness of much of our ordinary state of
consciousness.
I have now mentioned several times that we believe certain things imply because we were trained to believe
them. Let us now look at the training process by which our current "normal" or ordinary state of consciousness
came about.
Enculturation
Figure 4-4 illustrates the concept of the spectrum of human potential. By the simple fact of being born human,
having a certain type of body and nervous system, existing in the environmental conditions of the planet earth, a
large (but certainly not infinite) number of potentials are possible for you. Because you are born into a particular
culture, existing at a particular time and place on the surface of the planet, however, only a small (perhaps a very
small) number of these potentials will ever be realized and become actualities. We can think of a culture[1] as a
group of people who, through various historical processes, have come to an agreement that certain human potentials
they know of are "good," "holy," "natural," or whatever local word is used for positively valuing them, and should
be developed. They are defined as the essence of being human. Other potentials, also known to the culture, are
considered "bad," "evil," "unnatural." The culture actively inhibits the development of these potentials in its
children, not always successfully. A large number of other human potentials are simply not known to that particular
culture, and while some of them develop owing to accidental circumstances in a particular person's life, most do not
develop for lack of stimulation. Some of these potentials remain latent, capable of being developed if circumstances
are right in later life; others disappear completely through not being developed at an early, critical stage.
Most of us know how to do arithmetic, speak English, write a check, drive an automobile, and most of us know
about things, like eating with our hands, which are repellent to us (naturally or through training?). Not many of us,
though, were trained early in childhood to enter a d-ASC where we can be, for example, possessed by a friendly
spirit that will teach us songs and dances as is done by some cultures. Nor were most of us trained to gain control
over our dreams and acquire spirit guides in those dreams who will teach us useful things, as the Senoi of Malaysia
are {88 or 115, ch. 9}. Each of us is simultaneously the beneficiary of his cultural heritage and the victim and slave
of his culture's narrowness. What I believe is worse is that few of us have any realization of this situation. Like
almost all people in all cultures at all times, we think our local culture is the best and other peoples are uncivilized
or savages.
Figure 4-4 shows two different cultures making different selections from and inhibitions of the spectrum of
human potential. There is some overlap: all cultures, for example, develop a language of some sort and so use those
particular human potentials. Many potentials are not selected by any culture.
We can change the labels in Figure 4-4 slightly and depict various possible experiences selected in either of two
states of consciousness. Then we have the spectrum of experiential potentials, the possible kinds of experiences or
modes of functioning of human consciousness. The two foci of selection are two states of consciousness. These
may be two "normal" states of consciousness in two different cultures or, as discussed later, two states of
consciousness that exist within a single individual. The fact that certain human potentials can be tapped in state of
consciousness A that cannot be tapped in state of consciousness B is a major factor behind the current interest in
altered states of consciousness.
Figure 4-4, then, indicates that in developing a "normal" state of consciousness, a particular culture selects
certain human potentials and structures them into a
functioning system. This is the process of enculturation. It
begins in infancy, possibly even before birth: there has been
speculation, for example, that the particular language sounds
that penetrate the walls of the womb from outside before
birth may begin shaping the potentials for sound production
in the unborn baby.
Figure 4-5 summarizes the main stages of the
enculturation process. The left-hand column represents the
degree to which physical reality shapes the person and the
degree to which the person can affect (via ordinary muscular
means) physical reality. The right-hand column indicates the
main sources of programming, the psychological influences
on the person. The main stages are infancy, childhood,
adolescence, adulthood, and senescence.
Infancy
Childhood
By the time an ordinary person reaches childhood, he has attained a basic membership in the consensus reality of
his culture. A normal child has a pretty good idea of the dos and don'ts of his culture and behaves in a generally
acceptable fashion. Many of the potentials present at the time of his birth are gone by now, but consensus reality has
been formed from the few that have been cultivated.
One of the main ways in which consciousness is shaped to fit consensus reality is through the medium of
language. The word for an object focuses a child's perception onto a specific thing considered important by the
culture. Social approval for this kind of behavior gives words great power. As a child gradually grows in his
mastery of language, the language structure and its effect on consciousness grow at an exponential rate. The tyranny
of words is one of the most difficult things from which we must try to free ourselves.
A child's basic membership in consensus reality is not complete. The mind of the child can still do many strange
(by adult standards) things. As Pearce {49, p. 56} comments:
The child's mind is autistic, a rich texture of free synthesis, halluncinatory and unlimited. His mind can skip over
syllogisms with ease, in a non-logical, dream-sequence kind of "knight's move" continuum. He nevertheless shows
a strong desire to participate in a world of others. Eventually his willingness for self-modification, necessary to win
rapport with his world, is stronger than his desire for autonomy. Were it not, civilization would not be possible. That
we succeed in moulding him to respond to our criteria shows the innate drive for communion and the flexibility of a
young mind. It doesn't prove an essential and sanctified rightness of our own constructs.
Maturity, or becoming reality adjusted, restricts and diminishes that "knight's move" thinking, and tends to make
pawns of us in the process. The kind of adult logic that results is dependent on the kinds of demands made on the
young mind by parents and society.
It is precisely this kind of childish strangeness that both frustrates us adults when we try to deal with children and
excites our envy when we realize children have a certain freedom we do not have.
Adolescence
Adolescence is a different stage from childhood, not just a continuation of it, because the influx of sexual
energies at puberty allows considerable change in the ordinary consciousness of the child. for most adolescents this
is a time of turmoil (at least in our culture) as they strive to adjust to bodily changes and to learn to satisfy their
sexual needs within the mores of the culture.
For many there is a continuity with childhood, and after a transitional period of being difficult, the adolescent
settles into a pattern of being a grown-up version of the child he was. For others a conversion of some sort occurs:
the sexual and other energies unleashed at puberty become sublimated into a belief system that may be radically
different from what they had as children. If this is traumatic or sudden, or if the belief system is radically at odds
with that of the parents, we notice this conversion. If the sublimation of the energies is into a socially accepted
pattern, we are not as likely to perceive it.
Conversion is a powerful psychological process that we do not understand well. It bears some similarity to the
concept of a discrete state of consciousness (introduced later) but more basically refers to a psychological process
of focusing, of giving great energy to selected structures, that may take place in any state of consciousness.
I do not believe that the conversion process is completely free to go wherever it will. By the time a person has
reached adolescence (or later, if conversion takes place later), many human potentials he possessed at birth are, for
lack of stimulation, simply no longer available. Of the latent potentials that still could be used, cultural selection
and structuring have already made some more likely than others t o be utilized in a conversion. Thus even the rebels
in a society are in many ways not free: the direction that rebellion takes has already been strongly shaped by
enculturation processes.
The adolescent is very much a member of the consensus reality of his culture: his ordinary state of consciousness
is well adapted to fit into, and he has a fair degree of control over his physical environment. For most "ordinary"
adolescents, there are far fewer possibilities for unusual functions of consciousness than there were in childhood.
Adulthood
Adults are full-fledged members of the consensus reality: they both maintain it through their interaction with
their peers and are shaped by it and by parts of it. Adults are, as Don Juan taught, always talking to themselves
about their ordinary things, keeping up a constant pattern of information flow in their minds along familiar routes.
This strengthens and maintains their membership in the consensus reality and their use of their ordinary state of
consciousness as a means for dealing with consensus reality.
Because of the power over physical reality given them by their consensus reality state of consciousness, adults
are the most free; yet, because they are the most thoroughly indoctrinated in consensus reality, they are the most
bound. They receive many rewards for participating in the consensus reality in an acceptable way, and they have an
enormous number of external and internalized prohibitions that keep them from thinking and experiencing in ways
not approved by the consensus reality. The Sufi teaching story, "Bayazid and the Selfish Man" {58 p. 180}, shows
how difficult it is for an adult to free himself from the power of ordinary consciousness and consensus reality, even
when he believes he wants to:
One day a man reproached Bayazid, the great mystic of the ninth century, saying that he had fasted and prayed
and so on for thirty years and not found the joy which Bayazid described. Bayazid told him that he might continue
for three hundred years and still not find it.
"How is that?" asked the would-be illuminate.
"Because your vanity is a barrier to you."
"Tell me the remedy."
"The remedy is one which you cannot take."
"Tell me, nevertheless."
Bayazid said: "You must go to the barber and have your (respectable) beard shaved. Remove all your clothes and
put a girdle around yourself. Fill a nosebag with walnuts and suspend it from your neck. Go to the marketplace and
call out: 'A walnut will I give to any boy who will strike me on the back of neck.' Then continue to the justices'
session so that they may see you."
"But I cannot do that; please tell me something else that would do as well."
"This is the first move, and the only one," said Bayazid, but I had already told you that you would not do it; so
you cannot be cured."
I stress the view that we are prisoners of our ordinary state of consciousness, victims of our consensus reality,
because it is necessary to become aware of this if we are to have any hope of transcending it, of developing a
science of the mind that is not culturally limited. Enormous benefits result from sharing in our consensus reality, but
these benefits must not blind us to the limits of this reality.
Senescence
The final stage in a person's life comes when he is too old to participate actively in the affairs of his culture. His
mid may be so rigid by this time that it can do little but rerun the programs of consensus reality while his abilities
diminish. If he is aware of other possibilities, he may find old age a way of freeing himself from cultural pressures
and begin to explore his mind in a new way. There are cultural traditions, in India, for example, where a person who
has fulfilled his main tasks in life is expected to devote his remaining years to exploring his own mind and
searching out spiritual values. This is difficult to think about in the context of our own culture, however, for we
have so overvalued youth and the active mode of life that we define older people as useless, a defining action that
often affects those older people so that they believe it.
This chapter opened with a drawing showing the naiveté of the view that perception and consciousness are means
of grasping physical reality. It ends with a drawing (Figure 4-6) that shows a truer and more complex view of
perception (and, to some extent, of the consciousness behind it). In the center of the drawing are depicted various
stimuli from others and from the physical world impinging on the individual. These stimuli produce effects that can
be classified as mental, emotional, and bodily. The innermost reaction circle represents clearly conscious
experiences. At this moment, as I write, I hear a pneumatic drill being used to break up the pavement outside my
window. I mentally speculate about the air pressure used to operate such an interesting tool but note that it is
distracting me; I emotionally dislike the disturbance of my writing; the muscles of my face and ears tighten a little,
as if that will reduce the impact of the noxious sound on me.
While the three-part classification of effects provides a simplification, in reality the mental, emotional, and
bodily responses to stimuli interact at both conscious and less than conscious levels. My mind notices the tension
around my ear and interprets that as something wrong, which, as a minor emotional threat, aggravates the
noxiousness of the sound, etc.
Immediately behind fully conscious experiences are easily experienceable phenomena, represented by the second
circle. The mental effect of these phenomena relates to the individual's explicit belief system: I believe that noise is
undesirable, but I am fascinated by the workings of machines. Their emotional effect relates to the things he readily
knows he likes or dislikes: loud noises generally bother me and make me feel intruded upon. Their bodily effect
relates to consciously usable skills and movements: I can relax my facial muscles. These phenomena affect the
individual at a level that is not in the focus of consciousness, but that can be easily made conscious by paying
attention.
These two levels are themselves affected and determined by a more implicit level of functioning, implicit in that
the individual cannot identify its content simply by wanting to and paying attention. Where did I get the idea that
noise is an intrusion? Why am I fascinated by the workings of machines? I do not know. I might be able to find out
by prolonged psychological exploration, but the information is not easily available, even though these things affect
me. Why do I have an immediate emotional dislike of noise? Is there some unconscious reaction behind it? How
have I come to maintain certain muscle sets in my face that are affected by stress in certain ways?
The outer circle in Figure 4-6 represents basic learnings, conditionings, motor patterns, instincts, reflexes,
language categories, and the like, which are so implicit the individual can hardly/ recognize their existence. This is
the level of the hardware, the biological givens, and the basic enculturation processes. The distance of these things
from consciousness makes it extremely difficult for him to discover and compensate for their controlling influences:
they are, in many ways, the basis of himself.
If the stimulus in the middle of Figure 4-6 is a cat, this whole complex machine functions, a machine designed by
our culture. We don't "just" see the cat! Our ordinary state of consciousness is a very complex construction indeed,
yet Figure 4-6 hardly goes into details at all. So much for the naturalness of our ordinary state of consciousness.
Figure 4-6
(back)
Footnote
The terms state of consciousness and altered state of consciousness have become very popular. As a consequence of
popularization, however, the terms are frequently used in such a loose fashion as to mean almost nothing in
particular. Many people now use the phrase state of consciousness, for example, to mean simply whatever is one
one's mind. So if I pick up a water tumbler and look at it, I am in "water tumbler state of consciousness," and if I
now touch my typewriter, I am in "typewriter state of consciousness." Then an altered state of consciousness simply
means that what one is thinking about or experiencing now is different from what it was a moment ago.
To rescue the concepts of state of consciousness and altered state of consciousness for more precise scientific
use, I introduce the terms and abbreviation discrete state of consciousness (d-SoC) and discrete state of
consciousness (d-ASC). I discuss in Chapter 2 the basic theoretical concepts for defining these crucial terms. Here,
I first describe certain kinds of experiential data that led to the concepts of
discrete states and then go on to a formal definition of d-SoC and d-ASC.
Mapping Experience
Figures 5-2 and 5-3 express what William James {30, p. 298} meant when he wrote:
Our ordinary waking consciousness... is but one special type of consciousness, whilst all about it, parted from it by
the filmiest of screens, there lie potential forms of consciousness entirely different. We may go through life without
suspecting their existence; but apply the requisite stimulus, and at a touch they are all there in all their
completeness, definite types of mentality which probably somewhere have their field of application and adaptation.
No account of the universe in its totality can be final which leaves these other forms of consciousness quite
disregarded. How to regard them is the question—for they are so discontinuous with ordinary consciousness.
It is important to stress that the pattern differences are the essential defining element of different d-SoCs.
Particular psychological functions may be identical to several d-SoCs, but the overall system functioning is quite
different. People still speak English whether they are in their ordinary waking state, drunk with alcohol, stoned on
marijuana, or dreaming; yet, we would hardly call these states identical because the same language is spoken in all.
We can define a d-SoC for a given individual as a unique configuration or system of psychological structures or
subsystems. The structures vary in the way they process information, or cope, or affect experiences within varying
environments. The structures operative within a d-SoC make up a system where the operation of the parts, the
psychological structures, interact with each other and stabilize each other's functioning by means of feedback
control, so that the system, the d-SoC, maintains its overall pattern of functioning in spite of changes in the
environment. Thus, the individual parts of the system may vary, but the overall, general configuration of the system
remains recognizably the same.
To understand a d-SoC, we must grasp the nature of the parts, the psychological structures/subsystems that
compose it, and we must take into account the gestalt properties that arise from the overall system—properties that
are not an obvious result of the functioning of the parts. For example, the parts of a car laid out singly on a bench
tell me only a little about the nature of the functioning system we call an automobile. Similarly, a list of an
individual's traits and skills may tell me little about the pattern that emerges from their organization into a
personality, into a "normal" state of consciousness. But understand adequately either the car or the individual, I
have to study the whole functioning system itself.[3]
To illustrate this, let us go back to the question I asked at the beginning of Chapter 2 about whether you are
dreaming you are reading this book rather than actually reading it in your ordinary d-SoC. To conclude that what
was happening was real (I hope you concluded that!) you may have looked at the functioning of your component
structures (my reasoning seems sound, sensory qualities are in the usual range, body image seems right) and
decided that since these component structures were operating in the range you associate with your ordinary d-SoC,
that was the condition you were in. Or you may have simply felt the gestalt pattern of your functioning, without
bothering to check component functions, and instantly recognized it as your ordinary pattern. Either way, you
scanned data on the functioning of yourself as a system and categorized the system's mode of functioning as its
ordinary one.
Let me make a few further points about the discreteness of different states consciousness, the quantum gap
between them.
First, the concept of d-SoCs, in its commonsense form, did not come from the kind of precise mapping along
psychological dimensions that is sketched in Figure 5-1. Rather, its immediate experiential basis is usually gestalt
pattern recognition, the feeling that "this condition of my mind feels radically different from some other condition,
rather than just an extension of it." The experiential mapping is a more precise way of saying this.
Second, for most of the d-SoCs we know something about, there has been little or no mapping of the transition
from the baseline state of consciousness (b-SoC) to the altered state. Little has been done, for example, in
examining the process by which a person passes from an ordinary d-SoC into the hypnotic state,[4] although for
most subjects the distinction between the well-developed hypnotic state and their ordinary state is marked.
Similarly, when a person begins to smoke marijuana, there is a period during which he is in an ordinary d-SoC and
smoking marijuana; only later is he clearly stoned, in the d-ASC we call marijuana intoxication. Joseph Fridgen and
I carried out a preliminary survey asking experienced marijuana users about the transition from one state to the
other. We found that users almost never bothered to look at the transition: they were either in a hurry to enter the
intoxicated state or in a social situation that did not encourage them to observe what was going on in their minds.
Similarly, Berke and Hernton {6} reported that the "buzz" that seems to mark this transitional period is easily
overlooked by marijuana users.
So, in general for d-SoCs, we do not know the size and exact nature of the
quantum jump, or indeed, whether it is possible to effect a continuous transition
between two regions of experiential space, thus making them extremes of one
state of consciousness rather than two discrete states. The important factor of
individual differences is discussed in Chapter 9.
Because the science of consciousness is in its infancy, I am forced to mention
too frequently those things we do not know. Let me balance that a little by
describing a study that has mapped the transition between two d-SoCs—ordinary
waking consciousness and stage 2 sleep. Vogel et al {143}, using
electroencephalographic (EEG) indices of the transition from full awakeness
(alpha EEG pattern with occasional rapid eye movement, REMs) to full sleep
(stage 2 EEG, no eye movements), awoke subjects at various points in the transition process, asked for reports of
mental activity just prior to awakening, and asked routine questions about the degree of contact with the
environment the subjects felt they had just before awakening. They classified this experiential data into three ego
states. In the intact ego state, the content of experience was plausible, fitted consensus reality well, and there was
little or no feeling of loss of reality contact. In the destructuralized ego state, content was bizarre and reality contact
was impaired or lost. In the restructuralized ego state, contact with reality was lost but the content was plausible by
consensus reality standards.
Figure 5-4 (reprinted from G. Vogel, D. Foulkes, and H. Trosman, Arch. Gen. Psychiat., 1966, 14, 238-248)
shows the frequency of these three ego states or states of consciousness with respect to psychophysiological
criteria. The psychophysiological criteria are arranged on the horizontal axis in the order in which transition into
sleep ordinarily takes place. You can see that the intact ego state is associated with alpha and REM or alpha and
SEM (slow eye movement), the destructuralized ego state mainly with stage 1 EEG, and the restructuralized ego
state mainly with stage 2 EEG. But there are exceptions in each case. Indeed, a finer analysis of the data shows that
the psychological sequence of intact ego —> destructuralized ego —> restructuralized ego almost always holds in
the experiential reports. It is more solid finding than the association of these ego states with particular physiological
stage. Some subjects start the intact —>destructuralized —> restructuralized sequence earlier in the EEG sequence
than others. This is a timely reminder that the results of equating psychological states with physiological indicators
can be fallacious. But the main thing to note here is the orderliness of the transition sequence from one discrete
state to another. This kind of measurement is crude compared with what we need to know, but it is a good start.
The intact ego state and the restructuralized ego state seem to correspond to bounded regions of experiential
space, d-SoCs, but it is not clear whether the destructuralized ego state represents a d-SoC or merely a period of
unstable transition between the b-SoC of the intact state (ordinary consciousness) and the d-ASC of the
restructuralized state (a sleep state).[5] We need more data about the condition they have labeled destructuralized
before we can decide whether it meets our criteria for a d-SoC. The later discussions of induction of a d-ASC,
transitional phenomena, and the observation of internal states clarify the question we are considering here.
We have now defined a d-SoC for a given individual as a unique configuration of system of psychological
structures or subsystems a configuration that maintains its integrity or identity as a recognizable system in spite of
variations in input from the environment and in spite of various (small) change in the subsystems. The system, the
d-SoC, maintains its identity because various stabilization processes modify subsystem variations so that they do
not destroy the integrity of the system. These stabilization processes are discussed in Chapter 6.
In closing this chapter, I want to add a warning about the finality of the discreteness of any particular d-SoC. In
Chapter 21 stated that the particular nature of the basic structures underlying the human mind limits their possible
interactions and so forms the basis of d-SoCs. Note carefully, however, that many of the structures we deal with in
our consciousness, as constructed in our personal growth, are not ultimate structures but compound ones peculiar to
our culture, personality, and belief system. Later chapters, particularly Chapter 9 on individual differences, clarify
this. Meanwhile I want to emphasize the pragmatic usefulness of a maxim of John Lilly's {35} as a guide to
personal and scientific work in this area: "In the province of the mind, what one believe to be true either is true or
becomes true within certain limits, to be found experientially and experimentally. These limits are beliefs to be
transcended." Lilly's work comparing the mind to a human biocomputer {34}, as well as his autobiographical
accounts of his explorations in consciousness {35}, are essential reading in this area.
Footnotes
[1] Forbidden zone applies under circumstances of a stable personality structure, and should not be taken too
absolutely: personality sometimes changes, and a person sometimes finds himself in an extraordinary situation.
(back)
[2] I want to emphasize the purely descriptive nature of the adjective altered. It means simply "basically
different" or "importantly different," without implying that the d-ASC is better or worse than any other d-SoC. The
first business of science is accurate description. Valuation cannot be avoided, but must not be confused with
description. This is discussed at greater length in Chapter 17. (back)
[3] A practical limitation on our understanding of d-SoCs is that they must have some reasonable stability over
time: we could imagine d-SoCs that would hold a particular pattern for only a second, but this time would be too
short for us to make many useful observations. All the d-SoCs about which we have some knowledge last for
periods ranging from minutes to hours to a lifetime. (back)
[4] Some preliminary psychoanalytic investigations by Gill and Brenman are of interest here {19}. (back)
[5] We should not equate the restructuralized ego state with ordinary nocturnal dreaming, as this state is usually
associated with stage 1 EEG and REMs later during the night. (back)
The basic function of a d-SoC is to cope successfully with an (external) environment. A d-SoC is a tool that senses
and interrupts what the world is and plans and executes strategies for dealing with that changing world. A good tool
should not break easily when applied to the job: the system of structures and energies that constitutes a state of
consciousness should maintain its integrity in coping with the changing world it was designed for. It would be most
unadaptive, for example, if, while you were driving on the freeway, your d-SoC suddenly converted to a d-ASC of
great ecstasy that totally shut down your senses! A d-SoC is a dynamic system: its components change all the time,
but the overall pattern/organization that is its nature is maintained because the possible interactions between the
component structures and subsystems are controlled and limited by various stabilization processes.
This chapter describes four major ways of stabilizing a system that constitutes a d-SoC. They are analogous to
the ways people control one another. If you want someone to be a good citizen (1) you keep him busy with the
activities that constitute being a good citizen, so he has no time or energy for anything else; (2) you reward him for
carrying out these activities; (3) you punish him if he engages in undesirable activities; and (4) you try to limit his
opportunities for engaging in undesirable activities. The following discussion applies to stabilizing a d-SoC as a
whole, but it should also be applied to the stabilization of the individual structures/subsystems within a d-SoC.
Loading Stabilization
The first type of stabilization is ballasting or loading, to use an electrical analogy. In electrical ballasting, you
impose a large electrical load on a circuit that draws on the power resources sufficiently so that very high voltages
cannot occur; the power supply lacks the capacity to produce them, given the load. Loading in general refers to any
activity that draws a large proportion of the energy of the system so that the system does not have excess free
energy available. A load may also store energy, giving the system inertia that prevents a sudden slowdown or
speedup.
Psychologically, loading means keeping a person's consciousness busy with desired types of activities so that too
little (attention/awareness) energy is left over to allow disruption of the system's operation. As Don Juan told Carlos
Castaneda {10}, people's ordinary, repeated, day-to-day activities keep their energies so bound within a certain
pattern that they do not become aware of nonordinary realities.
For example, right now, in your ordinary d-SoC, a number of things act as loading stabilization processes. The
stable physical world you constantly deal with, the dependable relationships in it, give you a pattern of input that
constantly stimulates you in expected patterns, in ways you are used to. If you push your hand against your chair,
the chair feels solid, just as it always has felt. If you push it again, it still feels solid, and so on. You can depend on
the lawfulness of the spectrum of experience we call physical reality. But, if the next time you pushed on the chair,
your hand passed through it, you would be surprised or alarmed. You would begin to suspect that this was not your
ordinary d-SoC or find it difficult to maintain your composure, your ordinary d-SoC.
Your body (and your internalized body image) is another source of stabilization by loading. Every morning when
you wake up you have sensations from one head, two arms, and two legs. Although the exact relationships of the
parts of your body to one another change as do your body's internal feelings, the changes are within a well-learned
range. If you suddenly felt half your body starting to disappear, you would question whether you were in your
ordinary d-SoC.
Body movement also supplies a type of loading. If you move your body, it has a certain feel to it. The kinesthetic
feedback information on the relation of parts of your body and on muscle tensions as you move is within an
anticipated range. If your arm suddenly felt three times as heavy as usual when you lifted it, this again would
disrupt your ordinary d-SoC. Conversely, if you felt sleepy but did not want to enter the d-ASC of sleep, getting up
and moving around would help you stay awake.
A final example of loading concerns the thinking process. You have a constant internal thinking process going on,
constant internal chatter, which runs through familiar and habitual associative pathways and keeps you within your
ordinary d-SoC. You think the kinds of things that please you; you feel clever as a result of thinking them; feeling
clever makes you relax; feeling relaxed makes you feel good; feeling good reminds you that you are clever; and so
on. This constant thinking, thinking, thinking loads your system and is extremely important in maintaining your
ordinary b-SoC.
The importance of this constant loading of consciousness by thinking in maintaining and stabilizing our ordinary
d-SoC cannot be overestimated. A Hindu metaphor for the ordinary d-SoC compares it to a drunken, horny monkey,
carousing madly through the treetops, driven by its desires for sex, food, pleasure. The linkages between thought
processes and emotional processes addict us to clever thoughts and make it hard to slow or stop the thinking
process. Don Juan instructed Castaneda {10} to "not do," cease the constant thinking and doing that maintain
ordinary consciousness, and Castaneda found this extraordinarily difficult to accomplish. This experience has been
shared by innumerable practitioners of meditation who have found how difficult it is to escape from the incessant
chatter of their minds.
The second type of stabilization is negative feedback. Particular structures or subsystems sense when the rate or
quality of operation of other subsystems goes beyond certain preset limits, and they then begin a correction process.
This correction process may be conscious, as for example, anxiety resulting when your thoughts stray into certain
areas you consider taboo. The anxiety then functions to restabilize subsystems within the acceptable range.
You may not be conscious of a particular feedback correction process, however. You may be lost in thought, for
example, and suddenly find yourself very alert and listening, although not knowing why. A sound that indicated a
potentially threatening event may have occurred very briefly, and while not intense enough to be consciously
perceived, it was sufficient to activate a monitoring structure that then sent out correction signals to bring the
system of consciousness back within optimal (for dealing with the threat) limits. This kind of negative feedback
stabilization essentially measures when a subsystem's or structure's operation is going beyond acceptable limits and
initiates an act of correction, reduces the deviation.
The third stabilization process, positive feedback, consists of structures or subsystems that detect when
acceptable activity is going on and then stimulate the emotional reward systems (making us feel good when we do a
particular activity) or otherwise strengthen the desired activity. We may or may not be particularly conscious of
feeling good, but we like to maintain and repeat the rewarded activity. During the formation of our ordinary d-SoC
during childhood, we are greatly rewarded by our parents, peers, and teachers for doing various socially approved
things, and because most of our socially approved actions are initiated by socially approved thoughts and feelings,
we then internalize this reward system and feel good simply by engaging in the thought or actions that were
rewarded earlier.
Let us illustrate how negative and positive feedback stabilization can work. Suppose you are driving home late at
night and are rather sleepy. Driving carefully was an active program in your ordinary d-SoC, but now, because of
fatigue, your mind is drifting toward a hypnagogic state even though you are managing to hold your eyes open.
Hypnagogic thoughts are very interesting and your mind starts pursuing them further. Because the integrity of your
ordinary d-SoC is now beginning to be disrupted, you do not make an appropriate correction as the car begins to
drift over toward the shoulder of the road. You run off the shoulder, narrowly avoiding an accident, and this jars you
back to full wakefulness. Learning occurs; a structure is formed. Sometime later the same circumstances occur
again, but this time the new structure notes two facts—that your thoughts are becoming interesting in that
hypnagogic way and that you are driving. Via the Emotion subsystem, the new structure sends a feeling of anxiety
or alarm through you that immediately activates various subsystems toward the "physical world survival priority"
mode of operating, and so reinstates full consciousness. This is negative feedback stabilization. Then you feel
clever at not succumbing to the hypnogogic state. It shows you are a good driver; all sorts of authorities would
approve: this constitutes positive feedback for keeping your consciousness within the wakefulness pattern.
Thus, a state of consciousness learns that certain processes indicate that part of its system is going beyond a safe
limit of functioning (the error information) and then does something to restore that ordinary range of functioning
(feedback control). You may or may not directly experience the feedback process.
Note that the terms positive feedback and negative feedback, as used here, do not necessarily refer to consciously
experienced good or bad feelings, although such feelings may be experienced and be part of the correction process.
Negative feedback refers to a correction process initiated when a structure or system starts to go or has gone beyond
acceptable limits, and designed to decrease undesirable deviation. Positive feedback refers to an active reward
process that occurs when a structure or subsystem is functioning within acceptable limits and that strengthens
functioning within those limits.
Limiting Stabilization
A fourth way of stabilizing a d-SoC, limiting stabilization, consists of interfering with the ability of some
subsystems or structures to function in a way that might destabilize the ongoing state of consciousness. It limits the
range of possible functioning of certain subsystems.
An example of limiting stabilization is one effect of tranquilizing drugs in blunting emotional responses of any
sort, limiting the ability of certain subsystems to produce strong emotions. Since strong emotions can be important
disrupting forces in destabilizing an ongoing state of consciousness, this limiting stabilizes the ongoing state.
Sufficient limiting of crucial subsystems would not only stabilize any d-SoC (although at some cost in
responsiveness of that d-SoC in coping with the environment), but would prevent transit into a d-ASC that required
changes in the limited subsystems either for inducing the d-ASC or for stabilizing the d-ASC if it were attained.
Loading stabilization can, in some instances, be a limiting stabilization, but the two types of stabilization are not
identical. Limiting directly affects certain structures or subsystems, while the effect of loading is indirect and
operates more by consuming energy than by affecting structures directly.
In a system as multifaceted and complex as a d-SoC, several of each of the four types of stabilization activities
may be going on at any given instant. Further, any particular action may be complex enough to constitute more than
one kind of stabilization simultaneously. For example, suppose I have taken a drug and for some reason decide I do
not want it to affect my consciousness. I begin thinking intensely about personal triumphs in my life. This stabilizes
my ordinary state of consciousness by loading it, absorbing most of my attention/awareness energy into that activity
so that it cannot drift off into thoughts that would help the transition to an altered state. It also acts as positive
feedback, making me feel good, and so increasing my desire to continue this kind of activity.
Many stabilizing processes use psychological energy, energy that could be used for other things. Thus there is a
cost to stabilizing a d-SoC that must be balanced against the gain the results from the focus obtainable from a stable
d-SoC. The question of the optimal degree of stabilization for a given d-SoC when functioning in a given degree of
stabilization for a given d-SoC when functioning in a given environment is important, although it has not been
researched. If there are too few stabilization processes, the d-SoC can be broken down too easily, a circumstance
that could be most unadaptive—when driving for example. If the d-SoC is too stabilized, if too much energy is
being consumed in stabilization processes, then that much less energy is available for other purposes. Some of the
psychological literature on rigidity as a personality variable might provide a good starting point for investigating
optimal stabilization.
A d-SoC, then, is not simply a collection of psychological parts thrown together any old way; it is an integral
system because various stabilization processes control the interaction patterns among the structures and subsystems
so as to maintain the functional identity of the overall system
We have now seen that a d-SoC is a system that is stabilized in multiple ways, so as to maintain its integrity in
the face of changing environmental input and changing actions taken in response to the environment. Suppose that
the coping function of the particular d-SoC is not appropriate for the existing environmental situation, or that the
environment is safe and stable and no particular d-SoC is needed to cope with it, and you want to transit to a d-
ASC: what do you do?
This chapter examines that process of inducing a d-ASC in general from the systems approach, and then
considers its application to three transitions from ordinary consciousness: to sleep, to hypnosis, and to meditative
states.
The staring point is the baseline state of consciousness(b-SoC), usually the ordinary d-SoC. The b-SoC is an
active, stable, overall patterning of psychological functions which, via multiple stabilization relationships (loading,
positive and negative feedback, and limiting) among its constituent parts, maintains it identity in spite of
environmental changes. I emphasize multiple stabilization, for as in any well-engineered complex system, there are
many processes maintaining a state of consciousness: it would be too vulnerable to unadaptive disruption if there
were only a few.
Inducing the transition to a d-ASC is a three-step process, based on two psychological (and/or physiological)
operations. The process is what happens internally; the operations are the particular things you do to yourself, or
someone does to you, to make the induction process happen. In the following pages the steps of the process are
described sequentially and the operations are described sequentially, but note that the same action may function as
both kinds of induction operation simultaneously.
The first induction operation is to disrupt the stabilization of your b-SoC, to interfere with the loading, positive
and negative feedback, and limiting processes/structures that keep your psychological structures operating within
their ordinary range. Several stabilization processes must be disrupted. If, for example, someone were to clap his
hands loudly right now, while you are reading, you would be somewhat startled. Your level of activation would be
increased; you might even jump. I doubt, however, that you would enter a d-ASC. Throwing a totally unexpected
and intense stimulus into your own mind could cause a momentary shift within the pattern of your ordinary d-SoC
but not a transition to a d-ASC. If you were drowsy it might totally disrupt one or two stabilization processes for a
moment, but since multiple stabilization processes are ongoing on, this would not be sufficient to alter your state of
consciousness.[1]
So the first operation in inducing a d-ASC is to disrupt
enough stabilization process to a great enough extent that
the baseline pattern of consciousness cannot maintain its
integrity. If only some of the stabilization processes are
disrupted, the remaining undisrupted ones may be
sufficient to hold the system together; thus, an induction
procedure can be carried out without actually inducing a d-
ASC. Unfortunately, some investigators have equated the
procedure of induction with the presence of a d-ASC, a
methodological fallacy discusses in Chapter 13.
Stabilization processes can be disrupted directly when
they can be identified, or indirectly by pushing some
psychological functions to and beyond their limits of functioning. Particular subsystems, for example, can be
disrupted by overloading them with stimuli, depriving them of stimuli, or giving them anomalous stimuli that
cannot processed in habitual ways. The functioning of a subsystem can be disrupted by withdrawing
attention/awareness energy or other psychological energy from it, a gentle kind of disruption. If the operation of one
subsystem is disrupted, it may alter the operation of a second subsystem via feedback paths, etc.
Drugs can disrupt the functioning of the b-SoC, as can any intense physiological procedure, such as exhaustion
or exercise.
The second induction operation is to apply patterning forces, stimuli that then push disrupted psychological
functioning toward the new pattern of the desired d-ASC. These patterning stimuli may also serve to disrupt the
ordinary functioning of the b-SoC insofar as they are incongruent with the functioning of the b-SoC. Thus the same
stimuli may serve as both disruptive and patterning forces. For example, viewing a diagram that makes little sense
in the baseline state can be a mild disrupting force. But the same diagram, viewed in the altered state, may make
sense or be esthetically pleasing and thus may become a mandala for meditation, a patterning force.
Figure 7-1 sketches the steps of the induction process. The b-SoC is represented as blocks of various shapes and
sizes (representing particular psychological structures) forming a system/construction (the state of consciousness) in
a gravitational field (the environment). At the extreme left, a number of psychological structures are assembled into
a stable construction, the b-SoC. The detached figures below the base of the construction represent psychological
potentials not available in the b-SoC.
Disrupting (and patterning) forces, represented by the arrows, are applied to begin induction. The second figure
from the left depicts this beginning and represents change within the b-SoC. The disruptive (and patterning) forces
are being applied, and while the overall construction remains the same, some the relationships within it have
changed. System change has about reached its limit: at the right and left ends of the construction, for example,
things are close to falling apart. Particular psychological structures/subsystems have varied as far as they can while
still maintaining the overall pattern of the system.[2]
Also shown is the changing relationship of some of the latent potentials outside consciousness, changes we must
postulate from this systems approach and our knowledge of the dynamic unconscious, but about which we have
little empirical data[3] at present.
If the disrupting forces are successful in finally breaking down the organization of the b-SoC, the second step of
the induction process occurs, the construction/state of consciousness comes apart, and a transitional period occurs.
In Figure 7-1 this is depicted as the scattering of parts of the construction, without clear-cut relationships to one
another or perhaps with momentary dissociated relationships as with the small square, the circle, and the hexagon
on the left side of the transition diagram. The disrupting forces are now represented by the light arrow, as they are
not as important now that the disruption has actually occurred; the now more important patterning forces are
represented by the heavy arrows. The patterning stimuli/forces must now push the isolated psychological structures
into a new construction, the third and final step of the processes in which a new, self-stabilized structure, the d-
ASC, forms. Some of the psychological structures/functions present in the b-SoC, such as those represented by the
squares, trapezoids, circles, and small hexagon, may not be available in this new state of consciousness; other
psychological functions not available in the b-SoC have now become available. Some functions available in the b-
SoC may be available at the same or at an altered level of functioning in the d-ASC. There is a change in both the
selection of human potentials used and the manner in which they are constructed into a working system.
Figure 7-1 also indicates that the patterning and disrupting forces may have to continue to be present, perhaps in
attenuated form, in order for this new state to be stable. The d-ASC may not have enough internal stabilization at
first to hold up against internal or environmental change, and artificial props may be needed. For example, a person
may at first have to be hypnotized in a very quiet, supportive environment in order to make the transition into
hypnosis, but after he has been hypnotized a few times, the d-ASC is stable enough so that he can remain
hypnotized under noisy, chaotic conditions.
In following this example you probably thought of going from your ordinary state to some more exotic d-ASC,
but this theoretical sequence applies for transition from any d-SoC to any other d-SoC. Indeed, this is also the
deinduction process, the process of going from a d-ASC back to the b-SoC. Disrupting forces are applied to
destabilize the altered state, and patterning forces to reinstate the baseline state; a transitional period ensues, and the
baseline state re-forms. Since it is generally much easier to get back into our ordinary state, we usually pay little
attention to the deinduction process, although it is just as complex in principle as the induction process.[4]
It may be that some d-SoCs cannot be reached directly from another particular d-SoC; some intermediary d-SoC
has to be traversed. The process is like crossing a stream that is too wide to leap over directly: you have to leap onto
one or more stepping stones in sequence to get to the other side. Each stepping stone is a stable place in itself, but
they are transitional with respect to the beginning and end points of the process. Some of the jhana states of
Buddhist meditation may be of this nature (see Goleman's chapter in Transpersonal Psychologies {128}). This kind
of stable transitional state should not be confused with the inherently unstable transitional periods discussed above,
and we should be careful in our use of the words state and period.
Let us know look at examples of three inductions of d-ASCs, all starting from a b-SoC of the ordinary waking
state—the process of falling asleep, the induction of hypnosis, and the practice of two kinds of meditation toward
the goal of reaching a meditative state. These examples are intended not as final analyses from the systems
approach, but simply as illustrations of how the systems approach to states of consciousness deals with the
induction of d-ASCs.
Going to Sleep
You begin by lying down in a quiet, dimly lit or dark room. the physical act of lying down, closing the eyes,
being in a quiet place, immediately eliminates much of the loading stabilization that helps to maintain your ordinary
d-SoC. Since there are far fewer sensory stimuli coming in from the quiet environment, energy is not required for
dealing with these stimuli, and some this psychological energy is freed. Some of it may, for example, go to
enhancing imagery. Further, incoming stimuli tend to pattern the kind of psychological energies that maintain your
active, waking state; they activate you. Without this stimulation, then, certain kinds of psychological energies are
no longer generated. When these activation energies are generated, they ordinarily circulate through and further
stabilize the waking state by loading it.
Lying down and relaxing eliminate another major source of loading stabilization, the familiar, expected pattern of
input from your body. Almost all your kinesthetic receptors for telling you what your body is doing respond
primarily to change, and when you are relaxed and still for long periods, these receptors stop sending messages into
the central nervous system. Your body, in a neural impulse sense, disappears; it is no longer there to pattern
consciousness.
You adopt an attitude that there is noting to accomplish, no goals to be attained, no problems to solve, nothing
important to deal with. Your attitude is that there is no normative pattern to hold your consciousness.
It is usually futile to try to go to sleep. The active attitude that works so well in doing things within your ordinary
waking d-SoC does not help here. Taking this passive attitude further withdraws attention/awareness energy from
many of your feedback stabilization processes. If there is no norm to hold to, there is no need to monitor for and
correct deviation from the norm. This is important for allowing thought processes and other psychological
processes to drift into the hypnagogic mode.
So far these attitudes (nothing is important) and physical actions (inactions really, lying still and relaxing) are
similar to the start of many other procedures for inducing various d-ASCs. What tips the balance toward inducing
the particular d-SoC of sleep are the physiological factors (not well understood, in spite of two decades of intense
research on sleep) we call tiredness, or need to sleep. These tiredness factors constitute both a further disrupting
forces for the waking state and a patterning force or forces for shaping the transitional period into the sleep state.
Their intensity is important in determining whether the induction is successful: if you are not at all tired, sleep will
probably not occur. If you are very tired, sleep may occur even if the other disrupting operations (lying down,
reducing sensory input, taking a "nothing is important" attitude) have not been carried out.
The study by Vogel and his colleagues of ego states during the transition to sleep, described in Chapter 5, showed
how the experiential mapping of consciousness fell into two (or perhaps three) distinct clusters, two (or perhaps
three) d-SoCs. For a time after lying down, the subjects retained a feeling of contact with the environment and their
thoughts remains plausible by consensus reality standards. This was the intact ego state. The subjects then moved
into the destructuralized ego "state," losing contact with the external environment and with their thoughts deviating
greatly from consensus reality standards of normality. They regained plausibility of thought in the restructuralized
ego state. The destructuralized ego "state" is transitional between the intact ego state and the restructuralized ego
state. Whether it constitutes a d-SoC by our definition is not clear from Vogel's data: we do not know whether there
was a coherent pattern or just constant change.
Inducing Hypnosis
The procedures for inducing hypnosis are many and varied but certain steps are common to most of these
procedures. The first such step usually involves having you sit or lie comfortably, so you do not have to exert any
effort to maintain your bodily position, and telling you not to move and to relax your body as much as possible.
This step has a variety of effects. For one thing, if you are somewhat anxious about what is going to happen, your
anxiety which intimately related to bodily tension, is at least partially relieved if you relax. You limit your ability to
feel anxiety. This makes it easier for you to alter your state of consciousness. Also, when your body is in a relaxed
position and lying still, many of the kinesthetic receptors adapt out, as in going to sleep. Thus the body as a whole
begins to fade out as a conscious experience; this known, patterned stimulation fades and no longer serves as a load
and patterning force to help stabilize your b-SoC.
Second, the hypnotist commonly tells you to listen only to his voice and ignore other thoughts or sensations that
come into your mind. Ordinarily you constantly scan the environment to see if important stimuli are present. This
constant scanning keeps up a continuous, varied pattern of information and energy exchanges among subsystems,
which tends to keep subsystems active in the waking state pattern: as varied perceptions come in, you must decide
whether they are important, you must draw on memories from the past in making these decisions, etc. By
withdrawing attention/awareness energy from this scanning of the environment, you withdraw a good deal of
psychological energy and activity from a number of subsystems: a major loading and patterning process is
attenuated.
A third common instruction is that you should not think about what the hypnotist is saying, but just listen to it
passively. If the hypnotist says your arm is feeling heavy, you are not to think, "He says it's feeling heavy, I wonder
if it really will get heavy, I remember it got heavy a long time ago but that's because there was a weight on it; well, I
guess I shouldn't be doubting..." In the ordinary d-SoC you constantly think about what is being said to you and
what is happening to you, and his maintains a great deal of evaluative and decision-making activity and again
activates other subsystems. Thus, this step also slows down the constant thinking that helps to maintain your
ordinary d-SoC through loading stabilization.
Fourth, you are frequently told to focus your attention on some particular thing in addition to the hypnotist's
voice. Let us take the example of your being asked to look fixedly at some simple object like a candle flame or a
bright, shiny disk. This fixation serves to reduce further your scanning of the environment, with the same effects
mentioned above, but it has an additional effect. It is unusual for you in your ordinary d-SoC to stare fixedly at one
thing. If you do, all sorts of unexpected (to most people) visual effects occur because the retina becomes fatigued.
Colored halos start to appear around the object being stared at, shadows appear and disappear, apparent movements
occur, parts of the object fade. To the extent that these are not part of your usual experience, they constitute a kind
of input that the Input-Processing subsystem (discussed later) is not used to handling, and so they tend to disrupt the
normal functioning of this subsystem.
Further, because the hypnotist earlier stated that he has the power to make you have unusual experiences, the fact
that you are now having unusual experiences enhances the prestige of the hypnotist and gives you more trust in
him. This is a kind of trick: by using physiological effects that you do not realize are the expected result of staring
at anything, the hypnotist manages to take credit and so enhances his psychological effectiveness. The importance
of this will become even clearer later when we discuss the Sense of Identity subsystem.
Fifth, the hypnotist commonly suggests to you that you are feeling sleepy or drowsy. This elicits a variety of
memory associations that help the induction process. Since going to sleep means that your b-SoC breaks down, this
suggestion acts as a disruptive force. And since going to sleep is associated with a fading out of your body image,
this suggestion enhances the fading of the body image that is already occurring because of the adaptation of
kinesthetic receptors to your relaxed, still posture. Further, since going to sleep is a passive activity, the suggestion
encourages a sense of passivity on your part and so reinforces the earlier instructions not to think about what the
hypnotist is saying but simply to accept it. the references to sleep also draw up memories and expectations of your
identity fading, so energy is not required to keep evaluating the situation in terms of your personal values.
Sixth, as well as suggesting sleep, the hypnotist often further indicates that this sleep is not quite the same as real
sleep because you will still hear him. The hypnotist may not need to suggest this overtly: everyone in our culture
knows enough about hypnosis to realize that the subject can still hear the hypnotist. This is a specific patterning
force. The suggestions telling you that what is happening is like sleep primarily serve to disrupt your d-SoC, but
since the hypnotist does not want you actually to go to sleep, he adds a patterning force to produce a passive
sleeplike state in which communication with the hypnotist is still effective.
Seventh, once you appear passive and relaxed, most hypnotic procedures go on to simple motor suggestions,
such as having you hold an arm horizontally out in front of you and telling you it is getting heavy. Motor
suggestions like this are relatively easy most people to experience, and as you begin to respond to these
suggestions, the hypnotist's prestige is further enhanced.
This automatic response to suggestion affects your Sense of Identity subsystem. Ordinarily it is your own "voice"
inside you that tells you to do a thing that you then do. Now the hypnotist's voice takes over this role, and your
sense of self begins to include the hypnotist. The special modulation from this subsystem that constitutes the ego
sense (discussed later) is added to the stimuli that would ordinarily be perceived as the voice of an outsider.
Psychoanalysts call this the transference element of hypnosis, especially when some of the transference involves
parental transferences onto the hypnotist. The deliberate or implicit encouragement of identification with the
hypnotist's voice is an application of patterning forces.
Success with simple motor suggestions also produces a novel kind of body stimulation: you feel your body
moving, but with different qualities than ordinarily. Your arm, for stance, feels exceptionally heavy and seems to
move by itself. This kind of datum again does not fit the habitual input-processing patterns, and so tends both to
disrupt the stabilization of your d-SoC and to help pattern the hypnotic state.
As you respond well to simple motor suggestions, the hypnotist usually goes on to harder and more impressive
motor suggestions and various kinds of cognitive suggestions, and continued success leads to increasing inclusion
of the hypnotist within your ego sense.
Finally, we should note that an important factor in understanding the hypnotic induction technique is the subject's
implicit expectations of what it is like to be hypnotized and how a hypnotized subject behaves. Shor {59} did a
survey showing that among college students there is a fairly good general knowledge of what hypnosis is like, in
spite of some misconceptions. So if a subject agrees to be hypnotized and believes that the hypnotist can do it, he
has implicit expectations that affect his reactions t o the particular thing the hypnotist does.
If the induction is successful and the neutral hypnotic state is developed, the result is a d-ASC characterized by a
quiet mind {78}; most of the structures are inactive, many of the psychological subsystems discussed in Chapter 8
are not actively functioning. Typically, if a deeply hypnotized subject is asked what he is thinking about or
experiencing, the answer is "Nothing." However, this state is also characterized by greatly enhanced suggestibility,
a greater mobility of attention/awareness energy, so when a particular experience is suggested to the subject he
usually experiences it far more vividly than he could in his ordinary d-SoC, often to the point of total experiential
reality. Thus the hypnotic state shows a high flexibility of functioning, even though it is relatively quiet between
particular functionings. The state is also characterized by a quality called rapport, a functioning of the Sense of
Identity subsystem to include the hypnotist as part of the subject's own ego.
It is easy to see how the various techniques mentioned above destabilize the ordinary pattern and operate on
various psychological subsystems to push them toward extreme values of functioning. But where is the actual
transition? We do not know. Studies of hypnosis have generally paid little attention to the transition between
hypnosis and waking. Some psychoanalytically oriented case studies {19} have reported marked transitional
effects, but no study has tried to map the exact nature and extent of the quantum jump.
Much modern research that has tried to determine whether hypnotic suggestibility is indeed greater than waking
suggestibility has committed an important methodological error (discussed in Chapter 9): using group data without
examining individual data. Thus, unless every individual makes the transition at exactly the same point on the
appropriate measure of psychological subsystem functioning, no transition point would appear in the group data.
Put another way, if there were some one variable on which the jump was made from the normal state into hypnosis,
and one subject jumped from a value of two to six to make his transition, and a second subject jumped from three to
seven, and a third from four to eight, etc., the group data would show absolute continuity and no evidence for a
transitional phase. Superimposing many maps destroys the patterns. The systems approach stresses the importance
of examining the transitional period of hypnotic phenomena.
One further idea should be mentioned. Because most or all subsystems in the unprogrammed deep hypnotic state,
so-called neutral hypnosis, are idling or relatively inactive, the hypnotic state may be better than the ordinary
waking state as a b-SoC with which to compare other states. The ordinary waking state seems an incredibly
complex, active, and specialized construction compared with the hypnotic state.
Meditation refers to variety of techniques that may or may not induce a d-ASC at a given time.
Meditation techniques are varied, but Naranjo and Ornstein {39} have classified them into three basic types: (1)
concentrative meditation, (2) opening-up meditation, and (3) expressive meditation. Here we consider the first two
and begin by analyzing a technique common to both before further distinguishing between them.
Most meditation techniques involve, as the initial step, sitting absolutely still in a posture that is not only
comfortable, but that involves keeping the head, neck, and spine in a straight vertical line. A small but significant
amount of muscular effort is needed to maintain this posture. Like the comfortable position assumed for inducing
sleep or hypnosis, the comfortable posture in meditation allows various kinesthetic receptors to adapt out, so the
body image generally fades. In contrast with going to sleep, the fact that a slight amount of muscular effort is
needed to hold the body in this upright position prevents sleep from occurring for most people. Hypnotic induction
procedures can allow the subject to slip in and out of actual sleep, but this is usually quite disruptive in meditative
procedures, as the person begins to fall over.
Since much of a person's sense of identity comes from his body image, the fading of the body in a comfortable,
steady posture also tends to reduce his sense of identity, thus helping to destabilize his b-SoC and to free energy.
Sitting absolutely still, not acting, also frees energy that would otherwise be automatically absorbed in acting:
meditation is a technically simplified situation in this way.
The vertical posture for head, neck, and spine is also of theoretical importance in meditation systems that believe
that a latent human potentiality, the Kundalini force, is stored at the base of the spine and may flow upward,
activating various other postulated latent potentials, the psychic energy centers or chakras, as it rises {128, ch. 6}.
Since the meditator is sitting absolutely still, his muscular subsystem similarly has little to do beyond postural
maintenance. This further reduces loading stabilization. Thus many sources of activity that maintain ordinary d-SoC
fade out when the meditative posture is assumed.
Concentrative Meditation
Concentrative meditation techniques basically instruct you to put all of your attention on some particular thing.
This can be an external object that is looked at fixedly or some internal sensation such as the rise and fall of the
belly in breathing. As in hypnotic induction, the meditater is told that if his mind wanders away from this focus he
is to bring it back gently[5] to this focus, and not allow it to distracted.
This greatly restricts the variety of input to the system, inhibits thinking about various stimuli that come from
scanning the environment, and in general takes attention/awareness energy away from and reduces the activity of
the various subsystems of ordinary consciousness.
The meditater fixes his attention on one thing, usually an external or internal sensation. This can produce
unusually phenomena due to various kinds of receptor fatigue, as in the induction of hypnosis, but most meditation
systems stress that these anomalous perceptual phenomena should not be taken as signs of success or be paid any
special attention. In Zen Buddhism, for example, there is a teaching story of a student excitedly rushing to his roshi
(master) to describe a vision of gods bowing down to him and feelings of ecstasy that occurred during his
meditation. The roshi asks him if he remembered to keep his attention fixed on the rise and fall of his belly in
breathing during the vision, as per the meditation instructions, and when the student says no (who would care about
the rise and fall of your belly during such a vision?), the roshi reprimands the student for allowing himself to
become distracted! Thus while anomalous perceptual phenomena may act as a disruptive forces for our ordinary
state, they do not attract the same amount of attention in meditation as they do in hypnosis and so may have
different effects.[6]
As in any induction technique, the person preparing to meditate has explicit and implicit expectations of what
will come about. His explicit expectations stem from his immediately conscious memories of what he knows about
meditation and his goal in doing it. His implicit expectations range from the implicit but potentially conscious ones
that come from other knowledge about meditation he could recall but is not recalling at the moment, to more
implicit ones that he has absorbed over a longer time and of which he may not be consciously aware. The more
implicit expectations may or may not accord with the teachings of the particular meditative system, for they may
have come through personality-induced distortions of teaching situations in the past. The discussion(in Chapter 4)
of the construction of ordinary consciousness and how it affects our perception of the world is relevant here.
Naranjo and Ornstein {39} describe the meditative state[7] of consciousness that can result from concentrative
meditation as a discrete state characterized as "voidness," "blankness," or "no-thingness." There seems to be a
temporary nonfunctioning of all psychological functions. In some sense, difficult to deal with verbally, awareness
seems to be maintained, but there is not object of awareness. The appearance of this meditative state seems to be
sudden and to clearly represent a quantum leap. The practice of meditation quiets down the various subsystems, but
there is a sudden transition to this pattern of voidness.
The meditative state may or may not be valued in and of itself, depending on the particular spiritual discipline
and its philosophy. What does generally seem to be valued is its aftereffect, generally described as a great
"freshening" of perception or increase in feelings of aliveness. In terms of the systems approach, a major aftereffect
of the concentration-produced meditation state is a decrease in processing and abstracting of sensory input from
what occurs in the ordinary d-SoC. Much more raw sensory data are passed to awareness, instead of the highly
selected abstractions usually seen, and this produces a great intensification of sensory perception of both the
external world and one's own body. this is usually felt as quite joyful. As Wordsworth put it in Ode on Intimations
of Immortality {147}:
There was a time when meadow, grove, and stream,
The earth and every common sight,
To me did seem
Apparelled in celestial light,
The glory and the freshness of a dream.
Going on to contrast this with perception in his ordinary d-SoC, he said:
It is not now as it hath been of yore;—
Turn whereso'er I may,
By night or day,
The things which I have seen I now can see no more.
I suspect that if Wordsworth were alive today he would be quite interested in altered states of consciousness.
This is a good place to remind ourselves that a state of consciousness generally has many processes stabilizing it.
Many of you have had the experience of sitting down and trying to meditate according to some prescription and
finding that rather than reaching some desirable d-ASC you only obtained a sore back! Sitting still in the correct
position and trying to do the technique may indeed disrupt some of the customary feedback processes that stabilize
your b-SoC, but if others are still active, such as continual thinking, no actual shift in state of consciousness will
result.
Confusion results when the word meditation is used to describe many different things. It is probably too late to
prevent sloppy usage, but ideally, the phrase tried to meditate means that the meditater attempted to carry out the
instructions but was not successful at concentrating or holding the posture. The phrase did meditate means the
meditater felt he was relatively successful in following the instructions, event though no meditative state developed.
The phrase reached a meditative state means that the meditater actually did so.
Opening-Up Meditation
Opening-up meditation refers to a variety of techniques whose aim is to help you achieve full sensitivity to and
awareness of whatever happens to you, to be a conscious observer observing what is happening to you without
being caught up in your reactions to it. It is a matter of being aware of what is happening without thinking about
what is happening to the exclusion of perceiving what is happening, or becoming identified with reactions to what
is happening. Vipassana is a Buddhist meditation of this sort. The word means something like bare attention—bare
attention to sensations, feelings, thoughts, and reactions to these things as they occur. The "simple" rule[8] is to
notice anything and everything that happens, to neither reject anything as unworthy of attention, nor welcome
anything as worthy of more attention than anything else. This includes being aware of "failures," such as thoughts,
rather than fighting them.
Opening meditation is usually practiced in the same sort of posture as concentrative meditation, so all the effects
of posture on disrupting the b-SoC are similar.
This non-identification with stimuli prevents attention/awareness energy from being caught up in the automatic,
habitual processes involved in maintaining the ordinary d-SoC. Thus while awareness remains active, various
psychological subsystems tend to drift to lower and lower levels of activity. Traditional accounts indicate that after
a high level of success is achieved, there is a sudden shift into a meditative state of consciousness characterized by
a great freshening of perception and deautomatization of the subsystem of Input-Processing. This is the meditative
state itself, rather than an aftereffect of it, as in concentrative meditation. Almost all psychological energy is present
in the awareness function, and there seems to be far less input-processing, so things are perceived more directly.[9]
The meditater experiences things as much more intense and clear; whether this means that he perceives the external
more accurately has not, to my knowledge, been tested.
Although meditation has been a neglected topic of scientific research, this is changing rapidly: the interested
reader should see the bibliography on research in this area put out by Timmons and Kamiya {141}, as well as the
recent updating of that bibliography by Timmons and Kanellakos {142}.
This concludes our brief survey of the process of inducing a d-ASC. In some ways it is too simplified: the actual
situation in which a person, either by himself or with the help of another, sits down to induce a d-ASC is influenced
by many variables that affect our lives, especially those implicit factors stemming from our personal and cultural
histories that are so hard for us to see.
One final example to illustrate the importance of these implicit and expectational factors. When phonograph
recordings were still something of a novelty, George Estabrooks {16}, one of the early researchers in hypnosis,
decided to see if hypnosis could be induced by simply recording the verbal procedure on a record and playing it to a
group of volunteer subjects. He recorded an induction procedure and got some volunteers from one of the college
classes he taught. At the time for the experiment, he put the record on and, to his consternation, found he has
brought the wrong record from his office: he was playing a record of Swiss yodeling! Deciding to let it entertain his
subjects while he got the right one, he said nothing but left and went to his office.
When he returned, he found one subject was in a deep hypnotic state! The professor had said this record would
hypnotize him, the student went into hypnosis.
Footnotes
[1] This particular example is true for your ordinary d-SoC. But if you had been asleep, you might have been
awakened as a result of the hand clap. It might have been sufficient in a sleep d-SoC to disrupt stabilization enough
to allow a transition back to ordinary waking consciousness. Also, if the expectational context were right, it could
cause a transition from your ordinary d-SoC to a d-ASC. The Abbe de Faria, in the early days of hypnosis,
"hypnotized" ignorant peasants by leading them through dark passages into a dark room, then suddenly setting off a
tray of flash powder while striking a huge gong {38}. This must be one of the most authentic ways of "blowing
one's mind." (back)
[2] There is a depth or intensity dimension within some b-SoCs (discussed in Chapter 14). So we could speak of
the b-SoC having reached its deepest (or shallowest) extreme. (back)
[3] Psychoanalytical studies {19} of hypnotic induction give us inferential information on such activities:
experiential phenomena reported during induction are interpreted as indicators of changes in unconscious forces,
drives, and defenses. (back)
[4] We might hypothesize that because the ordinary d-SoC is so tremendously overlearned compared with almost
any other d-SoC, whenever there is a transitional period the dominant tendency is to repattern the ordinary d-SoC
mode. Sleep would also be likely. Only the presence of special patterning forces allows some d-ASCs to be
structured from a transitional state. (back)
[5] Gently bringing attention back to the concentration focus is important: if you violently bring it back, fight the
distractions, this sends large quantities of attention/awareness to them, and so keeps attention/awareness energy
circulating through the system generally. This stabilizes the ordinary d-SoC, which involves many Rows of
attention/awareness energy to a variety of things. (back)
[6] Another important difference is that in hypnosis induction the hypnotist takes credit for these anomalous
effects, thus helping to incorporate himself into the subject's own psyche We have given little attention to the role of
the hypnotist as "outsider," for he only becomes effective as he becomes able to control the subject's own
attention/awareness energy. The meditator in the Buddhist tradition is seeking to free himself from control by
external events or persons, and so does not value particular phenomena (back)
[7] We speak here of a single state resulting from concentrative meditation because our rudimentary scientific
knowledge goes only this far. But we should remember that spiritual disciplines distinguish many states where we
see one. In Buddhist terms, for example, eight distinct states of samadhi (concentration) are described, each of
which may be a d-SoC (see Chapter 17 and [128]). Whether these are actually useful descriptions of eight d-SoCs
or only descriptions of techniques is a question for the developing science of consciousness to research (back)
[8] "Simple" to say, extremely difficult to do! (back)
[9] We do not know enough at present to adequately describe how the d-ASC reached from opening meditation,
characterized by freshened perception, differs from the feeling of freshened perception occurring within one's
ordinary d-SoC as an aftereffect of concentrative meditation. (back
8. Subsystems
We began this discussion of the systems approach to consciousness by describing the concepts of
attention/awareness, energy, and structure. We defined a structure as a basic unit that can be assembled into larger
structures or be analyzed into substructures. At present, our scientific knowledge is generally too rudimentary to
allow the breakdown of structures into their components. We can, however, describe the assembly of multiple
structures into major experiential and experimental divisions—subsystems—of consciousness. Ten such subsystems
are described in this chapter. They are convenient conceptual tools for understanding the currently known range of
variations in d-ASCs. They do not refer to localized regions of the brain. They are concepts I have developed by
classifying the greatly varying experiences and behaviors reported in d-ASCs into clusters of phenomena that seem
to hold together, on the basis of both their own internal similarity and other known psychological data.
In their present form, I find these subsystems a useful conceptual tool for organizing the otherwise chaotic
masses of data about d-ASCs. I also believe that further thinking can sharpen our ideas about the properties of these
subsystems and their possible interactions with each other and allow us to predict d-ASCs in addition to those
already known. Making these predictions and testing them should further sharpen our conceptions about the nature
of various subsystems, and so further increase our understanding. This is the standard scientific procedure of
conceptualizing the data as well as possible, making predictions on that basis, confirming and disproving various
predictions, and thus sharpening the conceptual system or modifying it. The socialized repetition of this procedure
is the essence of scientific method.
Figure 8-1 sketches ten major subsystems, represented by the labeled ovals, and their major interaction routes.
The solid arrows represent major routes of information flow: not all known routes are shown, as this would clutter
the diagram. The hatched arrows represent major, known feedback control routes whereby one subsystem has some
control over the functioning of another subsystem. The dashed arrows represent information flow routes from the
subconscious subsystem to other subsystems, routes that are inferential from the point of view of the ordinary d-
SoC. Most of the subsystems are shown feeding information into, or deriving information from, awareness, which
is here considered not a subsystem but the basic component of attention/awareness and attention/awareness energy
that flows through various systems.
A brief overview of a state of consciousness as a functioning system, as represented in Figure 8-1, can be
described as follows. Information from the outside world comes to us through the Exteroception subsystem
(classical sense organs), and information from our own bodies comes to us via the Interoception subsystem
(kinesthetic and other bodily functioning receptors). Data from both sets of sense organs undergo Input-Processing
(filtering, selecting, abstracting), which in turn influences the functioning of Exteroception and Interoception.
Input-Processing draws heavily on stored Memory, creates new memories, sends information both directly into
awareness and into our subconscious, and stimulates our Sense of Identity and our Emotions. Information we are
aware of is in turn affected by our Sense of Identity and Emotions. We subject this information to Evaluation and
Decision-Making; and we may act on it, produce some sort of motor output. This Motor Output subsystem produces
action in the body that is sensed via Interoception, in a feedback process through the body. The Motor Output also
produces effects on the external world that are again sensed by Exteroception, constituting feedback via the external
world. Our perception and decision-making are also affected by our Space/Time Sense. Also shown in Figure 8-1
are some latent functions, which may be tapped in a d-ASC, but are not available in the b-SoC.
In the following pages the basic nature of each subsystem is defined and the range of both quantitative and
qualitative alterations that occur in its functioning over the range of various d-ASCs is indicated. Of necessity, these
descriptions are somewhat sketchy. One of the major tasks of future research is to fill in the details about each of
these subsystems, their change in d-ASCs, and their interaction with other subsystems.
Exteroception
The subsystem Exteroception includes the classical sense organs for registering changes in the environment:
eyes, ears, nose, taste organs, and touch organs.
The exteroceptive organs constitute a model of a whole system of consciousness. First, they are active organs.
While all of them can respond to stimulation when they are passive, as when a light is suddenly shined in your eye,
they normally engage in an active scanning of the environment. Your eyes dart about; you turn your head or perk up
your ears to hear sounds more clearly; you reach out to touch things that interest you. Similarly, consciousness can
be passively stimulated, but ordinarily it is an active process.
Second, each of the classical exteroceptive sense organs has limited responsiveness. The eye cannot respond to
ultraviolet light, the ear cannot pick up sounds above or below certain frequencies, touch cannot respond to
exceptionally subtle stimuli. Similarly, consciousness can be passively stimulated, but ordinarily it is an active
process.
Second, each of the classical exteroceptive sense organs has limited responsiveness. The eye cannot respond to
ultraviolet light, the ear cannot pick up sounds above or below certain frequencies, touch cannot respond to
exceptionally subtle stimuli. Similarly, any state of consciousness has certain limits to what it can and cannot react.
Third, you have some voluntary control over the input to your exteroceptive sense organs. If you do not want to
see something, you can look away or close your eyes; if you do not want to hear something, you can move away
from the sound source or put your fingers in your ears. In any state of consciousness, you have some voluntary
control over exteroceptive functioning. But the control is limited: if the sound is intense enough, it is difficult not to
hear it at all, even with your hands over your ears.
Although many changes in perception of the external environment are reported in d-ASCs, these usually do not
represent changes in the exterocepters themselves, except possibly in some drug-induced d-ASCs. Each of the
classical sense organs is a masterpiece of engineering; it is already as sensitive as it can be. Thus its useful
sensitivity is not increased, even if a person experiences himself as being in more contact with the environment in a
d-ASC. AS we shall see later, practically all phenomena dealing with feelings of increased contact with the
environment are related to changes in the Input-Processing subsystem.
Sometimes when a drug is used to induce a d-ASC there may be some physiological changes in the
exterocepters. LSD, for example, may actually cause pupillary dilation, thus allowing in more light (although one
might quarrel whether this is a direct physiological effect or a secondary effect due to the increased attention being
paid to the external environment). Similarly, since psychedelic drugs affect neural functioning generally, they may
have some direct effects on the neural components of the sense organs themselves, but little is known of this now.
So, in terms of present knowledge about d-ASCs, changes in the exterocepters seem of little importance.
Input to the exterocepters is usually deliberately manipulated and patterned in the course of attempting to induce
a d-ASC. Although most of the important changes resulting from these techniques occur in Input-Processing, some
do start with direct effects on the exterocepters and should be noted.
Input from the environment that, while varying, remains within a learned, anticipated range, acts as a source of
loading stabilization. Thus, changing the input to the exteroception may interfere with the loading stabilization
function and/or inject anomalous input that may destabilize a d-SoC.
A major way of doing this is to reduce or eliminate sensory input. In the induction process for many d-ASCs,
there is an attempt to make the environment quiet, to cut down the amount of sensory input a person has to handle.
Consider, for example, the techniques of guided imagery {3} or twilight imagery, where, while lying down with
closed eyes, a person enters more and more into fantasy. A genuine d-ASC may develop in some cases, as fantasy
intensifies, but it is clear the sensory input must usually be kept at a low level to both induce and maintain this d-
ASC. I have seen people get into intense experiences through guided imagery techniques, but the simple act of
opening the eyes and allowing visual input from the physical world to enter immediately disrupts this state.
Reduction of sensory input to a level as near zero as possible is a potent technique for inducing d-ASCs. In the
fifties and early sixties, there were many sensory deprivation experiments during which the subject lay comfortably
in a dark, quiet room without moving. The findings were interpreted as showing that if the brain did not receive
sufficient sensory input, the subject went "crazy." It is now clear {46, 55} that practically all these studies were
severely contaminated, as were the contemporary studies of psychedelic drugs, by implicit demand characteristics
that account for most of the phenomena produced. If you a person through a procedure he thinks will make him
crazy, in a medical setting, he is likely to act crazy. That tells you something about suggestibility, but little about the
effects of reduced sensory input per se. Traditional literature from many spiritual psychologies {128} as well as
accounts from people who have been trapped in isolation situations, indicate that sensory deprivation can be a
powerful technique in affecting consciousness. But its effect is apparently always patterned by other factors.[1]
Changing the patterning of input to the exterocepters, and the subsequent processing of the information of Input-
Processing, can also be a major way of altering consciousness. When the same kind of input is repeated over and
over again, so that the exterocepters become saturated, all sorts of changes take place. For example, if, by means of
special apparatus, an image is held absolutely still on the retina of the eye, it soon begins to break up and display all
sorts of unusual perceptual changes. Even when we believe we are looking steadily at something, there are actually
tiny saccadic movements of the eye that keep the image moving slightly on the retina. Like so many of our
receptors, the eye actually responds to slight, continuous change and cannot "see" absolutely steady input.
Overloading the exterocepters is another way of inducing d-ASCs. The principle is recognized by people who
attend rock concerts. Even if they have not taken some drug to help induce a d-ASC, the light show of complex,
changing patterns accompanied by exceptionally loud music overloads and fatigues the exterocepters, blowing their
minds.
Interoception
The subsystem Interoception includes the various senses that tell us what is going on inside our bodies—the
position of our limbs, the degree of muscle tension, how our limbs are moving, pressure in our intestines, bodily
temperature. It is a way of sensing our internal world, as opposed to our external world. Many of the output signals
from our interoceptors seems to be permanently excluded from our awareness; many of our sensing systems for
governing the function of internal organs seem to have no representation in consciousness, regardless of conditions.
For example, the functioning of our kidneys is regulated, but I know of no one who claims to have a direct
experiential feel for what his kidneys are doing. We should, however, be careful about setting any ultimate limits on
what aspects of Interoception can never reach or be affected by consciousness. The modern technology of
biofeedback enables us to focus attention on and to control many bodily processes formerly thought to be
completely incapable of voluntary control.
Many other interoceptive signals not normally in our awareness can be put in our awareness by turning our
attention/awareness to them. For example, you may not have been thinking of sensations in your belly a moment
ago, but now that I mention them and your attention/awareness turns there, you can detect various signals. With
practice you might become increasingly sensitive to signals from this area of your body. Thus, as with our
exterocepters, we have some voluntary control over what we will attend to, but this control is limited.
We can also control interoceptive input by doing various things to our bodies. If you have an unpleasant
sensation from some part of your body, you can relax, change position, take a deep breath, and change the nature of
that signal, presumably by changing whatever is causing it. This is an ability we take for granted and know little
about, but it is an important way of affecting interoceptive input. Some techniques for inducing d-ASCs, such as
hatha yoga procedures, have a highly sophisticated technology for affecting one's body and how one perceives it.
This is the reason biofeedback technology is sometimes said to have the potential to become an "electronic yoga," a
way of rapidly learning about various internal conditions and using them to affect consciousness. We are still a long
way from attaining this, however.
As is the case with exterocepters, there is little evidence that actual physiological changes take place in the
interoceptors during various d-ASCs, except possibly in some drug-induced d-ASCs. Also as in Exteroception, the
learned, anticipated range of constant input from Interoception acts as a source of loading stabilization for
maintaining the ordinary d-SoC.
The pattern of input from interoceptors can be subsumed under a useful psychological concept, the body image.
You not only have a real body whose actual sensations are picked up by the interoceptors, but, in the course of
enculturation, you have learned to perceive your own body in learned, patterned ways, just as you have learned to
perceive the external world in socially learned ways. The degree to which your body image corresponds to your
actual body may vary considerably. My own observations suggest that people's internal images of their bodies can
differ amazingly from what an external observer sees.
An individual's body image may be very stable. An intriguing example of this is the phantom limb phenomenon.
When an arm or a leg is amputated, the patient almost always reports he can still feel the limb, even though he can
see and otherwise intellectually know it is not there. Sensations coming in from the severed nerve tracts are
nonconsciously organized in the learned, habitual way so that the patient perceives the limb as still there. Most
patients soon lose perception of their phantom limbs as they are subjected to considerable social pressure to do so.
In some, however, the phantom limb persists in spite of all attempts to unlearn it. The sensations may or may not be
painful.
The primary things to note are that the body image can be very rigid and may or may not show much
correspondence to the actual body contours and what actually goes on in the body. I am convinced that as
Westerners we generally have distorted images of our bodies and poor contact with sensations that go on in them.
Since body sensations often represent a thinking about, or data processing of, experience, and a way of expressing
emotions, our lack of contact with our actual body sensations puts us out of contact with ourselves. This is
considered further in connection with the Subconscious subsystem.
People's experiential reports from d-ASCs indicate that enormous changes can take place in Interoception. The
body may seem to get larger or smaller, change in shape, change in internal functioning, change in terms of the
relationships of its parts, so that the body may not "work" in the usual fashion. Most of this range of experience
probably represents changes in Input-Processing, rather than changes in the interoceptors themselves.
As with Exteroception, changing your body image is a common technique for inducing d-ASCs. Reducing
interoceptive input, overloading it, or patterning it in novel ways have all been used. The primary effects are on
Input-Processing, but the techniques start by affecting the interoceptors themselves. Let us look at some of these
techniques briefly.
Immobilizing the body in a relaxed position is a major way of causing the output from Interoception to fade and,
consequently, causing the body image either to fade or to change, since it is no longer stabilized by actual input
from the interoceptors. The discussion of the induction of hypnosis, going to sleep, and meditation in Chpater7
mentions the importance of allowing the interoceptors to adapt out so the input from the body disappears. In
sensory deprivation techniques it is important to relax the body and at the same time not move at all. Even a slight
movement can stimulate large numbers of interceptors and reestablish the body image readily.
Overloading interoceptors is an important technique for altering consciousness. A good massage, for instance, or
sensory awareness exercises that make you aware of bodily stimuli normally overlooked, have been known to
induce d-ASCs. At the opposite end of the continuum from this pleasurable kind of manipulation of Interoception,
pain and torture are some of the surest ways of inducing d-ASCs.
Patterning interoceptive input in unusual fashions is another way of inducing d-ASCs. Mudras, gestures of
symbolic significance used in yoga, consist of putting the body into certain positions. I suspect that the actual
bodily posture has a definite patterning effect on interoceptive input and can affect consciousness if you are
sensitive to input from your own body, the patterning of interoceptive input may occur, but since not much
awareness is gained, posture does not pattern attention/awareness energy in a way that would affect consciousness.
Another way of patterning interoceptive input is the altered states of consciousness induction device (ASCID)
developed by Masters and Houston {37} on the basis of medieval accounts of the witch's cradle. This is an upright
frame into which a person straps himself. the frame is hung from a short rope, so slight motions cause it to rock in
erratic patterns. This produces anomalous patterns of input for the occupant to process: some interoceptors tell him
he is standing up and therefore needs to exert certain muscular actions to maintain this posture, but other
interoceptors tell him he is standing up and therefore needs to exert certain muscular actions to maintain this
posture, but other interoceptors tell him he is relaxed and not making these muscular actions. Other interoceptive
sense indicate that he is moving and must do things to maintain his balance, but there are in conflict with other
interoceptive sensations that he is passive. Since he is not used to such an anomalous, conflicting pattern of
stimulation, it can greatly disrupt Input Processing.
Input Processing
Before reaching awareness, all input data, whether interoceptive or exteroceptive, normally goes through various
degrees of processing. The Input-Processing subsystem consists of a complex, interlocking series of totally
automatic processes that compares incoming data against previously learned material stored in memory, rejects
much of the data as irrelevant, selects some of them as important enough to deserve further processing, transforms
and abstracts these important data, and passes this abstraction along to awareness. Thus, a major function of Input-
Processing is rejection. At any given instant, you are generally bombarded by an enormous quantity of sensory data
of all sorts. Most of the data is not important in terms of defined needs, such as your biological survival. Since your
ability to handle information and awareness is limited, you would be overwhelmed if all this mass of incoming data
came through. Instead, you receive a small abstraction of incoming information that is important by personal and
consensus reality standards.
Input-Processing is totally automatic. Look at this thing that is in your hands with the question, "What is it?" in
your mind. Immediately you see a book. You did not have the experience of seeing a whitish rectangular object with
dark spots on it. You did not further experience these spots as being arranged in lines, and the individual spots as
having distinctive characteristics, which you then, by painstaking examination, arranged into words and sentences,
and so concluded that this was a book in your hands. No, the recognition of this thing as a book was instantaneous
and automatic. To demonstrate how automatic the processing is, look at the book again and try to see it as simply a
collection of incoming, assorted stimuli instead of as a book.
Unless you have some unusual abilities, you find it very difficult to see this object as anything but a book.
Numerous psychological studies have focused on the way perception is automated. Many of these studies have
mistakenly assumed they were studying the "accuracy" of perception. What they were usually studying was the
agreement with consensus reality standards for perceiving things. An immediate, automatic perception of socially
defined reality is taken as being "realistic" and as a sign of a "good-observer."
Thus, Input-Processing is a learned behavior, probably the most complex a human being has to acquire. Think of
the number of connections among stimuli and the number of responses associated with the various stimuli that an
infant must learn before he can be said to "think." the task is staggering. The infant must learn to perceive instantly
and automatically all major features of consensus reality as his parents, peers, and teachers do. This means that an
immense amount of information must be stored in memory (it does not matter whether it is stored in the Memory
subsystem or in a special Input-Processing memory) and be almost instantly available to Input-Processing. Total
automation of the process is equated with efficiency: if I have to struggle to identify an object, I feel stupid; but if I
recognize it right away, I feel competent and smart.
In relation to enculturation process, we discussed the fact that a child has more options for his consciousness than
a teenager or an adult. This is another way of saying that the automatization of Input-Processing and its efficiency
become comprehensive with increasing age, until by the time we are adults almost everything in our world is
instantly recognized and dealt with "appropriately." An adult sees things almost exclusively in a culturally approved
way and makes culturally approved responses. Rigidity increases with age: that is what Timothy Leary meant when
he said, "Don't trust anyone over thirty." The statement is overgeneralized, but it does contain an important
psychological truth: older people are liable to be less able to see things differently from the way they have always
been accustomed to seeing them.
Numerous psychological studies show variation in Input-Processing that are related to differences within
consensus reality. An early study of perception, for example, showed that poor children tend to perceive coins as
physically larger than rich children do. People with strong religious values tend to pick up words and other stimuli
relating to religion more readily than they do those relating to economics, and vice versa. People with neuroses or
psychoses tend to be especially sensitive to certain stimuli that trigger their neurotic structures and to distort
perception in ways that fit these neurotic structures. Projective tests, in which the subject is shown a relatively
ambiguous stimulus like an ink blot and asked to describe what he sees, are a way of investigating the underlying
structures of Input-Processing. If he repeatedly sees a murdered baby in several different blots, we might begin to
wonder about the way he has dealt with aggression in his life or about his feelings toward his parents.
In terms of the basic concepts of attention/awareness, psychological energy, and structure, Input-Processing
represents a large number of structures, each specialized in responding to certain kinds of stimulus patterns. It has a
certain amount of psychological energy always available, so that this active set of structures almost always stands
between you and your sense. Input-Processing is automatized in the sense that the structures always draw energy of
some sort when activated and process information in a relatively fixed way before passing this information on to
awareness.
The ubiquity of Input-Processing is a main reason I have elsewhere distinguished consciousness from awareness.
Some kind of "pure" awareness may be a basic from which we start, but ordinarily we experience consciousness,
awareness as it is vastly modified by the machinery of the mind. Here Input-Processing in effects places a number
of structures between us and our sensory input, and even our sensory input comes through the Exteroception and
Interoception subsystems, which are themselves structures with characteristics of their own. Other subsystems are
also structures that modify or pattern basic awareness into consciousness. The systems diagram presented as Figure
8-1 shows awareness in a distinct place, but it really spreads through the various subsystems and so becomes
consciousness.
The main function of Input-Processing, then, is abstraction. This subsystem is rather like a vast organization that
keeps track of an industry's progress and problems and, through hierarchical chains, passes on only the most
abstracted reports to the president of the company.
Input-Processing also generalizes, gives a familiar abstracted output to unfamiliar situations that are reasonably
close to particular perceptions that have been learned. Thus you recognize this object as a book even though you
have never seen this particular book before: it is similar enough to other books to have label automatically applied
to it. This kind of generalization may be greatly affected by dominated needs and emotions: all apples look alike to
a hungry man.
Various aspects of Input-Processing can show extremely large changes in various d-ASCs. There are large
quantitative changes, that is, the range of continuous changes in various aspects of Input-Processing may be greater
or less than in your ordinary d-SoC. Your ability to focus attention on particular percepts, for example, may be
quantitatively greater or quantitatively less in various d-ASCs.
There are also many important qualitative changes that may be experienced as entirely new modes of perception.
Some of these may be the activation of latent human potentials. Patterns may be seen in ordinarily ambiguous data,
making it obviously meaningful. An important effect of marijuana intoxication, for example, is the ability to look at
normally ambiguous material, such as the grain pattern in a sheet of wood, and see it as an actual picture. New
shades of color are reported in various d-ASCs, new qualities to sound. We shall reserve judgment for the moment
on whether these are veridical with respect to the actual stimulating objects.
Apparently fixed properties of perceptual organization may change in various d-ASCs as Input-Processing
changes. Carlos Castaneda {9} for example, describes how Don Juan taught him how to turn into a crow while he
was intoxicated with a hallucinogenic plant: an outstanding aspect of this experience was that his visual field from
each eye became split, so that he had two quite different fields, just as if his eyes were on separate sides of his head,
instead of the usual overlapping, integrated field.
Illusions and hallucinations, frequently reported in d-ASCs, represent important changes in Input-Processing. The
conventional definition of illusion is a misinterpretation of a stimulus that is actually there, as, for example, when
on entering a dimly lit room you mistake a coat hanging on a rack for a person. Hallucination is conventionally
defined as a vision of something that is not there at all, as, for example, when on entering the same dimly lit room
you see a person, even though the room is empty. While it is easy to distinguish these two extremes, there is
obviously a continuum between them: there is always a certain amount of random neural firing in your retina, a
"something" there.
In a more general sense, we must realize that "misperception" and "what is and is not there" are usually defined
in terms of consensus reality. We may hope that our consensus reality has a high degree of accuracy with respect to
physical reality, but to assume automatically that it does is to be very parochial. If one person hears a given piece of
music as exceptionally beautiful in its melody, and another hears it as quite common, was the first person suffering
an illusion, or was he really more perceptive? We must be particularly careful in dealing with phenomena from d-
ASCs that our consensus reality automatically defines as hallucinatory. Should we have so much faith in the
conceptual schemes evolved in our ordinary d-SoC that we automatically dismiss anything that does not fit with
them? It is bad science to continue to do so.
An illusion, then, is Input-Processing's interpretation of a stimulus in a way that does not match consensus reality
standards. Whether the interpretation added by the illusion is a richer and more accurate perception of a stimulus
pattern, or a more distorted and less accurate one, varies with individual cases. In terms of d-ASCs we know about,
my general impression is that they possess the property of making our perception more accurate in some ways and
less accurate in others.
A hallucination is a functioning of Input-Processing whereby stored information is drawn from Memory, worked
over by Input-Processing, and passed along to awareness as if it were sensory data. The special label or quality that
identifies the source of this vivid image as memory is missing; the quality that identifies it as a sensory stimulus is
present. Depending on the type of d-ASC, a hallucination may completely dominate perception, totally wiping out
all sensory input coming through Input-Processing, or may be mixed with processed sensory data. The intensity of
the hallucination may be as great as that of ordinary sensory information, even greater, or less.
An interesting dimension of variability of Input-Processing in d-ASCs is the degree to which it can be voluntarily
altered. The degree of control may be high or low. I recall participating in some experiments on the effect of
psilocybin, a psychedelic like LSD, when I was a graduate student. While intoxicated by the drug, I had to sort
through a batch of file cards, each of which contained a statement of various possible symptoms. If I was
experiencing the symptom, I was to put the card in the "true" pile, if I was not, in the "false" pile. I quickly found
that I could make almost every statement true if I so desired, simply by reading it several times. I would pick up a
statement like "My palms are sweating green sweat," think that would be an interesting experience, reread the
statement several times, and then look at my hands and see that, sure enough, they were sweating green sweat! I
could read a statement like "The top of my head is soft" several times and feel the top of my head become soft!
Thus, while intoxicated with psilocybin my degree of voluntary control over Input-Processing became very large,
sufficiently to create both illusions and hallucinations by merely focusing attention/awareness energy on the desired
outcome.
Another type of variation that can occur in Input-Processing in d-ASCs is the partial or total blocking of input
from exterocepters or interoceptors. The d-ASC of deep hypnosis is an example. One can suggest to a talented,
deeply hypnotized subject that he is blind, that he cannot feel pain, that he cannot hear, and experientially this will
be so. The subject will not respond to a light or to objects shown him, and both during the d-ASC and afterward in
his ordinary d-SoC, will swear that he perceived nothing. His eyes are still obviously functioning, and evoked brain
responses recorded from the scalp show that input is traveling over the sensory nerves from his eye to his brain, but
at the stage of Input-Processing the input is cut off so it does not reach awareness. Similarly, analgesia to pain may
be induced in hypnosis and other d-ASCs.
When input is completely blocked in Input-Processing there may or may not be a substitution of other input.
Thus information may be drawn from memory to substitute a hallucination for the actual blocked information. If,
for example, a deeply hypnotized subject is told that he cannot see a particular person who is in the room, he may
not simply experience a blank when looking at that person (which sometimes happens), he may actually hallucinate
that details of the room behind the person and thus see no anomalous area in his visual field at all.
Another important change in d-ASCs is that, experientially, there may seem to be less Input-Processing, less
abstracting, so a person feels more in touch with the raw, unprocessed input from his environment. This is
especially striking with the psychedelics and is also reported as an aftereffect of concentrative meditation and as a
direct effect of opening-up meditation. I know of no experimental studies that have thoroughly investigated whether
one can actually be more aware of raw sensory data, but this is certainly a strong experiential feeling. It is not
necessarily true, however. Vivid illusions can be mistaken for raw sensory data or (probably what happens) there
can be a mixture of greater perception of raw data and more illusion substituted. Whether there is any particular d-
ASC in which the balance is generally toward better perception through less abstracting is unknown at present.
Psychedelic-drug-induced conditions are particularly noteworthy for the experience of feeling in contact with the
raw data of perception, and this makes perceptions exceptionally beautiful, vibrant, and alive. By contrast, usual
perception in the ordinary d-SoC, seems lifeless, abstract, with all the beauty of reality removed to satisfy various
needs and blend in with consensus reality.
Also reported in d-ASCs is an experience of feeling more in touch with the actual machinery of Input-Processing,
gaining some insight or direct experience of how the abstracting processes work. For example, I was once watching
a snowfall through a window at night, with a brilliant white spotlight on the roof illuminating the falling snow. I
was in an unusually quiet state of mind (it was too brief for me to decide whether it was a d-ASC), and suddenly I
noticed that instead of simply watching white snow fall (my usual experience), I was seeing each snowflake glinting
and changing with all colors of the spectrum. I felt strongly that an automated Input-Processing activity that makes
snow white had temporarily broken down. Afterward, it struck me that this was likely, for white is actually all the
colors of the spectrum combined by Exteroception (eyes) and Input-Processing to the sensation of white. Thus a
snowflake actually reflects all the colors of the spectrum, and active "doing" (to use Don Juan's term) on the
viewer's part is required to turn it into white. There is no light energy of "white" in the physicist's world. Similarly,
persons have reported gaining insights into how various automatic processes organize their perception by being able
to see the lack of organization of it or by seeing the alternative organizations that occur.
Synesthesia is another radical change in Input-Processing that sometimes takes place in some d-ASCs.
Stimulation of one sense is perceived in awareness as though a different sense had been stimulated at the same time.
For example, hearing music is accompanied by seeing colored forms. This is the most common and perhaps the
most beautiful form of synesthesia, and is sometimes reported with marijuana intoxication.
All techniques for inducing d-ASCs, except drug or physiological effects that act directly on various bodily
functions, must work through Input-Processing. That subsystem mediates all communication. Yet it is useful to
distinguish between induction techniques that are primarily designed to disrupt stabilization of the b-SoC in some
other subsystem without significantly affecting Input-Processing per se, and those that are designed to disrupt
Input-processing directly as a way of destabilizing the b-SoC.
In this latter class is a wide variety of techniques designed to give a person input that is uncanny in terms of the
familiar ways of processing input in the b-SoC. The input is uncanny, anomalous in a sense of seeming familiar yet
being dissimilar enough in various way to engender a pronounced feeling of nonfitting. Often the events are
associated with an emotional charge or a feeling of significance that makes that fact that they do not fit even more
important. Don Juan, for example, in training Carlos Castaneda to attain various d-ASCs would often frighten
Castaneda or destabilize his ordinary state to an extraordinary degree by doing something that seemed almost, but
not quite, familiar, such as simply acting normally but with subtle differences at various points.
The use of uncanny stimuli is not limited to inducing a d-ASC from an ordinary d-SoC.; it can work in reverse.
When a person talks about "being brought down" from a valued d-ASC, he means he is presented with stimulation
patterns that Input-Processing cannot handle in that d-ASC, so the d-ASC is destabilized, and he returns to his
ordinary d-SoC.
Memory
The Memory subsystem is concerned with information storage, with containing residues of past experiences that
are drawn upon in the present. Memory is thus a large number of semipermanent changes caused by past
experience. We can think of memory as structures, presumably in the brain (but perhaps also in the body structure),
which, when activated, produce certain kinds of information. And we should not assume that there is just one
Memory; there is probably a special kind of memory for almost every subsystem.
Conventional psychological views of Memory also often divide memory functioning into short-term or
immediate memory, medium-term memory, and long-term memory. Short-term memory is the special memory
process that holds information about sensory input and internal processes for a few seconds at the most. Unless it is
transferred to a longer-term memory, this information is apparently lost. Thus, as you look at a crowd, searching for
a friend's face for a short time, you may remember a lot of details about the crowd. Then you find your friend's face,
and the details about the crowd are lost. There is no point in storing them forever. This short-term memory is
probably an electrical activity within the brain structure that dies out after a few seconds: no long-term structural
changes occur. Once the electrical activity dies out, the information stored in the pattern or in the electrical activity
is gone forever.
Medium-term memory is storage of from minutes to a day or so. It probably involves partial structural changes as
well as patterns of energy circulation. You can probably recall what you had for breakfast yesterday morning, but in
a few days you will not remember the contents of that meal.
Long-term memory involves semipermanent structural changes that allow you to recall things experienced and
learned a long time ago.
This division into short-, medium-, and long-term memory is of interest because these kinds of memories may be
differentially affected during d-ASCs. At high levels of marijuana intoxication, for example, short-term memory is
clearly affected {105}, although long-term memory may not be. Thus, a marijuana user often reports forgetting the
beginning of a conversation he is engaged in, but he continues to speak English. There is little more we can say
about differential effects of various d-ASCs on these three kinds of memory, as they have not yet been adequately
studied. They offer a fruitful field for research.
A most important aspect of Memory subsystem functioning in various d-ASCs is the phenomenon of state-
specific memory. In a number of studies, subjects learned various materials while in d-ASCs, usually drug-induced,
and were tested for retention of these materials in a subsequent ordinary d-SoC. Generally, retention was poor. The
researchers concluded that things were not stored well in Memory in various d-ASCs. it is now clear that these
studies must be reevaluated. Memory is specific. The way in which information is stored, or the kind of Memory it
is stored in, is specific to the d-SoC the material was learned in. The material may be stored, but may not transfer to
another state. If material is learned in a d-ASC and its retention tested in another d-SoC and found to be poor, the
nonretention may indicate either an actual lack of storage of the information or a state-specific memory and lack of
transfer. The proper way to test is to reinduce the d-ASC in which the material was learned and see how much
material is retained in that state. State-specific memory has been repeatedly demonstrated in animals, although the
criterion for the existence of a "state" in such studies is simply that the animals were drugged to a known degree, a
criterion not very useful with humans, as explained later.
There is now experimental evidence that for high levels of alcohol intoxication there is definite state-specific
memory in humans {21}. It is an experimental demonstration of the old folk idea that if you lose something while
very drunk and cannot find it the next day, you may be able to find it if you get very drunk again and then search.
Experiential data collected in my study of marijuana users {105} also indicate the existence of state-specific
memory, and I have recently received verbal reports that laboratory studies are finding state-specific memory for
marijuana intoxication. There also seems to be state-specific memory for the conditions induced by major
psychedelic drugs.
State-specific memory can be readily constructed for hypnosis that is, state-specific memory may not occur
naturally for hypnosis, but it can be made to occur. If you tell a hypnotized subject he will remember everything
that happened in hypnosis when he comes back to his ordinary state such will be his experience. On the other hand,
if you tell a deeply hypnotized subject he will remember nothing of what went on during hypnosis or that he will
remember certain aspects of the experience but not others, this will also be the case when he returns to his ordinary
state. In any event he will recall the experiences the next time he is hypnotized. This is not a pure case of state-
specific memory, however, because amnesia for hypnotic experiences in the waking state can be eliminated by a
prearranged cue as well as by reinducing the hypnosis.
Another excellent example of state-specific memory is that occurring in spiritualist mediums. A medium enters a
d-ASC in which his ordinary consciousness and sense of identity appear to blank out for a time. He may report
wandering in what may be loosely called a dreaming state. Meanwhile, an alleged spirit entity ostensibly possesses
him and acts as if it has full consciousness. Upon returning to a normal state, the medium usually has total amnesia
regarding the events of the d-ASC. The alleged spirit communicator, however, usually shows perfect continuity of
memory from state to state.[2]
I suspect that state-specific Memory subsystems will be discovered for many or most d-ASCs, but the necessary
research has not been done. The kinds of state-specific memories may vary in completeness. The ones we know of
now—from marijuana intoxication, for example—are characterized by transfer of some information to the ordinary
d-SoC but nontransfer of other information, the latter often being the most essential and important aspects of the d-
ASC experience.
Ordinarily, when we think of Memory we think of information becoming accessible to awareness, becoming part
of consciousness, but we should note that we "remember" many things even though we have no awareness of them.
Your current behavior is affected by a multitude of things you have learned in the past but which you are not aware
of as memories. You walk across the room and your motion is determined by a variety of memories, even though
you do not think of them as memories.
Note also that you can remember things you were not initially aware of. When you scan a crowd looking for a
friend's face, you may be consciously aware of hardly any details of other faces, being sensitive only to your
friend's. A minute later, when asked to recall something about the crowd, however, you may be able to recall a lot of
information about it. For this reason, Figure 8-1 shows a direct information flow arrow from Input-Processing to
Memory. We store in Memory not only things that have been in awareness, but also things that were never much in
awareness to begin with.
An interesting quality of information retrieved from Memory is that we generally know, at least implicitly, that
we are retrieving memories. We do not confuse these with sensations or thoughts. Some kind of operating signal or
extra informational quality seems to be attached to the memory information itself that says "This is a memory."
There is an intriguing analogy for this. In the early days of radio, when a newscast tuned you in to a foreign
correspondent, there was an obvious change in the quality of the audio signal, a change that you associated with a
foreign correspondent broadcasting over a long distance on short wave. The sound was tinny, the volume faded in
and out, there were hisses and crackles. This was a noninformational extra that became so associated in listeners'
minds with hearing a real foreign correspondent that many radio stations resorted to the trick of deliberately adding
this kind of distortion years later when communication technology had improved so much that the foreign
correspondent's voice sounded as if he was actually in the studio. The added distortions made the listeners feel they
were indeed hearing a faraway reporter and made the broadcast seem more genuine. Similarly, memory information
is usually accompanied by a quality that identifies it as memory. The quality may be implicit: if you are searching
actively for various things in your Memory, you need not remind yourself that you are looking at memories.
This extra informational quality of memory can sometimes be detached from memory operation per se. It is
possible to have a fantasy, for example, with the "this is a memory" quality attached, in which you mistakenly
believe you are remembering something instead of just fantasizing it. Or, the quality may be attached in a d-ASC to
an incoming sensory perception, triggering the experience of déjà vu, the feeling that you have seen this before.
Thus you may be touring in a city you have never visited and it all looks very familiar; you are convinced you
remember what it is like because of the presence of the "this is a memory" quality.[3]
When information is actually drawn from Memory without the quality "this is a memory" attached, interesting
things can happen in various d-ASCs. Hallucinations, for example, are information drawn from memory without the
memory quality attached, but with the quality "This is a perception" attached.
Much of the functioning of the Sense of Identity subsystem (discussed later) occurs via the Memory subsystem.
You sense of who you are is closely related to the possession of certain memories. If the "this is a memory" quality
is eliminated from those memories so that they become just data, you sense of identity can be strongly affected.
Other variations of Memory subsystem functioning occur in various d-ASCs. The ease with which desired
information can be retrieved from memory varies so that in some d-ASCs it seems hard to remember what you
want, in others it seems easier than usual. The richness of the information retrieved varies in different d-ASCs, so
that sometimes you remember only sketchily, and at other times in great detail. The search pattern for retrieving
memories also varies. If you have to go through a fairly complex research procedure to find a particular memory,
you may end up with the wrong memories or associated memories rather than what you were looking for. If you
want to remember an old friend's name, for example, you may fail to recall the name but remember his birthday.
Finally, we should note that a great many things are stored in Memory but not available in the ordinary d-SoC.
The emotional charge connected with those memories makes them unacceptable in the ordinary d-SoC, and so
defense mechanisms repress or distort our recall of such
information. In various d-ASCs the nature of the defense
mechanisms may change or their intensity of functioning may
alter, allowing the memories to become more or less available.
Subconscious
The Evaluation Decision-Making subsystem refers to those intellectual, cognitive processes with which we
deliberately evaluate the meaning of things and decide what to do about them.[4] It is the subsystem constituting
our thinking, our problem-solving, our understanding. It is where we apply a logic to data presented to us and reach
a conclusion as a result of processing the data in accordance with that logic.
Note that a logic is a self-contained, arbitrary system. Two and two do not make four in any "real" sense; they
make four because they have been defined that way. That a particular logic is highly useful in dealing with the
physical world should not blind us to the fact that it is basically an arbitrary, self-contained, assumptive system.
Thus, when I define the Evaluation and Decision-Making subsystem as processing information in accordance with a
logic, I do not intend to give it an ultimate validity, but just to note that there is an assumptive system, heavily
influenced by culture and personal history, which processes data. In our ordinary d-SoC there may actually be
several different logics applied at various times. I might apply the logic of calculus to certain kinds of problems in
electronics, but not to problems of interpersonal relationships.
We should also note, as honest self-observation will reveal, that much of what passes as rationality in our
ordinary d-SoC is in fact rationalization. We want something, so we make up "good" reasons for having it.
The discussion that follows is confined to intellectual, conscious evaluation and decision-making. Some aspects
of this become automated and go on in the fringes of awareness, but they are potentially available to full
consciousness should we turn our attention to them. Other subsystems, such as Emotions and the Subconscious,
also evaluate data, classify them as good or bad, threatening or benign, etc. We are not concerned with these here,
however; we shall consider only conscious, intellectual kinds of decision-making and evaluation.
Figure 8-3 illustrates the typical operation of the Evaluation and Decision-Making subsystem for the ordinary d-
SoC. The process starts (lower left-hand corner) when you encounter some kind of problem situation in life. The
stimuli from this situation, coming in via the Exteroception subsystem, are subjected to a large amount of Input-
Processing, and some abstraction of the situation reaches your awareness. Assume this initial abstraction is
puzzling: it doesn't make sense to you and you don't know what to do. So the Evaluation and Decision-Making
subsystem draws upon information stored in the Memory subsystem in order to evaluate it. Figure 8-3 shows
information both coming from Memory and going to memory to guide the retrieval of memory information, making
it selective and relevant. Further assume that, given the presented information and what is available in Memory, the
situation still makes only partial sense. You decide to seek more information. Controlling information is sent to
Input-processing to produce more information about the situation, to look at it from another angle. Getting this
further information, you again compare it against what you already know, and one of two sequences results. If the
situation still does not make sense, and you have no way of getting further information, you may take the option,
shown by the upward-slanting arrow, of simply not acting on the situation for the time being. If it doesn't make
sense, in accordance with whatever logic you are using, you can then consult your memory for criteria for valued or
appropriate kinds of actions, given your understanding of the situation, and then act in that appropriate way. Your
action modifies the situation, which changes the data reaching you from the situation through Exteroception and
Input-Processing, and the whole process may be repeated. Continuous cycling through this sort of process is what
we call thinking and action.
In the ordinary d-SoC, the operation of the Evaluation and Decision-Making subsystem is often hyperactive to
the point of constituting noise—noise in the sense that the overinvestment of attention/awareness energy in this
process lowers the ability to notice and deal with other sources of relevant information. You cannot hear your sense
over the noise of your thoughts. The cycle shown in Figure 8-3 tends to be endless and self-perpetuating.
Something happens, you think about it, reach a decision, and act, which changes the situation and makes you
reevaluate it. Or you do not act, but thinking about it reminds you of something else, which reminds you of
something else, about which you make a decision, which results in action that modifies another situation, which
starts more evaluation and association processes. For example, someone on the street asks me for money, which
starts me thinking about disinterested charity versus the work ethic ("Why doesn't he get a job? I work for my
money. Maybe he is unfortunate, but he could also be too lazy. Maybe I'm being manipulated; I've been
manipulated before, etc. etc.") and I'm so involved in this thought process that I do not notice various perceptual
cues that would inform me about this person's actual situation and intentions.
Earlier, in discussing the stabilization processes that maintain a state of consciousness I pointed out that this
endless thinking process is a major source of loading stabilization in an ordinary d-SoC. It continually reinforces
consensus reality, for we tend to think continuously about the things we have been reinforced for thinking about,
and it absorbs such a large amount of our attention/awareness energy that we have little of that energy available for
other processes. This Evaluation and Decision-Making subsystem activity has an extremely large amount of
psychological inertia: if you are not fully convinced of this, I suggest that you put this book down right now and try
to turn the system off for five minutes. Don't think of anything, don't evaluate anything for the next five minutes.
That also means don't think about not thinking.
Now, unless you a rare individual indeed, you have seen the difficulty of stopping activity of your Evaluation and
Decision-Making subsystem. This enormous psychological inertia is excellent for maintaining your social
membership in consensus reality, but if your personality structure and/or consensus reality is unsatisfactory and/or
you wish to explore other d-SoCs besides you ordinary one, this endless activity of the Evaluation and Decision-
Making subsystem can be a tremendous liability.
Within the ordinary d-SoC, there is some quantitative variation in the activity of the Evaluation and Decision-
Making subsystem. Some days you feel intellectually sharp, and your mind is quick and you solve problems
accurately on the first try. Other days you mind seems dull; you fail to grasp things right away, have to think a lot
just to understand elementary points, have a hard time putting things together. There is also some variation within
the ordinary d-SoC in the overall quantity of thoughts: some days your thoughts seem to race, other days they are a
bit slower than normal. There is probably also quantitative variation in the redundancy of thinking, the degree to
which you use multiple, overlapping processes to check on your own accuracy. And there is a quantitative variation
in the degree to which you logical evaluation is distorted by emotional factors. When you are in a situation that
activates conscious and subconscious emotions, your logic borders on pure rationalization; in a less threatening
situation your logic may be relatively flawless. But these variations all stay within an expected range that you have
come to think of as your ordinary d-SoC.
All the above relatively quantitative variations in the functioning of the Evaluation and Decision-Making
subsystem may be exaggerated in various d-ASCs. Your thoughts may seem to race faster than you can comprehend
them; the slowing down or accuracy of your logic processes can seem much more extreme than in your ordinary d-
SoC. A drunk, for example, may not be able to think through a simple problem, while someone intoxicated on
marijuana may have crystal-clear insights into a formerly baffling problem. I cannot be more specific about this, as
there has been little quantitative research on it so far. However, experiential reports suggest that the quantitative
variations can be large.
Even more interesting are qualitative variations in various d-ASCs. One of these is the substitution of a different
logic from one ordinarily used in your b-SoC. Martin Orne {44} has reported some interesting demonstrations. A
deeply hypnotized subject is given a suggestion—for example, "The number three no longer makes any sense, the
idea of three is a meaningless concept." The subject is then given various arithmetical problems such as two plus
one equals what? Depending on subsidiary assumptions the subject makes, he rapidly evolves a new arithmetical
logic that does not involve the number three. To the question, "What does two plus one equal?" he answers, "Four."
To the question, "Sic divided by two equals what?" he answers either, "Two" or "Four," depending on the subsidiary
assumptions. Thus a whole new logic can be readily programmed in the d-ASC of hypnosis. Various state-specific
logics have been reported for meditative and psychedelic states, but they do not seem communicable in the ordinary
d-SoC.
In the ordinary d-SoC, we are intolerant of contradictions in logic; in a d-ASC, tolerance for contradictions may
be much higher. Again, an example from hypnosis is illustrative. I once suggested to an extremely susceptible
subject, while he was in the hypnotic d-ASC, that mentally he was getting up from his chair, going down the hall
and outside the laboratory building. he described this experience to me as it was happening. He experienced himself
as being in the yard in back of the laboratory, where he reported seeing a mole come up to the surface from its
tunnel. I asked him to catch the mole and hold on to it, and he said he had. Later I had him in his mental journey
come back into the laboratory, walk upstairs, reenter the room where we were sitting, and stand in the middle of the
floor. I asked him what he saw in the room, and he gave a general overall description of the room, omitting any
mention of the chair in which he was sitting. Something like the following dialogue then occurred:
CT: Is there anyone sitting in the chair?
T: I am.
CT: Didn't you just tell me you were standing in the middle of the room?
S: Yes, I am standing in the middle of the room.
CT: Do you think it's contradictory to tell me you're standing in the middle of the room and sitting in the chair at
the same time?
S: Yes.
CT: Does this contradiction bother you?
S: No.
CT: Which one of the two selves is your real self?
S: They are both my real self.
This stumped me until I finally thought of another question.
CT: Is there any difference at all between the two selves?
S: Yes, the me standing in the middle of the floor has a mole in his hands.
It is tempting to view this tolerance for contradictions as a deterioration in logic, but remember that contradiction
is itself defined in terms of a particular logic, and since logics are self-contained assumptive structures, thinking in a
pattern containing contradictions according to one system of logic may not necessarily mean that the thinking is
useless or absolutely invalid. Indeed, some investigators have hypothesized that an increased ability to tolerate
contradictions is necessary for creative thought. It should also be noted that many people who experience this
ability to tolerate contradictions in d-ASCs believe it to be a transcendent, superior quality, not necessarily an
inferior one. Sometimes they feel they are using a superior logic. Nevertheless, the ability to tolerate contradictions
per se is not necessarily a superior quality.
Since this book is written in ordinary, Western d-SoC logic, there are difficulties in writing about d-ASC logics.
New logics can emerge, appropriate to a particular d-ASC. New sets of (implicit) assumptions and rules for
handling information in accordance with these assumptions seem to be inherent or learnable in a particular d-ASC.
Within that particular d-ASC, and in repeated experiences in that d-ASC, these rules may be quite consistent and
illogical. But writing about this is difficult because new state-specific logics may not seem like logics at all in other
d-SoCs. From the viewpoint of some other d-SoC (usually the ordinary one) the logic is apparent, consistent, and
useful. The existence of such state-specific logics is obvious to a number of people who experienced them in d-
ASCs: they have not yet been proved to exist in a way acceptable to ordinary d-SoC evaluation.
The question whether there are state-specific logics or merely inferior, error-ridden logics in d-ASCs is further
complicated by the tendency of new experiencers of d-ASCs to overvalue their experiences in those d-ASCs. The
experiences are so fascinating and often so emotionally potent in a d-ASC that is new to you that you tend to accept
uncritically everything about it. Clearly, the sense of "This is a remarkable, obviously true and wonderful truth" is a
parainformational quality, like the quality "This is a memory" discussed earlier, and can attach itself to various
contents regardless of their logical truth value. The feeling that something is true, no matter how emotionally
impressive, is no guarantee of its truth. The final test of whether a state-specific logic exists for a particular d-ASC
will involve not only the sequential validation and replication of a logic of an individual experiencer as he reenters
a particular d-ASC time after time, but also his ability to communicate that logic to others in that d-ASC and have
them independently validate it, a point elaborated later in connection with state-specific sciences.
An exciting finding of recent psychological research is the apparent existence of two discrete modes of cognition
associated with functioning of the left and right cerebral hemispheres, respectively {47}. In the normal person there
are a huge number of interconnections via the corpus callosum between these two hemispheres, and on that
physiological basis a person should be able to alternate between two modes of thinking quite readily, choosing
whichever is appropriate for a problem. Our culture, however, has greatly overvalued the style of thinking
associated with left hemisphere activity—linear, sequential, rational, intellectual, cause-and-effect, analytical
thinking. Right hemisphere functioning seems more concerned with pattern recognition, with wholes, with
simultaneity rather than sequence, and with bodily functioning. The right hemisphere mode is more an analog mode
than a digital mode. Since each mode of evaluation is highly valid when appropriately applied to a problem it is
suited for, we become limited and less effective if we overvalue one mode and apply it to problems more
appropriate to the other mode. In the ordinary d-SoC, especially among Western academics, linear thinking is
greatly overvalued, so we exist in a unbalanced, pathological state. The reasoning behind this is complex, and the
interested reader should consult Ornstein's The Psychology of Consciousness {47} and the sources he draws upon.
Many d-ASC experiences seem to reflect a greatly increased use of the right hemisphere mode of cognition.
Experiencers talk of seeing patterns in things, of simultaneously and instantaneously grasping relationships they
cannot ordinarily grasp, of being unable to express these things verbally. The experience is usually reported as
pleasant and rewarding and often is valued as a higher or more true form of cognition. Apparently left and right
hemisphere functioning is more balanced or there may even be a shift to dominance of right hemisphere
functioning. The experience does not lend itself to verbal description, but may be communicable in other ways, as
through music or dance. It should be noted as a major shift in the Evaluation and Decision-Making subsystem that
can occur in d-ASCs.[5]
In the ordinary d-SoC, constant, repetitious thinking absorbs a great deal of attention/awareness energy and acts
as a form of loading stabilization. Since attention/awareness energy is taken away from this left hemisphere type of
activity in d-ASCs, and the energy becomes more freely available, psychological functions that are only latent
potentials in the ordinary d-SoC may become noticeable. They are made noticeable not only through the availability
of attention/awareness energy, but also because the noise of constant thinking is reduced. These new functions may
resemble instincts giving us information about situations or, since a right hemisphere mode of functioning may emit
some of its output in the form of bodily sensations (a hypothesis of mine that I believe future research will
validate), they may enhance sensitivity to such sensations. It is as if in our ordinary d-SoC we are surrounded by a
crowd of people talking and shouting continually. If they would all quiet down, we might be able to hear
individuals or to hear someone at the edge of the crowd
who is saying something important.
Emotions
The Emotions subsystem is one which I, as a typical overintellectualized Western academic, feel least qualified to
write out. I share the intellectual's distrust of emotions as forces that distort my reasoning and are liable to lead me
astray. And yet, like most people, my life and consciousness are strongly controlled by the pursuit of pleasant
emotions and the avoidance of unpleasant ones.
Emotions are feelings that can be named but not easily defined. They are feelings that we call grief, fear, joy,
surprise, yearning, anger, but that we define inadequately in terms of words: at best we use words to evoke
memories of experiences that fit those names.
The Emotions subsystem is, in one sense, the most important subsystem, for it can exert tremendous influence. If
you are experiencing the emotion of fear, it may very well control you evaluations and decisions, the memories you
draw upon, how you see the world and how you act. Any strong emotion tends to constellate the rest of
consciousness about it. Indeed, I think that while mild levels of any emotion can occur within the region of
experiential space we call the ordinary d-SoC, most strong levels of feeling may actually constitute d-ASCs. If you
talk about feeling mildly angry, somewhat angry, or extremely angry, you can imagine all these things occurring in
your ordinary d-SoC. But if you speak of being enraged, the word evokes associations of changes of perception
(such as "seeing red") and cognition that strongly suggest that somewhere in the anger continuum there was a
quantum jump, and a d-ASC of rage developed. The same is true for other strong emotions. I shall not develop the
idea further here, as strong emotional states have seldom been studied scientifically as they must be to determine if
they actually constitute d-SoCs. The idea holds promise for future research.
Our culture is strongly characterized by poor volitional control over the Emotions subsystem in the ordinary d-
SoC. Emotions can change with lightning rapidity; external events can induce them almost automatically. We have
accepted this in a despairing way as part of the human condition, ambivalently regarding attempts to control
emotions as either virtuous (since all emotions make us lose control, we should suppress them) or artificial (not
"genuine"). Techniques from various spiritual disciplines indicate, however, that there can be emotional control that
does not involve simple suppression or denial of content of the emotion {128}. Don Juan, for example, stated that
since becoming a "man of knowledge" he had transcended ordinary emotions, but could have any one he wished
{11}. In d-ASCs, people often report either greatly increased or decreased control over their emotions.
In addition to changes in the degree of control over emotions, the intensity of emotions themselves may also
change in d-ASCs. Dissociation from or dis-identification with emotions also occurs: a person reports that an
emotion is going on quite strongly within him, yet is not "his": he is not identified with it and so little affected by it.
In some d-ASCs new emotions appear, emotions that are never present in the ordinary d-SoC. These include
feelings like serenity, tranquillity, and ecstasy. Because we use these words in our ordinary d-SoC we think we
understand them, but those who have experienced such emotions in d-ASCs insist that we have only known the
palest shadows of them.
Space/Time Sense
Events and experiences happen at a certain time in a certain place. The naive view of this situation is that we
simply perceive the spatial and temporal dimensions of real events. A more sophisticated analysis shows that space
and time are experiential constructs that we have used to organize sensory stimuli coming to us. Because the
organization has been so often successful for dealing with the environment, we have come to believe that we are
simply perceiving what is "out there," rather than automatically and implicitly imposing a conceptual framework on
what comes in to us. Ornstein {47} illustrates this in considerable detail in his analysis of time perception, showing
that psychological time is a construct, as is physical time, and that a simple equation of the two things is
misleading. If we bear in mind that our ordinary concepts of space and time are psychological constructs—highly
successful theoretical ones, but nonetheless only constructs—then we shall be less inclined to label as distortions
the changes in the functioning of the Space/Time subsystem reported in d-ASCs.
In the ordinary d-SoC there is a small amount of variation in Space/Time sense, but not much. On a dull day time
drags somewhat and on an exciting day it goes by quickly, but this range is not large. The dull hour may seem two
or three hours long, a walk home when you are tired may seem twice as far, but this is about the maximum
quantitative variation for most people in the ordinary d-SoC. Many other aspects of the space/time framework this
subsystem generates are unchanging in the ordinary d-SoC: effects do not precede causes, up and down do not
reverse, your body does not shrink or grow larger with respect to the space around it.
Variations in the apparent rate of time flow may be much larger in some d-ASCs than ordinarily. In the d-ASC of
marijuana intoxication, for example, a common experience is for an LP record to seem to play for an hour or more.
Since an LP record generally plays for about fifteen minutes, this is approximately a fourfold increase in
experienced duration. Ornstein {47} believes that a person's estimate of duration is based on the number of events
that have taken place in a given period, so as more things are experienced the elapsed time seems longer. Since
marijuana intoxication, like many d-ASCs, involves major changes in Input-Processing so that more sensory
information is admitted, this experience of increased duration for a single record and for similar events may be due
to the fact that a lot more is happening experientially in that same period of clock time. The converse effect can also
happen in d-ASCs: time seems to speed by at an extraordinary rate. An experience that seems to have lasted a
minute or two actually lasted an hour.
A rare but especially intriguing experience reported from some d-ASCs is that the direction of flow of time seems
to change. An event from the future happens now; the experiencer may even know it does not belong in the now but
will happen later. An effect seems to precede the cause. Our immediate reaction, resulting from our deeply
ingrained belief in the total reality of clock time, is that this cannot be "true," and we see the phenomenon as some
confusion of time perception or possibly a hallucination.
A rewarding d-ASC experience is an increased focus on the present moment, a greatly increased here-and-
nowness. In the ordinary d-SoC, we usually pay little attention to what is actually happening in the present. We live
among memories of the past and amid plans, anticipations, and fantasies about the future. The greatly increased
sense of being in the here and now experienced in many d-ASCs usually accompanies a feeling of being much more
alive, much more in contact with things. Many meditative practices specifically aim for this increased sense of
here-and-nowness. Some d-ASCs seem to produce the opposite effect: the size of the present is "narrowed," making
it very difficult to grasp the present moment.
The experience of archetypal time, the eternal present, is a highly valued and radical alteration in time sense
reported in various d-ASCs. Not only is there a great here-and-nowness, a great focus on the present moment, but
there is a feeling that the activity or experience of the moment is exactly the right thing that belongs in this moment
of time. It is a perfect fit with the state of the universe, a basic that springs from one's ultimate nature. Some of
informants in my studies of marijuana intoxication {105} expressed this, in terms of relationships, as no longer
being the case of John Smith and Mary Williams walking together in New York City on June 30, 1962, but Man and
Woman Dancing Their Pattern Together, as it always has been and always will be.
The experience of archetypal time is similar to, and may be identical with, the experience of timelessness, of the
feeling that my kind of temporal framework for an experience is meaningless. Experiences simply are, they do not
seem to take place at a specific time. Samadhi, for example, is described as lasting for an eternity, even though the
meditater may be in that d-ASC for only a few seconds. Occasionally in such timeless experiences some part of the
mind is perceived as putting a temporal location and duration of the event, but this is seen as meaningless word play
that has nothing to do with reality. In some of mystical experiences in d-ASCs, the adjectives timeless and eternal
are used almost interchangeably. Eternity probably did not arise as a concept, but as a word depicting an experience
of timelessness, an immediate experiential reality rather than a concept of infinite temporal duration.
Déjà vu, the French phrase meaning "seen before," is a time experience that occasionally happens in the ordinary
d-SoC (it may actually represent a momentary transition into a d-ASC) and happens more frequently in d-ASCs. As
an event is unfolding you seem to be remembering it, you are convinced it has happened before because it has the
quality of a memory. In discussing the Memory subsystem, we speculated that Déjà vu might sometimes result from
a misplacement of the quality "this is a memory" on a current perceptual event. Other types of Déjà vu experiences
may represent an alteration of functioning of the Space/time subsystem, where the extra informational quality "this
is from the past" is added to current perceptual events.
The quantitative variations in space perception that occur in the ordinary d-SoC may occur in greatly increased
form in d-ASCs. Distances walked, for example, may seem much shorter or much longer than ordinarily. Nor is
active movement through space necessary for changes in distance to occur: as you sit and look something, it may
seem to recede into the distance or to come closer. Or it may seem to grow larger or smaller.
Depth is an important quality of spatial experience. A photograph or a painting is usually seen as a two-
dimensional, flat representation of what was in reality a three-dimensional scene. Perception of a three-dimensional
quality in the two-dimensional painting is attributed to the artist's technical skill. In d-ASCs, the degree of depth in
ordinary perceptions may seem to change. Aaronson {88 or 115, ch. 17} notes that in many psychotic states, such as
those associated with depression, the world seems flat, the depth dimension seems greatly reduced, while in many
valued d-ASCs, such as those induced by psychedelic drugs, the depth dimension seems enhanced, deeper, richer.
In some intriguing experiments, Aaronson shows that by artificially altering a hypnotized subject's depth perception
through suggestion, to flatter or deeper, he can produce great variations in the subject's moods, and perhaps actually
produce d-ASCs by simply changing this basic operation of the Space/Time subsystem.
The ability to see three-dimensional depth in two-dimensional pictures is an interesting phenomenon reported for
marijuana intoxication {105}. The technique my main informant reported is to look at a color picture through a
pinhole held right at the eye, so your field of vision includes only the picture, not any other elements. If you are
highly intoxicated with marijuana, the picture may suddenly become a three-dimensional scene instead of a flat,
two-dimensional one.
Another d-ASC-associated spatial change is loss of the spatial framework as a source of orientation. Although
there are enormous individual differences, some people always keep their orientation in physical space plotted on a
mental map; they generally know what direction they are facing, in what direction various prominent landmarks are
located. This kind of orientation to the physical spatial framework may simply fade out, not be perceived in d-
ASCs, or it may still be perceptible but become a relatively meaningless rather than an important type of
information.
This kind of change can be accompanied by new ways of perceiving space. Lines may become curved instead of
straight, for example. Some people report perceiving four or more dimensions in d-ASCs, not as a mathematical
construct but as an experiential reality. The difficulties of expressing this in a language evolved from external
adaptation to three-dimensional reality are obvious.
We ordinarily think of space as empty, but in d-ASCs space is sometimes perceived as having a more solid
quality, as being filled with "vibrations" or "energy," rather than as being empty. Sometimes experiences believe
this to be an actual change in their perception of the space around them; sometimes they perceive it as a projection
of internal psychological changes onto their spatial perception.
Our ordinary concept of space is a visual one, related to maps, lines and grids, visual distances, and diagrams.
Space may be organized in other ways. Some marijuana smokers, for example, report that space becomes organized
in an auditory way when they are listening to sounds or music with their eyes closed. Others report that tactual
qualities determine space.
I recall a striking evening I once spent with some friends. One of them had just rented a new house, which none
of us had seen. We arrived after dark, were blindfolded before entering the house, and spent the next couple of
hours exploring the house by movement and touch alone, with no visual cues at all. They concept that gradually
evolved of the space of the house without the usual visual organizing cues was vastly different from the subsequent
perception of the space when the blindfolds were removed.
Sense of Identity
We noted earlier that an extra informational "This is a memory" quality is either explicitly or implicitly attached
to data coming from the Memory subsystem and that this quality is sometimes attached to non-memory information
in consciousness, producing interesting phenomena. The primary function of the Sense of Identity subsystem is to
attach a "This is me" quality to certain aspects of experience, to certain information in consciousness, and thus to
create the sense of an ego. Presumably semipermanent structures exist incorporating criteria for what the "This is
me" quality should be attached to. However, the functioning of the Sense of Identity subsystem varies so greatly,
even in the ordinary d-SoC, that I emphasize the extra informational aspects of the "This is me" quality rather than
the structures underlying it.
Any item of information to which the "This is me" quality is attached acquires considerable extra potency and so
may arouse strong emotions and otherwise control attention/awareness energy. If I say to you, "The face of
someone you don't know, a Mr. Johnson, is ugly and revolting," this information probably will not be very
important to you. But if I say to you, "Your face is ugly and revolting," that is a different story! But why do you
react so strongly to the latter sentence? True, under some circumstances such a statement might preface more
aggressive action, against which you want to defend yourself, but often such a remark prefaces no more than
additional words of the same sort; yet, you react to those words as if to actual physical attack.[6] Adding the ego
quality to information radically alters the way that information is treated by the system of consciousness as a
whole.
At any given time only some of the contents of awareness are modulated by the ego quality. As I sit writing and
pause to glance around the room, I see a large number of objects: they become the contents of my consciousness,
but they are not me. The ego quality has not been added to them. Much our experience is just information; it does
not have a special ego quality added.
Another major function of the Sense of Identity subsystem is the exact opposite of its usual function: a denial of
the sense of self to certain structures. Because certain of our personal characteristics and mind structures are
considered undesirable and/or evoke unpleasant emotions in us, we create blocks and defenses against perceiving
them as parts of ourselves. Many of these interdicted structures are culturally determined, many are specific
products of personal developmental history and are not widely shared in the culture. So we deny that we have
certain characteristics or we project them on to others: I am not quarrelsome, he is!
I mention this function only in passing, in spite of its enormous importance, for it leads into the vast realm of
psychopathology, and is beyond the scope of this book.
The functioning of the Sense of Identity subsystem is highly variable in the ordinary d-SoC, much more variable
than we are ordinarily aware. There are many transient identifications, many short-term modulations of particular
information, by the ego feeling. When you read a good novel or see a good movie and empathize with one of the
characters, you are adding the ego sense to the information about that character. Empathy is the ability to take in
information about another's experiences and treat it as if it were you own. However, a person's degree of control
over, and self-awareness of, empathy is highly variable. Lack of control over ability to identify with particular
things can cause psychological difficulties. For example, if a shopkeeper treats you brusquely, you may feel hurt
and upset about it all day long, even though you know intellectually that he is a brusque person who treats everyone
that way. Your ego sense was attached to that particular information and is difficult to detach. Thus, various kinds of
stimulus patterns can catch the ego sense and are difficult to disentangle.
To illustrate the high variability of functioning of the Sense of Identity subsystem, consider how it can be
invested in possessions. Suppose you are in New York City, having a "sophisticated" discussion with a friend about
the breakdown of social values and the consequent rebellion by young people. Through the window you see some
teenagers across the street trashing a car, and, with detachment, you point out to your friend that these unfortunate
teenagers are what they are because their parents could not transmit values they lacked themselves. Then you notice
it is your car they are trashing, and your feelings of sympathy for those poor teenagers vanish rather quickly!
Each person has a number of relatively permanent identifications, well-defined experiential and behavioral
repertoires that he thinks of as himself. His role in society gives him several of these: he may be a salesman in one
situation, a father in another, a lover in another, a patient in another, an outraged citizen in another. Often these
various roles demand behaviors and values that are contradictory, but because he identifies strongly with each role
at the time he assumes it, he does not think of this other roles, and experiences little conscious conflict. For
example, a concentration camp guard who brutalizes his prisoners all day may be known as a loving and doting
father at home. This ability to compartmentalize roles is one of the greatest human dilemmas.
Some roles are situation-specific. Others are so pervasive that they continue to function in situations for which
they are not appropriate. For example, if you take your job concerns home with you or to a party where other kinds
of experiences and behavior are desired and expected, you have overidentified with a particular role.
One of a person's most constant, semipermanent identifications is with his body, more precisely, with his body
image, the abstract of the data from his body as mediated through the Exteroception, Interoception, and Input-
Processing subsystems. This body image he identifies with may or may not have much actual resemblance to his
physical body as other people see it. The degree of identification with the body may vary from time to time. When I
am ill I am very aware of my physical body and its centrality in my consciousness; when I am healthy and happy I
am aware of my body more as a source of pleasure, or I forget it as I become involved in various tasks.
On the basis of this mass of transient and semipermanent identifications, with various degrees of
compartmentalization, each of us believes in something he calls his ego or self. He may assume that this elf is a
property of his soul and will live forever. He may vigorously defend this self against slights or other attacks. But
what is this ego, this "real" self?
This difficult question has long plagued philosophers and psychologists. I am intrigued by the Buddhist view that
asks you to search your experience to find the basic, permanent parts of it that constitute the essence of your ego.
When you do this, you find it hard to identify anything as being, finally, you. You may discern certain long-term
constancies in your values, connected sets of memories, but none of these qualifies as an ultimate self. The
Buddhist view is that you have no ultimate self, thus you need not defend it. Since it is the ego that suffers,
realization that ego is an illusion is supposed to end suffering.
In terms of the systems approach, we can characterize ego as a continuity and consistency of functioning to
which we attach special importance, but which does not have the reality of a solid thing somewhere, which is only a
pattern of operation that disappears under close scrutiny. I believe that this view is congruent with the enormous
changes that can occur in the sense of self in various d-ASCs. The ego or self is thus a certain kind of extra
informational modulation attached to other contents of consciousness. It is not a solid sort of thing, even though
there must be some semipermanent structures containing the information criteria for controlling the functioning of
this subsystem. A change in the pattern of functioning changes the ego.
Reports from d-ASCs indicate that the sense of ego can be disengaged from a wide variety of kinds of
information and situations to which it is normally attached. Memories, for example, may come into your
consciousness accompanied by the feeling that this is your memory, as just information pulled from memory. This
can be therapeutically useful for recovering information about traumatic events from a patient who is unable to
handle the emotional charge on the events. The sense of ego can also be detached from the body, so that you are
associated simply with a body rather than your body. Reaction to pain, for instance, can be altered this way. You
may feel a stimulus as just as painful as ordinarily, but you do not get upset about it because you are not being
injured. Situations that evoke particular roles may not evoke such roles in d-ASCs. For example, all the necessary
stimulus elements may be present for automatically invoking the role of teacher, but in the d-ASC the role does not
appear. The sense of ego can be detached from possessions and responsibilities, and even from actions, so that
things you do seem not to be your actions for which you are responsible, but just actions.
Sometimes the sense of ego is detached from several or all of the above concepts so that you feel entirely egoless
for a while. There is experience, but none of it is "possessed" by you in any special ego sense.
The converse effect can also occur in d-ASCs: the sense of ego may be added to things it is not ordinarily
attached to. A situation, for example, may call for a certain role that is not important to you ordinarily but which
you come to identify with strongly.
This detachment and addition of the ego sense that accompanies d-ASCs may result in actions that are later
regretted when the ordinary d-SoC returns. In our culture, the classic case is the person who behaves while drunk as
he would never behave sober. A certain amount of social tolerance exists for drunken behavior, so while some
people have profound regrets on realizing what they did, others are able to compartmentalize these experiences and
not be particularly bothered by them.
These large shifts in ego sense in d-ASCs may later modify the ordinary d-SoC functioning of the Sense of
Identity subsystem. When things you firmly identify with in the ordinary d-SoC are experienced in a d-ASC as
detached from you, your conviction of their permanence is undermined and remains so when you resume your
ordinary d-SoC. You are then receptive to other possibilities.
Since attachment of the sense of ego to certain information greatly increases the power of that information, these
large shifts in Sense of Identity subsystem functioning can have profound consequences. For example, if the sense
of ego is used to modulate most information about another person, you may feel united with that person. The usual
ego-object dichotomy is broken. If your sense of being an ego separate from other things is greatly reduced or
temporarily abolished in a d-ASC, you may feel much closer to another person because there is no you to be
separate from him. The other may be a perceived, real person or a concept religiously respected person, a saint, or
god, you may have a mystical experience in which you feel identified with something greater than yourself.
It is important to note, however, that the expansive or contractive change in the Sense of Identity subsystem that
allows identification with something greater than/or outside oneself can have negative consequences and can be
used to manipulate others. Group procedures at some religious meetings or political rallies, such as the Nazis held,
illustrate how an intense emotional state can be generated which disrupts the stabilization of the ordinary d-SoC and
leaves it vulnerable to psychological pressure to identify with the cause being promoted. Whether the cause is that
of the Nazi party or of Christian salvation, the method is manipulation, playing on a subject's ignorance to disrupt
his d-SoC and then reprogramming him.
These negative aspects should be emphasized, for too many people who have had good experiences in d-ASCs
tend to think d-ASCs are inherently good. Consider, therefore, one more example, that of the berserkers. The
English word berserk, meaning "violently running amuck, killing and slaying at random," comes from the
Scandinavian word berserker, referring to groups in medieval times who took a psychedelic drug in order to
become better killers. Tradition has it that these Vikings, to whom raiding and killing was a respectable way of life,
ingested Amanita muscaria, a mushroom with psychedelic properties, under ritual conditions (patterning forces) to
induce a day-long d-ASC in which they became exceptionally ferocious killers and fighters, carried away by rage
and lust, supposedly impervious to pain, an possessed of extra strength. Such a d-ASC experience hardly creates
"flower children."
Additionally we should note that the semiconstancy of the consensus reality we live in imposes a fair degree of
consistency on the kinds of experiences and contents of consciousness to which the Sense of Identity subsystem
attaches the ego quality. Every morning you awaken with an apparently identical body; people call you by the same
name; they have relatively fixed expectations of you; they reward you for fulfilling those expectations; you are
usually surrounded by a fair number of possessions that reinforce your sense of identity. As long as these consensus
reality conditions remain relatively constant, you can easily believe in the constancy of your ego. But if these props
for your Sense of Identity are changed, as they sometimes are deliberately as a way of destabilizing the b-SoC in
preparation for inducing a d-ASC, your sense of ego can change radically. An example familiar to some readers is
induction into the army: you are stripped of personal possessions, including clothes; all your ordinary social roles
are gone; your name is replaced by a number or a rank; and you are "reeducated" to be a good soldier. Induction
into the army and induction into a d-ASC have much in common, but because the army is a well-known subset of
consensus reality it is not considered odd, as hypnosis or dreaming are.
Finally, because of its enormous ability to control emotional and attention/awareness energy, the Sense of
Identity subsystem can at times constellate the entire structure of consciousness about particular identity patterns,
just as can archetypes (in the Jungian sense) arising from the Collective Unconscious can.
Motor Output
The Motor Output subsystem consists of those structures which we physically affect the external world and our
own bodies. In terms of conscious awareness, these structures are primarily the skeletal, voluntary musculature. If I
take a minute out from writing to pet my cat, I am using my Motor Output subsystem with full awareness. The
Motor Output subsystem elements that primarily affect our own bodies are glandular secretions and other internal,
biological processes. These latter, involuntary effectors are controllable not directly, but through intermediates. I
cannot directly increase the amount of adrenaline in my bloodstream, for example, but if I make myself angry and
wave my fists and shout and holler, I will almost certainly increase the amount of adrenaline secreted.
Two kinds of inputs control Motor Output: input from the Evaluation and Decision-Making subsystem, conscious
decisions to do or not to do something, and input from a series of controlling signals that bypasses the Evaluation
and Decision-Making subsystem. The latter includes reflexes (jumping at a sudden sound, for example), emotional
reactions, and direct control of Motor Output from the Subconscious subsystem. Subconscious control in the
ordinary d-SoC includes qualities added to otherwise conscious gestures that reflect nonconscious mental
processes: you may state, for example, that a certain person does not make you angry, but an observer notices that
your fists clench whenever this person is mentioned.[7]
Motor Output operates with almost constant feedback control. By monitoring the environment with the
Exteroception subsystem and the body with the Interoception subsystem, you constantly check on the effect of your
physical actions and on whether these are desirable and make adjustments accordingly.[8]
Many voluntary movements are quite unconscious in terms of their details. You decide to lift your arm, yet you
have little awareness of the individual muscle actions that allow you to do so. In d-ASCs, greatly increased
awareness of particular aspects of the Motor Output subsystem are sometimes reported. Greatly decreased
awareness has also been reported: actions that are ordinarily subject to conscious awareness, via feedback from the
interoceptors, are done with no awareness at all. During my first experience with a psychedelic drug, mescaline, I
told my body to walk down to the end of the hall. Then my awareness became completely absorbed in various
internal events. After what seemed a very long time, I was surprised to notice that my body had walked down the
hall and obligingly stopped at the end, with no conscious participation or awareness on my part. To some extent this
occurs in an ordinary d-SoC, especially with well-learned actions, but the effect can be much more striking in a d-
ASC. We should distinguish lack of sensory awareness of body actions from awareness of them but without the
sense of ego added. The latter also creates a different relationship with motor actions.
Deautomatization of motor actions is another sort of altered awareness of motor output that can occur in a d-
ASC. Either you become unusually aware of components of automatized actions normally inaccessible to
consciousness or you have deliberately to will each of these component actions to take place because the whole
automated action will not occur by itself.
D-ASC related changes in the way the body is experienced via the Exteroception subsystem and in awareness of
functioning of the Motor Output subsystem can alter the operating characteristics of voluntary action. You may
have to perform a different kind of action internally in order to produce the same kind of voluntary action. Carlos
Castaneda {9} gives a striking example of this in a drug-induced d-ASC. His body was completely paralyzed from
the "little smoke" in terms of his ordinary way of controlling it. Doing all the things he ordinarily did to move
produced zero response. But if he simply willed movement in a certain way, his body responded.
Changes in the awareness of the functioning of the Motor Output subsystem may include feelings of greatly
increased strength or skill, or of greatly decreased strength or skill. Often these feelings do not correspond with
performance: you may feel exceptionally weak or unsure of your skill, and yet perform in a basically ordinary
fashion. Or you may feel exceptionally strong, but show no actual increase in performance. The potential for a true
increment in strength in d-ASCs is real, however, because in the ordinary d-SoC you seldom use your musculature
to its full strength. Safety mechanisms prevent you from fully exerting yourself and possibly damaging yourself.
For example, some muscles are strong enough to break your own bones if they were maximally exerted. In various
d-ASCs, especially when strong emotions are involved, these safety mechanisms may be temporarily bypassed,
allowing greater strength, at the risk of damage.
In a d-ASC the Subconscious subsystem may control the Motor Output subsystem or parts of it. For example, if a
hypnotist suggests to a subject that his arm is moving up and down by itself, the arm will do so and the subject will
experience the arm moving by itself, without his conscious volition. If a hypnotist suggests automatic writing, the
subject's hand will write complex material, with as much skill as in ordinary writing, without any conscious
awareness by the subject of what he is going to write and without any feeling of volitional control over the action.
This kind of disassociated motor action can also sometimes occur in the ordinary d-SoC, where it may represent the
action of a disassociated d-ASC.
This ends our survey of the main subsystems of states of consciousness. It is only a survey, pointing out the
major variations. Much literature already exists from which more specific information about various subsystems
can be gleaned, and much research remains to be done to clarify our concepts of particular subsystems. Particularly
we need to know exactly how each subsystem changes for each specific d-ASC.
So we must know our parts better, although I emphasize again that it is just as important to know how these parts
are put into the functioning whole that constitutes a system, a d-SoC.
Footnotes
[1] Lilly's work {34, 35}, in which a mature person uses the ultimate in sensory deprivation (floating in body-
temperature water in the quiet and dark) as a tool, under his own direction, to explore consciousness, should be
consulted by anyone interested in this area. Lilly's use of sensory deprivation as a tool under the subject's own
control, rather than as a "treatment," imposed by people who are studying "craziness," is a breakthrough in research
in this area. Suffice it to note here that sensory deprivation, by removing a major source of loading stabilization by
the exteroceptors, can be a major tool for inducing d-ASCs and deserves much study. (back)
[2] The d-ASC or d-ASCs entered into by spiritualist mediums are a promising, but almost totally neglected field
of research. Scientists have generally avoided having anything to do with mediums as a result of a priori dismissal
of the claims made for survival of bodily death. The few scientists (parapsychologists) who have studied mediums
have been concerned with whether the alleged surviving entities can provide evidence that they actually had an
earthly existence, and whether this evidence could be explained by other hypotheses than postmortem survival. The
nature of the medium's trance state per se is virtually unknown, yet it is clearly one of the most profound d-ASCs
known and has tremendous effects on its experiencers. I mention this to alert researchers to an opportunity for
learning a great deal with even a small investment of decent effort. (back)
[3] Note that while this is probably the cause of most déjà vu, experiences, some kinds of déjà vu, may actually
represent paranormal experience. (back)
[4] Much meaning is automatically supplied by Input-Processing: when you see a stop sign, you need not
consciously evaluate its meaning. (back)
[5] I do not consider right and left hemisphere modes of functioning to be two d-SoCs themselves, but rather two
modes of functioning of the Evaluation and Decision-Making subsystem. The balance can vary in different d-ASCs.
(back)
[6] The old childhood rhyme, "Sticks and stones will break my bones/ But names will never hurt me!/Call me
this, and call me that/And call yourself a dirty rat!" must be looked upon as a morale-builder, or perhaps an
admonition that we adults should heed, but certainly not as a statement of truth. We are terribly hurt by names and
words and what people think of usoften much more hurt than by sticks and stones. People have "chosen" to die in a
burning house rather than run out of it naked.(back)
[7] In relation to subconscious control of movement, Gurdjieff {24} put forth an idea about body movement that
is interesting because it parallels the idea of discrete states of consciousness on a body level. He states that any
person has only a set number of postures and gestures that he uses of his own will. The number varies from person
to person, perhaps as low as fifty, perhaps as high as several hundred. A person moves rapidly, almost jerks, from
one preferred posture to another. If he is forcibly stopped in between discrete postures, he is uncomfortable, even if
it is not a physical strain. Since the functioning of consciousness seems to be strongly affected by body postures and
strains, these "discrete states of posture" (d-SoPs) are important to study.
Gurdjieff used this as a basis for his "Halt" exercise. Pupils agreed to freeze instantly whenever the command
"Halt!" was given. The exercise was intended to show the pupils some of their limitations, among other things.
Gurdjieff claims it is a dangerous exercise unless used by someone with an exceptional knowledge of the human
body. The idea suggests interesting research possibilities. More information can be found in Ouspensky {48}.
(back)
[8] Conscious control over aspects of bodily functioning long considered to be automatic, not susceptible to
voluntary control, is now a major research area under the rubric of biofeedback. The interested reader can find the
most important researches reprinted each year in Biofeedback and Self-Control, an annual published by Aldine
Publishing Company, Chicago. (back)
9. Individual Differences
Inadequate recognition of individual differences is a methodological deficiency that has seriously slowed
psychological research. Lip service is paid to individual differences, but in reality they are largely ignored.
Psychologists, caught up in the all-too-human struggle for prestige, ape the methods of the physical sciences, in
which individual differences are not of great significance and the search is for general fundamental laws. I believe
this failure to recognize individual differences is the rock on which psychology's early attempts to establish itself as
an introspective discipline foundered. Following the lead of the tremendously successful physical scientists, the
early psychologists searched for general laws of the mind, and when their data turned out to be contradictory, they
quarreled with each other over who was right, not realizing they were all right, and so wasted their energies. They
tried to abstract too much too soon before coming to terms with the experiential subject matter.
We psychologists all too often do the same thing today, albeit in a more sophisticated form. Consider, for
example, the procedure described in Chapter 5 for mapping a person's location in experiential space. Suppose that
in the course of an experiment we measure two variables, X and Y, in a group of subjects. To concretize the
example, we can define X as the degree of analgesia (insensitivity to pain) the subject can show and Y as the
intensity of the subject's imagery. Tempted by the convenience and "scientificness" of a nearby computer, we feed
our group data in a prepackaged analysis program and get the printout in the lower chart of Figure 9-1—a straight
line fitted to the data and indicating a highly significant (thus publishable) correlation coefficient between variables
X and Y. It looks as if ability to experience analgesia is linearly related to intensity of imagery, that in this region of
experiential space there is a straight-road connection: if you do whatever is needed to enhance imagery, you
automatically increase analgesia.
If we distrust such great abstraction of the data, we can ask the computer to print out a scatter plot of the raw
data, the actual position of each subject instead of the abstraction for all subjects. This new printout (lower left-hand
chart of Figure 9-1) apparently reassures us that the fitted curve
and correlation coefficient are adequate ways of presenting and
understanding our results. The straight road is somewhat broad,
but still basically straight. More imagery goes with more
analgesia.
We have extracted a principle (more imagery leads to more
analgesia) from group data that is based on one pair of
observations from each subject. Suppose, however, that we
actually go back to our subjects and test some of them repeatedly,
obtain samples over time, an experiential mapping, of their
simultaneous abilities to experience analgesia and imagery. Then
we find that our subjects actually fall into three distinct types, as
shown in the upper charts of Figure 9-1. Type A shows either a
low degree of both analgesia and imagery or a fair degree of
analgesia and imagery, but no other combinations. Type B shows
a low to fair degree of analgesia and imagery or a very high
degree of analgesia and imagery, but no other combinations. Type
C shows a high variability of degree of analgesia and imagery, a
much wider range of combinations.
For subjects of type C, the conclusion, drawn from the group
data, of a linear relationship between intensity of imagery and
intensity of analgesia, is valid. But how many type C subjects are
included in our group? Subjects of types A and B, on the other
hand, do not show a linear relationship between analgesia and
Figure 9-1. Problems arising when individual differences
imagery. There is no straight road, only some islands of are ignored. Charts A, B, and C are experiential
experience. For type A subjects, analgesia and imagery cluster mappings of the sort done in Figure 5-1. The other two
together at low levels or at moderate levels of functioning, but charts are summary charts, as explained in the text.
show no clear linear relationship within either cluster. For type B
subjects, analgesia and imagery cluster at low to moderate or at very high levels, and again show no clear linear
relationship within either clustering. Indeed, subjects of types A and B show the clustering used in Chapter 5 to
define the concept of multiple d-SoCs, while subjects of type C seem to function in only a single d-SoC.
Thus the conclusion drawn from the grouped data about relations between analgesia and imagery in this region of
experiential space turns out to apply only to some people and to misrepresent what others experience. Indeed, the
error may be more profound: people may be only of the A and B types, but combining their results as subjects when
some are in one part of experiential space and some in another gives us a set of numbers that spans the whole range.
This leads us to the straight-road or linear relationship concept, even though that concept actually represents no
one's experience.
It is hard to realize the full impact of individual differences because of the deep implicitness of the assumption
that we all share a common d-SoC. Since we are members of a common culture, this is generally true, but the more
I come to know other individuals and get a feeling for the way their minds work, the more I am convinced that this
general truth, the label ordinary d-SoC, conceals enormous individual differences. If I clearly understood the way
your mind works in its ordinary d-SoC, and if you understood the same about me, we would both be amazed. Yet
because we speak a common language, which stresses external rather than internal events, we are seldom aware of
these differences.
Psychologically, each of us assumes that his own mind is an example of a "normal" mind and then projects his
own experiences onto other people, unaware of how much projecting he is doing. For example, most of us have
imagery in our ordinary d-SoC that is unstable and not very vivid, so that trying to visualize something really
steadily and intensely is impossible. Some people report that in d-ASCs their imagery is much more intense and
controllable, steady. Yet the inventor Nikolai Tesla had such intense, controllable imagery in his ordinary d-SoC.
When Tesla designed a machine, he did it in his head, without using physical drawings: nevertheless, he could
instruct a dozen difference machinists how to make each separate part, to the nearest ten-thousandth of an inch, and
the completed machine would fit together perfectly. Tesla is also reported to have tested wear on his machines
through imagery. He designed the machine by visualization, put the imaged parts together into a complete machine,
started it running in his mind, forgot about it, resurrected the image thousands of hours later, mentally dismantled
the machine, and inspected the parts for wear to see what needed reinforcement of redesign {43}. Regardless of
how one evaluate the accuracy of such imagery, Tesla's procedure is a good example of what for most of us is
exotic imagery associated with d-ASCs, but what was for him the imagery of his "ordinary" d-SoC.
On those occasions when we do recognize great differences in the mental functioning of others, we are tempted
to label the differences weird or abnormal of pathological. Such blanket labels are not useful. What are the specific
advantages and disadvantages under what circumstances for each individual difference of pattern?
This tendency to project implicitly the workings of one's own mind pattern as a standard for the working of all
minds can have interesting scientific results. For example, controversy rages in the literature on hypnosis over
whether the concept of a d-SoC is necessary to explain hypnosis, or whether the hypnotic "state" is in fact
continuous with the ordinary "state," is simply a case of certain psychological functions, such as suggestibility and
role-playing involvement, being pushed to higher levels of activity than they are under ordinary conditions. A chief
proponent of this latter view, Theodore X. Barber {4}, can produce most of the classical hypnotic phenomena in
himself without doing anything special.[1] The phenomena included in his ordinary d-SoC encompass a range that,
for another person, must be attained by unusual means. How much does this affect his theorizing? How much does
anyone's individual psychology affect his thinking about how other minds work? Again consider Figure 9-1.
Whereas A and B type people may have two d-SoCs, one that we call their ordinary d-SoC and a second called their
hypnotic state, the ordinary range of consciousness of type C people includes both these regions. Thus it may be
more accurate to say that what as been called hypnosis, to stick with this example, is indeed merely an extension of
the ordinary range of functioning for some people, but for other people it is d-ASC.
I cannot emphasize too strongly that the mapping of experience and the use of the concept of d-SoCs must first
be done on an individual basis. Only then, if regions of great similarity are found to exist across individuals, can
common names that apply across individuals be legitimately coined.
This idealistic statement does not reflect the way our concepts actually evolved. The very existence of names like
dreaming state or hypnotic state indicates that there appears to a fair degree of commonality among a fair number of
individuals. Though I often speak as if this commonality were true, its veracity cannot be precisely evaluated at the
present stage of our knowledge, and the concept is clearly misleading at times. Several d-ASCs may be hidden
within common names like hypnosis or dreaming.
In addition to the large individual differences that may exist among people we think are all in the same d-SoC,
there are sit from one d-SoC to another. In discussing stabilization processes, I mentioned that some people seem
overstabilized and others understabilized. The former may be able to experience only a few d-SoCs, while the latter
may transit often and effortlessly into d-ASCs. Understabilized people may undergo breakdown of the ordinary d-
SoC and be unable to form a new d-ASC, unable to organize consciousness into a stable coping form. Some types
of schizophrenia may represent this understabilized mode of consciousness.
Besides the sheer number of simultaneous and reinforcing stabilization processes, the degree of voluntary control
over them is important. To the extent that your stabilization processes are too powerful or too implicit to be altered
at will, you are stuck in one mode of consciousness. These dimensions of stabilization, control, and ability to transit
from one d-SoC to another are important ones that must be the focus of future research, as we know almost nothing
about them now.
Footnote
[1] As discussed in Chapter 12, some individuals may
transit so rapidly and easily between d-SoCs that they do
not notice the transitions and so mistakenly believe they
experience only one d-SoC. This case is ordinarily difficult
to distinguish from that of actual continuity through a wide
region of experiential space. (back)
Serious misunderstandings occur when an external technique that might induce a d-ASC is equated with that altered
state itself. This error is particularly seductive in regard to psychoactive or psychedelic drugs, for we tend
automatically to accept the pharmacological paradigm that the specific chemical nature of the drug interacts with
the chemical and physical structure of the nervous system in a lawfully determined way, invariably producing
certain results. This view may be mostly true at a neurological or hormonal level, but is misleading at the level of
consciousness. Within this paradigm, observed variability in human reactions is seen as the "perverseness" of
psychological idiosyncrasies interfering with basic physiological reactions, and is averaged out by treating it as
"error variance." While this pharmacological paradigm seems usefully valid for a variety of simple drugs, such as
barbiturates that induce drowsiness and sleep, it is inadequate and misleading for the psychedelic drugs, such as
marijuana or LSD.
Nondrug Factors
Figure 10-1 depicts a model of the effects of drugs on consciousness that I developed when I was beginning to
study marijuana intoxication {103, 105}. In addition to the physiological effects that constitute disrupting and
patterning forces impinging on the subject (upper right portion of the figure), there are a large number of
psychological disrupting and patterning forces that are, in many cases, more important than the physiological
effects in determining whether a d-ASC will occur and what the content of that altered state will be. Thus while it is
useful to know what psychoactive drug a subject has taken, the quantity of the drug, and the method of
administration, such information may be relatively unimportant. Without one knowledge of the psychological
factors, accurate prediction of the subject's behavioral and experiential reactions maybe very difficult.
These nondrug factors can be classified in three groups: long-term factors, immediate factors, and factors related
to the setting in which the drug is used.
Long-term factors include (1) the culture the subject was raised in and all the effects that has had in terms of
structuring his ordinary d-SoC, and providing specific expectations about the drug; (2) the personality of the
subject; (3) possible specific physiological vulnerabilities he may have to the drug; and (4) his learned drug skills—
whether he has taken this drug many times before, and learned to enhance desired reactions and inhibit undesired
reactions, or is naive with respect to this drug, so that most of his energy will be needed to cope with the (often
stressful) effects of the novelty.
Immediate factors are (5) the subject's mood when he takes the drug, since this mood may be amplified or
inhibited; (6) the subject's expectations about the experience; and (7) whether these expectations are the same as
what he desires to experience.
Factors related to the situation or experimental setting in which the drug is taken include (8) the physical setting
and its effect on the subject; (9) the social setting and its effect—the kinds of people who are with the subject and
how they interact with him (a frightened person present, for example, may communicate his fright sufficiently to
make the effect of the drug quite anxiety-provoking); (10) in the case of an experiment, the formal instructions
given to the subject and how he reacts to and interprets them; and (11) the demand characteristics {45, 55}, the
implicit instructions, and how they affect the subject (for example, if the experimenter tells the subject the drug is
relatively harmless, but asks him to sign a comprehensive medical release form, the total message communicated
belies the statement that this is a relatively harmless drug).
Further, the subject or user is not just a passive recipient of all these forces, reacting mechanically. He may
selectively enhance the action of some and inhibit others. If the social situation is "bringing you down," you can
leave. If you feel unsettled and unsure of your control, you can choose to use only a small amount of the drug. If
certain aspects of the situation are unsettling, you can try not to focus attention on them but on more pleasant or
useful aspects of the situation. This aspect is indicated by the feedback arrow in Figure 10-1.
Since, as discussed earlier, as person's control of his attention and energy is limited, to some extent he is at the
mercy of the various factors diagrammed in Figure 10-1. In the experimental situation particularly, the subject
usually has no control at all over most of these factors and so is at their mercy. This is important because so much
of our scientific knowledge in this area is based on experimental studies of drugs—studies that might be assumed to
be the most dependable. Unfortunately, a close reading of the experimental literature on drugs suggests that most
experimenters were not only unaware of the importance of the psychological factors diagrammed in Figure 10-1,
and so failed to report them, but usually set up the experiment in a way that maximized the probability of bad trips,
of anxiety-filled unpleasant reactions.
This situation is summarized in Table 10-1. The values of drug and psychological factors listed in the rightmost
column are those that increase the probability of a bad trip; those in the third left column, a good trip. Knowing that
the values of some of three factors are in one of the other direction has little predictive value at the present stage of
our knowledge, but knowing that most of them are in one direction allows fair prediction. I infer (sometimes from
the published description per se, sometimes from reading between the lines of talking to former subjects) that in the
more than one thousand scientific experiments on drug-induced d-ASCs reported in the literature that most
experiments had most of the determining factors in the bad trip direction. Thus most of our scientific knowledge
about drug effects is badly confused with effects of coping with the stress of a bad trip.
Given this cautionary note on the complexity of using drugs to induce d-ASCs, a few general things can be said
about drug-induced states in terms of the systems approach.
Particular drugs may specifically affect the neurological bases of various psychological structures/subsystems,
exciting or activating some of these structures/subsystems, suppressing or slowing the activity of other
structures/subsystems, altering or distorting the mode of information-processing within some structures/subsystems.
Psychological processes in relatively unaffected structures/subsystems may, however, compensate for changes in
affected subsystems and/or maintain sufficient stabilization processes so that the d-SoC does not break down. The
drug may both disrupt and pattern on a physiological level, but not necessarily induce a d-ASC. Remember that a d-
SoC is multiply stabilized.
When physiological effects occur in various structures/subsystems, their interpretation by the subject determines
much of his (multilevel) reaction and whether a d-ASC results. Changing the interpretation of a sensation alters its
importance and the degree of attention/awareness energy it attracts. For example, if you consider a tingling
sensation in your limbs "just" a dull feeling from "tiredness," you handle it differently than if you interpret it to
mean that you are getting high, that the drug is beginning to work.
An excellent example comes from marijuana use. Most marijuana smokers have to learn how to achieve the d-
ASC we refer to as marijuana intoxication or being stoned. Typically, the first few times a person smokes
marijuana, he feels an occasional isolated effect like tingling, but the overall pattern of his consciousness stays quite
ordinary and he usually wonders why others make so much fuss about a drug that has so little effect. With the
assistance of more experienced drug users, who suggest he focus his attention on certain kinds of happenings or try
to have certain specified kinds of experiences, additional psychological factors, patterning and disrupting forces, are
brought to bear to disrupt the ordinary d-SoC and pattern the d-ASC. Often the transition takes place quite
suddenly, and the smoker finds that he is now stoned. This is a good illustration of how the physiological action of
the marijuana disrupts many of the ordinary feedback stabilization processes of the ordinary d-SoC, but too few to
destabilize and alter the d-SoC.
The fact that a naive user can smoke enormous amounts of marijuana the first several times without getting
stoned, and then easily get stoned with a tenth as much drug once he has learned how, is paradoxical to
pharmacologists. They call it the reverse tolerance effect. This effect is not at all puzzling in terms of the systems
approach. It simply means that the physiological disrupting and patterning effects of the drug per se are generally
not sufficient to destabilize the b-SoC. Once the user knows how to deploy his attention/awareness properly,
however, this deployment needs only a small boost from the physiological effects of the drug to finally destabilize
the b-SoC and pattern the d-ASC—being stoned.
Indeed, the placebo response of getting stoned on marijuana from which the THC (tetrahydrocannabinol, the
main and perhaps only active ingredient) has been extracted may not illustrate the idea that some people are
hypersuggestible so much as the fact that psychological factors are the main components of the d-ASC associated
with marijuana use.
We should also note that it is a common experience for marijuana users {105} to say they can come down at will,
that if they find themselves in a situation they feel unable to cope with adequately while in the d-ASC of marijuana
intoxication, they can deliberately suppress most or all the effects and temporarily return almost instantly to the
ordinary d-SoC. By psychological methods alone they can disrupt the altered state and pattern their ordinary state
into existence: yet the same amount of THC is still circulating in their bloodstreams.
A third and quite striking example of the importance of psychological factors in determining whether a drug
produces a d-ASC comes from a review by Snyder {60} for the attempts to use marijuana in medicine in the
nineteenth century:
It is striking that so many of these medical reports fail to mention any intoxicating properties of the drug. Rarely, if
ever, there an indication that patients—hundreds of thousands must have received cannabis in Europe in the
nineteenth century—were "stoned," or changed their attitudes toward work, love, their fellow men, or their
homelands...When people see their doctor about a specific malady they expect a specific treatment and do not
anticipate being "turned on."
Apparently, then, unless you have the right kinds of expectations and a "little help from your friends," it is
unlikely that marijuana will produce a d-ASC. Equating the inhalation of marijuana with the existence of a d-ASC
is a tricky business.
This should not be interpreted to mean that marijuana is a weak drug, however. Some people fail to respond to
large doses of far more powerful drugs like LSD.
The results of using the very powerful drugs, like LSD, mescaline, or psilocybin, are extremely variable. Almost
everyone who takes these more powerful psychedelic drugs experiences a disruption of his ordinary d-SoC. The
primary effect of the powerful psychedelic drugs is to disrupt the stabilization processes of the ordinary d-SoC so
that d-SoC breaks down. But, while there is a great deal of commonality of experience among marijuana users (at
least in our cultural setting) {105}, so that it is useful to speak of the "marijuana state" as a distinctive d-ASC across
users, the variability of experience with powerful psychedelics is so great that there seems to be no particular d-
ASC necessarily produced by them. Rather, a highly unstable condition develops characterized by temporary
association of scattered functions in the third part of Figure 7-1 illustrates this. There is a continuous transition
between various kinds of unstable conditions. The colloquial phrase tripping is appropriate: one is continually
going somewhere, but never arriving.[1]
While this is probably true for most experience with powerful psychedelics in our culture, it is not universally
true. Carlos Castaneda's accounts of his work with Don Juan {9-12} indicate that Castaneda's initial reactions to
psychedelic drugs were of this tripping sort. But Don Juan was not interested in having him trip. Among other
things, Don Juan tried to train Castaneda to stabilize the effects of the psychedelic drugs so that he could get into
particular d-ASCs suited to particular kinds of tasks at various times. Thus, the addition of further psychological
patterning forces to the primarily disruptive forces caused by psychedelic drugs enables development of d-ASCs
with particularly interesting properties.
Meanwhile, we should avoid terms like "the LSD state." We should not believe that the statement, "X took LSD"
(or any powerful psychedelic drug), tells us much about what happened to X's consciousness. Indeed, a statement
like "subjects were administered 1.25 micrograms of LSD per kilogram of body weight," commonly found in the
experimental literature, is especially misleading because it seems so precise. It must be replaced by statements like
"subject number 2 was administered such and such as dose of LSD, which then produced a d-ASC of type X, while
subject number 3 did not enter a d-ASC with the same dose of LSD."
I want to emphasize that I am in no way downgrading the potential value of psychedelic drug experiences simply
because they probably seldom become stable d-ASCs in our culture. When used under the right circumstances by
individuals who have been prepared, psychedelic drug experiences can be very valuable. Perhaps the most basic
value is simply the total, experiential demonstration that other modes of awareness exist, that the ordinary d-SoC is
only one of the many possible ways of structuring the mind. Specific insights into a person's ordinary self, which
are valuable for therapy and growth, can also occur, and data and ideas about the nature of the mind can be
obtained. This book is not the place to discuss the growth and therapeutic use of psychedelics: the interesting reader
should consult several chapters in Altered States of Consciousness {88 or 115}.
Footnote
[1] Alternatively, this variability can be interpreted as indicating very rapid transitions from one d-SoC of a few
seconds' duration to another, to another, etc., but as discussed earlier, a d-SoC cannot be readily studied unless it
lasts for a while. (back)
Table 10-1
Values of Variables for Maximizing Probability of Good or Bad Trip
Unknown drug or
unknown
Drug factors Quality Pure, known
degree of (harmful)
adulterants
Known accurately,
adjusted Unknown, beyond
Quantity
to individual's individual's control
desire
Long-term Acceptance, belief Rejection, belief in
Culture
factors in benefits detrimental effects
Unstable, rigid, neurotic,
Personality Stable, open, secure
or psychotic
Specific adverse
Physiology Healthy vulnerability
to drug
Little or no
experience or
Wide experience gained
preparation,
Learned drug skills under supportive
unpleasant
conditions
past
experience
Happy, calm, Depressed, overexcited,
Immediate
Mood relaxed, repressing significant
factors
or euphoric emotions
Expectations Pleasure, insight, Danger, harm,
known manipulation,
eventualitites unknown eventualities
General pleasure, Aimlessness, (repressed)
specific desires to harm or
Desires
user-accepted degrade
goals self for secondary gains
Pleasant and Cold,
Experiment
esthetically impersonal,"medical,"
or Physical
interesting by "psychiatric,"
situation setting
user's "hospital,"
fctors
standards "scientific"
Depersonalization or
Friendly,
manipulation of the
Social events nonmanipulative
user,
interactions overall
hostility
Clear,
Formal understandable, Ambiguous, dishonest,
instructions creating trust and creating mistrust
purpose
Contradictory to explicit
Congruent with
communications and/or
Implicit explicit
reinforcing other
demands communications,
negative
supportive
variables
Observation of internal events is often unreliable and difficult. Focusing on external behavior or physiological
changes in useful, but experiential data are primary in d-SoCs. We must develop a more precise language for
communicating about such data.
Observing oneself means that the overall system must observe itself. Thus, in the conservative view of the mind
self-observation is inherently limited, for the part cannot comprehend the whole and the characteristics of the parts
affect their observation. In the radical view, however, in which awareness is partially or wholly independent of
brain structure, the possibility exists of an Observer much more independent of the structure.
Introspection, the observation of one's own mental processes, and the subsequent communication of these
observations to others have long been major problems in psychology. To build a general scientific understanding
requires starting from a general agreement on what are the facts, what are the basic observations across individuals
on which the science can be founded. Individuals have published interesting and often beautiful accounts of their
own mental processes in the physiological literature, but analysis of these accounts demonstrates little agreement
among them and little agreement among the analyzers that the accounts are precise descriptions of observable
mental processes. Striving for precise understanding is an important goal of science.
One reaction to this has been behaviorism, which ignores mental processes and declares that external behavior,
which can be observed more easily and reliably, is the subject matter of psychology. Many psychologists still accept
the behavioristic position and define psychology as the study of behavior rather than the study of the mind. That
way is certainly easier. One hundred percent agreement among observers is possible, at least for simple behaviors.
For example, in testing for susceptibility to hypnosis with the Stanford Hypnotic Susceptibility Scale {144}, the
examiner suggests to the subject that his arm is feeling heavier and heavier and will drop because of the increased
weight. The hypnotists and observers present can easily agree on whether the subject's arm moves down at least
twelve inches within thirty seconds after the end of the suggestion.
Behaviorism is an extremely valuable tool for studying simple behaviors, determining what affects them, and
learning how to control them. But it has not been able to deal well with complex and important human experiences,
such as happiness, love, religious feelings, purposes. The behavioristic approach is of particularly limited value in
dealing with d-ASCs because almost all the interesting and important d-ASC phenomena are completely internal. A
behavioristic approach to the study of a major psychedelic drug like LSD, for example, would lead to the
conclusion that LSD is a sedative or tranquilizer, since the behavior frequently produced is sitting still and doing
nothing!
If we are to understand d-SoCs, introspection must become an important technique in psychology in spite of the
difficulties of its application. I have primarily used peoples' reports of their internal experiences in developing the
systems approach, even though these reports are undoubtedly affected by a variety of biases, limitations, and
inadequacies, for such reports are the most relevant data for studying d-SoCs.
I believe psychology's historical rejection of introspection was premature: in the search for general laws of the
mind, too much was attempted too soon. Mental phenomena are the most complex phenomena of all. The physical
sciences, by comparison, deal with easy subject matter. We can be encouraged by the fact that many spiritual
psychologies {128} have developed elaborate vocabularies for describing internal experiences. I do not understand
these psychologies well enough to evaluate the validity of these vocabularies, but it is encouraging that others,
working over long periods, have at least developed such vocabularies. The English language is well suited for
making reliable discriminations among everyday external objects, but it is not a good language for precise work
with physical reality. The physical sciences have developed specialized mathematical languages for such work that
are esoteric indeed to the man in the street. Sanskrit, on the other hand, has many presumably precise words for
internal events and states that do not translate well into English. There are over twenty words in Sanskrit, for
example, which carry different shades of meaning in the original. Development of a more precise vocabulary is
essential to progress in understanding consciousness and d-SoCs. If you say you feel "vibrations" in a d-ASC, what
precisely do you mean?
The Observer
In science the word observation usually refers to scrutiny of the external environment, and the observer is taken
for granted. If the observer is recognized as possessing inherent characteristics that limit his adequacy to observe,
these specific characteristics are compensated for, as by instrumentally aiding the senses or adding some constant to
the observation; again the observer is taken for granted. In dealing with the microworld, the particle level in
physics, the observer cannot be taken for granted, for the process of observation alters the phenomena being
observed. Similarly, when experiential data are used to understand states of consciousness, the observation process
cannot be taken for granted.
For the system to observe itself, attention/awareness must activate structures that are capable of observing
processes going on in other structures. Two ways of doing this seem possible, which we shall discuss as pure cases,
even though they may actually be mixed. The first way is to see the system breaking down into two semi-
independent systems, one of which constitutes the observer and the other the system to be observed. I notice, for
example, that I am rubbing my left foot as I write and that this action seems irrelevant to the points I want to make.
A moment ago I was absorbed in the thinking involved in the writing and in rubbing my foot, but some part of me
then stepped back for a moment, under the impetus to find an example to illustrate the current point, and noticed
that I was rubbing my foot. The "I" who observed that I was rubbing my foot is my ordinary self, my personality,
my ordinary d-SoC. The major part of my system held together, but temporarily singled out a small, connected part
of itself to be observed. Since I am still my ordinary self, all my characteristics enter into the observation. There is
no objectivity to my own observation of myself. My ordinary self, for example, is always concerned with whether
what I am doing is useful toward attaining my short-term and long-term goals; thus the judgment was automatically
made that the rubbing of the foot was a useless waste of energy. Having immediately classified foot-rubbing as
useless, I had no further interesting in observing it more clearly, seeing what it was like. The observation is mixed
with evaluation; most ordinary observation is of this nature.
By contrast, many meditative disciplines take the view that attention/awareness can achieve a high degree or
even complete independence from the structures that constitute a person's ordinary d-SoC and personality, that a
person possesses (or can develop) an Observer that is highly objective with respect to the ordinary personality
because it is an Observer that is essentially pure attention/awareness, that has no judgmental characteristics of its
own. If the Observer had been active, I might have observed that I was rubbing my foot, but there would have been
no structure immediately activated that passed judgment on this action. Judgment, after all, means relatively
permanent characteristics coded in structure to make comparisons against. The Observer would simply have noted
whatever was happening without judging it.
The existence of the Observer or Witness is a reality to many people, especially those who have attempted to
develop such an Observer by practicing meditative disciplines, and I shall treat it as an experiential reality.
The question of its ultimate reality is difficult. If one starts from the conservative view of the mind, where
awareness is no more than a product of the nervous system and brain, the degree of independence or objectivity of
the Observer can only be relative. The Observer may be a semi-independent system with fewer characteristics than
the overall system of consciousness as a whole, but it is dependent on the operation of neurologically based
structures and so is ultimately limited and shaped by them; it is also programmed to some extent in the
enculturation process. Hilgard {26} has found the concept of such a partially dissociated Observer useful in
understanding hypnotic analgesia.
In the radical view of the mind, awareness is (or can become) different from the brain and nervous system. Here
partial to total independence of, and objectivity with respect to, the mind/brain can be attained by the Observer. The
ultimate degree of this objectivity then depends on whether awareness per se, whatever its ultimate nature is, has
properties that limit it.
It is not always easy to make this clear distinction between the observer and the Observer. Many times, for
example, when I am attempting to function as a Observer, I Observe myself doing certain things, but this
Observation immediately activates some aspect of the structure of my ordinary personality, which then acts as an
observer connected with various value judgment that are immediately activated. I pass from the function of
Observing from outside the system to observing from inside the system, from what feels like relatively objective
Observation to judgmental observation by my conscience or superego.
Some meditative disciplines, as in the vipassana meditation discussed earlier, strive to enable their practitioners
to maintain the Observer for long periods, possibly permanently. The matter becomes rather complex, however,
because a major job for the Observer is to Observe the actions of the observer: having Observed yourself doing
some action, you then Observe your conscience become activated, rather than becoming completely caught up in
the conscience observation and losing the Observer function. Such self-observation provides much data for
understanding the structure of one's own consciousness. For a comprehensive discussion of this method of
understanding, I refer the reader to Riodan's and Goleman's chapter in Transpersonal Psychologies {128}.
The distinction between these two kinds of observers is important in considering the transition period between
two d-SoCs. If we ask questions about what phenomena are experienced during the transition period, we must ask
who is going to make these experiential observations for us. Since the ordinary observer is the structure, then the
radical destructuring necessary for transition into a d-ASC eliminates the ability to observe. At worst, if there is
total destructuring we can expect no direct experiential observation of the transitional period, perhaps only a feeling
of blankness. Such blackouts are often reported.
Yet people do report transitional experiences. Destructuring of the b-SoC may not be total, certain parts of it may
hold together a subsystems through the transition period, partial observations may be made by these subsystems,
and such observations are recoverable on return to the b-SoC or in the d-ASC. But the observations are necessarily
limited and incomplete, since they come from a partially incapacitated observer.
Now consider the role of the Observer, if it is well developed in a particular person, during the transition from
one d-SoC to another. Because the Observer is either not at all based in particular structures, only partially based in
particular structures, or based in structures that are not part of the b-SoC undergoing destructuring, it should be able
to observe transitional phenomena. Exactly this sort of phenomenal report has come from reporters who feel they
have a fairly well-developed Observer. They believe this Observer can make essentially continuous observations
not only within a particular d-SoC but during the transition among two or more d-SoCs.
For example, Evans-Wentz {17} describes the following Tibetan yogic exercise for comprehending the nature of
dreaming:
That which hath been called "the initial comprehending of the dream," refereth to resolving to maintain unbroken
continuity of consciousness throughout both the waking-state and the dream-state...sleep on the right side, as a lion
doth. With the thumb and ring-finger of the right hand press the pulsation of the throat-arteries; stop the nostrils
with the fingers (of the left and); and let the saliva collect in the throat.
Evans-Wentz comments:
As a result of these methods, the yogin enjoys as vivid consciousness in the dream-state as in the waking-state; and
in passing from one state in another experiences no break in the continuity of memory.
I can say no more about the nature of the Observer here because we know so little about it in our Western
scientific tradition. However, I think it is extremely important to find out to what extent the Observer's apparent
objectivity is a reality and to what extent a fiction. Insofar as it is a reality, it offers an objectivity and a possible
escape from cultural consensus reality conditionings that are highly important.
I must, however, caution the reader against taking this discussion of the Observer too concretely. I am using
words to describe a certain kind of experience, but the words are not the experience. As Korzybski said: "The map
is not the territory." Unfortunately, we not only habitually mistake the map for the territory, we prefer the map to the
territory—it is so much clearer! I find it difficult to express the concept of Observing, and words can do no more
than create analogies that point to aspects of your own experiences. The term Observer is a way of referring to an
important aspect of experience, a process, but we must not become too attached to the concept of one "thing"
separate from and observing another "thing
Self-observation, observation of others, and psychoanalytic data indicate that various stimuli can produce marked
reorgnaizations of ego functioning very rapdily, even though these all remain within the consensus reality
definitions of "normal" consciousness. These identity states are much like d-SoCs and can be sutdied in the systems
approach framework. They are hard to observe in ordinary life because of the ease and rapidity of transiton, their
emotional charge, and other reasons. The isolation of knowledge and experience in various identity states is
responsible for much of the psychopathology of everyday life.
The concept of d-SoCs comes to us in commonsense form, as well as in terms of my initial research interests,
from people's experiences of radically altered states of consciousness—states like drunkenness, dreaming,
marijuana intoxication, certain meditative states. These represent such radical shifts in the patterning, the system
properties of consciousness, that most people experiencing them are forced to notice that the state of their
consciousness is quite different, even if they are poor observers. A person need not have developed an Observer in
order to notice such a change in his state of consciousness: so many things are so clearly different that the
observation is forced on him.
Although this is the origin and the main focus of the concept of d-SoCs, the systems approach is applicable to
important variations occurring within the overall pattern we call the ordinary d-SoC, variations that can be termed
identity states. My own self-observation and much scattered psychological data, particulary data gathered in the
course of psychoanalytic investigations, indicate that as different situations impinge on a person and activate
different emotional drives, distinct changes in the organization of his ego can take place. Certain drives become
inhibited or activated, and the whole constellation of psychological functioning alters its configuration around them.
The most cogent formulation of these data into a comprehensive picture is that of the Armenian philosopher and
spiritual teacher, George Gurdjieff. The following selection from Ouspensky's report of Gurdjieff's early lectures
{48, pp. 59-60} expresses Gurdjieff's idea that we have many "I's," many little egos:
"One of man's important mistakes," he said, "one which must be remembered, is his illusion in regard to his I.
"Man such as we know him, the 'man machine,' the man who cannot 'do,' and with whom and through whom
everything 'happens,' cannot have a permanent and single I. His I changes as quickly as his thoughts, feelings, and
moods, and he makes a rpofound mistake in considering himself always one and the same person; in reality he is
always a different person, not the one he was a moment ago.
"Man has no permanent and unchangeable I. Every thought, every mood, every deisre, every sensation, says 'I.'
And in each case it seems to be taken for granted that this I belongs o the Whole, to the whole man, and that a
thought, a desire, or an aversion is expressed by this Whole. In actual fact there is no foudnation whatever for this
assumption. Man's every thought and desire appears and lives quite separately and independently of the Whole. And
the Whole never expresses itself, for the simple reason that it exists, as such, only physically as a thing, and in the
abstract as a concept. Man has no individual I. But there are, instead, hundreds and thousands of separate small I's,
very often entirely unknown to one another, never coming into contact, or, on the contrary, hostile to each other,
mutually exclusive and incompatible. Each minute, each moment, man is saying or thinking 'I.' And each time his I
is different. Just now it was a thought, now it is a desire, now a sensation, now another thought, and so on,
endlessly. Man is a plurality. Man's name is legion.
"The alternation of I's, their continual obvious struggle for supremacy, is controlled by accidental external
influences. Warmth, sunshine, fine weather, immediately call up a whole group of I's. Cold, fog, rain, call up
another group of I's, other associations, other feelings, other actions. There is nothing in man able to control this
change of I's, chiefly because man does not notice, or know of it; he lives always in the last I. Some I's, of course,
are stronger than others. But it is not hteir own conscious strength; they have been created by the strength of
accidnets or mechanical external stimuli. Education, imitation, reading, the hypnotism of religion, caste, and
traditions, or the glamour of new slogans, create very strong I's in man's personality, which dominate whole series
of other, weaker, I's. But their strength is the dtrength of the 'rolls'[1] in the centers. "And all I's making up a man's
personality have the same origin as these 'rolls'; they are the results of external influences; and both are set in
motion and controlled by fresh external influences.
"Man has no individuality. He has no single, big I. Man is divided into a multiplicity of small I's.
"And each separate small I is able to call itself by the name of the Whole, to act in the name of the Whole, to
agree or disagree, to give promises, to make decisions, with which another I or the Whole will have to deal. This
explains why people so often make decisions and so seldom carry them out. A man decides to get up early
beginning from the following day. One I, or a group of I's, decide this. but getting up is the business of another I
who entirely disagrees with the decision and may even know absolutely nothing about it. Of course the man will
again go on sleeping in the morning and in the evening he will again decide to get up early. In some cases this may
assume very unpleasant consequences for a man. A small accidental I may promise something, not to itself, but to
someone else at a certain moment simply out of vanity or for amusement. Then it disappears, but the man, that is,
the whole combination of other I's who are quite innocent of this, may have to pay for it all his life. It is the tragedy
of the human being that any small I has the right to sign checks and promissory notes and the man, that is, the
Whole, has to meet them.
People's whole lives often consist in paying off the promissory notes of small accidental I's."
Gurdjieff's concept of these rapdily alternating I's is similar to the systems approach concept of d-SoCs. If we call
each I an identity state, then each (1) has an overall pattern of functioning, a gestalt, which gives it a system identity
and distinguishes it from other identity states; (2) is composed of structures/subsystems, psychological functions,
skills, memories; (3) possesses unique properties not present in other identity states; (4) presumably has some
stabilizing processes, although apparently fewer than the ordinary d-SoC as a whole, since identity states can
change so rapdily; (5) functions as a tool for coping with the world, with varying degrees of effectiveness; and (6)
requires an induction process to transit from one identity state to another, a requisite stimulus to bring on a new
identity state.
These alterations in functioning that I call identity states can thus be usefully studied with the systems approach
to consciousness. Yet they are almost never identified as d-SoCs in ordinary people, for several reasons.
First, each person has a large repertoire of these identity states and transits between one and another of them
extremely readily, practically instantly. Thus, no obvious lapses or transitional phenomena occur that would make
him likely to notice the transitions.
Second, all these identity states share much psychological functioning in common, such as speaking English,
responding to the same proper name, wearing the same sets of clothes. Thse many common properties amke
differences difficult to notice.
Third, all a person's ordinarily used identity states share in his culturally defined consensus reality. Although
certain aspects of reality are emphasized by particular identity states, the culture as a whole implicitly allows a wide
variety of identity states in its definitions of "normal" consciousness and consensus reality. Within the cultural
consensus reality, for example, there are well-understood concepts, perceptions, and allowed behaviors associated
with being angry, being sad, feeling sexual desire, being afraid.
Fourth, a person's identification is ordinarily very high, complete, with each of these identity states. He projects
the feeling of "I" onto it (the Sense of Identity subsystem function discussed in Chapter 8). This, coupled with the
culturally instilled need to believe that he is a single personality, causes him to gloss over distinctions. Thus he says,
"I am angry," "I am sad," rather than, "A state of sadness has organized mental functioning differently from a state
of anger." The culture also reinforces a person for behaving as if he were a unity.
Fifth, identity states are driven by needs, fears, attachments, defensive, maneuvers, coping mechanisms, and this
highly charged quality of an identity state makes it unlikely that the person involved will be engaged in self-
observation.
Sixth, many identity states have, as a central focus, emotional needs and drives that are socially unacceptable or
only partially acceptable. Given the fact that people need to feel accepted, an individual may have many important
reasons for not noticing that he has discrete identity states. Thus, when he is in a socially "normal" identity state,
being a good person, he may be unable to be aware of a different identity state that sometimes occurs in which he
hates his best friend. The two states are incompatible, so automatized defense mechanisms (Gurdjieff calls them
buffers) prevent him from being aware of the one identity state while in the other. This is, in systems approach
terminology, state-specific knowledge. Ordinarily, special psychotherapists techniques are required to make a
person aware of these contradictory feelings and identity states within himself. Meditative practices designed to
create the Observer also facilitate this sort of knowledge.
The development of an Observer can allow a person considerable access to observing different identity states. An
outside observer can often clearly infer different identity states, but a person who has not developed the Observer
function well may never notice his many transitions from one identity state to another. Thus ordinary
consciousness, or what society values as "normal" consciousness, may actually consist of a large number of d-SoCs,
identity states. But the overall similarities between these identity states and the difficulty of observing them, for the
reasons discussed above, lead us to think of ordinary consciousness as relatively unitary state.
Gurdjieff sees the rapid, unnoticed transitions between identity states, and their relative isolation from one
another, as the major cause of the psychopathology of everyday life. I agree with him, and believe this topic
deserves intensive psychological research.
An identity state, like a d-SoC, has coping functions. The culture a person is born into actively inhibits some of
his human potentials, as well as developing some. Thus, even in the most smoothly functioning cultures, there is
bound to be some disharmony, some conflict between a person's emerging and potential self and he demands placed
on him to which he must conform in one way or another if he is to survive in that social environment. The
psychopathology of everyday life is abundantly obvious and has been amply documented by psychological studies.
At the fringes of consciousness, then, there is a vast unknown, not simply of relatively neutral potentials that
never developed, but of emotionally and cognitively frightening things, conflicts that were never resolved,
experiences that did not fit consensus reality, feelings that were never expressed, problems that were never faced.
Immersion is consensus reality in the oridnary d-SoC is a protection from this potentially frightening and
overwhelming unknown; it is the safe, cultivated clearing in the dark, unexplored forest of the mind.
An identity state is a specialized version of the ordinary d-SoC, a structure acceptable to consensus reality
(ignoring obviously pathological identity states). The extrainformational "This is me" quality from the Sense of
Identity subsystem added to certain contents/structures constellates the energies of consciousness around them and
produces an identity, a role[2] that a person partially or completely identified with for the time. The identity "eats
energy."
A particular identity state thus acts as loading stabilization for the oridnary d-SoC; it absorbs much available
energy that might otherwise activate unknown and perhaps implicitly feared contents that are not acceptable. When
you "know" who are, when you take on an identity state, then you immediately have criteria for dealing with
various situations. If I am a "father" in this moment I know that certain things are expected and desired of me and I
can cope well within that framework with situations involving my children. If the situation changes and I now
become a "professor," then I have a new set of rules on how to cope with situations involving people who have
identified with the roles of "students."
Some of a person's most important problems arise when his is in an identity state that is not really suited to the
situation: my children are unhappy when I am a professor when they want a father, and I am not comfortable when
my students want me to be like a father when I think the role of professor is more appropriate.
Being caught in a situation in which one has no ready role to use and identify with is unusual. For most people
such situations can be lightly confusing or frightening, since they do not know how to think or act. They can bcome
susceptible to any authority who offers ready-made roles/solutions in such situations. If the country is "going to
hell" and nobody seems to have any answer, it may feel much better to be a "patriot" and blame "traitors" than to
live with your confusion. On the other hand, lack of an immediately available role can offer a unique opportunity to
temporarily escape from the tyranny of roles.
Once a person has identified with a role, the resulting identity state stabilizes his d-SoC not only through loading
stabilization, but through the other three stabilization processes discussed in Chapter 6. When he is coping
successfully and thus feeling good in a particular identity state, this constitutes positive feedback stabilization; he
tends to engage in more thoughts and actions that expand and strengthen the identity state. If the fear of having no
identity is strong and/or the rewards from a particular identity state are high, this can hinder escape from that
identity state. Consider how many successful businessmen work themselves to death, not knowing how to stop
being businessmen for even short periods, or how many men die within a few years of retiring, not having their
work identity to sustain them.
Success from being in a particular identity state encourages a person to avoid or suppress thoughts and actions
that tends to disrupt that state: this is negative feedback stablization. A "good soldier" is obtaining valuable
information about enemy troop movements—information that may save the lives of his buddies—by torturing a
native child: he actively suppresses his own identity state of a "father" is order to function effectively in his "soldier'
identity.
Being in a particular identity state also functions as limiting stabilization. The identity leads to selective
perception to make perceptions congruent with the reigning identity state. Certain kinds of perceptions that might
activate other identity states are repressed. The tortured child is perceived as an "enemy agent," not as a "child."
This keeps emotional and attention/awareness energy out of empathic processes that, if activated, would undermine
and disrupt the "soldier" identity.
Identity states, then, are both tools for coping with the environment and ways of avoiding the unknown. The
degree to which they srve mainly one or the other funciton probably varies tremendously form individual to
individual and identity to identity. Some people are terribly afraid of anything outside the few narrow identities they
always function in: by staying in one of the other of those identity states constantly, they never feel the fear of the
unknown. Others have less fear of the unknown, but find the rewards from functioning in a few identity states are
so high that they have no real need or interest to go outside them. The latter type probably characterizes a stable,
well-integrated society, with most citizens quite content in a socially accepted identity states.
For discussion of radically altered discrete states like hypnosis or drunkenness, the concept of the ordinary d-
SoC as relatively unitary is useful. As the systems approach becomes more articulated, however, we shall have to
deal with these identity states that exist within the boundaries of the ordinary d-SoC and that probably also function
within the boundaries of various d-ASCs.
In this book, I continue to use the terms discrete state of consciousness and discrete altered state of
consciousness to refer to the rather radical alterations like hypnosis or drunkenness that gave rise to the concept in
the first place. I use the phrase identity state to indicate the more subtle division.
Footnotes
[1] The analogy is to old phonograph rolls: we would say "programs" with a computer analogy today [C.T.]
(back)
[2] I use the term role to indicate that a person consciously knows he is acting a part that is not really him, and
the term identity state to mean he has become the part. Clearly, the degree of identification can vary rapidly. (back)
13. Strategies in Using the Systems Approach
The systems approach generates a number of strategies for studying states of consciousness. Some of these are
unique consequences of using a system approach, some are just good-sense strategies that could come from other
approaches. Many of these methodological strategies have been touched on in previous chapters; some are brought
out in later chapters. Here I bring together most of these methodological points and introduce some new ones.
Realizing that the ordinary d-SoC is not natural and given, but constructed according to semiarbitrary cultural
constraints, gives us the freedom to ask some basic questions that might not otherwise occur to us. And it should
make us more cautious about labeling other states as "pathological" and other cultures as "primitive." The
Australian bushmen, for example, are almost universally considered one of the world's most primitive cultures
because of their nomadic life and their paucity of material possessions. Yet Pearce {49} argues that, from another
point of view, these people are among the most sophisticated in the world, for they have organized their entire
culture around achieving a certain d-ASC, which they refer to as the experience of "Dream Time." Our bias toward
material possessions, however, makes us unable to see this.
Recognizing the semiarbitrary nature of the system of the ordinary d-SoC that has been constructed in our culture
should make us especially aware of the implicit assumptions built into it, assumptions were so taken for granted
that it never occurs to us to question them. In Transpersonal Psychologies {128}, nine expert practitioners of
various spiritual disciplines wrote about their disciplines not as religions, but as psychologies. In the course of
editing these contributions, I was increasingly struck by the way certain assumptions are made in various spiritual
psychologies that are different from or contrary to those made in Western psychology. As a result, I wrote a chapter
outlining several dozen assumptions that have become implicit for Western psychologies and that, by virtue of
being implicit, have great control over us.
I have found that when asked what some of these assumptions are, I have great difficulty recalling them: I have
to go back and look at what I wrote! Although my study of systems that make different assumptions brought these
implicit assumptions to mind, they have already sunk back to the implicit assumptions to mind, they have already
sunk back to the implicit level. We should not underestimate the power of culturally given assumptions in
controlling us, and we cannot overestimate the importance of trying to come to grips with them.
We should also recognize that the enculturation process, discussed earlier, ties the reward and punishment
subsystems to the maintenance and defense of ordinary consensus reality. We are afraid of experiencing d-ASCs
that are foreign to us and this fear strengthens our tendency to classify them as abnormal or pathological and to
avoid them. It also further strengthens our resolve to deal with all reality from the point of view of the ordinary d-
SoC, using only the tool or coping function of the ordinary d-SoC. But since the ordinary d-SoC is a limited tool,
good for some things but not for others, we invariable distort parts of reality. The tendency to ignore or fight what
we do not consider valuable and to distort our perceptions to make them fit is good for maintaining a cohesive
social system, but poor for promoting scientific inquiry. A possible solution is the proposal for establishing state-
specific sciences, discussed in Chapter 16.
The systems approach stresses the importance of attention/awareness as an activating energy within any d-SoC.
Yet if we ask what awareness is or how we direct it and so call it attention, we cannot supply satisfactory answers.
We may deal with this problem simply by taking basic awareness for granted, as we are forced to do at this level
of development of the systems approach, and work with it even though we do not know what it is. After all, we do
not really know what gravity is in any ultimate sense, but we can measure what it does and from that information
develop, for example, a science of ballistics. We can learn much about d-SoCs in the systems approach if we just
take basic awareness and attention/awareness energy for granted, but we must eventually focus on questions about
the nature of awareness. We will have to consider the conservative and radical views of the mind to determine
whether awareness is simply the product of brain and nervous system functioning or whether it is something more.
System Qualities
The systems approach emphasizes that even though a d-SoC is made up of components, the overall system has
gestalt qualities that cannot be predicted from knowledge of the components alone. Thus, while investigation of the
components, the subsystems and structures, is important, such investigative emphasis must be balanced by studies
of the overall system's functioning. We must become familiar with the pattern of the overall system's functioning so
we can avoid wasting energy on researching components that turn out to be relatively unimportant in the overall
system. We might, for example, avoid spending excessive research effort and money, as is now being done, on
investigating physiological effects of marijuana intoxication, as we have seen, indicates that psychological factors
are at least as important as the drug factor in determining the nature of the d-ASC produced.
The systems approach also emphasizes the need to examine the system's functioning under the conditions in
which it was designed to function. We are not yet sure what, if anything, d-ASCs are particularly designed for, what
particular they have. We must find this out. On the other hand, we should try not to waste effort studying d-ASCs
under conditions they were clearly not designed for. For example, conducting studies that show a slight decrement
in arithmetical skills under marijuana intoxication is of some interest, but since no record exists of anyone using
marijuana in order to solve arithmetical problems, such studies are somewhat irrelevant. This emphasizes a point
made earlier: that it is generally useless to characterize any d-ASC as "better" or "worse" than any other d-SoC. The
question should always be, "Better or worse for what particular task?" All d-ASCs we know of seem to associated
with improved functioning for certain kinds of tasks and worsened functioning for others.[1] An important research
aim, then, is to find out what d-ASCs are optimal for particular tasks and how to train people to enter efficiently
into that d-ASC when they need to perform that task. This runs counter to a strong, implicit assumption in our
culture that the ordinary d-SoC is the best one for all tasks; that assumption is highly questionable when it is made
explicit. Remember that in any d-SoC there is a limited selection from the full range of human potential. While
some of these latent human potentials may be developable in the ordinary d-SoC, some are more available in a d-
ASC. Insofar as we consider some of these potentials valuable, we must learn what d-SoCs they are operable in and
how to train them for good functioning within those d-SoCs.
This last point is not an academic issue: enormous numbers of people are now personally experimenting with d-
ASCs to attain some of these potentials. While much gain will undoubtedly come out of this personal
experimentation, we should also expect much loss.
Individual Differences
As we have seen, what for one individual is a d-ASC may, for another individual, be merely part of the region of
his ordinary d-SoC, one continuous experiential space. By following the common experimental procedure of using
group data rather than data from individual subjects, we can (Chapter 9) get the impression of continuity (one d-
SoC) when two or more d-SoCs actually occurred within the experimental procedure. We should indeed search for
general laws of the mind that hold across individuals, but we must beware of enunciating such laws prematurely
without first understanding the behavior and experiences of the individuals within our experiments.
Recognizing the importance of individual differences has many application outside the laboratory. If a friend tries
some spiritual technique and has a marvelous experience as a result, and you try the same technique with no result,
there is not necessarily something wrong with you. Rather, because of differences in the structures of your ordinary
d-SoCs, that particular technique mobilizes attention/awareness energy in an effective way to produce a certain
experience for him, but is not an effective techniques for you.
Operationalism is a way of rigorously defining some concept by describing the actual operations required to
produce it. Thus an operational definition of the concept of "nailing" is defined by the operations (1) pick up a
hammer in your right hand; (2) pick up a nail in your left hand; (3) put the point of the nail on a wood surface and
hold the nail perpendicular to the wood surface; (4) strike the head of the nail with the hammer and then lift the
hammer again; and (5) repeat step 4 until the head of the nail is flush with the surface of the wood. An operational
definition is a precise definition, allowing total reproducibility.
Some claim that whatever cannot be defined operationally is not a legitimate subject for scientific investigation.
That is silly. No one can precisely specify all the steps necessary to experience "being in love," but that is hardly
justification for ignoring the state of being in love as an important human situation worthy of study. A further
problem is that in psychology, operationalism implicitly means physical operationalism, specifying the overt,
physically observable steps in a process in order to define it. In the search for an objectivity like that of the physical
sciences, psychologists emphasize aspects of their discipline that can be physically measured, but often at the cost
of irrelevant studies.
An example is the equating of the hypnotic state, the d-ASC of hypnosis, with the performance of the hypnotic
induction procedure. The hypnotic state is a psychological construct or, if induction has been successful, an
experiential reality to the hypnotized person. It is not defined by external measurements. There are no obvious
behavioral manifestations that clearly indicate hypnosis has occurred and no known physiological changes that
invariably accompany hypnosis. The hypnotic procedure, on the other had, the words that they hypnotist says aloud,
is highly amenable to physical measurement. An investigator can film the hypnotic procedure, tape-record the
hypnotist's voice, measure the sound intensity of the hypnotist's voice, and accumulate a variety of precise,
reproducible physical measurements. But that investigator makes a serious mistake if he then describes the
responses of the "hypnotized subject" and means by "hypnotized subject" the person to whom the hypnotist said the
words. The fact that the hypnotist performs the procedure does not guarantee that the subject enters the d-ASC of
hypnosis. As discussed earlier, a person's b-SoC is multiply stabilized, and no single induction procedure or
combination of induction procedures will, with certainty, destabilize the ordinary state and produce a particular d-
ASC.
I stress that the concept of the d-SoC is a psychological, experiential construct. Thus, the ultimate criterion for
determining whether a person is in a d-ASC is a map of his experiences that shows him to be in a region of
psychological space we have termed a d-ASC. The external performance of an induction technique is not the same
as achievement of the desired d-ASC. A hypnotic induction procedure does not necessarily induce hypnosis; lying
down in bed does not necessarily induce sleeping or dreaming; performing a meditation exercise does not
necessarily induce a meditative state.
When an induction procedure is physiological, as when a drug is used, the temptation to equate the induction
procedure with the altered state is especially great. But the two are not the same, even in this case. As discussed in
Chapter 10, smoking marijuana does not necessarily cause a transition out of the b-SoC. Nor, as is shown in
Chapter 14, is knowledge of the dose of the drug an adequate specification of depth.
We do need to describe techniques in detail in our reports of d-ASCs, but we must also specify the degree to
which these techniques were actually effective in altering a subject's state of consciousness, and we must specify
this for each individual subject. In practice, physiological criteria may be sometimes so highly correlated with
experiential reports indicating a d-ASC that those criteria can be considered an indicator that the d-ASC has
occurred. This is the case with stage 1 REM dreaming. Behavioral criteria may be similarly correlated with
experiential data, though I am not sure any such criteria are well correlated at present. But the primary criteria are
well correlated at present. But the primary criterion is an actual assessment of the kind of experiential space the
subject is in that indicates the induction procedure was effective.
Operationalism, then, which uses external, physical, and behavioral criteria, is inadequate for dealing with many
of the most important phenomena of d-ASCs. Most of the phenomena that define d-ASCs are internal and may
never show obvious behavioral or physiological[2] manifestations.
Ultimately we need an experiential operationalism, a set of statements such as (1) if you stop all evaluation
processes for at least three minutes, (2) and you concurrently invest no attention/awareness energy into the
Interoception subsystem for perceiving the body, (3) so that all perception of the body fades out, then (4) you will
experience a mental phenomenon of such and such a type. Our present language is not well suited to this, as
discussed earlier, so we are a long way from a good experiential operationalism. The level of precision of
understanding and communication that an experiential operationalism will bring is very high; nevertheless, we
should not overvalue operationalism and abandon hope of understanding a phenomenon we cannot define
operationally.
Implicit in the act of mapping an individual's psychological experiences is the assumption of a reasonable degree
of stability of the individual's structure and functioning over time. The work necessary to obtain a map would be
wasted if the map had to be changed before it had been used.
Ordinarily we assume that an individual's personality or ordinary d-SoC is reasonably stable over quite long
periods, generally over a lifetime once his basic personality has been formed by late adolescence. Exceptions to this
assumption occur when individuals are exposed to severe, abnormal conditions, such as disasters, which may
radically alter parts of their personality structure, or to psychotherapy and related psychological growth techniques.
Although the personality change following psychotherapy is often rather small, leaving the former map of the
individual's personality relatively useful, it is sometimes quite large.
The validity of assuming this kind of stability in relation to research on d-SoCs is questionable. The people who
are most interested in experiencing d-ASCs are dissatisfied with the ordinary d-SoC and so may be actively trying
to change it. But studies confined to people not very interested in d-ASCs (so-called naive subjects) may be dealing
with an unusual group who are afraid of d-ASCs. Stability of the b-SoC or of repeatedly induced d-ASCs is
something to be assessed, not assumed. This is particularly true for a person's early experiences with a d-ASC,
where he is learning how to function in the d-ASC with each new occurrence. In my study of the experiences of
marijuana intoxication {103, 105}. I deliberately excluded users who had had less than a dozen experiences of
being stoned on marijuana. The experience of these naive users would have mainly reflect learning to cope with a
new state, rather than the common, stable characteristics of the d-ASC of being stoned.
An individual may eventually learn to merge two d-SoCs into one. The merger may be a matter of transferring
some state-specific experiences and potentials back into the ordinary state, so that eventually most or many state-
specific experiences are available in the ordinary state. The ordinary state, in turn, undergoes certain changes in its
configuration. Or, growth or therapeutic work at the extremes of functioning of two d-SoCs may gradually bring the
two closer until experiences are possible all through the former "forbidden region."
Pseudomerging of two d-SoCs may also be possible. As an individual more and more frequently makes the
transitions between the two states, he may automate the transition process to the point where he no longer has any
awareness of it, and/or efficient routes through the transition process are so thoroughly learned that the transition
takes almost no tie or effort. Then, unless the individual or an observer was examining his whole pattern of
functioning, his state of consciousness might appear to be single simply because transitions were not noticed. This
latter case would be like the rapid, automated transitions between identity states within the ordinary state of
consciousness.
Since a greater number of human potentials are available in two states than in one, such merging or learning of
rapid transitions can be seen as growth. Whether the individual or his culture sees it as growth depends on cultural
valuations of the added potentials and the individual's own intelligence in actual utilization of the two states. The
availability of more potentials does not guarantee their wise or adaptive use.
The sequential strategies for investigating d-SoCs that follow from the systems approach are outlined below.
These strategies are idealistic and subject to modification in practice.
First, the general experiential, behavioral or physiological components of a rough concept of a particular d-ASC
are mapped. The data may come from informal interviews with a number of people who have experienced that
state, from personal experiences in that d-ASC. This exercise supplies a feeling for the overall territory and its main
features.
Then the experiential space of various individuals is mapped to determine whether their experiences show the
distinctive clusterings and patternings that constitute d-SoCs. This step overlaps somewhat with the first, for the
investigator assumes or has data to indicate a distinctness about the d-ASC for at least some individuals as a start of
his interest.
For individuals who show this discreteness, the third step of more detailed individual investigation is carried out.
For those who do not, studies are begun across individuals to ascertain why some show various discrete states and
others do not: in addition to recognizing the existence of individual differences, the researcher must find out why
they exist and what function they serve.
The third step is to map the various d-SoCs of particular individuals in detail. What are the main features of each
state? What induction procedures produce the state? What deinduction procedures cause a person to transit out of
it? What are the limits of stability of the state? What uses, advantages does the state have? What disadvantages or
dangers? How is the depth measured? What are the convenient marker phenomena to rapidly measure depth?
With this background, the investigator can profitable ask questions about interindividual similarities of the
various discrete states. Are they really enough alike across individuals to warrant a common state name? If so, does
this relate mainly to cultural background similarities of the individuals studied or to some more fundamental aspect
of the nature of the human mind?
Finally, even more detailed studies can be done on the nature of particular discrete states and the
structures/subsystems comprising them. This sort of investigation should come at a late stage to avoid premature
reductionism: we must not repeat psychology's early mistake of trying to find the universal Laws of the Mind
before we have good empirical maps of the territory.
Footnotes
[1] Objectivity is hard to maintain here, for functions that are improved in a particular d-SoC may not be valued
functions for the culture of the investigator. The first thing we can do is be explicit about our value judgments,
rather than pretending we do not make them. (back)
[2] I refer to present-day levels of physiological measurement: in principle, if we could measure the
microstructures of the brain finely enough, we could distinguish d-ASCs that are presently not distinguishable from
scalp recordings of brain activity. (back)
"According the general opinion of the uninitiated," mused Nasrudin, as he walked along the road, "dervishes are
mad. According to the sages, however, they are the true masters of the world. I would like to test one, and myself,
to make sure."
Then he saw a tall figure, robed like a Akldan dervish—reputed to be exceptionally enlightened men—coming
towards him.
"Friend," said the Mulla, "I want to perform an experiment, to test your powers of psychic penetration, and also
my sanity."
"Proceed," said the Akldan.
Nasrudin made a sudden sweeping motion with his arm, then clenched his fist. "What have I in my hand?"
"A horse, chariot, and driver," said the Akldan immediately.
"That's no real test,—Nasrudin was petulant—"because you saw me pick them up." {57, p. 79}
In d-ASCs people often claim to have exceptional and important insights about themselves or about the nature of
the world that they are unable to communicate to the rest of us owing to the ineffability of the experience, the
inadequacy of language, or the "lowness" of the ordinary d-SoC that makes us incapable of understanding "higher"
things. The general scientific opinion, however, is that communicative ability deteriorates in various d-ASCs, such
as drug-induced or mystical states. This opinion is usually based on the observation that the experimenter/observer
has difficulty understanding what the person in the d-ASC is talking about; his comments make no sense by
ordinary consensus reality standards.
I suspect that sometimes this judgment is based on fear, on the semiconscious recognition that what a person in a
d-ASC is saying may be all too true, but somehow unacceptable. I recall the time when a friend of mine was having
a psychotic breakdown: it struck me that half the things he said were clearly crazy, in the sense of being unrelated to
the social situation around him and reflecting only his own internal processes, but the other half of the things he
said were such penetrating, often unflattering, observations about what other people were really feeling and doing
that they were threatening to most of us. Bennett {5} makes the same observation, noting that after his wife had a
cerebral hemorrhage she seemed to lose all the usual social inhibitions and said directly what she felt. This was
extremely threatening to most people and was regarded as senile dementia or insanity; yet to a few who were not
personally threatened by her observation, her comments were extremely penetrating. If you label someone as crazy,
you need not listen to him.
How can we decide in an objective fashion whether someone in a d-ASC is able to communicate more or less
clearly? Perhaps this is the wrong question. I propose that, for at least some d-ASCs, there are significant alterations
in the manner in which a person communicates. Changes in various subsystems, especially the Evaluation and
Decision-Making subsystem, produce a new logic, so that the grammar of communication, including the nonverbal
aspects of expression, constitutes a different kind of language, one that may be just as effective in communicating
with someone else in the same d-ASC as ordinary communication is in the ordinary d-Soc. We must consider this
possibility in an objective manner, but be careful not implicitly to equate "objectivity' with the standards of only
one d-SoC.
For a given d-ASC, then, how can we determine whether there is deterioration, improvement, or simply alteration
in communication ability, or a complex combination of all three? More specifically, we must ask this question with
respect to communication across d-SoCs—about communication between two persons in different d-SoCs as well
as about communication between two persons in the same d-SoC. In regard to the last two situations, only
theorizing is possible, for all published research deals only with the restricted situation of an experimental subject in
a d-ASC and the experimenter/observer in his ordinary d-SoC.
If the grammar of communication is altered in a d-ASC, then clearly a judge in an ordinary d-SoC cannot
distinguish between the hypotheses of deterioration and of alteration in the communicative style of a person in a d-
ASC. The specialized argot of a subcultural group may sound, to an outside observer, like the talk of
schizophrenics. A person familiar with that subculture, on the other hand, finds the communications exchanged
among the group perfectly meaningful, perhaps extraordinarily rich. In this example, contextual clues may make the
outsider suspect this is a subcultural argot, but if the group is in an institutional setting and is labeled
"schizophrenic," he may readily conclude that its speech has indeed deteriorated, without bothering to study the
matter further.
To judge adequately whether communicative patterns have altered (and possibly improved) rather than
deteriorated, the judge must function in the same d-ASC as the communicator. Experienced marijuana smokers, for
example, claim they can subtly communicate all sorts of things—especially humor—to each other while intoxicated
{105}. The degree to which an observer in a different d-SoC—for example, his ordinary d-SoC—can understand
the same communication is interesting, but not a valid measure of the adequacy of the communication within the d-
ASC. And, as explained in earlier chapters, identification of a person as being in a particular d-ASC must be based
not just on the fact that he has undergone an induction procedure (for example, taken a drug) but on actual mapping
of his location in experiential space.
Suppose the judge is in the same d-ASC as the subjects in the study, and reports that their communication is rich
and meaningful, not at all deteriorated. How do we know that the judge's mental processes themselves are not
deteriorated and that he is not just enjoying the illusion of understanding, rather than prosaically judging the
subjects' communication? The question leads to general problems of measuring the accuracy and adequacy of
communication, an area I know little about. All the work in this area has been done with respect to ordinary d-SoC
communication, but I believe the techniques can be applied to this question of adequacy of communication in d-
ASCs. I shall try to show this by describing one technique for rating ordinary d-SoC communication with which I
am familiar that could be readily applied to judging d-ASC communication.
It is the Cloze technique {140}. It measures, simultaneously, how well a written or verbal communication is both
phrased (encoded) and how well it is understood by a receiver or judge. From a written message or a transcript of a
spoken message, every fifth word is deleted. Judges then guess what the deleted words are, and the total number of
words correct is a measure of the accuracy and meaningfulness of the communication. If a judge understands the
communicator well, he can fill in a high proportion of the words correctly; if he does not understand him well he
gets very few correct. This technique works because ordinary language is fairly redundant, so the overall context of
the message allows excellent guesses about missing words. This technique can be applied to communications
between subjects as judged both by a judge in the same d-ASC, thus testing adequacy of communication within the
d-ASC, and by a judge in a different d-SoC, thus measuring transfer across states. We think of the different d-SoC,
thus measuring transfer across states. We think of the different d-SoC as being the ordinary state, but other d-SoCs
are possible, and we can eventually use this technique for a cross-comparison across all d-SoCs we know of and
produce important information about both communication and the nature of various d-SoCs.
Two problems arise in applying the Cloze technique in investigating communications in d-ASCs. One is that a
particular d-ASC may be associated with a switch to more nonverbal components of communication. This difficulty
could probably be remedied by making videotapes of the procedure, and systematically deleting every fifth second,
and letting the judges fill in the gap. The second problem is that communication in a d-ASC may be as adequate,
but less redundant, a circumstance that would artificially lower the scores on the Cloze test without adequately
testing the communication. I leave this problem as a challenge to others.
Another important methodological factor is the degree of adaptation to functioning in a particular d-ASC. I am
sure techniques of the Cloze type would show deterioration in communication within d-ASCs for subjects who are
relatively naive in functioning in those d-ASCs. Subjects have to adapt to the novelty of a d-ASC; they may even
need specific practice in learning to communicate within it. The potential for an altered style of communication,
state-specific communication, may be present and need to be developed, rather than being available immediately
upon entering the d-ASC. I do not imply simply that people learn to compensate for the deterioration associated
with a d-ASC, but rather that they learn the altered style of communication inherent in or more natural to that
particular d-ASC.
In Chapter 16, in which I propose the creation of state-specific sciences, I assume that communication within
some d-ASCs is adequate: this is a necessary foundation for the creation of state-specific sciences. In making this
assumption, I depend primarily on experiential observations by people in d-ASCs. Objective verification with the
Cloze technique or similar techniques is a necessary underpinning for this. As state-specific sciences are developed,
on the other hand, technique for evaluating the adequacy of communication may be developed within particular
states that can be agreed upon as "scientific" techniques within that state, even though they do not necessarily make
sense in the ordinary d-SoC.
Another interesting question concerns transfer of communicative ability after the termination of a d-ASC to the
ordinary (or any other) d-SoC. Experienced marijuana smokers, for example, claim that they can understand a
subject intoxication on marijuana even when they are not intoxication themselves because of partial transfer of
state-specific knowledge to the ordinary d-SoC. We need to study the validity of this phenomenon.
In earlier chapters I avoid talking about "higher" states of consciousness, as the first job of science is description,
not evaluation. Here, however, I want to speculate on what one relatively objective definition of the adjective
higher, applied to a d-SoC, could mean with respect to communication. If we consider that understanding many
communications from other people is more valuable than understanding few of their communications, then a higher
d-SoC is one in which communications form a variety of d-ASCs are adequately understood; a lower d-SoC is one
in which understanding is limited, perhaps to the particular lower d-SoC itself.
In previous chapters I argue that the ordinary (or any) d-SoC is a semiarbitrary construction, a specialized tool,
useful for some things but not for others. A consequence of this is that science is specialized, because it is a one-d-
SoC science. As a method of learning science has been applied only in a limited way because it has been used in
only one of many possible d-SoCs. This chapter works out the consequences of this idea in detail and proposes that
if we are to understand d-ASCs adequately, as well as ourselves as human beings, we must develop state-specific
sciences.[1]
Blackburn {7} recently noted that many of our most talented young people are "turned off" from science: as a
solution, he proposed that we recognize the validity of a more sensuous-intuitive approach to nature, treating it as
complementary to the classical intellectual approach.
I have seen the same rejection of science by many of the brightest students in California, and the problem is
indeed serious Blackburn's analysis is valid, but not deep enough. A more fundamental source of alienation is the
widespread experience of d-ASCs by the young, coupled with the almost total rejection by the scientific
establishment of the knowledge gained during the experiencing of d-ASCs. Blackburn himself exemplifies this
rejection when he says: "Perhaps science has much to learn along this line from the disciplines, as distinct from the
context, of Oriental religions" (my italics).
To illustrate, a 1971 Gallup poll {41} indicated that approximately half of American college students have tried
marijuana and that a large number of them use it fairly regularly. They do this at the risk of having their careers
ruined and going to jail for several years. Why? Conventional research on the nature of marijuana intoxication tells
us that the primary effects are a slight increase in heart rate, reddening of the eyes, some difficulty with memory,
and small decrements in performance on complex psychomotor tests.
Would you risk going to jail to experience these?
A young marijuana smoker who hears a scientist or physician refer to these findings as the basic nature of
marijuana intoxication will simply sneer and have his antiscientific attitude further reinforced. It is clear to him that
the scientist has no real understanding of what marijuana intoxication is all about (see {105} for a comprehensive
description of this d-ASC).
More formally, an increasingly significant number of people are experimenting with d-ASCs in themselves and
finding the experiences thus gained of extreme importance in their philosophy and style of life. The conflict
between experiences in these d-ASCs and the attitudes and intellectual-emotional systems that have evolved in the
ordinary d-SoC is a major factor behind the increased alienation of many people from conventional science.
Experiences of ecstasy, mystical union, other dimensions, rapture, beauty, space-and-time transcendence, and
transpersonal knowledge, all common in d-ASCs, are simply not treated adequately in conventional scientific
approaches. These experiences will not go away if we crack down more on psychedelic drugs, for immense
numbers of people now practice carious nondrug techniques for producing d-ASCs, such as meditation {39} and
yoga.
My purpose here is to show that it is possible to investigate and work with the important phenomena of d-ASCs
in a manner that is perfectly compatible with the essence of scientific method. The conflict discussed above is not
necessary.
States of Consciousness
To review briefly, a d-ASC is defined as a qualitative alteration in the overall pattern of mental functioning, such
that the experiencer feels his consciousness is radically different from the way it functions ordinarily. A d-SoC is
defined not in terms of any particular content of consciousness or specific behavior or physiological change, but in
terms of the overall patterning of psychological functioning.
An analogy with computer functioning can clarify this definition. A computer has a complex program of many
subroutines. If we reprogram it quite differently, the same sorts of input data may be handled in quite different
ways; we can predict little from our knowledge of the old program about the effects of varying the input, even
though old and new programs have some subroutines in common. The new program with its input-output
interactions must be studied in and of itself. A d-ASC is analogous to a temporary change in the program of a
computer.
The d-ASCs experienced by almost all ordinary people are dreaming states and the hypnagogic and hypnopompic
states, the transitional states between sleeping and waking. Many others experience another d-ASC, alcohol
intoxication.
The relatively new (to our culture) d-ASCs that are now having such an impact are those produced by marijuana,
more powerful psychedelic drugs such as LSD, meditative states, so-called possession states, and autohypnotic
states.[2]
It is useful to compare this concept of a d-SoC, a qualitatively distinct organization of the pattern of mental
functioning, with Kuhn's {32} concept of paradigms in science. A paradigm is an intellectual achievement that
underlies normal science and attracts and guides the work of an enduring number of adherents in their scientific
activity. It is a "super" theory, a formulation wide enough in scope to affect the organization of most or all of the
major known phenomena of its field. Yet it is sufficiently open-ended that there still remain important problems to
be solved within that framework. Examples of important paradigms in the history of science have been Copernican
astronomy and Newtonian dynamics.
Because of their tremendous success, paradigms undergo a change which, in principle, ordinary scientific
theories do not undergo. An ordinary scientific theory is always subject to further questioning and testing as it is
extended. A paradigm becomes an implicit framework for most scientists working within it; it is the natural way of
looking at things and doing things. It does not seriously occur to the adherents of a paradigm to question it (we may
ignore, for the moment, the occurrence of scientific revolutions). Theories become referred to as laws: people talk
of the law of gravity, not the theory of gravity, for example.
A paradigm serves to concentrate the attention of a researcher on sensible problem areas and to prevent him from
wasting his time on what might be trivia. On the other hand, by implicitly defining some lines of research as trivial
or nonsensical, a paradigm acts as a blinder. Kuhn has discussed this blinding function as a key factory in the lack
of effective communications during paradigm clashes.
The concept of a paradigm and a d-SoC are quite similar. Both constitute complex, interlocking sets of rules and
theories that enable a person to interact with and interpret experiences within an environment. In both cases, the
rules are largely implicit. They are not recognized as tentative working hypotheses; they operate automatically and
the person feels he is doing the obvious or natural thing.
Human beings become emotionally attached to the things that give them success and pleasure, and a scientist
making important progress within a particular paradigm becomes emotionally attached to it. When data that make
not sense in terms of the (implicit) paradigm are brought to his attention, the usual result is not a reevaluation of the
paradigm, but a rejection or misperception of the data. This rejection seems rational to others sharing that paradigm
and irrational or rationalizing to those committed to a different paradigm.
The conflict now existing between those who have experienced certain d-ASCs (whose ranks include many
young scientists) and those who have not is a paradigmatic conflict. For example, a subject takes LSD and tells his
investigator, "You and I, we are all one, there are no separate selves." The investigator reports that his subject
showed a "confused sense of identity and distorted thinking process." The subject is reporting what is obvious to
him; the investigator is reporting what is obvious to him. The investigator's (implicit) paradigm, based on his
scientific training, his cultural background, and his normal d-SoC, indicates that a literal interpretation of the
subject's statement cannot be true and therefore the statement must be interpreted as mental dysfunction on the part
of the subject. The subject, his paradigms radically changed for the moment by being in a d-ASC, not only reports
what is obviously true to him, but perceives the investigator as showing mental dysfunction because he is incapable
of perceiving the obvious!
Historically, paradigm clashes have been characterized by bitter emotional antagonisms and total rejection of the
opponent. Currently we see the same sort of process: the respectable psychiatrist, who would not take any of those
"psychotomimetic" drugs himself or experience that crazy meditation process, carries out research to show that
drug-takers and those who practice meditation are escapists. The drug-taker or meditater views the same
investigator as narrow-minded, prejudiced, and repressive, and as a result drops out of the university.
Communication between the two factions is almost nil.
Must the experiencers of d-ASCs continue to see the scientists as concentrating on the irrelevant, and scientists
see the experiencers as confused[3] or mentally ill? Or can science deal adequately with the experiencers of these
people? The thesis I present is that we can deal with the important aspects of d-ASCs using the essence of scientific
method, even though a variety of non-essentials, unfortunately identified with current science, hinder such an effort.
Science deals with knowledge. Knowledge may be defined as an immediately given experiential feeling of
congruence between two different kinds of experience, a matching. One set of experiences may be regarded as
perceptions of the external world, of others, of oneself; the second set may be regarded as a theory, a scheme, a
system of understanding. The feeling of congruence is something immediately given in experience, although many
refinements have been worked out for judging degrees of congruence.
All knowledge, then, is basically experiential knowledge. Even my knowledge of the physical world can be
reduced to this: given certain sets of experiences, which I (by assumption) attribute to activation of my sensory
apparatus by the external world, I can compare them with purely internal experiences (memories, previous
knowledge) and predict with a high degree of reliability other kinds of experiences, which I again attribute to the
external world.
Because science has been highly successful in dealing with the physical world, it has been historically associated
with a philosophy of physicalism, the belief that reality is all reducible to certain kinds of physical entities. The vast
majority of phenomena of d-ASCs have no known physical manifestations: thus to physicalistic philosophy they are
epiphenomena, not worthy of study. But since science deals with knowledge, it need not restrict itself to physical
kinds of knowledge.
As satisfying as the feeling of knowing can be, we are often wrong: what seems like congruence at first, later
does not match or has no generality. Man has learned that his reasoning is often faulty, his observations often
incomplete or mistaken, and that emotional or other nonconscious factors can seriously distort both reasoning and
observational processes. His reliance on authorities, "rationality," or elegance," are no sure criteria for achieving
truth. The development of scientific method may be seen as a determined effort to systematize the process of
acquiring knowledge in such a way as to minimize the pitfalls of observation and reasoning.
There are four basic rules of scientific method to which an investigator is committed: (1) good observation, (2)
the public nature of observation, (3) the necessity to theorize logically, and (4) the testing of theory by observable
consequences. These constitute the scientific enterprise. I consider below the wider application of each rule to d-
ASCs and indicate how unnecessary physicalistic restrictions may be dropped. I also show that all these
commitments or rules can be accommodated in the development of state-specific sciences.
Observation
The scientist is committed to observe as well as possible the phenomena of interest and to search constantly for
better ways of making these observations. But his paradigmatic commitments, his d-SoCs, make him likely to
observe certain parts of reality and to ignore or observe with error certain other parts of it.
Many of the most important phenomena of d-ASCs have been observed poorly or not at all because of the
physicalistic labeling of them as epiphenomena, so that they have been called "subjective," "ephemeral,"
"unreliable," or "unscientific." Observations of internal processes are probably much more difficult than those of
external physical processes, because of their inherently greater complexity. The essence of science, however, is to
observe what there is to observed, whether or not it is difficult.
Furthermore, most of what is known about the phenomena of d-ASCs has been obtained from untrained people,
almost none of whom have shared the scientist's commitment to constantly reexamine observations in greater and
greater detail. This does not imply that internal phenomena are inherently unobservable or unstable; we are
comparing the first observations of internal phenomena with observations of physical sciences that have undergone
centuries of refinement.
We must consider one other problem of observation. One of the traditional idols of science, the "detached
observer," has no place in dealing with many internal phenomena of d-SoCs. Not only are the observer's
perceptions selective, he may also affect the things he observes. We must try to understand the characteristics of
each individual observer in order to compensate for them.
A recognition of the unreality of the detached observer in the psychological sciences is becoming widespread,
under the topics of experimenter bias {55} and demand characteristics {45}. A similar recognition long ago
occurred in physics when it was realized that he observed was altered by the process of observation at subatomic
levels. When we deal with d-ASCs where the observer is the experiencer of the d-ASC, this factor is of paramount
importance. Not knowing the characteristics of the observer can also confound the process of consensual validation.
Observations must be public in that they must be replicable by any properly trained observer. The experienced
conditions that led to the report of certain experiences must be described in sufficient detail that others can
duplicate them and consequently have experiences that meet criteria of identicality. That someone else may set up
similar conditions but not have the same experiences proves that the original investigator gave an incorrect
description of the conditions and observations, or that he was not aware of certain essential aspects of the
conditions.
The physicalistic accretion to this rule of consensual validation is that, physical data being the only "real" data,
internal phenomena must be reduced to physiological or behavioral data to become reliable or they will be ignored
entirely. I believe most physical observations to be much more readily replicable by any trained observer because
they are inherently simpler phenomena than internal ones. In principle, however, consensual validation of internal
phenomena by a trained observer is possible.
The emphasis on public observations in science has had a misleading quality insofar as it implies that any
intelligent man can replicate a scientists observations. This may have been true early in the history of science, but
nowadays only the trained observer can replicate many observations. I cannot go into a modern physicist's
laboratory and confirm his observations. Indeed, his talk of what he has found in his experiments (physicists seem
to talk about innumerable invisible entities) would probably seem mystical to me, just as descriptions of internal
states sound mystical to those with a background in the physical sciences.[4]
Given the high complexity of the phenomena associated with d-ASCs, the need for replication by trained
observers is exceptionally important. Since it generally takes four to ten years of intensive training to produce a
scientist in any of the conventional disciplines, we should not be surprised that there has been little reliability of
observations by untrained observers of d-ASC phenomena.
Further, for the state-specific sciences I propose, we cannot specify the requirements that constitute adequate
training. These can only be determined after considerable trial and error. We should also recognize that very few
people may complete the training successfully. Some people do not have the necessary innate characteristics to
become physicists, and some probably do not have the innate characteristics to become scientific investigators of
meditative states.
Public observation, then, always refers to a limited, specially trained public. It is only by basic agreement among
those specially trained people that data become accepted as a foundation for the development of a science. That
laymen cannot replicate the observations is of little relevance.
A second problem in consensual validation arises from a phenomenon predicted by my concept of d-ASCs, but
not yet empirically investigated: state-specific communication. Given that a d-ASC is an overall qualitative and
quantitative shift in the complex functioning of consciousness, producing new logics and perceptions (which
constitute a paradigm shift), it is quite reasonable to hypothesize that communication may take a different pattern.
For two observers, both of whom, we assume, are fluent in communicating with each other in a given d-SoC,
communication about some new observations may seem adequate or may be improved or deteriorated in specific
ways. To an outside observer, an observer in a different d-SoC, the communication between these two observers
may seem deteriorated.
Practically all investigations of communication by persons in d-ASCs have resulted in reports of deterioration of
communication abilities. In designing their studies, however, these investigators have not taken into account the fact
that the pattern of communication may have changed. If I am listening to two people speaking in English, and they
suddenly begin to intersperse words and phrases in Polish, I, as an outside (non-Polish-speaking) observer, note a
gross deterioration in communication. Adequacy of communication between people in the same d-SoC and across
d-SoCs must be empirically determined. This is discussed in Chapter 15.
Thus consensual validation may be restricted by the fact that only observers in the same d-ASC are able to
communicate adequately to each other. Someone in a different d-SoC, say normal consciousness, might find their
communication incomprehensible.[5]
Theorizing
A scientist may theorize about his observations as much as he wishes, but the theory he develops must
consistently account for all he has observed and should have a logical structure that other scientists comprehend
(but not necessarily accept).
The requirement to theorize logically and consistently with the data is not as simply as it looks, however. Any
logic consists of a basic set of assumptions and a set of rules for manipulating information based on these
assumptions. Change the assumptions, or change the rules, and there may be entirely different outcomes from the
same data. A paradigm, too, is a logic: it has certain assumptions and rules for working within these assumptions.
By changing the paradigms, altering the d-SoC, the nature of theory-building may change radically. Thus a person
in d-SoC 2 might come to a very different conclusions about the nature of the same events that he observed in d-
SoC 1. An investigator in d-SoC 1 can comment on the comprehensibility of the second person's ideas form the
point of view (paradigm) of d-SoC 1, but can say nothing about their inherent validity. A scientist who could enter
either d-SoC 1 or d-SoC 2, however, could evaluate the comprehensibility of the other's theory and the adherence of
that theory to the rules and logic of d-SoC 2. Thus, scientist trained to work in the same d-SoC can check on the
logical validity of each other's theorizing. So we can have inter-observer validation of the state-specific logic
underlying theorizing in various d-SoCs.
Observable Consequences
Any theory a scientist develops must have observable consequences, it must be possible to make predictions that
can be verified by observation. If such verification is not obtained, the theory must be considered invalid, regardless
of its elegance, logic or other appeal.
Ordinarily we think of empirical validation, validation in terms of testable consequences that produce physical
effects, but this is misleading. Any effect, whether interpreted as physical or nonphysical, is ultimately an
experience in the observer's mind. All that is essentially required to validate a theory is that it predict that when a
certain experience (observed condition) has occurred, another (predicted) kind of experience will follow, under
specified experiential conditions. Thus a perfectly scientific theory may be based on data that have no physical
existence.
State-Specific Sciences
We tend to envision the practice of science like this: centered around interest in some particular range of subject
matter, a small number of highly selected, talented, and rigorously trained people spend considerable time making
detailed observations on the subject matter of interest. They may or may not have special places (laboratories) or
instruments or methods to assist them in making finer observations. They speak to one another in a special language
that they feel conveys precisely the important facts of their field. Using this language, they confirm and extend each
other's knowledge of certain data basic to the field. They theorize about their basic data and construct elaborate
systems. They validate these by recourse to further observation. These trained people all have a long-term
commitment to the constant refinement of observation and extension of theory. Their activity is frequently
incomprehensible to laymen.
This general description is equally applicable to a variety of sciences or areas that could become sciences,
whether we called such areas biology, physics, chemistry, psychology, understanding of mystical states, or drug-
induced enhancement of cognitive processes. The particulars of research look different, but the basic scientific
method is the same.
I propose the creation of various state-specific sciences. If such sciences can be created we will have a group of
highly skilled, dedicated, and trained practitioners able to achieve certain d-SoCs, and able to agree with one
another that they have attained a common state. While in that d-SoC, they can investigate other areas of interest—
totally internal phenomena of that given state, the interaction of that state with external physical reality, or people in
other d-SoCs.
The fact that the experimenter can function skillfully in the d-SoC itself for a state-specific science does not
necessarily mean he must always be the subject. While he may often be the subject, observer, and experimenter
simultaneously, it is quite possible for him to collect data from experimental manipulations of other subjects in the
d-SoC, and either be in that d-SoC himself at the time of data collection or be in that d-SoC himself for data
reduction and theorizing.
Examples of some observations made and theorizing done by a scientist in a specific d-ASC would illustrate the
nature of a proposed state-specific science. But this is not possible because no state-specific sciences have yet been
established.[6] Also, any example that would make good sense to the readers of this chapter (who are, presumably,
all in an ordinary d-SoC) would not really illustrate the uniqueness of state-specific science. If it did make sense, it
would be an example of a problem that could be approached adequately from both the d-ASC and our ordinary
terms of accepted scientific procedures for our ordinary d-SoC and miss the point about the necessity for
developing state-specific sciences.
Some aspects of organized religion appear to resemble state-specific sciences. There are techniques that allow
that believer to enter a d-ASC and then have religious experiences in that d-ASC that are proof of his religious
belief. People who have had such experiences usually describe them as ineffable, not fully comprehensible in an
ordinary d-SoC. Conversions at revival meetings are the most common examples of religious experiences occurring
in d-ASCs induced by an intensely emotional atmosphere.
The esoteric training systems of some religions seem to have even more resemblance to state-specific sciences.
Often there are devoted specialists, complex techniques, and repeated experiencing of the d-ASCs in order to
further religious knowledge.
Nevertheless, the proposed state-specific sciences are not simply religion in a new guise. The use of d-ASCs in
religion may involve the kind of commitment to searching for truth that is need for developing a state-specific
science, but practically all the religions we know can mainly be defined as state-specific technologies, operated in
the service of a prior belief systems. The experiencers of d-ASCs in most religious contexts have already been
thoroughly indoctrinated in a particular belief system. This belief system may then mold the content of the d-ASCs
to create specific experiences that reinforce or validate the belief system.
The crucial distinction between a religion utilizing d-ASCs and a state-
specific science is the commitment of the scientist to reexamine constantly
his own belief system and to question the "obvious," in spite of its intellectual
or emotional appeal to him. Investigators of d-ASCs will certainly encounter
an immense variety of phenomena labeled religious experience or mystical
revelation during the development of state-specific sciences, but they must
remain committed to examining these phenomena more carefully, sharing
their observations and techniques with colleagues, and subjecting the beliefs
(hypotheses, theories) that result from such experiences to the requirement of
leading to testable predictions. In practice, because we are aware of the
immense emotional power of mystical experiences, this is a difficult task, but
it is one that must be undertaken by disciplined investigators if we are to
understand various d-ASCs.[7]
Any (state-specific) science may be considered as consisting of two parts: observations and theories. The
observations are what can be experienced relatively directly: the theories are the inferences about what
nonobservable factors account for the observations. For example, the phenomenon of synesthesia (seeing colors as
a result of hearing sounds) is a theoretical proposition for me in my ordinary d-SoC; I do not experience it and can
only generate theories about what other people report about it. If I were under the influence of psychedelic drug
such as LSD or marijuana {105}, I could probably experience synesthesia directly, and my descriptions of the
experience would become data.
Figure 16-1 (reprinted from C. Tart, Science, 1972, 176 1203-1210, by permission of the American Association
for the Advancement of Science) demonstrates some possible relationships between three state-specific sciences.
State-specific sciences 1 and 2 show considerable overlap.
The area labeled O1O2 permits direct observation in both sciences. Area T1T2 permits theoretical inferences
about common subject matter from the two perspectives. In area O1T2, by contrast, the theoretical propositions of
state-specific science 2 are matters of direct observation for the scientist in d-SoC 1, and vice versa for the area
T1O2. State-specific science 3 consists of a body of observation and theory exclusive to that science and has no
overlap with the two other sciences: it does not confirm, contradict, or complement them.
It would be naively reductionistic to say that the work in one state-specific science validates or invalidates the
work in a second state-specific science; I prefer to say that two different state-specific sciences, where they overlap,
provide quite different points of view with respect to certain kinds of theories and data, and thus complement[8]
each other. The proposed creation state-specific sciences neither validates nor invalidates the activities or normal
consciousness sciences. The possibility of developing certain state-specific sciences means only that certain kinds
of phenomena may be handled more adequately within these potential new sciences.
Interrelationships more complex than these illustrated in Fig. 16-1 are possible.
The possibility of stimulating interactions between different state-specific sciences is very real. Creative
breakthroughs in normal consciousness sciences have frequently been made by scientists temporarily in a d-ASC
{18}. In such instances, the scientists concerned saw quite different views of their problems and performed
different kinds of reasoning, conscious or nonconscious, which led to results that could be tested within their
normal consciousness science.
A current example of such interaction is the finding that in Zen meditation (a highly developed discipline in
Japan) there are physiological correlates of meditative experiences, such as decreased frequency of alpha-rhythm,
which can also be produced by means of instrumentally aided feedback-learning techniques {23}. This finding may
elucidate some of the processes peculiar to each discipline.
Individual Differences
A widespread and misleading assumption that hinders the development of state-specific sciences and confuses
their interrelationships is the assumption that because two people are "normal" (not certified insane), their ordinary
d-SoCs are essentially the same. In reality I suspect that there are enormous differences between the d-SoCs of
some normal people. Because societies train people to behave and communicate along socially approved lines,
these differences are obscured.
For example, some people think in images, others in words. Some can voluntarily anesthetize parts of their body,
most cannot. Some recall past events by imaging the scene and looking at the relevant details; others use complex
verbal processes with no images.
This means that person A may be able to observe certain kinds of experiential data that person B cannot
experience in his ordinary d-SoC, no matter how hard B tries. There may be several consequences. Person B may
think A is insane, too imaginative, or a liar, or he may feel inferior to A. Person A may also feel himself odd, if he
takes B as a standard of normality.
B may be able to enter a d-ASC and there experience the sorts of things A has reported to him. A realm of
knowledge that is ordinary for A is then specific for a d-ASC for B. Similarly, some of the experiences of B in his
d-ASC may not be available for direct observation by A in his ordinary d-SoC.
The phenomenon of synesthesia can again serve as an example. Some individuals possess this ability in their
ordinary d-SoC, most do not. Yet 56 percent of a sample of experienced marijuana users experienced synesthesia at
least occasionally {105} while in the drug-induced d-ASC.
Thus bits of knowledge that are specific for a d-ASC for one individual may be part of ordinary consciousness
for another. Arguments over the usefulness of the concept of states of consciousness may reflect differences in the
structure of the ordinary d-SoC of various investigators, as we discussed in Chapter 9.
Another important source of individual differences, little understood at present, is the degree to which an
individual can first make an observation or form a concept in one d-SoC and then reexperience or comprehend it in
another d-SoC. Many items of information hat were state-specific when observed initially may be learned and
somehow transferred (fully or partially) to another d-SoC. Differences across individuals, various combinations of
d-SoCs, and types of experience are probably enormous.
I have outlined only the complexities created by individuals differences in normal d-SoCs and have used the
normal d-SoC as a baseline for comparison with d-ASCs, but it is evident that every d-SoC must eventually be
compared against every other d-SoC.
If we use the practical experience of Western man with d-ASCs as a guide, the development of state-specific
sciences will be beset by a number of difficulties. These difficulties will be of two kinds: general methodological
problems stemming from the inherent nature of some d-ASCs, and those concerned with personal perils to the
investigator.
State-Related Problems
The first important problem in the proposed development of state-specific sciences is the "obvious" perception of
truth. In many d-ASCs, one's experience is what one is obviously and lucidly experiencing truth directly without
question. An immediate result of this may be an extinction of the desire for further questioning. Further, this
experience of "obvious" truth, while not necessarily preventing the investigator from further examining his data,
may not arouse his desire for consensual validation. Since one of the greatest strengths of science is its insistence on
consensual validation of basic data, this can be a serious drawback. Investigators attempting to develop state-
specific sciences must learn to distrust the obvious.
A second major problem in developing state-specific sciences is that in some d-ASCs one's abilities to visualize
and imagine are immensely enhanced, so that whatever one imagines seems perfectly real. Thus one can imagine
that something is being observed and experience it as datum. If the scientist can conjure up anything he wishes,
how can he ever get at truth?
One approach to this problem is to consider any such vivid imaginings as potential effects: they are data in the
sense that what can be vividly imagined in a d-SoC is important to know. It may be that not everything can be
imagined with equal facility and relationships between what can be imagined may show a lawful pattern.
Another approach is to realize that this problem is not unique to d-ASCs. One can have illusions and
misperceptions in the ordinary d-SoC. Before the rise of modern physical science, all sorts of things were imagined
about the nature of the physical world that could not be directly refuted. The same techniques that eliminated these
illusions in the physical sciences can also eliminate them in state-specific sciences dealing with nonphysical data.
All observations must be subjected to consensual validation and all their theoretical consequences must be
examined. Those that do not show consistent patterns and cannot be replicated can be distinguished from those
phenomena that do show general lawfulness across individuals.
The effects of this enhanced vividness of imagination in some d-ASCs will be complicated further by two other
problems: experimenter bias {45, 55} and the fact that one person's illusion in a given d-ASC can sometimes be
communicated to another person in the same d-ASC so that a false consensual validation results. Again, the only
long-term solution is the requirements that predictions based on concepts arising from various experiences be
verified experientially.
A third major problem is that state-specific sciences probably cannot be developed for all d-ASCs: some d-ASCs
may depend or result from genuine deterioration of observational and reasoning abilities or from a deterioration of
volition. But the development of each state-specific science should result from trial and error, and not from a priori
decisions based on reasoning in the ordinary d-SoC that would rule out attempts to develop a science for some
particular state.
A fourth major problem is that of ineffability. Some experiences are ineffable in the sense that (1) a person may
experience them, but be unable to express or conceptualize them adequately to himself.; (2) while a person may be
able to conceptualize an experiencer to himself he may not be able to communicate it adequately to anyone else.
Certain phenomena of the first type may simply be inaccessible to scientific investigation. Phenomena of the
second type may be accessible to scientific investigation only insofar as we are willing to recognize that a science,
in the sense of following most of the basic rules, may exist only for a single person. Since such a solitary science
lacks all the advantages gained by consensual validation, we cannot expect it to have as much power and rigor as
conventional scientific endeavor.
Many phenomena that are now considered ineffable may not be so in reality. Their apparent ineffability may be a
function of general lack of experience with d-ASCs and the lack of an adequate language for communicating about
d-ASC phenomena. In most well-developed languages the major part of the vocabulary was developed primarily in
adaptation to survival in the physical world.[9]
Finally, various phenomena of d-ASCs may be too complex for human beings to understand. The phenomena
may depend on or be affected by so many variables that we can never understand them. In the history of science,
however, many phenomena that appeared too complex at first eventually became comprehensible.
Personal Perils
The personal perils an investigator faces in attempting develop a state-specific science are of two kinds: those
associated with reactions colloquially called a bad trip and a good trip.
Bad trips, in which an extremely unpleasant emotional reaction is experienced in a d-ASC, and from which there
are possible one-term adverse consequences on personal adjustment, often occur because upbringing has not
prepared us to undergo radical alterations in our ordinary d-SoC. We depend on stability, we fear the unknown, and
we develop personal rigidities and various kinds of personal and social taboos. It is traditional in our society to
consider d-ASCs as signs of insanity; d-ASCs therefore can cause great fear in those who experience them.
In many d-ASCs, defenses against unacceptable personal impulses become partially or wholly ineffective, so that
the person feels flooded with traumatic material he cannot handle. All these things result in fear and avoidance of d-
ASCs, and make it difficult or impossible for some individuals to function in a d-ASC in a way that is consistent
without he development of state-specific science. Maslow {36} discusses these as pathologies of cognition that
seriously interfere without the scientific enterprise in general, as well ordinary life. In principle, adequate selection
and training can minimize these hazards for at least some people.
Good trips may also endanger an investigator. A trip may produce experiences so rewarding that they interfere
with the scientific activity of the investigator. The perception of "obvious" truth and its effect of eliminating the
need for further investigation or consensual validation have already been mentioned. Another peril comes from the
ability to imagine or create vivid experiences. They may be so highly rewarding that the investigator does not
follow the rule of investigating the obvious regardless of his personal satisfaction with results. Similarly, his
attachment to good feelings, ecstasy, and the like, and his refusal to consider alternative conceptualizations of these,
can stifle the progress of investigation.
These personal perils emphasize the necessity of developing adequate training programs for scientists who wish
to develop state-specific sciences. Although such a training program is difficult to envision, it is evident that much
conventional scientific training is contrary to what is needed to develop a state-specific science, because it tends to
produce rigidity and avoidance of personal involvement with subject matter, rather than open-mindedness and
flexibility. Much of the training program must be devoted to the scientist's understanding of himself so that the
(unconscious) effects of his personal biases are minimized during his investigations of a d-ASC.
There are scientists who, after becoming personally involved with d-ASCs, have subsequently become poor
scientists or have experienced personal psychological crises. It is premature, however, to conclude that such
unfortunate consequences cannot be avoid by proper training and discipline. In the early history of the physical
sciences many scientist were fanatics who were nonobjective about their investigations. Not all experiencers of d-
ASCs develop pathology as a result: indeed, many seem to become considerably more mature. Given the current
social climate, we hear of the failures, but not the successes. Only from actual attempts to develop state-specific
sciences can we determine the actual d-SoCs that are suitable for development and the kinds of people best suited to
such work.[10]
Prospects
I believe that an examination of human history and our current situation provides the strongest argument for the
need to develop state-specific sciences. Throughout history man has been influenced by the spiritual and mystical
factors expressed (usually in watered-down form) in the religions that attract the masses. Spiritual and mystical
experiences are primary phenomena of various d-ASCs: because of such experiences, untold numbers of both the
noblest and most horrible acts of which men are capable have been committed. Yet in all the time that Western
science as existed, no concerted attempt has been made to understand these d-ASC phenomena in scientific terms.
Many hoped that religions were simply a form of superstition that would be left behind in our "rational" age. Not
only has this hope failed, but our own understanding of the nature of reasoning now makes it clear that it can never
be fulfilled. Reason is a tool, a tool that is yielded in the service of assumptions, beliefs and needs that are not
themselves subject to reason. The irrational, or better, the arational, will not disappear from the human situation.
Our immense success in the development of the physical sciences has not been particularly successful in
formulating better philosophies of life or increasing our real knowledge of ourselves. The sciences we have
developed to date are not very human sciences. They tell us how to do things, but give us no scientific insights on
questions of what to do, what not to do, or why to do things.
The youth of today and mature scientists are turning to meditation, Oriental religions, and personal use of
psychedelic drugs in increasing numbers. The phenomena encountered in these d-ASCs provide more satisfaction
and are more relevant to the formulation of philosophies of life and decisions about appropriate ways of living, than
"pure reason" {40}. My own impressions are that large numbers of scientists are now personally exploring d-ASCs,
but few have begun to connect this personal exploration with their scientific activities.
It is difficult to predict the chances of delving state-specific sciences. Our knowledge is still to diffuse ad
dependent on the normal d-SoC. Yet I think it is probable that state-specific sciences can be developed for such d-
ASCs as autohypnosis, meditative states, lucid dreaming, marijuana intoxication, LSD intoxication, self-
remembering, reverie, and biofeedback-induced states {88 or 115}. In all these d-ASCs, volition seems to be
retained, so that the observer can indeed carry out experiments on himself or others or both. Some d-ASCs, in
which the volition to experiment during the state may disappear, but in which some experimentation can be carried
out if special conditions are prepared before the state is entered, are alcohol intoxication, ordinary dreaming,
hypnagogic and hypnopompic states, and high dreams {88 or 115}. It is not clear whether other d-ASCs are suitable
for developing state-specific sciences or whether mental deterioration is too great. Such questions can only be
answered by experiment.
I have nothing against religious and mystical groups. Yet I suspect that the vast majority of them have developed
compelling belief systems rather than state-specific sciences. Will scientific method be extended to the development
of state-specific sciences to improve our human situation? Or will the immense power of d-ASCs be left in the
hands of many cults and sects?
Footnotes
[1] I originally presented the proposal for state-specific sciences in an article in Science {119}. Most of it is
reprinted here with the permission of the American Association for the Advancement of Science. I have updated the
text and terminology to fit the rest of this book. (back)
[2] Note that a d-SoC is defined by the stable parameters of the pattern that constitute it, not by the particular
technique of inducing that pattern. (back)
[3] States of confusion and impaired functioning may certainly be aspects of some drug-induced d-ASCs for
some people, but are not of primary interest here. (back)
[4] The degree to which a science can seem incomprehensible, even ridiculous, to someone not specializing in it
never ceases to astound me. I have always thought I had a good general background in science. So much so that, for
example, I was able to appreciate some of the in-group humor in an article I read in Science some years ago about
quarks. Quarks? Yes, quarks. To me, the article was obviously a put-on, about how physicists were hunting for
particles no one had ever seen, called quarks. Much of the humor was too technical for me to understand, but I was
pleased that a staid journal like Science could unbend enough to publish humor. Of course, it was not humor.
Physicists are very serious about quarks, even though no one has ever detected one with certainty (at least not yet,
despite an awful lot of research). (back)
[5] A state-specific scientist might find his own work somewhat incomprehensible when he was not in his work
d-ASC because of the phenomenon of state-specific memory. Not enough of his work would transfer to his ordinary
d-SoC to make it comprehensible, even though it would again make perfect sense when he was again in the d-ASC
in which he did his scientific work. (back)
[6] "Ordinary consciousness science" is not a good example of a pure state-specific science because many
important discoveries have occurred during d-ASCs such as reverie, dreaming, and meditative states. (back)
[7] The idea of state-specific knowledge, introduced earlier, casts some light on an aspect of organized religions,
the "dryness" of theology. Consider the feeling so many, both inside and outside organized religion, have had that
theology is intellectual hair-splitting, an activity irrelevant to what religion is all about. I believe this is true in many
cases, and the reason is that the essence of much religion is state-specific knowledge, knowledge that can really be
known only in a d-ASC. The original founders of the religion know certain things in a d-ASC, they talk about them
in the ordinary d-SoC. They realize the words are a poor reflection of the direct experiential knowledge, but the
words are all they have to talk with. As the generations pass, more and more theologians who have no direct
knowledge of what the words are about discuss the meaning of the words at greater and greater length, and the
divergence of the words from the original state-specific knowledge becomes greater and greater.
There are warnings in some religious literature {128} not to take the words literally, to use them only as pointers
of the direction experience must go, but our culture is so fascinated with words that we seldom heed such warnings.
So perhaps ideas like "we are all one" or "love pervades the entire universe" cannot be adequately comprehended
in the ordinary d-SoC, no matter how hard we try, although they may appropriately affect our thoughts and actions
in the ordinary d-SoC if we have first experienced them, understood them, in the appropriate d-ASC. (back)
[8] The term complement is used in a technical sense here, as it is in physics, meaning that each of two
explanatory systems deals well with overlapping data areas, but neither disproves the other and neither can be
incorporated into some more comprehensive theoretical system as a special case. For example, the electron can be
treated adequately as a wave or as a particle. The wave theory handles some kinds of data better than the particle
theory, and vice versa. (back)
[9] Note too that we are a hyperverbal culture, so ineffable essentially means not communicable in words. But
there are other forms of communication. Riding a bicycle or swimming are both ineffable, in the sense that I have
never seen a good verbal description of either, but they can be taught. Ornstein {47} presents convincing data that
the right hemisphere of the brain specializes in nonverbal functioning, and argues that many of the seemingly exotic
techniques of Eastern spiritual disciplines are actually ways of communicating and teaching in the nonverbal mode.
(back)
[10] The d-ASCs resulting from very dangerous drugs may be scientifically interesting, but the risk may be too
high to warrant developing state-specific sciences for them. The personal and social issues involved in evaluating
this kind of risk are beyond the scope of this book. (back)
A common reaction to the proposal for creating state-specific sciences is that the project is not necessary, that there
is already a superior d-SoC for understanding things. Orthodox scientists {122} aver that the ordinary, "normal" d-
SoC is the best, most rational d-SoC possible, so we need only continue the scientific research already begun in that
state to ultimately find answers to all our questions. On the other hand, some people who have experienced d-ASCs
believe that there are higher d-SoCs in which Truth can be directly known so we need not develop sciences in these
d-SoCs, only experience them: ultimately we can experience states of enlightenment in which all that is worth
knowing or attaining is known and attained.
However, the feeling of being in direct contact with the Truth is no guarantee that such contact has actually been
achieved. Such feelings are a part of being human, but such "certain truths," when acted upon, often turn out to be
false. They do not work. A primary rule of science is that you must test your understandings against the observable
area of reality/experience to which they apply: if observed experience does not tally with the prediction of your
truth/theory/understanding, then your truth/theory/understanding is false or needs revision. Scientifically, we cannot
broadly assume that any particular d-SoC is higher, in the sense of supplying more insight into truth; we must study
and test the various aspects of various d-SoCs in detail. Since a principal task of science is reliable, detailed
description, it seems preferable to discard the idea of higher states altogether at this stage and concentrate on
description.
Yet since experiences of d-ASCs often describe them as higher
or lower states, we should, to be adequately descriptive, examine
more closely the idea of higher states.
What does a person mean when he says, "I'm high" or "I'm in a
higher state of consciousness"?
On its simplest level, the statement "I'm high" simply means
that I feel better now that I did under some other condition. If I had
a bad toothache a few minutes ago, and now the pain has stopped,
I can say that now I'm high. I feel much better than before. If I am
neurotic in my ordinary d-SoC and suffer constant tensions, fears,
and anxieties, and I get drunk and feel good, again I can say I'm
high by comparison. To reverse this, if I become frightened or feel
sick when I am drunk, I can use the phrase "I'm high" to describe
my ordinary d-SoC in which I do not feel frightened or sick.
If, then, we clearly describe the reference states and the way in
which the current state differs from it, the statement "I'm high" is a
useful relative description. Unfortunately, people usually employ
the phrase without any clear description of the reference state or
the specific way in which the current condition differ from it. Add
to this the great individual differences in ordinary d-SoCs, and the
degree to which the common language of consensus reality glosses
over these differences, and you can see that "I'm high" is usually
an ambiguous phrase indicating only that I feel better than in some
other, unknown condition. Perhaps I am in a state of fear and
anxiety now and that is better than the terror I experienced a few
minutes ago, or perhaps I feel blissfully at one with the whole cosmos.
There is a more specific use of the adjectives higher and lower, where the user envisions some absolute ordering
of d-SoCs on a value scale. Thus higher and lower become much more specific, less relative, terms. Five such value
scales are discussed below. None are scientific scales in the sense of being subjected to prolonged and precise
scrutiny by groups of scientists; no such scales exist at this stage of our knowledge.
The first value scale is depicted in Figure 17-1. It is the value-scaling of d-SoCs implicitly held by most Western
intellectuals. I stress that it is held implicitly: it is conveyed along with the general value system of our society in
the enculturation process, without need for a teacher to say explicitly, "Complete rationality is our goal and
anything less than that is an inferior, lower state of consciousness."
The primary value in this scheme is rationality, adherence to logic and values our culture believes are true. The
scheme recognizes that the ordinary state is occasionally neurotic, in that rationality is often replaced by
rationalization of processes based on unconscious drives and emotions. If only we could be cured of these
occasional neurotic flaws, it is reasoned, we could be completely rational (although we do not like "completely
rational" to being equated with being computerlike). Dreaming is a lower d-SoC because there are many logical
flaws in it and the dreamer is out of touch with (consensus) reality.
Psychotic states[1] are even lower in these ways, and toxic
psychoses (states induced by major poisonings) are usually the
most irrational and out-of-touch states of all.
Some ambivalent recognition is given to the value of creative
states, so they are shown between ordinary rationality and
dreaming. Most intellectuals consider such creative states the
province of artists or fringe intellectuals, not themselves, and,
since these states are associated with emotionality, they are viewed
ambivalently. Marijuana intoxication is generally valued about the
same as dreaming: it is irrational and out of touch, but probably
not too harmful. Psychedelic-drug-induced changes in
consciousness are considered more dangerous and out of touch,
like psychoses.
This ordering of these conditions and d-SoCs is not scientific for
it has never been made explicit and subjected to detailed
examination to determine how well it orders reality. Further, its
implicitness under ordinary circumstances makes it a barrier to
better understanding. When a value system or a set of assumptions
is implicit, you do not know you have it, so you do not question its
value. You automatically perceive and think in terms of the
value/assumption system. For example, anything said by a person
labeled "psychotic" must be viewed as a sign of his craziness, not
to be taken at face value. Patients are crazy; the doctors are sane.
Many individuals have valuations of d-SoCs somewhat different
from the scheme shown in Figure 17-1, of course, but this
generally represents the d-SoC valuation system of most
intellectuals, doctors, psychiatrists, psychologists, and scientists—
the people thought to be authorities in these matters.
A quite different valuing of d-SoCs is held by many people we can call hip. As is true of the orthodox ordering,
there important individual exceptions, but the scheme fits many people, especially the young. If you are a parent
whose valuation system is orthodox you may well have experienced some bitter arguments with your sons or
daughters whose valuation system is hip.
In this system (Figure 17-2) the highest states are mystical experiences, often experienced in conjunction with
psychedelic-drug-induced states of meditative states. Creative states and marijuana intoxication are next in value,
and some of the experiences of the higher states can be achieved in them, albeit at reduced intensity. Then comes an
open or loose rationality, an ordinary d-SoC in which, because you do not take too seriously the apparent rationality
of your culture's consensus reality. You can function well enough in an ordinary d-SoC, but you do not value that d-
SoC as highly as do those who have no other reference experiences of higher states.
Ordinary, neurotically flawed rationality is the next lower state. A state of complete rationality is valued
somewhere between open and ordinary rationality, a reflection of existing suspicion of a totally unemotional,
computerlike state. Dreaming is generally considered somewhat lower than ordinary rationality, although it is
recognized that some dreams can be inspired; psychoses and toxic psychoses are at the bottom of the value
continuum. As with dreaming, there is recognition that psychotic states can sometimes be very high, however.
Which of these two value continua is true? Which is more useful?
Neither. In neither have details about each state and the performance potential with respect to specific tasks in
each state been clarified.
Can you argue that the orthodox ordering is more workable for surviving in consensus reality? What about those
other adherents to the relatively high state of ordinary rationality who order napalm dropped on children to protect
them from________ (fill in your favorite-ism)? Can you argue that the hip ordering is better for realizing oneself?
What about all the starving children in countries like India, where mystical states have long been considered the
highest by cultural norms? Or the near total failure rate of communes of American young people who accept the hip
value ordering?
I offer not answers to these questions. Indeed, the questions and examples I have chosen are designed to illustrate
how poor our understanding is at present. Higher or lower for what specific thing? That is the question we must
keep constantly in mind.
Three systems for value-ordering d-SoCs are described below to illustrate that explicit and detail orderings are
possible. Two are from the Buddhist tradition and one from the Arica traditions. While none of these is scientific,
each is capable of being cast as a scientific theory and tested.
Figure 17-3 presents an ordering of nine d-SoCs that are all higher than ordinary consciousness. These are d-
SoCs[2] to be obtained sequentially in seeking enlightenment through a path of concentrative meditation in
Buddhism.
The underlying value dimension here might be called freedom. The Buddha taught that the ordinary state is one
of suffering and entrapment in the forms and delusions of our own minds. The root cause of this suffering is
attachment, the (automatized) desire to prolong pleasure and avoid pain. The journey along the Path of
Concentration starts when the meditater tries to focus attention on some particular object of concentration. As he
progresses, his concentration becomes more subtle and powerful and he eventually moves from formed experiences
(all form has the seeds of illusion in it) to a series of formless states, culminating in the eighth jhana, where there is
neither perception nor nonperception of anything.
Figure 17-4 illustrates another succession of higher states within the Buddhist framework. Here the technique
involves not one-pointed, successively refined concentration, but successively refined states of insight into the
ultimate nature of one's own mind. Starting from either the state of Access Concentration (where ability to focus is
quite high) or the state of Bare Insight (proficiency in noticing internal experiences), the meditater becomes
increasingly able to observe the phenomena of the mind, and to see their inherently unsatisfactorily character. The
ultimate goal is a state called nirodh, which is beyond awareness itself. Nirodh is the ultimate accomplishment in
this particular version of Buddhism, higher than the eighth jhana on the Path of Concentration. The reader
interested in more detail about these Buddhist orderings should consult Daniel Goleman's chapter to Transpersonal
Psychologies {128}.
The third ordering (Figure 17-5) is John Lilly's conceptualization of the system taught by Oscar Ichazo in Arica,
Chile. More background is available in the chapter by John Lilly and Joseph Harts in Transpersonal Psychologies
{128}, as well as in Lilly's Center of the Cyclone {35}.
In the Arica ordering the value dimension is one of freedom and of which psychic center dominates
consciousness. The numerical designation of each state indicates the number of cosmic laws supposedly governing
that state, as expounded by Gurdjieff (see Kathy Riordan's chapter on Gurdjieff in Transpersonal Psychologies
{128} and Ouspensky {48}), with a plus sign indicating positive valuation of that state. For example, in the +3 state
only three laws govern; a person is less free in the +6 state, where six law govern. A minus sign indicates negative
emotions. Thus the ordinary d-SoC, the-24 state, is a neurotic one of pain, guilt, fear, and other negative emotions.
The-24 state is also under 96 laws, making it less free, as the number of governing laws doubles at each lower level.
Lilly notes that this ordering of highness does not hold for all possible tasks in this scheme. The +12 state and
higher, for instance, involve a progressive loss of contact with external reality and so become lower states if one has
to perform some external task like driving a car or eating.
Now, is the +24 state higher or lower than the sixth jhana? Is the state of realization on the Path of Insight higher
or lower than the +3 state? Which state in these three orderings is best for coping with the world food shortage? For
understanding an artist's message? For dying?
Arguing a particular answer to any one of these or similar questions involves first fully understanding the system
that defines one state, and then fully understanding the system that defines the other state. We must grasp the many
implicit assumptions that underlie the world-view of each system. If we do not, we waste our time using common
words that carry dissimilar implicit assumptions. When we understand the world-views behind these systems, we
still must examine how well each system orders the experience/realities of its own practitioners and how well it
orders and explains experiences by nonpractitioners.
What, then, is a higher state of consciousness? It is something many of us long for; it is something some of us
have put into our value ordering systems; it is a reality that exists under various sets of circumstances. But it is not
something we can handle well scientifically, at least not at this stage of our knowledge. But we can begin by
making our system of valuing states explicit.
Foototes
[1] I use "state" very loosely in this chapter, for we do not know whether all of these value-ordered "states" arc
stable d-SoCs. (back)
[2] We do not know enough about these states in scientific terms to be sure whether they represent nine d-SoCs
with the quantum jump between each or a smaller number of d-SoCs, some of whose distinctions actually are
differences in depth within a d-SoC For purposes of discussion here, however, we will assume these jhana states,
and the states described in Figures 17-4 and 17-5, are all d-SoCs. (back)
8th JHANA
Neither perception nor nonperception,
equanimity and one-pointedness.
7th JHANA
Awareness of no-thingness
equanimity and one-pointedness. FORMLESS
6th JHANA STATES
Objectless infinite consciousness,
HIGH equanimity and one-pointedness.
5th JHANA
Consciousness of infinite space,
equanimity and one-pointedness.
4th JHANA
Equanimity and one-pointedness, bliss,
all feelings of bodily pleasure cease.
VALUE
DIMENSION 3rd JHANA
Feelings of bliss, one-pointedness, and
equanimity. Rapture ceases.
2nd JHANA
Feelings of rapture, bliss, one-pointedness.
No thought of primary object of concentration.
MATERIAL
1st JHANA STATES
LOW Hindering thoughts, sensory perception, and awareness of
painful bodily states all cease. Initial and unbroken sustained
attention to primary object of concentration, feelings of
rapture, bliss, and one-pointedness
ACCESS STATE
Hindering thoughts overcome, other thoughts remain. Awareness
of sensory inputs and body states, primary object of concentration
dominates thought. Feelings of rapture, happiness, equanimity.
Initial and sustained thoughts of primary object.
Flashes of light or bodily lightness.
NIRODH
Total cessation of consciousness.
EFFORTLESS INSIGHT
Contemplation is quick, effortless, indefatigable.
Instantaneous knowledge of Anatta, Anicca, Dukkha.
Cessation of pain, pervasive equanimity
HIGH
REALIZATION
Realizations of the dreadful, unsatisfactory, and wearisome nature of physical and
mental phenomena, physical pain, arising of desire to escape these phenomena.
Perception of vanishing of mind and objects, perception fast and
flawless, disappearance of lights, rapture, etc.
PSEUDONIRVANA
Clear perception of the arising and passing of each successive mind moment,
accompanied by various phenomena such as brilliant light, rapturous feelings,
VALUE tranquility, devotion, energy, happiness, strong mindfulness, equanimity toward
DIMENSION objects of contemplation. Quick and clear perception,
and attachment to these newly arisen states.
STAGE OF REFLECTIONS
These processes seen as neither pleasant nor reliable. Experience of Dukkha,
unsatisfactoriness. These processes are seen to arise and pass away at every
moment of contemplation. Experience of Anicca. Impermanence. These
dual processes are seen as devoid of self. Experience of Anatta, not-self,
LOW as distinct and separate processes.
MINDFULNESS
Mindfulness of bodily function, physical
sensations, mental states, or mind objects.
ACCESS CONCENTRATION BARE INSIGHT
Previous attainment of access. Achievement of ability to notice all phenomena
Concentration on path of of mind, to point where interfering thoughts
concentration do not seriously disturb practice.
+3
Classical Satori. Fusion with Universal Mind, union with God, being
one of the creators of energy from the void. Functioning in the Ma'h
spiritual center above the head.
+6
HIGH Being a point source of consciousness, energy, light, and love.
Astral travel and other PSI phenomena. Fusion with other entities
in time. Functioning in the path mental center in the head.
+12
Blissful, Christ-attuned state. Reception of Baraka (Divine Grace),
cosmic love, cosmic energy, heightened bodily awareness. Highest function
of bodily and planetside consciousness, being in love, being in a positive LSD
energy state. Functioning in the Oth emotional center in the chest.
VALUE
DIMENSION +24
Professional Satori or basic Satori. All the needed programs are in
the unconscious of the biocomputer, operating smoothly: The self is lost
in pleasurable activities that one knows best and likes to do. Functioning
in the Kath moving center in the lower belly.
+/-48
The neutral biocomputer state. Absorption and transmission of new ideas,
reception and transmission of new data and new programs, doing, teaching,
LOW and learning with maximum facility. Emotionally neutral.
On the earth, excellent reality contact.
-24
Neurotic states, negative states: Pain, guilt, fear, doing what one
has to do but in a state of pain, guilt, fear. Slightly too much alcohol,
small amount of opium, or first stages of lack of sleep.
Physics distinguishes between a pure energy state and a matter state, with both energy and matter operating
within the framework of space and time. A convenient abbreviation for this quaternity is MEST (matter, energy,
space, time). The first principle is that whenever pure energy is converted into matter , it generally (universally?)
creates a pair of particles whose properties are, in some important way, opposite. An electron and a positron may be
created, for example, with opposite electrical charges, or a pair of particles may be created that spin in opposite
directions. Conversely, the proper interaction of a pair of such opposite particles results in their annihilation as
particles and their transformation back into pure energy. Thus the transformation of energy into matter is generally
done in a dualistic manner. The principle seems so general that whenever a new particle is discovered, its exact
opposite is looked for as a matter of course.
Assuming that a resulting duality in a transition from an energy state to a matter state is a general universal
principle, a parallel manifestation at the psychological level is seen in a phenomenon encountered in some d-ASCs,
the mystical experience of unity. This is a direct experience of a condition of consciousness in which all duality is
transcended. In contrast to ordinary existence in a world dominated by opposites, there is to up and down, good and
evil, creator and created, I and thou; everything is oneness. Our language, of course, cannot express the experience
adequately. The experience of what may have been consciousness of the Void (Chapter 14) in William's ultradeep
hypnotic state may be an example of this kind. In Buddhist literature, the highest kind of samadhi, reached by
successive refinements of concentration, is described as a state in which there is neither perception nor
nonperception {20}. This state of consciousness seems analogous to the condition of pure, undifferentiated energy.
But we do not live in such a state of consciousness. Few people ever attain it, and even to them it is a transient
experience, though of supreme importance. All the spiritual systems {128} that have this realization of a
transcendence of duality as an experiential basis teach that in the ordinary d-SoC (and in many d-ASCs) duality is a
basic principle governing the manifestation of consciousness. Thus pleasure cannot exist without pain, hope cannot
exist without despair, courage cannot exist without fear, up cannot exist without down. The state of mystical unity,
of Void consciousness, seems to be the experience of pure awareness, transcending all opposites, like the pure
energy state, while consciousness, the condition of awareness deeply intermeshed with and modified by the
structures of the mind and brain, is a realm of duality, the analog of the matter state. This seems to be a
manifestation of the principle of duality in he psychological realm.
It is an exotic example, as most of us lack an experiential basis for understanding it. When we deal with human
consciousness we do not deal with undifferentiated energy manifesting as two opposite particles, the simple,
primary phenomena with which physics deals, but with complex, interacting systems made up of untold numbers of
more elementary systems constituting the structures of the mind and brain, activated by awareness and construction,
consciousness (as opposed to pure awareness), is the experiential area with which we are most familiar. As we shall
see in considering the other basic principles, the fact that our ordinary psychological experience is almost always
with the complex, ongoing structure of human consciousness makes it difficult to see how these basic principles,
derived for ideally simplified situations, can be applied precisely.
The quantum principle in physics states that because of the nature of certain physical systems, most obviously
that of the atom, certain transitions from one energy configuration to another can occur only in a complete, all-or-
none jump. In an atom, for example, an electron can be in one or another precise energy state, but cannot occupy an
energy level intermediate between these two. It must go from one to the other, given the requisite energy to bring
this about, in an all-or-none fashion. Thus there is one state, a forbidden zone, and then a second state. There may
be a third state, a fourth state, and so on, but the transition is always all-or-none. When dealing macroscopic objects
or systems that are made up of large numbers of the more elementary components governed by quantum laws, the
aggregate, the macroscopic system, may seem to show continuity over wide ranges of intermediate values, but this
is statistical illusion from a gross level of observation. For example, an aggregate made up of units, many of which
are in a quantum state that we can call two, and many of which are in a quantum state that we can call three, can
have an average value anywhere between two and three, depending on the relative distribution of the quantum
units.
I see the quantum principle, as stated in physics, as particular manifestation of a more general principle that
various components of the universe have a "shape" or "structure" or "energy configuration." On a familiar,
macroscopic level, for example, water can be in three distinct states, a solid (ice), a liquid (ordinary water), or a gas
(steam). There can be mechanical mixtures of the three states, as of water droplets falling or floating in the air, but
the solid, liquid, and gas states are quite distinct.
The application to consciousness of this general principle, that various components of reality have properties that
therefore determine the way they can interact with other units, is outlined in Chapter 2. To recapitulate briefly, a d-
SoC is a system or a pattern or an overall configuration of many psychological subsystems or structures. Each
subsystem shows variation within itself within certain limits, but maintains its overall identity as a subsystem. Since
identity means properties, this limits the number of possible ways a stable system can be built up from the
subsystems and thus limits the number of d-SoCs possible for a human being.
The induction of a d-ASC involves the application of disrupting forces to the b-SoC to push one or more
subsystems beyond their stable limits and/or to disrupt the feedback loops between subsystems that stabilize the b-
SoC. When enough feedback loops have been disrupted and/or enough subsystems pushed beyond their stable,
ordinary ranges of functioning, the overall organization of the b-SoC breaks down, and a transitional period of
varying duration occurs, with the subsystems having only transient, unstable relationships to each other. then, with
the application of appropriate patterning forces, the subsystems are reassembled in a new configuration that is
stable and that we call the d-ASC.
This process constitutes a kind of quantum jump. albeit not the neat quantum jump of an electron from one
discrete energy state to another in an atom. We are dealing with highly composite, complex structures, and even
when such structures are made up of units that operate on quantum principles, the aggregate may show various
degrees of continuity. Recall the earlier discussion of individual differences. For certain individuals, the transition
from a b-SoC to a d-ASC definitely shows a quantum jump, with no consciousness during the transition period. The
system properties of the d-ASC are quite different from those of the b-SoC.
The quantum jump from one d-SoC to a d-ASC may be a leap along what we conceive of as a continuum or it
may be the emergence of a totally new function or pattern of functioning.
The d-ASCs of which we now have some scientific knowledge occur in human beings who have been thoroughly
conditioned by enculturation processes, so the quantum jumps we have seen in investigating various d-ASCs may
largely represent the results of semiarbitrary cultural conditioning. That is, in a particular culture you might have to
be either straight or stoned, but in another culture you may be able to be a little of each simultaneously. However,
we can postulate as a general principle that the various subsystems and structures that make up the human mind
cannot be put together in just any arbitrary way: each structure has properties of its own that restrict its possible
interaction with other structures into a larger structure or system. Insofar as we can learn to study the mind beyond
the semiarbitrary cultural conditionings of consciousness, the study of d-ASCs may eventually tell us something
about the fundamental properties of the human mind and the way in which the overall system of consciousness can
thus be structured, what its basic states and forbidden zones are.
In nonmathematical terms the relativity principle in physics is that there is not such thing as a neutral observer.
Rather, any observer exists within a particular MST framework, and this framework affects his observations.
This is more profound than saying that an observer's sense organs affect his observations. We realize, for
example, that we do not naturally know how the world looks in the ultraviolet spectrum of light, but we can build
instruments to make a translation for us. What is here being said is that the observer is an inherent part of the
MEST framework, and this gives the observer himself characteristics, over and above what can be compensated for
by special instruments, which affect his observations of thins outside himself.
The principle of relativity applies in a variety of ways in psychological work, even though most psychologists
have not seriously accepted it. Indeed, it applies to you and me in our everyday lives, even though we do not always
accept it. At one level, each human being, functioning in his ordinary d-SoC (or in a d-ASC), shows selective
perception, selective thinking, selective action that in turn controls his perceptions. Because of his particular culture
and the consensus reality to which his ordinary d-SoC has adapted him, plus his personal idiosyncrasies, he (1) is
more prone to observe certain things; (2) is unlikely to observe other kinds of things at all; and (3) may have a great
many transformations and distortions of what he does sense before it reaches his consciousness. This all happens
unconsciously, automatically, and smoothly in the normally functioning adult. For example, the Christian
missionary of the 1800s "saw" sin in the form of public display of "lust" in a native village, when the natives would
have said that they were only giving polite approval to the dancers.
This kind of relativity is becoming recognized in psychology under the topics of experimenter bias and the
implicit demand characteristics of experiments. An experimenter's desire to prove the hypothesis he believes in not
only can influence how he perceives his data, but also can subtly influence his subjects to cooperate in ways that
will erroneously "prove" his hypothesis. Your beliefs about the nature of things around you can influence the way
you see things and subtly influence others to uphold your view of reality.
In addition to this culturally and individually conditioned relativity, the fact that each person is human and
therefore born with certain basic properties in his nervous system, sensory receptors, and perhaps in the nature of
the awareness that enters into or comes from the operation of his nervous system, equips him with built-in biases
for seeing the universe in certain kinds of ways and not other ways. This applies not only to the external universe
perceived through his senses or with instrumental aids, but to his observations of his own internal experiences.
It is amazing how little recognized this idea is. The old concept of the "neutral observer," common in nineteenth
century physics but now long abandoned by physicists, is alive and well within the ranks of psychologists,
implicitly guiding almost all experiments. A wiser course is always to assume that an observer or experimenter has
biases and selectivities in the way he perceives, evaluates, and acts, even when these are not obvious.
D-ASCs are of particular interest here. The ordinary d-SoC is a complex system incorporating various
selectivities for perceiving the outside world and our own internal experiences, and functioning as a tool for coping
with our external and internal worlds. Transiting to a d-ASC constitutes a qualitative as well as a quantitative
restructuring of the systems, which may be looked at as a new set of filters, biases, and tools for the
observer/theorizer. By observing both the external and internal worlds from a variety of d-SoCs, rather than only
one, we can develop a number of state-specific sciences within various d-ASCs. This enables a complementary
series of views of the external and internal universes, which may partially compensate for the limits of the view
found in any one d-SoC. I emphasize partially compensate, because no matter how many different d-SoCs we
observe from, we are still human, and that probably implies ultimate limits on what we can do. We have not begun
to approach these ultimate limits.
Note again that the idea that we must obtain complementary (I use this term in the sense it is used in physics)
views of the universe from various d-SoCs, in order to get as full as view of it as possible, collides with an implicit
and pervasive assumption that the ordinary d-SoC is the optimal, most logical state of consciousness and thus the
one in which ultimate understandings will occur. This powerful and implicit bias, a product of enculturation,
seriously hinders our thinking. We should always be open to the possibility that there is some "higher" d-SoC of
which all other d-SoCs can be seen as fully comprehensible subsets: perhaps this is what enlightenment means in
some ultimate sense. The ordinary d-SoC, with all its culturally conditioned limitations, is an unlikely candidate for
this high degree.
The last two basic principles of physics do not have obvious parallels in known psychological functioning
because the complexity of the human mind precludes such simple analogies. It is interesting, however, to consider
them and assume that they ought to be manifest in the psychological realm if they are true. In this way, we can alert
ourselves to look for parallels.
The basic expression of the principle of conservation in physics is that in any reaction nothing is lost. The sum
total of what goes in is the sum total of what goes out, even if there are transformations in form. This was originally
thought of as the conservation of mass: the amount of matter that went into a chemical reaction was exactly equal to
the amount of matter that came out of it. Because of various theoretical prospective changes, as well as the
development of extremely precise measurement techniques, this definition was seen to be too simple and the
principle was rephrased in terms of the conservation of the sum of mass and energy. Thus mass can be traded for
energy, for example, but the sum is still the same. Modifications of the exact quantities are put into this equivalence
equation in various physical situations, but the basic principle that what goes in equals what comes out holds
generally through physics.
I do not see the obvious application of this to conscious experiences that we know of, because we almost never
have simple, straightforward actions of consciousness that allow this kind of input-output comparison. Even
apparently simple psychological reactions may consist of many separate steps that are perceived dimly or not at all
due to automatization {14}. Also, experience at almost all times involves several things going on in rapid
succession or even apparently simultaneously, and we know that important unconscious reactions can occur
simultaneously with conscious ones. Thus we may have conscious experiences that seem to deplete or use up
psychological energy or create psychological experience (the equivalent of mass?), and other kinds of experiences
that seem to increase energy, but we do not know how to assess or measure these in a clear enough way to begin to
measure what goes in and what goes out and see whether they are equivalent. We may be able to develop indirect
indicators of unconscious reactions or make unconscious reactions more conscious by means of therapeutic or self-
observational techniques.
The physical expression of this principle is that nature is economical: when a process can occur in several
alternate ways, the one requiring the least expenditure of energy is the one used. Apparent exceptions generally turn
out to conform to the principle and to have seemed exceptional because they were viewed in isolation: when
considered as a part of a larger system, the principle of least action is, in fact, followed.
An initial glance at psychological experience seems to show many contradictions to this. We do all sorts of things
every day in ways that, even to our own perception, are certainly not the most economical ways. An observer may
detect even more wasted energy. Suppose I carry a book from here into the next room. If I observe the action
carefully, I will probably find that I have not used my body in a way that requires a minimal expenditure of energy
to move the book from here to there. The complicating factor in trying to apply the fifth principle to psychology is
the human propensity for doing several things simultaneously, many of them not in consciousness or even available
to consciousness. So while carrying the book from this room to the next I may also be thinking about what to write
in this chapter an using "body English" as part of my thinking process. I may also be semiconsciously trying to
improve my posture, semiconsciously rebelling against the need to try and improve myself so much of the time, and
so deliberately wasting some energy, either bodily or psychological energy, in order to express my "freedom."
A claim made in many spiritual writings, supported by some experiential data from various d-ASCs, is that, with
effort, we can become more and more conscious of exactly what we are doing. Whether we can become conscious
of everything we are doing psychologically at a given moment is unknown. Thus it is unclear whether we can ever
be in a position adequately to assess whether the law of least action applies to psychological phenomena. But it may
be profitable to postulate that the fifth principle does apply and then proceed to look for manifestations.
In the history of science it has often been fruitful to postulate some principle as true before there is good evidence
for it, and then to examine the subject matter of the particular science with the postulate in mind. It may be
profitable to follow this plan for the fourth and fifth principles. They may be true; if they are not, the need to
develop more precise ways of measuring many psychological phenomena simultaneously in order to test the truth
of the principles will be a major advance in itself.
As above, so below?
Footnote
[1] I In the spring of 1973, my colleagues at the Institute for the Study of Human Consciousness and I heard an
exceptionally lucid presentation by Dean Brown, Stanford Research Institute, of the basic principles of physics,
general principles that seem to emerge repeatedly in all areas of physics and that may represent fundamental
principles underlying the universe, Brown suggested that these same principles may have parallels in the study of
the mind, although he did not expound on this idea. The suggestion took firm root in my mind and has resulted in
this chapter. I am also indebted to Andrew Dienes for helping me to understand and express some of the physics
ideas in this chapter. (back)
Footnotes
[1] I use the Buddhist term samsara in a general sense to indicate a d-SoC (ordinary or nonordinary) dominated
by illusion, as detailed throughout this chapter, rather than in a technically strict Buddhist sense. I express my
appreciation to Tarthong Tulku, Rinpoche, for helping me understand the Buddhist view. (back)
[2] Note an implicit, quantitative assumption here that in the competition of two processes, whichever has the
greater energy (both attention/awareness energy and other kinds of energies) wins, subject to modification by the
particulars of the structures involved. Certain structures may use energy more effectively than others. This line of
thought needs development. (back)
The discussion in Chapter 19 involves a value judgment that should be made more explicit: being in clear contact
with external reality is good; being in poor contact with it is bad. This statement should not be overgeneralized:
there is nothing wrong, for example, with deliberately becoming absorbed in a good movie and deliberately
ignoring those aspects of reality that are inconsistent with enjoying the movie. It is undesirable, on the other hand,
to believe you are in good contact with reality when you are not.
I think most readers will have difficulty accepting Chapter 19 on more than an intellectual level. In some of our
bad moments we may be unhappy with the ordinary d-SoC, but generally we seem pleased. Feeling happy is a
function of a viable culture. If the culture is to survive, the majority of its members must feel contented with what
they are doing and feel they are carrying out a meaningful function in life. Whether we generally feel happy or not,
however, my personal observations and understanding of much of the research findings of modern psychology have
convinced me that the analysis of ordinary consciousness as samsara is basically true. The present chapter is based
on the assumption that it is true and is concerned with ways out of a state of illusion. It is not a guide to
"enlightenment," for that is both inappropriate in the context of the present volume and beyond the reach of my
competence.
Why, then, would you or I or anyone want to escape from the samsaric state that is our ordinary state of
consciousness? the exact answer varies for every individual, but in general there is a mixture of cultural, personal,
and growth/curiosity reasons.
A major function of a culture is to provide a consensus reality that not only deals adequately with the physical
world about it but also produces a psychologically satisfactory life for the majority of its members. Each of us
needs to feel that he belongs and that his life has meaning in terms of some valued, larger scheme of things. So
every society has a mythos, a set of explicit and implicit beliefs and myths about the nature of reality and the
society's place in it, that makes the activities of the people in that society meaningful. The mythos that has sustained
dour society for so long, largely the Judeo-Christian ethic, is no longer a very satisfactory mythos for many people.
Similarly, the rationalism or scientism or materialism that tried to replace the religious mythos of our society has
also turned out to be unsatisfactory for a large number of people. So we are faced with disruptions and conflicts in
our society has also turned out to be unsatisfactory for a large number of people. So we are faced with disruptions
and conflicts in our society as people search consciously or unconsciously for more satisfying values. Our wheels of
life, to continue the analogy of Figure 19-2, are not rolling along smoothly through our consensus reality. There are
too many flat spots on the wheel that produce unpleasant jolts, and too many pieces of broken glass and potholes in
the road of our consensus reality. So the ride is no longer comfortable.
Personal reason for desiring a way out may involve initial poor enculturation, so we don't fit in well, knowledge
of other cultural systems that seem advantageous in certain ways, and/or hope that a more satisfactory substitute can
be found for our faulty culture. Various kinds of personal discontent make it difficult or impossible for an individual
to find meaning in his life within the consensus reality of the culture. If he acts out these discontents, he may be
classified as neurotic or psychotic, as a criminal, or as a rebel, depending on his particular style. If he acts out in a
way that capitalizes on widespread cultural discontent, he may be seen as a reformer or pioneer. Or, he may
outwardly conform to the mores of contemporary society but be inwardly alienated.
Finally, a person may want to escape for what I call growth/curiosity reasons, a healthy curiosity or desire to
know. He may be able to tolerate the limitations and dissatisfactions of the culture around him and cope
satisfactorily with it, and yet really want to know what lies outside that consensus reality, what other possibilities
exist. He may see the limitations of the current worldview and want to know what worldviews could replace it or
whether it can be modified.
I emphasize scientific curiosity in this book, the desire to understand coupled with realization that science is an
excellent tool for gaining understanding. But even those of us who seek larger scientific understanding are also
motivated by cultural and personal forces.
A major intellectual theme in the Western world lately has been that there are no ways out. Seeing the
irrationality and horror, the samsaric nature of much of the world about us, some philosophers have concluded that
this simply is human nature and that the best we can hope to do is tolerate it in existential despair or try, without
much hope, to do the best we can. Indeed, a person can use such despair as a prop for the ego by priding himself on
his "realism" and courage in facing such a dismal situation. While I respect these philosophies of despair for their
honest recognition that there is no easy way out, I am of an optimistic nature myself and cannot accept despair as an
end goal.
More importantly, my studies of people's experiences in various d-ASCs have convinced me that people can and
do have vital, living experiences that are ways out. People have what Maslow {36} called peak experiences of
openness, freedom, and belonging in which they feel they transcend, at least temporarily, the samsaric condition of
ordinary consciousness. It can be argued that these experiences are just other illusions, that there is no freedom. But
the belief that a way out does not exist may be just as illusory.
When the search for a way out is triggered by discontent with the ordinary d-SoC, a common reaction is to blame
your discontent on some particular aspect of yourself or your society and look for ready-made solutions. There are
thousands of leaders and groups who have ready-made solutions to sell you or give you—a multitudes of-isms and-
ologies. Give yourself to Jesus, join this commune, join political party X and remake the world, support the
revolution, the truth is now revealed through yogi Z, eat your way to enlightenment with organic foods, find health
and happiness with a low-cholesterol (or a high-cholesterol) diet, live in foreign country K where nobody hassles
you.
This is not meant to imply a blanket criticism of all communities, political and social ideas, or spiritual systems:
indeed, in Transpersonal Psychologies {128} I attempt to promote the psychologies inherent in spiritual disciplines
because of their great value. Most of the-isms and-ologies being offered contain valuable techniques for personal
growth, ideas and techniques that can help you get out. But, when you motive for escape stems from a momentary
discomfort with your present consensus reality, from a feeling that your wheel of life has too many flat spots and is
hitting too many bumps, you may be seeking not radical change in your self as the root cause of your problems, but
simply a more satisfactory belief system, a rounder wheel, and a nicely protected consensus reality that has no
bumps. Any tool for personal or spiritual growth that humanity has ever devised can be perverted from its original
function and used for simply making a person feel comfortable. Too often, a person is not really interested in
looking more directly at reality, he simply wants his current samsaric wheel of life, the structures of his mind,
overhauled or replaced with a new set that provides many good feeling sand hardly any bad feelings.
Figure 20-1 is a revision of Figure 19-1, used to illustrate the concept of samsara. The content of the associational
chains that are activated is altered, and the tone of the emotional energies is changed from negative to positive, and
so the person's experience is positive. The labels on the figure make it self-explanatory. Still, all that happens in
reality is that a stranger walks up and says, "Hi, my name is Bill." But this time the person, who we can call Sara,
becomes extremely happy as a result and feels very good about herself. Yet she is as much in a state of illusion,
samsara, as she was before. She has a set of internal structures, internal machinery, that make her feel good, but she
is no more in touch with reality than before.
Since the ordinary d-SoC is the creator and maintainer of consensus reality on a personal level, and since the
sharing of similar, ordinary, "normal" d-SoCs by others is the maintainer of the consensus reality on a social level,
one way out of samsara is to enter a d-ASC, spend as much time there as possible, and get all your friends into that
d-ASC too. You would choose a d-ASC or d-ASCs you valued, where you felt "high." To many people today the
solution to the discomfort of current reality seems to be to get high and stay high.
Many of us are currently fascinated with the possibilities of being happy or solving our problem by entering into
various d-ASCs, using chemical or nonchemical means. We have not yet learned to estimate realistically the costs
of this route. We know the costs of chronic alcohol use, but seem willing to tolerate them. We do not know the costs
of other d-ASCs very well. Consensus realities can exist and be created in various d-ASCs. The explanation of
ordinary consciousness as samsara may well apply in d-ASCs such as drunkenness or marijuana intoxication. In
other d-ASCs, such as meditative states, samsaric illusion may be less common, but this has not yet been shown
scientifically.
We tend to get into what John Lilly {35} calls "overvaluation spaces"; we tend to be carried away by the contrast
between our experience of the d-ASC and the ordinary d-SoC, and so overvalue the d-ASC. I think this is largely a
function of novelty or need motivated blindness. Especially if we have taken a risk, such as using illegal drugs, to
attain a d-ASC, we have a need to convince ourselves that the experience was worthwhile.
Further discussion of the costs of various d-ASCs seems to me premature. The immense amount of cultural
hysteria and propaganda in this area gives us distorted and mostly false views of what the costs are, and we must
work through this and build up some scientific knowledge before we can talk adequately about costs and benefits of
d-ASCs.
The values of experiencing and working in d-ASCs can b exceptionally high. But, as is true of all the many tools
that have been devised for human growth, a d-ASC's value depends on how well it is used. Experiencing a d-ASC
carries no guarantee of personal betterment. Achieving a valuable d-ASC experience depends on what we want,
how deeply and sincerely we want it, what conflicting desires we have, how much insight we have into ourselves,
and how well prepared we are to make use of what we get in the d-ASC. There is a saying in many spiritual
traditions: "He who tastes, knows." The process is not that automatic. A truer saying is: "He who tastes has an
opportunity to know."
In the d-ASCs we know much about scientifically, the experiencer can be in a samsaric condition, involved in a
personal or a consensus reality that is cut off from reality, even though its style is different, interesting, or
productive of greater happiness than the ordinary d-SoC.
Techniques exist, however, that are intended to free a person's awareness from the dominance of the structure, of
the machinery that has been culturally programmed into him. In terms of the radical view of awareness, whatever
basic awareness ultimately is, there are techniques that at least produce the experience of freeing awareness
partially or wholly from the continual dominance of structure, of moving toward a freer, more wide-ranging
awareness rather than a consciousness that is primarily a function of the automated structure pattern of consensus
reality. Let us consider the general categories into which these techniques fall, remembering that any discussion of
their ultimate usefulness is beyond current science.
The first step in using any of these techniques is to recognize that there is a problem. Assume, therefore, that an
individual, through self-observation, has acquired enough experiential knowledge of his samsaric condition to know
that he needs to and want to do something. Although there are many religious definitions of what a clear or higher
state of consciousness simply as one in which external reality is recognized more for what it is, less distorted by
internal processes.
Discriminative Awareness
One way to begin to escape from the samsaric condition is to pay enough directed attention to your mental
processes so that you can distinguish between primary perception coming in from the external world and
associational reaction to it. We tend to assume that we do this naturally, but I believe it is rare. This may be done by
understanding how your associational structures are built and how they generally operate, thus distinguishing
associational reactions on a content basis, and/or by getting a general experiential "feel" for a quality that
distinguishes associational reactions. If you can keep your primary perception and your reactions to it clearly
distinguished in your consciousness, you are less likely to project your reactions to stimuli onto the environment
and others or to distort incoming perception to make your perceptions consistent with internal reactions.
I have found, from both personal observation and indications in the psychological literature that making this
discrimination, putting a fairly high degree of awareness on the beginnings of the associational process, tend to
undercut their ability to automatically stimulate other associational chains and thus activate emotions. You need not
do anything in particular to the association, just be clearly aware that it is an associational reaction. The situation is
analogous to being on your good behavior when you know others are watching, whether or not those others are
doing anything in particular to influence your behavior.
If you refer to Figure 19-1 and 20-1, you will notice the label, DEROPP'S "WATCHMAN AT THE GATE"
ENTERS HERE. The analogy taken from DeRopp's book {15}, is to a watchman at the city gate (the senses) who
knows that certain slums in the city of the mind have outbursts of rioting when certain mischievous characters
(stimulus patterns) are allowed into the city. The watchman scrutinizes each traveler who comes up and does not
admit those he knows will cause rioting. If you have a good understanding of your associational and reaction
patterns, your prepotent needs, and the particular kinds of stimuli that set them off, you can maintain an attentive
watchfulness on your primary perception. When you realize that an incoming stimulus is the sort that will trigger an
undesirable reaction, you can inhibit the reaction. It is easier to become self-conscious, and thus remove some of
the energy from incoming stimuli before they have activated associational chains and prepotent needs, than to stop
the reactions once they have been activated.
To a certain extent the practice of discriminative awareness, described above, performs this function. Setting up
the watchman, however, provides a more specialized discrimination, paying special attention to certain troublesome
kinds of stimuli and taking more active measure when undesirable stimuli are perceived. The watchman robs the
reaction of its power early enough to prevent it from gaining any appreciable momentum; discriminative awareness
allows the reaction to tap into various prepotent needs, even though the continuous observation of it lessens
identification and so takes away some of its power.
Nonattachment
A classical technique in the spiritual psychologies for escaping from samsara is the cultivation of nonattachment,
learning to "look neutrally" on whatever happens, learning to pay full attention to stimuli and reactions but not to
identify with them. The identification process, the quality added by the operation of the Sense of Identity subsystem
discussed in Chapter 8, adds a great deal of energy to any psychological process. Without it, these processes have
less energy and therefore make less mischief.
Vipassana meditation is a specific practice of nonattachment performed in the technically restricted meditative
setting. Recall that the instructions (Chapter 7) are to pay attention to whatever happens, but not to try to make
anything in particular happen or to try to prevent anything in particular from happening. The idea is neither to
welcome nor reject any particular stimulus or experience. This is quite different from the ordinary stance toward
events, where a person seeks out and tries to pleasant ones. Meditation, as Naranjo {39} points out, is a technically
simplified situation: a person removes himself from the bustle of the world to make learning easier. But it is also
designed to teach nonattachment so the practice can be transferred to everyday life.
If one is successful in practicing nonattachment, the machinery of the mind runs when stimulated, but does not
automatically grab attention/awareness so readily; reactions and perceptions do not become indiscriminately fused
together; and attention/awareness energy remains available for volitional use.
These are two clear ways in which the practice of nonattachment can be flawed. Often a person believes that he is
unaffected by certain things, that he just is not interested in them or that they do not bother him. This apparent
indifference, however, actually comes from an active inhibitory process that takes place outside that focus of
awareness. So he is really up-tight even if he does not feel it. Self-observation and/feedback from others is a
corrective for this. Effective growth practices can thus promote unhappiness and upset by breaking through an
inhibitory layer before being able to work on the disturbances themselves.
The other flaw is that while nonattachment may free a person from the habitual loss of attention/awareness
energy to the machinery of the mind, the machinery is still there. He no longer automatically identifies with the
machinery; it no longer forcibly grabs his attention/awareness, but the machinery itself, while dormant, has not
been dismantled. What happens if he is put in totally new circumstances in which he has not practiced
nonattachment?
Recall that once the machinery of the mind is activated, it grabs attention/awareness energy, and after this,
control may be difficult or impossible. Totally new circumstances may activate the previously inactive structures in
novel ways so that they cannot be stopped. A person may be unaware that the machinery has begun operating, so it
can grab his attention/awareness energy and plunge him into a samsaric state again. This appears to have happened,
for example, to some Indian yogis who began living in the West. Their practice of nonattachment as a principal
discipline in India had enabled them to achieve a special serenity of mind, but this was under particular cultural
circumstances. As one example, yogis and holy men are treated as nonsexual beings in India. Thus women may
worship them, but in a completely nonsexual way. When they come to the West and are besieged in a sexual way by
beautiful young girls, the yogis, lacking practice in handling this, are subject to strongly activated samsaric
mechanisms.
Dismantling Structures
The above techniques are mindfulness techniques, involving an increase in awareness of what is happening and
how one is reacting to it, usually with some discipline, such as nonattachment, practiced in conjunction with this
increased awareness. To some extent, these mindfulness techniques can actually dismantle some of the structures of
the mind. This happens in two ways. First, some structures seem to need to operate in the dark; they cannot
continue to operate when one is fully conscious of what is happening. Thus, insight into the nature of a structure
results in its partial or full dissolution. Second, some structures and combinations of structures seem to need to be
activated periodically to maintain their integrity. By practices like the watchman at the gate or nonattachment,
which do not allow energy to flow freely into them, they are starved and gradually lose their integrity, Gurdjieff's
{48} technique of self-observation, for example, involves paying full attention to one's reactions without making
any attempt to change them. Many people practicing self-observation have had the experience of watching an
undesirable reaction occur repeatedly, then weakly and later not at all, even though the requisite stimulus occurs.
Many structures and subsystems are an intimate part of a person's enculturated personality, however, and are not
only highly resistant to change by insight, but may be incapable of being perceived well at all. They are so
connected to prepotent needs and defense mechanisms that they cannot be observed clearly, or else they are so
implicit that they are outside awareness. They are never observed, so observation and mindfulness techniques do
not work.
Here is where Western-developed psychotherapy becomes exceptionally valuable. Through feedback and
pressure provided by others, whether a single therapist or a group, ordinarily invisible aspects a person's self may be
so surcharged with emotional energy that he is forced to confront them, and this insight may change them. If insight
alone is not sufficient, a variety of techniques are available, ranging from operant-conditioning to guided imagery
techniques {3}, which can deliberately change specific structures.
Western-style psychotherapy is limited because it is likely to be used not on structures that are basic to the
samsaric condition, but only on structures that produce experiences and behaviors that are not acceptable in the
particular consensus reality. Thus many psychotherapists are not growth agents in a general sense, but rather work
to readjust a deviant person to the consensus reality of his culture. This is not a conscious manipulation on the part
of these psychotherapists, but simply a reflection of the power and implicitness of their own enculturation
processes. Psychotherapy can be a subversive tool in some practitioners' hands, for some of the assumptions of the
consensus reality can be questioned in it, and the patient can grow beyond his culture in some ways. All too often,
however, the implicit assumptions are not even questioned.
If we assume, for the purpose of this discussion, the 9at least partial) validity of the radical view of the mind,
then what are the limits to human consciousness and awareness? Figure 20-2 presents some speculation along this
line.
Consider reality as divided into two realms: MEST, the physical world, of which we know many of the basic
laws and are discovering more, and the realm of awareness, whose basic laws are essentially unknown to us at this
time. The ordinary d-SoC, then, is the gestalt product of awareness and structure, determined and limited by
whatever laws inherently govern each realm, and yet is also an emergent synthesis not fully predictable from the
laws of either realm.
In some ways the composite system is even more limited, for both the MEST structure and awareness have been
further restricted in the enculturation process. Thus the ordinary d-SoC is capable of considerable expansion: we
can change existing structures and build new ones, and we can cultivate the ability to control awareness more freely
within these structures and to pay attention to things other than what the culture has defined as important.
Judging from experiential reports, some d-ASCs seem to be much less mechanical, much less controlled by
structures and allowing more free range of awareness. This is represented in Figure 20-2 by the oval just to the left
of the ordinary d-SoC penetrating more into the realm of awareness and less into the realm of MEST. Similarly,
experiential reports from some d-ASCs—those caused by sedatives, for example—suggest that there is less
awareness and far more mechanicalness, that consciousness is far more restricted by structure than ordinarily. Thus
another oval, further to the left, shown as more into the MEST realm and less into the awareness realm. The
extreme case of this, of course, is mechanical intelligence, the computer, which (as far as we know) has no
awareness at all but processes information in a totally mechanical way, a way totally controlled by the laws of the
MEST realm. Present computers are also partially limited by cultural structuring; it only occurs to us to program
them to do certain "sensible" things, giving them a range that is probably less than their total capability.
Up to this point the discussion is still compatible with the orthodox view of the mind, which sees awareness as a
function of the brain. The circle to the far right in Figure 20-2, however, is compatible only with the radical view
that awareness can operate partially or totally independently of the brain structure. In some mystical experiences,
and in states called out-of-they-body experiences, people report existing at space/time locations different from that
of their physical bodies, or being outside of space/time altogether. I believe that parapsychological data require us
to consider this kind of statement as more than interesting experiential data, as possibly being valid rather than
simply being nonsense. The reader interested in the implications of parapsychology for the study of consciousness
should consult other writings of mine {128, 129, 131}. Let me note here that to the extent that this may be true,
awareness may potentially become partially or wholly free of the patterning influence of MEST structure.
An awareness of how structures and systems of structures tend automatically to grab attention/awareness and
other psychological energies makes it easy to form a picture of structure as bad and to see d-SoCs that are less
involved with structure as automatically better or higher. This is a mistake. Structures perform valuable functions as
well as confining ones. A d-SoC is not just a way of limiting awareness; it is also a way of focusing
attention/awareness and other psychological energies to make effective tools, to enable us to cope in particular
ways.
I have observed people in d-ASCs where they seem less caught in structures, more inclined toward the
unstructured awareness dimension of mind. My impression is that it was both a gain and a loss: new insights were
gained, but there was often an inability to hold to anything and change it in a desired direction. Certainly there are
times when not attempting to change anything, just observing, is the best course, but the ability to move between
activity and passivity as appropriate is optimal. The structures of d-SoCs aid us by restricting awareness and
facilitating focusing. Perhaps as meditative and similar exercises teach us to control attention/awareness more
precisely, we may have less need for structures.
As a scientist, I have tried to keep the speculation in these last three chapters compatible with the scientific
worldview and the scientific method as I know them. I have often drawn on data not generally accepted in orthodox
scientific circles, but they are data that I would be willing to argue are good enough to deserve closer examination.
Because I have set myself that restriction in writing this book, I now end speculation on how far human awareness
might be able to go, for to continue would take me further from my scientific data base than I am comfortable in
going at this time.
Let me conclude with what may seem a curious observation: Western psychology has collected an immense
amount of data supporting the concept in the first place. We have studied some aspects of samsara in far more detail
than Eastern traditions that originated the concept of samsara. Yet almost no psychologists apply this idea to
themselves! They apply all this knowledge of human compulsiveness and mechanicalness to other people, who are
labeled "abnormal" or "neurotic," and assume that their own states of consciousness basically logical and clear.
Western psychology now has a challenge to recognize this detailed evidence that our "normal" state is a state of
samsara and to apply the immense power of science and our other spiritual traditions, East and West, to the search
for a way out.
Figure 20-1. Development of samsaric consciousness with positive rather than negative emotional tone. As in
Figure 19-1, internal processes soon overwhelm perception and are mistaken for perception. (back)