pg48433 Images
pg48433 Images
pg48433 Images
Critique of Judgement
This ebook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United
States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it
away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg
License included with this ebook or online at
www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the United
States, you’ll have to check the laws of the country where you
are located before using this eBook.
Title: Kant’s Critique of Judgement
Author: Immanuel Kant
Translator: J. H. Bernard
Release date: March 8, 2015 [eBook #48433]
Language: English
Credits: Produced by Charlie Howard and the Online
Distributed
Proofreading Team at http://www.pgdp.net (This file was
produced from images generously made available by The
Internet Archive)
*** START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK
KANT’S CRITIQUE OF JUDGEMENT ***
Transcriber’s note: Cover created by Transcriber
and placed into the Public Domain.
KA N T ’ S
C R IT IQU E OF
J U D GE ME N T
MACMILLAN AND CO., LIMITED
LONDON · BOMBAY · CALCUTTA
MELBOURNE
BY
J. H. BERNARD.
TRINITY COLLEGE, DUBLIN,
May 24, 1892.
* * * * *
More than twenty-one years have passed since the first
edition of this Translation was published, and during that time
much has been written, both in Germany and in England, on
the subject of Kant’s Critique of Judgement. In particular, the
German text has been critically determined by the labours of
Professor Windelband, whose fine edition forms the fifth
volume of Kant’s Collected Works as issued by the Royal
Prussian Academy of Sciences (Berlin, 1908). It will be
indispensable to future students. An excellent account of the
significance, in the Kantian system, of the Urtheilskraft, by
Mr. R. A. C. Macmillan, appeared in 1912; and Mr. J. C.
Meredith has published recently an English edition of the
Critique of Aesthetical Judgement, with notes and essays,
dealing with the philosophy of art, which goes over the ground
very fully.
Some critics of my first edition took exception to the
clumsiness of the word “representation” as the equivalent of
Vorstellung, but I have made no change in this respect, as it
seems to me (and so far as I have observed to others who have
worked on the Critique of Judgement), that it is necessary to
preserve in English the relation between the noun Vorstellung
and the verb vorstellen, if Kant’s reasoning is to be exhibited
clearly. I have, however, abandoned the attempt to preserve the
word Kritik in English, and have replaced it by Critique or
criticism, throughout. The other changes that have been made
are mere corrections or emendations of faulty or obscure
renderings, with a few additional notes. I have left my original
Introduction as it was written in 1892, without attempting any
fresh examination of the problems that Kant set himself.
JOHN OSSORY.
THE PALACE, KILKENNY,
January 6, 1914.
GLOSSARY OF KANT’S
PHILOSOPHICAL TERMS
Absicht; design.
Achtung; respect.
Affekt; affection.
Angenehm; pleasant.
Anschauung; intuition.
Attribut; attribute.
Aufklärung; enlightenment.
Begehr; desire.
Begriff; concept.
Beschaffenheit; constitution or characteristic.
Bestimmen; to determine.
Darstellen; to present.
Dasein; presence or being.
Eigenschaft; property.
Empfindung; sensation.
Endzweck; final purpose.
Erkenntniss; cognition or knowledge.
Erklärung; explanation.
Erscheinung; phenomenon.
Existenz; existence.
Fürwahrhalten; belief.
Gebiet; realm.
Gefühl; feeling.
Gegenstand; object.
Geist; spirit.
Geniessen; enjoyment.
Geschicklichkeit; skill.
Geschmack; Taste.
Gesetzmässigkeit; conformity to law.
Gewalt; dominion or authority.
Glaube; faith.
Grenze; bound.
Grundsatz; fundamental proposition or principle.
Hang; propension.
Idee; Idea.
Leidenschaft; passion.
Letzter Zweck; ultimate purpose.
Lust; pleasure.
Meinen; opinion.
Neigung; inclination.
Objekt; Object.
Prinzip; principle.
Real; real.
Reich; kingdom.
Reiz; charm.
Rührung; emotion.
Schein; illusion.
Schmerz; grief.
Schön; beautiful.
Schranke; limit.
Schwärmerei; fanaticism.
Seele; soul.
Ueberreden; to persuade.
Ueberschwänglich; transcendent.
Ueberzeugen; to convince.
Unlust; pain.
Urtheil; judgement.
Urtheilskraft; Judgement.
Verbindung; combination.
Vergnügen; gratification.
Verknüpfung; connexion.
Vermögen; faculty.
Vernunft; Reason.
Vernünftelei; sophistry or subtlety.
Verstand; Understanding.
Vorstellung; representation.
Wahrnehmung; perception.
Wesen; being.
Willkühr; elective will.
Wirklich; actual.
Wohlgefallen; satisfaction.
Zufriedenheit; contentment.
Zweck; purpose.
Zweckmässig; purposive.
Zweckverbindung; purposive combination, etc.
PREFACE
We may call the faculty of cognition from principles a
priori, pure Reason, and the inquiry into its possibility and
bounds generally the Critique of pure Reason, although by this
faculty we only understand Reason in its theoretical
employment, as it appears under that name in the former work;
without wishing to inquire into its faculty, as practical Reason,
according to its special principles. That [Critique] goes merely
into our faculty of knowing things a priori, and busies itself
therefore only with the cognitive faculty to the exclusion of the
feeling of pleasure and pain and the faculty of desire; and of
the cognitive faculties it only concerns itself with
Understanding, according to its principles a priori, to the
exclusion of Judgement and Reason (as faculties alike
belonging to theoretical cognition), because it is found in the
sequel that no other cognitive faculty but the Understanding
can furnish constitutive principles of cognition a priori. The
Critique, then, which sifts them all, as regards the share which
each of the other faculties might pretend to have in the clear
possession of knowledge from its own peculiar root, leaves
nothing but what the Understanding prescribes a priori as law
for nature as the complex of phenomena (whose form also is
given a priori). It relegates all other pure concepts under
Ideas, which are transcendent for our theoretical faculty of
cognition, but are not therefore useless or to be dispensed
with. For they serve as regulative principles; partly to check
the dangerous pretensions of Understanding, as if (because it
can furnish a priori the conditions of the possibility of all
things which it can know) it had thereby confined within these
bounds the possibility of all things in general; and partly to
lead it to the consideration of nature according to a principle of
completeness, although it can never attain to this, and thus to
further the final design of all knowledge.
It was then properly the Understanding which has its
special realm in the cognitive faculty, so far as it contains
constitutive principles of cognition a priori, which by the
Critique, comprehensively called the Critique of pure Reason,
8
was to be placed in certain and sole possession against all
other competitors. And so also to Reason, which contains
constitutive principles a priori nowhere except simply in
respect of the faculty of desire, should be assigned its place in
the Critique of practical Reason.
Whether now the Judgement, which in the order of our
cognitive faculties forms a mediating link between
Understanding and Reason, has also principles a priori for
itself; whether these are constitutive or merely regulative (thus
indicating no special realm); and whether they give a rule a
priori to the feeling of pleasure and pain, as the mediating link
between the cognitive faculty and the faculty of desire (just as
the Understanding prescribes laws a priori to the first, Reason
to the second); these are the questions with which the present
Critique of Judgement is concerned.
A Critique of pure Reason, i.e. of our faculty of judging a
priori according to principles, would be incomplete, if the
Judgement, which as a cognitive faculty also makes claim to
such principles, were not treated as a particular part of it;
although its principles in a system of pure Philosophy need
form no particular part between the theoretical and the
practical, but can be annexed when needful to one or both as
occasion requires. For if such a system is one day to be
completed under the general name of Metaphysic (which it is
possible to achieve quite completely, and which is supremely
important for the use of Reason in every reference), the soil
for the edifice must be explored by Criticism as deep down as
the foundation of the faculty of principles independent of
experience, in order that it may sink in no part, for this would
inevitably bring about the downfall of the whole.
We can easily infer from the nature of the Judgement
(whose right use is so necessarily and so universally requisite,
that by the name of sound Understanding nothing else but this
faculty is meant), that it must be attended with great
difficulties to find a principle peculiar to it; (some such it must
contain a priori in itself, for otherwise it would not be set apart
by the commonest Criticism as a special cognitive faculty).
This principle must not be derived a priori from concepts, for
these belong to the Understanding, and Judgement is only
concerned with their application. It must, therefore, furnish of
itself a concept, through which, properly speaking, no thing is
cognised, but which only serves as a rule, though not an
objective one to which it can adapt its judgement; because for
this latter another faculty of Judgement would be requisite, in
order to be able to distinguish whether [any given case] is or is
not the case for the rule.
This perplexity about a principle (whether it is subjective
or objective) presents itself mainly in those judgements that
we call aesthetical, which concern the Beautiful and the
Sublime of Nature or of Art. And, nevertheless, the critical
investigation of a principle of Judgement in these is the most
important part in a Critique of this faculty. For although they
do not by themselves contribute to the knowledge of things,
yet they belong to the cognitive faculty alone, and point to an
immediate reference of this faculty to the feeling of pleasure
or pain according to some principle a priori; without
confusing this with what may be the determining ground of the
faculty of desire, which has its principles a priori in concepts
of Reason.—In the logical judging of nature, experience
exhibits a conformity to law in things, to the understanding or
to the explanation of which the general concept of the sensible
does not attain; here the Judgement can only derive from itself
a principle of the reference of the natural thing to the
unknowable supersensible (a principle which it must only use
from its own point of view for the cognition of nature). And
so, though in this case such a principle a priori can and must
be applied to the cognition of the beings of the world, and
opens out at the same time prospects which are advantageous
for the practical Reason, yet it has no immediate reference to
the feeling of pleasure and pain. But this reference is precisely
the puzzle in the principle of Judgement, which renders a
special section for this faculty necessary in the Critique; since
the logical judging according to concepts (from which an
immediate inference can never be drawn to the feeling of
pleasure and pain) along with their critical limitation, has at all
events been capable of being appended to the theoretical part
of Philosophy.
The examination of the faculty of taste, as the aesthetical
Judgement, is not here planned in reference to the formation or
the culture of taste (for this will take its course in the future as
in the past without any such investigations), but merely in a
transcendental point of view. Hence, I trust that as regards the
deficiency of the former purpose it will be judged with
indulgence, though in the latter point of view it must be
prepared for the severest scrutiny. But I hope that the great
difficulty of solving a problem so involved by nature may
serve as excuse for some hardly avoidable obscurity in its
solution, if only it be clearly established that the principle is
correctly stated. I grant that the mode of deriving the
phenomena of the Judgement from it has not all the clearness
which might be rightly demanded elsewhere, viz. in the case
of cognition according to concepts; but I believe that I have
attained to it in the second part of this work.
Here then I end my whole critical undertaking. I shall
proceed without delay to the doctrinal [part] in order to profit,
as far as is possible, by the more favourable moments of my
increasing years. It is obvious that in this [part] there will be
no special section for the Judgement, because in respect of this
faculty Criticism serves instead of Theory; but, according to
the division of Philosophy (and also of pure Philosophy) into
theoretical and practical, the Metaphysic of Nature and of
Morals will complete the undertaking.
INTRODUCTION
I. OF THE DIVISION OF
PHILOSOPHY
We proceed quite correctly if, as usual, we divide
Philosophy, as containing the principles of the rational
cognition of things by means of concepts (not merely, as logic
does, principles of the form of thought in general without
distinction of Objects), into theoretical and practical. But then
the concepts, which furnish their Object to the principles of
this rational cognition, must be specifically distinct; otherwise
they would not justify a division, which always presupposes a
contrast between the principles of the rational cognition
belonging to the different parts of a science.
Now there are only two kinds of concepts, and these admit
as many distinct principles of the possibility of their objects,
viz. natural concepts and the concept of freedom. The former
render possible theoretical cognition according to principles a
priori; the latter in respect of this theoretical cognition only
supplies in itself a negative principle (that of mere contrast),
but on the other hand it furnishes fundamental propositions
which extend the sphere of the determination of the will and
are therefore called practical. Thus Philosophy is correctly
divided into two parts, quite distinct in their principles; the
theoretical part or Natural Philosophy, and the practical part or
Moral Philosophy (for that is the name given to the practical
legislation of Reason in accordance with the concept of
freedom). But up to the present a gross misuse of these
expressions has prevailed, both in the division of the different
principles and consequently also of Philosophy itself. For what
is practical according to natural concepts has been identified
with the practical according to the concept of freedom; and so
with the like titles, ‘theoretical’ and ‘practical’ Philosophy, a
division has been made, by which in fact nothing has been
divided (for both parts might in such case have principles of
the same kind).
The will, regarded as the faculty of desire, is (in this view)
one of the many natural causes in the world, viz. that cause
which acts in accordance with concepts. All that is represented
as possible (or necessary) by means of a will is called
practically possible (or necessary); as distinguished from the
physical possibility or necessity of an effect, whose cause is
not determined to causality by concepts (but in lifeless matter
by mechanism and in animals by instinct). Here, in respect of
the practical, it is left undetermined whether the concept which
gives the rule to the causality of the will, is a natural concept
or a concept of freedom.
But the last distinction is essential. For if the concept
which determines the causality is a natural concept, then the
principles are technically practical; whereas, if it is a concept
of freedom they are morally practical. And as the division of a
rational science depends on the distinction between objects
whose cognition needs distinct principles, the former will
belong to theoretical Philosophy (doctrine of Nature), but the
latter alone will constitute the second part, viz. practical
Philosophy (doctrine of Morals).
All technically practical rules (i.e. the rules of art and skill
generally, or of prudence regarded as skill in exercising an
influence over men and their wills), so far as their principles
rest on concepts, must be reckoned only as corollaries to
theoretical Philosophy. For they concern only the possibility of
things according to natural concepts, to which belong not only
the means which are to be met with in nature, but also the will
itself (as a faculty of desire and consequently a natural
faculty), so far as it can be determined conformably to these
rules by natural motives. However, practical rules of this kind
are not called laws (like physical laws), but only precepts;
because the will does not stand merely under the natural
concept, but also under the concept of freedom, in relation to
which its principles are called laws. These with their
consequences alone constitute the second or practical part of
Philosophy.
The solution of the problems of pure geometry does not
belong to a particular part of the science; mensuration does not
deserve the name of practical, in contrast to pure, geometry, as
a second part of geometry in general; and just as little ought
the mechanical or chemical art of experiment or observation to
be reckoned as a practical part of the doctrine of Nature. Just
as little, in fine, ought housekeeping, farming, statesmanship,
the art of conversation, the prescribing of diet, the universal
doctrine of happiness itself, or the curbing of the inclinations
and checking of the affections for the sake of happiness, to be
reckoned as practical Philosophy, or taken to constitute the
second part of Philosophy in general. For all these contain
only rules of skill (and are consequently only technically
practical) for bringing about an effect that is possible
according to the natural concepts of causes and effects, which,
since they belong to theoretical Philosophy, are subject to
those precepts as mere corollaries from it (viz. natural
science), and can therefore claim no place in a special
Philosophy called practical. On the other hand, the morally
practical precepts, which are altogether based on the concept
of freedom to the complete exclusion of the natural
determining grounds of the will, constitute a quite special
class. These, like the rules which nature obeys, are called
simply laws, but they do not, like them, rest on sensuous
conditions but on a supersensible principle; and accordingly
they require for themselves a quite different part of
Philosophy, called practical, corresponding to its theoretical
part.
We hence see that a complex of practical precepts given
by Philosophy does not constitute a distinct part of Philosophy,
as opposed to the theoretical part, because these precepts are
practical; for they might be that, even if their principles were
derived altogether from the theoretical cognition of nature (as
technically practical rules). [A distinct branch of Philosophy is
constituted only] if their principle, as it is not borrowed from
the natural concept, which is always sensuously conditioned,
rests on the supersensible, which alone makes the concept of
freedom cognisable by formal laws. These precepts are then
morally practical, i.e. not merely precepts or rules in this or
that aspect, but, without any preceding reference to purposes
and designs, are laws.
FIRST BOOK
ANALYTIC OF THE BEAUTIFUL
FIRST MOMENT
12
OF THE JUDGEMENT OF TASTE ACCORDING TO
QUALITY
§ 11. The judgement of taste has nothing at its basis but the
form of the purposiveness of an object (or of its mode of
representation)
ANALYTIC OF THE
SUBLIME
§ 23. Transition from the faculty which judges of the
Beautiful to that which judges of the Sublime
64
DEDUCTION OF [PURE ] AESTHETICAL
JUDGEMENTS
Genius is the talent (or natural gift) which gives the rule to
Art. Since talent, as the innate productive faculty of the artist,
belongs itself to Nature, we may express the matter thus:
Genius is the innate mental disposition (ingenium) through
which Nature gives the rule to Art.
Whatever may be thought of this definition, whether it is
merely arbitrary or whether it is adequate to the concept that
we are accustomed to combine with the word genius (which is
to be examined in the following paragraphs), we can prove
already beforehand that according to the signification of the
word here adopted, beautiful arts must necessarily be
considered as arts of genius.
For every art presupposes rules by means of which in the
first instance a product, if it is to be called artistic, is
represented as possible. But the concept of beautiful art does
not permit the judgement upon the beauty of a product to be
derived from any rule, which has a concept as its determining
ground, and therefore has at its basis a concept of the way in
which the product is possible. Therefore, beautiful art cannot
itself devise the rule according to which it can bring about its
product. But since at the same time a product can never be
called Art without some precedent rule, Nature in the subject
must (by the harmony of its faculties) give the rule to Art; i.e.
beautiful Art is only possible as a product of Genius.
We thus see (1) that genius is a talent for producing that
for which no definite rule can be given; it is not a mere
aptitude for what can be learnt by a rule. Hence originality
must be its first property. (2) But since it also can produce
original nonsense, its products must be models, i.e. exemplary;
and they consequently ought not to spring from imitation, but
must serve as a standard or rule of judgement for others. (3) It
cannot describe or indicate scientifically how it brings about
its products, but it gives the rule just as nature does. Hence the
author of a product for which he is indebted to his genius does
not himself know how he has come by his Ideas; and he has
not the power to devise the like at pleasure or in accordance
with a plan, and to communicate it to others in precepts that
will enable them to produce similar products. (Hence it is
probable that the word genius is derived from genius, that
peculiar guiding and guardian spirit given to a man at his birth,
from whose suggestion these original Ideas proceed.) (4)
Nature by the medium of genius does not prescribe rules to
Science, but to Art; and to it only in so far as it is to be
beautiful Art.
§ 54. Remark
§ 55
Remark I.
Remark II.
APPENDIX
§ 60. Of the method of Taste
§ 76. Remark
§ 85. Of Physico-theology
§ 86. Of Ethico-theology
Remark
Remark
This moral proof is not one newly discovered, although
perhaps its basis is newly set forth; since it has lain in man’s
rational faculty from its earliest germ, and is only continually
developed with its advancing cultivation. So soon as men
begin to reflect upon right and wrong—at a time when, quite
indifferent as to the purposiveness of nature, they avail
themselves of it without thinking anything more of it than that
it is the accustomed course of nature—this judgement is
inevitable, viz. that the issue cannot be the same, whether a
man has behaved candidly or falsely, fairly or violently, even
though up to his life’s end, as far as can be seen, he has met
with no happiness for his virtues, no punishment for his vices.
It is as if they perceived a voice within [saying] that the issue
must be different. And so there must lie hidden in them a
representation, however obscure, of something after which
they feel themselves bound to strive; with which such a result
would not agree,—with which, if they looked upon the course
of the world as the only order of things, they could not
harmonise that inner purposive determination of their minds.
Now they might represent in various rude fashions the way in
which such an irregularity could be adjusted (an irregularity
which must be far more revolting to the human mind than the
blind chance that we are sometimes willing to use as a
principle for judging of nature). But they could never think
any other principle of the possibility of the unification of
nature with its inner ethical laws, than a supreme Cause
governing the world according to moral laws; because a final
purpose in them proposed as duty, and a nature without any
final purpose beyond them in which that purpose might be
136
actualised, would involve a contradiction. As to the [inner]
constitution of that World-Cause they could contrive much
nonsense. But that moral relation in the government of the
world would remain always the same, which by the
uncultivated Reason, considered as practical, is universally
comprehensible, but with which the speculative Reason can
make far from the like advance.—And in all probability
attention would be directed first by this moral interest to the
beauty and the purposes in nature, which would serve
excellently to strengthen this Idea though they could not be the
foundation of it. Still less could that moral interest be
dispensed with, because it is only in reference to the final
purpose that the investigation of the purposes of nature
acquires that immediate interest which displays itself in such a
great degree in the admiration of them without any reference
to the advantage to be derived from them.
By IMMANUEL KANT
KANT’S CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY FOR ENGLISH
READERS. By J. P. MAHAFFY, D.D., and The Right
Rev. J. H. BERNARD, D.D. Two vols. Crown 8vo.
By BENEDETTO CROCE
PHILOSOPHY OF THE PRACTICAL. Economic and
Ethic. Translated by DOUGLAS AINSLIE, B.A. 8vo. 12s.
net.
ÆSTHETIC AS SCIENCE OF EXPRESSION AND
GENERAL LINGUISTIC. Translated by DOUGLAS
AINSLIE, B.A. 8vo. 10s. net.
ENCYCLOPÆDIA OF THE PHILOSOPHICAL
SCIENCES. Edited by WILHELM WINDELBAND and
ARNOLD RUGE. English Edition under the Editorship of
Sir HENRY JONES. 8vo.
WORKS ON PHILOSOPHY
THE SCHOOLS OF PHILOSOPHY
A HISTORY OF THE EVOLUTION OF
PHILOSOPHICAL THOUGHT
BY VARIOUS WRITERS
EDITED BY
* * * * *
• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive
from the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated
using the method you already use to calculate your
applicable taxes. The fee is owed to the owner of the
Project Gutenberg™ trademark, but he has agreed to
donate royalties under this paragraph to the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each
date on which you prepare (or are legally required to
prepare) your periodic tax returns. Royalty payments
should be clearly marked as such and sent to the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the address
specified in Section 4, “Information about donations to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation.”
• You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who
notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of
receipt that s/he does not agree to the terms of the full
Project Gutenberg™ License. You must require such a
user to return or destroy all copies of the works possessed
in a physical medium and discontinue all use of and all
access to other copies of Project Gutenberg™ works.
• You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full
refund of any money paid for a work or a replacement
copy, if a defect in the electronic work is discovered and
reported to you within 90 days of receipt of the work.
• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.