Social Comprehension and Judgment PDF

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 437

Social Comprehension and Judgment

The Role of Situation Models,


Narratives, and Implicit Theories
Social Comprehension and Judgment

The Role of Situation Models,


Narratives, and Implicit Theories

Robert S. Wyer, Jr.


Hong Kong University of Science and Technology

LAWRENCE ERLBAUM ASSOCIATES, PUBLISHERS


2004 Mahwah, New Jersey London
This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2008.

“To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s
collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.”
Copyright © 2004 by Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.
All rights reserved. No part of the book may be reproduced in
Any form, by photostat, microform, retrieval system, or any other
means, without the prior written permission of the publisher.

Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc., Publishers


10 Industrial Avenue
Mahwah, New Jersey 07430

Cover design by Kathryn Houghtaling Lacey

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

Wyer, Robert S., Jr.


Social comprehension and judgment : the role of situation models, narratives, and implicit
theories / Robert S. Wyer.
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-8058-4190-3 (alk. paper)
1. Social perception. 2. Human information processing—Social aspects. 3. Judgment. 4.
Memory. I. Title.

BF323.S63W94 2003
153—dc21
2003052865
ISBN 1-4106-0900-6 Master e-book ISBN

Books published by Lawrence Erlbaum Associates are printed on acid-free paper,


and their bindings are chosen for strength and durability.
Dedicated to

Rashmi, Kathy, and Natalie

and

The Social Cognition Group


Contents

Preface xi

PART I: INTRODUCTION AND BASIC CONCEPTS

1. INTRODUCTION 3
Types of Social Knowledge 6
The Representation of Knowledge in Memory 10
Situation Models 16
Generalized Event Representations 17
Generalized Entity Representations 22

2. THE ARCHITECTURE OF THE INFORMATION-PROCESSING 26


SYSTEM
Limitations of Wyer and Srull’s (1989) Theory 26
Structure of the Processing System 29
Storage and Retrieval Processes 37
Goal-Directed Versus Non-Goal-Directed Processing:
Spontaneous Reminding Processes 41
Concluding Remarks 45

3. DETERMINANTS AND EFFECTS OF KNOWLEDGE 47


ACCESSIBILITY
General Considerations 47
Frequency and Recency Effects of Knowledge Activation
on Judgments and Decisions 49
Effects of Awareness 53
Effects of Knowledge Accessibility at Different Stages
of Processing 57
The Effects of Prior Judgments on Subsequent Ones 63
Determinants and Consequences of the Accessibility
of Goals and Motives 65
The Activation of Behavioral Dispositions 72
Concluding Remarks 75

vii
viii CONTENTS

PART II: COMPREHENSION PROCESSES

4. THE COMPREHENSION AND VALIDATION OF INFORMATION 79


ABOUT FAMILIAR PEOPLE AND EVENTS: THE ROLE OF
SITUATION MODELS
The Content and Structure of Situation Models 80
The Role of Visual Imagery in Comprehending Social Events 83
Spontaneous Comprehension Processes 88
The Comprehension of Verbal Statements 92
Spontaneous Validity Judgments 98
Concluding Remarks 104

5. THE CONSTRUCTION OF EPISODE MODELS AND GENERALIZED 106


NARRATIVE REPRESENTATIONS
The Construction of Episode Models 106
The Construction of Generalized Narrative Representations 116

6. THE IMPACT OF GENERALIZED EVENT REPRESENTATIONS ON 124


COMPREHENSION AND MEMORY
The Role of Prototypic Event Representations in the
Comprehension of One’s Own and Others’ Experiences 125
The Effects of Communicating About an Experience
on Memory and Judgment 137
Concluding Remarks 149

7. PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES ON THE INTERPRETATION 151


OF STATEMENTS MADE IN A SOCIAL CONTEXT
General Considerations 152
Responses to Uninformative Messages 155
Reactions to Communications That One Believes to Be Untrue
160
Pragmatic Influences on Impression Formation in Informal
Conversations 165
The Effect of Nonverbal Behavior and Conversational
Style on Impression Formation, Judgment, and Information
Seeking 178
Pragmatic Communication in Close Relationships 186
Concluding Remarks 187
CONTENTS ix

8. THE DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION: THE EFFECTS 189


OF INFORMATIONAL CONTEXT ON THE INTERPRETATION
AND ELABORATION OF NARRATIVES
Historical Background 192
A Comprehension–Elaboration Theory of Humor Elicitation 198
Cognitive Elaboration Processes 209
Reactions to Disparaging Humor 218
Concluding Remarks 227

PART III: INFERENCE PROCESSES

9. CRIMES, VACATIONS, AND POLITICAL CANDIDATES: 231


THE CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES IN SOCIAL
JUDGMENTS
The Impact of Narratives on Jury Decision Making 232
A Comparison of Narrative-Based Versus Nonnarrative-Based
Information Processing 234
The Influence of Narratives on Political Impression Formation
240
The Role of Visual Imagery on Verbal Information Processing:
Additional Considerations 249
General Effects of Narrative-Based Processing on Explanation
and Prediction 255
Concluding Remarks 265

10. THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES AND IMPLICIT 267


THEORIES ON INFERENCES ABOUT ONESELF AND OTHERS
General Considerations 267
Effects of Implicit Theories on Reconstructive Memory 274
Motivational Influences on Implicit Theory Construction
and Use 278
The Role of Implicit Theories in Heuristic-Based Judgments 280
Individual Differences in Implicit Theories 286
Implicit Theories of Social Support: The Effect of Perspective
on Theory Activation 288
Cultural Differences in Implicit Theories 290
The Role of Implicit Theories in Marital Satisfaction 295
Effects of Implicit Theories on Behavioral Decisions 299
Final Comment 305
x CONTENTS

11. THE ROLE OF AFFECT IN INFORMATION PROCESSING 306


General Considerations 307
Affect and Concept Accessibility 312
The Influence of Affect on the Recall and Interpretation
of Information 315
The Use of Affect as Information 322
Affective Versus Descriptive Bases for Judgment 325
Affect-Confirmation Processes 332
Adjustments for Bias 336
Automatic Influences of Affect on Information
Processing 339
Motivational Influences of Affect on Information
Processing 342
A Performance-Feedback Model of Affect as Information 344
Affect, Attitudes, and Behavior 358
Final Comments 363

12. EPILOGUE: THE BOOK, THE AUTHOR, AND PHILOSOPHICAL 365


RUMINATIONS

APPENDIX: SUMMARY OF POSTULATES 374


REFERENCES 380

AUTHOR INDEX 405


SUBJECT INDEX 415
Preface

Authors often become disenchanted with the books they have written
almost as soon as they are published. Perhaps this is inevitable. Although
a book reports the culmination of one’s theoretical and empirical work at
the time it goes to press, it nevertheless contains the seeds of discontent.
That is, the author in writing the book becomes painfully aware of the
limitations of his research and the conceptualization underlying it, and
consequently is already motivated to move beyond the confines of this
conceptualization by the time it appears in print.
At least, this has been true of me. A book I published in 1974, entitled
Cognitive Organization and Change, provided a fairly rigorous analysis of
cognitive consistency theories of the way beliefs and attitudes were
organized in memory, individual and situational differences in the
cognitive responses to new information, and the way in which different
features of information were combined to form judgments. The book
assumed that humans were analogous to computers, generating outputs
based on operations that were specified in various “software” routines
that were activated by the “user” (in the case of humans, the demands of
the social environment).
By the time the book was published, however, I had already begun to
appreciate the need for a more general conceptualization of mental
representation. A second book (Social Inference and Attribution, with Don
Carlston, published in 1979) proposed a rather complex associative
network model of social memory that took into account the role of
knowledge accessibility in judgments and decisions. In this book, we
recognized the impact that script-like representations of events could have
on social judgment. However, we did not explore this possibility with any
degree of rigor. More generally, the cumbersome nature of the network
representation, coupled with the fact that it provided little insight into
how the information represented was actually used, convinced me of the
futility of using this approach to account for many phenomena that were
being identified in research on person impression formation and the use
of judgmental heuristics.
xi
xii PREFACE

The third book (Memory and Cognition in Its Social Context, with Thom
Srull) appeared in 1989. This book remedied several deficiencies of the
1979 volume, providing a comprehensive description of social information
processing that specified the activities at several different stages: the
interpretation, organization, and storage of information in memory, its
later retrieval and integration with other relevant knowledge to make a
subjective judgment or decision, and the translation of this subjective
response into an overt one. This rather grandiose formulation not only
generated specific predictions that received empirical support but had the
flexibility to integrate the implications of more specific theories of research
that had been developed.
By the time the book was published, however, I had become aware of
several obvious limitations. For one thing, the title of the book was a
misnomer. The theory I had proposed purported to describe the
comprehension and use of information of the sort that one encounters in
daily life, In fact, however, it was applied almost exclusively to the
processing of linguistic information of the sort people receive in laboratory
situations but are unlikely to encounter elsewhere (e.g., lists of unrelated
behaviors of a fictitious person, verbal descriptions of routine sequences
of events of little intrinsic interest, etc.) In short, although the book
purported to be about cognition “in its social context,” the social context
was typically absent in much of the research to which the theory was
applied.
Stimulated by our dissatisfaction with the applicability of the theory
to phenomena outside the laboratory, my students and I began to examine
the processing of information of the sort people actually encounter in the
course of their daily lives. This research took many directions. For example,
we investigated the impressions people formed on the basis of a person’s
opinions about social policies with which they agreed or disagreed rather
than abstract behaviors that had few implications for matters of personal
concern to the recipients. Moreover, we studied the impressions people
formed on the basis of information conveyed in conversations rather than
written lists of unrelated behaviors described out of context. Moreover,
we explored the way individuals respond to information that violated
social norms of communication and that was conveyed for the purpose of
eliciting amusement rather than to convey an impression of its referent or
to espouse a particular point of view. In doing so, we began to take more
seriously the fact that information conveyed in social situations was
frequently in the form of a narrative, or story, and was often accompanied
by visual images that were either based on pictures or direct observation
or generated by the recipients themselves. Finally, we explored the role of
affect in information processing.
PREFACE xiii

This book provides a conceptual integration of this work. It proposes


a general theoretical formulation of the way that the sort of information
acquired in the course of daily life is comprehended and represented in
memory, and how it is later used as a basis for judgments and behavioral
decision. In doing so, it takes into account both the spontaneous
comprehension of information about specific persons and events and the
more deliberative, goal-directed interpretation of information that occurs
when information is acquired in a social context. In addition, it considers
not only the representation of this information in memory but also the
way the information is later used as a basis for judgments and decisions.
A major emphasis throughout the volume is on the construction and use
of narrative representations of knowledge and the way visual images
influence the formation of these representations and the judgments that
are based on them. The role of affective reactions in this cognitive activity
is also discussed.
The book is divided into three sections. After a conceptual overview
of the approach to be taken (chap.1), it outlines the general theoretical
framework within which the discussion is housed, focusing on
assumptions about the storage and retrieval of information (chap. 2) and
reviews recent research on the impact of knowledge accessibility on
judgments and decisions (chap. 3). Although the architecture of the
information-processing system we propose is similar to that described in
the 1989 volume, the conceptualization of memory processes provided
here is quite different.
The second section deals specifically with the comprehension of
information. Chapter 4 discusses the mental simulations that are formed
of situationally and temporally specific events (i.e., “event models”) in
the course of comprehending descriptions of familiar persons and events,
and specifies the conditions in which information that stimulates these
simulations is spontaneously recognized as true or false. Chapter 5
discusses both the representation of situation-specific sequences of events
that are formed spontaneously in the course of comprehending the events
and more abstract representations that constitute implicit theories about
the causal and temporal relations among events of the sort people
encounter in daily life. Chapter 6 discusses the manner in which
generalized narrative representations influence memory for the specific
experiences that exemplify them. In this context, the influence of
socialization practices on the construction of narratives about oneself, and
on the self-concepts that result from these representations, are considered.
The next two chapters discuss cognitive reactions to information that
violates either normative expectations for the type of information that is
conveyed in the social context at hand (chap. 7) or expectations that result
xiv PREFACE

from previously acquired information about the information’s referents


(chap. 8). In the latter context, we consider the effects of expectancy
violations on the elicitation of humor and the extent to which the cognitive
activities that occur in response to these violations can increase or decrease
the humor that is elicited in a social context.
The final section describes the inferences that are based on information
of the sort that is conveyed in social situations. Chapter 9 outlines the
way visual characterizations of events (either pictures or self-generated
images) influence the impact of verbal descriptions of the events. Chapter
10 discusses the effects of people’s implicit theories about their social
world on the inferences they draw from specific experiences. Finally,
chapter 11 analyzes the role of affective reactions in information
processing and the judgments and decisions that result from this
processing.
Many individuals have contributed both directly and indirectly to the
content of this volume. My consideration of the role of narratives in
information processing was stimulated in large part by a multisemester
workshop conducted at Illinois by Julian Rappaport. G. A. Radvansky’s
empirical and theoretical work on the nature of situation models was also
a major stimulant. My conceptualization of the role of affect in information
processing was profoundly influenced by my participation in an ongoing
seminar on emotion and cognition conducted by Jerry Clore. Clore’s work
and that of his students are well represented in this volume.
However, I am particularly indebted to the University of Illinois Social
Cognition group. This group, an informal consortium of faculty,
postdoctoral students, and graduate students from several disciplines, met
weekly over a 20-year period to discuss theoretical and experimental issues
in the general area of information processing. Members of this group, both
individually and collectively, have had a profound influence on the ideas
represented in this volume and on my professional career more generally.
I am particularly indebted to two subsets of individuals whose work is
widely cited in this volume. Galen Bodenhausen, Lee Budesheim, Bob
Fuhrman, Deborah Gruenfield, Alan Lambert, Victor Ottati, Jong Won Park,
L. J. Shrum, and Dave Trafimow, participants in the Group during the
period in which my views on social information processing were rapidly
changing, were not only inspirational colleagues but close friends, and
are largely responsible for many of the changes in my thinking that
occurred. The stimulation provided in later years by Dolores Albarracin,
Stan Colcombe, Carol Gohm, Linda Isbell, Eric Mankowski and Michaela
Wänke was equally influential. The research and ideas of all of these
individuals are readily apparent throughout this book. I should also
acknowledge the contributions of Donnel Briley, Catherine Yeung, and
PREFACE xv

Candy Fong, who worked with me at the Hong Kong University of Science
and Technology, whose work is also represented.
I owe a special note of appreciation to Rashmi Adaval. Both as a
collaborator and as a wife, she has contributed in both tangible and
intangible ways both to this book in particular and to my personal and
professional life more generally. Her research on both the role of narratives
in memory and judgment, and on affect and information processing, is
prominent throughout this book. However, her personal support and
encouragement has been equally invaluable. It is extremely difficult for
anyone to be both a colleague and a spouse. Her willingness to play these
two often conflicting roles, her tolerance for my idiosyncratic work habits,
and her love and support throughout the past decade, has been
inexpressibly gratifying.
Finally, I want to acknowledge my deep appreciation to Larry Erlbaum
and his staff at Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. The support he has given
me over the past 30 years has been a constant source of gratitude. Larry’s
commitment to excellence, and his sincere dedication to the enhancement
of basic research in psychology, have won him the respect and admiration
of all psychologists who have had the opportunity to work with him. I
can only hope that this volume confirms his confidence in me and
approximates the standards of excellence for which he strives.

Robert S. Wyer, Jr.


P A R T

I
INTRODUCTION AND
BASIC CONCEPTS
C H A P T E R

1
Introduction

Human memory is a collection of thousands of stories we remember


through experience, stories we remember by having heard them, and sto-
ries we remember by having composed them. Any story in memory could
have gotten there in one of these three ways. The key point is that, once
these stories are there in our memory, we rely upon them for all that we
can say and understand. . . .
—Schank and Abelson (1995, p. 3)

Schank and Abelson (1995) argued that virtually all the meaningful social
knowledge we acquire is in the form of stories. This claim is probably over-
stated (Brewer, 1995; Rubin, 1995). Nevertheless, the role of narratives in
the acquisition and transmission of information in daily life is undeniable.
The content of everyday conversations almost invariably includes stories
we tell about ourselves and personal acquaintances, descriptions of books
we have read or movies we have seen, and jokes that we tell to one an-
other. Narratives are also invoked in the course of understanding the
causes or likely consequences of real and hypothetical social events (e.g.,
the outcome of a presidential election, or the India–Pakistan dispute over
Kashmir). Persuasive messages and television commercials often stimulate
us to imagine the sequence of events that might result from taking a partic-
ular course of action. Life itself is in the form of a narrative, consisting of a
sequence of temporally related events that we experience as either partici-
pants or observers. In short, narratives are fundamental to an understand-
ing of ourselves and of the world in which we live.
The importance of narrative forms of knowledge is recognized in virtu-
ally every area of psychology. Research and theory on prose comprehen-

3
4 CHAPTER 1

sion and learning have long been concerned with the comprehension and
mental representation of stories and temporally ordered sequences of
events (Graesser, 1981; Mandler & Johnson, 1977; Stein & Glenn, 1979). De-
velopmental psychologists (e.g., Miller, 1994; Nelson, 1993) have identified
the role of stories in parent–child interaction and socialization more gener-
ally. Narrative forms of knowledge can often constitute implicit theories
that people use both to explain their own and others’ past experiences and
to predict the future (Dweck & Leggett, 1988; Ross, 1989). The influence of
these theories on behavior and judgments has been identified in research
on topics as diverse as personal achievement (Dweck, 1975), predictions of
future life events (Oishi, Wyer, & Colcombe, 2000), marital relations
(Holmes & Murray, 1995; Murray & Holmes, 1996), personality development
(McAdams, 1988) and community–individual relations (Mankowski &
Rappaport, 1995).
Despite the consideration of narratives in these specific areas of re-
search, few attempts have been made to develop a broader theoretical for-
mulation of social information processing that permits their influence to be
conceptualized in relation to that of other types of knowledge that people
encounter in their daily lives. Several types of knowledge representations
are likely to exist (Pennington & Hastie, 1993), and their role in information
processing can differ. One must understand the factors that govern the re-
trieval of this knowledge, how it is used to comprehend and construe the
implications of new information to which it is relevant, and the nature of its
influence on judgments and behavioral decisions about its referents.
This book attempts to provide this understanding. In particular, it is con-
cerned with the comprehension and use of information of the sort people
encounter in the course of their daily lives. This information can be ob-
tained through direct experience, from movies and television, from reading
newspapers, or from conversations with friends or strangers. The informa-
tion can be transmitted in writing but also visually or acoustically. More-
over, it can be conveyed in several modalities simultaneously. Finally, al-
though the information can sometimes concern hypothetical people and
situations, it more often refers to actual persons and events about which re-
cipients already have substantial knowledge. Finally, the information is of-
ten conveyed in a social context, and can elicit affective or emotional reac-
tions toward either its referent or, in some cases, the communicator. Much
of this information, particularly that which is acquired through direct expe-
rience, is necessarily transmitted in the form of a narrative, that is, a tempo-
rally related sequence of events.
The conceptualization we propose addresses the way this information is
comprehended and represented in memory, and how it is later recalled and
used in making judgments and decisions. Our focus on “real-world” infor-
mation processing does not imply that the research we bring to bear on it
INTRODUCTION 5

has not been conducted in controlled laboratory settings. In fact, most of


the research reported is of this variety. However, the type of information of
concern in this research, the referents of the information, the context in
which it was presented, and the type of judgments and decisions for which
it had implications, is similar to that encountered in daily life situations.
The results of this research, and the formulation we bring to bear on it, are
consequently more likely to generalize to nonlaboratory situations than
work we have done in the past.
In this introductory chapter, we review the different types of knowledge
people acquire in their daily lives, and discuss briefly the various ways this
knowledge is represented in memory. Chapter 2 describes the theoretical
formulation of information processing within which the research and the-
ory discussed later is conceptualized. This formulation has features in com-
mon with the earlier formulation proposed by Wyer and Srull (1989). How-
ever, it is modified in several important ways that permit it to account for
the comprehension and use of information about familiar persons and
events of the sort we acquire in daily life. Chapter 3, another introductory
chapter, discusses the determinants and effects of knowledge accessibility,
which is central to much of the theory and research presented in later
chapters.
Part II of the book is devoted to the representation of knowledge about
social events and its role in comprehension. Chapters 4 and 5 examine the
sorts of representations that people form specifically in the course of com-
prehending social events that they either read about or directly experience.
Chapter 5 also discusses the more abstract event representations that are
formed in the course of deliberative goal-directed activity. Chapter 6 ad-
dresses the extent to which generalized event representations can influ-
ence the representations that are formed of situation-specific occurrences,
and the impact of forming abstract representations of an experience on
later memory for the experience. Chapter 7 considers the effects of the situ-
ational context in which information is presented on its comprehension.
Finally, chapter 8 applies the conceptualization developed in previous
chapters to a phenomenon that has received surprisingly little attention in
research on social information processing but is a central ingredient of
communication outside the laboratory: namely, the reactions to humor.
Part III of this volume examines the use of social information to make judg-
ments and behavioral decisions. Chapter 9 focuses specifically on the way
verbal and visual information combine to affect judgments under conditions
in which narrative representations of information are and are not likely to be
constructed. Chapter 10 considers more generally the impact of narrative
representations of knowledge on judgment, focusing largely on the impact of
implicit theories that people construct and use as a basis for inferences
6 CHAPTER 1

about specific events. Finally, chapter 11 addresses an issue largely ignored


in previous chapters but nevertheless of central importance in understand-
ing the effects of information in situations outside the laboratory, namely, the
impact of affective reactions on judgments of the persons, objects, and
events to which these reactions are (or, in some cases, are not) relevant.
The conceptualization proposed in this volume has been largely stimu-
lated by research conducted in our own laboratory during the past 15
years. However, its implications for phenomena identified in other areas
are considered as well. We therefore hope that the conceptualization pro-
vides a perspective on the dynamics of information processing in everyday
life situations that is not only useful in integrating a variety of known phe-
nomena but suggests new directions for research and theorizing.

TYPES OF SOCIAL KNOWLEDGE

Social knowledge can vary in terms of its referent (what the knowledge is
about), its modality (verbal, visual, or affective), the generality of its impli-
cations, and the way in which it is acquired (through direct experience, or
through cognitive operations that are performed on other cognitive mate-
rial). Two types of knowledge should be distinguished at the outset. Declar-
ative knowledge concerns the referents of our everyday life experience
(e.g., persons, objects, events, social issues that we read about, or oneself).
In contrast, procedural knowledge concerns the sequence of actions that
one performs in pursuit of a particular goal (driving a car, using a word
processor, etc.). Whereas declarative knowledge is reflected in the informa-
tion we can recall about an entity or that we implicitly draw on in the
course of attaining a particular objective, procedural knowledge is reflected
in the sequence of cognitive or motor acts that are actually performed in
the pursuit of this objective. People can of course have declarative knowl-
edge about how to attain a particular objective, and might sometimes con-
sult this knowledge for use as a behavioral guide. Once the procedure is
well learned, however, it may often be applied automatically, with little if
any conscious cognitive mediation.
These automated procedures can be conceptualized as “productions” of
the sort suggested by J. R. Anderson (1982, 1983; see also E. R. Smith, 1990).
Thus, they may metaphorically have the form of “If [X], then [Y]” rules in
which [X] is a configuration of perceptual or cognitive stimulus features
and [Y] is a sequence of cognitive or motor acts that are elicited automati-
cally when the eliciting conditions are met. These productions, which are
acquired through learning, are strengthened by repetition, and can ulti-
mately be activated and applied with minimal cognitive mediation. The rou-
INTRODUCTION 7

tines involved in driving a car (e.g., putting in the clutch, turning on the igni-
tion, putting the car in gear, gradually releasing the clutch while stepping
on the gas, etc.) initially require conscious thought. However, they ulti-
mately come to be performed without consultation of one’s declarative
knowledge about the sequence of steps involved, and require few if any
cognitive resources (Schneider & Shiffrin, 1977). As Bargh (1997) asserted, a
very large amount of our social behavior is likely to involve the use of these
automatically activated productions.
Procedural knowledge plays a very important role in social information
processing, as I indicate frequently throughout this volume. For the pres-
ent, however, I will concentrate my discussion on the content and structure
of declarative knowledge. I first consider the referents of this knowledge,
and the modality in which it is acquired. I then turn briefly to the different
ways in which this knowledge is represented in memory, and discuss the
need to understand these matters in conceptualizing the processing of in-
formation of the sort we receive in the course of daily life.

Referents of Social Knowledge

The stimulus information that impinges on us in a given social situation can


often far exceed our capacity to assimilate its implications. In a conversa-
tion, for example, several persons typically communicate to one another
both verbally and nonverbally, and in doing so, are likely to convey infor-
mation about not only the topic under discussion but also about them-
selves. Moreover, this information is often transmitted in the context of
many other situational stimuli that are largely irrelevant to either the topic
at hand or the individuals who are discussing it. We are usually not passive
recipients of this information. Rather, we actively try to determine its mean-
ing. Furthermore, we might construe its implications for the attainment of a
particular goal that we have in mind. In doing so, however, we necessarily
pay more attention to some features than to others. The features that re-
ceive the greatest attention depend in part on our perception of the refer-
ent (i.e., what the information is supposed to be about).
The referent of a piece of information can be either an entity (a person or
object, a place, oneself, etc.) or an event. However, most events involve per-
sons and objects and occur in a specific (although perhaps unspecified) lo-
cation. Furthermore, one’s knowledge about an entity often concerns
events in which the entity has been involved. As a consequence, the refer-
ent of information is often subjective, depending on not only the context in
which the information is received but also the interests and objectives of
the recipient. For example, consider the statement, “Muhammad Ali
knocked out George Foreman in Zaire.” This statement could be about Ali,
Foreman, or the event itself. In some cases, of course, perceptions of the
8 CHAPTER 1

referent of information are determined by the context in which the informa-


tion is received. Thus, someone who hears the aforementioned statement
during a discussion of Muhammad Ali is likely to identify Ali as its referent,
whereas someone who reads the statement in a magazine article about box-
ing might consider the event itself to be the referent. In addition, however,
individual differences in prior knowledge and motivation (e.g., whether one
is a fan of Muhammad Ali or George Foreman) can also influence percep-
tions of a statement’s referent. These situational and individual differences
in perception of the referent can have an impact on how the knowledge is
represented in memory and the likelihood that the knowledge comes to
mind later. For example, a person who learns that Ali knocked out Foreman
in a conversation about Ali, and consequently perceives Ali to be the refer-
ent, may not recall the information later when information about George
Foreman is being discussed. (For further discussion of this possibility, see
Wyer & Srull, 1989.)
Furthermore, when the information conveyed in a particular situation is
detailed and complex, recipients are likely to think more extensively about
features that pertain to its referent (as they perceive it) than other features.
Thus, the referent-related features are likely to be retained, whereas more
peripheral features seem to be forgotten. For example, a man who learns
that V. S. Naipaul won the Nobel Prize for Literature might remember the
specific context in which he acquired the information a short time after it
was conveyed. Over time, however, the information becomes part of his
general knowledge and the conditions that led to its acquisition are not
recalled.1

Affect and Emotion. Although the referents of knowledge are usually


external to the organism, internally generated stimulation can also be a
source of information. (See Strack and Deutsch, 2002, for a theoretical anal-
ysis of these alternative sources of information.) For example, external
stimuli can elicit affective or emotional reactions, and these reactions can
be used as bases for both thoughts and overt responses to the stimuli
(Schwarz & Clore, 1983, 1996; Wyer & Carlston, 1979). This does not mean

1
1 The dissociation of knowledge from the context in which it is learned does not mean that
contextual features are erased from memory. In the previous example, I learned about Naipaul’s
award from my wife, who stopped into my office to tell me about it one day at work, and I wrote
the preceding paragraph shortly afterwards. I would normally not be able to recall where and
when I acquired knowledge of the award. However, being reminded of the example while going
over this manuscript several months later was sufficient to stimulate a relatively detailed men-
tal image of the event, including my own and my wife’s physical locations in the room. Thus, al-
though these contextual features became “lost” in the interim, they continued to exist in mem-
ory and could be retrieved by a subset of cues that identified the event and its use as an example
in this book. The theory to be proposed in this volume attempts to account for this and related
memory phenomena.
INTRODUCTION 9

that affective reactions per se are part of stored knowledge. Rather, they
are conditioned or unconditioned responses to cognitions about their refer-
ent, and can sometimes be the referents of cognitions, but they are not
themselves part of the cognitive system (Wyer, Clore, & Isbell, 1999). This
view, which contrasts with that proposed by Wyer and Srull (1989; see also
Bower, 1981), is discussed more fully in chapter 11.

Relational Knowledge. Much of the knowledge we require about enti-


ties and events is relational. These relations may be physical or conceptual.
For example, we know not only that a nose and eyes are parts of a face but
also their positions in relation to one another. Furthermore, we know that
our bedroom is down the hall from the living room, that Chicago is west of
New York, that lions are larger than rabbits, and that the earth goes around
the sun. We also know that people graduate from high school before going
to college, that smoking is a cause of lung cancer, and that people have to
order a meal in a restaurant before they eat it. This knowledge requires not
only understanding of the entities being related but the relations them-
selves (“larger than,” “causes,” “above or below,” etc.). Note that in many
instances, the mental representation of these relations requires visual im-
agery.

Modalities of Knowledge

Information is conveyed in many different modalities and formats. For ex-


ample, it can be transmitted verbally in the form of propositions. It can also
be conveyed visually as in a picture or movie, or acoustically, as in music.
Our knowledge can likewise be in different modalities. That is, our knowl-
edge of a person could consist in part of verbal descriptions of the person’s
traits, and our knowledge of restaurants could include abstract character-
izations of the events that usually take place there. However, we also have
mental images of people we meet and places we visit, and might have
acoustic representations of a person’s voice, or of the Beatles’ rendition of
“Hey Jude.” Social experiences are often a configuration of verbal, visual,
and acoustic stimulation that combines to form our knowledge of what oc-
curred.
There has been some controversy about whether information is actually
coded into memory in the modality in which it is conveyed or is repre-
sented in a common format that can be decoded into different modalities,
depending on situational demands (J. Anderson, 1978; Kosslyn, 1980; Pyly-
shyn, 1973). Certainly we can easily translate many visual stimuli into lin-
guistic terms, and can form visual images of people and events on the basis
of verbal descriptions of them. Images can be acoustic as well as visual.
(This is apparent from the fact that people who have seen a foreign movie
10 CHAPTER 1

are later unable to remember whether actors’ statements to one another


were conveyed in subtitles or were dubbed.) Linguistic representations of
the actors’ utterances become integrated with the visual representation of
the movie and the quality of the speakers’ voices in a way that provides a
memory of the events very similar to the memory one would have if the
words had actually been spoken.
Be that as it may, it is most convenient in the present volume to assume
that codings of information in different modalities do exist in memory and,
in some cases, can be stored independently. Several studies we describe in
this volume attest to the importance of visual and auditory information
processing and the impact of visually coded knowledge on memory and
judgment. The way in which visual and verbal codings of knowledge theo-
retically combine to influence the representations that are formed, and how
these representations are later used, are detailed in chapters 4 and 5.

THE REPRESENTATION OF KNOWLEDGE


IN MEMORY

General Considerations

As the preceding discussion testifies, it is virtually impossible to discuss


the type of knowledge we acquire without making implicit assumptions
about the representation of this knowledge in memory. However, the men-
tal representation of information can differ in several ways from the infor-
mation itself. Some features of the information we receive are not stored in
memory at all, whereas other features that were not specified in the infor-
mation may be added (Barclay, 1973; Loftus, 2000). Furthermore, detailed
descriptions of an event can often be interpreted in terms of abstract (e.g.,
attribute) concepts that are stored in memory independently of these de-
scriptions (Carlston, 1980; Higgins, 1996; Wyer & Srull, 1989). In addition, in-
formation might be mentally reorganized into a form that is relevant to the
goal one happens to be pursuing (cf. Hamilton, Katz, & Leirer, 1980; Wyer &
Bodenhausen, 1985). Moreover, information that is transmitted visually may
be coded into memory linguistically, and verbal information may some-
times elicit visual images.
It might nevertheless be argued that people extract similar implications
from information regardless of the mental representation they form of it. If
this were so, an understanding of the mental representations that are
formed of information would be of little importance in predicting its impact.
We would simply need to characterize clearly the stimulus information to
which people are exposed, and to obtain a reliable indication of which as-
INTRODUCTION 11

pects of this information they retain (as evidenced by the aspects of the in-
formation they can recall). This would be sufficient to determine its impact.
In fact, however, research in social and cognitive psychology since the
1970s suggests this contention is naïve. That is, a conceptualization of the
cognitive operations that are performed on information, and of the mental
representations that result from these operations, is essential for under-
standing its influence. Because the comprehension and mental representa-
tion of experiential knowledge is a central focus of this volume, some em-
pirical support for this conclusion may be worth summarizing.

1. Communication and Persuasion

One of the first demonstrations in social psychology of the need to take


into account the cognitive activities that people perform in response to in-
formation was constructed by Greenwald (1968). He showed that the influ-
ence of a persuasive message was often unrelated to the implications of
those aspects of the message that participants could recall. Rather, its im-
pact was governed by the implications of the thoughts they had about the
message at the time it was received. These cognitive responses, which in-
cluded elaborations of the message content, counterarguments, and
thoughts that were unrelated to the message itself, presumably reflected re-
cipients’ comprehension of the message and their evaluation of its validity
as well as the implications of other previously acquired knowledge that
they brought to bear on the position advocated.
In a study by Loken (1984), participants read a list of information items
pertaining to a college professor with instructions either to form an impres-
sion of the individual or to decide whether they wanted to take a course
from him. The information consisted of either favorable or unfavorable trait
descriptions, and either favorable or unfavorable consequences of taking
the course. In some cases, individual pieces of information had implications
for both attitudes toward taking the course and attitudes toward the profes-
sor (e.g., “Dolan is interesting,” “Taking Dolan’s course is time consuming,”
etc.). In other cases, they had implications for only one of these attitudes
(e.g., “Dolan is clumsy,” “Taking Dolan’s class fulfills a graduation require-
ment,” etc.). Later, participants reported their attitudes toward both the
person and the behavior, and then recalled the information they had re-
ceived. The type of information that participants recalled was influenced by
the task objectives they were given. Nevertheless, the effects of experimen-
tal variables on attitude judgments did not mirror their effects on recall.
Moreover, correlations between attitudes and the evaluative implications
of attitude-relevant information that participants recalled were very low,
ranging from .05 to .24. Loken concluded that participants spontaneously
formed attitudes toward both the professor and taking the course at the
12 CHAPTER 1

time the information was received, and later reported these attitudes inde-
pendently of the information they could remember at the time of judgment.

2. Person Impression Formation


In a study by Carlston (1980), participants read descriptions of a target
person’s behavior that exemplified two traits with evaluatively different im-
plications. In one condition, for example, behaviors (e.g., “told his girlfriend
that her hair-do was ugly”) could be interpreted as both honest and unkind.
Participants judged the target with respect to one of the two traits and
then, either a few minutes or several days later, evaluated him with respect
to the other trait. Participants’ second judgments were evaluatively biased
by the first. In other words, participants who initially evaluated the target’s
honesty (and thus judged him to be honest) later reported him as being
more kind than participants who had not made this initial judgment. Corre-
spondingly, participants who made kindness judgments at the outset (and
thus rated the target as unkind) judged him to be less honest than other
participants did. Moreover, these effects increased over time. Participants
apparently interpreted the information in a way that was relevant to the
first judgment they made and formed a mental representation of the target
as the type of person who had the trait being judged. Then, having done so,
they based their second judgment on the implications of this representa-
tion rather than reconsidering the original information they had received.
In a series of studies by Srull and Wyer (1983), some participants read de-
scriptions of a person’s behavior that were either predominantly favorable
or predominantly unfavorable with instructions to form an impression of the
actor. Then, after either a short or long delay (5 min or 45 min), they were
asked to report their liking for him. Other participants, who were asked to re-
call the behaviors they had learned, remembered fewer behaviors after a
long delay than after a short delay. However, participants rated the target
more extremely in the long delay condition (e.g., as more likable or more
dislikable, depending on the predominant implications of the behaviors). Ap-
parently, these participants formed a generally favorable or generally unfa-
vorable impression of the target on the basis of the predominant theme of
the behaviors they had read. After a delay, their recall of the specific behav-
iors diminished, but their overall impression remained. Therefore, their judg-
ment, based on this impression alone, was more polarized.

3. Assimilation and Contrast


In a study by Higgins and Lurie (1983), subjects rated the harshness of
sentence imposed on a criminal by a “target” judge (Jones) along with the
sentences recommended by three “context” judges. Participants rated
Jones’s sentence as more lenient when sentences recommended by the
INTRODUCTION 13

context judges were long than when they were short. The critical condi-
tions of the study, however, occurred a week later. At this time, participants
were given a sample of the sentences imposed by a different group of con-
text judges that were again either long or short. Then, after receiving the in-
formation, they were asked to recall the actual sentence that Jones had im-
posed, as conveyed in the first session. Instead of recalling this sentence
directly, however, participants apparently recalled their rating of him as
harsh or lenient, and then reinterpreted the implications of this rating with
reference to the sentence imposed by the context judges in Session 2.
Therefore, they “recalled” the target’s sentence to be longer when the sen-
tences imposed by the second set of judges were long than when they were
short, and this was true regardless of the sentences imposed by the context
judges in Session 1.

4. Impact of Information That One


Is Told to Disregard

In a study by Wyer and Budesheim (1987; see also Wyer & Unverzagt,
1985), participants read a series of behaviors of a target person with in-
structions to form an impression of him. In some cases, the first behaviors
were favorable and the last behaviors were unfavorable. In other condi-
tions, the order was reversed. On the pretense that an error had been
made, some subjects were told after reading the first set of behaviors that
these behaviors actually pertained to a different person than the one they
were supposed to consider and to disregard them. Other participants read
the entire set of behaviors and then were told to disregard the last set they
had considered. Finally, participants were asked both to judge the target
with respect to the traits to which the information pertained and to recall
the information they received. When participants had been told to disre-
gard the first behaviors in the series, their judgments were not influenced
by these behaviors although they could recall the behaviors quite well.
When participants had been told to disregard the last behaviors in the se-
ries, these behaviors had an impact on their judgments although their re-
call of the behaviors was poor. Thus, instructions to disregard the informa-
tion had opposite effects on recall and judgments in the two conditions.
These studies suggest that the mental representations that participants
form of information can exert a major influence on their judgments inde-
pendently of the information itself, and that the magnitude of this influence
can increase over time. Greenwald and Banaji (1995) described several ad-
ditional situations in which people are influenced by information they can-
not recall and, in some cases, are unaware that they ever received (see also
Bargh, 1997). Thus, neither the implications of the information that people
receive nor the implications of the information they can remember provide
14 CHAPTER 1

much insight into the impact of this information on judgments. Rather,


the impact is mediated by the cognitive operations that people perform
on the information and the mental representation that results from these
operations.

A Conceptual and Methodological Approach


to Investigating the Influence of Mental Representations

To the extent that mental representations of information have an impact on


judgments, a question arises as to how their content and structure can be
determined. Any characterization of the mental representations that people
form from information is obviously metaphorical and does not reflect the
physical representation of the information in the brain. For one thing, infor-
mation is not stored in particular locations, but rather, is distributed
throughout the cerebral cortex. Thus, all theoretical models of mental rep-
resentation must be viewed in terms of their utility and not whether they
are true or false.
The general logic underlying theory and research on mental representa-
tions can be conveyed with reference to Fig. 1.1. This figure distinguishes
between input processes, recall processes, and judgment processes. Both
the type of stimulus information presented and the recipients’ processing
objectives at the time they encounter it can influence the cognitive opera-
tions they perform on the information and, therefore, the mental represen-
tation they construct. This representation is then stored in memory. If par-
ticipants are later asked to recall the information, they may activate a
procedure for extracting this information from the representation they
formed earlier. If, on the other hand, they are called upon to make a judg-
ment or behavioral decision, they may engage in search and retrieval oper-
ations that are relevant to this objective, and may use the material they ex-
tract from the mental representation as a result of these operations to
compute their response.
Two things are worth noting, however. First, the objectives that exist at
the time the information is received may differ from those that occur later,
at the time the information is retrieved for use in attaining a particular ob-
jective. Second, the search, retrieval, and computational operations that
are performed at this second stage depend on the particular judgment or
decision to be made and, therefore, are likely to differ from the operations
that are performed when people’s objective is to recall the information they
received. This means there may be little relationship between the implica-
tions of the information people recall and the judgments they make, as the
research cited earlier suggests.
This leads to the logic underlying research on social information proc-
essing in general, and much of the research to be summarized in this vol-
FIG. 1.1. Relations among various components of social judgment. Observable (independent
and dependent) variables are enclosed by solid lines, and mediating variables by dashed lines.
Rectangles denote “states” and ovals denote “processes.”

15
16 CHAPTER 1

ume more specifically. That is, the mental representation that is formed
from information is a hypothetical construct and cannot be observed di-
rectly. However, given a specific set of assumptions about the retrieval op-
erations that occur when people are asked to recall the information, and a
metaphor for describing the associations among features of the information
that exist in memory, one can use the amount, type, and order of informa-
tion to conceptualize the content and structure of the mental representa-
tions that was formed at the time the information was received. Then, once
this is established, one can hypothesize and investigate empirically the way
this mental representation is used to attain specific objectives to which it is
relevant. Much of the research and theory summarized in this volume is
based, implicitly or explicitly, on this general approach.
The social knowledge we acquire can be represented in memory in sev-
eral ways. The nature of these representations, when they are constructed,
and how they are used, are a major focus of this book. Two types of mental
representations that occupy our greatest attention are worth noting briefly.
These representations, to be denoted situation models and generalized repre-
sentations, are distinguished in terms of both their content and structure
and the point at which they typically come into play in social information
processing. Although we consider both types of representations in detail in
subsequent chapters, a general overview of the representations is perhaps
desirable.

SITUATION MODELS

We assume that people who receive information about situation-specific


events, either verbally or through direct experience, form mental simula-
tions of these events in the course of comprehending them that indicate not
only the people and objects that are involved in the events but their spatial
and temporal relatedness. These mental simulations, or situation models
(Johnson-Laird, 1983, 1989; Kintsch, 1998) are often represented in memory
in terms of mental images of the events and, in some cases, propositionally
as well. To the latter extent, the representations are somewhat analogous
to a “picture plus caption.” Moreover, a temporally and thematically related
sequence of events might be represented by a multiple-segment represen-
tation somewhat analogous to a “comic strip.” (For a similar metaphor in
conceptualizing the mental representation of event sequences, see
Abelson, 1976.)
We assume that situation models are often formed spontaneously in the
course of comprehending information (see chap. 4 for a discussion of these
processes). This information could be either obtained through direct expe-
rience or conveyed verbally. However, a necessary condition for the con-
INTRODUCTION 17

struction of these models is that the events or states to which they refer are
temporally and spatially specific. That is, the phenomena must occur at a
specific (although not necessarily specified) place and point in time. This
constraint is implicit in the assumption that a mental image is formed.
Thus, the statements, “The boy kicked the ball” and “The book is on the ta-
ble” describe events or states of affairs that existed at a particular time and
place, and a mental picture can be formed of them. In contrast, “the boy
owns a ball,” or “the book is interesting,” are not spatially or temporally
constrained, and a mental picture of the situations is not constructed
(Radvansky, Wyer, Curiel, & Lutz, 1997). Rather, a generalized representa-
tion is formed on the basis of these statements that does not have an image
component.

GENERALIZED EVENT REPRESENTATIONS

More complex generalized representations can also be formed in the


course of higher level goal-directed processing that occurs once informa-
tion has initially been comprehended. For example, people who wish to tell
someone about a movie they have seen might describe the things that hap-
pened in more abstract terms than they were shown in the movie and, in
doing so, might construct a more general, linguistic representation of the
sequence of events that occurred. Generalized event representations can
also be formed in the course of evaluating the implications of a persuasive
message, describing someone’s personality, or generating a conclusion on
the basis of logical reasoning. Although these goal-directed representations
might also be based on previously formed situation models, they are stored
in memory independently of these models.

The Dimensionality of Event Representations

Generalized event representations can vary along several dimensions.

Generalizability. A generalized event representation might refer to a


particular experience that involves specific individuals and occurs at a
given time and place. Alternatively, it could pertain to a general class of in-
dividuals, situations, or events, instances of which occur frequently at dif-
ferent types. Thus, for example, I might have a representation of going to
dinner at Zorba’s with Rashmi at 7 p.m. last Thursday. In addition, I might
have a representation of going out to eat at restaurants that generalizes
over times and places.
18 CHAPTER 1

Abstractness. A narrative representation could be encoded in terms of


specific concepts that apply to single entities. Thus, the representation of
my dinner at Zorba’s might specify where I sat, what I ate, and the details
of the conversation I had over dinner. Alternatively, it could be coded in
very abstract terms similar to those used to convey the example provided
in the preceding paragraph.

Personal Relevance. Event representations can be about oneself and


one’s personal experiences, about acquaintances, or about unknown or fic-
titious individuals. Similarly, they can describe either events one has per-
sonally encountered (e.g., one’s observation of a teacher’s interchange with
an obnoxious student) or those that occur in a remote and unfamiliar clime
(e.g., the border dispute between India and Pakistan).

Time Frame. A representation could refer to people and events in ei-


ther the past, the present, or the future, or could extend over two or more
of these time periods.

Types of Generalized Event Representations

Several different types of event representations can be distinguished in


terms of values along these dimensions. In this volume, we refer to all repre-
sentations as narratives. Certain types of narratives are nevertheless worth
distinguishing, including scripts, stories, histories, and implicit theories.

1. Scripts and Plans


Scripts are prototypic sequences of events that occur in a particular situ-
ational context (Schank & Abelson, 1977). They can refer to either specific
persons (e.g., my wife’s ritual of getting ready for a dinner party) or people
in general (a visit to a restaurant). However, although scripts can refer to
particular individuals and situations, they apply to routinized sequences of
actions that involve these persons and situations that typically occur under
the circumstances at hand.
A plan is a special type of script in which the events described produce a
particular (typically favorable) end state. These constructions are typically
applied to new situations, often serving as behavioral guides. For example,
an individual who has formed a script of changing a flat tire as a result of
observing others engage in the activity could use this script as a plan in de-
termining how to change a tire when personally required to do so.
Most research on the representation of scripts in memory (Bower, Black,
& Turner, 1979; Graesser, 1981; Nottenburg & Shoben, 1980; Trafimow &
Wyer, 1993) has focused on mundane event sequences that are very famil-
iar to members of a Western culture. As noted earlier, however, individuals
INTRODUCTION 19

can form routinized sequences events that are specific to themselves, or


their family (e.g., I might have a representation of the sequence of acts my
spouse routinely performs when getting ready for a party). As we see in
chapter 5, there is some question about how often these representations
are actually constructed (cf. Colcombe & Wyer, 2002). Nevertheless, several
such constructions undoubtedly exist.
The fact that the events that compose scripts are routinized and gener-
ally mundane distinguishes them from other types of narratives in two
ways. First, they are likely to have little evaluative significance for the per-
sons involved. (A visit to a restaurant, for example, which terminates with
paying the bill and leaving, has relatively neutral implications.) Second,
scripts are unlikely to be the topic of conversation. That is, the events that
compose them are expected to occur, and so mentioning them has little in-
formation value.

2. Stories

Stories, unlike scripts, concern sequences of events at least one of which


is unique. That is, it deviates from expectations based on prior knowledge
about the types of people and situations involved. In addition, the events
have some evaluative significance for the protagonists (Mandler & Johnson,
1977; Stein & Glenn, 1979). This conceptualization of a story is more re-
stricted than Schank and Abelson’s (1995). In fact, a substantial literature in
cognitive psychology has been concerned with both the appropriate defini-
tion of stories and their representation in memory (cf. Black, Galambos, &
Read, 1984; Brewer, 1995; Brewer & Lichtenstein, 1981; Mandler & Johnson,
1977; Stein, 1982). In this work, stories are postulated to have certain com-
mon features that are captured in large part by a “story grammar” (Mandler
& Johnson, 1977; Stein & Glenn, 1979). Although these grammars differ in de-
tail (see Stein, 1982, for a comparison of alternative story grammars), they
share the assumption that stories have a definable beginning and end along
with an event that provides a transition between these states.
Other features that are sometimes used to distinguish stories from other
representations are of less utility. For example, Brewer and Lichtenstein
(1981) argued that a story must also elicit some degree of affect or emotion
in the recipient. However, it seems undesirable to define a story in terms of
responses of the recipient rather than attributes of the story itself. (Brewer
and Lichtenstein’s conceptualization implies that the same narrative might
constitute a story to one person but not to another, depending on the affect
it happens to elicit.)
Brewer and Lichtenstein (1981) also assumed that the function of stories
is to entertain. However, the same narrative might be communicated for the
purpose of being entertaining in one context but for the purpose of making
20 CHAPTER 1

a point or exemplifying a principle in another context. It would be concep-


tually confusing to define the same narrative differently, depending on the
conditions in which it is conveyed.
It therefore seems more reasonable to define a story as simply a narra-
tive that (a) describes events involving specific individuals or groups that
are localized in time and place, (b) contains at least one event that deviates
from expectations based on prior knowledge of the type of individuals and
situations involved, and (c) whose end state has emotional significance for
one or more of the protagonists.

3. Histories
A history, like a story, consists of a sequence of events that are specific
to a particular person or group and are localized in time and place. Unlike
stories, however, a history does not necessarily contain unique or unex-
pected events. Nor does it necessarily have emotional significance for the
protagonists. Histories can concern real-world events in which one is not in-
volved. However, it can also refer to oneself or an acquaintance. The mental
representation of a personal history is clearly not a single sequence of
events that occurs over the course of a lifetime. Rather, an individual is
likely to construct several histories, each of which is restricted to life
events that are relevant to the purpose for which it is formed (communicat-
ing about oneself to another, comprehending one’s own or another’s per-
sonal experience, etc.). Once constructed, these sets of segments are likely
to be stored independently of one another in memory.
As these observations imply, histories can contain overlapping seg-
ments. Moreover, a history does not usually cover all the events that occur
during the time period to which it pertains. Thus, one might construct dif-
ferent histories that cover the same or overlapping time period. For exam-
ple, a personal history of how one became a psychologist could temporally
overlap a history of one’s romance with an ex-call girl. However, the events
that compose these mental constructions might be totally different.
According to this conceptualization, stories and histories are not mutu-
ally exclusive constructs. A history would be a story to the extent it con-
tains unexpected events and is emotionally significant for one or more of
the parties involved. However, not all histories are stories, and not all sto-
ries are histories.

4. Implicit Theories and Implicational Molecules


A theory, like a script, is composed of a prototypic sequence of events.
However, the events are causally as well as temporally related. Moreover,
the events are often defined more broadly. A theory is not localized in time
and, therefore, can be applied in many different circumstances. It might
INTRODUCTION 21

nevertheless concern a particular individual (e.g., oneself) or general cate-


gory of individuals (African Americans, fraternity members, etc.) as well as
people in general. Similarly, it could be specific to a particular type of situa-
tion (living in public housing, student–faculty interactions) or could apply
more generally. In all cases, however, the events that compose a theory are
likely to recur at different times.
For example, one might have an implicit theory that (a) people with alco-
holic fathers feel insecure, (b) these feelings lead them to pursue unrealisti-
cally high goals, (c) their failure to attain these goals leads to depression
and ultimately to drinking, and (d) they wind up becoming alcoholic like
their fathers. Each segment encompasses a large number of more specific
events and functions as a general concept that can be used to interpret and
organize new information. To this extent, a theory can function as an event
stereotype.
Theories play a very important role in processing new information about
the world in which we live and making inferences on the basis of it. They
are used both to explain events that have occurred in the past and to pre-
dict the future. Moreover, they can be used to fill in “gaps” in a sequence of
events about which one has incomplete information.
In this regard, some theories can consist of only two or three segments
that, in combination, constitute a general principle. In these instances, the
principle could function as a linguistically coded “title,” or “header” of the
theory to which it refers. For example, the principle “people get what they
deserve” could be the title of a two-segment theory composed of the events
“A person does something bad” and “The person gets punished.” These the-
ories can be conceptualized as implicational molecules of the sort suggested
by Abelson and Reich (1969; see also Wyer & Carlston, 1979, 1994). That is,
they consist of a set of general propositions that have become associated
through learning. For example, the propositions associated with the princi-
ple that people get what they deserve could compose the molecule

[P does something good (bad); Something good (bad) will occur to P].

The use of an implicational molecule is theoretically governed by a com-


pletion principle. That is, if the information one receives about a specific sit-
uation instantiates all but one of the propositions that compose a molecule,
an instantiation of the remaining proposition will be inferred. Thus, people
who have formed the implicational molecule described in the preceding ex-
ample might predict that a particular person who has done a bad thing will
be punished. However, they might also infer that someone who has experi-
enced misfortune has done a bad thing or for other reasons deserves his or
her fate. Several other examples of the use of implicational molecules, and
implicit theories more generally, are discussed in detail in chapter 10 of this
volume.
22 CHAPTER 1

GENERALIZED ENTITY REPRESENTATIONS

Generalized representations are obviously not restricted to events. They


can also pertain to persons, to groups of persons, to objects, or to places. In
fact, most of the mental representations that have typically been investi-
gated in social information processing research (for reviews, see Carlston &
Smith, 1996; Wyer & Carlston, 1994) are of this type. For example, people
who receive descriptions of someone’s traits and behaviors with the goal of
forming an impression of them may think about the individual pieces of in-
formation in relation to one another in order to understand their related-
ness or, perhaps, to reconcile apparent inconsistencies among them. In the
course of this cognitive activity, associations are presumably formed
among the pieces of information that influences the ease of recalling the in-
formation later.
The entity representations that are constructed in the course of goal-
directed processing can often be conveyed metaphorically in terms of an
associative network. That is, concepts and units of knowledge (e.g., situa-
tion models) are represented by nodes in memory. When a person thinks
about one concept or knowledge unit in relation to another, an association
is formed between them that is represented by a pathway. Thus, suppose
people are asked to form an impression of a person, John, on the basis of
set of behavior descriptions. If they interpret a particular behavior of the
person (e.g., “returned a lost wallet”) as honest, this establishes an associa-
tion between a concept denoting the behavior and the trait concept “hon-
est.” If they interpret several other behaviors (“refused an opportunity to
cheat on an examination,” “told his girlfriend that her hair-do was ugly,”
etc.) in terms of the same trait, an association is formed between these be-
haviors and the trait concept as well, leading to a trait–behavior cluster as
shown in Fig. 1.2a.
Alternatively, suppose both these and other behaviors (e.g., “honks at
slow drivers,” “reads poetry,” etc.) are thought about with reference to
John without construing their trait implications. Then, associative path-
ways are formed between the behavior concepts and the person concept,
“John,” as shown in Fig. 1.2b. General traits that are attributed to John as a
result of processing these behaviors can also become associated with this
concept. If people happen to think about some of the behaviors in relation
to others, associative links may be formed between the behaviors as also
shown in the figure. Finally, if they think extensively about John’s engaging
in some behaviors but not others, the former behaviors may become more
strongly associated with John than the latter ones do. This difference is
conveyed by the thickness of the associative links between the behaviors
and John (cf. Wyer & Carlston, 1979), as also shown in Fig. 1.2b.
INTRODUCTION 23

FIG. 1.2. (a) Metaphorical trait-based representations formed as a result of in-


terpreting behaviors in terms of trait concepts. (b) Metaphorical representa-
tion of a person, “John,” described by behaviors and traits. Thicker lines de-
note stronger associations.

The representations of the sort shown in Fig. 1.2 are theoretically the re-
sult of conscious cognitive activity (but see Chartrand & Bargh, 1996, 2002,
for a different conclusion). Moreover, the associations shown in the figure
reflect the implications of specific assumptions about the nature of this ac-
tivity. Given assumptions about the processes that underlie the extraction
of specific features from the network, these implications can be evaluated
24 CHAPTER 1

empirically. One set of assumptions, espoused by Hastie and Kumar (1979)


and others (Srull, 1981; Srull, Lichtenstein, & Rothbart, 1985; Wyer & Srull,
1989), which captures the processes involved in person impression forma-
tion on the basis of linguistically coded traits and behaviors, is discussed
briefly in chapter 7. However, an associative network metaphor has been
applied successfully in other domains as well (cf. Park, Yoon, Kim, & Wyer,
2001; Park & Wyer, 1993; Wyer & Carlston, 1979).
The conceptualization described previously has typically been applied
to representations that are formed of fictitious entities. Representations of
actual people and objects may be similar with two exceptions. First, the
representation of a familiar person might often include the referent’s name
and also a mental image of his or her physical appearance. Second, the fea-
tures that are associated with the individual might be added to the repre-
sentation over a period of time, as new information about the person is ac-
quired. These additional features simply become linked to the central
concept of the referent, much as the ones that were conveyed at the outset.
On the other hand, once features have become part of a representation,
they cannot be modified or erased. (See chap. 2 for an elaboration of this
assumption.) When an existing representation appears to be inappropriate,
a new representation is constructed whose features differ from the original.
Thus, people might form different representations of the same person or
object that are stored independently in memory, each with a different (al-
though perhaps overlapping) set of associated attributes.
Finally, representations might pertain to a group or category as well as a
single entity. For example, people might form a representation of the per-
sons in a particular social group, of U.S. Presidents, or of African Ameri-
cans. These representations might consist not only of features that are typi-
cally associated with members of the group or category as a whole, but also
names of the members that belong to the group and have been thought
about in relation to it. In this regard, the name of a particular person who
belongs to several groups could be contained in several different represen-
tations. However, these representations would not be interconnected but
would exist independently in memory. This assumption distinguishes the
present conceptualization from more general associative network models
(e.g., Collins & Loftus, 1975; Wyer & Carlston, 1979), which assume that all
representations with common features are interconnected.
An assumption underlying the conceptualization is that once a mental
representation is formed (either spontaneously in the course of compre-
hension or as a result of goal-directed processing), this representation is
stored in memory as a single unit of knowledge and is later retrieved as a
whole. Thus, in our example, a representation of John would presumably
be stored in memory as a unit and might later be retrieved as a whole when
information about “John” is sought. Other representations of the individual,
INTRODUCTION 25

based on information obtained at different times, might also be formed and


stored independently. These latter representations might include situation
models of the sort described earlier. This means than when information
about a person or object is sought, the type and implications of the infor-
mation retrieved depends on which of several potentially applicable knowl-
edge representations come to mind. This, in turn, depends on its accessibil-
ity in memory. This matter is discussed more fully in chapter 2 within the
framework of the general information-processing formulation we propose.
C H A P T E R

2
The Architecture of the
Information-Processing System

A complete theoretical formulation of information processing must specify


the content and structure of memory, the storage and retrieval processes
that are involved in the transmission of knowledge throughout the cogni-
tive system, and the way this knowledge comes into play in the pursuit of
specific goals to which it is relevant. Wyer and Srull’s (1989) theory attains
many of these objectives, and several features of this earlier theory are re-
tained in the conceptualization I now propose. However, several assump-
tions of the earlier formulation must be modified in order to account for the
processing of information about familiar people and events that is acquired
through direct experience. Before describing these modifications, certain
limitations of the earlier model are worth noting. (These limitations are
shared by other, more restricted conceptualizations of social information
processing as well; see Brewer, 1998; Carlston, 1994; Smith, 1990; Wyer &
Carlston, 1979.)

LIMITATIONS OF WYER AND SRULL’S (1989)


THEORY

The Comprehension and Validation of Information


About Familiar People and Events

Perhaps the most general deficiency of the original model is its failure to
specify the operations that govern the comprehension of information at the
time the information is first encountered, before goal-directed cognitive ac-

26
ARCHITECTURE OF THE INFORMATION-PROCESSING SYSTEM 27

tivity is initiated. Wyer and Srull simply assumed that input information is
spontaneously encoded in terms of “low level” semantic concepts that are
applied independently of the modality in which the information is received.
They provided no indication of how this is done. Furthermore, their as-
sumption that all incoming information is encoded semantically constrains
the model’s ability to address the comprehension of information that per-
tains to people and events about which one already has substantial knowl-
edge. The model assumed that referent-specific knowledge does not come
into play until a later, goal-directed stage of processing.
One implication of this assumption is that the validity of information
about well-known people and events is not assessed until some time after
the information is comprehended, and may not occur at all unless people
have a specific goal to which this assessment is relevant. This seems intu-
itively unlikely. Most Americans would almost immediately recognize that
the assertion “Abraham Lincoln was President of the United States” is true
in the course of comprehending it. By the same token, they are equally
quick to recognize that “Mao Tse Tung was President of the United States”
is false. These validity assessments appear to occur spontaneously in the
absence of any specific goal that requires them.
Not all information is spontaneously verified at the time it is compre-
hended, however. The statement “Abraham Lincoln visited Boston” is likely
to be comprehended without any conscious recognition that it is either true
or false. Statements that refer to unknown persons may be similarly com-
prehended without spontaneously validating them. The conditions in which
spontaneous validity assessments do and do not occur in the course of
comprehending information is not specified by either the Wyer and Srull
(1989) formulation or others.
Information is likely to be processed quite differently when it is compre-
hended with reference to previously acquired knowledge about its refer-
ents than when it is not. For example, suppose people receive information
that a person is kind, followed by information that he both (a) bought din-
ner for a street person who did not have enough money to eat and (b) be-
rated his secretary for coming 10 minutes late to work. Recipients are likely
to think more extensively about the second behavior, which is ostensibly
inconsistent with the trait description than about the first one, leading this
behavior to be better remembered later (Hastie & Kumar, 1979; Srull, 1981;
Wyer & Gordon, 1982). However, suppose people receive information that a
conservative Republican has both organized a sit-in at a nuclear power
plant and picketed an abortion clinic. In this case, recipients are less likely
to think about the behaviors in terms of their consistency with the general
characteristics of the actor. Rather, they think about them with reference to
their knowledge about the social implications of the behavior and their per-
ception that these implications are desirable. Consequently, they have
28 CHAPTER 2

better recall of the behaviors that reflect policies they consider to be incor-
rect or undesirable (Wänke & Wyer, 1996; Wyer, Lambert, Budesheim, &
Gruenfeld, 1992). In short, information that has little relevance to one’s
prior knowledge about its referents is likely to be thought about in terms of
the semantic consistency of its implications. However, information about
persons and situations about which one has prior knowledge is usually
thought about with reference to this knowledge, and so its semantic consis-
tency has less impact.
The aforementioned studies provide only few examples of the role of ref-
erent-specific knowledge in comprehending and validating new informa-
tion. The effects of spontaneously recognizing information as true or false
in the course of comprehending it, and the reactions to the implications of
these assessments, are central to an understanding of humor elicitation
(Wyer & Collins, 1992), emotional communication (Gaelick, Bodenhausen, &
Wyer, 1985; Scott, Fuhrman, & Wyer, 1991) and persuasion (Gruenfeld &
Wyer, 1992; Wyer & Gruenfeld, 1995). This becomes clear in later chapters
of this volume.

The Nonverbal Coding of Social Events

A second limitation of Wyer and Srull’s (1989) theory is its focus on linguisti-
cally coded information processing. The information we acquire in daily life
is often obtained nonverbally, through direct observation. Although linguis-
tically coded information (e.g., verbal utterances) can accompany our ob-
servations, this information is also conveyed in the context of visual and
acoustic features that are important for comprehending it. (One’s interpre-
tation of a colleague’s comment “You idiot!” is clearly different, depending
on the speaker’s facial expression and tone of voice.) The interpretation of
nonverbal behavior, both in isolation and in the context of verbal behavior,
has received much attention (for a recent review, see DePaulo & Friedman,
1998). However, although the multiple modalities in which information can
be represented in memory have been recognized in cognitive psychology
(A. Anderson, Garrod, & Sanford, 1983; Graesser, Singer, & Trabasso, 1994;
Schank & Abelson, 1977, 1995; Zwaan, Magliano, & Graesser, 1995), the impli-
cations of this fact has rarely been considered in social psychological the-
ory and research. Carlston (1994) noted that visual and linguistic process-
ing systems can interact in the course of attaining a specific processing
objective (i.e., impression formation). However, the nature of this interac-
tion is left ambiguous in his model. Wyer and Srull (1989) allowed for the
construction of mental representations in multiple sense modalities, but
they also fail to articulate the nature of these representations and the con-
ditions in which they are formed.
ARCHITECTURE OF THE INFORMATION-PROCESSING SYSTEM 29

In this regard, the modality in which information is presented is not nec-


essarily the modality in which it is reported. Visual information can some-
times be encoded into memory linguistically. Moreover, linguistically coded
information can elicit mental images (Bransford, Barclay, & Franks, 1972;
Garnham, 1981; Radvansky, Gerard, Zacks, & Hasher, 1990; Reyes, Thomp-
son, & Bower, 1980; Wyer, Adaval, & Colcombe, 2002). These processes,
however, are not articulated in the theory proposed by Wyer and Srull
(1989).
Other, more specific problems with the original theory will be noted
presently in the context in which they become relevant. The conceptualiza-
tion we propose in this and later chapters is intended to address the earlier
deficiencies while at the same time preserving the general architecture of
the information-processing system of the original model and, therefore,
many of its implications. In the next section, we outline the general struc-
ture of the proposed system, noting the assumptions that differ from those
of the original model. We then summarize the assumptions we now make
concerning information storage and retrieval, which differ significantly
from those of the original formulation.

STRUCTURE OF THE PROCESSING SYSTEM

The architecture of the social information-processing system we propose is


described in Fig. 2.1. The system, which is structurally very similar to that
postulated by Wyer and Srull (1989), consists metaphorically of four infor-
mation storage units (the Sensory Store, the Work Space, the Permanent
Storage Unit, and a Goal Specification Box), four special-purpose processing
units (the Comprehender, Encoder/Organizer, Inference Maker and Re-
sponse Selector), and an Executor that directs the transmission of cognitive
material from one unit to another. The original theory differs from the
model to be proposed in terms of (a) the organization of memory in Perma-
nent Storage, (b) the functions of the Comprehender, and (c) the processes
of information retrieval.

Storage Units

Of the four storage units the theory postulates, the Sensory Store is least
important for the issues of concern in this volume. This unit simply records
the configuration of sensory input material that impinges on the cognitive
system at any given movement, in fairly veridical form. However, the trace
of this information decays rapidly (in a manner of seconds), and if it is not
involved in further processing, it is lost (cf. Sperling, 1960). The postulation
of this storage unit recognizes that information in multiple sense modalities
30
FIG. 2.1. Schematic representation of the information processing system. Circles and ovals re-
fer to processing units. Rectangles denote storage units. Arrows indicate the direction of trans-
mission of cognitive material between these units.
ARCHITECTURE OF THE INFORMATION-PROCESSING SYSTEM 31

can simultaneously impinge on the processing system and can serve as in-
put to the Comprehender (see Fig. 2.1). However, its importance for the is-
sues of concern here is limited, and the unit will generally not be discussed
further.

1. The Work Space

The structure and function of the Work Space is similar to that of the
original model. This unit functions as a temporary store of all information
that has been encoded by the Comprehender along with other material
that is or has recently been involved in higher level goal-directed process-
ing. As shown in Fig. 2.1, input to the Work Space can include material that
has been interpreted and transmitted to it by the Comprehender, con-
cepts and knowledge representations that have been retrieved from Per-
manent Storage for use in attaining specific processing objectives, and the
results of this processing. The capacity of the Work Space is large, and as
long as its contents are relevant to the attainment of a processing objec-
tive that is active, it can be retained indefinitely. However, if a processing
goal has been attained, or if information has not been used for some time,
the Work Space may be cleared to permit easier access to material that is
relevant to other, more immediate objectives. This may be done either au-
tomatically, as new material is deposited, or volitionally (for evidence, see
Srull & Wyer, 1983). Phenomenally, this simply means that people can in-
tentionally stop thinking about material of relevance to one objective and
concentrate on a second.2
These considerations become important in the context of an additional
assumption of both the Wyer and Srull model and the present one. That is,
only the output of higher order goal-directed processing is transmitted to
Permanent Storage. Therefore, once the Work Space is cleared, any input
information from the Work Space that has not been involved in goal-
directed cognitive activity is irretrievably lost.

2. Permanent Storage

A major modification of the present model in relation to that proposed


by Wyer and Srull surrounds the conceptualization of long-term memory or,
in other words, Permanent Storage. We first describe the assumptions of the
original model, and then discuss the modifications to be made.

2
2 On the surface, this implication appears inconsistent with the result of research on thought
suppression (Bodenhausen & Macrae, 1998; Wegner, 1994), which suggests that conscious at-
tempts not to think about a concept increases its accessibility in memory. However, this incon-
sistency is illusory, as we point out later in this volume.
32 CHAPTER 2

The Original Model. Wyer and Srull conceptualized long-term memory


metaphorically as a number of content-addressable storage bins. One, se-
mantic bin, was likened to a “cognitive dictionary” that contained semantic
concepts necessary to interpret incoming stimulus information. Referent
bins, which in combination functioned as a cognitive “encyclopedia,” con-
tained representations of a particular referent (entity, event, etc.) that are
formed in the course of goal-directed cognitive activity. Each bin was identi-
fied by a “header,” or set of features that defined or circumscribed its con-
tents. Different representations could be formed of a referent at different
points in time, being stored in a bin as separate units of knowledge in the or-
der they are constructed. Thus, more recently formed representations were
on top. These representations, which might differ in form and modality,
could theoretically be retrieved independently of one another in the course
of a top-down search of the bin contents. This means that the most recently
formed and deposited representations are most likely to be identified later.
Different bins were theoretically formed to contain information about
referents at different levels of specificity. Thus, an individual might form a
“George W. Bush” bin containing information about Bush’s actions and poli-
cies while in office, but also a “U.S. President” bin containing more general
information about U.S. Presidents, the names of specific exemplars, and so
on. Note from this example that pieces of knowledge in one bin (e.g., the
name of a specific U.S. President) can include features in the header of an-
other bin. Moreover, not all information about a referent is necessarily
stored in the bin that pertains to this referent. Thus, suppose one’s objec-
tive at the time a piece of information is received about George W. Bush
pertains to presidents in general rather than to Bush in particular. Then, it
would be stored in a “U.S. Presidents” bin. Consequently, it would not be re-
trieved if one is later searching in the “Bush” bin for relevant knowledge
about George W. Bush.

The Proposed Modification. The “bin” construct permitted the Wyer


and Srull model to predict and explain a number of phenomena that are dif-
ficult for alternative formulations to capture (e.g., see Srull & Wyer, 1980,
1983; Wyer & Bodenhausen, 1985; Wyer & Budesheim, 1987; Wyer & Unver-
zagt, 1985). At the same time, the conceptualization is inadequate to ac-
count for the comprehension of information about known people and
events. One problem derives from the aforementioned assumptions that (a)
the information contained in a referent bin is only accessed in the course of
goal-directed cognitive activity, and (b) a top-down search of the bin is re-
quired in order to identify it. Because of these assumptions, the conceptual-
ization has difficulty accounting for the spontaneous comprehension of
information about known people and events, or for the spontaneous recog-
nition that the information one receives is true or false.
ARCHITECTURE OF THE INFORMATION-PROCESSING SYSTEM 33

In the revised theory, therefore, we drop the construct of bins. Instead,


following multiple-trace theories of long-term memory (cf. Hintzman, 1986),
we assume that each mental representation that is formed of a given body
of information (either at the time the information is first received or later, in
the course of higher order, goal-directed processing) has its own memory
trace. Each of these representations can become involved in the processing
of information at the initial comprehension stage as well as at later stages,
in ways that we specify presently. This modification of the theory permits
new information about a known referent (e.g., George W. Bush) to be com-
prehended immediately in terms of a specific representation of this referent
without requiring goal-directed cognitive activity.

3. Goal Specification Box


The Goal Specification Box is a temporary store of the procedures that
are currently being used to attain the particular goals that are actively be-
ing pursued at the time. These procedures, or goal schemas, are drawn from
Permanent Storage, and are consulted by the Executor for instructions
about the cognitive steps required to attain these goals. More than one goal
schema can be stored in the Goal Specification Box at one time. This means
that the system has the capability of pursuing more than one goal simulta-
neously. However, the size of the Goal Specification Box is limited. Conse-
quently, if a particular procedure is complex, the number of other proce-
dures that can be stored in the Goal Specification Box, and, therefore, the
number and complexity of other ongoing cognitive activities that can be
pursued simultaneously, decreases.

Special Purpose Processing Units

The Wyer and Srull conceptualization postulates four special purpose proc-
essing units, each of which performs a particular function. The first, Com-
prehender, is an initial lower level encoding device that interprets stimulus
input information that enters the processing system from the Sensory
Store. Unlike other processing units, the Comprehender is not controlled by
the Executor. That is, it receives stimulus information from the Sensory
Store and automatically interprets it in terms of concepts and knowledge
structures that are drawn from Permanent Storage (Fig. 2.1). This is done in-
dependently of any more specific processing objective that might exist.
In the original theory, the activities of the Comprehender were restricted
to the encoding of information in terms of semantic concepts. In the pres-
ent conceptualization, however, the functions and capabilities of the Com-
prehender are expanded in ways that permit it to interpret information in
terms of previously acquired referent-specific knowledge as well. These
processes are articulated in detail in chapter 4.
34 CHAPTER 2

The other three processing units come into play in the course of specific
goal-directed activity, and are activated on the basis of instructions in a
goal schema that is used by the Executor to monitor this activity. The char-
acteristics of these units are not appreciably different from those described
by Wyer and Srull (1989). The Encoder/Organizer interprets stimulus infor-
mation transmitted to it from the Comprehender in terms of more abstract
concepts that are relevant to the goal being pursued, or organizes the infor-
mation with reference to a pre-existing configuration of features that are
specified in the information. The Inference Maker generates specific subjec-
tive inferences on the basis of new or pre-existing information using logical,
algebraic or other combinatorial rules, or, in some cases, heuristics. The
Response Selector then translates subjective inferences into an overt re-
sponse, which could be a behavioral decision, a judgment along a category
response scale, or a verbal utterance.
Each processing unit is equipped with a library of routines (conceptually
equivalent to cognitive productions, as mentioned in chap. 1) that it draws
on to perform its functions. The nature of these productions can depend on
both the goal being pursued and the type of information being processed.
Thus, for example, the procedures performed by the Inference Maker de-
pend on whether the goal is to form a general impression or to make a com-
parative judgment. On the other hand, they can also depend on whether
the information is conveyed visually or verbally, or whether it is conveyed
in a list or a narrative (cf. Adaval & Wyer, 1998).

The Executor

The Executor monitors the flow of cognitive material between memory stor-
age units and special purpose processing units. It has no “mind” of its own,
but instead, takes instructions from a pre-existing goal schema that is ac-
tive in the Goal Specification Box. These schemas presumably provide step-
by-step descriptions of the sequence of steps that must be performed in or-
der to attain the objective at hand.
For example, suppose people receive descriptions of a person for the
purpose of forming an impression. The goal schema that guides the attain-
ment of this objective might indicate that the individual behaviors should
be interpreted in terms of trait concepts, that the evaluative implications of
these traits should be assessed, and the implications of these assessments
should then be combined to form an inference of the person’s general like-
ableness, and that this evaluation should be communicated to another ver-
bally. The Executor would presumably recognize the first two (trait and
evaluative) encoding tasks to be the responsibility of the Encoder/Organ-
izer and would direct the information to this unit with instructions to per-
form the encoding. Once the results of the evaluative encoding are avail-
ARCHITECTURE OF THE INFORMATION-PROCESSING SYSTEM 35

able, the Executor would transmit these encodings to the Inference Maker
with instructions to combine their implications into an overall inference.
Then, once this inference is computed, the Executor would transmit the in-
ference to the Response Selector with a request to generate an overt re-
sponse in a language that was applicable (a verbal utterance or, if the infer-
ence is to be reported in an experiment, a numerical value along a response
scale).
Note that the routines contained in the libraries of the various process-
ing units, as well as the goal schemata used by the Executor to govern the
flow of information in pursuit of specific processing objectives, are gener-
ally not specified by the conceptualization we propose. These routines and
procedures are the subject of research on specific types of cognitive activ-
ity of the sort described by Wyer and Srull (1989) as well as later chapters
of the present volume. However, many social psychological theories de-
rived from this research can incorporated into the more general conceptu-
alization we have proposed. For example, the model of person impression
formation and memory proposed by Srull and Wyer (1989; for earlier ver-
sions, see Hastie & Kumar, 1979; Srull, 1981), which specifies the cognitive
processes involved in forming an impression and the cognitive representa-
tions that are formed as a result of these processes, can be viewed as a
specification of an “impression formation” goal schema along with a specifi-
cation of the organizational processes performed by the Encoder/Organizer
and stored in the Encoder/Organizer’s library. The algebraic integration
processes postulated by Norman Anderson (1971; 1981), several of the cog-
nitive heuristics identified by Tversky and Kahneman (1974), and the attri-
bution processes postulated by Bem (1972) and Jones and Davis (1965), can
be viewed as theories about the routines performed by the Inference Maker
and the conditions in which they are applied. The impact of contextual
stimuli on the use of category response scales (Lynch, Chakravarti, & Mitra,
1991; Ostrom & Upshaw, 1968; Parducci, 1965; Wyer, 1974) and opinion sur-
vey responses (Schwarz, 1994; Strack, 1994) are essentially theories about
the processes performed by the Response Selector. These and other theo-
retical formulations can in principle be incorporated into the general frame-
work we propose.

Effects of Multiple Goal Schemata

Two more general aspects of the conceptualization are worth noting at this
point. First, more than one goal schema might be relevant to the attainment
of a given objective. An alternative to the sequence described in our exam-
ple might involve a comparison of the configuration of trait encodings to
the pre-existing knowledge representation of a known person, or alterna-
tively, a prototype, and, if there is sufficient match, an inference of the per-
36 CHAPTER 2

son’s likeableness from a pre-existing evaluation of the person to which this


representation refers (Fiske & Pavelchak, 1986). (Thus, for example, the
configuration of features might match those of one’s roommate or, alterna-
tively, the “typical college professor,” leading the evaluation to be similar to
that associated with this individual.) In this case, which alternative schema
is applied could depend on its relative accessibility in memory and the ease
of performing the cognitive operations it specifies (Logan, 1988).
In this regard, several recent formulations of information processing
have been viewed as “dual processing” models (e.g., see Chaiken & Trope,
1999). These models recognize that different processes are likely to govern
memory and judgment, depending on a number of situational and motiva-
tional factors that happen to exist. These alternative processes are gener-
ally implicit in the conceptualization we propose and also the Wyer and
Srull theory, both of which postulate that several different cognitive proc-
esses may be specified in the alternative goal schemata that can potentially
be brought to bear on the attainment of a particular processing objective as
well as in the libraries of various processing units. Although the present
conceptualization does always not specify the nature of these processes, it
clearly allows for their existence. Moreover, the conceptualization takes
into account the possibility that different processes can operate simulta-
neously. Several alternative processes of encoding, organization, and infer-
ence are described in detail throughout this volume.

Conscious Versus Nonconscious Processes

Second, Wyer and Srull assume that “consciousness” resides in the Execu-
tor. Thus, the Executor is “aware” of the general processing stages to be
performed, as specified in the goal schema. Furthermore, it is aware of the
inputs to processing units, the material that is drawn from Permanent Stor-
age to use in operating on these inputs, and the output of processing at
each stage. On the other hand, the cognitive operations performed by the
various processing units, which are governed by procedures stored in the
libraries of these units, are not subject to awareness.
For example, suppose a man is asked his impression of a woman who
reads Tolstoy and pickets abortion clinics. He might judge the woman to be
both “intellectual” and “feminist” on the basis of these behavioral descrip-
tions. Furthermore, he might be aware that the characterization reminded
him of a college professor he knew in the 1960s, and that he based his liking
for the woman on his feelings about this professor. This is because the out-
put of processing at each stage is retained in the Work Space and, as such,
is accessible to the Executor. On the other hand, the man would have little
insight into why he interpreted the behavior in terms of these particular
traits rather than others, or into the processes that led to his inference that
ARCHITECTURE OF THE INFORMATION-PROCESSING SYSTEM 37

the woman was similar to the professor. We consider the results of auto-
matic and deliberative processing later in this volume. For the time being, it
is sufficient to note that the theory can account in principle for differences
in conscious and nonconscious processing and can specify the conditions
in which each type of processing may operate.

STORAGE AND RETRIEVAL PROCESSES

The assumptions surrounding the storage and retrieval of information are


intimately connected to assumptions about the structure of memory. In the
original theory, information in Permanent Storage was identified by (a)
compiling a set of features (“probe cues”) that specify the type of informa-
tion desired, (b) identifying a referent bin whose header contains these fea-
tures, and (c) conducting a probabilistic, top-down search of memory for a
knowledge representation that contains these features. These assumptions
imply that the likelihood of identifying a particular knowledge representa-
tion will increase with both the recency of its acquisition and use (and,
therefore, its proximity to the top of the bin) and the frequency of its acqui-
sition and use (i.e., the number of times it is represented). In the present
theory, we retain the construct of “probe cues.” However, the bin construct
is eliminated and with it, the sequential search processes that Wyer and
Srull (1989) postulated. Consequently, the effects of recency and frequency
on accessibility are accounted for in other ways.

Storage

Our assumptions about the storage of information can be stated simply in


terms of a postulate:

Postulate 2.1. Each knowledge representation that is formed, either in the


course of comprehension or in the course of higher level, goal-directed pro-
cessing, constitutes a separate unit of knowledge that is stored independently
of other knowledge units.

This assumption has broad implications. For example, it suggests that if


two conceptually related representations of a referent are formed at differ-
ent times, they will be stored separately in memory. Consequently, one rep-
resentation can later be retrieved independently of the other. Thus, for ex-
ample, suppose people who have formed a detailed representation of a
personal experience are later asked to describe this experience to others.
They may do so by retrieving the representation and encoding it in terms of
38 CHAPTER 2

more general, semantic concepts that can be communicated verbally. This


more general, verbally coded representation is then stored separately from
the more detailed representation on which it is based, and can correspond-
ingly be retrieved independently of the latter representation for use in later
processing.
This latter processing could lead still other representations to be con-
structed. In the preceding example, people might later recall their abstract
representation of the experience and use it to make a trait inference about
the protagonists. This inference, in turn, could constitute yet another repre-
sentation that is stored independently of either of the others. Note that ac-
cording to Postulate 2.1, a higher order representation does not replace the
original. That is, all of the knowledge representations that have been
formed coexist in memory. Whether or not a given representation is re-
trieved, however, depends on factors described shortly.
Direct evidence for the independent-storage postulate is somewhat lim-
ited. However, a study by Klein and Loftus (1993) is suggestive. Participants
were asked both to report whether they had each of several traits and, in
addition, to recall a specific behavior that exemplified the traits. However,
the order of responding to the two requests was varied. The time that par-
ticipants required to verify that they had a trait did not depend on whether
they had previously recalled a behavior that exemplified it. By the same to-
ken, the time to report a trait-related behavior did not depend on whether
or not participants had previously reported having the trait implied by this
behavior. Thus, participants did not base their trait judgments on the rele-
vant behavior that was salient to them at the time. Furthermore, making a
trait judgment that a behavior exemplified did not facilitate their later recall
of this behavior. These findings suggest the independence of traits and be-
havior in memory. The independence of trait representations and behav-
ioral representations may be more characteristic of self-knowledge than of
knowledge about others. However, other evidence of the independence of
conceptually related knowledge representations are discussed in chapter 6
as well as elsewhere in this volume.
This conceptualization obviously requires the assumption that Perma-
nent Storage has unlimited capacity. That is, once a representation has
been encoded into memory, it is never erased. Given the virtually infinite
number of experiences that individuals have over the course of a lifetime,
this assumption may seem nonsensical. An alternative assumption is sug-
gested by distributed memory or connectionist models, which assume that
memories are not localized but rather, are represented by an array of acti-
vated features that, in different strengths and combinations, can capture
the sum total of experiences to which the system has been exposed. In prin-
ciple, a very large number of unique memories can theoretically be cap-
tured by a small number of feature nodes. (E.g., 10 nodes, each of which can
ARCHITECTURE OF THE INFORMATION-PROCESSING SYSTEM 39

be assigned 10 different strengths, could potentially represent 1010 unique


memories.)
Several distributed memory models of social information processing
have been proposed (e.g., Humphreys & Kashima, 2002; Smith & DeCoster,
1998, 1999), and it is conceivable that such a conceptualization of Perma-
nent Storage would be viable in the present context. However, all theories
of mental representation are inherently metaphorical, as noted in chapter
1, and should be evaluated on the basis of their utility and not their validity.
The assumptions underlying the conceptualization we propose provide a
more parsimonious account of the phenomena being considered in this vol-
ume than the distributed memory models proposed to date.

Retrieval Processes

The retrieval processes we postulate are borrowed in part from a previous


formulation by Ratcliff (1978) and make use of a “tuning fork” metaphor (for
related conceptualizations, see Albrecht & Myers, 1995; Kintsch, 1998).
Many implications of this conceptualization are somewhat similar to those
of a spreading activation, associative network model (cf. J. Anderson, 1983;
Collins & Loftus, 1975; Wyer & Carlston, 1979). In contrast to these latter
models, however, our formulation requires no assumptions about the orga-
nization of these knowledge representations in memory.
We assume that when a configuration of stimulus features is activated,
they “vibrate” and this causes the configuration to resonate with knowl-
edge representations (memory traces) that contain some or all of these fea-
tures. If the resonance of a knowledge representation exceeds a threshold
value, it is also activated. When a knowledge representation is no longer in-
volved in processing, it becomes deactivated. Like a tuning fork, however,
the resonance does not dissipate instantly, but decreases gradually over
time. These processes can be stated more formally in terms of five addi-
tional postulates.Ç

Postulate 2.2. The activation of a set of stimulus features causes all knowl-
edge representations that contain these features to resonate. The resonance
of a given representation, k, increases with (a) the similarity of its features to
those in the stimulus set and (b) the length of time the stimulus set has been
activated. The subjective similarity of the stimulus features to the representa-
tion, and thus the rate at which its resonance increases, is estimated by the
quantity:
n(pI k )
Res(k) = ,
n(k )
where n(k) is the number of features in the representation and n( p I k ) is the
number of features that are common to both the representation and the stim-
40 CHAPTER 2

ulus set. If the resonance reaches a threshold value, T (k), the representation
is activated.

One implication of Postulate 2.2 is worth noting at this point. That is, when
features of the probe set are contained in more than one representation,
the resonance at the representation with the fewest number of noncommon
features will reach threshold faster. Thus, the probe “football game” is
more likely to activate an abstract representation of football games than a
specific representation of the 2002 Super Bowl.

Postulate 2.3. (a) If two or more representations resonate with a given set of
probe cues, the one that reaches threshold most quickly is identified. (b) If
several representations reach threshold simultaneously, a composite of the
features is activated. The weight of each feature in the composite is a positive
function of the proportion of times it occurs in the set of representations in-
volved.

Postulate 2.3a is consistent with the assumptions of the independent


trace model proposed by Logan (1988). Postulate 2.3b is suggested by
Hintzman’s (1986) conception of the process of abstracting general con-
cepts from exemplars. For example, it implies that when several relevant
knowledge representations are activated by a given set of stimulus fea-
tures, the features that are typical of these representations as a whole are
most likely to come to mind and other features, which characterize only a
few of these representations, tend to be filtered out. Thus, suppose a base-
ball fan who encounters the statement “Nolan Ryan pitched a no-hitter” has
a single instance of this event represented in memory. In this case, the fea-
tures “Nolan Ryan” and “no-hitter” in combination should activate a de-
tailed representation of the game in question. In contrast, a fan who has ob-
served all six of Ryan’s no-hit games is likely to activate a more general set
of features that are common to these games without thinking about any
particular one of them. But suppose the same two individuals encounter
the general statement “a ball player pitched a no-hitter.” In this case, both
fans might activate a general set of features that do not specify any given
baseball pitcher or behavior.
The preceding analysis suggests that if baseball fans encounter the state-
ment “Nolan Ryan pitched a no-hitter,” they will typically comprehend it in
terms of a previously formed representation of Nolan Ryan engaging in this
activity rather than in terms of more general semantic concepts associated
with baseball players and no-hit games. That is, they will comprehend the
statement in terms of different concepts than they would if they encoun-
tered the statement “a baseball player pitched a no-hitter.” Although these
observations may seem intuitively obvious, Wyer and Srull’s (1989) model
would not make these distinctions.
ARCHITECTURE OF THE INFORMATION-PROCESSING SYSTEM 41

Determinants of Knowledge Accessibility

The next two postulates, which are implied by numerous studies of the de-
terminants and effects of knowledge accessibility (for reviews, see Bargh,
1997; Higgins, 1996; Wyer & Srull, 1989), become important in conceptualiz-
ing the effect of previously using a knowledge representation on their sub-
sequent reactivation and use at a later time.

Postulate 2.4. If a knowledge representation has resonated with a set of


probe cues, this resonance does not dissipate immediately but rather, decays
gradually over time.

Postulate 2.5. The activation threshold of a knowledge representation in


memory, T(k), is an increasing function of the number of times the represen-
tation has been activated in the past.

In effect, Postulate 2.4 permits the theory to account for the effect of re-
cency of activation on concept and knowledge accessibility that is consis-
tently observed in research on priming effects (Higgins, Bargh, & Lombardi,
1985; Srull & Wyer, 1979). Postulate 2.5 permits the theory to account for the
effect of frequency of activation that is also observed in these studies. One
implication of these postulates is worth noting. Specifically, the effect of re-
cency of activation, which is a function of the residual resonance that exists
at a memory location after the knowledge representation at the location
has been deactivated, is transitory. That is, the effect decreases over time
as the residual resonance dissipates. In contrast, the effect of activation fre-
quency, which is localized in the level of the activation threshold, is rela-
tively permanent. These implications of the theory are discussed more fully
in chapter 3.

GOAL-DIRECTED VERSUS NON-GOAL-DIRECTED


PROCESSING: SPONTANEOUS REMINDING
PROCESSES

Postulate 2.2 specifies the rules that govern the retrieval of a particular
knowledge representation from Permanent Storage, given that a set of fea-
tures are identified for use as “probe cues.” However, it does not indicate
the processes that underlie the selection of these features. These processes
typically come into play once information has been comprehended and
transmitted to the Work Space and, therefore, are governed by the Execu-
tor. The nature of this cognitive activity depends in part on whether or not
the information is processed in pursuit of a particular goal.
42 CHAPTER 2

Goal-Directed Retrieval Processes

If previously acquired knowledge is required for a particular purpose, the


following steps are assumed:

1. The Executor compiles a set of features that exist in the Work Space,
giving greater weight to those that have been activated and used more re-
cently. These features (“probe cues”) are likely to be ones that (a) are rele-
vant to the objectives one is pursuing and (b) have recently been transmit-
ted to the Work Space by the Comprehender. However, the number of
features that are compiled may depend on the specificity of the objective be-
ing pursued. When this objective is relatively nonspecific, features may be
fortuitously included in the set that are not relevant to it.
2. The probe cues identified in Step 1 vibrate, leading them to resonate
with knowledge representations in either the Work Space or Permanent Stor-
age that contain them. The representation(s) that reach activation threshold
most quickly, based on criteria specified in Postulate 2.2, are identified, and
copies of them are transmitted to the Work Space for use in goal-directed ac-
tivity.
3. If no representation is identified in Step 2, the set of probe features is
recompiled and the search is repeated.

These processes are somewhat similar to those proposed by Norman


and Bobrow (1979) in accounting for the retrieval of information from “very
long-term memory.” The fact that goal-irrelevant features are sometimes in-
cluded in the probe set has two noteworthy implications. First, the inclu-
sion of these features can sometimes prevent the identification of a goal-
relevant representation that exists in memory. This may be experienced
subjectively as a “tip of the tongue” phenomenon, where one is temporarily
unable to identify the name of a well-known acquaintance or a movie one
has seen. In these instances, extraneous probe cues may interfere with the
retrieval of a representation containing this information, and so the name
may not come to mind unless the set of probe cues is recompiled.
Second, the configuration of probe cues that results from the presence
of a goal-irrelevant feature can sometimes lead to the retrieval of knowl-
edge that would not normally come to mind. This can account for the spon-
taneous recall of a person or event that had not been thought about for
many years. To borrow an example from Wyer and Srull (1989), a person
who is asked to describe his hometown might normally use the name of the
town (e.g., “Delhi, New York”) as a probe cue, activating a general represen-
tation of its physical characteristics and the type of people who live there.
However, suppose the individual had been discussing religion just before
being asked to provide this description. Then, a feature activated by this
ARCHITECTURE OF THE INFORMATION-PROCESSING SYSTEM 43

discussion (e.g., “church”) might be fortuitously included in the probe set.


This feature, in combination with the town’s name, might stimulate a mem-
ory of adjourning to the basement of the church while the collection was
being taken in order to avoid putting money in the plate. This behavior may
not have been thought about for 40 years, and might have been buried in
memory forever if the two probe features had not been fortuitously acti-
vated in combination.3

Information Processing During the Free Flow


of Thought

Much of our cognitive activity in daily life appears to occur without any par-
ticular objective in mind. We frequently engage in daydreaming, or let our
minds wander aimlessly from one topic to another in an ostensibly haphaz-
ard manner. In the course of this free flow of thought, however, we may be
reminded of something we have to do, or of a problem we need to solve,
and we suddenly find ourselves immersed in thoughts about how to accom-
plish these objectives. At other times, our cognitive musings can stimulate
a memory of a past experience or acquaintance that we have not thought
about in years. A complete formulation of information processing in situa-
tions outside the laboratory must be able to specify the processes that sur-
round the free flow of thought and the transition of these processes into
more deliberative, goal-directed cognitive activities.
To account for these processes within the present conceptualization, we
assume that when individuals do not have a specific goal in mind, the proc-
essing system enters into a continuous feedback loop that continues indefi-
nitely until a goal is identified, either as a result of external demands (i.e.,
transmitted by the Comprehender) or internally generated cognitive activ-
ity. These processes can be described easily with reference to Fig. 2.2. The

3
3 In comparing the retrieval processes described here with the processes postulated by
Wyer and Srull (1989), one further implication should be noted. The earlier model assumed that
in the pursuit of goal-relevant information, the Work Space was searched first, before informa-
tion is retrieved from Permanent Storage. In the present conceptualization, this assumption is
an implicit by-product of Postulate 2.5. That is, a set of probe cues is likely to resonate to the
greatest extent with existing knowledge representations that have been activated and used
most recently. Because the knowledge representations contained in the Work Space have typi-
cally been used recently in the pursuit of processing objectives, they would normally be reacti-
vated more quickly than representations in Permanent Storage for use in attaining goals to
which they are relevant. To this extent, the two conceptualizations are quite compatible. On the
other hand, the content of the Work Space typically consists of representations that have either
been (a) recently recalled from Permanent Storage, or (b) recently formed and transmitted to
Permanent Storage by the Executor. These representations would be activated in Permanent
Storage according to criteria assumed by Postulate 2.2. To this extent, the implications of the as-
sumption that the Work Space is searched first are largely redundant with those of the retrieval
postulates that we have already stated.
FIG. 2.2. Flow diagram of information processing in the absence of a specific
objective (e.g., during the free flow of thought). Circles denote the processes
involved. Diamonds indicate conditions that give rise to different types of
processing.

44
ARCHITECTURE OF THE INFORMATION-PROCESSING SYSTEM 45

first two stages of processing are similar to Steps 1 and 2 of the process as-
sumed to underlie goal-directed retrieval. That is, the Executor identifies a
set of features that happen to exist in the Work Space (either transmitted
from the Comprehender or resulting from prior cognitive activity). These
features in combination activate a representation in Permanent Storage, a
copy of which is sent to the Work Space. The Executor scans this represen-
tation for a goal specification and, if none is found, repeats the process just
described, recompiling a set of probe cues and using them to activate an-
other representation in Permanent Storage. This continues until a goal
specification is identified as a result of the content of the material retrieved
from Permanent Storage or transmitted from the Comprehender.
Phenomenologically, this simply means that when people do not have a
particular goal in mind, the configuration of cognitions they happen to be
thinking about cues the retrieval of a previously formed representation.
Features of this representation, once retrieved, may combine with other ac-
tivated concepts to cue the retrieval of yet another representation, and so
on until a goal is identified.
Thus, for example, suppose a student overhears a conversation in which
one person comments that “John gave Peter an answer during the exam.” A
representation of the statement that is constructed in the course of com-
prehending it is transmitted to the Work Space. Features of this representa-
tion (e.g., “exam”) along with other features that happen to be in the Work
Space at the time (e.g., “psychology”) are sampled, and a set of features is
compiled (e.g., “psychology, exam”). These features may resonate with a
representation in Permanent Storage that contains them (e.g., the thought
that the final exam in psychology is only 3 days before Christmas). As this
knowledge does not have goal implications, a new set of probe features is
compiled which might now include “Christmas.” These features then reso-
nate with representations in Permanent Storage that contain this feature,
perhaps leading a representation to be retrieved that concerns buying a
Christmas present for one’s boyfriend. In this case, however, the Executor
recognizes this as a goal. Consequently, the system leaves the feedback
loop. That is, the Executor identifies a goal schema pertaining to the objec-
tive and deposits it in the Goal Specification Box, and then uses the content
of the schema to direct processing relevant to attainment of the goal (e.g.,
the construction of a plan about what to buy and where to purchase it).

CONCLUDING REMARKS

The information-processing model outlined in this chapter provides a


framework for conceptualizing much if not all of the theory and research
discussed in the remainder of this volume. This will be particularly clear in
46 CHAPTER 2

our analysis of the comprehension of personal experiences, and of informa-


tion about actual persons and events of the sort we encounter in the course
of daily life. Several important implications of the conceptualization are lo-
calized in Postulates 2.4 and 2.5, which govern the factors that influence the
accessibility of knowledge in memory and, therefore, the likelihood that
this knowledge is brought to bear on the processing of new information. In-
deed, knowledge accessibility is a primary consideration in all phases of in-
formation processing from the initial comprehension of information to the
generation of an overt response. Before embarking on a more detailed anal-
ysis of comprehension and judgment, therefore, a more general discussion
of the determinants and effects of knowledge accessibility will be useful.
The next chapter provides this discussion.
C H A P T E R

3
Determinants and Effects
of Knowledge Accessibility

The retrieval postulates outlined in chapter 2 come into play at many


stages of processing and therefore play a role in our discussion throughout
this volume. However, they have particular implications for the factors that
influence the accessibility of concepts and knowledge in memory. The im-
portant role of knowledge accessibility in information processing is recog-
nized in numerous areas of social psychology, including the comprehen-
sion of information in terms of semantic concepts (Higgins, Rholes, & Jones,
1977; Srull & Wyer, 1979, 1980), stereotyping (Bodenhausen & Macrae, 1998),
consumer judgment (Adaval & Monroe, 2002), cultural influences on judg-
ment (Briley & Wyer, 2002; Hong, Morris, Chiu, & Benet-Martinez, 2000), and
overt behavior (Bargh, Chen, & Burrows, 1996; Dijksterhuis & van
Knippenberg, 1998). Higgins (1996) provides an extensive review of this re-
search, and a duplication of his efforts is unnecessary here. In this chapter,
we restrict our attention to representative phenomena for which the pro-
posed conceptualization has implications.

GENERAL CONSIDERATIONS

The general effects of concept and knowledge accessibility are intuitively


obvious. That is, people who are called upon to make a judgment or deci-
sion seldom consider the implications of all of the knowledge they have ac-
quired that bears upon it. Instead, they use the first relevant judgment or
decision criterion that comes to mind, ignoring other criteria that might be
equally or more applicable. Taylor and Fiske (1978) were among the first to

47
48 CHAPTER 3

recognize this possibility, arguing that many judgments and decisions are
made “off the top of the head.” A more formal statement of this phenome-
non was proposed by Chaiken (1980, 1987). She argued that people who
have to make a judgment or decision first apply the criterion that comes to
mind most quickly and easily and then assess their confidence that the im-
plications of using this criterion are sufficient to attain the goal at hand.
Only if this confidence is below some minimal “confidence threshold” do
they search for additional criteria. Thus, they may search further if they are
highly motivated to make a “correct” decision, or if for some reason they
believe that the criterion they initially applied may be biased. Normally,
however, they base their judgment or decision on the first relevant crite-
rion they happen to think about.
The implications of Chaiken’s conceptualization can be formalized in the
following, sufficiency postulate:

Postulate 3.1. People retrieve and use only the amount of information that
they consider to be sufficient for attaining the processing objective they are
pursuing at the time. The information they use is likely to be the first goal-
relevant information that comes to mind or, alternatively, permits their objec-
tive to be attained most quickly and easily.

Chaiken’s formulation has been applied primarily in conceptualizing re-


sponses to persuasive communications (Chaiken, 1987; Chaiken, Wood, &
Eagly, 1996). However, it has more general applicability to information proc-
essing (Chaiken, Liberman, & Eagly, 1989), and many of the phenomena
reviewed later in this volume can be viewed from the perspective she sug-
gests. The discussion in this chapter is restricted to representative re-
search that bears on three main points to which the formulation outlined in
chapter 2 is particularly relevant:

1. The primary determinants of knowledge accessibility are (a) the re-


cency with which knowledge has been acquired and/or used in the past and
(b) the frequency with which it has been applied. In the latter regard, knowl-
edge that has been employed in many situations over a long period of time
can become “chronically” accessible.
2. The accessibility of knowledge representations for use in attaining a
particular processing objective can be activated by extraneous factors that
are objectively irrelevant to this objective and of which persons may not be
consciously aware. In fact, increasing awareness of these extraneous factors
is likely to decrease their influence.
3. The effects of differences in knowledge accessibility are apparent at
several stages of processing, including the spontaneous comprehension of
information at the time it is first received, the more deliberative interpreta-
DETERMINANTS AND EFFECTS OF KNOWLEDGE ACCESSIBILITY 49

tion of information that occurs in the course of attaining a particular goal, in-
ference processes, and behavioral decision making. Differences in knowl-
edge accessibility can also influence the goals that individuals pursue under
conditions in which more than one objective is potentially relevant, and the
procedures that are spontaneously activated and used to attain a particular
goal (e.g., productions of the sort postulated by Anderson, 1983).

FREQUENCY AND RECENCY EFFECTS


OF KNOWLEDGE ACTIVATION ON JUDGMENTS
AND DECISIONS

The earliest research in social cognition to examine the impact of knowl-


edge accessibility was conducted in the area of person impression forma-
tion. When people are asked to form an impression of someone on the basis
of the person’s behaviors, they often interpret these behaviors in terms of
traits. This activity is presumably performed by the Encoder/Organizer
based on concepts that are transmitted to it by the Executor. Many behav-
iors are ambiguous. That is, they have implications for values along several
different trait dimensions or, alternatively, for different values along the
same dimension. Under these conditions, the interpretation of the behavior
can depend on the particular concept that is brought to bear on it. This, in
turn, can depend on both the recency and the frequency of its use in the
past and, therefore, its accessibility in memory (Postulates 2.4 and 2.5).
Once the behavior of a person is interpreted, this interpretation provides
the basis for a more general characterization of the person and an evalua-
tion of his or her general likeableness.

Early Demonstrations

Higgins et al.’s (1977) well-known study was among the first to demonstrate
the effects of recency. Participants were asked to form an impression of a
target person who ostensibly wanted to cross the Atlantic in a sailboat, was
well aware of his ability to do things well, felt that he didn’t need to rely on
others, and rarely changed his mind once he had made a decision. Before
reading a description of these characteristics, however, participants were
unobtrusively exposed to a number of trait adjectives in the course of per-
forming a color-naming (Stroop) task. These adjectives could all be used to
interpret the target’s behaviors. In some cases, however, the adjectives
were favorable (“adventurous,” “confident,” “independent,” and “persis-
tent”) and in other cases, they were unfavorable (“reckless,” “conceited,”
“aloof,” and “stubborn”). Participants apparently interpreted the informa-
tion in terms of concepts activated by the trait adjectives to which they had
50 CHAPTER 3

been exposed in the color-naming task, and these interpretations influ-


enced their evaluations of the target. That is, they evaluated the target
more favorably when they had been exposed to favorable trait adjectives
than when they had been exposed to unfavorable ones.
In a similar series of studies (Srull & Wyer, 1979, 1980), participants per-
formed a sentence construction task that required the use of concepts asso-
ciated with hostility. Later, they were asked to form impressions of a target
person whose behaviors were ambiguous with respect to this trait (e.g., “re-
fused to pay the rent until the landlord painted his apartment,” “demanded
his money back from a salesperson,” etc.). Both the number of hostility-
related items presented in the sentence-construction task and the time in-
terval between this task and the impression formation task (immediately, 1
hour or 1 day) were manipulated. Both of these factors influenced the likeli-
hood that participants interpreted the target’s behavior as hostile, indicat-
ing that both frequency and recency played a role. Moreover, a supplemen-
tary study indicated that the effects only occurred when participants were
exposed to trait concepts before they read the target information (Srull &
Wyer, 1980). When the concepts were activated after the information was
presented, they had no effect at all. This indicates that the effects of primed
concepts on judgments were mediated by their impact on the interpreta-
tion of the trait information at the time the information was received and
did not have a direct influence on judgments independently of this informa-
tion.

The Relative Persistence of Frequency


and Recency Effects

Although the frequency and recency of prior activation both have an im-
pact on the use of trait concepts to interpret information, the underlying ba-
sis for these effects theoretically differ. As noted earlier, the effects of re-
cency of activation implied by Postulate 2.4 are transitory, whereas the
effects of activation frequency, which impacts on the activation threshold
(Postulate 2.5) are more enduring.
This was demonstrated empirically by Higgins, Bargh, and Lombardi
(1985). Participants were initially exposed to adjectives exemplifying both
favorable and unfavorable trait concepts (“adventurous” vs. “reckless”)
that could each be used to interpret the same behavior (e.g., “crossing the
Atlantic in a sailboat”). However, the relative frequency and recency of ex-
posure to the adjectives were varied. When participants were asked to in-
terpret the behaviors a very short time after exposure to the trait adjective,
they tended to use the more recency primed trait concept rather than the
frequently activated one. When a longer period of time had elapsed, how-
ever, the effects of activation frequency predominated over recency, as im-
DETERMINANTS AND EFFECTS OF KNOWLEDGE ACCESSIBILITY 51

plied by Postulates 2.4 and 2.5. (For an alternative conceptualization of


these effects, see Higgins et al., 1985.)
The enduring influence of activation frequency has important implica-
tions. That is, concepts that have been frequency used in the past can be-
come chronically accessible and, therefore, can influence comprehension
and judgments in the absence of any immediate situational factors that acti-
vate them. A study by Anderson, Reynolds, Schallert, and Goetz (1977) pro-
vides an example. Participants were asked to read the following story:

Every Saturday night, four good friends get together. When Jerry, Mike, and
Pat arrived, Karen was sitting in her living room writing some notes. She
quickly gathered the cards and stood up to greet her friends at the door. They
followed her into the living room but as usual, they couldn’t agree on exactly
what to play. Jerry eventually took a stand and set things up. Finally, they be-
gan to play. Karen’s recorder filled the room with soft and pleasant music.
Early in the evening, Mike noticed Pat’s hand and the many diamonds. As the
night progressed, the tempo of play increased. Finally, a lull in the activities
occurred. Taking advantage of this, Jerry pondered the arrangement in front
of him. Mike interrupted Jerry’s reverie and said, “Let’s hear the score.” They
listened carefully and commented on their performance. When the comments
were all heard, exhausted but happy, Karen’s friends went home.

After reading the story, participants were asked what the protagonists had
commented about.
The story is normally interpreted as the description of a card game.
However, it could also describe the rehearsal of a woodwind ensemble.
Some participants, who were students in a weight-lifting class, typically in-
dicated that the protagonists had commented on how well they were play-
ing cards. In contrast, students who were planning a career in music educa-
tion indicated that the protagonists had commented on the sound of their
music. Thus, concepts and knowledge that were chronically accessible to
participants as a result of their curriculum and interests apparently af-
fected their interpretation of the story and this interpretation influenced
their answers to questions about it.

The Additivity of Situationally Induced


and Chronic Knowledge Accessibility

A further implication of Postulates 2.4 and 2.5 is of particular interest in this


regard. That is, the effect of activation frequency (which are mediated by
changes in activation threshold) and the recency of activation (which are
mediated by the amount of residual resonance that remains at a knowledge
representation once it is no longer activated) are independent. This inde-
pendence was demonstrated by Bargh, Bond, Lombardi, and Tota (1986).
52 CHAPTER 3

They showed that the chronic accessibility of a trait concept (inferred from
individual differences in the a priori likelihood of using the trait to describe
acquaintances in a previous experiment) and situationally induced accessi-
bility of the trait (resulting from exposure to the trait in a laboratory task)
had independent and additive effects on the use of the concept to describe
a target person on the basis of information about the target’s behavior.
Although the independence of these interpolated effects are implied by
Postulates 2.4 and 2.5, they are difficult to explain on the basis of the “bin”
conceptualization proposed by Wyer and Srull (1989). According to the lat-
ter conceptualization, priming trait concepts should make them equally ac-
cessible (either in the Work Space or in the “semantic” bin) regardless of
the frequency of their prior activation, and consequently should lead these
concepts to be used to an equal extent regardless of their chronic accessi-
bility. In other words, recency should override the effects of chronic acces-
sibility. Therefore, Bargh et al.’s (1986) findings are embarrassing to the
Wyer and Srull model. On the other hand, they are quite consistent with the
retrieval postulates of the present conceptualization.

Generalizability of Concept Activation


Over Attribute Dimensions

In the study by Higgins et al. (1977), activating favorable and unfavorable


trait concepts that were descriptively inapplicable for interpreting the tar-
get’s behavior had no influence on participants’ evaluations of him. This
finding suggests that the effects of activating trait concepts do not have a
direct impact on judgments of the target, but rather, influence judgments
only through their mediating influence on how the information about the
person’s behaviors is interpreted. As we noted earlier, however, impression
formation is a two-stage process. Once a target person’s behaviors are in-
terpreted and a general impression is formed of him, the person may be in-
ferred to have other attributes that are characteristic of the sort of individ-
ual implied by this impression. Thus, as Srull and Wyer (1979, 1980) found,
activating concepts associated with hostility led the target person not only
to be described as hostile but also to have other attributes that are typical
of a hostile individual. (For a more recent explication of these two process-
ing stages, see Trope, 1986.)
The conclusion that activated trait concepts influence the interpretation
of only those behaviors to which they are descriptively applicable may nev-
ertheless need to be qualified. Stapel and Koomen (2000) found that when
stimulus attributes with extreme evaluative implications (“malevolent,”
“warm,” etc.) are primed, they do appear to influence the interpretation of
behaviors that are descriptively unrelated to them. Apparently, adjectives
with extreme implications spontaneously activate more general evaluative
DETERMINANTS AND EFFECTS OF KNOWLEDGE ACCESSIBILITY 53

concepts (“good” or “bad”) that, once activated, influence the interpreta-


tion of information along evaluative as well as descriptive dimensions.

EFFECTS OF AWARENESS

Many effects of previously acquired concepts and knowledge on the inter-


pretations of information can occur without awareness of the factors that
led them to become accessible in memory. This possibility is implicit in the
conceptualization we propose. That is, consciousness theoretically resides
in the Executor. The processes performed by the Comprehender, which are
not controlled by the Executor, occur without awareness. Correspondingly,
the knowledge representations that are involved in these spontaneous
comprehension processes can later be activated and applied without con-
sciousness of why they came to mind or, for that matter, without awareness
that these representations had recently been used. For similar reasons, the
representations that are later identified by the Executor for use in goal-
directed processing are unlikely to contain cognitions about the recency or
frequency with which the representations have been formed or used in the
past, as these cognitions are typically irrelevant to the objectives for which
the representations were formed. Therefore, these representations are
likely to be used as bases for judgments and decisions without considering
the reasons for their accessibility. Consequently, as studies cited in the pre-
ceding section testify, factors that fortuitously make knowledge accessible
in memory can increase the use of this knowledge. Moreover, this can oc-
cur without awareness of the factors that influence its accessibility.

Nonconscious Effects of Knowledge Accessibility

The first compelling demonstration of the nonconscious influence of con-


cepts and knowledge was reported by Bargh and Pietromonaco (1982). In
this research, participants were exposed to a computerized text of “percep-
tual vigilance” that required them to press a button as soon as a light ap-
peared on the computer screen. In actuality, the points of light were words
that were presented subliminally. In some conditions, a number of words
conveyed hostility (“hostile,” “kill,” etc.). After performing the task, partici-
pants as part of a different experiment were asked to form an impression of
a person on the basis of behaviors that were ambiguous in terms of the hos-
tility they conveyed. Participants were unable to distinguish between
words that were presented and those that were not presented in a recogni-
tion memory task after the experiment. Nevertheless, they judged the tar-
get to be more hostile if they had been subliminally exposed to hostility-
related words than if they had not.
54 CHAPTER 3

Even when people are conscious of the conditions in which knowledge


has been acquired, they may not include a specification of these conditions
in the representation of this knowledge that they store in memory. Conse-
quently, they may later retrieve and use the representation as a basis for
judgment without considering the conditions that led the knowledge to be
acquired. Two studies are interesting to view in this light. In a study by
Hasher, Goldstein, and Toppin (1977; see also Kelley & Lindsey, 1993), par-
ticipants completed a general knowledge questionnaire in which they
judged the validity of several statements about unfamiliar events and situa-
tions. Then, in a second session of the experiment, they completed a similar
questionnaire containing some of the same statements they had considered
earlier. Participants reported stronger beliefs in the validity of these state-
ments than they had in the first session. Representations of the belief state-
ments that participants had considered in the first session were apparently
stored in memory without any indication of the conditions in which they
were encountered. Consequently, these representations were retrieved
when participants encountered the statements in the second session, lead-
ing the statements to seem familiar. However, participants attributed the
statements’ familiarity to information they had received outside the labora-
tory rather than to the presence of the statements in the original question-
naire. As a result, they inferred that the statements were likely to be true.
In a conceptually similar study, Jacoby, Kelley, Brown, and Jasechko
(1989) exposed participants to a number of names of persons, some of
whom were familiar and others of whom were fictitious. Then, 24 hours
later, they were given a second list that included a subset of the fictitious
names they had seen earlier and were asked to indicate which names in the
list referred to well-known persons. Participants were more likely to mis-
identify fictitious persons as well known if they had seen their names in the
earlier list than if they had not. Thus, both this study and Hasher et al.’s re-
search suggest that knowledge that is activated in one context can later be
recalled and used as a basis for judgments without considering the reasons
that led it to be familiar.
The general tendency for representations of knowledge to be stored in
memory independently of the conditions in which the knowledge was ac-
quired has particularly important implications for the impact of daily life
experiences on perceptions of social reality. As Shrum and his colleagues
(O’Guinn & Shrum, 1997; Shrum, Wyer, & O’Guinn, 1998) have found, people
often confuse the persons and events they encounter in the real world with
those they have seen on television. Consequently, heavy television viewers
tend to overestimate the incidence of events that occur frequently in soap
operas and crime shows. We elaborate this research more fully in chapter
10 in the context of discussing the role of implicit theories on judgments
and decisions.
DETERMINANTS AND EFFECTS OF KNOWLEDGE ACCESSIBILITY 55

Effects of Awareness on Avoidance of Bias

In fact, when people are aware that the concepts they used when perform-
ing an ostensibly unrelated task might influence their interpretation of the
information they receive later, they may consciously avoid the use of
these concepts. In a study by Lombardi, Higgins, and Bargh (1987), for ex-
ample, participants were exposed to trait concepts in a priming task that
were associated with earlier (a) adventurousness and self-confidence or
(b) recklessness and conceitedness. They were then asked to report their
impressions of a person whose behaviors could exemplify both sets of
traits and, finally, were asked to recall the priming words to which they
had been exposed. Participants who could not remember the priming
words were positively influenced by them in much the same way ob-
served by Higgins et al. (1977) in the study described earlier. However,
participants who could remember the words showed a boomerang effect;
that is, they were less inclined to interpret the target’s behavior in terms
of the primed concepts than in terms of the alternatives. Similar results
were obtained by Strack, Schwarz, Bless, and Kuebler (1993) in a different
research paradigm.
Even when people are aware of the reasons why concepts and knowl-
edge come to mind, they may not always avoid using them. This avoidance
should only occur when the individuals are both motivated and able to
search for alternatives. Martin, Seta, and Crelia (1990) demonstrated these
contingencies under conditions in which trait concepts that were applica-
ble for interpreting a target’s behavior were blatantly primed. When partici-
pants were both able and motivated to search for alternative concepts to
use, boomerang effects of priming occurred; that is, participants were less
inclined to use the primed concept than they were in the absence of prim-
ing. However, when participants were distracted while performing the eval-
uation task and were less able to search for alternative concepts to apply,
primed concepts had a positive impact on judgments similar to those ob-
served by Higgins et al. (1977) and others.
A second study by Martin et al. (1990) showed that primed concepts only
had a positive influence on target judgments when participants had little in-
trinsic motivation to think about the information received (i.e., low need for
cognition; see Cacioppo & Petty, 1982) but had boomerang effects on judg-
ments by participants whose motivation (need for cognition) was high. Par-
ticularly interesting are the results of a third study in which participants
were led to believe they were forming impressions of the target person ei-
ther as individuals or as members of a group. Primed concepts had boo-
merang effects on judgments by individuals who believed they were partici-
pating as individuals. However, participants who thought they were
participating as a group engaged in “social loafing” (Harkins, Latane, & Wil-
56 CHAPTER 3

liams, 1980). That is, they used the primed concepts as a basis for interpret-
ing the information without bothering to seek alternatives.

The Effect of Thought Suppression


on Concept Accessibility

It therefore seems reasonable to conclude that when people are aware


that the concepts and knowledge that come to mind at the time they make
a judgment, they often actively avoid the biasing influence of these cog-
nitions and, in doing so, are actually less likely to use them than they might
otherwise be. However, the effects of this cognitive activity can be some-
what ironic. Suppose individuals consciously avoid the use of a concept or
knowledge representation in responding to a stimulus. This conscious sup-
pression takes cognitive effort. Moreover, it is impossible to consciously
avoid using a concept without thinking about the concept one is trying
to avoid. Consequently, active attempts to avoid using a concept can actu-
ally increase its accessibility in memory, making the concept more likely to
be used later under conditions in which attempts to suppress it are no lon-
ger made. Thus, as Wegner (1994) noted, instructing people to avoid think-
ing about a white bear may stimulate conscious thoughts about the bear,
thus making it more accessible in memory than it would have been in the
absence of this cognitive activity and, therefore, more likely to come to
mind later.4
An intriguing series of studies by Bodenhausen, Macrae, and their col-
leagues demonstrated the effects of conscious thought suppression in the
use of stereotypes (for a review, see Bodenhausen & Macrae, 1998). In a rep-
resentative set of studies (Macrae, Bodenhausen, Milne, & Jetten, 1994),
participants were given information about a skinhead with instructions to
form an impression of him. However, some participants were told not to
rely on stereotypes in arriving at their impression, whereas others were not
given this instruction. The former participants, relative to those who had
not been told to avoid using the stereotype, (a) responded more quickly to
stereotype-related words in a subsequent lexical decision task, (b) de-
scribed a second skinhead more stereotypically once the request to avoid
using stereotypes was no longer imposed, and (c) sat further away from a
skinhead while waiting to participate in a later part of the experiment. Thus,

4
4 A game we used to play as children anticipated Wegner’s insight. That is, we would tell
naïve playmates to try not to think of a white horse and then, after ensuring that they were doing
so, would ask them to report the direction in which the horse was facing. They invariably found
this question quite meaningful and responded to it quickly. Attempts to suppress thoughts
about the horse typically elicited an image of the horse that individuals found easy to describe
despite their assurances that they were trying not to think about it.
DETERMINANTS AND EFFECTS OF KNOWLEDGE ACCESSIBILITY 57

the attempt to suppress the use of the stereotype in the initial task in-
creased rather than decreased the accessibility of concepts associated with
the stereotype. Consequently, it increased the use of the stereotype as a ba-
sis for judgments and behavioral decisions in situations in which the sanc-
tions against using it were removed.

EFFECTS OF KNOWLEDGE ACCESSIBILITY


AT DIFFERENT STAGES OF PROCESSING

The retrieval processes implied by Postulates 2.1 through 2.5 apply at all
stages of cognitive activity, from the initial interpretation of information to
the generation of an overt response. The role of knowledge accessibility in
these processes is central to our discussion throughout this volume, being
particularly evident in conceptualizing the impact of generalized represen-
tations on memory for exemplars (chap. 5), the role of implicit theories in
explanation and prediction (chap. 10), and the impact of affective reactions
on judgments and decisions (chap. 11). In anticipation of this discussion, a
brief review of the effects of knowledge accessibility at different stages of
processing may be helpful. This review is not intended to be exhaustive (for
more extensive reviews, see Bargh, 1997; Higgins, 1996). Instead, we provide
representative examples of the effects that occur, several of which raise
considerations that become important in our later discussion.

Input Processes: Selective Attention


and the Activation of Bipolar Concepts

As Bargh and Pietromonaco’s (1982) findings indicate (see also Srull &
Wyer, 1979, 1980), information that is ambiguous in terms of its implications
for a given attribute (e.g., hostility) is more likely to be interpreted as exem-
plifying this attribute when concepts associated with this attribute are eas-
ily accessible in memory than when they are not. However, many attribute
concepts are bipolar (hot vs. cold, hostile vs. kind, etc.). Moreover, these
concepts may become associatively linked in memory by virtue of having
been thought about in relation to one another. If this is so, exposure to one
bipolar concept (e.g., “honest”) is likely to activate the other (“dishonest”)
as well and, therefore, to increase the likelihood that the latter concept is
used to interpret information to which it applies.
To see the implications of this, suppose two pairs of bipolar concepts,
“honest/dishonest” and “kind/unkind,” are associatively linked as shown in
Fig. 3.1. Suppose further that the behavior, “refuses to give an answer to a
friend during an exam” is associatively linked to both “honest” and “un-
58 CHAPTER 3

FIG. 3.1. Hypothetical associative network showing the relations among be-
haviors, bipolar trait concepts (honest, dishonest, kind, and unkind), and the
priming stimuli that activate these concepts (Ph, Pd, Pk, and Pu, respectively).

kind.” Then, priming “honest” should increase the likelihood of interpreting


the behavior as “honest,” whereas priming “unkind” should increase the
likelihood of interpreting it as “unkind.” However, because “dishonest” and
“kind” are associatively linked to “honest” and “unkind,” respectively, prim-
ing these concepts should have similar effects. In other words, priming
either bipolar concept along a trait dimension should increase the likeli-
hood of using a value along this dimension to interpret information to
which the dimension is relevant.
Park, Yoon, Kim, and Wyer (2001) confirmed these hypotheses. In one ex-
periment (Park et al., 2001, Experiment 1), participants performed a scram-
bled sentence task that required the use of one of four concepts: kind (e.g.,
“offered carry to help elder and luggage”), unkind (“refused carry to help el-
der and luggage”), honest (e.g., “homework to copy refused another’s”) or
dishonest (e.g., “homework to copy tried another’s”). Later, they read a
story containing descriptions of a target person’s behavior that could be in-
terpreted as both honest and unkind (“told a girlfriend that her new hair
style looked terrible,” “insisted that a friend leave his address on a car he
had barely scratched,” etc.). Participants read the behaviors and then both
described the target in their own words and, after doing so, evaluated the
person.
The proportions of participants who used the trait exemplified by the be-
havior (i.e., either honest or unkind) to describe the target are shown in Ta-
ble 3.1 as a function of priming conditions. When primed concept was di-
rectly applicable for interpreting the target’s behavior, participants were
more likely to use this concept (pooled over the two relevant priming con-
ditions, M = .294) than to use the equally applicable but unprimed concept
DETERMINANTS AND EFFECTS OF KNOWLEDGE ACCESSIBILITY 59

TABLE 3.1
The Proportion of Times the Target Was Described
as Honest and Unkind as a Function of Priming Conditions

Primed Concept Primed Concept


Applicable for Inapplicable for
Describing Target Describing Target

Honest Unkind Dishonest Kind

Proportion of times the


target was described as
Honest .280 .115 .407 .231
Unkind .160 .308 .074 .231

Note. Based on data from Park et al. (2001).

(M = .137). However, this was also true when the bipolar opposite (inappli-
cable) concepts were primed (.315 vs. .152, respectively).5
Finally, these interpretations influenced participants’ overall evalua-
tions of the target. That is, participants evaluated the target more favor-
ably when they had been primed with a trait pertaining to hostility (M =
4.55) than when they had been primed with a trait pertaining to kindness (M
= 3.76), and this was true regardless of whether the primed trait was di-
rectly applicable for interpreting the behavior (4.08 vs. 3.58 when “honest”
and “unkind” were primed, respectively) or when the bipolar opposites
were primed (5.02 vs. 3.94, when “dishonest” and “kind” were primed, re-
spectively).
The behavioral information that participants received in the preceding
study pertained to two different dimensions, but its implications along each
dimension were very clear. An additional experiment (Park et al., 2001, Ex-
periment 2) showed that when the implications of information along a di-
mension are ambiguous, activating concepts can influence not only the di-
mension along which the information is evaluated but also the value it is
assigned along this dimension. In this study, participants first performed a
task that required the use of concepts associated with either “good health,”
“bad health,” “good taste,” or “bad taste.” Later, they were given the de-
scription of a milk product as having “more artificial sweeteners.” Although
this description clearly implied that the product was bad for the health, its
implications for tastiness were ambiguous. That is, it could imply that the

5
5 This latter effect appears more pronounced when “dishonest” was primed than when “kind”
was primed. However, this difference results from a more general tendency to judge the target
as honest rather than as unkind, which inflates the effect of priming “dishonest” but decreases
the effect of priming “kind.” Pooling over the two trait replications, the overall effect of priming
was similar in magnitude regardless of whether the primed concept was applicable for describ-
ing the target or its bipolar opposite.
60 CHAPTER 3

product was either good tasting (sweet) or bad tasting (too sweet). Partici-
pants who had been exposed to health-related concepts described the
product as unhealthy regardless of whether “good health” or “bad health”
was primed. In contrast, participants who were exposed to taste-related
concepts described it as having either good taste or bad taste, depending
on which taste-related concept had been activated. Thus, primed concepts
influenced not only the dimension along which the information was inter-
preted but also the value it was assigned along this dimension.

Inference Processes: Belief Formation and Change

People who are asked to report their belief that a statement concerning it is
true are unlikely to search memory for all of the belief-related knowledge
they have acquired. Rather, they are apt to rely on the first belief-relevant
knowledge that comes to mind (Postulate 3.1). That is, they search memory
for a possible reason why the statement might or might not be true and, if
they find such a reason, use its implications as a basis for their judgment
without further ado. To this extent, the reason they identify and, therefore,
the belief they report, may depend on the recency with which the reason
had been thought about. We discuss this possibility in more detail in chap-
ter 10 of this volume. However, two examples are worth mentioning in the
present context.
Participants in a study by Henninger and Wyer (1976) were asked to re-
port their beliefs in a series of propositions. Some propositions were syllo-
gistically related. That is, one, “informational” proposition, A (e.g., “The
army is recruiting people of below average intelligence”), had implications
for the validity of a second, target proposition, B (e.g., “The quality of the
peace-time army is deteriorating”). In some cases, beliefs in the informa-
tional proposition were reported early in the questionnaire, and the target
proposition was not considered until later. In other conditions, the target
proposition was considered at the outset. Participants’ use of their belief in
the informational proposition as a basis for inferring the validity of the tar-
get was inferred on the basis of a quantitative model of syllogistic inference
proposed by Wyer and Goldberg (1970; see also McGuire, 1960, 1981).6 Par-

6
6 If beliefs are defined in units of probability (along a scale from 0 to 1), the model asserts that

P(B) = P(A)*P(B/A) + P(~A)*P(B/~A)

Where, P(B) is the belief that Proposition B is true, P(A) and P(~A) are the beliefs that A is and is
not true, and P(B/A) and P(B/~A) are beliefs that B is true if A is and is not true, respectively.
This model provides an accurate quantitative description of the relations among these beliefs,
and also the effect of changing beliefs in A on beliefs in B (Wyer, 1970, 1974; for summaries of evi-
dence, see Wyer, 1974; Wyer & Hartwick, 1980). The implications of this model are discussed
more fully in chapter 10.
DETERMINANTS AND EFFECTS OF KNOWLEDGE ACCESSIBILITY 61

ticipants based their beliefs in the target on their beliefs in the informa-
tional proposition when they had evaluated this proposition earlier in the
questionnaire. When they evaluated the target proposition at the outset,
however, they typically identified a different subset of previously acquired
knowledge to use as a basis for reporting their belief, and so this belief was
inconsistent with their belief in the informational proposition they consid-
ered subsequently.
Interestingly, when participants reported their beliefs again a week later,
their beliefs in the target were consistent with their beliefs in the informa-
tional proposition in both order conditions. Apparently, the informational
proposition, having been reported in Session 1, was accessible to both
groups of participants in Session 2, and so both groups of participants used
it as a basis for inferring the validity of the target.
This interpretation obviously assumes that no other relevant informa-
tion bearing on the validity of the target was received or thought about dur-
ing the 1-week interval between sessions. The target propositions pertained
issues that participants were unlikely to think about spontaneously, and so
this assumption seems reasonable. In an unpublished study by Wyer and
Hartwick (see Wyer & Srull, 1989), however, some participants were asked
to report their beliefs that drinking coffee was desirable after having been
exposed to a proposition that either implied that this was true (“Coffee
keeps you alert”) or implied that it was false (“Caffeine destroys nerve
cells”). Others were asked to report their beliefs that student use of the uni-
versity health center would increase after exposure to a proposition sug-
gesting that the event was likely to occur (“Dental services are scheduled to
be provided at the health center”) or unlikely (“Some doctors at the health
center are about to lose their licenses”). In both cases, participants based
their beliefs in the target proposition on the implications of the particular
information proposition to which they had been exposed. However,
whereas the effects of informational propositions on participants’ beliefs
about the use of the health center were still evident in a second experimen-
tal session 1 week later, their effects on beliefs in the desirability of drinking
coffee were not. The reason for this difference is rather obvious. That is,
participants in the 1-week interval between experimental sessions were
likely to have numerous coffee-drinking experiences with implications for
the desirability of this activity, and these more salient implications over-
rode the effects of the knowledge they had selectively activated and used in
the first experimental session. In contrast, participants had few if any expe-
riences with implications for the use of the health center during the 1-week
interim, and so the knowledge they had activated in the first session contin-
ued to have an impact.
The studies described in this section demonstrate the effects of activat-
ing prior knowledge about an issue on beliefs and opinions. However, this is
62 CHAPTER 3

not the only type of knowledge that people bring to bear on these judg-
ments. An equally important source of information is provided by one’s
own past behavior toward the persons and objects to which the issue per-
tains. Bem (1972), for example, noted that people often use their past be-
havior (e.g., a decision to advocate a position publicly) to infer their belief
that the position is valid (see also Albarracin & Wyer, 2000). These effects
are likely to be mediated by an implicit theory that people have acquired
about the causal relatedness of their beliefs and their behavior under the
particular situational conditions at hand. We explore this possibility more
fully in chapter 10.

Response Processes: The Use of Activated Concepts


as Standards of Comparison

The effects of accessible concepts on the interpretation of information typi-


cally occur at the time the information is first received. At the time a judg-
ment is made, the same concepts can have other effects. In particular, judg-
ments are typically made with reference to a standard of comparison.
Moreover, these standards may be applied spontaneously, without aware-
ness. Thus, we may judge a baby to be “big” and a house to be “small” with-
out feeling any inconsistency in these judgments at all.
The effects of knowledge on standards of comparison can sometimes off-
set or override the effects that occur at the comprehension stage. A study
by Herr (1986) is of interest in this context. Participants were initially ex-
posed to the names of persons who were known to be either moderately
hostile (e.g., Muhammad Ali or Howard Stern) or extremely hostile (e.g.,
Adolf Hitler or Genghis Khan). Later, they were asked to form impressions
of a person whose behaviors were ambiguous with respect to this trait. It
seems reasonable to suppose that the priming stimuli employed in this
study had two effects. First, they activated trait concepts that were associ-
ated with the individuals being primed, leading participants to interpret the
target’s behaviors in terms of these concepts. At the same time, they acti-
vated concepts of the individuals themselves that participants later used as
standards of comparison in evaluating the target. These effects could po-
tentially offset one another.
Herr’s results were consistent with this possibility. Participants who
were exposed to moderate exemplars of hostility judged the target as more
hostile than participants in a control condition, confirming the findings ob-
tained by Srull and Wyer (1979) and by Bargh and Pietromonaco (1982).
However, participants who were exposed to extreme exemplars judged the
target to be less hostile than control participants did. The exemplars to
which participants were exposed may have been used as standards of com-
parison in both conditions. When the exemplars were only moderately ex-
DETERMINANTS AND EFFECTS OF KNOWLEDGE ACCESSIBILITY 63

treme, however, the effect of using them as standards was not sufficient to
override the effect of the activated trait concepts on interpretation of the
information at the time it was received. When the exemplars provided a
more extreme standard of comparison, the effect of using them in this ca-
pacity predominated, producing a contrast effect. In this regard, standards
of comparison for evaluating a person are generally less likely to be acti-
vated by trait concepts per se than by the exposure to persons who pos-
sess the traits. Thus, as Stapel, Koomen, and van der Pligt (1997) found (see
also Moskowitz & Skurnik, 1999), contrast effects of priming are more likely
to be evident in the latter case than the former.
The activation and use of stimuli as standards of comparison can occur
without awareness. This was demonstrated in a series of studies by Adaval
and Monroe (2002). In some of their studies, participants were exposed sub-
liminally to either high or low numbers before being asked to judge a target
product whose price fell between the two sets of priming stimuli. Partici-
pants’ judgments of the target product were lower when high numbers had
been subliminally primed than when low numbers had been primed. That
is, the target was judged as less expensive, but also less desirable, in the
former condition than in the latter. Thus, priming stimuli appeared to in-
duce a disposition to use either a high or low value as a standard of com-
parison regardless of the dimension along which judgments were made.

THE EFFECTS OF PRIOR JUDGMENTS


ON SUBSEQUENT ONES

In most research on the effects of knowledge accessibility, the concepts


and knowledge that participants bring to bear on their judgments have
been activated by situational and individual differences factors that are os-
tensibly irrelevant to the judgment or decision they are called upon to
make. However, concepts and knowledge are often activated in the course
of cognitive activity that is directly relevant to the persons or objects being
judged. For example, people in the course of judging an object may retrieve
concepts and knowledge that are specifically relevant to this judgment. If
these cognitions remain accessible at the time a second judgment or deci-
sion is made, they may influence the latter response as well.
Studies described earlier can be interpreted in this light. For example,
participants in an early study by Carlston (1980) were given behaviors that
exemplified by kindness and honesty (e.g., “told his girlfriend that her new
hair style was ugly”), and were asked to judge the person with respect to
one of these traits. In the course of making this judgment, participants pre-
sumably formed a general impression of the person, based on their prior
knowledge about the sort of individual who typically possesses the trait
64 CHAPTER 3

they are asked to judge. Once this impression was formed, it may have in-
fluenced their later judgments independently of the behavioral information
they had received earlier. Thus, in our example, participants who were
asked to judge the target’s honesty judged him as honest. Having done so,
they later judged the target as more kind than they would have done if they
had not made the initial judgment.
A quite different series of studies by Thomas Mussweiler and Fritz Strack
(for a review, see Mussweiler, 2003) provide a further example of these ef-
fects and confirm assumptions underlying their interpretation. In a typical
study (Mussweiler & Strack, 2000b), participants were first asked to indicate
whether Mt. Everest was greater or less than a specific anchor value (e.g.,
“Is Mt. Everest higher or lower than feet?”). The anchor value was ei-
ther high or low. In all cases, these values were sufficiently extreme that
participants would normally consider the target to fall in between them. In
some cases, however, the values were fairly plausible (e.g., 45,000 ft. vs.
2,000 ft.), whereas in other cases, the values were totally implausible (e.g.,
300,000 ft. vs. 65 ft.). Participants after making the comparative judgment
were asked to estimate the actual height of Mt. Everest. Participants typi-
cally judged the actual height of Mt. Everest to be greater when they had
compared it to a high value than when they had compared it to a low one.
Moreover, this tendency was even greater when the anchor values were im-
plausible (115,728 ft. vs. 9,271 ft., respectively) than when they were plausi-
ble (36,106 ft. vs. 27,783 ft., respectively).
On the surface, these results appear to resemble the anchoring-and-
adjustment phenomenon identified by Tversky and Kahneman (1974). That
is, people in judging a stimulus arbitrarily identify a high or low anchor
value along the judgment dimension and then adjust upward or downward
in relation to this standard. However, they do not adjust enough, with the
result that their judgment is displaced toward the anchor they have arbi-
trarily used (for examples of this effect in social judgment, see Schwarz &
Wyer, 1985). Mussweiler and Strack (1999a) raise an alternative possibility,
however. That is, people who estimate a stimulus in relation to a standard
may activate a body of general knowledge that is consistent with it. Al-
though they may ultimately reject the anchor value as implausible, the sub-
set of knowledge and its implications, having been made accessible, is then
used as a basis for their own estimates.
To distinguish between the two alternative interpretations, Mussweiler
and Strack (1999a) asked participants after making their comparative judg-
ments to perform a lexical decision task requiring them to identify words
that were semantically associated with either high anchor values, low an-
chor values, or irrelevant. Participants were quicker to identify words that
were associated with the anchor to which they had been exposed than the
opposite anchor, confirming the assumption that exposure to the anchor in-
DETERMINANTS AND EFFECTS OF KNOWLEDGE ACCESSIBILITY 65

creased the accessibility of anchor-consistent knowledge in memory. The


anchoring-and-adjustment processes assumed by Tversky and Kahneman
(1974) would not predict this difference.
The phenomena identified by Mussweiler and Strack generalize over a
variety of content domains (Mussweiler & Strack, 1999a, 1999b, 2000b). A
particularly intriguing implication of their conceptualization surrounds the
effects of comparing oneself to a standard on self-judgments. In one study
(Mussweiler & Strack, 2000b), participants were first asked whether the
number of simple mathematical computations (e.g., 2 + 5 = ?) they could
perform in 1 minute was greater or less than either a high value (62) or a
low one (10). After doing so, they estimated the actual number they could
do and also rated their intelligence along a scale from 1 to 7. Consistent
with results of earlier studies, participants estimated that they could do
more problems when they had been exposed to the high anchor than when
they had been exposed to the low one. On the other hand, they rated their
general intelligence to be lower in the first condition.
This combination of results makes salient two different effects that stan-
dards of comparison can have. On one hand, a standard can activate a se-
lective subset of general knowledge that is consistent with it, thus biasing
the criteria that people bring to bear on their numerical estimates. At the
same time, the standard can influence the range of subjective values with
which these numerical estimates are associated, as suggested by Parducci
(1965) and Upshaw (1969), leading persons to assign lower values to these
estimates when the anchor is high than when it is low (for an analysis of
these effects and the processes underlying them, see Ostrom & Upshaw,
1968; Wyer & Srull, 1989).

DETERMINANTS AND CONSEQUENCES


OF THE ACCESSIBILITY OF GOALS AND MOTIVES

The preceding discussion focused on the accessibility of concepts and


knowledge that are used to interpret and make inferences about an exter-
nal referent. As noted in chapters 1 and 2, however, goals and motives are
also components of the cognitive system. As such, the activation of these
motives and their influence on judgments and decisions should be subject
to similar processes. People are obviously motivated by a wide variety of
general and specific goals, and the behaviors that are required to attain
these goals in any given situation may not be compatible. In this case, peo-
ple’s behavioral decisions may depend in part on which goal happens to
predominate at the time the decisions are made.
In some cases, the relative accessibility of a particular goal or motive is
likely to be activated by features of the stimuli to which the goal is relevant.
66 CHAPTER 3

Shiv and Fedorikhin (1999), for example, found that people were inclined to
choose to eat chocolate cake rather than fruit salad when they did not have
the opportunity to think about their decision, whereas the reverse was true
when they were able to deliberate. Presumably, the visual stimulus features
of the cake led hedonic goals to be activated very quickly, whereas the
competing goal of good health took more time to be activated.
In many instances, however, people may acquire more general motiva-
tional orientations that, once activated, can influence their judgments and
behavior in a variety of specific situations. Such general motivational dispo-
sitions are often activated by features of a stimulus situation to which they
are relevant. However, their accessibility can also be influenced by extrane-
ous factors that are not directly relevant to the situation at hand. Two quite
different bodies of literature provide evidence of this possibility. One con-
cerns the desire to maintain beliefs in a just world (Lerner, Miller, &
Holmes, 1976). A second surrounds the relative emphasis placed on posi-
tive versus negative consequences in making a behavioral decision (cf. Hig-
gins, 1997).

The Motivation to Believe in a Just World:


Implications for Reactions to Rape

Motivational influences on attitudes and opinions, which were called to the


attention of social psychologists by Festinger (1957), are well established.
The nature of these effects obviously depends on the particular motive in-
volved (e.g., see Arkin, Gleason, & Johnson, 1976; Baumeister & Newman,
1994; Giner-Sorolla & Chaiken, 1987; Psyzczynski & Greenberg, 1987; Zanna
& Cooper, 1976). One motivational determinant of judgments, proposed by
Lerner et al. (1976; Lerner & Miller, 1978), is the desire to believe that the
world is just. Lerner et al. assume that people have a need to maintain be-
liefs in a just world in order to reassure themselves that they (who are
righteous) will personally not fall victim to misfortune for reasons beyond
their control. One manifestation of this motivational disposition is that peo-
ple are not only disposed to believe that individuals who do something
wrong will be punished but also, that people who encounter misfortune are
responsible for their fate. In other words, individuals not only get what they
deserve but deserve what they get.
Lerner et al. (1976) provided several examples of this tendency. Walster
(1966), for example, found that people judged victims of an automobile acci-
dent more negatively if the victims had been seriously injured than if they
had not. Similarly, Lerner and Simmons (1966) found that observers of a
“learning” experiment in which a confederate was ostensibly shocked for
making errors disparaged the learner more when the shocks were severe
than when they were mild.
DETERMINANTS AND EFFECTS OF KNOWLEDGE ACCESSIBILITY 67

Beliefs in a just world are not the only possible basis for judgments and
decisions, of course. To this extent, the use of this criterion should be in-
creased by situational factors that increase the accessibility of these beliefs
and the motive to maintain them. This possibility was demonstrated by
Wyer, Bodenhausen, and Gorman (1985) in a study of the cognitive media-
tors of reactions to rape. We were interested in whether activating aggres-
sion-related concepts in one context might influence people’s reactions to
rape situations that they encountered in a different, ostensibly unrelated
context. To do so, we asked participants to engage in two ostensibly unre-
lated experiments. The first study was ostensibly concerned with the things
shown in the media that college students find objectionable. On this pre-
tense, we exposed participants to slides of 12 pictures. Nine of these pic-
tures showed objects and events that participants were unlikely to con-
sider offensive. The other three pictures varied. In one condition, these
slides showed aggressive acts of the sort that occurred frequently (e.g., po-
lice subduing a criminal, a boxing match, etc.) and, therefore, activated con-
cepts that aggression is normal and socially sanctioned. In a second condi-
tion, the pictures portrayed severely negative outcomes of aggression that
activated the concept that human beings were cruel and inhumane (e.g., a
lynching episode, a dead soldier with a hole in his head, etc.). The third,
“control” set portrayed stimuli that might be considered unpleasant but
were unrelated to aggression (e.g., deformed babies, a smoking advertise-
ment, etc.).
Participants rated each of the 12 pictures in terms of how objectionable
it was. Then, they were told that the experiment (which took about 10 min)
was over, but that because there was time remaining, we would like them to
help out another faculty member who was conducting a study in a different
room down the hall. The “new” study was introduced as an investigation of
the factors that people consider important in judging criminal cases. On
this pretense, participants were asked to read descriptions of four rape
cases, and in each case, to report several reactions. Two questions con-
cerned (a) whether the defendant should be convicted and (b) whether he
actually was convicted. Three others concerned the victim’s responsibility
for the incident (e.g., whether she provoked the rape, whether she could
have avoided it, etc.).
We assumed that the pictures presented in the first experiment would
activate concepts that participants would use to construe the implications
of the rape scenarios they encountered in the second experiment. On a pri-
ori grounds, several hypotheses seemed plausible. First, if pictures of so-
cially sanctioned acts of aggression activated concepts that aggression is
normal, they might decrease beliefs that the defendant should be con-
victed. On the other hand, if pictures of extremely negative consequences
of aggression activate concepts that people are cruel and inhumane, they
68 CHAPTER 3

might increase beliefs that the defendant should be convicted. Moreover,


they might increase sympathy for the victim, decreasing beliefs that she
was responsible for the incident.
An alternative possibility, however, is suggested by the assumption that
exposure to instances of aggression threaten people’s beliefs that the world
is just and, therefore, activate a motive to reaffirm this belief. This motive,
once activated, may influence participants’ reactions to the rape incidents
they encounter subsequently. If this is so, exposure to severe conse-
quences of aggression should increase beliefs that the defendant was pun-
ished (i.e., that he got what he deserved). However, it should also increase
beliefs that the victim was responsible for the incident (that she deserved
what she got).
Results summarized in Table 3.2 confirm the latter hypothesis. Exposure
to acts of aggression had little influence on judgments of either the defen-
dant or the victim. (If anything, they increased beliefs that the defendant
should be convicted, contrary to the assumption that these beliefs would
be mediated by perceptions that aggression was normal and socially sanc-
tioned.) Moreover, exposure to severe consequences of aggression also
had no effect on participants’ beliefs that the defendant should be con-
victed. However, exposure to these stimuli increased beliefs that the defen-
dant was convicted and, at the same time, increased beliefs that the victim
was responsible for the incident. Thus, these results are consistent with the
hypothesis that exposure to extreme consequences of aggression activated
concepts that threatened participants’ perceptions that the world is just.
Therefore, it motivated them to reaffirm these perceptions by believing not
only that the defendant got what he deserved, but also that the victim de-
served what she got.
These results could have implications for the impact of the media on
perceptions of rape and reactions to aggression more generally. The effects

TABLE 3.2
Judgments of the Defendant and Victim as a Function
of Concepts Activated by Priming Stimuli

Priming Stimuli

Socially Severe
Sanctioned Outcomes of
Control Aggressive Acts Aggression

Belief that defendant should be convicted 8.97 9.62 8.70


Belief that defendant was convicted 3.95 3.47 5.10
Belief that victim was responsible 2.97 3.07 4.20

Note. Judgments are reported along a scale from 0 (not at all likely) to 10 (very likely). Based
on data from Wyer, Bodenhausen, and Gorman (1985).
DETERMINANTS AND EFFECTS OF KNOWLEDGE ACCESSIBILITY 69

of situationally primed concepts on judgments are often of short duration


(but see Srull & Wyer, 1979, for evidence of priming effects over a period of
24 hours). However, the effects of frequent exposure to stimuli on concept
accessibility are much more enduring (Higgins, 1996; Higgins, Bargh, &
Lombardi, 1985). It therefore seems reasonable to assume that frequent ex-
posure to extreme violence could induce a chronic tendency to maintain
beliefs in a just world that is manifested in a variety of contexts. To this ex-
tent, it could have effects similar to those that Wyer, Bodenhausen, and
Gorman (1985) observed.

The Motivation to Avoid Negative Outcomes

People who are confronted with a decision are likely to base their judg-
ments on their perception of its possible consequences. In doing so, they
might potentially consider both the positive consequences that might re-
sult from their decision and the negative consequences it could have. How-
ever, both individual and situational differences may exist in the relative
emphasis that people place on these consequences.
This possibility is recognized by Higgins’ (1997) conceptualization of reg-
ulatory focus. Higgins postulates that individuals can have either a promo-
tion focus (which is manifested by a concern with positive consequences of
one’s behavior) or a prevention focus (characterized by a concern with
avoiding negative decision outcomes). These motivational orientations may
reflect general dispositions that, once activated, generalize over situations.
Although chronic individual differences can exist in these orientations,
their relative influence can also be determined by situational factors that in-
fluence their relative accessibility.

1. Chronic Differences in Promotion


Versus Prevention Focus
Chronic differences in the motivation to attain positive outcomes or
avoid negative ones are suggested in a study by Briley, Morris, and
Simonson (2000). At the same time, these motives may not be activated
spontaneously. Briley et al. speculated that European Americans were dis-
posed to be promotion focused, whereas Asians were more inclined to be
prevention focused. To examine this possibility, representatives of both
cultural groups were asked to choose between (a) an alternative with a
very favorable value along one dimension (A) and a very unfavorable value
along a second dimension (B), (b) an alternative with a very unfavorable
value along A and a very favorable value along B, and (c) an alternative
with moderate values along both dimensions. Thus, the first two alterna-
tives had both more favorable and more unfavorable features than the
third, “compromise” alternative. Briley et al. reasoned that participants
70 CHAPTER 3

who were primarily motivated by the desire to attain positive outcomes


would prefer either of the first two alternatives to the third. However, indi-
viduals who were motivated to avoid negative outcomes would prefer the
compromise alternative. They found that when participants were asked to
make decisions without having to justify their choices, cultural differences
in these choices did not emerge. However, asking European Americans to
give a reason for their decision increased their preferences for the alterna-
tives with extremely favorable values, whereas asking Asians to give a rea-
son increased their preferences for the compromise alternative. Thus,
chronic cultural differences in promotion and prevention focus appear to
exist. However, these differences are only evident if participants are stimu-
lated to think about the basis for their decisions.

2. Situational Influences on Promotion


Versus Prevention Focus

Feelings of Membership in an Ad Hoc Group. Situational factors that


induce concerns about avoidance of negative consequences can override
chronic differences in this tendency. A series of studies conducted by
Donnel Briley (Briley & Wyer, 2002) investigated this possibility and, in do-
ing so, confirmed the generalizeability of the motivational orientations that
Higgins postulates. Aaker and Lee (2001) found evidence that stimulating
people to think of themselves as part of a group increases their focus to
negative features of a situation relative to positive ones. Based on these
findings, we assumed that stimulating people to feel part of a group would
induce a prevention focus, the effects of which would generalize over a vari-
ety of decision situations.
In two studies, participants’ feelings of group membership were induced
by having them ostensibly participate in either a group or an individual
achievement task. After doing so, participants in Experiment 1 reported
their agreement with implications of a number of proverbs, some of which
emphasized the desirability of balance and equality (e.g., “it takes two to
make a quarrel,” “when the shoulder pole is not secure at both ends, the
load will slip off,” “the pole is easy to carry if the load is balanced,” etc.).
(For evidence that responses in this task are correlated with preferences
for equality in actual decision situations, see Briley et al., 2000; Weber, Hsee,
& Sokolowska, 1998.) We expected that participants with a prevention focus
would prefer situations that minimized the likelihood that one individual
would receive negative outcomes at others’ expense, and, therefore, would
be more likely to endorse proverbs that advocated outcome equality than
would participants without this orientation. This was in fact the case, as
shown in the first column of Table 3.3 (top); people reported stronger
DETERMINANTS AND EFFECTS OF KNOWLEDGE ACCESSIBILITY 71

TABLE 3.3
Mean Evaluations of Equality-Oriented Proverbs, and Proportion
of Participants Who Chose Candies of Different Types, as a Function
of Participating as Individuals or in a Group and Regulatory Focus

No Instructions Promotion Prevention


(Experiments Focus Focus
1 and 2) (Experiment 3) (Experiment 3)

Endorsement of equality-oriented
proverbs
Individual participation 5.07 5.08 5.49
Group participation 5.60 5.07 5.60
M 5.34 5.07 5.55
Proportion of participants choos-
ing candy of different types
Individual participation .45 .50 .59
Group participation .73 .55 .81
M .61 .43 .71

Note. Based on data from Briley and Wyer (2002).

agreement with these proverbs when they had participated as part of a


group than when they had taken part as individuals.
In Experiment 2, participants after performing the group task were dis-
missed. Upon leaving the experiment, however, they were given the oppor-
tunity to take two candies as an additional reward for participating. Two
types of attractive candy were available, and so participants could choose
either two candies of the same type or one candy of each type. We ex-
pected that individuals with a desire to avoid negative consequences of
their choice would be inclined to choose one candy of each type, thereby
minimizing the risk of experiencing postdecisional regret if their momen-
tary preference for the two types of candy happened to change. Consistent
with this reasoning, participants were more likely to choose candies of dif-
ferent types after participating in the experiment as members of a group
(.73) than after participating as individuals (.45).
To confirm the assumption that the effects of group membership on be-
havior in these studies were mediated by its impact on prevention focus,
we conduced an additional experiment in which this focus was manipulated
more directly (Briley & Wyer, 2002, Experiment 3). This study was virtually
identical to the first two experiments except that participants were told ei-
ther that (a) the individual/group who performed best on the achievement
test would receive a monetary reward (promotion-focus conditions) or, alter-
natively, (b) individuals/groups would receive a reward except for those
who did poorer than average (prevention-focus conditions). Proverb en-
dorsement and candy choices under these two conditions are shown in the
last two columns of Table 3.3. Participants were more inclined to endorse
72 CHAPTER 3

equality-related proverbs, and also more likely to choose candies of differ-


ent types, under prevention-focus conditions than under promotion-focus
conditions.
Note also that under promotion-focus conditions, proverb endorsement
and candy choice were each very similar to that observed under individual-
participation conditions of Experiments 1 and 2, whereas under prevention-
focus conditions, they were similar in magnitude to that observed under
group-participation conditions of the first two experiments. Thus, these
data provide strong confirmation of the assumption that inducing feelings
of group membership activated a prevention focus, and therefore had the
same impact as a more direct manipulation of this motivational orientation.

Feelings of Cultural Identity. A second series of studies (Briley & Wyer,


2002, Experiments 5 and 6) confirmed these conclusions using a quite differ-
ent means of inducing feelings of group membership, and also different in-
dices of prevention focus. Specifically, participants were both European
American and Hong Kong Chinese college students whose feelings of group
membership were activated by making them aware of their cultural iden-
tity. This was done by exposing representatives of each culture to symbols
of their own or a different culture as part of an ostensibly unrelated test of
general knowledge. (Specifically, European Americans were exposed to pic-
tures of Marilyn Monroe, a Dixieland jazz band, the American flag, etc. Chi-
nese were exposed to pictures of the Great Wall, a Chinese musical instru-
ment, people doing calligraphy, etc.).
Following this task, some participants were asked to state their prefer-
ences for different combinations of outcomes to themselves and another
in a hypothetical resource allocation task. Others were administered the
product choice task employed by Briley et al. (2000) and described earlier.
Exposing participants to symbols of their own culture not only increased
their preferences for equality in the resource allocation task but also in-
creased their likelihood of choosing the compromise alternative in the
product choice task, and this was true of both European Americans and
Hong Kong Chinese. Thus, making participants aware of their cultural
identity activated a disposition to avoid negative outcomes that overrode
the chronic cultural differences in prevention focus that Briley et al. (2000)
observed.

THE ACTIVATION OF BEHAVIORAL DISPOSITIONS

Behavior that results from promotion and prevention focus is likely to be


mediated by conscious decisions to seek positive outcomes or avoid nega-
tive ones. In some cases, however, behavior may be mediated by “produc-
DETERMINANTS AND EFFECTS OF KNOWLEDGE ACCESSIBILITY 73

tions” of the sort postulated by Anderson (1983) and described in chapter 1,


which are activated and applied spontaneously, with a minimum of con-
scious deliberation. These productions, like declarative knowledge repre-
sentations, could depend on their accessibility in memory at the time.
A series of studies by Bargh and his colleagues are particularly intrigu-
ing. In one study (Bargh, Chen, & Burrows, 1996, Experiment 1), participants
completed a sentence construction task that required the use of concepts
associated with either politeness or rudeness. Upon completing the task in
the experimenter’s absence, they went to another room to turn in their
work. Upon arriving, however, they found the experimenter engaged in a
discussion with a graduate student. The time that participants waited
before they interrupted the conversation was recorded. Participants inter-
rupted more quickly if they had previously been primed with rudeness-
related concepts than if they had been primed with politeness-related con-
cepts. On the other hand, participants’ post-experiment judgments of the
experimenter’s own rudeness was not influenced by the priming manipula-
tion. Thus, the primed concepts appeared to influence participants’ behav-
ior independently of their interpretation of the experimenter’s actions.

Effects of Stereotype Activation on Own Behavior

Two additional studies by Bargh et al. (1996) demonstrated that the activa-
tion of stereotypes can induce stereotype-consistent behavior, and that this
is true even when individuals are not themselves members of the stereo-
typed group. In a particularly provocative study (Bargh et al., 1996, Experi-
ment 2), participants completed a similar sentence construction that in this
case required the use of concepts associated with the elderly (“aged,”
“bingo,” etc.). After completing the task, participants were dismissed from
the experiment, and the time they took to walk to the elevator was re-
corded. Participants who were primed with elderly related concepts walked
more slowly to the elevator than control participants. This was true even
though the participants themselves were not elderly but rather were col-
lege students.
Participants in a third study (Bargh et al., 1996, Experiment 3) were sub-
liminally exposed to pictures of either African-American or European-
American faces while they performed a tedious perceptual task on the
computer. Upon completing the task, however, they were told that the
computer had malfunctioned and they would have to perform the task a
second time. Participants’ nonverbal behavior (facial expressions, etc.)
were recorded and coded for manifestations of irritation and hostility.
Participants manifested significantly more hostility when they had been
exposed to African-American faces than when they had been exposed to
European-Americans.
74 CHAPTER 3

Qualifications and Extensions

Bargh et al.’s studies combine to suggest that unobtrusively exposing par-


ticipants to stimuli can activate sequences of behavior under conditions in
which they are minimally aware of either the priming stimuli or the behav-
ior itself. Moreover, these effects are not mediated by their effects on prim-
ing on the interpretation of the situation or the person toward whom the
behavior is directed. To this extent, they are consistent with the assump-
tion that features of the priming stimuli activated a production that elicited
a behavioral sequence automatically, with minimum awareness of the con-
ditions that gave rise to it. It should be noted, however, that the priming
stimuli may not by themselves be sufficient to activate the production. That
is, the eliciting conditions of a production are likely to include features of
the situation as well. It seems unlikely that people who are primed with
rudeness-related concepts in Bargh et al.’s first experiment would have
been rude if the experimenter’s own behavior had not provoked it. Nor
would the exposure to African-American faces activate hostile behavior in
the absence of situational conditions in which the behavior was potentially
appropriate. Rather, both primed features and situational features in com-
bination may be necessary to form the eliciting conditions for a production.
In fact, the same primed features might elicit quite different behavior, de-
pending on the situational features that accompany them.
This possibility is made salient in a series of studies by Stanley
Colcombe (Colcombe & Wyer, 2001). In some conditions of this study, Cau-
casian participants were first subliminally primed with either African Amer-
ican, Asian, or Caucasian faces using procedures very similar to those em-
ployed by Bargh et al. (1996). Then, they completed a shortened version of
the mathematics section of the Graduate Record Examination. African
Americans are stereotyped as unmotivated to perform well in intellectual
activity, whereas Asians are stereotyped as highly motivated to achieve. To
this extent, priming African-American faces should decrease White partici-
pants’ attempts to perform well on the mathematics test, whereas priming
Asian faces should increase the effort they expend. Results shown in the
first column of Table 3.4 confirm this hypothesis. That is, participants at-
tained lower scores on the test when African-American faces had been
primed, and higher scores when Asian faces had been primed, than they
achieved when White faces had been primed.
The fact that the effects of priming stimuli on participants’ behavior oc-
curred without awareness was made salient by additional conditions in
which the priming stimuli were presented above awareness threshold. (To
justify this, participants were told that the perceptual task had been used in
another, unrelated experiment and that we had been unable to modify the
program to eliminate the stimuli from being shown.) As shown in the right-
hand column of Table 3.4, participants under these conditions performed
DETERMINANTS AND EFFECTS OF KNOWLEDGE ACCESSIBILITY 75

TABLE 3.4
Mathematics Test Performance as a Function
of Priming Stimulus and Prime Type

Subliminal Prime Overt Prime

African American faces 420 502


Caucasian faces (control) 452 446
Asian faces 512 524

Note. Scores are converted to percentiles based on GRE norms. Adapted from Colcombe and
Wyer (2001).

better when they had been exposed to either African-American or Asian


faces than under control conditions. In these conditions, participants who
were exposed to African-American faces apparently worked hard in order to
distance themselves from this stereotypically low achieving group, whereas
those who were exposed to Asian faces were stimulated to work hard in or-
der to emulate this stereotypically high achieving group. Thus, participants
performed better in both conditions, albeit for different reasons.
The effects observed under subliminal priming conditions require fur-
ther consideration, however. It is not completely clear why activating a
stereotype would have a positive influence on the behavior of individuals
to whom the stereotype does not apply. A conceptualization by Prinz (1990)
suggests one possible explanation. He postulated that in order to compre-
hend another person’s behavior, one must often imagine oneself perform-
ing it. This mental simulation could establish an association between a rep-
resentation of others’ behavior and a representation of one’s own. As a
result of this association, factors that activate concepts of another’s behav-
ior might activate a representation of one’s own behavior in similar situa-
tions, producing the effects that both Bargh et al. (1996) and Colcombe and
Wyer (2001) observed.

CONCLUDING REMARKS

As the research in this chapter testifies, cognitive responses to situations


are determined to a large extent by the subset of concepts and knowledge
that happen to be easily accessible in memory at the time the responses
are generated. The research we have described does not begin to cover the
numerous ways in which differences in knowledge accessibility can have an
impact. It nevertheless suffices to indicate the importance of taking these
differences into account in conceptualizing information processing of the
sort we discuss in the chapters that follow. This becomes immediately im-
portant in the next section, where we analyze the comprehension of social
information of the sort we acquire through direct experience.
P A R T

II
COMPREHENSION PROCESSES
C H A P T E R

4
The Comprehension and
Validation of Information
About Familiar People and Events:
The Role of Situation Models

The comprehension of an event can occur in two stages. The first stage is
spontaneous and automatic, and occurs whenever the event can be easily
understood in terms of concepts and knowledge that comes easily to mind
at the time. It is difficult to observe a boy pounding a nail into a piece of
wood, or to see a book lying on a table, without comprehending this experi-
ence. It is equally difficult to read descriptions of these events without com-
prehending them. For example, try not to understand “The boy pounded a
nail into a piece of wood,” or “the book is on the table.” For a native English
speaker, the comprehension of such statements is spontaneous and virtu-
ally uncontrollable.
In many cases, however, comprehension requires deliberative cognitive
activity. Just as we comprehend some verbal statements spontaneously, we
immediately recognize that others cannot be easily understood. For exam-
ple, “The nail pounded a tree into the boy” is structurally identical to “The
boy pounded a nail into a tree.” To understand the first statement, how-
ever, one must consciously construct a cartoon-like mental image of an ani-
mated nail driving the tree into a screaming juvenile. This construction is
deliberative and requires cognitive effort.
Moreover, the comprehension of some events requires an understand-
ing of other events that precede or follow them. This information is particu-
larly necessary when the event is inconsistent with a preexisting concep-
tion of the things that typically occur in the situation at hand. For example,
a nuclear physics professor might have difficulty computing a 15% tip at a
restaurant. Or, a person’s comment at a party might violate a conversa-
tional norm to be polite, informative, or truthful (Grice, 1975). These events

79
80 CHAPTER 4

are likely to stimulate conscious cognitive activity in an attempt to under-


stand why they occurred.
However, this deliberative cognitive activity is only likely to occur when
the comprehension processes that are spontaneously activated by expo-
sure to information are insufficient. Before discussing this activity and the
conditions that give rise to it, one must first understand the processes that
underlie the spontaneous comprehension of information. The present chap-
ter focuses on these processes. We first describe the mental representa-
tions that are formed in the course of comprehending events of the sort we
often encounter or read about in daily life. Then, we discuss the processes
that underlie the construction of these representations. Finally, we con-
sider the implications of our conceptualization for the spontaneous recog-
nition of statements about known persons and events as either true or
false. These latter implications are of considerable importance in under-
standing responses to information outside the laboratory, as our discussion
in later chapters testifies.

THE CONTENT AND STRUCTURE


OF SITUATION MODELS

Most social experiences are dynamic. That is, they take place over a period
of time. Such an experience can be conceptualized as a sequence of states
of affairs along with events (e.g., behaviors) that transform one state into
another. When an experience is described verbally, however, the entire se-
quence of events that occur is unlikely to be specified. For example, our ob-
servation of a boy throwing a ball necessarily includes both the action itself
and features of the situation in which it takes place. It might also include
other events that precede or follow the ball-throwing event per se (e.g., the
ball sailing through the air and being caught by another person). In con-
trast, a verbal description of the event (e.g., “The boy threw the ball”) does
not specify its antecedents or consequences. Nor for that matter, does it in-
dicate the nature of the ball, physical characteristics of the thrower, or the
situational context in which the event occurred. To infer these characteris-
tics, therefore, we must relate the verbal description to a past experience
we have had whose features match those of the description but contain
others as well. These latter features may then be added to the mental repre-
sentation we form.
The comprehension process just described essentially involves a mental
simulation of the event to which the information refers. We conceptualize
this mental simulation as a situation model. The situation model construct is
not new (Johnson-Laird, 1983, 1989). In cognitive psychology, it has been
used to conceptualize the processes that underlie language comprehension
THE ROLE OF SITUATION MODELS 81

(Johnson-Laird, 1983; Kintsch, 1998; Zwaan & Radvansky, 1998), spatial mem-
ory (Taylor & Tversky, 1992) and logical reasoning (Schaeken, Johnson-
Laird, & d’Ydewalle, 1996). Other research has examined their role in both
comprehending observed events (e.g., a movie; Magliano, Dijkstra, &
Zwaan, 1996) and imagining experiences that have not yet occurred (cf.
Glenberg, 1970; Glenberg, Kruley, & Langston, 1994; Graesser, Singer, &
Trabasso, 1994). Perhaps surprisingly, however, their role in social informa-
tion processing is not widely recognized.
The mental simulation of a situation typically requires assumptions
about the relations among the entities (persons and objects) involved in it.
These relations are most easily represented in a mental “image.” An image
is often coded visually, and thus can be likened to a “picture.”7 However, it
should not be equated with a photograph. For one thing, not all features
that are found in a photograph are likely to be mentioned. (Thus, the men-
tal image that is formed in response to the statement “the boy kicked the
ball” might specify the nature of the ball and portray the boy in the act of
kicking it, but might not include a specification of the boy’s hair color or
what he was wearing.) On the other hand, a mental image, as we conceptu-
alize it, may convey information in other modalities. Thus, a representation
of “The man shouted, ‘Get out of my way!’ ” may contain an acoustically
coded representation of the man’s tone of voice as well as the thing he said.
Two types of situation models are of particular relevance in conceptual-
izing social experiences. Event models are simulations of specific actions
and, in isolation, are similar to states of affairs. However, a number of tem-
porally and thematically related event models might be combined to form a
multiple-segment episode model that conveys the temporal and causal relat-
edness of the events as well as the events themselves.
As the preceding discussion implies, all event and episode models are
assumed to have an image component. This is true regardless of whether
the information that leads the model to be constructed is conveyed
nonverbally, orally, or in writing. When information is conveyed verbally,
the representation of it in memory is also likely to have a propositional
component that provides a linguistic description of the event or situation
being represented. To this extent, an event model might be analogous to a
“picture plus caption,” and an episode model to a mental “comic strip.”
Note, however, that although the verbal description of an event may spon-
taneously lead to the construction of a mental image in the course of com-
prehending it, an observation or a picture of the event can often be compre-

7
7 The representation of visual images in memory has been somewhat controversial (cf.
Kosslyn, 1980; Pylyshyn, 1973; Shepard & Metzler, 1971). However, we do not intend to enter into
this debate. The construct of a visual image as used in this volume, like mental representations
more generally, should be evaluated in terms of their utility as metaphors and not in terms of
their validity as depictions of the physiology of the brain.
82 CHAPTER 4

hended without recoding it linguistically. In this case, the recoding may not
normally be performed (see Postulate 3.1).
The preceding discussion can be summarized in two postulates:

Postulate 4.1. Event and episode models are mental simulations of an event,
or sequence of events, that are temporally and spatially constrained. These
models are constructed spontaneously in the course of comprehending
events that occur at a specifiable (although not necessarily specified) time
and place.

Postulate 4.2. An event model can consist of both a mental image and a lin-
guistically coded description of the event or state of affairs to which it refers.
Although the image component of the model is obligatory, the linguistic com-
ponent is optional.

A critical feature of our conceptualization is indicated in Postulate 4.1.


That is, not all of the representations that people form of social information
are situation models. Situation models are restricted to events or states of
affairs that are localized in space and time. This restriction is important. Al-
though the time and place of an event is not always specified, it must be im-
plicit. Thus, statements such as “The book is on the table,” or “The boy
kicked the ball,” refer to states and events that necessarily occurred at a
particular place and point in time. However, many verbal statements that
people encounter are not temporally or situationally constrained. For ex-
ample, “The book is interesting,” or “The boy owns a ball,” are unrestricted
as to time and place. Therefore, the comprehension of these statements
would not involve the construction of a situation model. For example, they
might be represented linguistically, but a mental image of their referents
might not be formed.
Note that although most visual images are situationally and temporally
specific, this is not necessarily the case. For example, a mental picture of an
acquaintance could contain nonverbally coded features of the person’s face
and other physical attributes but might be independent of any particular
situation in which the individual is involved. Moreover, a schematic repre-
sentation of a prototypic situation could provide expectations for the type
of events that are likely to occur without its features being verbally articu-
lated. These schematic representations can influence the spontaneous ini-
tial appraisals of a new situation that one encounters in a manner similar to
that postulated by Lazarus (1982, 1991), eliciting feelings that the situation
is benevolent or hostile without a clear understanding of why this is so.
These schematic representations, or “situation prototypes,” can also be
part of the eliciting conditions of a production of the sort noted in chapter
1, which automatically stimulate behavior under conditions in which they
are activated. Thus, people often behave quite differently in a classroom sit-
THE ROLE OF SITUATION MODELS 83

uation than at a party, and differently with friends than with casual acquain-
tances. These behavioral dispositions are activated and applied without
conscious analyses of the situational factors that give rise to them.

Headers

Episode models are often assigned a header, or title, that constitutes a gen-
eralization of the sequences of events to which the model refers and that
essentially tells what the model is about. The header of a model may be
coded propositionally. Thus, “the fiasco at Lydia’s dinner party” might be
the title of an episode model whose segments depict my stumbling into a ta-
ble and spilling a bloody Mary on a guest’s new dress, causing her to drop a
dish of guacamole on the hostess’s white shag rug. Features of a model’s
header can serve as retrieval cues for the model itself, activating the model
as a result of the processes described in chapter 2. In this regard, many
general statements that convey attitudes and opinions could be headers of
more specific episode models that exemplify them. For example, “Religious
fanaticism is dangerous” could be the header of an episode model of the
events surrounding the attack on the World Trade Center.
Not all propositions are model headers, of course. On the other hand, a
given proposition might be the header of more than one model. It is inter-
esting to speculate that the strength of one’s belief in a given proposition is
a positive function of the number of episode models for which it serves as a
header. Because episode models are constructed from specific experi-
ences, this proposition would be consistent with Fazio’s (1990) proposal
that the strength of an attitude (or opinion) is typically greater when it is
derived from personal experience than when it is not.
In this and the following chapter, we describe the construction of event
and episode models and their role in the comprehension of social informa-
tion. Before doing so, however, it will be useful to discuss more generally a
fundamental assumption that underlies the postulation of these models,
namely, that verbal event descriptions are often spontaneously encoded in
terms of mental images.

THE ROLE OF VISUAL IMAGERY IN


COMPREHENDING SOCIAL EVENTS

According to Postulates 4.1 and 4.2, verbal images are fundamental compo-
nents of situation models and, therefore, are formed spontaneously in the
course of comprehending events that are temporally and situationally con-
strained. This is true even when the events are described verbally. On the
other hand, the linguistic coding of the events that compose a situation
84 CHAPTER 4

model is optional. Therefore, this coding is not always performed in the


course of comprehending events that are conveyed visually (e.g., in terms
of pictures).

The Construction of Images in Text Comprehension

Some of the earliest and best-known indications that mental images are
constructed in the course of comprehending text were provided by John
Bransford and his colleagues (cf. Bransford, Barclay, & Franks, 1972;
Bransford & Johnson, 1972). In an early study (Bransford et al., 1972), some
participants were asked to learn sentences that on the surface appeared
anomalous (e.g., “The haystack was important because the cloth would
rip,” or “The notes were sour because the seam was split”). Not surpris-
ingly, their memory for these sentences was typically poor. In another con-
dition, however, the same sentences were each preceded by a single word
(in our examples, “parachute” and “bagpipes,” respectively). In the context
of these words, memory for the sentences improved substantially. The
most plausible explanation of these results is that the cue word stimulated
the construction of a mental image of an event or sequence of events in
which the statements made sense (e.g., an image of a parachutist landing in
a pile of hay, or a frustrated piper trying to get music out of his defective in-
strument). Although these results could perhaps be interpreted without re-
course to the assumption that mental images were formed of the events, an
explanation in terms of this assumption is the most parsimonious.
A study of recognition memory by Garnham (1981) provided circumstan-
tial evidence of a different sort. In this study, participants after being asked
to learn a number of sentences were given a recognition memory test in
which the test sentences differed slightly from those they had seen earlier.
In some cases, the events described in the two sentences presumably oc-
curred in the same situation; for example, participants were initially ex-
posed to “The hostess bought a mink coat from the furrier” but were later
asked to verify “The hostess bought a mink coat at the furrier’s.” In other
cases, however, the events described by the two sentences occurred in dif-
ferent situations; for example, “The hostess received a telegram from the
furrier” and “The hostess received a telegram at the furrier’s.” In each case,
the learning and test sentences were identical in structure. However, the
events described in the first pair of sentences presumably occurred in the
same situation and, therefore, were likely to elicit similar mental images. In
contrast, the events described in the second pair occurred in different situ-
ations and were likely to elicit quite different mental images. Therefore, if
participants constructed these images spontaneously in the course of com-
THE ROLE OF SITUATION MODELS 85

prehending the sentences, they should be more likely to confuse the first
pair of sentences than to confuse the second pair, as reflected in their rec-
ognition responses. This was in fact the case.
A study by Glenberg, Meyer, and Lindem (1987) is particularly compel-
ling. Participants read a story in which a sweatshirt either was associated
with the protagonist at the outset (“John put on his sweatshirt and went
jogging”) or was separated from him (e.g., “John took off his sweatshirt and
went jogging”). Their recognition of specific features mentioned in the pas-
sage (including “sweatshirt”) was then assessed. The time that elapsed be-
tween the mention of the feature in the story and its occurrence in the
recognition list was the same in all cases. Nevertheless, participants recog-
nized the target object more quickly in the first condition than in the sec-
ond. Participants in the first condition apparently formed a mental image of
John wearing the sweatshirt that persisted throughout the mental represen-
tation they formed of the events that occurred later, and this image was sa-
lient at the time of recognition. In the second condition, however, this was
not the case.
Finally, a study by Black, Turner, and Bower (1979) suggested that when
people form mental images on the basis of event descriptions, they con-
struct these images from a specific visual perspective. Participants read
passages describing pairs of events that were either likely to be imagined
from the same perspective (e.g., “Mary was reading a book in her room.
John came in to talk to her.”) or from different perspectives (“Mary was
reading a book in her room. John went in to talk to her.”). Participants typi-
cally took longer to read and comprehend the second type of passage than
the first. In the first case, readers presumably formed an image of Mary
from someone in the room that was maintained while comprehending the
second. In the second case, however, the second sentence stimulated a
mental image from the perspective of someone outside the room, and so
readers were required to shift their perspective in order to comprehend it
in the context of the first sentence. As a consequence, reading and compre-
hension time increased.

Differences in the Comprehension of Picture


and Text Information

Using quite different methodologies, all four studies described earlier con-
verge on the conclusion that mental images are constructed spontaneously
in the course of comprehending information about situation-specific events.
In all cases, however, the evidence is circumstantial. More direct support
for Postulate 4.2, requires a comparison of the comprehension of verbal de-
scriptions of events with comprehension of the same events when they are
86 CHAPTER 4

conveyed in pictures. Specifically, suppose participants read a verbal de-


scription of an event. If this description spontaneously stimulates a mental
image of the event, the event should later be identified just as easily on the
basis of a picture as it would be if a picture of the event had been conveyed
in the first place.
Wyer, Adaval, and Colcombe (2002) examined this possibility. In doing
so, we also evaluated the assumption that although verbal descriptions of
an event are spontaneously encoded in terms of mental images, pictures of
events are not spontaneously encoded linguistically. We constructed two
scenarios of about 14 events each. One scenario, which concerned a day at
school, described a male student getting up in the morning, getting
dressed, eating breakfast, leaving his apartment, finding that his bicycle
had a flat, walking to school, getting to class late, leaving, meeting a friend,
going to the library, and falling asleep at the table. The second, a dating sce-
nario, portrayed the student getting ready for a date, meeting the date, buy-
ing tickets for a movie, buying some popcorn, eating it while watching the
show, leaving, going to a pub, observing his date flirt with a friend, sulking
while walking home, but kissing his date goodnight at the door. Four sets of
stimuli were constructed for each scenario, two composed of “pictures”
and two composed of “captions.” The two “picture” scenarios were com-
posed of photographs of the events, with one set taken from different per-
spectives than the other. The two “caption” scenarios were also con-
structed composed of verbal descriptions that were similar in meaning but
different in wording (e.g., “discovered his bicycle tire was flat” vs. “saw that
his bike had a flat tire”).
Participants were shown the events composing one of the two scenarios
on a computer screen with instructions that we were interested in how peo-
ple comprehend everyday life events. This was done in three conditions. In
picture-only conditions, only pictures of the events were presented. In cap-
tion-only conditions, only verbal descriptions of the event were conveyed,
and in a third, picture-plus-caption condition, both pictures and verbal de-
scriptions were shown.
After receiving the event descriptions and a short delay, participants
were presented stimuli portraying a number of events with instructions to
decide whether the event had occurred in the sequence they had seen
earlier. Some of the events were described verbally and others were de-
scribed in pictures. Moreover, some stimuli referred to the same events
that occurred in the original scenario but were from a different perspec-
tive (in the case of photographs) or were worded differently (in the case
of verbal descriptions). Other stimuli, however, described different events
entirely. Participants were told that the stimuli they would see would not
be identical to those they had seen earlier, and to base their judgments on
whether the stimulus event was “similar in meaning” to the one they had
THE ROLE OF SITUATION MODELS 87

seen earlier. In each case, the time that participants took to judge the
stimuli was recorded.

1. Results
Participants under all conditions presumably formed a multiple-seg-
ment episode model on the basis of the events they encountered regard-
less of the modality in which they were conveyed. According to Postulate
4.2, however, participants who received written descriptions of the events
should spontaneously form mental images of them and, therefore, should
have these images in memory at the time of judgment. Therefore, they
should later be able to identify pictures of the events as easily as they
would if pictures of the events had been presented in the first place. Data
shown in the top half of Table 4.1 support this hypothesis. That is, when
participants were asked to verify an event on the basis of a picture, they
responded just as quickly if the event had been described verbally (M =
1.90 s) as they did if the event had been portrayed in a similar but not
identical picture (M = 1.97 s).
However, Postulate 4.2 also implies that people do not spontaneously
code pictures verbally when these codings are not necessary to compre-
hend the events they portray. If this is the case, however, participants who
are later asked to verify an event on the basis of a verbal description of it
must recode the picture linguistically at the time of judgment in order to
perform the verification. This recoding presumably takes time. Conse-
quently, participants should take longer to verify the event than they would
if a verbal description had initially been presented. This was also the case,
as Table 4.1 indicates. That is, when participants were told to identify an
event on the basis of a verbal description of it, they took longer to do so
when the event had initially been conveyed in a picture (M = 2.53 s) than
when it had been described in words (M = 1.71 s).
TABLE 4.1
Mean Time to Verify Pictures and Captions as a Function of Presentation
Order and the Type of Information Initially Presented

Picture Plus
Verbal Verbal
Picture Description Description

Narrative order
Response time to pictures 1.97 (19) 1.90 (14) 2.05 (20)
Response time to verbal descriptions 2.53 1.71 1.96
Scrambled order
Response time to pictures 2.16 (19) 2.50 (18) 1.91 (16)
Response time to verbal descriptions 2.26 2.23 2.09

Note. Adapted from Wyer et al. (2002).


88 CHAPTER 4

2. A Qualification

The results just described are quite consistent with Postulate 4.2. There
are nevertheless some qualifications on the validity of this postulate. In
other conditions of Wyer et al.’s study, the events were presented in scram-
bled order rather than in the order they occurred. In this condition, partici-
pants could not spontaneously form a multiple-segment episode model of
the sequence as a whole. Rather, comprehension of this sequence required
deliberative cognitive activity. Results shown in the bottom half of Table 4.1
indicate that in this condition, participants could verify an event on the ba-
sis of a verbal description of it just as quickly when the event had originally
been conveyed in a picture (M = 2.26 s) as when the event had been de-
scribed verbally in the first place (M = 2.23 s). However, they took longer to
verify an event on the basis of a picture when the event had been described
verbally (M = 2.50 s) than when it had been described pictorially (M = 2.16).
Although this pattern of response times was unexpected, it has a plausible
explanation. Verbal symbols are easier to manipulate mentally than visual
images are. Consequently, participants who received pictures of the events
in scrambled order may have subjectively translated them into linguistic
terms in order to construct a mental representation of the sequence of
events as a whole. As a result, they could later verify a verbal description of
the events just as easily as participants who had been given verbal descrip-
tions of the events in the first place. When participants received verbal de-
scriptions of the events in scrambled order, however, they relied on linguis-
tic codings alone to construct a representation of the sequence without
including visual images in this representation. Therefore, when they were
later asked to verify a picture, they were required to recode it linguistically in
order to compare it with the linguistic representation they had constructed
earlier, and this took time. As a consequence, they took longer to make this
comparison than participants who had received a picture at the outset.

SPONTANEOUS COMPREHENSION PROCESSES

To reiterate, much of the knowledge we acquire in daily life consists of


event and episode models of specific events that we observe or read about.
This knowledge may often pertain to the activities of actual people and situ-
ations that we learn about over a period of time. To this extent, new infor-
mation about the person and situations is likely to be comprehended in
terms of this referent-specific knowledge rather than in terms of more ab-
stract concepts of persons and events in general. Thus, new information
about Bill Clinton’s affair with Monica Lewinsky is likely to be compre-
hended spontaneously in terms of prior knowledge about these specific
protagonists rather than more general concepts pertaining to U.S. Presi-
THE ROLE OF SITUATION MODELS 89

dents and staff associates, or to men and women more generally. As we


noted earlier, the conceptualization proposed by Wyer and Srull (1989)
could not account for this possibility.
Earlier in this chapter, we distinguished three different types of repre-
sentations that might be constructed spontaneously in the course of com-
prehending new information. The representations differ in both the type of
input information that stimulates their construction and the terms in which
the representation is encoded. Specifically:

1. Episode and event models may be constructed from either verbal de-
scriptions of situationally and temporally specific events or direct ob-
servations of these events. These representations consist of mental im-
ages and, in some cases, linguistically coded descriptions of the events
being depicted.
2. Nonspecific representations of persons and events can be constructed
from verbal descriptions that are not temporally or situationally spe-
cific (e.g., “the boy owns a baseball,” “John went to college at Yale,”
“Peter is dishonest”). These representations are coded linguistically
but do not contain mental images.
3. Situational appraisals are constructed of the context in which more
specific information is conveyed. These appraisals, and the represen-
tations formed of them, are nonverbal.

All three types of representations obviously come into play in social in-
formation processing. They are not only formed from new information but,
once constructed, can be used as bases for comprehending experiences
and information that are acquired subsequently. In this chapter, we focus
primarily on the construction of event models in the course of compre-
hending events involving familiar persons of the kind we are likely to ob-
serve or read about, and will defer our discussion of the construction of epi-
sode models to the chapters that follow. Much of our discussion, however,
is applicable to the construction of nonspecific person and event represen-
tations as well.

Functions of the Comprehender

The comprehension processes we propose are theoretically localized in the


Comprehender (see Fig. 2.1). Our conceptualization of this unit differs from
that of the corresponding unit in the Wyer and Srull (1989) model in terms
of its accessibility to knowledge in Permanent Storage and, therefore, its
ability to comprehend information about specific persons and events with
which one is already familiar. The Comprehender is assumed to have two
components: a Parser and a Simulator. These components and when they
come into play are shown schematically in Fig. 4.1.
90 CHAPTER 4

FIG. 4.1. Theoretical sequence of processing steps involving the Parser and
Simulator in the course of comprehending visual and verbal information.

1. The Parser

The Parser only comes into play when the input information is coded lin-
guistically. In this case, the Parser transforms verbal information into the
equivalent of a Subject–Predicate proposition. The output of this Parser
then resonates with previously constructed mental representations in Per-
manent Storage. In this regard, a major difference between the conceptual-
THE ROLE OF SITUATION MODELS 91

ization of the Simulator and those of the Comprehender postulated by


Wyer and Srull lies in the range of material in Permanent Storage to which it
has access. In the original theory, the Comprehender had access to only se-
mantic concepts that were stored in a semantic bin. In contrast, the Simula-
tor has access to all previously formed knowledge representations that ex-
ist. Thus, information about a specific person or event about which one already
has knowledge is comprehended with reference to aspects of this referent-
specific knowledge without requiring any interpolated cognitive activity. This
process is elaborated presently.
If the input information is verbal and a previously constructed represen-
tation exemplifies the subject–predicate proposition that is formed of it, the
Parser retrieves this representation from Permanent Storage and uses it to
form a linguistically coded representation of the new information as well. If
the predicate describes an event or stimulus that is situationally and tem-
porally constrained, however, it is also likely to resonate with a preexisting
nonverbally coded representation (e.g., an event or episode model). In this
case, the Simulator is activated.

2. The Simulator

The basic operations performed by the Simulator are theoretically simi-


lar regardless of whether the original stimulus information is conveyed vi-
sually (as in a picture or movie) or verbally. It has the ability to (a) identify
referential knowledge in Permanent Storage, (b) evaluate the compatibility
of new information with previously formed event and episode models, (c)
substitute features of the new information for those of preexisting models
to form a new model, and (d) combine individual segments extracted from
previously formed models to form a new episode model that depicts a
unique sequence of events.
The output of the Simulator is largely nonverbal (visual or acoustic). If
both a verbally coded representation has been formed by the Parser and a
nonverbally coded representation has been formed by the Simulator, these
representations are then integrated into a single representation, as indi-
cated in Fig. 4.1.
The general processes outlined in Fig. 4.1 are potentially applicable re-
gardless of the type of input information, and theoretically underlie the for-
mation of all three types of representations described earlier. However, the
most complex comprehension processes occur when verbal information is
presented about situationally and temporally specific events. In the pages
that follow, therefore, we first discuss these processes and present some
empirical evidence bearing on them. In doing so, we note the implications
of the conceptualization for not only the comprehension of information but
also the spontaneous recognition of its validity or invalidity. Finally, we
92 CHAPTER 4

turn briefly to the processes that underlie the comprehension of events


that are directly observed. These latter considerations raise some addi-
tional issues that become important in later chapters of this volume.

THE COMPREHENSION OF VERBAL STATEMENTS

Theoretical Considerations

To reiterate, a verbal statement that enters the Comprehender is theoreti-


cally transformed by the Parser into the equivalent of a proposition consist-
ing of a subject and a predicate. The subject can refer to either a specific
person (“Michael Jordan”), an object (“Gone with the Wind”), or a general
category (“basketball players,” “book,” etc.). The predicate can convey a
specific or general act (“sank a three-pointer,” “played basketball”), or can
specify a relation between the statement’s subject and an attribute (e.g., “is
an athlete,” “has brown hair,” “is on the table”). Although our examples typ-
ically refer to predicates that describe actions, they apply equally well to
predicates of other types.
Once the Parser identifies the subject and predicate, it uses the linguistic
codings of them as retrieval cues to access concepts in Permanent Storage
that they exemplify and forms a linguistic representation of the statement
in terms of these concepts. In addition, it transmits a specification of the
subject and predicate to the Simulator. The functions of the Simulator are
captured in four postulates:

Postulate 4.3. The subject and predicate identified by the Parser are inde-
pendently used as probe cues of memory, resonating with all of the mental
representations that contain them (see Postulate 2.2). In each case, the repre-
sentation whose resonance level reaches threshold most quickly is most
likely to be identified.

One implication of this postulate should be noted at the outset. That is,
the type of representations activated by the subject and predicate are likely
to differ. In particular, the subject’s features are likely to activate a general-
ized person representations of the sort described in chapter 1 (Fig. 1.2).
That is, this representation may consist of a set of general features that are
independently associated with the individual to whom the subject refers.
Although some of these features can be specific behaviors the individual
has performed, they are also likely to include more general descriptions of
the person’s personality and behavior.
On the other hand, the features of the predicate, which pertain to behav-
iors or actions, are likely to activate previously formed event and episode
models of these actions. The actors depicted in these representations could
THE ROLE OF SITUATION MODELS 93

sometimes be the same person that is specified in the subject of the state-
ment to be comprehended. However, they could include many other indi-
viduals as well.
In each case, the speed with which a previously formed knowledge rep-
resentation reaches threshold depends on factors specified in the retrieval
postulates described in chapter 2. That is, it increases with the number of
features of the representation that are also contained in the probe set (Pos-
tulate 2.2) and also the degree to which the representation is already “vi-
brating” as a result of prior cognitive activity (Postulate 2.4). Note that if a
preexisting knowledge representation exists that contains both the probe
cues pertaining to the subject and the probe cues pertaining to the predi-
cate, it is likely to be activated much more quickly than other representa-
tions that contain only one set of cues. Moreover:

Postulate 4.4. If a memory search activates a previously formed knowledge


representation whose features include both the subject probe cues and the
predicate probe cues, the new information is spontaneously recognized as re-
dundant with prior knowledge and a new representation is not formed.

When the two sets of probe cues activate different knowledge represen-
tations, it means that a previously formed knowledge representation of the
information does not exist. Then, the process we assume is somewhat more
complicated. In this case, the probe cues associated with the subject are
likely to activate a number of knowledge representations that contain them,
some of whose features are more likely to overlap than others. In addition,
the predicate probe cues activate all of the models that explicate this ac-
tion or state of affairs. (If the stimulus is “Michael Jordan sank a three-
pointer,” for example, it would activate all preexisting situation models
whose predicate was “sank a three-pointer” or the equivalent.) The sub-
jects of these situation models could vary, but they are likely to have a sub-
set of features in common. In the composite set of subject features that are
activated, the features that are represented most often are weighted most
heavily. Then, the following postulate applies:

Postulate 4.5. If no previously formed model (i.e., knowledge unit) refers to


both the subject and predicate of a target statement, the features that are acti-
vated by the target’s subject are compared to a weighted composite of the
features associated with the target’s predicate. This comparison yields a global
estimate of similarity, S. A new situation model is formed if either (a) S is greater
than a minimum threshold value, TC, or (b) the target’s subject contains a subset
of features that are common to the subject of all models activated by the probe.
In the latter case, the new model is constructed by combining the composite of
features activated by the subject and the composite of features activated by
the predicate. In all cases, however, only the features that are weighted heavily in
the composite are included in the new model that is constructed.
94 CHAPTER 4

This postulate obviously requires unpacking. Suppose the target state-


ment is “Michael Jordan sank a three-pointer.” According to Postulate 4.3,
features of the Subject resonate with all previously stored representations
containing these cues, whereas “sank a three-pointer” resonates with all
previously formed event models of this activity. However, several of these
models are likely to have Michael Jordan as the subject. Then, according to
Postulate 4.4, these representations should be activated by resonance from
both the target’s subject and the target’s predicate, and the statement
should be regarded as redundant with prior knowledge.
However, suppose the target statement is “Michael Jordan rode a motor-
cycle.” In this case, the predicate may not activate models whose subject is
Michael Jordan. However, features that are frequently associated with mo-
torcycle riders are “big,” “muscular,” and “athletic.” Because these features
are likely to be conveyed in the generalized person representations that are
activated by “Michael Jordan,” the similarity, S, should be above threshold
TC . Therefore, a new model is likely to be constructed.
In contrast, suppose the target statement were “Woody Allen rode a mo-
torcycle.” In this case, the person representations activated by “Woody Al-
len” are less likely to include “big,” “muscular” and “athletic.” Conse-
quently, the similarity index computed on the basis of a comparison
features and the composite set activated by “rides a motorcycle” may be
below threshold. Nevertheless, the features of “Woody Allen” are likely to
include those that are common to all previously formed models of motorcy-
cle riders (e.g., “human”). Thus, a new model of this statement might still be
formed, but it would not be constructed as quickly as it would if statement
had referred to Mr. Jordan.
Finally, suppose the target statement was “A hippopotamus rode a mo-
torcycle.” In this case, the similarity index would not only be below thresh-
old, but the features of the subject would not be shared by all previously
formed models of “rode a motorcycle.” In this case, therefore, a situation
model of the statement would not be constructed spontaneously.
The implications of this analysis for comprehension become clear in the
context of the next postulate:

Postulate 4.6. A statement is comprehended spontaneously if it is redundant


with prior knowledge or if a new model is constructed of it. If neither is the
case, comprehension of the statement is not spontaneous, but requires (Exec-
utor-controlled) goal-directed processing.

Thus, to summarize our example, “Michael Jordan sank a three-pointer”


and “Michael Jordan rode a motorcycle” would both be comprehended
very quickly. “Woody Allen rode a motorcycle” would also be compre-
hended spontaneously, but would take more time to comprehend than the
THE ROLE OF SITUATION MODELS 95

first two statements. In contrast, “A hippopotamus rode a motorcycle”


would not be comprehended spontaneously, but would require conscious
Executor-controlled processing.
An interesting implication of the preceding analysis derives from Postu-
late 4.5. When a new situation model is formed, only those features that oc-
cur frequently in the representations that are activated by the subject and
predicate are depicted in this model. This means that the greater the amount
of information one has acquired about a referent in the past, the less detailed
the new information is likely to be. Thus, the representation of Michael Jor-
dan riding a motorcycle is likely to be less detailed if one has encountered
numerous instances of people riding motorcycles, or has had exposure to
Mr. Jordan in many different situations, than if one’s previous experience is
limited in these respects. More generally, one’s initial encounter with an ex-
emplar is likely to be represented more vividly than later encounters that
have been comprehended in terms of more general sets of features.
A related implication surrounds the comprehension of a statement about
members of a general category (e.g., “basketball players”). According to
Postulate 4.5, comprehending such a statement should depend on the diver-
sity of exemplars who are known to have engaged in the action described.
For example, consider the statement “A basketball player wore Nikes.” In
this case, a generalized person representation of “basketball players” may
be activated that refers to Michael Jordan as an exemplar (see chap. 1).
Moreover, previously formed situation models of “wears Nikes” are likely to
include Michael Jordan as the subject as a result of television commercials
that portray him as such. Consequently, the resonance elicited by “basket-
ball player” and “wears Nikes” could lead a previously formed model of Mi-
chael Jordan in Nike sports shoes to be activated very quickly, and so the
statement might be comprehended almost as quickly as a statement that re-
fers to Michael Jordan directly.
In contrast, suppose the category does not have a known exemplar that
has engaged in the activity in question. Then, different predictions would
be made. For example, “The tennis player wore Nikes” should be compre-
hended less quickly than “The basketball player wore Nikes.” This should
be true even though Nikes are associated just as strongly with playing ten-
nis as with playing basketball. The reason is that wearing Nikes and playing
basketball are both strongly associated with “Michael Jordan,” whereas
wearing Nikes is less likely to be associated with a previously formed model
of a specific tennis player.

Empirical Evidence

Wyer and Radvansky (1999) reported evidence in support of this conceptu-


alization. In one study, participants read a series of statements on a com-
puter screen with instructions to press one of two designated keys on the
96 CHAPTER 4

keyboard to indicate whether the statement was comprehensible or not.


Some of the statements were anomalous (e.g., “A show played poker”). Oth-
ers were meaningful and of four different types:

a. true exemplar–referent statements (e.g., “Jane Fonda does aerobics”)8


b. false exemplar–referent statements (e.g., “Jane Fonda plays profes-
sional hockey”);
c. exemplar–referent statements of unknown validity (e.g., “Jane Fonda
rides a motorcycle”)
d. category–referent statements that are likely to be true but for which
there is no known exemplar (e.g., “A steel worker does aerobics”).

All four of these statements were judged as comprehensible (mean likeli-


hood = .92). However, they differed significantly in the time required to
make this assessment. Of particular interest is a comparison of the time to
comprehend true exemplar–referent statements and the time to compre-
hend category–referent statements. According to the earlier Wyer and Srull
(1989) theory, the subject and predicate of the exemplar–referent state-
ments would have to be instantiated in terms of more general semantic con-
cepts in order to be comprehended. According to this theory, therefore, it
should take longer to comprehend these statements than to comprehend
statements that were already conveyed in terms of these concepts. In con-
trast, the present theory implies that true exemplar–referent statements
are interpreted in terms of preexisting situation models, and therefore
should be comprehended very quickly.
This was in fact the case. The first column of Table 4.2 (Experiment 1)
shows the mean time to comprehend the four types of statements de-
scribed earlier. True exemplar–referent statements were comprehended
more quickly (M = 1.35 s) than either category–referent statements (M = 1.68
s), false exemplar–referent statements (M = 1.64 s), or exemplar–referent
statements of unknown validity (M = 1.55 s).
Other differences in comprehension time are also consistent with expec-
tations. For example, exemplar–referent statements for which a previously
formed model exists should take less time to comprehend than statements
for which a new model must be constructed. Moreover, false exemplar–ref-
erent statements (e.g., “Jane Fonda plays professional basketball”) should
take longer to comprehend than statements of uncertain validity. This is be-
cause the similarity index that is computed on the basis of a global compar-
ison of features activated by their subject (“Jane Fonda”) with features that
are common to the models activated by the predicate (“plays professional

8
8 At the time of this study, Jane Fonda was a well-known promoter of aerobics on television
and magazines.
THE ROLE OF SITUATION MODELS 97

TABLE 4.2
A Comparison of the Time Required to Comprehend
Statements and the Time to Judge Their Validity

Comprehension Validation
Time Time Difference

Experiment 1

Exemplar-referent statements
Definitely true (e.g., “Mozart wrote a Symphony”) 1.35 1.55 0.20
Definitely false (e.g., “Mozart played rock and roll”) 1.64 1.86 0.22
Unknown validity (e.g., “Jane Fonda “read her
horoscope”) 1.55 2.07 0.52
Category-referent statements with no known exem-
plar (e.g., “a Musician did aerobics”) 1.68 1.88 0.20

Experiment 2

True exemplar-referent statements (e.g., “Jane Fonda


did aerobics”) 1.84 1.99 0.15
Category-referent statements with known exemplar
(e.g., “An actress does aerobics”) 2.17 2.23 0.06

Note. Response times are in seconds. Adapted from Wyer and Radvansky (1999).

basketball”) is below comprehension threshold, leading to an additional


stage of processing (Postulate 4.5). Although the difference in time to com-
prehend the two types of statements (1.64 s vs. 1.55 s) was not statistically
significant, it directionally confirmed this expectation.
In a second study, participants were asked to comprehend either true
exemplar–referent statements (“Jane Fonda does aerobics”) or statements
that referred to the category to which the exemplar belonged (e.g., “an ac-
tress does aerobics”). According to our assumptions, the second type of
statement should activate the same preexisting event model as the first
type and, therefore, should be comprehended nearly as quickly. This was in
fact the case, as also shown in Table 4.2 (Experiment 2). Although compre-
hension generally took longer in this study than in the first one, the times to
comprehend true exemplar–referent statements and category–referent
statements with a known exemplar did not appreciably differ (1.84 s vs. 2.00
s, respectively).

Priming Effects

Wyer and Radvansky’s (1999) second experiment evaluated a more subtle


implication of the theory we propose. These implications are suggested in
part by Postulate 2.4, that the resonance of a previously accessed knowl-
edge representation decreases gradually over time. This means that if the
98 CHAPTER 4

residual resonance has not dissipated at the time resonance is emitted


from other sources, the representation may be activated more quickly than
it otherwise would. This possibility has unique implications for the effects
of exposure to an exemplar-referent statement on the comprehension of a
category-referent statement that refers to the same or a different event.
For example, suppose participants are exposed to an exemplar-referent
statement (e.g., “Jane Fonda did aerobics”). This statement may increase
the accessibility of other event models that refer to the same subject (e.g.,
“Jane Fonda played in a movie”). This, in turn, should increase the speed of
recognizing a new statement that refers to this activity, making it easier to
comprehend. Moreover, this should be true even if the new statement re-
fers to someone else. Thus, exposure to “Jane Fonda did aerobics” should
increase the speed of comprehending not only “Jane Fonda played in a
movie” but statements about other persons in the same activity (e.g.,
“Dustin Hoffman played in a movie”). In contrast, the subject of a category-
referent statement (e.g., “An actress did aerobics”) should activate a gener-
alized person representation (cf. Fig. 1.2), but is less likely to activate event
models. Consequently, exposure to this type of statement should not influ-
ence the comprehension of statements that refer to different behaviors.
The second experiment reported by Wyer and Radvansky (1999) pro-
vided some support for this prediction. Participants were first asked to
comprehend either an exemplar-referent statement about a person’s behav-
ior (e.g., “Jane Fonda did aerobics”) or a statement that referred to a cate-
gory to which the exemplar belonged (e.g., “An actress did aerobics”).
Then, they were asked to comprehend a target statement that referred to
either the same behavior or a different one with which the exemplar was as-
sociated (e.g., “played in a movie”). Exposure to a category-referent state-
ment decreased the time required to comprehend a target statement only if
the two statements referred to the same behavior. In contrast, exposure to
an exemplar-referent statement decreased the time to comprehend a target
statement regardless of whether it referred to the same behavior or to a dif-
ferent behavior with which the exemplar was also associated.

SPONTANEOUS VALIDITY JUDGMENTS

The most unique implications of Wyer and Radvansky’s (1999) formulation


have yet to be considered. As noted earlier, people who receive informa-
tion about a known person or event may not only comprehend the event
but may judge it to be true or false. Moreover, this determination is often
made automatically in the course of comprehending the statement, in the
absence of a more specific goal that requires its assessment. Thus, the
THE ROLE OF SITUATION MODELS 99

statement “Abraham Lincoln wore a beard” is comprehended and immedi-


ately recognized a true. By the same token, “Abraham Lincoln shot John F.
Kennedy” is immediately recognized as false. These assessments occur
spontaneously, in the absence of any goal that requires them.
These phenomena and the conditions in which they occur are taken into
account in the formulation we propose. According to the theory, the recog-
nition that a statement is true or false is often a necessary by-product of the
comprehension processes embodied in Postulates 4.4 and 4.5. This is most
obvious when people’s comprehension of a statement activates a pre-
existing situation model of the event to which it refers. In this case, aware-
ness of the prior existence of the model is typically sufficient to affirm its
validity. There may be exceptions to this. Situation models can obviously
be constructed of fictitious events (e.g., “Santa Claus came down the chim-
ney on Christmas Eve”). However, the representation of these events is
likely to contain a “tag” denoting their fictional character. In the absence of
this tag, statements that instantiate an existing situation model may be
spontaneously recognized as true in the course of comprehending them.
The following postulate formalizes this assumption.

Postulate 4.7. A statement is spontaneously recognized as true in the course


of comprehending it if (a) a situation model of the event or state described al-
ready exists in memory and (b) no tag has been attached to the model that
designates it as false.

Spontaneous judgments of a statement’s validity can also occur when a


previously formed model of the situation does not exist. As Postulate 4.5 im-
plies, comprehension may often be a two-stage process. That is, persons
who encounter a statement first compute a global estimate of the similarity
(S) between the statement and the referents of previously formed situation
models of the predicate, and comprehend the statement if this similarity is
above threshold. In the course of this determination, however, they theo-
retically become aware of the value of S in relation to two other threshold
values that are necessary to confirm or disconfirm its validity. If S exceeds
or falls short of these values, the statement may be identified spontane-
ously as true or false. To formalize:

Postulate 4.8. A statement about an event is recognized as true in the course


of comprehending it if the similarity of its subject to those of previously
formed models of the event (S) exceeds an upper threshold, TT . The state-
ment is identified as false if S is below a lower threshold, TF . If S falls between
TT and TF , the statement is comprehended but its validity is not spontane-
ously evaluated.
100 CHAPTER 4

Postulate 4.9. Spontaneous inferences that a statement is true or false are


transferred to the Work Space along with a representation of the statement
that has been formed in the course of comprehending it.

Thus, as an example, “An Israeli donated money to a synagogue” would


be quickly judged as plausible because the categorical representation of
“Israeli” is likely to share many features with the subject of these models (S
> TT). In contrast, “Hitler donated money to a synagogue” is likely to be im-
mediately recognized as false, because few features of Hitler are likely to
characterize the subject of previously formed models of donating money to
a synagogue (i.e., S < TF). Finally, “Madonna donated money to a syna-
gogue” would not be immediately evaluated as either true or false, because
Madonna’s known features are neither highly similar nor highly dissimilar
to those of the relevant models subjects (TF < S < TT). That is, the latter
statement would be comprehended, but its validity would only be assessed
if more specific goal-directed processing required it.

Empirical Evidence

Wyer and Radvansky (1999) obtained support for the implications of these
postulates in the two experiments described earlier. Rather than being
asked to comprehend the statements they were presented in these condi-
tions, some participants in these studies were asked to indicate whether
the statements were true or false. If statements were verified spontane-
ously in the course of comprehending them, there would be little difference
between the time required to make these verifications and the time re-
quired to comprehend them. If verification requires additional processing
subsequent to comprehension, the time to perform the verification should
be greater than comprehension time. According to Postulate 4.8, however,
this latter condition arises only when the subject of a statement is neither
similar nor dissimilar to the subject of preexisting models associated the
predicate (e.g., “Madonna donated money to a synagogue”).
Data bearing on these possibilities are summarized in Table 4.2. The first
column of data refers to the time required to comprehend different types of
target statements, as indicated in our earlier discussion. The second col-
umn summarizes the time to judge whether the same statements were true
or false. Although the statements in Experiment 1 were verified more slowly
than they were comprehended, this difference was appreciable only for ex-
emplar–referent statements of unclear validity. The difference in all other
cases was small and did not differ over the three types of statement, sug-
gesting a general response bias that was independent of the cognitive proc-
esses underlying judgment. In Experiment 2, the time to verify statements
THE ROLE OF SITUATION MODELS 101

and the time to comprehend them were even more similar. Thus, these re-
sults are quite consistent with the formulation we propose.

Further Implications

The results we have brought to bear on the comprehension and validation


of propositions were obtained in a rather artificial research situation. How-
ever, results of research in other areas are consistent with this conceptual-
ization. Of particular interest in this regard are the implications of Postu-
late 4.7. To reiterate, this postulate states that if a pre-existing situation
model of a statement exists in memory, and if no tag has been attached to
the model that denotes it a false, the statement will become spontaneously
as true. Thus, suppose participants construct a new situation model of a
statement in one context in the course of comprehending it but do not
spontaneously assess its validity. Later, however, they encounter the same
statement in a different context. To comprehend the statement, they pre-
sumably retrieve the situation model they constructed of it earlier (Postu-
late 4.4). However, because the statement is comprehended in terms of this
model, it should be spontaneously identified as true (Postulate 4.7). Put
more simply, the exposure to and comprehension of a statement at one
point in time may increase beliefs in the statement’s validity at a later time.
The study by Hasher et al. (1977) described in chapter 3 provides direct
support for this prediction. That is, people who had reported their beliefs
in statements about unfamiliar events and situations in an initial experimen-
tal session increased their beliefs in the statements when they encountered
them in a second experimental session 1 week later. Presumably, partici-
pants’ comprehension of the statements in the initial session led them to
construct situation models of the events described by the statements. Con-
sequently, they retrieved and used these models to comprehend the same
statements when they encountered them later. However, the pre-existence
of these models in memory should increase inferences of the statements’
validity, as Hasher et al.’s findings indicate.
These phenomena may pertain not only to the verification of a single
event, but also to sequences of events of which multiple-segment episode
models are constructed. In a study by Green and Brock (2000), participants
read a story about a violent crime. They were clearly aware that the story
was factual. Nevertheless, they later estimated the incidence of story-rela-
ted events in the real world to be higher than participants who had not
read the story.
In a similar vein, Shrum and his colleagues (O’Guinn & Shrum, 1997;
Shrum, Wyer, & O’Guinn, 1998) found that heavy television viewers were
more likely than light viewers to overestimate the incidence of crime-
related events in the real world. These quite different sets of studies con-
102 CHAPTER 4

verge on the possibility that people, either in the laboratory or when watch-
ing television, construct episode models of the events they encounter and
store these models in memory. Later, they are likely to retrieve the models
when contemplating events that are redundant with their implications, and
therefore estimate the events to be more likely to occur. Similar conclu-
sions can be drawn from research on the effects of generating an explana-
tion for hypothetical events on later beliefs that the event will occur (Ross,
Lepper, Strack, and Steinmetz, 1977; Sherman, Skov, Hervitz, & Stock, 1981).
We discuss these studies in more detail in chapter 9.

An Alternative Conceptualization

The conceptualization proposed in this chapter should be considered in


the context of a formulation proposed by Gilbert (1991) on the role of com-
prehension on beliefs. Gilbert hypothesized that belief formation is a two-
step process, which first involves comprehension and only later involves
verification. Moreover, in order to comprehend a statement, one must nec-
essarily entertain the possibility that it is true. Thus, for example, compre-
hension of the statement “George W. Bush donated money to the Taliban”
entails a tentative acceptance of this state of affairs, and only later is the
statement’s validity rejected. One implication of this conceptualization is
that people who have been asked to learn true and false statements under
conditions of high information load are more likely to recall false state-
ments as true than to recall true statements as false. This is presumably be-
cause the heavy processing demands prevent the second (verification)
stage of processing from occurring. Thus, the statements are likely to be
judged as true, based on results of the first stage of processing alone. As a
consequence, objectively true statements are evaluated correctly but ob-
jectively false statements are not.
The processes that Gilbert postulates to occur at the comprehension
stage are compatible with those assumed by the conceptualization pro-
posed here. That is, the comprehension of a statement about an event in-
volves the construction of a mental simulation of it (i.e., a situation model).
Moreover, the storage of this representation in memory increases its likeli-
hood that a statement asserting the event it describes will later be judged
as true (Postulate 4.8). On the other hand, this postulate distinguishes be-
tween the comprehension of a statement and the criteria that are used to
estimate its validity. Moreover, it specifies the conditions in which the lat-
ter assessment is made spontaneously rather than at a later, postcompre-
hension stage of processing. Our conceptualization and Gilbert’s are there-
fore compatible with one qualification. That is, according to the proposed
model, statements that differ substantially from the subset of previously
formed models of the events they describe are likely to be below falsifica-
THE ROLE OF SITUATION MODELS 103

tion threshold (TF). These statements should be judged as invalid spontane-


ously at the time the statements are comprehended and should later be
reported as false regardless of information processing load. Thus, for exam-
ple, the proposed theory predicts that the statement “Abraham Lincoln
landed on the moon” would be spontaneously judged as false regardless of
processing load. Gilbert’s formulation does not seem to make this predic-
tion. With this exception, however, the two formulations are consistent.

The Comprehension of Observed Events and Situations

The comprehension of observed events is in some respects simpler and in


other respects more complex than the comprehension of verbal descrip-
tions of the events. For one thing, observations typically consist of not just
one but a continuous stream of actions. For another, observations typically
include features of not only the event itself but also the situational context
in which it occurs.
In the first regard, it seems unlikely that people store a continuous
stream of experiences in memory. Rather, as Newtson (1973, 1976) argued,
we are likely to extract visual frames from an ongoing stream of events that
identify the actions that occur. The specific nature of these frames has been
somewhat controversial. Newtson (1973, 1976), for example, assumed that
the frames extracted are located at breakpoints between the end of one
event and the onset of another. As Ebbesen (1980; see also Wyer & Srull,
1989) pointed out, however, this assumption seems rather tenuous, and the
empirical support for it is equivocal.
Following Ebbesen (1980), we assume that the representation formed in
the course of comprehending an ongoing sequence of behavioral events
consists of static frames, each of which corresponds to a meaningful act,
and therefore, constitutes a mental “picture” of the event that occurred.
Thus, suppose a person enters his house, takes off his coat, goes into the
kitchen, opens the refrigerator and gets a can of beer. Observers do not
need to store a mental “movie” of these actions in order to comprehend
and remember what went on. Rather, they need only to extract a frame that
is typical of each event and that permits its essential features to be identi-
fied. Each of these frames could normally be represented in a mental image
of the sort we assume to compose an event model, and the sequence of
frames as a whole could constitute an episode model.
The operations of the Simulator in this process must nevertheless be
clarified. We assume that as an individual observes a sequence of events,
features of these events resonate with previously constructed event mod-
els in memory. Although the features of the observation are constantly
changing, the features that occur within the time interval associated with a
104 CHAPTER 4

meaningful event are all likely to be sufficiently similar to those of a previ-


ously formed event model to activate it. Thus, for example, the features ex-
tracted from the observation of someone taking off his coat may all reso-
nate with a static event model of this behavior, leading the model to be
accessed and used in much the same manner it is used to comprehend a
verbal description of the event.
However, the features of an observed event sequence also include as-
pects of the situational context in which the sequence occurred. These fea-
tures can also resonate with situational features of preexisting event and
episode models in Permanent Storage. The subset of situational features
that are most typical of these models could constitute a situational ap-
praisal of the sort described earlier in this chapter. However, because situa-
tional features are common to all of the specific events that are observed,
these features, along with others that occur frequently in the models that
have been activated, may be transmitted to the Work Space as a separate
representation that is independent of the more specific event models that
are constructed. This situational representation could operate in several
ways. First, if the events that are specified in the activated models are rela-
tively homogenous, the situational appraisal defined by these features
could give rise to expectations for the sorts of events that are likely to oc-
cur in the situation at hand. Second, the appraisal, once it is transmitted to
the Work Space, might be included among the eliciting conditions of a pro-
duction of the sort described in chapter 1, and thus could stimulate the ob-
server’s own behavior in the situation. This possibility, which could help to
account for the different effects of concept activation on behaviors de-
scribed in chapter 3 (cf. Bargh et al., 1996; Colcombe & Wyer, 2001), is con-
sidered further in chapter 7, where we discuss the situational norms that
govern expectations for the communications that are exchanged in social
interaction and the impact of deviations from these expectations on the in-
terpretation of these communications.

CONCLUDING REMARKS

To summarize, the proposed formulation specifies the conditions in which


a statement about a situation-specific event or state of affairs is spontane-
ously identified as true or false in the course of comprehending it. Our anal-
ysis has largely been restricted to statements about events and states that
are temporally and situationally constrained (i.e., those that are compre-
hended by constructing a situation model). However, similar processes
should guide the comprehension and verification of other types of state-
ments as well. Be that as it may, the implication that many statements are
verified spontaneously in the course of comprehending them has further
THE ROLE OF SITUATION MODELS 105

implications. As implied by Postulate 4.9, statements that are spontane-


ously verified as true or false are transmitted to the Work Space along with
a designation of their validity, and this spontaneous validity assessment
may be subject to further processing. For example, communications that
are obviously true or obviously false may violate normative principles of
conversation, and therefore may stimulate a conscious effort to understand
why the communication was uttered. This additional processing may some-
times lead to a reconstrual of the statement’s meaning that differs from the
meaning implied by the situation model that was constructed in the course
of comprehending it. We elaborate this possibility and its implications in
chapter 6.
However, the discussion of comprehension processes in this chapter has
focused on the representations formed of statements about single events
or, alternatively, on event models. Equally important considerations sur-
round the way in which event models are combined to form a multiple-
segment episode model of a thematically related sequence of events. The
next chapter is devoted to these matters.
C H A P T E R

5
The Construction of Episode
Models and Generalized
Narrative Representations

Chapter 4 focused largely on the comprehension of statements about single


events of the sort that are represented in memory as event models. Most of
the information we acquire in daily life, however, consists of sequences of
events that theoretically give rise to the construction of multiple-segment
episode models. To understand the conditions in which these models are
constructed, several questions must be answered. These questions concern
the number of episode models that are formed from a given sequence of
events, the role of thematic relatedness in the construction of these mod-
els, and the way in which the temporal order of events is reconstructed
when the events are not contained in the same model. We attempt to pro-
vide tentative answers to these questions in this chapter.
Not all mental representations of event sequences are episode models,
of course. In the last section of this chapter, we discuss briefly the construc-
tion of generalized narrative representations. Then, in chapter 6, we con-
sider the conditions in which these generalized representations are used to
comprehend specific experiences, and also the extent to which abstract
representations of an experience, once constructed, can influence memory
for this experience.

THE CONSTRUCTION OF EPISODE MODELS

How Many Episode Models Are Formed?

People obviously do not construct a single representation of their experi-


ences over the course of a lifetime, or even over the course of a day. Nor do
they construct a single representation of the events they read about in a

106
EPISODE MODELS AND GENERALIZED NARRATIVE REPRESENTATIONS 107

novel or see in a movie. Rather, they are likely to construct several different
episode models, each pertaining to a given sequence of events that are the-
matically as well as temporally related. Thus, the statements “John packed
his bags. John left for the airport.” may be represented in a two-segment ep-
isode model because they refer to the same person and are both related to
going on a trip. In contrast, the sentences “John packed his bags. Mary wa-
tered the flowers.” are likely to be represented in different models because
they appear to have little to do with one another. These considerations are
captured by a more general postulate:

Postulate 5.1. Once a situation model has been formed, subsequent informa-
tion is integrated into the model if and only if this information concerns the
same situation as the model or a thematically related one.

This integration is presumably performed by the Simulator. Thus, the


Simulator presumably forms an event model of the first piece of informa-
tion it receives. When it encounters a second piece, it forms an event model
of this as well and then compares its features with those of the first model.
If the two sets of known features are compatible, features of one model that
are either unspecified or absent are instantiated in terms of specified fea-
tures of the other. An episode model is then formed composed of both
event models in combination. On the other hand, suppose the features of
the second model are incompatible with those of the first. Then, the inte-
gration is not performed.
Thus, suppose people who have formed an event model of “George
packed his bags” encounter the statement “He left for the airport.” The ref-
erent of “he” in the second statement is compatible with the representation
of “George” in the first statement, and so a model of the second statement
is likely to be integrated with the first model, producing an episode model
of the events described two statements in combination. However, suppose
the second statement is “She left for the airport.” In this case, “she” cannot
be instantiated in terms of the features of the first representation, and so a
separate model of the event is constructed.
In some cases, there might be an a priori reason to suppose that state-
ments are thematically related despite appearances to the contrary. In this
case, an integration of the two statements might be performed. However,
this would not occur spontaneously by the Simulator, but rather, would in-
volve higher order, Executor-controlled processing. Thus, in our example,
people might speculate that “George” is actually a woman. Or, they might
infer that “she” refers to an individual who was mentioned in a previous
statement to which they are not privy. However, these speculations would
not occur automatically.
108 CHAPTER 5

Note that these latter, more deliberative integration processes require a


modification of the representation that was initially formed of the first
statement. As we indicated in chapter 2, new features can be added to a
representation, but existing features can never be erased. Thus, the goal-
directed processing described in the previous paragraph would result in
two representations: (a) the initial event model, which contains only the
original information, and (b) a second representation that contains implica-
tions of both the original information (as modified to accommodate the new
material) and the new. This assumption, which becomes of particular im-
portance in our discussion of higher order comprehension processes (see
chap. 7), is captured by the following postulate:

Postulate 5.2. When new information requires a modification of an event or


episode model that had been constructed on the basis of prior information,
the original model is retained in memory. However, a second representation
is constructed consisting of a modified version of the first model along with
the implications of the new information.

In this regard, the thematic relatedness of information is not an inherent


property of the information itself. That is, it can depend to a large extent on
the prior knowledge of the recipient. For example, the statements “Mary got
a coke. John went to the bathroom.” may appear to be more thematically
related to people who know that John and Mary are preparing to see a
movie at a local theater than to people who do not have this knowledge. A
more graphic example is provided by the following passage written by
Nancy McCarrell (see Bransford & Stein, 1984):

Remember Sally, the person I mentioned in my last letter? You’ll never guess
what she did this week. First, she let loose a team of gophers. The plan back-
fired when a dog chased them away. She then threw a party but the guests
failed to bring their motorcycles. Furthermore, her stereo system was not
loud enough. Sally spent the next day looking for a “Peeping Tom” but was un-
able to find one in the yellow pages. Obscene phone calls gave her some hope
until the number was changed. It was the installation of blinking neon lights
across the street that finally did the trick. Sally framed the ad from the classi-
fied section and now has it hanging on her wall. (p. 51)

To the naive reader, the events described in the passage appear to have lit-
tle to do with one another. However, a reader who has prior knowledge that
the woman is trying to get rid of her noisy neighbors is much better able to
understand the causal and thematic relatedness of the events.
The question is how to determine empirically whether episode models
are formed of information and, if so, how many. A procedure for determin-
ing this was developed by Radvansky and Zacks (1991) in investigating the
EPISODE MODELS AND GENERALIZED NARRATIVE REPRESENTATIONS 109

construction of situation models of states of affairs. In a typical study


(Radvansky & Zacks, 1991), participants were asked to learn statements
concerning an object and its location. In multiple-object, single-location condi-
tions, the statements described 1, 2, or 3 objects in a given location (e.g.,
“The book is on the table.” “The cup is on the table.” “The pen is on the ta-
ble.” In single-object, multiple-location conditions, the sentences described a
given object in 1, 2, or 3 locations (“The book is on the table.” “The book is
on the chair.” “The book is on the floor.”). Radvansky and Zacks (1991) rea-
soned that people can easily imagine several objects in a given location
and, therefore, would construct a single situation model under multiple-
object, single-location conditions regardless of the number of objects in-
volved. However, an object cannot occupy different locations at the same
time. Therefore, in single-object, multiple-location conditions, participants
would have to form a different model on the basis of each statement.
Participants after learning the statements to criterion were given a rec-
ognition memory test, and the time to verify the statement was observed.
Radvansky and Zacks argued that if participants formed a different model
on the basis of each statement, the models would interfere with one an-
other at the time of retrieval, and the magnitude of this interference would
increase with the number of models involved. To this extent, the time to
recognize a given statement should increase with the number of statements
in the set. However, suppose the statements were integrated into a single
situation model. Then, there should be no interference, and so the verifica-
tion time should not depend on the number of statements. Results were
consistent with expectations based on this assumption. That is, response
times increased with the number of statements presented under single-
object, multiple-location conditions, but were independent of the number of
statements presented in multiple-object, single-location conditions.
Radvanksy and Zacks’ study not only provided insight into the construc-
tion of situation models but also suggested a general methodology for de-
termining the conditions in which they are constructed (for other demon-
strations of the effectiveness of the procedure, see Radvansky, Spieler, &
Zacks, 1993). This methodology was therefore applied in investigating the
validity of Postulate 5.1. In this study (Radvansky, Wyer, Curiel, & Lutz,
1997), participants were asked to learn sentences each describing the rela-
tionship of a person (e.g., a lawyer) to an object (e.g., a toothbrush). In
some cases, the person and object were related in terms of a specific be-
havior (e.g., “the lawyer is buying a toothbrush”), whereas in other cases,
they were related in terms of ownership (e.g., “the lawyer owns a tooth-
brush”). Finally, the objects presented in some conditions (e.g., a tooth-
brush, shaving cream, and aspirin) could all be purchased in a single loca-
tion (e.g., a drugstore) but in other cases, the objects (e.g., a toothbrush, a
bicycle, and a diamond ring) were typically purchased in different loca-
110 CHAPTER 5

tions. As in Radvansky and Zacks’ (1991) studies, participants after learning


the statements were asked to indicate whether or not these statements
(along with distracters) had been among those they had been asked to
learn. Response times to presented items were recorded.
Although the design of the study was complex, the predictions were
straightforward. That is, participants should form a single episode model
from statements that describe a single person buying objects in a single lo-
cation. In this case, therefore, the time to verify such statements should not
depend on the number that were presented. However, separate event mod-
els should be formed of a person who buys objects in different locations, or
of different persons who buy the same object regardless of location. Finally,
when the relationship involves ownership, which is not temporally con-
strained, event models should not be formed at all. Therefore, in all cases
but the first, verification times should increase with the number of state-
ments presented.
Results shown in Fig. 5.1 are quite consistent with these expectations. The
figure shows mean verification times to statements in each experimental con-
dition as a function of the number of statements presented. The top left panel
shows that when the statements described a single person’s purchase of ob-
jects in a single location, verification time was virtually identical regardless of
the number of statements presented. In all other conditions, however, verifi-
cation time increased with the number of statements presented.
Thus, these findings confirm the implications of Postulate 5.1. First, event
models are only likely to be formed in the course of comprehending state-
ments about events that are situationally and temporally constrained. Sec-
ond, event models are likely to be integrated into a single multiple-segment
episode model only if the events occur in a single situation. A qualification
on the latter conclusion, however, is indicated in the next section.

Effects of Thematic Relatedness

Radvansky et al.’s (1997) study indicated that events that occur in different
locations may be represented separately in memory rather than integrated
into a single episode model. However, the construction of episode models
may be influenced by other factors, the effects of which could override the
impact of situational differences. If events are causally related, for example,
they may be incorporated into a single model even if they occur in different
locations. By the same token, thematically unrelated events are likely to be
represented in different models even if they occur in the same situation.
An early study by Wyer and Bodenhausen (1985) provided indirect evi-
dence of these differences. Participants read a story about events that oc-
curred at a cocktail party that was written from the perspective of a person
who attended it. Two target episodes were included among several others
FIG. 5.1. Mean time to verify a statement as a function of (a) the number of persons associated with a given ob-
ject (denoted by squares) or (b) the number of objects associated with a given person (denoted by circles).
The two top panels show responses to items pertaining to buying objects that could be found in either a single

111
location (a drugstore) or different locations. The two bottom panels show responses to items pertaining to
owning these objects. RT = response time. Based on data reported by Radvansky et al. (1997).
112 CHAPTER 5

that took place in the course of the party. One episode consisted of events
that were causally related and occurred in the same situation. Specifically,
someone bumped a guest’s arm as he was reaching for an hors d’oeuvre,
causing him to spill his drink on a woman’s dress. The woman thereupon
called the offender a disparaging name and stalked off to the bathroom to
clean up. In contrast, the events composing a second episode were causally
related but occurred in different physical locations. That is, it concerned a
guest’s telling a story about Willa, who learned that her father was dying,
packed her bags and got on a plane to San Francisco, had three drinks on
the plane to calm herself, but felt tipsy by the time the plane landed. Conse-
quently, she forgot the name of the hospital where her father was staying
and wound up crying on the streets of San Francisco.
One of the episodes was conveyed nearer the end of the party scenario
than the other. However, the order in which the events composing each epi-
sode were described was varied, sometimes being in chronological order
and in other cases being in the reverse order (e.g., “Willa had cried on the
streets of San Francisco. She had forgotten the name of the hospital where
her father was staying. She was feeling tipsy as a result of having three
drinks on the plane . . .”). Moreover, the events were all mentioned in se-
quence or were separated by other, unrelated events that occurred at the
party and temporarily distracted the visitor from those involved in the epi-
sode being described.
Participants after reading the entire cocktail party narrative and a short
delay were asked to recall what they had read. Participants typically re-
called the events composing each target scenario in chronological order re-
gardless of the order in which they had been presented and regardless of
whether the descriptions of them were separated by unrelated events. This
suggests that they integrated the events in each scenario into a multiple-
segment episode model that they later used as a basis for recalling what
had occurred, and this was true regardless of whether the events occurred
in the same physical situation or in different situations. However, they re-
called the last story mentioned in the narrative before recalling the one
that occurred earlier. Thus, participants formed separate episode models
of the two event sequences despite their occurrence in the same general
situation (the party), perhaps assigning them a common header (e.g., “the
cocktail party”). Thus, the residual resonance of the more recently con-
structed episode model led it to be the first one retrieved and reported
(Postulate 2.4).

Temporal Coding of Episode Models

The conclusion that thematically unrelated sequences of events are orga-


nized into different episode models and are stored separately in memory is
quite plausible. But if this is the case, how can the temporal order of the se-
EPISODE MODELS AND GENERALIZED NARRATIVE REPRESENTATIONS 113

quences of events be reconstructed? We can often remember going to Bali


on vacation before George Bush was elected President despite the fact that
the events are totally unrelated. How is this accomplished? The order of
such events may in some situations be computed rather than remembered.
For example, the events may each be compared to a “landmark” event (e.g.,
my wife’s having a baby) that is personally relevant and whose temporal
position is fixed (Loftus & Marburger, 1983). Or, people may simply apply a
“heuristic,” reasoning that the more they can remember about an event, the
more recently it probably occurred (Brown, Rips, & Shevell, 1985). Even
within the same situation, however, the order of events that are ostensibly
unrelated to one another can often be constructed fairly accurately.
It is conceivable that in the latter situations, people may assign temporal
“tags” to events that denote the order of their occurrence and permit their
order to be reconstructed later. This possibility was examined by Wyer,
Shoben, Fuhrman, and Bodenhausen (1985). People read a version of the
“Willa” story employed by Wyer and Bodenhausen (1985) and mentioned
earlier. In some cases, however, the first and last scenes were modified to
make them ostensibly unrelated to those that occurred in the middle one.
These events, which were presented in a paragraph, were as follows:

Willa was awakened by the alarm.


She got out of bed.
She had breakfast.
She got on a plane to San Francisco.
She had three drinks.
She felt dizzy.
She was glad when the plane landed.
She went shopping in the city.
She bought a sweater.

It seemed reasonable to suppose that participants would construct three


episode models in the course of comprehending the events (pertaining to
getting up in the morning, the plane ride, and the shopping spree), desig-
nating each by a header that refers to what the model is about. They might
also assign a temporal tag to each model (e.g., “early,” “middle,” “late,” etc.)
to indicate when the episode occurred in relation to others. Thus, suppose
participants are later asked which of two events occurred earlier. They
might first identify the episode model(s) in which the events were con-
tained and compare the tags associated with them. If the tags differ, they
can make a quick decision. If the tags are the same, however, participants
must compute the order of the events on the basis of their location in the
episode model itself, and so they take more time to respond. Thus, the
overall decision time, Ttotal , might be given by the equation:
114 CHAPTER 5

Ttotal = t0 + tI + tC1 + tC2 ,

Where tI is the time to identify the episode model in which the events are
contained, tC1 is the time to compare the temporal tags associated with the
models, and tC2 is the time to locate the relative positions of the events
within a given episode model should this prove necessary.
To evaluate this conceptualization, participants after reading the pas-
sage were given several different pairs of events and asked in each case to
decide which event in the pair occurred sooner. Participants took more
time to make this decision when one or both events occurred at the bound-
ary of an episode model than when they occurred in the middle, suggesting
that more time was required to identify the model in which an event was
contained (tI ) when its location was relatively ambiguous. Second, partici-
pants took more time to compare events if they occurred in the same
model than if they occurred in different ones, and this was true independ-
ently of the positions of the events in the story as a whole. This finding is
consistent with the assumption that when the events are contained in the
same model, their order cannot be determined on the basis of the temporal
tags assigned to the models. Therefore, an additional amount of time (tC2 ) is
required to make this determination.9
In additional conditions of Wyer, Shoben, Fuhrman, and Bodenhausen
(1985) study, the three scenes of the story were similar to those employed
by Wyer and Bodenhausen (1985) and, therefore, were thematically related.
In this case, decision times were generally longer than they were when the
scenes were unrelated. Wyer et al. attributed this difference to an increase
in tI (the time to identify the model in which the events were contained).
However, other results were comparable to those that occurred when
the scenes were unrelated, suggesting that different episode models were
formed in this condition as well. This conclusion might seem to contradict
the implications of Wyer and Bodenhausen’s findings. However, a se-
quence of thematically related events may be more likely to be integrated
into a single episode model when the events are described in the context of
several other, unrelated episodes, as was the case in the cocktail party
story that Wyer and Bodenhausen’s participants read. When a sequence of

9
9 As an aside, it might be noted that the conceptualization predicts that in general, the time to
compare two events will be less when they are far apart in the sequence than when they are
close together. This suggests a “symbolic temporal distance” effect of the sort observed by
Nottenburg and Shoben (1980) and similar to that obtained in other judgment domains (cf.
Banks, 1977). According to this conceptualization, however, the effect results from the fact that
the likelihood that the events being compared are in different models (and, therefore, tC2 = 0) in-
creases with the distance between them. In fact, although a symbolic distance effect was ob-
served in Wyer, Shoben, and Bodenhausen’s (1985) study, it was eliminated when the relative
numbers of between-model and within-model comparisons was controlled.
EPISODE MODELS AND GENERALIZED NARRATIVE REPRESENTATIONS 115

events is conveyed in isolation, the different situations appear more dis-


tinct, and so different models may be constructed.

Effects of Familiarity

An additional factor that might determine the extent to which a sequence of


events is divided into different episode models is the similarity of the se-
quence to ones that participants have been exposed in the past and are al-
ready represented in memory. For example, it seems intuitively reasonable
to suppose that familiar sequences are encoded into broader conceptual
units than novel ones (Newtson, 1973, 1976). Thus, multiple-segment episode
models may be formed more frequently in the first case than the second.
Stan Colcombe and I (reported in Wyer et al., 2002) examined this possi-
bility using procedures similar to those employed by Radvansky and his
colleagues and described earlier. We constructed four stories, each com-
posed of events that occurred in three related situations. The events in two
stories were fairly novel; one described Willa’s ill-fated trip to visit her sick
father and a second described a woman’s encounter with a bear while
camping. The events composing the other two stories were routine, de-
scribing a visit to a restaurant (with scenes pertaining to entering, eating,
and paying) and going to a movie (with scenes pertaining to buying tickets,
eating some popcorn, and seeing the show).
Three versions of each story were prepared. Each version described six
events, with the number of events taken from each scene (1, 2, or 3) varying
in a counterbalanced design. (Thus, one version of the restaurant story de-
scribed one event that occurred while entering, two events that occurred
while ordering, and three events that occurred while paying; another de-
scribed three events that occurred while entering, one while eating, and
two while paying, etc.) Participants read the stories under one of two condi-
tions. In other-referent conditions, the protagonist in the story was a hypo-
thetical person. In self-referent conditions, participants were told to imagine
themselves experiencing the situations described, and the protagonist was
referred to as “you.”
After learning the stories to criterion, participants were asked to verify
the events that were mentioned in each story. We assumed that the extent
to which verification time increased with the number of events described in
each scene of the stories indicated the extent to which participants formed
a single episode model of the scene or separate models. Pooled over other-
referent and self-referent conditions, the time to verify novel events in-
creased with the number presented in the scene to which they pertained
(1.23 s vs. 1.35 s when 1 vs. 3 events were presented, respectively), suggest-
ing that a different model was formed of each scene. In contrast, the time to
verify familiar events did not depend on the number presented (1.48 s vs.
116 CHAPTER 5

1.40 s, respectively). These data therefore confirm the expectation that par-
ticipants are more likely to construct a single episode model from a series
of familiar events than from a sequence of novel ones.
In addition, the effects of set size were contingent on the nature of the
protagonist. Specifically, verification times increased with the number of
events presented in a scene when the protagonist was described as “you”
(1.32 s vs. 1.41 s, when 1 vs. 3 events were presented, respectively). This
was not the case, however, when hypothetical others were involved (1.40 s
vs. 1.33 s, respectively). Thus, participants were apparently less likely to
construct a single multiple-segment episode model of events that they
imagined themselves experiencing than events that they imagined an unfa-
miliar other experiencing, and this was true even when the situation de-
scribed was very familiar. These results suggest that the criteria that peo-
ple employ in comprehending self-referent events may differ from those
they apply when comprehending information about unfamiliar others. More
direct evidence of this difference (Colcombe & Wyer, 2002) is described in
chapter 6.

THE CONSTRUCTION OF GENERALIZED


NARRATIVE REPRESENTATIONS

Episode models of social experiences are presumably formed spontane-


ously in the course of comprehending them. However, more abstract narra-
tive representations of temporally related events exist in memory as well.
Unlike episode models, these generalized event representations are un-
likely to be constructed automatically. Rather, they are formed in the
course of conscious goal-directed activity that requires them. This activity
can potentially be of several types.
First, people who wish to tell others about an experience they have had or
a movie they have seen may describe the events that occurred in fairly gen-
eral terms. In pursuit of this objective, they may form a linguistically coded
representation of the events that is more abstract than the episode model
they formed of these events in the course of comprehending them, and may
store the representation it in memory independently of this model.
Second, people who have had a number of very similar experiences in a
given type of situation might form a generalized representation of the
events containing features that the experiences have in common but are
not specific as to time and place. Thus, for example, people might form a
general representation of the events that occur in a restaurant (looking at
the menu, ordering, eating, etc.) based on a number of specific experiences
in which the events have occurred. These generalized representations,
which have been referred to elsewhere as scripts (Schank & Abelson, 1977),
EPISODE MODELS AND GENERALIZED NARRATIVE REPRESENTATIONS 117

event prototypes (Colcombe & Wyer, 2002) or event schemas (Graesser &
Nakamura, 1982; Wyer & Srull, 1989), can function as implicit theories about
the events that occur in the type of situation at hand. As we note in the next
chapter, however, the abstraction of generalized representations from spe-
cific exemplars may occur less frequently than is often assumed. Colcombe
and Wyer (2002) showed that people typically do not form generalized nar-
rative representations of events on the basis of exemplars unless they are
exposed to several different exemplars of the generalized narrative in tem-
poral proximity. Even then, the abstraction may not occur unless people
are stimulated to think about the exemplars in relation to one another.
Thus, although generalized event representations undoubtedly exist in
memory, they may be constructed in other ways.
In fact, many generalized event representations might not be based on
personal experience at all. Rather, people might acquire a general under-
standing of the causal relations among event concepts through social learn-
ing, without directly experiencing the individual events that exemplify
these concepts. Thus, a child may be told that people who study hard get
good grades in school, and that these grades help them to get a good job
upon graduation. This sequence of events could constitute an implicit the-
ory that the child accepts without first-hand knowledge of any specific in-
stance in which the theory holds.
Finally, people may construct generalized event representations in the
course of making a judgment to which it is relevant. For example, people of-
ten wish to explain why a past event occurred, or to predict a future event.
Alternatively, they might wish to assess the desirability of a particular
course of action. These events could either be situation specific or more
general. For example, one might wish to explain either why a particular
friend got AIDs or, alternatively, why the incidence of AIDs in underdevel-
oped countries is increasing. Because the processes of constructing these
generalized representations are somewhat less obvious than the process of
constructing other types, these processes and their implications are worth
discussing in somewhat more detail.

General Considerations

To explain or predict a specific event, people might attempt to identify a


pre-existing episode model in which the event is embedded and use seg-
ments that precede or follow this event as bases for their inference. When
such a model does not exist, however, a two-stage process may be re-
quired. First, people identify a generalized propositional representation of
the event to be explained (i.e., “people get AIDs”). Then, having done so,
they search memory for propositions that describe possible antecedents of
it and, if they find one, they base their explanation on this proposition.
118 CHAPTER 5

The assumption that people spontaneously think about the antecedents


and consequences of an event is suggested by McGuire and McGuire (1991)
in conceptualizing the content and structure of thought systems. This con-
ceptualization, which was stimulated in part by McGuire’s (1960, 1981) ear-
lier work on the cognitive organization of propositional knowledge, as-
sumes that individuals who are intrinsically or extrinsically motivated to
construe the likelihood that an event will occur may search memory for an-
tecedents of the event (i.e., factors that will either facilitate or interfere with
the event’s occurrence). In contrast, individuals who are stimulated to con-
sider an event’s desirability are likely to ponder its consequences. In sup-
port of these assumptions, the McGuires found that when people were
asked to report their spontaneous thoughts about a target event (e.g., “a
vaccine to prevent AIDS will be developed”), 78% of their thoughts per-
tained to either antecedents of the event or consequences of it. Moreover,
providing information about others’ beliefs that an event would occur stim-
ulated participants to generate more thoughts about antecedents of the
event than about its consequences (56% vs. 22%), whereas providing infor-
mation about others’ estimates of the event’s desirability stimulated more
thoughts about its consequences than about its antecedents (55% vs. 31%).
The McGuires’ research does not indicate which of several antecedents
or consequences happens to be identified in the course of this cognitive ac-
tivity. However, when several alternative propositions (or, in some cases,
sets of propositions) could potentially describe a cause or effect of a target
event, people are likely to identify and use the one that is most accessible
in memory at the time (see chap. 3). The accessibility of such a proposition
presumably depends on the strength of its previously formed association
with the target or, if no prior association exists, on the frequency or re-
cency with which it has previously been identified and used for other pur-
poses (see Postulates 2.4 and 2.5). In either case, the identification of the
proposition establishes (or strengthens) an association between the propo-
sition and the target, and so the two propositions in combination may be
stored in memory as a unit, thus functioning as an implicit theory of the
sort described in chapter 1. The construction of this theory should have at
least two consequences. First, people who recall one proposition are likely
to recall the other as well. Second, they should be inclined to use the the-
ory that is constructed from the propositions as a basis for judgments to
which it is applicable.

Empirical Evidence

A study with Jon Hartwick (Wyer & Hartwick, 1984) confirmed these predic-
tions. Participants were first given a list of randomly ordered propositions
and instructed to indicate whether the propositions were understandable.
EPISODE MODELS AND GENERALIZED NARRATIVE REPRESENTATIONS 119

Thirty-two of the propositions comprised 16 pairs of assertions that occu-


pied the positions of A and B in a causal statement of the form, “If A, then
B.” Moreover, the likelihood that A was true, and the clarity of its implica-
tions for B, were systematically varied over the 16 pairs. (Thus, for exam-
ple, a pair in which A was likely to be true and that had clear implications
for B consisted of the statements, “Trucks conveying heavy cargo destroy
highways,” and “The weight limit on truck cargo will be decreased.” In con-
trast, a pair in which A was likely to be true and had unclear implications
for B was composed of the statements, “There will be no national borders
by the end of the year 2000” and “War will be a thing of the past by the end
of the [20th] century.”) This task presumably increased the accessibility of
the propositions in memory and, therefore, increased the likelihood that
participants would later identify and use them for purposes for which they
were applicable.
Participants then completed a two-part questionnaire in which they were
asked to report their beliefs in half of the propositions they had encoun-
tered in the comprehension task (i.e., the likelihood that the events de-
scribed would occur) and to estimate the desirability of the events de-
scribed in the remaining ones. This was done in such a way that for a given
A–B pair, participants reported either (a) their beliefs in both A and B, (b)
the desirability of both propositions, (c) their belief in A and the desirabil-
ity of B, or (d) their belief in B and the desirability of A. They were then dis-
missed but returned for a later session 1 week later, at which time they
were asked to recall as many of these propositions as they could.
We expected that participants who were asked to report their belief in B
would search memory for an antecedent of the event. Moreover, they
should use the first relevant antecedent that comes to mind (Postulate 3.1;
see Henninger & Wyer, 1976). Therefore, if A had been encountered in the
comprehension task and had clear implications for B, participants should
identify and use it as a basis for their judgment, thereby establishing an as-
sociation between A and B that might otherwise not have existed. Similarly,
participants who were asked to report the desirability of A should search
for a consequence and identify B, and this should also establish an associa-
tion between the two propositions. In contrast, participants who are asked
to report their belief in A should not identify B. Correspondingly, people
who are asked to estimate the desirability of B should not consider A. In
these conditions, therefore, an association between A and B should not be
formed.
The strength of association that participants formed between A and B in
the first session of the experiment should be reflected in their recall of the
propositions later. Specifically, suppose participants had established an as-
sociation between A and B. Then, if they recall B during the second session,
they should think of A as well. In other words, their likelihood of recalling A
120 CHAPTER 5

TABLE 5.1
Strength of Association Between Syllogistically Related Propositions as a Function
of the Plausibility of the Antecedent (A), the Clarity of its Implications for the
Consequence (B) and the Type of Ratings Made of A and B

Rating Made Rating Made


of Consequence (B) of Antecedent (A)

Characteristics of Antecedent (A) Likelihood Desirability Likelihood Desirability

Clear implications for consequence


Plausible .734 .505 .442 .798
Implausible .462 .156 .274 .345
Mean .598 .331 .358 .572
Unclear implications for consequence
Plausible .320 .439 .366 .393
Implausible .375 .402 .482 .295
Mean .347 .420 .424 .344

Note. Numbers refer to the difference between the probability of recalling A given that B was re-
called and the probability of recalling A given that B was not recalled. Adapted from Wyer and Hartwick
(1984).

if they recall B should be greater if they have recalled B than if they have
not. The difference between these two conditional probabilities therefore
provided an index of the strength of association that people had formed be-
tween A and B in the first session of the experiment.
This index is shown in Table 5.1 as a function of (a) the a priori likelihood
that A was true, (b) the clarity of A’s implications for B, and (c) the type of
rating that participants had made of the propositions in the first session of
the experiment (likelihood vs. desirability). When A had clear implications
for B, it was more strongly associated with B when participants had re-
ported either the likelihood that B was true (.598) or the desirability of A
(.572) than when they had reported either the likelihood that A was true
(.358) or the desirability of B (.331). When A’s implications for B were un-
clear, however, these contingencies were not apparent. Thus, when A’s im-
plications for B were not obvious, participants were less likely to recognize
their relatedness during the first session of the experiment, and so they
based their judgments on other criteria. As a result, an association between
the two propositions was not formed, and so their recall of B had no impact
on the likelihood of recalling A.

Other Determinants of Association

Wyer and Hartwick’s (1984) findings obviously did not provide a complete
picture of the associations that are formed among general propositions of
the sort that compose an implicit theory or implicational molecule. McGuire
EPISODE MODELS AND GENERALIZED NARRATIVE REPRESENTATIONS 121

and McGuire (1991) identified several other factors that can exert an influ-
ence on these associations. For example, they postulated that people are
likely to think about antecedents of events over which they feel they have
control, but are more inclined to think about consequences of events over
which they have little influence. Therefore, because people feel they have
more control over the events in their personal lives than over events in
the society at large, they tend to think about antecedents of personal life
events (e.g., having a paper rejected for publication) but are more likely
to think about consequences of social events (e.g., a terrorist bombing).
For possibly similar reasons, people are disposed to think about the ante-
cedents of events that are likely to occur in the distant future but to think
about the consequences of immediately impending events over which they
have less control.
Other motivational factors could also influence the type of associations
that people form. For example, people may be motivated to think about de-
sirable rather than undesirable consequences of events that are likely to
occur, and to think about factors that facilitate rather than inhibit the oc-
currence of events they consider desirable. Although the effects of these
factors were not consistently supported by the McGuires’ data, their poten-
tial importance should not be entirely dismissed.
Indeed, a study by Albarracin and Wyer (2001) provided evidence of
these effects. Briefly, participants who had been induced to feel either
happy or unhappy by writing about a past experience read a persuasive
message containing either strong or weak arguments in favor of performing
a particular behavior. This was done in either the presence or absence of
situational distraction. After reading the message, participants reported
their attitudes toward the behavior being advocated, followed by estimates
of the likelihood and desirability of specific behavioral consequences. Par-
ticipants who were not distracted based their beliefs and evaluations of the
consequences on the content of the message, and these beliefs and evalua-
tions determined their overall attitude toward the behavior. In contrast,
participants who were distracted from thinking about the communication
based their attitudes on the extraneous affect they were experiencing and
misattributed to their feelings about the behavior. Once these attitudes
were formed, however, they had reciprocal effects on outcome-related be-
liefs and evaluations. For example, participants with favorable attitudes re-
ported stronger beliefs that desirable consequences would occur, and re-
ported that likely-to-occur outcomes were more desirable.

The Construction of Implicational Molecules

Propositions that become associated as a result of the processes described


in this chapter constitute an implicit theory about the causal relatedness of
the events they describe that can be used to comprehend and make infer-
122 CHAPTER 5

ences about more specific experiences. A conceptualization of these infer-


ence processes was mentioned briefly in chapter 1. To reiterate, sets of gen-
eral propositions that become associatively linked in memory can form
implicational molecules that are stored in memory as conceptual units and,
therefore, can be brought to bear on the comprehension of new informa-
tion that exemplifies them (Abelson & Reich, 1969; Wyer & Carlston, 1979,
1994). In combination, the propositions that compose a molecule can exem-
plify a general principle that one uses to comprehend and make inferences
about the world in which one lives. Many types of molecules can potentially
exist.10 The molecules of primary concern in the present context consist of
two or more verbally coded propositions, each describing a different event
or state of affairs. In combination, the segments of a molecule exemplify a
generalization about the world in which we live. For example, the general-
ization that smoking causes lung cancer might be represented in the two-
segment molecule:

[P smokes; P has (will get) lung cancer].

Other generalizations may have moral overtones. For example, the general-
ization that people get what they deserve might be conveyed in a “just-
deserts” molecule; i.e.:

[P does a bad thing; P encounters misfortune]

or, alternatively,

[P does a good thing; P has good fortune].

Once implicational molecules are formed, they can be used to interpret


specific events to which they are applicable. This possibility is particularly
important when not all of the information that is necessary to instantiate
the propositions in a molecule is available. For example, people might use
the “smoking” molecule described earlier to infer that a person who
smokes will get lung cancer. Alternatively, they might infer that a person
they hear has lung cancer is a smoker. Similarly, they might use the just-
deserts molecule to infer that a person who stole money will be punished,
or that a person who was involved in a serious accident was likely to have

10
10 Not all implicational molecules pertain to events. Some, implied by cognitive balance the-
ory (Heider, 1957), may concern the sentiment relations among a group of individuals (Picek,
Sherman, & Shiffrin, 1975; Sentis & Burnstein, 1979). Other, “syllogism molecules” may specify
the logical relations among propositions (Loken & Wyer, 1983). These possibilities, and empiri-
cal evidence bearing on them, have been summarized elsewhere (cf. Wyer & Carlston, 1979,
1994).
EPISODE MODELS AND GENERALIZED NARRATIVE REPRESENTATIONS 123

done something wrong. A more formal statement of these inference proc-


esses is provided in chapter 10, where we discuss the impact of implicit the-
ories on judgments and decisions in some detail.
The associations that give rise to the construction of an implicational
molecule can often be formed as a result of the cooccurrence of its constitu-
ents in the course of comprehending information and making judgments.
However, they can also be motivationally determined. As Kunda (1990)
pointed out, people can often be motivated to believe that they have desir-
able attributes and that these attributes will allow them to have a happy
and successful life. Therefore, they may often construct implicit theories
and implicational molecules that confirm this belief. In doing so, they may
selectively attend to new information, and selectively seek and retrieve pre-
viously acquired knowledge, that confirms their desire to maintain a favor-
able view of themselves and their world. This possibility is elaborated in
chapter 10, where we consider the motivational factors that underlie the
construction and use of implicit theories in more detail.
C H A P T E R

6
The Impact of Generalized
Event Representations on
Comprehension and Memory

People construct at least two types of narrative representations of the


experiences they encounter in daily life. On one hand, they spontane-
ously form episode models in the course of comprehending specific events
they personally experience, observe, or read about. In addition, they may
intentionally form generalized representations of events in the pursuit of
a more specific objective that requires them. These latter representa-
tions can sometimes be abstract codings of events that that occur fre-
quently in certain types of situations and, therefore, constitute event proto-
types (Colcombe & Wyer, 2002) or schemata (Graesser & Nakamura, 1982).
They can also be linguistically coded descriptions of a specific experience
that people form in the course of communicating about the experience
to others.
Although generalized event representations and episode models are the-
oretically stored in memory as separate units of knowledge (Postulate 2.1),
they can obviously exert an influence on one another. For example, event
prototypes can be used as a basis for comprehending new experiences that
exemplify them and, therefore, can influence the mental representation that
is formed of these experiences. Moreover, an abstract narrative representa-
tion that is formed in the process of communicating about an experience
might later be recalled and used to attain other objectives to which it is rel-
evant, and this could be done without consulting the episode models on
which the representation was originally based.
The present chapter discusses these possibilities in detail and presents
data bearing on them. We first examine the role of prototypic event repre-

124
IMPACT OF GENERALIZED EVENT REPRESENTATIONS 125

sentations on the comprehension and representation of new experiences


that exemplify them. In doing so, we consider the conditions in which these
prototypes are formed and the extent to which they are actually used to
comprehend one’s own experiences and those of familiar others. Second,
we discuss the abstract representations that people form of a personal ex-
perience in the course of communicating about the experience to others,
and consider the way in which these representations can influence memory
for details of the experience being represented. Finally, we discuss the im-
plications of these communication phenomena for the impact of telling sto-
ries about oneself on self-perceptions. In this context, we consider differ-
ences in the storytelling that characterizes parent–child interactions in
different societies and discuss their implications for cultural differences in
self-perception.

THE ROLE OF PROTOTYPIC EVENT


REPRESENTATIONS IN THE COMPREHENSION
OF ONE’S OWN AND OTHERS’ EXPERIENCES

Many of the events that compose our daily life experiences are fairly rou-
tine. That is, they occur repeatedly, with minor variations, at many different
times and in many places. The events that typically occur in the course of
visiting a restaurant, cashing a check at the bank, or changing a flat tire,
and the sequence in which these activities take place, are fairly common-
place, and there is widespread agreement within a particular culture con-
cerning the events and when they occur. People may also engage in se-
quences of behaviors that, although idiosyncratic, they personally perform
routinely on a daily basis. For example, I typically get up at 5 a.m., brush my
teeth, do 30 sit-ups, and read a novel while drinking a cup of coffee. I then
walk the dog, return home and take a shower before beginning work at
about 8 a.m. This series of behaviors is unlikely to describe anyone but my-
self. Nevertheless, it is fairly invariant.
It might therefore seem intuitively likely that people construct general-
ized representations of sequences of events that they personally experi-
ence or observe others experience. However, these representations would
not have the character of an episode model. In particular, the events are
likely to be coded propositionally rather than in terms of mental images. To
the extent these event prototypes are formed, they seem likely to influence
the comprehension of new experiences that exemplify them. In fact, how-
ever, the conditions in which this influence occurs are more restricted than
one might expect. In the pages that follow, we consider the nature of these
restrictions.
126 CHAPTER 6

Preliminary Considerations

The assumption that people construct event prototypes is quite common in


research and theory on prose comprehension (e.g., Bower, Black, & Turner,
1979; Graesser, 1981; Graesser, Gordon, & Sawyer, 1979; Schank & Abelson,
1977). These representations are unlikely to be formed spontaneously, how-
ever. Rather, they are constructed in the pursuit of specific processing ob-
jectives that require them. This might be done in a manner similar to that
suggested by Hintzman’s (1986) conceptualization of the construction of
schematic representations from exemplars. Once such a representation is
formed, however, people store it in memory, and can later recall and use it
to comprehend new experiences to which it is applicable.
Several theories have been proposed to address these matters (Bower et
al., 1979; Graesser et al., 1979; Graesser & Nakamura, 1982; Trafimow &
Wyer, 1993). Most of these theories employ a principle of cognitive econ-
omy similar to that implied by Postulate 4.4. That is, they assume that when
people encounter a sequence of events that is redundant with the events
contained in an event prototype, they usually do not construct a detailed
representation of these events. Rather, they retain only enough features
that permit them to reconstruct the events that occurred on the basis of
the prototype. However, the theories make different assumptions about the
nature of the features that are retained.
For example, Graesser et al. (1979; see also Bower et al., 1979) assume
that when a sequence of events can be predicted on the basis of a more
general event prototype, people typically do not store a representation of
these events in memory at all. Rather, they store only a “pointer” to the pro-
totype (i.e., a set of retrieval cues that identify it) along with a set of transla-
tion rules that instantiate features of the prototype in terms of specific fea-
tures of the exemplar. Thus, suppose people read that Joe went to Dom’s
Patio Villa for dinner, ordered lasagna and a bottle of Chianti, and paid
$15.95 for the meal. They might not construct an episode model of the
events. Instead, they might store a pointer to a prototypic restaurant sce-
nario along with the translation rules, customer = “Joe,” restaurant =
“Dom’s,” meal = “lasagna,” drink = “Chianti,” etc. These translation rules,
along with the content of the prototype, would be sufficient to reconstruct
what had occurred. They could also be used to infer the occurrence of
other events that were not specified in the information but typically occur
in restaurants (e.g., that John looked at the menu or actually ate the meal).
Note that these inferred events cannot be distinguished in the representa-
tion from the events that were actually mentioned. As a result, errors may
occur in recalling the information later (Graesser et al., 1979).
A related conceptualization was proposed by Graesser and Nakamura
(1982). They suggest that when people read descriptions of events the
events that compose a prototype, they comprehend these events in terms
IMPACT OF GENERALIZED EVENT REPRESENTATIONS 127

of the prototype and copy them into the representation they form, in-
stantiating the generic features of the prototype in terms of specific ones
that are mentioned in the information. However, they do not include seg-
ments of the prototype to which the information does not refer. Thus, the
events that were specified in the information and those that were not men-
tioned can be more easily distinguished.
A limitation of both conceptualizations, however, surrounds the repre-
sentation of events that are not instantiations of the prototype. The occur-
rence of these events in daily life is less often the exception than the rule.
For example, a man who visits a restaurant is likely to look at the menu, or-
der the meal, eat and pay the bill. However, he might also ponder a painting
on the wall, say hello to a colleague who is seated at a nearby table, and
spill some of his wine on the tablecloth. The way in which these latter
events are integrated into the representation of the experience as a whole
is not clearly specified. In fact, the theories simply assume that the events
are appended to the representation as “tags.” To this extent, there would
be no way to reconstruct the point in the sequence that the events oc-
curred. In many cases, however, this reconstruction is obviously possible.
A conceptualization developed by David Trafimow (Trafimow & Wyer,
1993) eliminates this ambiguity. Trafimow, like Graesser et al. (1979), as-
sumes that people who encounter a sequence of events that exemplify a
prototypic sequence do not normally retain these events in the representa-
tion they form. However, there is an important exception to this rule. That
is, when a nonprototypic event occurs, people retain a prototypic event
that occurred in temporal proximity to it in order to localize its position in
the sequence. Thus, in our restaurant example, people who learn about
John’s visit to Dom’s might not normally retain the events that occurred.
However, suppose that while John was ordering his meal, he said hello to a
colleague at the next table. In this case, the person may retain a depiction
of John’s ordering the meal in the representation, thus permitting the point
at which the nonprototypic event took place to be reconstructed.

1. An Empirical Test

Trafimow designed an intriguing series of experiments to evaluate these


possibilities. Suppose that when participants interpret a sequence of events
in terms of a prototype, they only retain prototype-relevant events in the
representation they construct if these events are necessary to localize
nonprototypic ones. Then, the addition of nonprototypic events to a se-
quence should increase the number of prototypic ones that are retained
and, therefore, should increase the ability to recall these events at a later
point in time. On the other hand, suppose participants do not comprehend
the sequence in terms of a prototype, but rather, construct an episode
128 CHAPTER 6

model of the events. In this case, additional event descriptions are likely to
increase comprehension difficulty and, therefore, to decrease the likeli-
hood of retaining the presented events in the representation that is formed.
In other words, the addition of the nonprototypic events might decrease the
recall of the other, prototype-related ones. (Evidence that the likelihood of
recalling a given event decreases as the total number of events increases is
consistent with the set size effects observed in other research paradigms;
see Anderson & Bower, 1973; Srull & Brand, 1983.)
To evaluate this possibility, Trafimow and Wyer (1993) identified several
situations with which college students were familiar (e.g., cashing a check,
photocopying a piece of paper, making tea, etc.) and constructed six events
that typically occurred in each. The photocopying sequence, for example,
included “found the article,” “got some change,” “found a machine,”
“aligned the copy,” “put in the coins,” and “pressed the button.” However,
several of the events composing each sequence were not unique to the situ-
ation at hand, but could occur in other situations as well. Therefore, with-
out a prior indication of the situation being described, the nature of the sit-
uation was unlikely to be immediately identified. In addition to the
prototypic events, six unrelated events were identified that could plausibly
occur in the situation of concern (e.g., “remembered he had to return a
phone call,” “ate a piece of candy,” “saw a person he knew,” etc.).
Stimulus stories were then constructed by combining the prototype-
related events and the prototype-unrelated ones. In one experiment (Trafi-
mow & Wyer, 1993, Experiment 2), the stories contained four prototype-
related events and either two or six unrelated ones. In some cases, the
story was introduced with a statement that identified the situation (e.g.,
“John needed to photocopy a paper”) and in other cases, the situation was
not indicated until the end (“After he had photocopied the paper, John
left”). Participants read four stories that differed in terms of (a) the number
of prototype-unrelated events presented, and (b) whether the prototype
was identified at the outset or not until the end. Then, after a short delay,
they were asked to recall all of the events they had read about.
Results were quite consistent with expectations. When the situation was
not identified at the outset, participants were unlikely to identify and use a
prototype to comprehend the information. In this case, increasing the num-
ber of nonprototypic events presented decreased the proportion of proto-
typic events that were recalled (from .218 to .195, when 6 vs. 2 unrelated
events were presented, respectively). When the situation was identified at
the outset, however (thus stimulating participants to comprehend in the in-
formation in terms of a prototype), increasing the number of nonprototypic
events presented increased the proportion of prototypic events that partic-
ipants recalled (from .179 to .279 when 2 vs. 6 nonprototypic events were
presented).
IMPACT OF GENERALIZED EVENT REPRESENTATIONS 129

More subtle implications of the theory were also confirmed. For exam-
ple, if participants retain prototypic events in the representation in order to
localize the nonprototypic events, the associations they form between
these events should lead one event to cue the recall of the other. To this ex-
tent, participants’ recall of a prototypic event should be preceded by the re-
call of the nonprototypic event that came before it in the sequence. When
the prototypic situation was identified at the outset, this occurred with a
greater probability than would be expected by chance. When the situation
was not specified until the end of the story, however, this was not the case.
A more general prediction of the theory results from its implication that
when no prototypic-unrelated events are included in the sequence, no pro-
totypic events at all should be retained in the representation that is formed.
Under these conditions, participants theoretically have no way of distin-
guishing between the prototypic events that were presented and those that
were not. Consequently, participants should not only have poor recall of
the presented events but also should tend to recall events as presented
when they actually were not mentioned. On the other hand, suppose sev-
eral unrelated events are added to the representation, leading the pre-
sented prototype-related events to be retained. Then, these events can
later be distinguished from the prototypic events that were not presented,
and so intrusion errors should decrease. An additional study (Trafimow &
Wyer, 1993, Experiment 3) confirmed these predictions. Participants read
stories composed of four prototype-related events and either four unre-
lated events or no such events. When the situation was identified at the out-
set, participants recalled a greater proportion of prototypic events when
four unrelated events had been presented than when none had been pre-
sented (.21 vs. .13), confirming the results of the earlier study. At the same
time, the number of intrusion errors was significantly lower in the former
condition than the latter (0.25 vs. 0.96).

2. Methodological Implications

Trafimow and Wyer’s (1993) findings, which were replicated by Col-


combe and Wyer (2002, Experiment 1), provide evidence of the impact of us-
ing event prototypes to comprehend situation-specific sequences of events.
However, the conditions in which this occurs may be more limited than one
might expect. For one thing, prototypic event representations are usually
not formed spontaneously. Rather, they are only constructed in order to at-
tain a specific objective that requires them. Moreover, even if these repre-
sentations have been formed and stored in memory, they may not always
be retrieved and used. As we assumed in chapter 4, people who encounter
a situation-specific sequence of events are likely to comprehend it with ref-
erence to a pre-existing episode model of the person and/or type of event in
130 CHAPTER 6

question. To this extent, they might interpret one exemplar of a routinized


sequence of behavior in terms of another exemplar that happens to come
to mind quickly rather than a more abstract representation that is less
easily accessible in memory. (Thus, I might interpret a description of some-
one’s visit to McDonald’s in terms of an episode model of a personal experi-
ence I have recently had at McDonald’s rather than a more general repre-
sentation of fast-food restaurant visits.)
It can sometimes be difficult to distinguish between the use of an exem-
plar and the use of a more general prototype (Barsalou, 1990). If the conclu-
sions drawn from Trafimow’s studies are valid, however, the procedure he
employed can be used for this purpose. Specifically, the use of an exemplar
or an event prototype to interpret a sequence of thematically related
events can be inferred from the effect of introducing theme-unrelated
events on the recall of theme-related ones. That is, suppose the introduc-
tion of these events increases the likelihood of recalling theme-related
events (as Trafimow and Wyer found when a prototype was not made sa-
lient at the outset). This would indicate that an abstract representation of
the sequence was used to interpret. If the introduction of these events de-
creases the recall of theme-related ones, however, it would indicate that a
more general event representation was not used. The studies described in
the following pages are based on this reasoning.

When Are Prototypes Formed?

As we have speculated, the conditions in which people spontaneously ab-


stract generalized event representations from a number of exemplars could
be quite limited. A large number of exemplars may be necessary to stimu-
late the construction of a generalized event sequence. A study with Stan
Colcombe (Colcombe & Wyer, 2002, Experiment 2) demonstrated this possi-
bility. Materials for the study were similar to those employed by Gick and
Holyoak (1983) in research in analogical reasoning. Specifically, we con-
structed six different exemplars of a problem situation that could be re-
solved by applying the same “convergence” principle (i.e., several small en-
tities can do the work of one if they converge simultaneously on the task at
hand). One story described a problem of fixing some laboratory equipment:

A woman walked into her physics lab to find that a very rare and expensive
type of light bulb had been left on overnight, fusing the filaments inside the
bulb together. The woman knew that a sufficiently intense blast from an ultra-
sonic wave generator would be able to separate the filaments and thus render
the bulb useful again. Several of these wave generators were available. Unfor-
tunately, a blast from the generator at an intensity high enough to separate
the filaments would shatter the glass bulb surrounding the filaments. How-
ever, the physicist took several generators and set them to a relatively low in-
IMPACT OF GENERALIZED EVENT REPRESENTATIONS 131

tensity. After carefully positioning the wave generators in a circle around the
bulb, she simultaneously discharged all of them. This short blast from many
different sources at low intensity separated the filaments and preserved the
glass bulb. Thus, the light bulb was repaired, and the woman’s physics experi-
ments continued successfully.

A second scenario described the dismantling of a bomb:

Security police discovered that a terrorist had planted a bomb at a major


American airport. A bomb squad was called in to deal with the problem. Un-
fortunately, the type of bomb that the terrorists had planted was so sensitive
that it was almost impossible to defuse. The bomb squad knew that if they
could cool the bomb down to a very low temperature using liquid nitrogen, it
might be possible to defuse. However, if they cooled the bomb down un-
evenly or too quickly, it would definitely explode. The only cooling device
they had at the airport used a single large hose, and would deliver too much
liquid nitrogen at a single point, thus setting off the bomb. However, the bomb
squad used an attachment to split the single hose into several smaller tubes.
They positioned these tubes in a circle around the bomb. Then, they slowly
released the nitrogen through the many different tubes. Focusing all of the
small tubes on the bomb simultaneously cooled the bomb down slowly and
evenly, and so the bomb was able to be defused.

Three other stories concerned (a) putting out the fire in a burning wood-
shed, (b) taking over a corporation, and (c) extinguishing an oil well fire.
Participants were exposed to either one or five of these context stories
followed by a target story. The target, which concerned an attack on the
stronghold of an evil dictator, had four versions. Two versions described
four theme-related events and either two or six unrelated ones. Two other
versions described four theme-unrelated events and either two or six re-
lated ones. For example, a story containing six theme-related events and
four theme-unrelated events was:

A small country was under the rule of an evil dictator who was despised by
the people. The dictator lived in a fortress with many roads leading to it like
spokes in a wheel. The dictator was cruel. Rebels realized that they had enough
forces to overrun the fortress if they could attack all at once. The rebel general
noted that the weather had been turning colder lately. A rebel spy reported back
that the dictator had planted mines that would allow only a few men to pass
at once along the many roads leading to the fortress. Given that all of the reb-
el forces must attack the fortress at once, it seemed as though the rebels’
plans were foiled. Birds flocked in a nearby tree. However, the rebel general
was very smart and instructed his men to split up into several groups, each
taking a different road to the fortress. A dog howled in the distance. In these
small groups, the men could pass over the mines without setting them off and
132 CHAPTER 6

meet up again at the fortress. Thus, the rebels overthrew the dictator, and the
people in the kingdom lived happily ever after.

Participants were introduced to the study with instructions that we were


interested in how people understand the sort of information they read in sto-
ries and novels outside the laboratory, and that they should read the stories
as if they encountered them in a book. Participants read the stories in se-
quence, with the target story being at the end. Finally, after a 5-min filler task,
participants recalled the target story in as much detail as possible.
If participants constructed an episode model of the target story without
referring to the stories they had read earlier, the addition of theme-un-
related events should decrease their recall of theme-related ones. This was
the case when only one exemplar of the prototype preceded the target
story. That is, participants recalled a greater proportion of theme-related
events when six unrelated ones were presented (M = .50) than when only
two were presented (M = .80).When participants had been exposed to five
exemplars before reading the target story, however, they recalled a greater
proportion of theme-related events in the first condition than in the second
(.83 vs. .60, when two vs. six unrelated events were presented, respec-
tively). Thus, exposure to five exemplars of the convergence problem ap-
peared to stimulate the extraction of a prototype that, once it was formed,
was used to comprehend subsequent stories. However, a single exemplar
was insufficient to accomplish this.
Colcombe and Wyer’s study provides one of the first empirical demon-
strations that new prototypic representations are actually formed on the
basis of accumulated past experience. Research in other domains (e.g.,
Klein & Loftus, 1993; Klein, Loftus, Trafton, & Fuhrman, 1992; Sherman &
Klein, 1994) suggests that the likelihood of using trait concepts rather than
specific behaviors to describe individuals in a given life domain increases
with the amount of experience one has had in this domain. In only one of
these studies, however (Sherman & Klein, 1994), was the amount of experi-
ence experimentally manipulated, and in this study, participants were given
an implicit impression formation goal before they received information
about the person to be described. Therefore, these results do not bear on
the extent to which people spontaneously extract new prototypic represen-
tations in the course of comprehending information that exemplifies them.
On the other hand, the generalizeability of the conclusions drawn from
Colcombe and Wyer’s study may also be limited. For one thing, the exem-
plars to which participants were exposed were presented in temporal conti-
guity. Although participants were not explicitly told to think about the sto-
ries in relation to one another, their juxtaposition in the same situation may
have stimulated them to believe they were supposed to do so. In everyday
life, these situational demands do not arise. Visits to a restaurant, or obser-
IMPACT OF GENERALIZED EVENT REPRESENTATIONS 133

vations of a spouse’s actions when getting up in the morning, occur very


frequently. However, these experiences are temporally separated, and may
seldom be thought about in relation to one another. Consequently, al-
though Colcombe and Wyer’s (2002, Experiment 2) findings suggest that
prototypic event sequences can sometimes be formed from exemplars
when they are encountered within a short period of time, the conditions in
which this occurs in the absence of a specific goal that requires it may nev-
ertheless be more the exception than the rule. This is particularly true in
the case of personal experiences, to which we now turn.

The Role of Episode Models and Prototypes


in Comprehending Personal Experiences

Many of the behaviors we perform in daily life (e.g., getting up in the morn-
ing, washing the dinner dishes, etc.) occur repeatedly with minor varia-
tions. The behaviors we see others perform (e.g., my wife’s getting ready
for a party, or a roommate’s studying behavior) may also be fairly invari-
ant. It might seem reasonable to suppose that people spontaneously ex-
tract a prototypic representation of the routinized behavior that they later
apply in explaining a particular instance of the behavior and predicting its
consequences. People might also use prototypic representations of their
own behavior to predict what others will do (Ross, Greene, & House, 1977).
However, this is not necessarily the case. For one thing, the conditions in
which people form prototypic representations of their own and others’ be-
havior may be limited. The construction of these representations is pre-
sumably stimulated by the need to abstract features that are common to
several different exemplars. In daily life, however, people are seldom called
upon to consider their own behavior at one point in time in relation to their
behavior at a different time. This is particularly true if the behavior is rou-
tine. As we suggested earlier, many routinized behaviors may be governed
by a production (Anderson, 1983) that, once activated, is applied with little
if any conscious cognitive mediation. To this extent, the behaviors that oc-
cur at one point in time may seldom need to be thought about in relation to
similar behavior that occurred earlier. Moreover, even when this need
arises, a single prior instance of these behaviors may be sufficient. To know
what to do at a McDonald’s restaurant, for example, I only have to recall my
most recent visit to the restaurant. I do not need to retrieve a prototypic
representations of fast-food restaurant visits in general.
A familiar other’s routinized behavior may also not be comprehended
with reference to an abstract representation of the behavior. That is, an epi-
sode model of the behavior may be constructed on the basis of a previously
formed episode model of the sequence that has been stored in memory, as
suggested by Postulate 4.5. (Moreover, if the sequence is redundant with a
134 CHAPTER 6

previously constructed model, a new representation might not be formed


of it at all; see Postulate 4.4.) An episode model of the other’s past behavior
may also be sufficient for both explaining the individual’s present actions
and predicting his or her future ones. Therefore, the conditions that stimu-
late the construction of a generalized event representation of a familiar
other’s routinized behavior could also be very limited.

1. The Comprehension of Routinized Events


Involving Self and Others
Two studies by Colcombe and Wyer (2002, Experiments 3 and 4) confirm
these conjectures. In one study, participants in an initial session of the ex-
periment were asked to list both (a) sequences of activities that they per-
formed on a daily basis and (b) sequences that they observed their mother
and their father perform regularly. Then, in a second session 1 week later,
we asked them to read four stories. One story was based on a routinized se-
quence of behaviors they had personally reported in Session 1, and a sec-
ond was based on the routinized activities that a different participant had
reported. A third story described activities that either their mother or their
father routinely performed, and the fourth was based on the activities of an-
other participant’s parent. Each story consisted of four routinized events
and either two or six events that were not part of the routine. Participants
in reading the stories were told to imagine that they (or one of their par-
ents) were performing the activities. Then, after a short delay, they were
asked to recall the stories they had read.
Results summarized in Table 6.1 are very clear. Participants consistently
recalled fewer routinized events when six novel behaviors were contained
in the story (M = .49) than when only two were contained in it (M = .60).
Moreover, this was true regardless of whether the stories pertained to

TABLE 6.1
Proportion of Routinized Events Recalled as a Function
of the Source of the Story, the Referent of the Story,
and the Number of Nonroutinized Events Presented

Source of Story

Self Different Person

Stories about self


Two unrelated events .63 .51
Six unrelated events .49 .45
Stories about parent
Two unrelated events .70 .55
Six unrelated events .57 .45

Note. Based on data from Colcombe and Wyer (2002).


IMPACT OF GENERALIZED EVENT REPRESENTATIONS 135

themselves (.47 vs. .57) or a parent (.51 vs. .62), and regardless of whether
the stories were based on routines that participants themselves performed
(.53 vs. .67) or those that another had engaged in (.45 vs. .53). Thus, these
data suggest that participants did not use a generalized representation to
interpret either stories about themselves or stories about their parent.

2. The Use of Previously Formed Prototypes


to Comprehend Another’s Behavior
There are two possible reasons why participants did not use prototypic
representations in the preceding study. First, as noted earlier, people might
not form prototypic representations of their own and well-known others’
behaviors. Another possibility, however, is that these generalized represen-
tations may exist in memory, but people may simply not draw upon them
for use in comprehending new experiences involving themselves and famil-
iar others. A second series of studies support the latter possibility. Partici-
pants in these studies read stories similar to those employed by Trafimow
and Wyer (1993). That is, each story consisted of four behaviors that exem-
plified a prototypic script (cashing a check, changing a tire, etc.) and either
two or six prototype-unrelated behaviors. In one study (Colcombe & Wyer,
2002, Experiment 1), participants were told that the protagonist in the sto-
ries was a hypothetical person (“Joe”), as in Trafimow and Wyer’s original
studies. In a second experiment, however (Colcombe & Wyer, 2002, Experi-
ment 4), they were told to imagine that the story was about their roommate.
(In this study, the protagonist was referred to as “he” or “she,” depending
on whether participants were male or female, respectively). In all cases, the
situation to which the sequence pertained was identified at the outset, thus
ensuring that participants aware of the applicability of the prototype for
comprehending it.
Results of the study are summarized in Table 6.2. When the stories re-
ferred to a hypothetical person, Trafimow and Wyer’s (1993) findings were

TABLE 6.2
Mean Proportion of Prototype-Related and Prototype-Unrelated
Events Recalled as a Function of the Number of Unrelated
Events Mentioned in the Story and the Type of Protagonist

Protagonist

Unfamiliar Other Roommate

Number of prototype-unrelated events mentioned in story


Two events .30 .50
Six events .42 .39

Note. Based on Colcombe and Wyer (2002, Experiments 1 and 4).


136 CHAPTER 6

replicated. That is, participants recalled a greater proportion of prototype-


related events when six unrelated events were presented than when two
were presented (.42 vs. .30, respectively), confirming the fact that partici-
pants used a prototype to comprehend the story. When participants imag-
ined the events occurring to their roommate, however, their recall of the
prototype-related events was poorer when six unrelated events were pre-
sented than when two were presented (.39 vs. .50, respectively). In this
case, therefore, a prototypic event representation was not employed.

Concluding Remarks

Colcombe and Wyer’s findings suggest that even when a generalized event
representation exists in memory, people do not always use it to compre-
hend information about themselves or familiar others. This conclusion is
consistent with the retrieval postulates described earlier, and the results
reported by Wyer and Radvansky (1999). That is, people who receive infor-
mation about the behavior of a well-known person can often construct a sit-
uation-specific event model involving this person very quickly. This is par-
ticularly true if a previously formed event model of the person’s behavior
already exists in memory. In this case, they are likely to use this model as a
basis for comprehending the information rather than relying on more gen-
eral knowledge that comes less quickly to mind.
In retrospect, this conclusion is not surprising. Unless people have a rea-
son to think about different instances of their own or familiar others’ behav-
ior in relation to one another, they are unlikely to engage in this cognitive
activity. In making behavioral decisions, a previously formed episode
model of the behavior and its consequences can often serve just as well as
an abstract prototype. Moreover, as noted earlier, routinized behavior may
be governed by productions and performed with minimal cognitive media-
tion. The influence of these productions is particularly evident when one is
distracted by thinking about something else. (For example, a person who is
thinking about how to revise a paper while driving to the grocery store may
suddenly find himself about to enter his office parking lot. Similarly, a per-
son may often forget whether he has locked the door to the house before
leaving.) As Bargh (1997) contended, a very large proportion of our behav-
ior may be governed by automatic processes, and there is little need to use
a generalized representation of this behavior that we have stored as part of
declarative knowledge.
Circumstances can nevertheless arise in which a prototypic event for ex-
ample representation is personally useful. When a person’s behavior has
undesirable consequences, the individual might be motivated to avoid
these consequences in the future and, therefore, may attempt to explain it.
To generate this explanation, the person might retrieve a number of epi-
IMPACT OF GENERALIZED EVENT REPRESENTATIONS 137

sode models of past behavior in situations in which a similar outcome has


occurred, and might abstract commonalities in the behavior’s antecedents.
Similar attempts might be made when a behavioral outcome is unexpected.
This cognitive activity is unlikely to occur spontaneously, however, but in-
stead, is driven by Executor-governed processing objectives.

THE EFFECTS OF COMMUNICATING ABOUT


AN EXPERIENCE ON MEMORY AND JUDGMENT

Many abstract representations of experiences are formed in the course of so-


cial communication. People are often called upon to describe an experience
to others. These communications can sometimes describe a procedure (e.g.,
instructions about how to change a tire or use a photocopier). More gener-
ally, however, they concern a situation-specific experience (e.g., a personal
encounter one has had, or a movie one has recently seen) that one considers
of sufficient interest to relate. In order to generate these communications,
people presumably construct a linguistically coded representation of the ex-
perience and, once it is formed, store this representation in memory.
The representations that people form in the process of communicating
about an experience are presumably based on episode models that they
formed of the experience at the time it occurred. However, the representa-
tions differ in several respects from the models on which they are based.
Features that are tangentially relevant to the communication goals may be
omitted entirely. Others, which were represented visually in the episode
models, are characterized in more abstract, linguistic terms.
The specific content and structure of the representations that are
formed can depend in part on the communication objective at hand. When
the goal is to describe the experience itself, the communication is likely to
consist of verbal descriptions of the events that occurred (e.g., “captions”
of the sort that sometimes accompany the images contained in an event or
episode model). Suppose, however, that people want to convey their im-
pressions of the events or the individuals involved in them. Then, their
communications might not describe the events themselves, but rather,
might consist of more general trait descriptions along with characteriza-
tions of their own attitudes or opinions. In each case, the representation
that people form may reflect the content and structure of the communica-
tion they generate, and this representation may be stored in memory sepa-
rately from the more specific episode models of the original experiences
that were used to construct it (Postulate 2.1).
This possibility has further implications. As noted in chapter 3, people
who are called upon to make a judgment or decision are unlikely to retrieve
and use all of the information they have available in memory that is poten-
138 CHAPTER 6

tially relevant to this decision. Rather, they retrieve only a subset of this in-
formation and do not search further unless their confidence in the validity of
the information or its implications is below threshold (Postulate 3.1; see also
Chaiken, 1987). This “sufficiency” postulate was applied earlier in conceptual-
izing the effects of knowledge accessibility on judgments. However, it has im-
plications for memory as well. For example, if a generalized representation of
information has recently been formed in the course of attaining a specific
goal, this representation is likely to be used as a basis for not only making
judgments but also reconstructing the events that occurred. That is, the orig-
inal representation may only be consulted if the implications of the more re-
cently formed goal-specific representation are below confidence threshold.
A classic study by Loftus and Palmer (1974) provides an example. Some
participants who had been shown a picture of an automobile accident were
later asked to indicate how fast they thought the car was going when it “hit”
the tree. Others were asked how fast it was going when it “crashed into” the
tree. Participants estimated that the car was going faster in the second con-
dition than the first. Moreover, when later asked to remember details of the
picture they had seen, participants in the second condition were also more
likely to report (incorrectly) seeing broken glass at the scene of the acci-
dent. Participants apparently reconstructed the scene of the accident in a
way that was consistent with implications of the question they had been
asked, forming a new mental representation that contained features in addi-
tion to those that were conveyed in the picture. Their later memory was
then based on this newly formed image independently of the one they had
constructed at the time they saw the picture.
In Loftus and Palmer’s study, however, participants’ processing objec-
tive stimulated them to add features to the representation they had formed
initially. When people wish to describe an experience to others, the repre-
sentation they form is more likely to omit features that are of peripheral rel-
evance to the description they are providing. This could also decrease the
accuracy of recalling information under conditions in which this represen-
tation is consulted. In a study by Schooler and Engstler-Schooler (1990),
participants were shown a series of human faces and asked to describe
some of these events verbally. Later, they were given a memory test for the
faces. One might expect that the increased amount of processing involved
in describing the picture would make it more memorable. In fact, however,
participants were less accurate in identifying the faces they had described
than faces they had seen but not described. Participants who wrote an ab-
stract description of a face apparently formed a new representation of it in
which certain specific features that were useful in distinguishing it from
other faces were omitted, and then used this new representation, which
was less detailed than the original representation, as a basis for their later
recognition responses.
IMPACT OF GENERALIZED EVENT REPRESENTATIONS 139

Note that the abstract representation that is formed in the course of


communicating verbally about an event does not replace the original (Pos-
tulate 5.2). However, because it was formed more recently, it is typically
more accessible in memory, and might often be considered a sufficient ba-
sis for recognition responses without consulting the more detailed repre-
sentation on which it is based. If a goal-specific representation is consid-
ered irrelevant, or if participants’ confidence in the judgments implied by
the representation is below threshold, the more detailed representation
would presumably be retrieved and used.

The Impact of Communication Objectives


on Memory for Observed Experiences

Adaval and Wyer (2003) investigated the conditions in which episode mod-
els and goal-specific representations of social experiences were likely to be
activated and used as a basis for reconstructing these experiences. In doing
so, we considered the effects of two communication objectives that people
often have in daily life outside the laboratory: communicating a description
of the events to another, and conveying an impression of the persons in-
volved in the events. We compared the effect of introducing these goals at
the time the event were observed with the effect of introducing them later,
after episode models of the events had already been formed.

1. Procedure
Participants in two studies watched the opening 12 minutes of Edward
Albee’s Who’s Afraid of Virginia Woolf. The segment concerns a married cou-
ple who return home from a party and prepare for the visit of some late-
evening guests. The protagonists engage in an animated conversation in
which both positive and antagonistic comments are exchanged, thus leav-
ing the couple’s actual feelings toward one another unclear. Although the
protagonists’ nonverbal behaviors during the interaction (working on a
crossword puzzle, washing dishes, fixing drinks, cleaning up papers in the
living room, etc.) were relevant to a description of the sequence of events
that occurred, they were relatively incidental to the couple’s personalities.
Participants in some conditions watched the movie with no specific goal
in mind, much as if they saw it in a theatre. After doing so, however, partici-
pants in impression-description conditions were asked unexpectedly to write
a 5-min description of their impressions of the protagonists’ personalities,
whereas participants in event-description conditions were asked to spend 5
min describing the sequence of events that occurred. Two other groups of
participants were told they would be asked to perform these tasks before
they viewed the movie. Finally, participants under comprehension-only con-
ditions watched the movie without being given specific objectives either be-
140 CHAPTER 6

fore or afterwards. (These participants spent 5 min after watching the


movie writing a description of the university campus.)
After performing the writing task, participants were given a recognition
memory test, the nature of which differed in the two experiments. In Experi-
ment 1, participants were given verbal descriptions of statements and be-
haviors and asked in each case to indicate whether the statement or behav-
ior described had occurred in the movie. In Experiment 2, we extracted
both pictures of events that had occurred and acoustically recorded state-
ments that protagonists made and presented these stimuli (along with pic-
tures and utterances from other parts of the movie) on a computer with in-
structions to indicate whether the stimuli had occurred in the movie or not.

2. Predictions
Participants were expected to construct a multiple-segment episode
model of the movie in the course of comprehending it. In addition, partici-
pants with a communication objective should construct a more general, lin-
guistically coded representation in the process of generating their commu-
nication, the content of which depends on the particular goal being
pursued. Specifically, persons who described the sequence of events that
occurred were expected to include characterizations of not only things the
protagonists said but also things they did, as both types of events were rel-
evant to this description. However, only protagonists’ verbal statements
were particularly relevant to an understanding of their personalities. Thus,
participants who were told to convey their impressions of the protagonists
were likely to include trait descriptions in their representations along with
descriptions of protagonists’ statements that exemplified these descrip-
tions, but were unlikely to include nonverbal behaviors.
When participants in these conditions are asked to verify a recognition
item, they should first retrieve the goal-specific representation they have
formed, which is most accessible in memory. If they consider the content of
this representation to be a sufficient basis for evaluating the item, they
should use it without further ado (Postulate 3.1). If it is not, relevant, how-
ever, they should default to the episode models they formed at the time
they watched the movie.
Thus, suppose participants who have written a description of the se-
quence of events that occurred are asked to verify a recognition item. They
should consider the representation they formed in the course of generating
this description to be a sufficient basis for verifying both protagonists’
statements and their nonverbal behaviors. However, because this represen-
tation is less detailed than the episode models they had formed, they
should be less able to recognize both types of items than they would if they
had not used this representation. In contrast, participants who conveyed
their impressions of the protagonist should consider the representation
IMPACT OF GENERALIZED EVENT REPRESENTATIONS 141

they formed in the course of this activity to be sufficient for evaluating pro-
tagonists’ statements but not their nonverbal behaviors. Therefore, they
should resort to the use of episode models to verify these behaviors. Con-
sequently, although their recognition of protagonists’ statements should be
adversely affected by the goal-specific representation they formed, their
recognition of the protagonists’ behaviors should not be.

3. Results
The results of both studies were very similar and were generally consis-
tent with expectations. Table 6.3 shows the difference between recognition
accuracy under each communication objective condition and accuracy un-
der comprehension-only conditions.11 Writing a description of the sequence
of events that occurred decreased recognition of both protagonists’ state-
ments and their nonverbal behaviors, and this was true regardless of
whether participants had watched the movie with this objective in mind or
were not told of the objective until afterwards. In contrast, communicating
an impression of the protagonists only decreased participants’ recognition
of things the protagonists said and did not influence their memory for
things the protagonists did. Moreover, this decrease was only evident when
participants were not given an impression-formation objective until after
they had seen the movie.
The effects of objectives that participants had in mind at the time they
watched the movie deserve further attention. All of the statements and be-
havior that participants consider interesting enough to communicate to
others are likely to be of interest to themselves as well and, therefore, to be
represented in the episode models they would normally form spontane-
ously while watching the movie. Therefore, the content of the goal-specific
representation formed by participants with an event-description objective
should be similar regardless of whether they were aware of this objective at
the time they watched the movie or not. To this extent, the decrement in ac-
curacy that results from their use of this representation as a basis for rec-
ognition should not depend on when this objective was imposed. This was
the case, as Table 6.3 indicates.

11
11 The index of recognition accuracy used in Experiment 1, which corrects for guessing, is
given by the equation:
P(hit) - P(False Alarm)
P(Acc) = ,
1 - P(False Alarm)
where P(Hit) and P(False Alarm) are the probabilities of identifying an item as having been pre-
sented when it was or was not presented, respectively (Hilgard, 1951). This index could not be
applied to Experiment 2, as the number of nonpresented items was too small to obtain a reliable
index of P(False Alarm).
142 CHAPTER 6

TABLE 6.3
Effects of Communication Objectives, and the Point at Which
These Objectives Were Induced on Recognition of Protagonists’
Statements and Nonverbal Behaviors

Experiment 1 Experiment 2

Statements Behaviors Statements Behaviors

Event-description objectives
Induced before watching movie –.189a –.360 –.070 –.046
Induced after watching movie –.065 –.297 –.044 –.095
Impression-description objectives
Induced before watching movie .130 .000 .045 .046
Induced after watching movie –.108 .021 –.022 .046

Note. Based on Adaval and Wyer (2002).


aCell entries refer to differences between the accuracy obtained under each task-objective

condition and accuracy observed in comprehension-only conditions. In Experiment 1, accuracy


was based on the index proposed by Hilgard (1951); see Footnote 12. In Experiment 2, accuracy
was based on the proportion of correct responses to recognition items.

In contrast, participants who are told at the outset that they would be
asked to describe their impressions may include features in the representa-
tion they form while watching the movie that are relevant to their impres-
sions but are not depicted in the episode models they would form if they
were only trying to comprehend what is going on. The implications of these
additional features may then be included in the communication they gener-
ate later, and their recognition may benefit, as results also suggest.

Effects of Reminders on Recognition

Suppose people after seeing a movie or observing an interaction are later


reminded of the events that occurred. They are likely to comprehend this
reminder with reference to a previously formed representation of the origi-
nal experience. In the course of doing so, they presumably construct yet an-
other representation of what went on. According to the conceptualization
we propose, the content of this new representation, and its consequent ef-
fects on memory, may depend on the nature of the previously formed rep-
resentation that was used to interpret the reminder.
Adaval and Wyer (2003) investigated these possibilities in a study that
provides further support for the implications of Experiments 1 and 2. In this
study, participants who had watched the movie with instructions to com-
prehend it were then asked to describe their impressions of the protago-
nists. After doing so, however, they were dismissed with instructions to re-
turn the next day for a second session of the experiment. In this session,
IMPACT OF GENERALIZED EVENT REPRESENTATIONS 143

some participants were re-exposed to the audio portion of a 4-min portion


of the movie they had seen without the accompanying video. Others were
re-exposed to the video portion without the accompanying audio. Still oth-
ers received no reminder at all. Finally, all participants were given the ver-
bal recognition task administered in Experiment 1.
Based on the reasoning underlying our interpretation of the first two ex-
periments, we assumed that participants who received a video reminder of
the protagonists’ nonverbal behavior would find the goal-specific represen-
tation they had formed while reporting their impressions to be inapplicable
for comprehending it and, therefore, would retrieve and use the episode
models they had constructed at the time they first watched the movie. Be-
cause this model contains representations of things the protagonists said
as well as things they did, both types of events should be included in the
new representation they form. Therefore, if participants use this recently
formed representation as a basis for recognition, their memory for both
statements and behaviors should be facilitated.
However, suppose participants receive an auditory reminder. These par-
ticipants should consider the goal-specific representation they formed to
be sufficient for interpreting it, and should use it without bothering to con-
sult their episode models of the original movie. In this case, the new repre-
sentation they form should be similar in content to the goal-specific repre-
sentation they had formed earlier, containing only abstract depictions of
the protagonists’ statements. Consequently, this representation should not
benefit their later recognition of these statements relative to conditions in
which the reminder was not given.
Results are consistent with these conjectures. Relative to conditions in
which no reminder was given, a visual reminder increased the likelihood of
recognizing not only protagonists’ nonverbal behaviors (mean increase =
.110) but their statements as well (M = .056). However, a visual reminder had
relatively little effect on participants’ recognition of protagonists’ state-
ments (M = .035) and actually decreased their likelihood of recognizing pro-
tagonists’ behaviors (M = -.126).

General Conclusions

Adaval and Wyer’s studies provide evidence of the influence of goal-di-


rected processing of a social experience on later memory for this experi-
ence. Some caution should be taken in overgeneralizing our specific find-
ings. Impressions of the protagonists in the movie we presented were
conveyed largely through their statements to one another, and their non-
verbal behaviors were relatively incidental to these impressions. In many
social situations, individuals’ nonverbal behavior is likely to have a greater
impact on the impressions that people form of them. In these cases, com-
144 CHAPTER 6

municating impressions of the individuals might interfere with observers’


memory for their behavior as well as the statements they make.

The Effects of Storytelling on Self-Representations


and Social Identity

The effects of goal-relevant event representations on memory of the sort


that Adaval and Wyer identified have potentially much broader implica-
tions. People are often called upon to recount a past experience they have
had. In doing so, they may tailor their descriptions of the experience to the
values and expectations of their audience, omitting some aspects they be-
lieve the audience may consider unpalatable while elaborating on others
that the recipient may like (Higgins & Rholes, 1978). The representation
they form as a result of this communication may be stored in memory and,
therefore, is likely to be called upon again when they tell about the experi-
ence a second time. After repeated iterations of this process, a number of
copies of the more abstract, goal-directed representation are formed that
are more accessible in memory than the original. As a result, their likeli-
hood of recalling this original representation may be low.
In some cases, this process could have psychological benefits. For exam-
ple, a man who has experienced a traumatic event might have a vivid epi-
sode model of the experience that elicits considerable negative affect when
it is activated. In communicating about the event to others, however, he
presumably forms a more abstract representation of the event. A second
description of the event may be based on this recently formed representa-
tion, leading a still more general representation to be constructed. As the
representations that are formed in the course of repeated communications
about the event become more abstract, fewer emotion-eliciting features
may be retained in them, and so the man can ultimately recall and discuss
the episode without re-experiencing the emotions that occurred earlier. On
the other hand, the original episode model of the experience is retained in
memory, and can potentially be reactivated by a set of retrieval cues that
are unique to a configuration of the features contained in it. In such an
event, the man might find himself re-experiencing the emotions elicited by
the original events even after a period of time has elapsed.
This process has more general implications for the development of in-
dividuals’ perceptions of themselves and others, and for the norms and
values that guide their behavioral decisions. McAdams (1988) argued that
the stories people tell about themselves provide the main source of their
personal and social identity (see Mankowski & Rappaport, 1995, for a simi-
lar view). However, suppose people modify the content of the stories they
tell in order to comply with certain expectations or desires of the recipi-
ent, and the representations they form in the course of telling these sto-
IMPACT OF GENERALIZED EVENT REPRESENTATIONS 145

ries are stored in memory. These stories may then become the basis for
their self-perceptions. This means that the self-perceptions that people de-
velop are likely to depend on the type of situations in which they are typi-
cally called upon to tell stories about themselves and the expectations
that others have for the content of these stories. Two bodies of research
and theory bear on these processes. One concerns the impact of par-
ent–child interaction in the construction of self-stories. A second area of
research provides insight into cultural and situational influences on indi-
viduals’ personal and social identity.

The Construction of Narratives


in Parent–Child Interaction

The role of narratives in the acquisition of social knowledge is particularly


evident at early stages of social development. Much of the knowledge that
children acquire about themselves derives from the stories they tell about
themselves and others. The role of storytelling in early childhood has been
investigated intensively by both Katherine Nelson (1989, 1993; Nelson &
Greundel, 1981) and Peggy Miller (1994, 1995; Miller, Fung, & Mintz, 1996) in
the context of parent–child interaction. Nelson’s research has been con-
cerned with the storytelling process itself and its impact on the construc-
tion of social reality. Miller’s research is based on similar assumptions but
has focused on cultural differences in the stories that are exchanged be-
tween parents and children and the consequent impact of these differences
on the norms and values that children acquire.

1. Basic Processes

Both Nelson and Miller note that children’s generalized representations


of their personal experiences are often constructed in the course of interac-
tions with their parents. Young children typically do not have a built-in
mechanism for organizing their memories. Therefore, this organization is
often acquired through parent–child interactions in which the parent stimu-
lates the child to recount aspects of an experience by questioning the child
and providing prompts that fill in gaps in the sequence of events that took
place. In other words, the child and the parent “collaborate” in constructing
the story the child tells about his or her experience. The co-narrative that
emerges may be retained in memory and thus may constitute the child’s
“reality.” In short, the child’s “memory” for the experience may be largely a
construction of the parent, based on the parent’s perception of the experi-
ence, rather than a true reflection of the experience from the child’s own
point of view.
146 CHAPTER 6

Certain consequences of this process could be insidious. As Schank and


Abelson (1995) pointed out, children may learn in the course of collabora-
tive storytelling that certain types of events should be recounted but others
should not. To the extent these “edited” stories become part of the child’s
“reality,” they may be hard to modify later. The extent to which this is true
is often difficult to disentangle. For example, children may fail to include as-
pects of a parent’s abusive behavior when describing the interaction be-
cause of the fear of repercussions. To this extent, these instances of child
abuse might later be difficult to retrieve. At the same time, as Ceci and
Brucks (1993) pointed out, a prosecutor who wishes to make a conviction
might harass a child into reconstructing an incident of child abuse that may
in fact not have occurred, leading this “false memory” to become part of the
story that the child “remembers” as part of the original experience. (Similar
false memories may result from therapy; see Hyman & Loftus, 2002.)
Although our description of these processes focuses on the construction
of an abstract representation of a single event, prototypic event representa-
tions could be formed similarly. A parent, for example, may rehearse the
behavior a child should perform in a given social context in order to teach
the child “proper” behavior. Furthermore, this could be done without refer-
ence to specific instances that exemplify the behavior. The children’s per-
ceptions of causality as well as of morality (what behavior are generally
appropriate) could be learned through these processes. Miller’s work pro-
vides examples of this learning.

2. Cultural Differences in Storytelling


Peggy Miller (1995; Miller et al., 1996; Miller, Sandel, Liang, & Fung, 2001)
has analyzed cultural differences in self-perceptions in terms of differences
in the type of collaborative storytelling that characterized parent–child in-
teraction. In an analysis of storytelling involving both European American
and Taiwanese families (Miller et al., 1996; Miller et al., 2000; Miller, Wiley,
Fung, & Liang, 1997), she found that quite different attention was given to
positive and negative behaviors in the stories that children were encour-
aged to construct and retain about themselves. These differences are par-
ticularly evident in stories about misdeeds. For example, Chinese parents
and their children are more likely than their American counterparts to
make the child’s present misbehavior a central part of the story the child
tells, but to relate this behavior to past transgressions as well. Thus, the
self-stories that are likely to emerge from these parent–child co-narrations
were likely to be self-critical and to focus on the child’s responsibility for
the misdeed. Furthermore, by relating the child’s current misdeed to earlier
ones, the stories encouraged the development of a more general conceptu-
alization of the child’s undesirable behavior that had implications for his or
her moral character.
IMPACT OF GENERALIZED EVENT REPRESENTATIONS 147

However, American parent–child co-narratives were more often charac-


terized by a “self-favorability” bias (Miller et al., 2001). These stories fo-
cused much less frequently on a child’s past transgression, and when they
did, the transgression was treated humorously, portraying the child in a
positive light despite his or her misdeed. Thus, for example, one story con-
cerned a child who had written on the wall and lied about it. Although the
mother acknowledged the seriousness of the child’s negative act, she at the
same time made light of it in helping the child communicate about the act
to others. Another example:

Tommy and his older brother remembered being punished for some misdeed
committed a few days earlier, but none of the participants—Tommy’s brother
or mother—could remember what they had done wrong, a baffling if not incon-
ceivable state of affairs from a Taiwanese perspective. This practice of down
playing transgressions in the narrative medium seemed to be part of a wider
set of practices that [European American] caregivers used to protect their
children’s self esteem. (p. 168)

An equally or more important difference in Eastern and Asian story tell-


ing was evident in the stories that parents told about themselves. Taipai
mothers’ self-stories typically provided positive examples for the child to
emulate. As Miller et al. (2001) suggested:

. . . Taipai mothers’ goal seems to be to encourage their children to live up to


their own high standards by citing concrete examples of admirable behavior
from their own or other family members’ lives . . . [T]eaching by example is
one of several traditional Chinese socializing strategies . . . (p. 170)

In contrast, European-American mothers’ stories about themselves were


more likely to preserve the children’s self-esteem by reassuring them that
something they had done was not really all that bad, and that even admira-
ble persons were prone to error. Therefore, their stories typically conveyed
their own misdeeds as a way of indicating that they were also not perfect
and to err is human, rather than setting themselves up as standards to emu-
late. In this regard, many European-American parents were prone to tell
“hell rising” stories about times in their youth in which they had behaved in
willed and irresponsible ways. In contrast, there was not a single instance
of this type of story by Taiwanese parents.
In summary, the stories that European-American parents encouraged
children to tell about themselves were focused on positive events or, when
they concerned misdeeds, tended to treat them as humorous rather than a
potentially serious defect in the child’s general personality. Moreover,
American parents’ stories about themselves were intended to suggest that
they, like their children, were also not perfect. The implications of these
148 CHAPTER 6

stories, which emphasized positive outcomes while minimizing the serious-


ness of misdeeds, seem likely to induce a general “promotion focus” (Hig-
gins, 1997), that is, a tendency to attach importance to positive outcomes
with little concern about negative consequences of behavior.
Unlike Americans, Chinese parents encouraged their children to focus
their stories on their misdeeds and to acknowledge responsibility for them.
Moreover, parents’ stories about themselves established a high standard of
excellence that their children were encouraged to emulate. In combination,
these socialization practices seem likely to induce a “prevention focus,”
that is, a concern with negative consequences of behavior. These general
differences seem likely to stimulate the development of different implicit
theories about oneself as responsible for negative outcomes and, more-
over, in the desire to avoid these outcomes. In fact, this difference exists be-
tween European and Asian adults, and can have a profound impact on judg-
ments and behavior (cf. Aaker & Lee, 2001; Briley et al., 2000; see chap. 3).

Cultural Influences on Socialization

The narrative representations that individuals acquire about themselves


and others are transmitted directly through parent–child interaction. As
Miller et al.’s research testifies, the character of these individual narratives
can vary over cultures, and also over communities and subcultures within a
society. However, cultural differences can also exist in more general narra-
tive representations that individuals construct. Mankowski and Rappaport
(1995) noted that the norms and values that pervade societies are governed
by a shared cultural narrative that not only serves to guide behavior in spe-
cific situations but influences individuals’ feelings of personal and social
identity. As they indicated:

. . . the phenomena of identity development and change may be understood in


terms of the appropriation of shared narratives into one’s personal life story
on the one hand, and the creation of new narratives or modification of exist-
ing narratives on the other. (p. 213)

For example, a narrative that pervades American culture is exemplified


by the “Horatio Alger” myth of individuals who persevere and behave righ-
teously in the face of poverty and adversity ultimately overcome their hard-
ships and become affluent and respected citizens. This narrative implies a
standard of morality and behavior that influences many Americans’ values
and behavioral decisions. Stories with similar implications surround the
original settlers in America (e.g., the “Mayflower” stories) and the settle-
ment of the “Wild West.” (Interestingly, these stories have been modified to
such an extent over the years that they typically bear little resemblance to
the actual events that occurred; see Zinn, 1980.) The life stories of a reli-
IMPACT OF GENERALIZED EVENT REPRESENTATIONS 149

gious figure can also provide the basis for shared norms and values in soci-
eties in which the religion predominates.
The suggestion that individuals in a society share a dominant cultural
narrative does not imply that the entire narrative exists as such in the mind
of a single individual. Moreover, the influence of such a narrative on the
construction of self-narratives may not be completely conscious. Just as
features of the content of children’s self-stories are modified to conform to
the values of their parents or others to whom they are communicating, a
cultural narrative may imply general norms and values that individual’s
consider socially desirable and, therefore, influence the content of the sto-
ries that individuals construct about themselves, leading some things to be
emphasized and others to be omitted. This may be done without a clear un-
derstanding of the roots of these norms and values. Moreover, the func-
tional autonomy of cultural norms and values from their original content is
well established in Boorstin’s (1973) sociological analysis of the develop-
ment of American thought. (Thus, e.g., the conviction that individuals have
the right to own firearms is a remnant of a period in the development of the
American West in which law enforcement was either nonexistent or ineffec-
tive, and individuals were required to “take law into their own hands” in or-
der to survive.)
It seems reasonable to suppose that once self-narratives become tai-
lored to cultural norms and values, they are later retrieved without a con-
scious consideration of the personal experiences on which they are based.
Thus, they ultimately become regarded as “true” by the storytellers them-
selves. As a result, they become part of individuals’ self-identity (McAdams,
1988) that are told to one’s children and others independently of the origi-
nal narrative representations of the events that were formed at the time
they occurred.

CONCLUDING REMARKS

The influence of generalized narrative representations on memory clearly


depends on the nature of the representation and how it is used. When
event prototypes of the sort referred to elsewhere as scripts (Shank &
Abelson, 1977) or event schemas (Graesser, 1981) are brought to bear on
the comprehension of verbal descriptions of events involving fictitious indi-
viduals, they can influence the content of the representations formed of
these events and stored in memory. However, these prototypes are much
less likely to come into play in comprehending events that people imagine
themselves or familiar others experiencing.
Generalized representations of single experiences that people form in
the course of telling or writing about these experiences may have a more
150 CHAPTER 6

profound influence on the memory for these experiences. Moreover, to the


extent that these representations are later retrieved and used as a basis for
judgments of oneself and others, they may come to function as “reality,”
and thus can have a pervasive influence on self-perceptions, personal
norms, and values. We return to this possibility in chapter 10, where we dis-
cuss the impact of generalized narrative representations on judgments and
behavior in some detail.
C H A P T E R

7
Pragmatic Influences on the
Interpretation of Statements
Made in a Social Context

Event and episode models are constructed spontaneously in the course of


comprehending information about social events. These processes are auto-
matic. Try not to understand the statement, “The boy kicked the ball.” For a
native English speaker, this is very difficult. However, the processes involved
in comprehending such a statement, described in chapter 4, are obviously
not sufficient to extract meaning from the information one receives. This is
particularly true when the information is conveyed verbally. Many state-
ments make use of terms with which the recipient is unfamiliar. Others ap-
pear anomalous upon first consideration. For example, statements such as
“The haystack was important because the cloth would rip” can only be as-
signed meaning in the context of a larger body of knowledge (e.g., a discus-
sion of the hazards of parachuting; cf. Bransford et al., 1972). When such
statements are encountered, they are theoretically transmitted by the
Comprehender to the Work Space with an indication that they cannot be un-
derstood, thus stimulating Executor-monitored comprehension processes.
Still other considerations arise when information is conveyed in a social
context. A person’s comments to one another are often made with a partic-
ular goal in mind: to convey new information, to entertain, to persuade, to
criticize, or to self-promote. Recipients’ interpretation of these comments
can depend on their perception of the communicator’s objective. More gen-
erally, recipients must not only comprehend a statement’s literal meaning
but also identify its pragmatic implications. These implications can concern
not only the meaning that the communicator intends to transmit but also
more general feelings, attitudes, and personality characteristics that the
speaker does not always wish to reveal.

151
152 CHAPTER 7

The meaning that communicators intend to transmit and the meaning


that recipients extract from their messages can often differ. For example, a
person who comments, “George W. Bush’s foreign policy is certainly mak-
ing America popular overseas” might intend to be sarcastic, and to dispar-
age Bush’s policy and not to praise it. However, a recipient might not per-
ceive this intention. Alternatively, a professor who describes his graduate
assistant as “about as helpful as a well-trained chimpanzee” might intend to
convey that the assistant’s competence leaves something to be desired.
However, a listener might infer that the professor is rather nasty and an un-
pleasant person to work for. In short, the pragmatic implications of a com-
munication do not always correspond to either the literal meaning of the
message or the meaning that the communicator would like to transmit.
A conceptualization of communication and comprehension in daily life
situations must take into account both (a) the factors that influence com-
municators’ attempts to tailor their comments in a way that will attain
their objectives and (b) the factors that govern recipients’ comprehension
of these communications (see Wyer & Adaval, 2003). In this chapter, how-
ever, we focus primarily on the second set of factors. In doing so, we con-
sider two questions. First, what factors stimulate a recipient to think
about the pragmatic implications of a message rather than taking it liter-
ally? Second, how does a recipient identify the pragmatic implications of a
communicator’s message, and how do these implications, once identified,
affect the recipient’s reactions to it? As we will see, these reactions can be
reflected not only in judgments that are made on the basis of a message
but also the search for additional information that explains why the mes-
sage was transmitted.

GENERAL CONSIDERATIONS

People’s perceptions of the pragmatic implications of a message can often


be stimulated by their own goals in the situation at hand. A woman who
must decide whether to accept a date might want to know whether the invi-
tation reflects a genuine desire for her company or only a desire to have
sex. More generally, people who wish to form an impression of a person or
product on the basis of a communicator’s description of the referent may
need to assess the likelihood that this description is biased. They may at-
tempt to identify the pragmatic implications of the communicator’s mes-
sage in order to make this assessment.
On the other hand, people often spontaneously recognize that a state-
ment’s literal meaning is not the meaning the communicator actually in-
tends to convey. This occurs when the statement’s literal meaning violates
normative expectations for the content and style of communications that
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 153

are typically exchanged in the situation at hand. As Grice (1975) first


pointed out and others have since elaborated (e.g., Green, 1989; Higgins,
1981; Sperber & Wilson, 1986), social communications are governed by a set
of implicit principles that are applied by both the communicator in generat-
ing a message and the recipient in construing its implications. In informal
situations, for example, speakers are normally expected to be

1. informative—to convey new knowledge that the recipient does not al-
ready have and is likely to find interesting;
2. truthful—to convey correct information as the communicator sees it;
3. relevant—to say things that are related to the topic under discussion;
4. polite—to avoid offending the individuals to whom one is communicat-
ing; and
5. modest—to avoid unduly promoting oneself.

These normative principles are obviously not universal. A modesty


norm, for example, is applied less often in job interviews than in informal
conversations, and truthfulness is less likely to guide exchanges between a
customer and a used car salesman than a student’s discussions with a pro-
fessor. Moreover, certain types of situations may activate specific expecta-
tions for communicators to ingratiate, to try to persuade, or to be amusing.12
It seems reasonable to suppose that when people receive a communica-
tion whose literal implications appear to deviate from expectancies for the
content and style of messages that are typically conveyed in the situation in
which they occur, they attempt to reconcile this discrepancy. In doing so,
they often reinterpret the message, or the communicator’s purpose in
transmitting it, in a way that is more consistent with their expectations.
This, in turn, may require the recipients to consider the communication in
relation to other available information in the situation at hand. As a result,
they may have better recall of this information later, and may be more in-
clined to use it as a basis for judgment.
The assumption that people spontaneously recognize that a communica-
tion violates a normative principle is based in part on Postulate 4.6. Accord-
ing to this postulate, many statements are spontaneously recognized as ei-
ther redundant with prior knowledge (and thus in potential violation of a
norm to be informative) or false (and thus in potential violation of a norm

12
12 The expectations for communications in a social situation can pertain not only to the con-
tent of the messages that are exchanged but the style in which they are transmitted. The extent
to which parties to a conversation elaborate answers to one another’s questions, or ask ques-
tions in return, may influence perceptions of the communicators’ attitudes toward both the con-
versation and one another (Wyer, Swan, & Gruenfeld, 1995). Nonverbal behaviors can obviously
play a role as well, as we note later in this chapter.
154 CHAPTER 7

to convey valid information) in the course of comprehending them. In the


first two sections of this chapter, we discuss the identification of these two
types of norm violations in some detail and describe research bearing on
responses to these violations. The cognitive dynamics that underlie the rec-
ognition of other norm violations are discussed in later sections.
Before embarking on this discussion, however, the basic processes we
assume to underlie the identification are worth reviewing. As we noted in
chapter 4, situation models are likely to be formed of the states or events
described in a verbal communication. In addition, features of the situational
context in which a communication is made can activate representations of
previously encountered situations that share these features. This configura-
tion of common features may be responded to schematically, thus consti-
tuting a situational appraisal of the sort suggested by Lazarus (1982, 1991).
The situation-specific representations that give rise to this appraisal, how-
ever, contain other features that are not common to all of these representa-
tions but nevertheless fall within a circumscribed range of values. These
features, which could pertain to characteristics of statements and behav-
iors that have occurred in the situation, give rise to expectations for the fea-
tures that are likely to exist in new situations.
Thus, suppose a specific communication (statement or verbal utterance)
is encountered in a given situation. The Comprehender presumably con-
structs a representation of the statement’s literal meaning with reference to
previously formed knowledge representations and computes an estimate of
it similarity to these representations (S; see chap. 4). If this similarity is ei-
ther very high (S > TT ; see Postulate 4.6) or very low (S < TF), the
Comprehender appends a “tag” that denotes the statement as true (i.e., as
redundant with prior knowledge) or false (i.e., inconsistent with prior
knowledge) and transmits it to the Work Space along with a representation
of the message itself.
When the Executor encounters a tag that denotes the statement as true
or false, it instructs a special-purpose processing unit (e.g., the Encoder/Or-
ganizer) to compare the statement’s similarity index (S) to the range of val-
ues that are specified in the situational appraisal and, if it falls within this
range, accepts the statement’s literal meaning. If, however, the similarity in-
dex falls outside this range, the Executor directs the Encoder/Organizer to
construe other interpretations of the statement that are more compatible
with situation-based expectations.
Stripped of the cumbersome terminology imposed by the theory, this
conceptualization simply means that people may spontaneously recognize
that a statement violates normative principles that govern communications
of the sort that are usually transmitted in the situation at hand. When this
occurs, they attempt to determine the reason for this violation. In doing so,
they may reinterpret the statement, or the purpose for which it was con-
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 155

veyed, in a way that is more consistent with the principle that is violated—
that is, whether the statement is interpreted as redundant with prior knowl-
edge or is interpreted as false. We consider these two possibilities in turn.

RESPONSES TO UNINFORMATIVE MESSAGES

Suppose the representation of a statement that is transmitted to the Work


Space is tagged as “true” (Postulate 4.6) and, therefore, as redundant with
prior knowledge. If the representation is inconsistent with expectations for
communications that are encountered in the situation at hand, it may stim-
ulate attempts to explain its occurrence. This may involve two steps, as
shown in the right half of Fig. 7.1:

1. Recipients consider why the source of the statement might consider it


to be informative. For example, they might speculate that the source is
unaware of their knowledge. Or, they might infer that the source knows
of a reason why the statement might not be true, thus making a reaffir-
mation of its validity necessary.
2. If recipients conclude that the statement cannot possibly be false, they
may conjecture that it is not intended to convey information about its
referent per se, but rather, is to convey the source’s implicit attitude to-
ward the event or state described in the statement.

Thus, for example, suppose a man hears someone comment, “George W.


Bush is not a card-carrying member of the Ku Klux Klan.” He might never
before have considered this possibility, and might normally regard the
statement as going without saying. Therefore, if the statement is made un-
der conditions in which communications are expected to be informative,
the recipient might speculate that Bush might actually have been accused
of belonging to the Klan, thus making a denial of his membership informa-
tive. This inference, however, could plant a seed of doubt in the recipient’s
mind about Mr. Bush’s status that did not exist before the denial was made.
To this extent, the denial might actually increase the recipient’s belief that
Bush belongs to the organization or, at least is in sympathy with the organi-
zation’s principles.
On the other hand, suppose people overhear the comment “Americans
are not allowed to vote until they reach the age of 18.” To Americans, this is
common knowledge and, furthermore, could not possibly be false. Conse-
quently, recipients who consider the statement to be uninformative are un-
likely to speculate that it might actually be invalid. Instead, they are likely
to infer that the communicator is intending to convey an implicit attitude
toward the state of affairs described (“Americans are not allowed to vote
156
FIG. 7.1. Theoretical flow diagram of processing steps involved in identifying the implications of
statements that are recognized as true or false. The source and recipient of the statement are
denoted S and R, respectively.
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 157

until they reach the age of 18, and this is certainly a good thing,” or “Ameri-
cans are not allowed to vote until they reach the age of 18, whereas citizens
of other countries can vote much earlier.”). To this extent, recipients would
not change their belief in the validity of the statement, but instead might
change their attitude toward the state of affairs that the statement de-
scribes. Note, however, that these effects should only occur under condi-
tions in which uninformative communications are counternormative. When
the messages are not intended to convey new information, they should the-
oretically be taken at face value, and attempts to make them informative
should not be evident.

Effects of Uninformative Statements


on Recipients’ Beliefs

Gruenfeld and Wyer (1992) investigated implications of the preceding analy-


sis. Participants read a series of statements about social events. In some
cases, the statements asserted the validity of target propositions that col-
lege students were likely on a priori grounds to believe to be false (e.g.,
“The CIA is engaged in illegal drug trafficking,” “Lyndon Johnson was re-
sponsible for the assassination of President John F. Kennedy,” etc.). In
other cases, however, the statements denied the validity of these proposi-
tions (e.g., “The CIA is not engaged in illicit drug trafficking,” etc.) and,
therefore, were uninformative. Finally, some participants believed that that
the statements were taken from newspapers (whose purpose is to convey
new information), whereas others believed they were taken from an ency-
clopedia (whose purpose is to preserve archival knowledge). Participants
first judged the importance of the information conveyed in the statements.
Then, after doing so, they estimated their beliefs in both the target proposi-
tions and related ones (e.g., “The CIA engages in other illegal activities,”
“Lyndon Johnson was an enemy of John F. Kennedy,” etc.).
Statements that affirmed the validity of the propositions constituted new
information, whereas statements that denied their validity were redundant
with participants’ prior knowledge about the persons and events in ques-
tion. However, we expected that when participants were told that the state-
ments came from encyclopedias, they would accept the statements without
further consideration. In contrast, participants who were told that the state-
ments came from newspapers should assume that they were intended to be
informative and, therefore, might infer that there was some reason to sup-
pose that the propositions being denied were in fact true. To this extent,
they might actually increase their belief in these propositions.
This was in fact the case. Table 7.1 shows the difference between beliefs
in propositions under each experimental condition (reported along a 0–10
scale) and beliefs reported by control participants who were not exposed
158 CHAPTER 7

TABLE 7.1
Effects of Assertions on Beliefs in Target
Propositions and Related Propositions

Assertion Type

Affirmation Denial

Effect on beliefs in target proposition


Newspaper source 1.16* 1.06*
Encyclopedia source 1.81* 0.48
Effect on beliefs in related propositions
Newspaper source 1.15* 1.20*
Encyclopedia source 1.62* 0.91*

Note. Cell entries refer to differences between beliefs reported after exposure to an asser-
tion and context-free beliefs reported in the absence of the assertion. Differences denoted by as-
terisks are significantly greater than 0, p < .05. Adapted from Gruenfeld and Wyer (1992).

to either denials or affirmations. Affirmations that were taken from encyclo-


pedias increased participants’ beliefs that target propositions were true,
whereas denials had little effect. These effects confirm the assumption that
affirmations constituted new information but denials did not. News head-
lines that affirmed the validity of the target propositions also increased be-
liefs that the propositions were true. (This increase was somewhat less
than it was when the statements came from encyclopedias, suggesting that
participants perceived newspapers to be relatively less credible.) On the
other hand, denials of the propositions’ validity that were taken from news-
papers also increased participants’ beliefs that the propositions were true.
In fact, this increase was just as great as the increase produced by affirma-
tions! Thus, participants attempted to interpret denials in a way that made
them informative, leading them to infer that there might be some reason to
suppose that the propositions were true, and this led the statements to
have a boomerang effect.

Effects of Uninformative Statements on Attitudes

As noted earlier, however, some uninformative assertions cannot possibly


be false. In this case, participants’ attempts to make them informative could
lead them to infer that they are implicit expressions of opinion. To this ex-
tent, the assertions might influence participants’ estimates of the desirabil-
ity of the state of affairs being denied by the proposition rather than their
beliefs in their validity. Gruenfeld and Wyer (1992) reported evidence of this
as well. For example, exposure to the news headline, “Wearing seatbelts is
required by law in Illinois” significantly decreased participants’ opinion
that wearing seatbelts should be required. Similarly, exposure to the state-
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 159

ment, “Many food products are sold in plastic and styrofoam containers”
decreased subjects’ beliefs that there should be restrictions on the packag-
ing of food product, and exposure to “Not all college students drive Ameri-
can automobiles” increased beliefs that college students should drive these
automobiles.

General Implications

1. Communication and Persuasion


The conditions constructed by Gruenfeld and Wyer (1992) provide exam-
ples of innuendo effects of the sort that are used intentionally by propagan-
dists. Their use is particularly common in the political arena. For example,
a candidate might attempt to plant a seed of doubt about an opponent’s in-
tegrity, not by asserting that the opponent has engaged in illegal activities
but rather, by actually denying it. For example, the assertions “I personally
have no evidence that my opponent embezzled funds while serving as an
executive of General Motors,” or “I do not for one minute believe that my
opponent is a card-carrying member of the Ku Klux Klan,” which might nor-
mally go without saying, could stimulate people to suppose that the oppo-
nent if not an embezzler or a Klan member, is nonetheless likely to have en-
gaged in activities that give rise to these suspicions.
A perhaps more familiar instance of the intentional application of the in-
formativeness principle occurs in advertising. Suppose an advertisement
for Brand X asserts, “X contains no hydratropine.” Consumers may have no
idea what hydratropine is. In an attempt to make the statement informative,
however, they may infer that there is some reason why promoters of Brand
X made the statement. In particular, they may infer that (a) hydratropine is
undesirable and (b) other products have it. Correspondingly, the equally
meaningless assertion, “X contains hydratropine” might stimulate them to
infer that hydratropine is desirable and that brands other than X do not
have it.

2. Communication of Emotions
Similar effects occur in interpersonal communication. For example, a
woman might comment to her spouse, “It’s cold in here.” If she has rarely
complained about the room temperature in the past, her husband may re-
gard this as new information and take steps to remedy the situation. How-
ever, suppose the wife’s remark is one of many similar comments she has
made over a period of time. In this case, the husband would consider the
statement to convey little new information about his wife’s feelings. Rather,
he might infer that the statement is a veiled criticism of his compulsion to
save energy by keeping the thermostat at 65°F. As this example points out,
160 CHAPTER 7

the recognition of a statement as uninformative, and the construal of its in-


tended meaning, often requires a substantial amount of shared knowledge.
Watzlawick, Beavin, and Jackson (1967) noted that people in close relation-
ships often acquire a private meaning system that permits them to convey
thoughts and feelings of which other listeners are unaware. This shared
knowledge presumably has its impact through its mediating influence on
perceptions of one another’s statements as uninformative and the reinter-
pretation of their literal meaning that results from it.

REACTIONS TO COMMUNICATIONS
THAT ONE BELIEVES TO BE UNTRUE

Statements that are transmitted to the Work Space by the Comprehender


may often contain tags that identify them as false or, at least, inconsistent
with the implications of prior knowledge (Postulate 4.6). These statements,
like statements that are redundant with prior knowledge, are likely to stim-
ulate cognitive activity in an attempt to understand why they were made.
These processes may be similar to those that underlie responses to viola-
tions of the informativeness principle. However, the inferences that result
from the activity are somewhat different.
The processes that seem likely to underlie reactions to untrue communi-
cations can be summarized with reference to the left half of Fig. 7.1. Spe-
cifically, individuals who hear a statement they recognize as false (S < TF , as
defined in Postulate 4.6) are likely to assess whether the communicator
knows that this is the case. If the source is likely to believe it is true, the re-
cipients may take the statement’s literal implications at face value. They
might also do so if they think that the source knows the statement is false
but is unaware that they share this knowledge. In this case, they might con-
clude that the source is trying to deceive them. However, suppose recipi-
ents believe that the source is aware of their knowledge. Then, they are
likely to infer that the source does not mean the statement to be taken liter-
ally, but rather, intends it to be ironic.
Reactions to ironic statements can depend on both their topic and
whether their literal implications are favorable or unfavorable. In some
cases, ironic statements are intended to be funny. In other cases, however,
they can be indirect expressions of hostility. These motives are sometimes
difficult to distinguish. Suppose a woman whose husband has had three
traffic accidents in the past 2 years comments to her guests, “My husband
is a wonderful driver.” The comment could be a true expression of opinion,
and an attempt to defend her spouse’s abilities despite his poor driving re-
cord. To the extent it is intended to be sarcastic, however, it could either
convey hostility or be meant as a tease. Which interpretation the guests
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 161

make is likely to depend on their view of the woman’s more general feelings
toward her spouse. If they believe that the couple’s relationship is basically
harmonious, they are likely to infer that the woman is teasing. If the couple
is known to have a history of marital conflict, however, they might interpret
the statement as hostile.
These observations are rather self-evident. The conceptualization out-
lined in Fig. 7.1b has greater interest, however, when a statement’s validity
is clearly a matter of opinion. Suppose a person comments, “What this
country needs is another Ronald Reagan.” This comment is more likely to
be ironic if it is made by a liberal Democrat than if it is made by a conserva-
tive Republican. On the other hand, conservative Republicans are less
likely than liberal Democrats to interpret the statement as ironic. That is,
they are more likely to believe that the statement is true, and to accept its
literal meaning as the intended meaning regardless of its source.

Accuracy Violations and Amusement:


The Identification of Witticisms

To reiterate, people often interpret a statement spontaneously as false in


the course of comprehending it (Postulate 4.6). When it is obvious to recipi-
ents that the source also believes the statement to be false and, therefore
interpret the statement as ironic, they are often amused. This was demon-
strated empirically by Isbell, Wyer, and Collins (2002). Participants were ex-
posed to a number of vignettes in which one person made a comment to an-
other. In some cases, the comment was likely to be true. In other cases, the
comment was literally false, but if interpreted as ironic, was similar in
meaning to the first statement. Finally, in some cases, the intended meaning
of the statement was more favorable than its literal meaning, and in other
cases, it was less so. For example, one vignette described a discussion be-
tween two students about where they had spent the summer. In some ver-
sions, one student made a true statement that conveyed either a favorable
description of its referent (“Switzerland is certainly a great place to spend
the summer—all those lakes and high mountains”) or an unfavorable de-
scription (“Champaign, Illinois, is certainly an awful place to spend the sum-
mer—all that corn and high humidity”). In other cases, however, the stu-
dent’s statement was literally false (“Switzerland is certainly an awful place
to spend the summer . . . ,” and “Champaign, Illinois is certainly a great
place to spend the summer . . .”), but its intended meaning was similar to
that of the corresponding true statement. In another scenario, two profes-
sors discussed who was the most (or least) intelligent public figure in the
20th century. In this case, the literally true statements were “Einstein gets
my vote (for most intelligent)” and “Dan Quayle gets my vote (for least in-
telligent)” and the corresponding false statements were “Einstein gets my
162 CHAPTER 7

vote (for least intelligent)” and “Dan Quayle gets my vote (for most intelli-
gent).”
Participants read one version of each vignette with instructions to esti-
mate how amused they would be if they overheard the statement being
made under the conditions described. Pooled over vignettes, participants
regarded ironic statements as more amusing than literal ones (4.9 vs. 2.7),
and this was true regardless of whether the intended meaning of the state-
ments was favorable (4.6 vs. 1.9) or unfavorable (6.3 vs. 3.5).
It would obviously be incorrect to conclude that all ironic statements are
amusing. Sarcasm can often not be amusing at all. A person who has just
been turned in by a classmate for cheating on an exam might respond to
the other, “You are certainly a fine friend,” which is intended to convey
quite the opposite. This comment is unlikely to elicit amusement. The nec-
essary conditions for humor elicitation are discussed in chapter 8 (see also
Apter, 1982; Wyer & Collins, 1992). Nevertheless, the evidence that ironic
statements are more likely to elicit amusement than their true counterparts
is worth noting.

Effects of Invalid Communications


on Information Search

The sources of the ironic statements presented in Isbell and Wyer’s study
obviously believed that their statements were false, and so recipients were
likely to believe that the statements were intended to amuse. In many in-
stances, however, people are uncertain of a source’s beliefs in the state-
ments that he or she makes. This is particularly true when the statements
express opinions that are somewhat controversial. People who encounter
statements of opinion that they personally believe to be invalid may often
attempt to seek additional information that helps them to understand why
the statements were made. In addition, they may review their prior knowl-
edge about the issues to which the statements pertain in order to confirm
their belief that the opinion expressed is incorrect.
This cognitive activity is likely to be reflected in recipients’ ability to re-
call the information later. Information that is thought about more exten-
sively with reference to prior knowledge is generally easier to recall (Craik
& Lockhart, 1972; Wyer & Hartwick, 1980). If this is so, however, people
should be more likely to recall opinion statements they spontaneously rec-
ognize as false than either statements they consider to be true or state-
ments whose validity they have not spontaneously evaluated.
This possibility has not been investigated under conditions in which in-
formation is conveyed in conversations. If the proposed conceptualization
is valid, however, the cognitive activities that underlie people’s recall of
opinion statements they recognize as false should occur even when the
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 163

statements are conveyed out of their social context. Several studies bear on
this possibility. In a study of impression formation reported by Wyer, Lam-
bert, Budesheim, and Gruenfeld (1992), participants received information
about a target person who was characterized as either a conservative Re-
publican or a liberal Democrat and, in addition, was described by either fa-
vorable or unfavorable trait adjectives (e.g., “kind,” “hostile,” etc.). This
general description was followed by a list of both (a) behaviors that were
both evaluatively consistent and evaluatively inconsistent with the trait de-
scriptions (e.g., “invited a charity collector for lunch,” “shouted and honked
at slow drivers,” etc.), and (b) opinion statements that reflected either a lib-
eral or conservative political orientation. Participants after receiving the in-
formation were asked to recall the information they had read.
Participants were more likely to recall behaviors that were consistent
with the target person’s initial trait description than behaviors that were in-
consistent with it, replicating the results of many other studies (Hastie &
Kumar, 1979; for a review, see Srull & Wyer, 1989). However, they were more
likely to recall opinions with which they disagreed than opinions with
which they agreed, and this was true regardless of the consistency of these
opinions with the target’s political ideology. Thus, when participants en-
countered opinion statements about matters with which they were familiar,
they comprehended these statements with reference to their previously ac-
quired knowledge, and devoted a particular amount of time trying to under-
stand the basis for opinions they regarded as incorrect. Therefore, they
had better recall of these opinions regardless of the opinions’ consistency
with the general attitudes of the individual who expressed them.13

1. Individual Differences in the Processing


of Invalid Information

People obviously differ in the amount of cognitive effort they perform in


an attempt to reconcile information they consider to be invalid. Wänke and
Wyer (1996) speculated that differences in this motivation might vary with
participants’ own social and political ideology. Participants with a liberal
social and political orientation are inclined to consider the underlying
causes of a person’s behavior when evaluating a person (Fletcher, Dani-
lovics, Fernandez, Peterson, & Reeder, 1986). Conservatives, on the other
hand, are more disposed to evaluate a person’s behavior in terms of its

13
13 Wänke and Wyer (1994) found that participants had better recall of behaviors that were
ideologically inconsistent with the liberal or conservative orientation of the actor. However, this
occurred only when the actor’s ideology was different from participants’ own (i.e., when the ac-
tor was an “outgroup” member). When the actor’s ideology was the same as participants’ (i.e.,
the target was an “ingroup” member), participants’ recall of the target’s behavior was similar re-
gardless of whether it was inconsistent or consistent with his ideology (.42 vs. .48, respectively).
164 CHAPTER 7

consequences. Note that this difference corresponds to different levels of


moral development, as defined by Kohlberg (1976). (For other evidence that
liberals and conservatives differ in this regard, see Emler, Renwick, &
Malone, 1983; Fishkin, Keniston, & MacKinnon, 1973; Nassi, Abramowitz, &
Youmans, 1983.)
Based on this evidence, we expected that liberals would be more in-
clined than conservatives to consider the attitudes that underlie a person’s
behavior when forming an impression of the person. On the other hand,
conservatives should be more disposed to evaluate behaviors in terms of
their desirability without considering the attitudes and opinions they re-
flect. Furthermore, these individual differences should be particularly evi-
dent under conditions that emphasize the use of these different judgmental
criteria.
To evaluate this possibility, participants who had been identified as hav-
ing a liberal or conservative political orientation were exposed to informa-
tion about a target person who was initially described as either liberal or
conservative and who had ostensibly engaged in a number of behaviors
that were normatively either liberal (e.g., “organized a sit-in at a nuclear
power plant,” “raised money for a public housing project,” etc.) or conser-
vative (“tried to prevent a theatre from showing an antireligious movie,”
“donated $1,000 to the National Rifle Association,” etc.). In behavior-focus
conditions, participants were told that we were specifically interested in
how people form impressions of others on the basis of their behavior. In
opinion-focus conditions, they were told that we were interested in how peo-
ple form impressions of persons on the basis of their opinions as reflected
in their behavior. Participants after receiving the information and evaluat-
ing the target person were asked to recall the behaviors they had read and
finally, were asked to evaluate the desirability of the behaviors that were
described in the information they had received.
Table 7.2 shows the proportion of behaviors that liberals and conserva-
tives recalled as a function of their perceptions of the behaviors’ desirabil-
ity and the criterion they were asked to use in forming their impressions.
When liberals were told to base their impressions on the target person’s
opinions, they recalled a greater proportion of behaviors they considered
to be undesirable than behaviors they considered to be desirable (.64 vs.
.37, respectively). This was also true of conservatives who were told to
base their judgments on behaviors (.66 vs. .35, respectively). However,
this difference was not apparent when liberals were told to focus on the
target’s behaviors per se, or when conservatives were told to consider the
opinions underlying these behaviors. In short, participants only thought
more extensively about behaviors whose implications were considered
undesirable when they were told to employ the criterion that they were
likely to use spontaneously to evaluate these behaviors. When they were
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 165

TABLE 7.2
Mean Proportion of Behaviors Recalled as a Function of Perceived
Desirability, Participants’ Ideology, and Instructional Conditions

Opinion-Focus Conditions Behavior-Focus Conditions

Liberal Conservative Liberal Conservative


Participants Participants Participants Participants

Desirable behaviors .37 .39 .46 .35


Undesirable behaviors .64 .33 .54 .66
Difference –.27 .06 –.08 –.31

Note. Adapted from Wänke and Wyer (1996).

told to use a criterion that differed from the one they typically employed,
this spontaneous cognitive activity was disruptive, and so recall differ-
ences were not evident.

PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES ON IMPRESSION


FORMATION IN INFORMAL CONVERSATIONS

The pragmatic implications of communications are particularly likely to


come into play when the communications are exchanged in informal con-
versations. People may spontaneously identify the pragmatic implications
of a person’s comments when they perceive the comments to be either un-
informative or untrue. However, their identification of these implications
can also be motivated by more specific goals they have at the time they en-
gage in the conversation. People who observe or take part in a social inter-
action are often disposed to form general impressions of the interaction
participants. In some cases, they are likely to form these impressions spon-
taneously, without any more specific goal in mind other than to get to know
the individuals better. In other cases, they might do so intentionally in or-
der to interpret the individuals’ comments about the topic at hand. For ex-
ample, a person’s disparaging remarks about another could convey valid in-
formation about the individual being described. On the other hand, they
could also indicate that the speaker is an unpleasant individual who criti-
cizes others indiscriminately regardless of their merits. Similarly, a person
who expresses a favorable opinion of a new television program either could
have discriminating tastes or could like almost anything, including mindless
situation comedies that most people would find dull and offensive. In these
circumstances, listeners are likely to assess a speaker’s general personality
characteristics in order to construe the implications of his or her remarks.
These possibilities have largely been ignored in much of the research on
the cognitive underpinnings of person impressions (for reviews, see Ander-
166 CHAPTER 7

son, 1981; Carlston & Smith, 1996; Wyer & Carlston, 1994). In this research,
participants are usually asked to form an impression of someone on the ba-
sis of trait and behavior descriptions that are conveyed out of their social
context. In doing so, they are expected to take the information at face value,
independently of its source. To this extent, the implications of this research
for person impression formation outside the laboratory may be limited.
The research described in the remainder of this chapter calls attention
to several of these limitations. To provide a perspective on this research,
we first review briefly the conclusions that have been drawn in the typical
research paradigm in which person impression formation has been investi-
gated. We then describe the results of a number of studies in which similar
information is conveyed in the context of informal conversations under
conditions in which the pragmatic implications of the information is taken
into account. Finally, we describe the role of nonverbal and paralinguistic
features of the communications exchanged in a conversation that influence
recipients’ perceptions of their implications and, therefore, the impressions
they form of both the topic being discussed and the persons who are dis-
cussing it.

Impression Formation in Nonsocial Contexts

Extensive research has been conducted on the impressions that people


form of someone on the basis of information that describes the person’s
traits and behaviors, and rigorous theories have been proposed to describe
the processes that underlie these impressions (Carlston & Smith, 1996;
Wyer & Srull, 1989). In a typical study (cf. Srull, 1981; Wyer, Bodenhausen, &
Srull, 1984; for a review, see Srull & Wyer, 1989), participants are asked to
form an impression of a target person on the basis of a favorable or unfa-
vorable trait description followed by a number of behaviors. Some behav-
iors are descriptively and evaluatively consistent with the initial trait de-
scription of the person and others are inconsistent with this description.
The target person is typically fictitious, and the trait description is con-
veyed in a way that suggests that its validity is not open to question. (For
example, the person might ostensibly be a character in a novel, and the
trait adjectives might have been used by the author to describe him; see
Wyer & Martin, 1986.) The mental representation that is formed under these
conditions, which presumably exemplifies a generalized person representa-
tion of the sort described in chapter 1, has been conceptualized using an as-
sociative network metaphor (Hastie & Kumar, 1979; Srull & Wyer, 1989).
That is, the concepts formed from information are represented by nodes,
and associations between them (formed by thinking about the concepts in
relation to one another) are represented by pathways. Stronger associa-
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 167

tions, resulting from more extensive thought, are designated by wider


paths. The accumulated evidence (Srull & Wyer, 1989) suggests the follow-
ing process.14

1. People who receive an initial trait description of a target person form


an evaluative concept of him on the basis of this description. If they later
learn about specific behaviors the target has performed, they encode the be-
haviors as either favorable or unfavorable and think about their implications
for the concept they formed of him earlier. This establishes associations be-
tween the behaviors and this concept. Thus, suppose a person is described
by a set of favorable traits, followed by the following sequence of favorable
and unfavorable behaviors: b+, b+, b-, b+, b-, b-, b+. Then, a favorable con-
cept of the person, P+, is formed on the basis of the traits, and the behaviors
become associated with it as shown in Fig. 7.2.
2. When a behavior is encountered that is evaluatively inconsistent with
the central person concept, people attempt to understand why the behavior
occurred. In doing so, they think about the behavior with reference to other
behaviors the person has performed, establishing associations between the
inconsistent behavior and others. Assuming that each inconsistent behavior
(b-) in our example is thought about with reference to the two behaviors
that precede it in the sequence, the interbehavior associations would be
those shown in Fig. 7.2.
3. In addition, people who encounter behaviors that are inconsistent with
their general concept of the target attempt to bolster their confidence in the
validity of this concept. They do this by reviewing behaviors that are consis-
tent with it, strengthening the association of these behaviors with the con-
cept, as also shown in the figure.

Numerous studies provide support for this conceptualization and its im-
plications. For example, note that as a result of people’s attempts to recon-
cile the occurrence of a behavior that is inconsistent with their initial im-
pression of the person, the behavior becomes more interconnected to
other behaviors than the consistent behaviors are. To this extent, the be-
haviors may be more easily recalled. Bolstering, however, strengthens the

14
14 Srull and Wyer (1989; see also Gordon & Wyer, 1987) postulated that in addition to the proc-
esses described here, people interpret the behaviors they read about in terms of the traits they
exemplify, leading trait-behavior clusters to be formed and stored separately from the more
general person representation. The role of these clusters is of considerable importance in con-
ceptualizing a number of phenomena, including the mental representation information about
commercial products (Park & Wyer, 1993) and the impact of information one is told to disregard
(Wyer & Budesheim, 1987; Wyer & Unverzagt, 1985). However, these representations are not
central to the issues of concern in this chapter, so they are not described in detail.
168 CHAPTER 7

FIG. 7.2. Metaphorical representation formed of a target person described by


a set of favorable traits and a series of behaviors that are evaluatively consis-
tent (b+) or inconsistent (b-) with the person concept formed from these
traits. Thicker lines denote stronger associations between the elements in-
volved. Each inconsistent behavior is thought about in relation to the two be-
haviors that precede it in the sequence.

association of evaluatively consistent behaviors with the central concept,


making these behaviors more accessible in memory. Thus, the influence of
inconsistency resolution and bolstering should be reflected by the ease of
recalling of inconsistent and consistent behaviors, respectively.
Many studies (e.g., Hastie & Kumar, 1979; Srull, 1981; Srull, Lichtenstein,
& Rothbart, 1985; Wyer, Bodenhausen, & Srull, 1984) show that inconsistent
behaviors are recalled better than consistent ones, suggesting that incon-
sistency resolution takes priority over bolstering. (See Abelson, 1959, for a
similar assumption in conceptualizing the processes of resolving inconsis-
tencies among beliefs and attitudes.) However, when people are given more
time to think about the information they receive, either as it is presented or
subsequently, bolstering may predominate, leading consistent behavior to
gain a recall advantage (Wyer, Budesheim, Lambert, & Martin, 1989; Wyer &
Srull, 1989; see also Wyer & Martin, 1986).

Effects of Social Context on Impression


Formation Processes

The person memory model developed by Srull and Wyer (1989) has been
applied successfully in conceptualizing numerous social phenomena, in-
cluding the impact of information that one is told to disregard (Wyer &
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 169

Budesheim, 1987; Wyer & Unverzagt, 1985), the combined influence of ste-
reotypes and idiosyncratic trait descriptions on person impressions (Wyer
& Martin, 1986), and the different impressions that are formed of persons
and groups (Srull, 1981; Wyer & Gordon, 1982). Nevertheless, the processes
implied by the theory are restricted to conditions in which information is
presented out of its social context. Quite different considerations arise
when a person’s traits and behaviors are described in the context of a con-
versation. For one thing, an acquaintance’s trait descriptions of someone in
the course of a conversation are matters of opinion and, as such, may not
be valid. Consequently, listeners may attempt to establish the validity of
these descriptions. To do this, they may construe the implications of the
descriptions for characteristics of the speakers who provide them as well
as for the individual being described.
Wyer, Budesheim, and Lambert (1990) examined this possibility. In their
studies, the trait and behavior descriptions that participants received were
very similar to those presented in more traditional impression formation
research (e.g., Wyer, Bodenhausen, & Srull, 1984). However, the information
ostensibly pertained to an actual person and was provided by acquain-
tances of the person in the course of a conversation. Specifically, partici-
pants were told they would listen to a tape-recorded conversation between
a male and a female student about a mutual acquaintance. The tape began
with instructions to the two speakers to select the person they wanted to
talk about and then, after doing so, to write down three general attributes
they would use to describe this person. At this point, the tape stopped, and
the listeners were given photocopies of the trait adjectives the speakers
had had ostensibly written down. The favorableness of each speaker’s trait
description of the target and the dimension to which this description per-
tained (intelligence or kindness) were varied independently.
After participants had read the target descriptions, the taped conversa-
tion was restarted, and participants heard the experimenter tell the speakers
to reminisce about things the target person had done that they had either
seen or heard about. The speakers then proceeded to exchange anecdotes,
interspersed with occasional pauses and promptings by the experimenter to
make the conversation seem natural. Over the course of the conversation,
each speaker mentioned 13 behaviors of which 6 were favorable (either kind
or intelligent), 6 were unfavorable (unkind or unintelligent) and 1 (occurring
near the beginning of the conversation) was neutral. These behaviors were
very similar to those presented in studies by Wyer et al. (1984) and Wyer and
Martin (1986), but were conveyed as they might be mentioned in a normal
conversation. An excerpt of one conversation, about a target named Don,
was as follows (for a complete transcript, see Wyer et al. (1990):

Experimenter: Okay, then, why don’t we begin. Who wants to start off?
170 CHAPTER 7

M: Well, let’s see . . . well, he walks a mile to school each day, even when
it’s freezing. I guess I thought of that because it’s so damn cold today.
I asked him if he wanted a ride, but he said he didn’t.
F: Yeah, he never seems to get sick. It must be because he works out 3
or 4 times a week—he’s in pretty good shape.
M: [Laughs] Better than me, anyway. . . . I remember he won the univer-
sity chess championship last fall.
F: [Laughs] Yeah. . . . I remember we went out to dinner that night to
celebrate and Don swore at the waiter at Eddies because he didn’t
get served as quickly as he wanted.
M: Yeah, I can just see him doing that . . . let’s see . . . well, he can’t seem
to follow simple directions people give him. Remember that time last
week at Jerry’s?
F: Yeah, [Laughs] . . . Oh, by the way, do you know Jerry lost his job at
the Union?
M: No, really? Gee, that’s rough.
F: Yeah. I thought of that ’cause he told me Don had loaned him 20
bucks for a date he had and stuff.
M: [Pause] Jeez, this is a lot harder than I thought. [To experimenter]
You want specific behaviors, right? Like I know he’s always smiling
and saying hello to people when I walk down the street. But one par-
ticular instance doesn’t stand out.
Experimenter: Well, try to be as specific as you can.
M: [Pause] Hmm . . . well, let’s see . . . well, someone said he’d flunked a
mechanics training course I took last summer—I don’t know why he
took it, anyway.

The other tape was identical except that the roles of the male and female
speakers were reversed.
We anticipated that people who listened to the conversation would spon-
taneously form impressions of the speakers as well as the target himself. To
understand the nature of these different impressions, we employed two in-
structional conditions. In speaker-impression conditions, participants were
explicitly told to form impressions of the speakers, and in target-impression
conditions, they were told to form an impression of the person the speakers
were discussing. In both cases, however, participants after listening to the
tape reported their liking for the target person along a -5 to +5 scale. In ad-
dition, they reported their perception of how well each of the speakers
liked the target and rated their own liking for the speakers. Finally, they re-
called the behaviors they had heard the speakers mention.
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 171

1. Speaker-Impression Conditions
Judgment Data. Participants evaluated each speaker more favorably
when the speaker’s trait descriptions of the target were favorable than
when they were unfavorable. Moreover, they inferred that the speakers
liked the target to a greater extent in the former conditions. However, the
favorableness of the speakers’ trait descriptions had contrast effects on
participants’ own liking for the target. That is, partners liked the target less
when both speakers’ trait descriptions were favorable than when both de-
scriptions were unfavorable. In combination, these results suggest that par-
ticipants based their impressions of the speakers on the speakers’ trait de-
scription of the target and then used these impressions as standards of
comparison in judging their liking for the target himself, independently of
the implications of the trait descriptions for his attractiveness.

Recall Data. The recall data were particularly provocative. The propor-
tion of behaviors recalled are shown in the top section of Table 7.3 as a
function of the speaker who mentioned the behaviors and the consistency
of the behaviors with each speaker’s trait description. When the two speak-
ers’ descriptions of the target were evaluatively similar, participants had
better recall of behaviors that were inconsistent with these descriptions (M
= .444) than behaviors that were consistent with them (M = .391). When the
two speakers’ descriptions differed in favorableness, however, participants
had substantially better recall of the behaviors mentioned by a given
speaker that were inconsistent with the trait description of the target by
the other speaker than behaviors that were consistent with this description
(.520 vs. .416). Thus, both sets of data suggest that participants had better
recall of behaviors mentioned by one speaker if they were inconsistent with
the trait description provided by the other speaker than if they were consis-
tent with this description (.482 vs. .401).
Although these data are confusing on first consideration, their interpre-
tation is actually quite clear. That is, participants apparently used the
speakers’ trait descriptions to form impressions of the speakers, and then
used speakers’ descriptions of the target’s behaviors to confirm the validity
of these impressions. Note that if a behavior mentioned by one speaker is
evaluatively inconsistent with the trait description of the target provided
by the other speaker, this suggests that the description is not a valid char-
acterization of the target but rather, reflects a general disposition of the
speaker to describe people favorable or unfavorably. Thus, these behaviors
confirm the impression that participants formed of the speaker on the basis
of his or her description of the target. Participants who sought to confirm
this impression thought more about these behaviors and, therefore, re-
called the behaviors better.
172 CHAPTER 7

TABLE 7.3
Proportion of Behaviors Recalled as a Function of the Speaker Who
Mentioned Them and the Behaviors’ Evaluative Consistency
With Each Speaker’s Trait Description of the Target

Consistent With Inconsistent With


Female’s Trait Female’s Trait
Description of Description of
Target Target M

A. Speaker-impression conditions
Behaviors mentioned by male
Consistent with male’s trait description
of target .430 .514 .412
Inconsistent with male’s trait descrip-
tion of target .403 .438 .421
M .416 .476
Behaviors mentioned by female
Consistent with male’s trait description
of target .351 .430 .390
Inconsistent with male’s trait descrip-
tion of target .527 .451 .489
M .439 .441
B. Target-impression conditions
Behaviors mentioned by male
Consistent with male’s trait description
of target .396 .437 .416
Inconsistent with male’s trait descrip-
tion of target .422 .424 .423
M .409 .430
Behaviors mentioned by female
Consistent with male’s trait description
of target .437 .528 .482
Inconsistent with male’s trait descrip-
tion of target .409 .472 .441
M .423 .500

Note. In each quadrant of the table, diagonal cells are those in which the two speakers’ trait
descriptions of the target are evaluatively similar, and off-diagonal cells are those in which the
descriptions are evaluatively dissimilar. Adapted from Wyer, Budesheim, and Lambert (1992).

Thus, suppose the female speaker described the target in terms of fa-
vorable traits and the male described him in terms of unfavorable traits.
Then, the mental representation that presumably results from the cogni-
tive activity described in the preceding paragraph can be captured in an
associative network of the form shown in Fig. 7.3a, where F+ and M- refer
to concepts of the male and female speakers, respectively, and the favor-
able and unfavorable behaviors mentioned by the speakers are denoted
b+ and b-, respectively.
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 173

2. Target-Impression Conditions

In these conditions, participants were told to form an impression of the


target rather than of the speakers. Despite these instructions, the results
were very similar to those observed in speaker-impression conditions. For
example, the favorableness of the speaker’s initial trait descriptions of the
target influenced both participants’ perceptions that the speakers liked the
target (1.58 vs. -0.93, when both speakers’ trait descriptions were favorable
vs. unfavorable, respectively) and also participants’ liking for the speakers
(1.04 vs. -0.42, respectively). However, in contrast to earlier studies in
which trait descriptions of the target provided the primary basis for evalua-
tions of him (Srull & Wyer, 1989), participants liked the target less when
both speakers described him favorably (M = -0.33) than when they did not
(M = 0.75). Thus, these data, like those obtained in speaker-impression con-
ditions, indicate that participants used the speakers’ trait descriptions of
the target to form impressions of the speakers themselves, and then, hav-
ing done so, used their impressions of the speakers as comparative stan-
dards in evaluating the target without considering the favorableness of the
speakers’ trait descriptions for characteristics of the target himself.
The recall data in this study were also similar to those observed in
speaker-impression conditions except that in this case, participants were
primarily disposed to confirm their impression of the female speaker rather
than the male. These data are summarized in the bottom half of Table 7.3.
When both speakers’ trait descriptions of the target were similar in favor-
ableness, participants had somewhat better recall of behaviors that were
evaluatively inconsistent with these descriptions (M = .448) than behaviors
that were consistent with them (M = .417). When the two speakers’ descrip-
tions differed in favorableness, participants were more inclined to recall be-
haviors that were inconsistent with the female speaker’s description of the
target (M = .482) than behaviors that were consistent with these descrip-
tions (M = .416), and this was true regardless of whether the behaviors were
mentioned by the male or the female. Thus, both sets of data could suggest
that participants organized the information around an evaluative concept
of the female speaker. Thus, they thought more extensively about behav-
iors she had personally mentioned that were inconsistent with this concept
in an attempt to reconcile their occurrence. On the other hand, they
thought more about behaviors the other speaker mentioned that were in-
consistent with this concept and, therefore, bolstered their perception that
the female’s trait description of the target reflected a general disposition to
judge people favorably or unfavorably independently of the target’s actual
attributes. The representation that participants may have formed under
this condition, therefore, would resemble that shown in Fig. 7.3b.
174 CHAPTER 7

FIG. 7.3. Representations formed under conditions in which participants (a)


were told to form impressions of speakers and (b) were told to form impres-
sions of the target. F+ and M- denote favorable and unfavorable concepts of
the female and male speakers, respectively, and b+ and b- denote favorable
and unfavorable descriptions of the target’s behaviors, respectively.

3. Summary
Considered in combination, the results obtained under speaker-impres-
sion and target-impression conditions suggest that participants who over-
hear a conversation about a person are inclined to form impressions of the
speakers, and that this is true regardless of whether they are explicitly told
to do so or are asked to form an impression of the person the speakers are
discussing. Moreover, they tend to use the speakers’ descriptions of the tar-
get’s behavior to confirm these impressions. Then, once these impressions
are formed, participants use them as comparative standards in evaluating
the person the speakers are discussing rather than basing their impres-
sions on the literal implications of the speakers’ descriptions of him.
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 175

The Influence of Modesty and Politeness Norms


on Impression-Related Information Processing

1. General Considerations

Participants in informal conversations are expected not to offend the


people to whom they are communicating. They are also expected to be
modest and not to toot their own horns unnecessarily. Consequently, peo-
ple who hear someone make a statement that appears to violate one of
these norms may attempt to reinterpret it in a way that is more consistent
with their normative expectations. These processes may be similar to those
that result from violations of informativeness and truthfulness norms.
For example, the interpretation of a statement as hostile or a tease may
depend in part on whether the statement violates a norm to be polite. This,
in turn, may depend on whether the target of the statement is present at
the time the statement is made. Thus, for example, a person’s comment
that a colleague has trouble balancing his checkbook is likely to be seen as
a tease if the comment is directed to the colleague himself. In the col-
league’s absence, however, a politeness norm might not be applicable, and
so the statement is more likely to be interpreted as antagonistic.
However, the effects of politeness norms on comprehension are not in-
dependent of its effects on truthfulness. Shortly after the publication of my
1974 book on cognitive organization and change, a friend remarked, “Con-
gratulations on your book. I’m looking forward to the publication of the
English language version.”15 Because I interpreted the statement as a tease
rather than an expression of hostility, I found it amusing. However, this re-
action was probably diluted by my lack of confidence in my writing skills
and, therefore, my belief that the statement’s implications might be valid. If
I had had more confidence in my writing ability, I might have construed the
implications of the statement to be definitely false. I might then have appre-
ciated the irony much more.
A related implication of this analysis is that statements are more likely to
be interpreted as teases if their literal implications are extremely disparag-
ing than if they are less so. This is because they are more likely to be seen
as invalid. I may be more disturbed by a mildly negative comment about my
writing ability than by a comment that my writing is slightly superior to that
of a chimpanzee. This is because I am inclined to believe that the first re-
mark is valid and thus to take it literally, whereas I perceive that the second
statement is clearly invalid and therefore, interpret it as a tease.

15
15 Appreciation is extended to John McCarty for this example.
176 CHAPTER 7

2. Effects of Politeness and Modesty Norms


on Reactions to Information
The conceptualization we propose implies that people who perceive that
a communication violates a norm-based expectation may think about the
communication more extensively in an attempt to understand the reason it
occurred. The fact that people have better recall of opinion statements they
regard as invalid (Wyer et al., 1992) provides indirect evidence of this more
extensive processing when information violates a norm of accuracy. How-
ever, similar effects should be evident when other norms are violated. A se-
ries of studies by Wyer, Budesheim, Lambert, and Swan (1994) confirmed
this possibility.
Participants listened to a tape-recorded conversation that was ostensi-
bly between two male student volunteers who knew each other well. In con-
trast to the study by Wyer et al. (1990), however, this conversation was
about one of the participants rather than a third party. Over the course of
the conversation, one person (O) described both favorable and unfavorable
things that the other, target person (T) had performed, whereas the target
conveyed both favorable and unfavorable things that he personally had
done. Some participants were asked to form an impression of O on the ba-
sis of O’s description of the target (other-impression, other-focus conditions);
others were told to form an impression of the target based on O’s descrip-
tion of him (target-impression, other-focus conditions), and still others were
asked to form an impression of the target on the basis of the target’s de-
scriptions of himself (target-impression, target-focus conditions).
The tape was constructed in much the same way as the one employed
by Wyer et al. (1990). That is, it began with the experimenter giving in-
structions to the two conversation partners (referred to in the tape as Don
and Bob). After deciding which of the persons would be the topic of dis-
cussion, O was asked to write down three trait adjectives describing the
target, and T was asked to write down three adjectives describing himself.
The tape was then temporarily interrupted, and participants were given
either a favorable or unfavorable trait description of the target that was
ostensibly prepared by the person on whom they were told to focus their
attention. (Thus, they were given the target’s trait description of himself
under target-impression, target-focus condition, but were given O’s de-
scription of the target in the other two conditions.) The tape was then re-
started and the conversation was played in which the two participants ex-
changed anecdotes about T’s behaviors. These behaviors were identical
to those described by the two speakers in Wyer et al. (1990) with minor
variations. Thus, an excerpt analogous to the one employed in the earlier
study was as follows, where T and O refer to the target and the other
speaker, respectively:
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 177

Experimenter: Okay, then, why don’t we begin. Why don’t you start, Don?
O: Well, let’s see . . . well, you walk a mile to school each day, even when
it’s freezing. I guess I thought of that because it’s so damn cold today.
Every time I offer you a ride, you always say no.
T: Yeah, I never seem to get sick. It must be because I work out 3 or 4
times a week—I’m in pretty good shape.
O: [Laughs] Better than me, anyway. . . . I remember you won the uni-
versity chess championship last fall.
T: [Laughs] Yeah . . . I remember we went out to dinner that night to cel-
ebrate and I swore at the waiter at Eddies because I didn’t get served
as quickly as I wanted.
O: Yeah . . . I remember after we left, and we were supposed to go to
that party at Jerry’s, you were trying to follow the directions he’d
given you to get to his house and you got us totally lost! . . . Oh, by
the way, do you know Jerry lost his job at the Union?
T: No, really? Gee, that’s rough.
O: Yeah. I thought of that ’cause he told me you had loaned him 20
bucks for a date he had and stuff.
T: [Pause] Jeez, this is a lot harder than I thought. [To experimenter]
You want specific behaviors, right? Like I know I’m always smiling
and saying hello to people when I walk down the street. But one par-
ticular instance doesn’t stand out.
Experimenter: Well, try to be as specific as you can.
T: [Pause] Hmm . . . well, let’s see . . . well, I flunked a mechanics train-
ing course I took last summer—I don’t know why I took it, anyway.

Participants after hearing the conversation were asked to indicate how well
they liked the two speakers, and then were asked to recall as many of the
behaviors as they could.
We expected that participants would have better recall of statements
that O made that violated a politeness norm, but would have better recall of
statements the target mentioned that violated a modesty norm. This was in
fact the case. Table 7.4 shows the mean proportion of favorable and unfa-
vorable behaviors that participants recalled in each instructional condition
as a function of the person who mentioned them. Participants had better re-
call of behaviors that O mentioned if they were unfavorable than if they
were favorable (.49 vs. .39, respectively), but had better recall of behaviors
the target himself mentioned if they were favorable than if they were unfa-
vorable (.45 vs. .38, respectively). The first difference was more pronounced
when participants were explicitly told to focus their attention on the behav-
iors that O mentioned, and the second was more pronounced when partici-
178 CHAPTER 7

TABLE 7.4
Proportions of Favorable and Unfavorable Behaviors Recalled as a
Function of Task Objectives and the Person Who Mentioned Them

Task Objectives

Target Impression, Target Impression, Other Impression,


Target Focus Other Focus Other Focus

Behaviors mentioned by
other (O)
Favorable .42 .40 .35
Unfavorable .45 .54 .49
Behaviors mentioned by
target (T)
Favorable .47 .50 .37
Unfavorable .45 .54 .34

Note. Adapted from Wyer, Budesheim, Lambert, and Swan (1994).

pants were told to focus their attention on behaviors that T mentioned.


However, the differences were evident in all three instructional conditions
and did not depend on the favorableness of the initial trait descriptions that
the speakers provided. In other words, participants spontaneously thought
more extensively about comments that violated norms to be polite and
modest. Furthermore, this was true even when the comments were not di-
rectly relevant to the impression formation objectives that participants
were pursuing, and regardless of whether the statements were consistent
or inconsistent with more general trait descriptions of the target.

THE EFFECT OF NONVERBAL BEHAVIOR


AND CONVERSATIONAL STYLE
ON IMPRESSION FORMATION, JUDGMENT,
AND INFORMATION SEEKING

The studies by Wyer et al. (1990, 1994) provide evidence that people who
hear a conversation pay attention to the pragmatic implications of things
that are said about a person rather than to their literal implications. More-
over, they pay particular attention to statements that violate normative ex-
pectations for the sorts of statements that are typically made in the type of
situation at hand. However, these expectations can pertain not only to the
content of the information that is exchanged in the situation but also to how
it is exchanged. People often manifest nonverbal behaviors that lead recipi-
ents to infer that the information they convey has implications that differ
from those implied by its content alone. Moreover, the style in which peo-
ple conduct a conversation (e.g., whether they ask other participants ques-
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 179

tions or elaborate answers to others’ questions) could have implications


for both their interest in the conversation and their liking for the persons
with whom they are conversing. These implications, in turn, could influence
people’s impressions of both the topic under discussion and the discus-
sants. Two quite different sets of studies bear on these possibilities.

Nonverbal Influences on Perceptions


of a Message’s Implications

The nonverbal behaviors that accompany a person’s comments in a social


interaction can obviously have an impact on recipients’ interpretation of
these comments. An individual’s disparaging remark to another is more
likely to be interpreted as a tease if the communicator is smiling than if he
or she is not. The frequency and duration of eye contact can often be used
as an indication of feelings of intimacy and of the intensity of feelings that
are conveyed by a communicator’s statements and, therefore, can influence
the interpretation of these statements (Ellsworth & Carlsmith, 1968). Other,
less controlled behaviors (e.g., eye contact, voice pitch, etc.) can influence
recipients’ perceptions of the communicator’s truthfulness and, therefore,
the validity of the information being communicated (for summaries of the
impact of nonverbal behaviors on these and other perceptions, see De-
Paulo & Friedman, 1998).
A recipient’s perception of the validity of a message can also be inferred
from manifestations of uncertainty. Speech style characteristics that reflect
hesitancy (stammering, a high frequency of “uhhs” and “ers,” etc.) could re-
sult from lack of confidence in how the information should be conveyed. On
the other hand, recipients might misattribute these characteristics to lack
of confidence in the validity of the information itself. For example, a person
who has read a story that advocates a particular point of view might try to
convey its contents to someone who opposes this view in a way that the re-
cipient will not find too offensive. Similarly, a student’s dissertation advisor
might wish to convey the essence of a colleague’s devastating criticisms of
a thesis proposal to the candidate in a way that is substantively correct but
is more dispassionate in tone. The communicator’s difficulty in attaining
these objectives could be reflected in characteristics of his or her speech
style. However, these characteristics could be misinterpreted by the recipi-
ent as uncertainty about the validity of the information being conveyed.
Gruenfeld and Wyer (1993; reported in Wyer & Gruenfeld, 1995) demon-
strated these effects under conditions in which the difference between com-
municators’ objectives and the ostensible purpose of the original informa-
tion was unobtrusively manipulated. Participants read a passage describing
an unfamiliar disease. They were told that the passage had been taken from
either a newspaper (whose objective is presumably to convey new and in-
180 CHAPTER 7

teresting information) or an encyclopedia (whose goal is to preserve archi-


val knowledge). Regardless of the passage’s source, however, participants
after reading it were told to convey its content to a naïve recipient in a way
that was either as interesting as possible or as accurate as possible. Thus,
in some cases, the assumed objectives of the message’s original source and
those of the communicator were ostensibly similar, and other cases, these
objectives differed. After delivering the message (which was tape re-
corded), both communicators and naïve recipients evaluated the serious-
ness of the disease and reported their specific beliefs about its prognosis,
cause, and treatment. These latter beliefs were coded so that more positive
values indicated stronger beliefs in the content of the original passage.
Communicators’ own beliefs and opinions about the disease were not af-
fected by either the source of the passage or their own objectives in com-
municating it. Moreover, a content analysis of communicators’ speech re-
vealed no differences in the actual content of the information they
conveyed in different conditions. Nevertheless, communicators exhibited
more characteristics of poor speaking style (e.g., a greater frequency of
“uhhs” and “errs”), and took longer to deliver the speech (an indication of
rambling), when their communication objectives differed from those of the
original message source than when they were similar. Correspondingly, re-
cipients reported less strong beliefs and opinions about the disease and its
seriousness in the former condition than the latter.
These results are perhaps not too surprising. However, their importance
in the present context lies in their implications that communicators take
into account not only their own objectives in conveying a message but also
the pragmatic implications of the source of the information they are trans-
mitting, and that these factors combine to influence recipients’ perceptions
of the validity of the information being communicated.

The Impact of Conversational Style on Liking


for the Communicator

The speech style characteristics identified by Gruenfeld and Wyer seem


likely to influence reactions to communications exchanged in an actual con-
versation. In this context, they might influence participants’ impressions of
one another as well as the topic under discussion. Additional factors are
likely to come into play, however. People who engage in an informal con-
versation are typically expected to converse in a way that will make it easy
for others to respond. One obvious way of accomplishing this is to ask
questions of one another. A related technique is to elaborate answers to
one another’s questions, thereby increasing the likelihood that the re-
sponse will stimulate a relevant idea in the listener. These techniques may
be acquired through social learning and be applied spontaneously, without
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 181

much deliberation. When the techniques are not applied, however, recipi-
ents are likely to find the conversation awkward and difficult to conduct,
and these reactions could affect their liking both for the conversation itself
and for the other participants.
These effects are particularly likely to occur in get-acquainted conversa-
tions, where participants are motivated to learn about one another and to
identify areas of mutual interest. For example, suppose a participant in
such a conversation asks, “Where are you from?” If the other responds,
“Chicago. How about yourself?” the first person finds it quite easy to con-
tinue the dialogue. Alternatively, if the other responds, “Well, I live in Chi-
cago now, but I just moved here from Florida,” the questioner might be
stimulated to ask about Florida and why the person moved, or might de-
scribe his or her own recent visits to the state. However, suppose the other
simply responds “Chicago,” without elaborating or asking a question in re-
turn. Then, the first individual is burdened with the task of finding a differ-
ent topic to discuss or a different question to ask. This burden increases
the difficulty of continuing the conversation and this difficulty, in turn could
decrease the person’s liking for both the conversation and the interaction
partner.
But other factors can enter into the picture as well. An individual’s fail-
ure to elaborate answers to another’s questions, or the failure to ask ques-
tions in return, could also be interpreted as an indication that the individual
is not really interested in interacting with the questioner. This inference
could also decrease the questioner’s liking for the individual independently
of the effects of these conversational characteristics on the ease of con-
ducting the conversation per se.
Wyer, Swan, and Gruenfeld (1995) investigated these effects in a get-
acquainted conversation. College students who were previously unac-
quainted took part in the study in same-sex pairs. However, only one mem-
ber of each pair was assigned the role of the actual subject. The subject’s
partner was recruited as an accomplice. Subjects and their partners arrived
at the experiment in different rooms so they would not see one another
prior to the experiment. Subjects were told we were interested in how peo-
ple engage in get-acquainted conversations, and that they would be asked
to take part in a 5-minute conversation with another student much as they
might if they met the person for the first time at lunch or on a break be-
tween classes. However, we indicated that to ensure that some of the infor-
mation exchanged in each conversation was similar, we would like them to
ask their partner five questions at some point during the conversation:

1. Where are you from?


2. Do you like school?
3. Where do you live on campus?
182 CHAPTER 7

4. What is your major?


5. How are you doing in your classes?

Subjects were given a list of the questions as a reminder, but were told they
could ask them in any order and to work them into the conversation in a
way that seemed natural. They were further told that their partner did not
receive any questions but was being told simply to conduct the conversa-
tion as naturally as possible.
Partners were given similar instructions about the study’s purpose. How-
ever, we went on to indicate that people vary in the amount of information
they give when they are asked about themselves and in whether they ask
questions in return, and that we were interested in how these factors influ-
enced impressions. We then gave the partner the same list of five questions
we had given to the subject and indicated that when the subject asked
these questions, he or she should respond in one of four ways. In elabora-
tion, question-reciprocation conditions, partners were told:

We would like you to do two things when your partner asks you these ques-
tions. First, rather than simply answering the questions with a yes-or-no an-
swer, elaborate your answer in one or two sentences. Then, after doing so,
ask the other person the same question in return. For example, when your
partner asks you if you like school, you might say, “Yes, I like the social life
but the tests are hard. How about you?” Or, when you are asked where you
are from, you might say, “I’m from the North side of Chicago, but before that I
lived in Detroit. Where are you from?” Answer the questions truthfully, but
don’t go into too much detail. Keep your answer to one or two sentences, and
then ask your partner the same question that you were just asked. Except for
your responses to the five questions that I have passed out to you, however,
carry on the conversation as naturally as possible.

Under no-elaboration, question-reciprocation conditions, partners were


told to restrict their answers to one or two words but then to ask the other
the same question in return. Instructions in elaboration, no-question-recipro-
cation and no-elaboration, no-question-reciprocation conditions, were similar
to those in the first two conditions except that partners were told not to ask
a question in return.
The subject was then ushered into the partner’s room and seated on the
other side of a partition so they could not see one another. The participants
were then introduced and left alone for 5 minutes to engage in their conver-
sation. Then, after completing the interaction, participants were asked to in-
fer how much they enjoyed the conversation, how easy it was to conduct it,
and how much they thought they would like their partner if they got to
know him or her better. They also predicted how interested their partner
was in them as a person and how much they thought the partner liked
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 183

them. Finally, they judged the partner with respect to several personality
attributes. Of these, the most relevant to his or her behavior in the conver-
sation was aloofness.
We expected that both partners’ elaboration and their reciprocation of
questions would influence participants’ ease of conducting the conversa-
tion, and that this, in turn, would infer their liking for the conversation and,
as a result, their liking for the partner. However, we also speculated that if
subjects found that their partner did not elaborate and reciprocate their
questions, they would interpret this behavior as an indication that their
partner had little interest in the interaction and might not like them, and
that these perceptions might also influence their liking for their partner. In
fact, both possibilities were evident.
The effects of conversational style can be seen most easily from path
analyses. Figure 7.4 shows the significant paths connecting the two commu-
nication style characteristics to the participants’ estimates of the ease of
conducting the conversation (Ease), their enjoyment of the conversation
(Enjoy), their perceptions that their partner (O) was interested in them (O
int S) and liked them (O like S) and their liking for the partner (like O). Fe-
males’ perception of the ease of conducting the conversation influenced
both males’ and females’ liking for their partner through its mediating influ-
ence on both their enjoyment of the conversation and their inference that
the partner liked them. However, whereas males’ perception of the ease of
conducting the conversation was primarily a function of their partner’s re-
ciprocation of their questions, females’ perceptions were influenced pri-
marily by the degree to which their partner elaborated responses to their
questions. In addition, partners’ elaborations also affected subjects’ percep-
tions that the partner was interested in them, and this factor also increased
their liking for their partner. On the other hand, partner’s conversational
style had no impact on participants’ perceptions of their aloofness, nor did
these perceptions influence liking for the partners.
The gender differences obtained in the study are provocative. As Wyer
et al. (1995) point out, women are typically more motivated than men to es-
tablish a sense of “connectedness” to the persons with whom they interact
(Chodorow, 1979; Gilligan, 1982; Tannen, 1990).Their partners’ elaboration
of answers to their questions may have increased their feelings of
connectedness, as evidenced by its impact on these subjects’ perceptions
that their partner was interested in them and liked them. In contrast, males
placed less emphasis on these factors. Perhaps because they are less so-
cially skilled than females, however, they found that the ease of conducting
the conversation was easier when their partners asked them questions.
In summary, partners’ counternormative communication style influ-
enced both men’s and women’s liking for their partner through its mediat-
ing impact on their perception of ease of conducting the conversation. In
184 CHAPTER 7

FIG. 7.4. Path diagrams of the effects of the partner’s conversational style on
subjects’ liking for their partner (O) and the variables that mediate these ef-
fects. Elab = O’s elaboration of responses to the subject’ question. Quest = O’s
reciprocation of the subject’s question. Ease = subjects’ perception of the ease
of conducting the conversation. OintS = subjects’ perception that O was inter-
ested in them. O like S = subjects’ perception that O liked them, and like O =
subjects’ liking for the partner.

addition, females attributed their partner’s conversational style to a lack of


interest in them and this attribution was also a major determinant of their
liking for her.

Influence of Counternormative Conversational Style


on Information Seeking

We have assumed that when people encounter an expectancy-violating


communication, they are likely to search for other information that might
explain its occurrence. This cognitive activity may be reflected in the recall
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 185

of the counternormative messages that give rise to it, as suggested by Wyer


et al. (1994). However, the assumption has other implications as well. That
is, if people seek additional information in an attempt to explain counter-
normative messages, the information they identify in the course of this
search may have greater influence on their judgments than it otherwise
would.
Evidence of this possibility was obtained in a second study by Wyer et al.
(1995) under conditions similar to those described in the experiment just
described. That is, female participants first engaged in a get-acquainted
conversation with a female partner who responded to their questions by ei-
ther (a) both elaborating their answers and asking them questions in return
(normative-behavior conditions) or (b) neither elaborating nor reciprocating
the participant’ questions (counternormative-behavior conditions). Before
engaging in the conversation, however, some participants (ostensibly by
mistake) were exposed to a description of their partner that another partic-
ipant had provided in a previous experimental session. In some instances,
this description indicated that the partner was sociable—a trait to which the
partner’s conversational style was relevant and, therefore, could provide
an explanation for the partner’s behavior. In other cases, the description in-
dicated that the participant was high in integrity—an attribute that was irrel-
evant to the partner’s interaction behavior. Participants in a third, control
condition received no trait information at all.
We expected that when the partner’s responses to subjects’ questions
were normatively consistent with the behavior that was likely to occur in
get-acquainted conversations, subjects would base their liking for her on
the interaction and that the other’s description of her would have little im-
pact on these judgments. When the partner’s behavior was counternorma-
tive, however, participants should seek an explanation for it and, therefore,
should pay more attention to the trait descriptions. As a consequence,
these descriptions should have more impact on their liking for their part-
ners than would otherwise be the case.
Results confirmed these hypotheses. Subjects’ evaluations of the partner
are shown in Table 7.5 as a function of the partner’s conversational style
and the relevance of the target descriptions provided. When partners’ con-
versational style was normative, subjects evaluated her favorably regard-
less of whether trait descriptions of the partner were available. (In fact,
their evaluations were nonsignificantly less favorable when trait descrip-
tions were provided, suggesting that, if anything, the traits detracted from
the impact of the interaction.) When the partner’s behavior was counter-
normative, however, participants evaluated her relatively unfavorably
when no trait descriptions were provided, but trait descriptions substan-
tially increased their evaluations. Note that this was true even when the
traits were irrelevant to the target’s interaction behavior. In other words,
186 CHAPTER 7

TABLE 7.5
Subjects’ Liking for Their Partner as a Function of the Partner’s
Conversational Style and Initial Trait Description

Initial Trait Description of Partner

Conversation- Conversation-
Irrelevant Relevant None M

Normative conversational style 8.56 8.78 8.95 8.76


Counternormative conversational style 6.63 6.78 3.88 5.89
M 7.50 7.78 6.56

Note. Adapted from Wyer et al. (1995).

trait descriptions of the partner only had an influence on subjects’ evalua-


tions of her when her behavior in the conversation deviated from expecta-
tions and, therefore, stimulated subjects to seek other information that
might account for it. Moreover, this search led the information to have an
impact regardless of whether it was relevant or irrelevant to the explana-
tion that subjects were seeking.

PRAGMATIC COMMUNICATION
IN CLOSE RELATIONSHIPS

The discussion in this chapter has focused largely on the pragmatic influ-
ences of communications that are exchanged among casual acquaintances.
When people know one another very well, the pragmatic implications of
their shared messages may be difficult for others to discern. As noted ear-
lier, married couples can often convey feelings to one another through a
statement that seems quite innocuous to observers who are unaware of the
pool of shared knowledge that the partners bring to bear on its interpreta-
tion (Watzlawick et al., 1967). Thus, for example, a wife who asks her spouse
at a party what time it is might be interpreted as making a serious request
for information. However, it could be interpreted by her husband as an indi-
rect expression of anger because of his failure to leave the party early
enough for her to see David Letterman.
On the other hand, miscommunication often arises between partners in
close relationships as well as casual acquaintances. This is particularly true
in the case of emotions. One reason for this could be that the expression of
some emotions is inherently ambiguous. However, other factors play a role
as well. A study by Gaelick, Bodenhausen, and Wyer (1985) provided insight
into these possibilities. In an initial session of their experiment, married
couples engaged in a 10-minute tape-recorded discussion of a problem they
were having in their relationship. Then, in a second session, each partner
PRAGMATIC INFLUENCES 187

viewed the tape of the conversation and identified three statements that
were made in the conversation that had had an important effect on their
feelings toward one another. Finally, in a third session, partners reviewed
the segments of the tape containing the statements that both they and their
spouse had identified. Partners rated statements they had personally made
in terms of the feelings they intended to convey, their expectations for how
the partner would interpret the statements, and how they thought the part-
ner would respond. They rated statements their partner had made in terms
of the feelings their partner intended to convey, how their partner thought
they would respond, and their actual response. Factor analyses of these rat-
ings revealed they fell along two independent dimensions pertaining to love
and hostility.
Several interesting results emerged. In general, partners attempted to
convey the emotion they perceived their spouse had conveyed to them.
However, they were only accurate in perceiving their spouse’s hostility.
Consequently, feelings of hostility were actually reciprocated, but feelings
of love were not. One implication of this is that hostility was more likely to
escalate over the course of the conversation than feelings of love.
Second, when wives communicated in a way they intended to be
affectively neutral, their husbands interpreted their statements as expres-
sions of hostility. In contrast, when husbands communicated in a way they
intended to be neutral, their wives interpreted their statements as expres-
sions of love. Gaelick et al. (1985) interpreted these miscommunications in
terms of the stereotyped social role expectations that men and women hold
for one another. Specifically, women are expected to be loving and affec-
tionate. Therefore, when women responded in a way they intended to be
neutral, their husbands interpreted this counternormative comment as hos-
tile and, as noted earlier, were likely to respond hostilely in return. Men,
however, are expected to be hostile and aggressive. Consequently, when
they intended to convey neutral affect, their wives interpreted this expec-
tancy-deviant statement as an indication of love, and presumably recipro-
cated this emotion. Unfortunately, however, because expressions of love
were typically misperceived, these attempts to deescalate the conflict were
unlikely to do much good.

CONCLUDING REMARKS

Although this chapter has covered a lot of ground, it clearly does not pro-
vide a complete account of the factors that theoretically influence people’s
perceptions of the pragmatic implications of the information they receive in
social situations. For example, the extensive research on social attribution,
stimulated by theories of Jones and Davis (1965) and Kelley (1967, 1987),
188 CHAPTER 7

bears indirectly on the situational factors that influence the implications


that people draw from a person’s statements and behavior. Research on
characteristics of the source of information that affect the impact of this in-
formation (for a review, see Eagly & Chaiken, 1993) also makes salient the
need to take into account the influence of pragmatic factors (e.g., the inten-
tions of the communicator) in conceptualizing the nature of this influence.
A discussion of this research is beyond the scope of this volume. Neverthe-
less, the work we have summarized suffices to point out the importance of
understanding these processes in the context of actual social situations.
At the same time, the pragmatic influences of information cannot be un-
derstood independently of the more fundamental processes that underlie
the spontaneous comprehension of information and an identification of its
validity or its redundancy with prior knowledge. The extent to which prag-
matic implications of a message are taken into account often depends on
the recognition that the message’s literal implications violate expectations
for the content and form of communications that are likely to occur. In the
research we described in this chapter, these expectations typically derived
from people’s prior knowledge about either the topic of the communication
(and, therefore, whether the message was redundant with prior knowledge
or false) or, alternatively, the source of the communication and the type of
situation in which it is conveyed.
Expectations for the meaning of a communication can also be based on
prior communications that have been conveyed in the same situational
context. Moreover, initial portions of a message can establish expectations
that are violated by later portions. The communications we considered in
this chapter were typically single statements (news headlines, witticisms,
responses to questions, etc.). As we emphasized in earlier chapters, how-
ever, many communications that we experience in a social context consist
of sequences of thematically related events, or narratives. In these in-
stances, information that occurs early in a narrative provides a context for
interpreting aspects of the narrative that occurs subsequently. However,
when these latter aspects violate violates based on the context that was es-
tablished by earlier features of the information, special circumstances can
arise that have not yet been considered. The next chapter addresses these
circumstances in some detail.
C H A P T E R

8
The Dynamics of Humor Elicitation:
The Effects of Informational
Context on the Interpretation
and Elaboration of Narratives

The communications we considered in the previous chapter consisted


largely of single statements. The interpretation of these statements was
based largely on previously acquired knowledge about not only the topic to
which the statements pertained but also the type of situation in which the
statements were made. Similar factors come into play when information de-
scribes a temporally related sequence of events and is conveyed in the
form of a narrative or story. There are some additional considerations,
however. People theoretically comprehend descriptions of a series of
situationally constrained events or states of affairs by constructing an epi-
sode model of the sequence of occurrences as a whole. In doing so, the in-
terpretation they give to each description in the sequence is likely to be in-
fluenced in part by the concepts and knowledge that they have used to
interpret the earlier ones.
To give an example, consider the following pairs of statements:

A. The pilot was killed when his landing gear malfunctioned. Flying airplanes
can be dangerous.
B. Mary’s husband and children were killed when a plane overshot the run-
way and crashed into their home near the airport. Flying airplanes can be
dangerous.

The second statement in B is likely to be interpreted quite differently than


the second statement in A. This is presumably because readers draw upon
different concepts and knowledge in constructing an event model of the
first statement in each pair and, having done so, apply these concepts and
knowledge to the second statement as well.

189
190 CHAPTER 8

In some instances, however, the concepts and knowledge that are acti-
vated and used to interpret the events that occur at the beginning of a se-
quence cannot be applied to the events that come later. In such cases, re-
cipients must reinterpret the initial events in terms of different concepts in
order to construct a complete understanding of the sequence of events as a
whole. In the preceding example, suppose the statement, “Flying airplanes
can be dangerous” is presented first. An individual who happens to inter-
pret this statement as equivalent in meaning to “It can be dangerous to fly
an airplane” might then encounter the statement “Mary’s husband and chil-
dren were killed. . . .” To comprehend the information as a whole, the recipi-
ent would presumably reinterpret the first statement as referring to the
hazards of living near an airport.
The comprehension processes that are involved in this example are sim-
ilar to those described in chapter 7 when a statement violates normative ex-
pectations. The only difference is that the expectations are not only acti-
vated by the social context in which it occurs. In addition, they result from
the interpretation that has been given to other information in the communi-
cation in which the statement is embedded.
Reinterpretations can also occur in the course of comprehending direct
experiences. A waiter whose outward appearance gives the impression of
elegance and sophistication but who is observed to spill soup in a cus-
tomer’s lap may be reconceptualized as a pretentious oaf. However, reinter-
pretations of written or oral communications are more common. Particu-
larly frequent examples occur in jokes and stories whose punch line
stimulates a reinterpretation of the events leading up to it. For example,
consider the following story:

A young Catholic priest is walking through town when a prostitute accosts


him. “How about a quickie for twenty dollars?” she asks.
The priest, puzzled, shakes her off and continues on his way, only to be
stopped by another prostitute. “Twenty dollars for a quickie,” she offers.
Again, he breaks free and goes on up the street.
Later, as he is nearing his home in the country, he meets a nun outside her
convent. “Pardon me, sister,” he asks, “but what’s a quickie?”
“Twenty dollars,” she says, “The same as it is in town.”

The events described in the punch line of this story stimulate the reinter-
pretation of two features of the previous information. First, one’s character-
ization of the nun is revised to include her service as a prostitute. Second,
the question, “What’s a quickie?”, which was first assumed to be equivalent
to “What does a ‘quickie’ mean?”, is reinterpreted as equivalent to “What’s
a quickie cost?”
Not all reinterpretations of information elicit amusement, as our exam-
ple of flying airplanes testifies. In fact, the cognitive and motivational un-
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 191

derpinnings of humor elicitation are not widely understood. This is sur-


prising in light of the central role that humor plays in social communica-
tion. It is a rare conversation in which at least one participant does not
respond with amusement to another person’s comments or behavior.
Jokes, witticisms, and other humorous events are commonplace in social
interaction situations and can have an impact on the quality of the interac-
tions. Although jokes are often told for the purpose of entertaining, they
can also be used strategically to decrease tension in a heated discussion
(Kane, Suls, & Tedeschi, 1977) or to enliven a boring one. In short, the
transmission and comprehension of humor are central features of social
experience.
Theoretical and empirical analyses of social interaction processes have
largely ignored these processes. Several theories of humor elicitation have
been proposed, beginning with the work of Freud (1928, 1960). However,
most research on humor (for summaries, see Chapman & Foot, 1976, 1977;
Goldstein & McGhee, 1972; McGhee & Goldstein, 1983) has focused on its
motivational bases (cf. LaFave, Haddad, & Maeson, 1976; Zillman & Cantor,
1976) and its personality correlates (Lefcourt & Martin, 1986; Mindess et al.,
1985). Yet, only a few attempts have been made to explicate the cognitive
processes that underlie perceptions that something is funny (Apter, 1982;
Long & Graesser, 1988; Suls, 1972, 1977). And of these, only Apter’s concep-
tualization is applicable to situations in which humor is elicited spontane-
ously in informal social interaction.
In this chapter, we provide a theoretical analysis of humor elicitation in
the context of the comprehension processes we have described in earlier
chapters. Our theory avoids many of the deficiencies of existing formula-
tions while at the same time providing an example of the potential applica-
bility of our more general conceptualization of comprehension phenomena
to information processing outside the laboratory. According to this concep-
tualization, humor elicitation is a by-product of the comprehension proc-
esses postulated in chapter 4 and in some cases, of higher order compre-
hension processes similar to those discussed in chapter 7. As we have
noted, however, merely the reinterpretation of previously acquired infor-
mation in the light of new information is not a sufficient condition for hu-
mor elicitation. Thus, several additional factors not discussed in earlier
chapters must be taken into account. We first circumscribe the conditions
in which humor is spontaneously elicited by information that people re-
ceive and consider the effects of more deliberative, elaborative processes
that occur once the humor-eliciting interpretation of information has been
identified. We then apply the conceptualization to a specific area in which
an understanding of humor elicitation is particularly important, namely, the
amusement elicited by jokes and stories that perpetuate a social stereotype
or are likely to be considered offensive for other reasons.
192 CHAPTER 8

HISTORICAL BACKGROUND

To provide a perspective on the conceptualization to be proposed in this


chapter, a brief review of earlier theories of humor elicitation may be help-
ful. These theories fall into two categories, one of which focuses on the mo-
tivational antecedents of humor elicitation and the other of which concerns
the cognitive processes that give rise to it. Considered in isolation, each
theory is insufficient to account for the numerous circumstances in which
amusement may occur. (A possible exception to this rule is Apter’s [1982]
theory to be discussed presently.) Nevertheless, the factors that the vari-
ous theories postulate to influence humor elicitation are generally compati-
ble. That is, the factors postulated by several theories could contribute to
humor elicitation, although not necessarily for the reasons the theories as-
sume.

Motivational Theories of Humor

1. Arousal-Reduction Theories
Responses to humor have sometimes been conceptualized in terms of a
release of tension or reduction in arousal. According to Freud (1905/1960,
1928), for example, people’s responses to humor-eliciting stimulus events is
motivated by the need to reduce tension or arousal they are inhibited from
expressing directly. This arousal, which was often assumed to be aggres-
sion- or sex-related, might either be induced by the stimulus itself or exist
before exposure to the stimulus. For example, the humor a joke elicits
could vary with the intensity of suppressed emotions that have previously
become associated with the type of stimulus to which the joke is relevant.
Although Freud’s conceptualization can account for some humor-
eliciting experiences, it is clearly not sufficient to explain the humor that is
elicited by all types of communications. For example, the conceptualization
appears to apply only under conditions in which features of the humor-
eliciting stimuli are similar to those to which the suppressed emotion is rel-
evant. Given the wide diversity of stimuli that a given individual finds hu-
morous, one would have to postulate a very large number of suppressed
emotions in order to argue that this is a necessary antecedent of humor
elicitation.
A conceptualization of humor elicitation by Berlyne (1969, 1971) is
broader in scope. He assumed an inverted-U relation between physiological
arousal and the experience of pleasure. That is, pleasure increases with
arousal up to a point and then decreases, ultimately reaching a level at
which it becomes aversive. Berlyne viewed a joke as a scenario that in-
duces arousal beyond its optimal value, followed by a punch line that de-
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 193

creases this arousal to a relatively more pleasant level. This increase in


pleasantness is experienced as amusement.
Although broader than Freud’s, Berlyne’s formulation is also limited in
generality. For one thing, arousal cannot be reduced unless it already ex-
ists. Thus, Berlyne’s theory seems applicable only when a situation-specific
build-up of arousal has occurred before the humor-eliciting event is encoun-
tered. This might be true in the case of stories that set the recipient up for a
punch line and, therefore, might induce a degree of cognitive tension. How-
ever, witticisms and other unexpected events that elicit humor spontane-
ously in informal conversations occur in the absence of any prior increase
in arousal.

2. Superiority and Disparagement Theories


A second group of theories (Bergson, 1911; LaFave, Haddad, & Maeson,
1976; Zillman & Cantor, 1976) assume that people derive pleasure from feel-
ings of mastery, and that laughter at another’s deformities or misfortunes
reflects an attempt to establish or maintain these feelings. These reactions
are most likely when there are no social repercussions of expressing them.
Thus, they may occur when the target of the disparagement is generally re-
garded as socially undesirable or is someone to whom people are indiffer-
ent. Americans are more inclined to be amused by a joke if it disparages
Texas Aggies (a group that is of no particular interest to anyone but affili-
ates of Texas A&M) than if it disparages Jews, African Americans, or
women. Disparagement theories are particularly useful in accounting for
sick or ethnic humor. On the other hand, they have trouble accounting for
self-referent humor that is elicited by one’s own ineptitude or by other
events that reflect unfavorably on oneself. Although some people undoubt-
edly do find it difficult to laugh at themselves, this is by no means universal.
In summary, motivation-based theories can potentially account for the
humor that is elicited in certain circumscribed situations. However, they
are insufficient to account for the spontaneous elicitation of humor that oc-
curs under conditions in which the specific motives postulated by these
theories do not exist. Moreover, the theories do not address the cognitive
mechanisms that give rise to humor and that distinguish humor-eliciting
communications from those that are simply disparaging, aggressive, or
arousal-reducing but do not elicit amusement.

Incongruity Resolution Theories

Many theories (cf. Apter, 1982; Koestler, 1964; Suls, 1972) assume that
amusement is stimulated by the awareness that a stimulus event has two al-
ternative interpretations, each of which could potentially apply but are in
some sense incongruous. Identification of the incongruity, however, may of-
194 CHAPTER 8

ten require access to a large body of knowledge about the type of persons
and events described. For example, consider a joke from the Antioch Hu-
mor Test (Mindess et al., 1985):

A blind man enters a department store, picks up his dog by its tail and begins
swinging it over his head. A clerk hurries over and says, “Can I help you, sir?”
“No, thanks,” the man replies, “I’m just looking around.”

In this joke, two planes of thought are brought together by the punch line,
one of which pertains to the idiomatic meaning of “looking around” and the
other of which concerns its literal meaning. However, an appreciation of
the joke also requires knowledge that blind individuals often rely on seeing-
eye dogs to do their “looking.”

1. Suls’ Formulation of Humor Elicitation

A more formal statement of incongruity-resolution processes, provided


by Suls (1972, 1983), is consistent with the conceptualization of comprehen-
sion processes we proposed in chapters 4 and 5 as well as more general
theories of prose comprehension (e.g., Graesser, 1981). Suls assumes that
when people begin to read a story, the persons and events described acti-
vate a body of conceptual knowledge (e.g., event or episode models as con-
ceptualized in this volume) that can be used to interpret it. This knowledge,
once activated, is brought to bear on the interpretation of information that
is conveyed subsequently. However, recipients may later encounter infor-
mation that cannot be understood in terms of this knowledge. When this oc-
curs, they must identify alternative concepts and knowledge structures that
can be used to comprehend the new information in the context of the old.
This process often requires a reinterpretation of the original information,
and the generation of this reinterpretation elicits humor.
Suls likens joke comprehension to a problem-solving task in which com-
prehension is analogous to solving the problem and amusement is analo-
gous to the pleasure that people get from arriving at the solution. This anal-
ogy has additional implications. Most obviously, people must recognize
that a “problem” exists (i.e., that the information cannot be interpreted in
terms of previously acquired concepts and knowledge). More important,
the problem must be neither so easy that the pleasure derived from solving
it is minimal nor so difficult that its solution requires excessive effort. This
suggests that humor is more likely to be elicited by jokes that are moder-
ately difficult to comprehend than by jokes that are either too easy or too
hard. We consider this possibility more fully in the conceptualization we
outline later.
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 195

2. Apter’s Reversal Theory

Although inconsistency resolution can be an important antecedent of hu-


mor elicitation, it is not a sufficient condition for its occurrence. Not all rein-
terpretations of previously acquired information in light of new information
are amusing. Scientific discoveries, or creative problem solving more gener-
ally, often involve the application of a new set of concepts to previously
acquired knowledge in a way that reconciles this knowledge with new infor-
mation that becomes available. Although these events can be very pleas-
ureful, they are not amusing.
A conceptualization proposed by Michael Apter (1982) is compatible
with Suls’ (1983) but specifies both the necessary and the sufficient condi-
tions for humor to be elicited. Apter explicitly recognizes that the social ex-
periences that elicit humor include not only the persons, objects, and
events to which a joke or story refers but also the communicator and as-
pects of the social situation in which the information is encountered. By tak-
ing these contextual factors into account, Apter is able to explain the hu-
mor that is elicited not only by jokes and cartoons but also by witticisms
and fortuitous life experiences that are not intended to be funny at all.
Apter (1982) assumed that people who encounter a social experience at-
tempt to interpret it in terms of concepts and knowledge about both its ref-
erents and the situational conditions that surround it. In doing so, they ar-
rive at a tentative understanding of the experience as it actually exists from
the perspective of the individuals involved in it. To acquire this understand-
ing, they may often infer unmentioned attributes of these individuals or of
the situation more generally. (Thus, if a protagonist is described as a law-
yer, he or she might be inferred to have characteristics that are typical of
lawyers, etc.) Moreover, if a communication is conveyed verbally, people’s
understanding of it may take into account not only the situation described
in the communication but also the purpose for which the communication is
transmitted (e.g., the goals of the communicator). Observed behavior is
likewise understood in terms of the presumed goals of the actor and the sit-
uational constraints that are placed on the behavior’s occurrence.
When an experience is composed of a sequence of events, however, the
concepts and knowledge that are activated and used to interpret initial as-
pects of the experience may turn out to be inapplicable. (The sentence
about flying airplanes described at the beginning of this chapter provides
an example.) Then, a reinterpretation of the initial features may be required
in order to arrive at a coherent understanding of the experience as a whole.
This interpretation may give rise to the realization that the situation, or the
persons and objects involved in it, are not actually what they were assumed
to be at first.
This process is very similar to the inconsistency-resolution process pro-
posed by Suls (1972). However, Apter postulates that for the reinterpreta-
196 CHAPTER 8

tion of a situation to elicit humor, two things must be true. First, the reinter-
pretation must not replace the original interpretation that was made. That
is, the perception of the experience that results from the reinterpretation
must not change one’s perception of the experience that purported to exist
at the outset. Rather, both interpretations must be taken into account si-
multaneously. (For a similar assumption, see Koestler, 1964.) Second, the
perception of the experience that is established by the new information
must in some sense be diminished in importance or value relative to the
conditions that were first assumed.
To see the applicability of the diminishment and nonreplacement princi-
ples, reconsider the “quickie” joke described earlier. To reiterate, this joke
actually exemplifies two types of shifts in interpretation. One, purely se-
mantic shift occurs in the interpretation of “What’s a quickie?” The second
shift occurs from the perception of the nun as a chaste and devout woman
to the perception of her as a prostitute. Note, however, that the reinterpre-
tation of “What’s a quickie?” that is implied by the nun’s response does not
negate the interpretation that was apparently intended by the priest. More-
over, the nun, although turning out to be a prostitute, remains a nun. In
other words, the new perception of the reality of the situation does not in-
validate the appearance of the situation that existed before the reality was
revealed. Finally, note that the nun’s holiness is diminished as a conse-
quence of being a prostitute on the side. Thus, both of the conditions that
Apter (1982) postulated to be necessary for human elicitation are met.
Diminishment should not be confused with disparagement. Although dis-
paraging reinterpretations may often be diminishing, not all diminishing re-
interpretations are disparaging. In the Wizard of Oz, for example, people are
amused by the lion who purports to be ferocious but who turns out instead
to be meek. The lion’s true attributes are less unfavorable than his pur-
ported ones. They are nevertheless more mundane and, therefore, elicit
amusement.

3. Summary
Apter’s conceptualization can account for a number of humor-elicitation
phenomena that are not easily explained by other formulations. To give
some examples:

Puns. Puns purport to convey interesting information but are revealed


to be silly and, therefore, trivialize the communication itself. For example:

Two Eskimos sitting in a kayak were chilly. However, when they lit a fire in
their craft, it sank, proving once again that you can’t have your kayak and
heat it too.
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 197

A group of chess enthusiasts were standing in a hotel lobby discussing their re-
cent tournament victories. After about an hour, the manager went up to them
and asked them to disperse. “But why?” they asked. “Because,” he said, “I can’t
stand chess nuts boasting in an open foyer.”

Mahatma Gandhi, as you know, walked barefoot most of the time, which pro-
duced an impressive set of calluses on his feet. He also ate very little, which
made him rather frail and with his odd diet, he suffered from bad breath. This
made him a super callused fragile mystic hexed by halitosis.

In each case, the humor is elicited by the realization that the communi-
cation is not intended to be informative but rather, sets up the reader for a
play on words.

Shaggy Dog Stories. These stories are characterized by a lengthy de-


scription of events that appear to lead up to something interesting or excit-
ing but turn out to be totally mundane. In this case, the humor does not
arise from an interpretation of the stories’ semantic content. Rather, it re-
sults from a reinterpretation of the situational context in which the informa-
tion is presented. That is, the story’s length and content gives the appear-
ance of leading to something of interest and importance, whereas the
“punch line” reveals it to have no interest whatsoever.

Slapstick. There are many forms of slapstick humor. A potential chal-


lenge to the diminishment assumption could be the Laurel and Hardy vari-
ety, in which amusement is elicited by protagonists’ repeatedly bludgeon-
ing one another with two-by-fours. Certainly hitting someone with a stick is
not inherently funny. The diminishment in this situation presumably arises
from the realization that the protagonists are not, in fact, killed or even
maimed by one another’s actions. That is, they only appear to hurt one an-
other. Thus, the actual situation turns out to be more mundane than the
purported one.

Expectancy Deviations. In a study by Nehrhardt (1976), blindfolded


participants were asked to judge a series of weights. After several expo-
sures to weights that were fairly similar to one another, they encountered
a weight that was either much lighter or much heavier than the others. On
receiving this weight, subjects typically smiled or laughed. Assuming that
participants were amused rather than simply registering surprise, the ques-
tion is why. It seems reasonable to assume that participants who encoun-
tered the deviant weight inferred that they were being tricked and that
the experiment was not a serious study of weight judgment after all. In
other words, participants interpreted the situation as a whole as less im-
198 CHAPTER 8

portant than they had originally interpreted, and this reinterpretation elic-
ited amusement.
In summary, the diminishment assumption not only helps to account for
a number of humor-eliciting phenomena that are hard for other theories to
explain, but also accounts for conditions in which experiences are reinter-
preted but do not elicit amusement. For example, scientific discoveries, the
attachment of meaning to a person’s dreams, and the reinterpretation of
events in mystery novels all involve a reinterpretation of a situation in light
of new information. In these cases, however, the reality that is implied by
the new information is of greater importance or value than the original, and
so amusement is not experienced.

A COMPREHENSION–ELABORATION THEORY
OF HUMOR ELICITATION

The conceptualization of humor elicitation that Wyer and Collins (1992) pro-
posed has much in common with incongruity-resolution theories and bor-
rows particularly heavily from Apter’s (1982) formulation. At the same time,
it is derived largely from the assumptions surrounding the comprehension
of information outlined in previous chapters. Specifically, we assume that
amusement is the by-product of comprehension processes similar to those
described in chapters 4 and 5. However, the amount of humor that a joke
elicits can depend on the difficulty of comprehending it. Moreover, it can be
increased or decreased as a result of the amount and type of cognitive elab-
oration that is performed after its humor-eliciting interpretation has been
identified. We first outline the basic assumptions of the formulation and
provide empirical evidence of its implications. We then turn more specifi-
cally to the role of cognitive elaboration in humor elicitation and its implica-
tions for reactions to stories that people consider offensive. In our discus-
sion, we focus largely on the humor elicited by jokes and stories to which
event and episode models pertain. As Wyer and Collins (1992) indicated,
however, the conceptualization is potentially applicable to the humor that
is elicited by social experiences in general.

Comprehension Processes

Although the comprehension processes we assume to underlie humor elici-


tation have been elaborated in previous chapters, it may be worthwhile to
reiterate them in the present context. This will again be done in terms of
postulates. The first postulate is simply a recapitulation of the processes
described in chapter 4.
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 199

Postulate 8.1. New experiences are spontaneously interpreted in terms of


previously formed event representations (e.g. situation models) with which
they have common features. When more than one alternative knowledge rep-
resentation is applicable for interpreting an experience, the representation
that is most easily accessible in memory is typically applied. The result of this
cognitive activity is a newly formed situation model of the event being com-
prehended.

When people have no goal in mind other than to comprehend the infor-
mation they receive, the concepts and knowledge they apply are typically
those they have used most frequently and recently in the past (cf. Higgins,
Bargh, & Lombardi, 1985; Srull & Wyer, 1979; see Postulates 2.4 and 2.5). If
recipients have a more specific goal in mind, however, this goal may acti-
vate concepts that are relevant to its attainment, and these concepts may
then be used instead.
The second postulate reiterates the processes that underlie the con-
struction of episode models, and formalizes the effect of previously encoun-
tered stimulus events on the processing of information about subsequent
ones.

Postulate 8.2. Once a mental representation has been formed of an experi-


ence, this representation, along with the concepts and knowledge that were
activated in the course of constructing it, is used to comprehend thematically
related experiences that occur subsequently.

Thus, for example, information that a man enters a restaurant activates


knowledge about things that are usually found in restaurants and the
events that occur, and this knowledge provides the basis for comprehend-
ing events that occur subsequently. In some cases, the information may be
quite redundant with previously acquired knowledge and therefore, as
noted in chapter 6, it may not be retained (Trafimow & Wyer, 1993). Other
events may not be redundant with one’s knowledge in the domain of con-
cern but can nevertheless be interpreted in terms of concepts that are
drawn from this knowledge.
Thus, people do not often spill their drinks in a restaurant. Nevertheless,
information that the man in our example spilled a glass of wine on his suit is
likely to stimulate the construction of an event model in terms of concepts
that compose one’s knowledge of restaurants and the things that are found
there. On the other hand, suppose the man entered the restaurant, took off
his clothes and started playing the guitar. These behaviors cannot be easily
understood in terms of concepts that compose one’s knowledge of restau-
rants. Thus, they may stimulate a reassessment of the situation being de-
scribed. (For example, recipients might conjecture that the restaurant was
located in a nudist colony, and the man was an entertainer and not a guest.)
200 CHAPTER 8

Similarly, the initial reference to the nun in the “quickie” joke mentioned
earlier activates expectations for her attributes that make her later com-
ment to the priest difficult to interpret. Consequently, recipients identify a
different domain of knowledge (e.g., knowledge about prostitutes) in order
to comprehend it, with the result that the nun is reconceptualized as being
a prostitute as well.
These processes are captured by a third postulate, which essentially re-
capitulates assumptions made by Suls (1972, 1983) and Apter (1982):

Postulate 8.3. When information about an event cannot be interpreted in


terms of concepts drawn from the same domain of knowledge that was ap-
plied to previous events, recipients attempt to identify concepts and knowl-
edge in a different domain that is applicable to both the new event and the
preceding ones. If these concepts can be found, the previously learned events
are reinterpreted in terms of them.16

This reinterpretation would not be made spontaneously, but would require


higher order, goal-directed processing.
Postulates 8.1 to 8.3 are generally applicable to the comprehension of in-
formation about a thematically related sequence of events. For humor to be
elicited as a result of reinterpretations of the sort described in Postulate
6.3, additional factors must be considered. We describe these factors in
turn along with empirical evidence bearing on their influence.

The Role of Diminishment in Humor Elicitation

1. General Considerations
The first factor we assume to underlie humor elicitation was suggested
by Apter (1982) and has already been discussed.

Postulate 8.4. Humor is elicited by a reinterpretation of a stimulus event only


if the features of one or more features of the event are diminished in value or
importance relative to that implied by the original interpretation.

Like Apter (1982), we further assume that diminishment can occur along
many dimensions and at several levels of generality. For example, the rein-
terpretation of a stimulus event might paint a more mundane (or, in some
cases, less desirable) picture of a person or event than the original interpre-
tation implied. Alternatively, the reinterpretation could render the event it-

16
16 Note that Postulate 8.3 could be applied not only to stories but also to observed experi-
ences or single statements that people make in a social context. To this extent, this postulate
governs processes similar to those described in chapter 7.
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 201

self, or the circumstances surrounding its occurrence, more mundane or


trivial than the original interpretation implied. Thus, the reinterpretation of
a statement describing person A’s behavior toward person B might dimin-
ish the importance of either an attribute of A, an attribute of B, A’s behavior
toward B, the statement that describes the behavior, or the situational con-
text in which the statement is made. Postulate 6.4 applies at any or all of
these levels.

2. Empirical Evidence
To the extent that a diminishing reinterpretation of the characteristics of
a person or event is unfavorable, Postulate 6.4 would be consistent with dis-
paragement or superiority theories of humor elicitation described earlier
(cf. Zillman & Cantor, 1976). As we have noted, however, not all diminishing
reinterpretations of an event are disparaging. Events that are initially inter-
preted as extremely aversive can elicit humor if they are later revealed to
be less so. Shurcliff (1968) provided a good example. Some participants
were told they would be asked to pick up and hold a white rat. Others were
led to believe they would extract blood from the rat with a syringe. The lat-
ter condition was elaborately staged, with participants being required to
wear a lab coat and being warned that the rat might bite. In both condi-
tions, however, participants upon picking up the rat found that it was made
out of rubber. After having this experience, participants were asked to rate
the humor it elicited. Participants who had expected to extract blood from
the rat rated the situation as more amusing than those who had only ex-
pected to handle it. This finding is consistent with Postulate 8.4. That is, the
reinterpretation of the rat as a rubber toy led to a greater diminishment of
the situation as a whole in the first condition, and the greater amusement it
elicited could be attributed to this fact.
An ambiguity in interpreting Shurcliff’s findings arises from the fact that
the situations he constructed elicited anxiety. To this extent, his findings
would be consistent with an arousal-reduction theory of humor elicitation.
However, several studies in our own laboratory do not have this ambiguity.
A study by Collins and Wyer (reported by Wyer & Collins, 1992) evaluated
the effects of diminishment employing variations of the quickie joke de-
scribed earlier. To reiterate, diminishment could come into play in two
ways in comprehension of the story. First, the nun’s response to the priest’s
question (“What’s a quickie?”), which reveals she is a prostitute, diminishes
her status as a devout and chaste individual. Second, her response stimu-
lates a reinterpretation of the priest’s question that diminishes its impor-
tance. Both factors could contribute to the humor that was elicited.
To evaluate this possibility, Collins and Wyer constructed four versions
of the story. One version was identical to the joke described earlier. In a
second, the nun’s response to the priest’s question was “I’ll show you, but it
202 CHAPTER 8

will cost you $20, just like in town.” Thus, this response preserves the origi-
nal meaning of the question rather than stimulating a reinterpretation of it.
The third and fourth versions were similar to the first two except that the
person the priest asked was a third prostitute rather than a nun; these ver-
sions, then, eliminated the shift in perception of the respondent. Results
shown in Table 8.1 are very clear. That is, the original story, in which both
diminishing shifts in meaning were present, was judged as amusing. How-
ever, eliminating either shift in interpretation decreased amusement, and
eliminating both reinterpretations decreased it still further.
In a second study by Collins and Wyer, participants read a story that
could be interpreted in two different ways, one of which was less likely to
be identified than the other. One story, for example, was likely to be inter-
preted spontaneously as a conversation about the best way to administer
harsh physical punishment to children, but could also be interpreted as a
discussion of the best way to open a jar of pickles. A second story was most
likely to be interpreted as a man’s comments to a woman in the course of
making love in the shower, but could also convey his comments in the
course of washing a dog.
No indication was given at the beginning of the story about the nature of
its subordinate theme. In some versions, however, a statement was in-
serted near the end of the story that was anomalous when considered in
terms of concepts activated by the dominant theme but made sense in
terms of the subordinate one (specifically, “But honey, you know there’s
nothing tougher than getting into a jar of pickles,” and “Honey, bring me the
flea powder,” in the two stories, respectively). In other versions, this con-
cluding statement was omitted. Participants were told to read the story for
understanding as they would if they encountered it in a magazine or novel.
After doing so, however, they reported how amused they were by it. Partici-
pants judged the stories more amusing when the statement that activated
the subordinate, trivializing theme was present than when it was not.

TABLE 8.1
Mean Humor Elicited by “Quickie” Joke as a Function of the Effects
of the Punch Line on Interpretation of Story Features

Effect of Punch Line on


Perceptions of Nun

Change No Change

Effect of punch line on interpretation of statement


Change in meaning 5.60 3.67
No change in meaning 3.33 2.18

Note. Judgments reported along a scale from 0 (not at all humorous) to 10 (extremely humor-
ous). Adapted from Wyer and Collins (1992).
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 203

Considered in isolation, this finding could have several alternative inter-


pretations. For example, humor might be elicited simply by any reinterpre-
tation of the story regardless of whether or not it was diminishing. This
problem was eliminated in a study by Linda Isbell (reported in Isbell, Wyer,
& Collins, 2002). Participants read a version of the “pickle” story that was
similar to that employed by Collins and Wyer but varied in terms of the rel-
ative salience of the two alternative interpretations. The story was given a
title that identified either the serious theme (“Disciplining the Children”) or
the mundane one (“Getting a Pickle”). Participants read this story along
with three filler stories with instructions that (a) the stories could each be
about two quite different situations, (b) each story was given a title that
identified one of the situations, and (c) they should generate an alternative
title that reflected a different interpretation. (The three filler stories de-
scribed situations that were similar in importance; e.g., a game of cards vs.
a woodwind ensemble rehearsal.) After generating an alternative title for
each story, they gave their reactions to the story along several 0–10 scales,
one of which pertained to the amusement they experienced. As expected,
participants were more amused when their reinterpretation of the story
was more mundane than the original title conveyed (M = 6.12) than when it
was less so (M = 4.29), and this was true regardless of which version of the
story they read.
Thus, the results of these studies converge on the conclusion that sto-
ries elicit more amusement if they are reinterpreted in a way that dimin-
ishes the importance of either their referents or the stories themselves. At
the same time, the results do not indicate that diminishment is a necessary
condition for humor elicitation. In the preceding experiment, for example,
both reinterpretations that participants generated could have elicited some
humor, differing only in magnitude. The study of people’s responses to wit-
ticisms, described in chapter 7, is worth reconsidering in this context. To
reiterate, participants read some scenarios in which a statement was either
likely to be taken literally or likely to be viewed as ironic. Moreover, the in-
tended meaning of the ironic statement was either less favorable than its lit-
eral meaning (thereby diminishing the value of its referent) or more so. Di-
minishing reinterpretations elicited more amusement than enhancing ones
(6.3 vs. 4.6 along a 0–10 scale), consistent with Postulate 8.4. On the other
hand, both types of ironic statements were interpreted as substantially
more amusing (M = 5.5) than their true counterparts (M = 1.7).17

17
17 A second aspect of these data is also worth noting. That is, statements with unfavorable im-
plications were judged more amusing than statements with favorable implications, and this was
true regardless of whether the statements were taken literally (3.5 vs. 1.9) or ironic (6.3 vs. 4.6).
This finding, which would be consistent with disparagement theories (Zillman & Cantor, 1976),
suggests that inconsistency resolution is also not a necessary condition for humor elicitation.
204 CHAPTER 8

Thus, these findings could suggest that diminishment is not a necessary


condition for humor elicitation. On the other hand, the realization that a
statement does not mean what it says could diminish the value or impor-
tance of the statement independently of its implications for the referent and,
therefore, could elicit amusement for this reason. Therefore, in light of the
ability for Postulate 8.4 to account for a wide range of humor elicitation phe-
nomena that would otherwise be difficult to explain (slapstick humor, puns,
etc.), it seems desirable to retain it pending more compelling evidence
against its validity.

Effects of Comprehension Difficulty

1. Theoretical Considerations
The diminishing reinterpretation of information is often quite easy to
identify. In some cases, however, the reinterpretation may be more difficult
to generate, and may depend on recipients’ special knowledge of the per-
sons and events involved. For example:

Descartes and two of his buddies go into a bar. The two friends both order a
scotch and soda. The bartender turns to Descartes and asks, “You, too?” Des-
cartes replies, “I think not,” and immediately disappears.

The humor elicited by this joke presumably derives from the reinterpreta-
tion of Descartes’ reply in the context of his philosophical conclusion, “I
think, therefore, I am.” However, someone who is not very familiar with Des-
cartes’ philosophy might find the joke very bewildering.
Even when a joke’s humor-eliciting interpretation can be identified, it
might not be perceived as funny if an excessive amount of cognitive activity
is required to understand it. On the other hand, jokes that are too easy to
understand are also unlikely to elicit much amusement. Thus, as suggested
by Suls’ (1972, 1983) problem-solving analogy, jokes that are either too easy
or too difficult to comprehend may be less amusing than those that are
moderately difficult. To formalize:

Postulate 8.5. The amount of amusement that is potentially elicited as a re-


sult of reinterpreting a stimulus event is a nonmonotonic (inverted-U) func-
tion of the time and effort that is required to make this interpretation.

In a sense, this postulate is not new. Many years ago, McClelland, Atkin-
son, Clark, and Lowell (1953) also hypothesized a nonmonotonic relation
novelty of a stimulus (and, therefore, the difficulty of understanding it in
terms of previously formed concepts and knowledge) and judgments of its
pleasantness. The question is why this relationship exists. Freud (1905/
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 205

1960) suggested that the sheer pleasure of engaging in cognitive activity in


relation to humor contributes to its gratification. Perhaps as comprehen-
sion difficulty increases up to a point, recipients feel more challenged, and
their success in comprehending the information is rewarding (White, 1959).
Beyond this optimal level, however, recipients might begin to feel stupid or
incompetent, and so their enjoyment decreases. Therefore, humor elicita-
tion might decrease correspondingly.

2. Empirical Evidence

The results of several studies are consistent with Postulate 8.5. Of partic-
ular relevance is a study by Zigler, Levine, and Gould (1967). Participants
read cartoons that systematically varied over four levels of comprehension
difficulty. Both subjects’ facial expressions as they read the cartoons and
their subsequent preference rating of the cartoons were recorded. An index
of participants’ difficulty of comprehending the jokes was also obtained.
This latter measure increased as expected over the four difficulty levels.
However, preference rankings of the cartoons were higher when they were
moderately difficult to comprehend than when they were either very easy
to comprehend or very difficult (but not impossible) to comprehend.
Codings of participants’ facial expressions revealed a similar pattern.
Collins and Wyer (reported in Wyer & Collins, 1992) also supported the
comprehension difficulty postulate using stimulus materials similar to
those described earlier. Participants read a story that was likely to be inter-
preted spontaneously as concerning a serious situation (either making love
in the shower or abusing children) but could alternatively be interpreted as
concerning a mundane one (giving a dog a bath or opening a pickle jar, re-
spectively). However, the salience of the mundane interpretation was var-
ied in two ways. First, a statement with an interpretation that required con-
cepts associated with the subordinate theme either was or was not inserted
near the end of the story. Second, the story was preceded by a title that dis-
posed subjects to think of either the serious theme or the mundane one.
(Thus, the story that could be interpreted as either love making in the
shower or giving a dog a bath was titled either “Mary’s bath” or “Spot’s
bath.” Correspondingly, the story that could concern either child abuse or
how to open a pickle jar was titled “Getting Out of a Pickle” or “Getting a
Pickle”). According to Postulate 6.5, participants should be more amused
when it was moderately difficult to identify the subordinate, diminishing in-
terpretation than when it was either very easy or very difficult.
This was in fact the case, as shown in Table 8.2. Pooled over the two sto-
ries, more humor was elicited when the humor-eliciting theme was sug-
gested in the text than when it was not (6.36 vs. 4.21), suggesting that this
theme was easier to identify in the former case than the latter. However,
when the theme was suggested in the text, mentioning the theme in the title
206 CHAPTER 8

TABLE 8.2
Humor Elicited by Stories as a Function of Allusion
to Subordinate Theme in the Title and Text

Theme Suggested in Title

Subordinate Dominant

Lovemaking vs. dog’s bath story


Subordinate theme suggested in text 6.17 6.85
Subordinate theme not suggested in text 576 4.32
Child abuse vs. pickle story
Subordinate theme suggested in text 5.76 6.67
Subordinate theme not suggested in text 3.87 2.94

Note. Judgments are reported along a scale from 0 (not at all humorous) to 10 (extremely hu-
morous). Adapted from Wyer and Collins (1992).

as well (thus making its identification even easier) decreased amusement


(5.96 vs. 6.76, when the theme was versus was not conveyed in the text, re-
spectively). In contrast, when the theme was not suggested in the text and
so identifying it was more difficult, mentioning the theme in the title in-
creased amusement (4.82 vs. 3.61, respectively).
As an additional test of Postulate 8.5, we constructed different versions
of the following joke:

Q. What did Adam say to Eve in the Garden of Eden?


A. Stand back! I don’t know how big this thing gets.

The first interpretation of Adam’s response, which is induced by the warn-


ing, “Stand back!”, connotes danger. The implications of this interpretation
are diminished by the subsequent realization that the “thing” is only an
erection rather than a real danger and that the warning results from
Adam’s sexual naivete. To understand the joke, however, one must realize
that the “thing” is, in fact, an erection, and must know that Adam and Eve
have no prior knowledge of sex. Identifying these concepts and knowledge
requires cognitive effort, the magnitude of which should depend on
whether the relevant information is explicitly provided.
To evaluate this possibility, we constructed eight versions of the joke
that varied in the explicitness of information bearing on three types of
knowledge that were necessary to understand it: (a) the “thing” referred to
an erection, (b) it was Adam’s first such experience, and (c) Adam did not
know its size. Thus, the punch line when all three pieces of information
were provided was “Stand back! This is my first erection and I don’t know
how big it gets!” In contrast, the punch line when none of the three pieces of
information was provided was simply “Stand back!”
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 207

TABLE 8.3
Humor Elicited by Adam and Eve Joke as a Function
of the Information Mentioned in the Punch Line

Ignorance of Ignorance of Size


Size Mentioned Not Mentioned

“First Time” “First Time” “First Time” “First Time”


Mentioned Not Mentioned Mentioned Not Mentioned

Erection mentioned 5.57 6.43 2.63 3.25


Erection not mentioned 6.00 8.00 2.12 1.00

Note. Judgments are reported along a scale from 0 (not at all humorous) to 10 (extremely hu-
morous). Adapted from Wyer and Collins (1992).

Humor ratings are shown in Table 8.3 as a function of the amount and
type of information conveyed in the punch line. The joke was generally
more amusing when the punch line explicitly stated that Adam did not
know the size of the erection. More important, however, is the fact that
when Adam’s lack of knowledge was not explicit, providing one or both of
the other pieces of information increased the ease of understanding the
joke and, therefore, increased the humor it elicited. When Adam’s lack of
knowledge was explicitly mentioned, however, providing the other two
pieces of information presumably reduced cognitive effort below the opti-
mal level required to appreciate the joke. Therefore, it decreased humor
ratings.

3. Situational and Individual Differences


in Comprehension Difficulty

The ease of identifying a humor-eliciting interpretation is not only a func-


tion of the explicitness of the information itself. Situational and individual
difference factors can play a role as well. For example, situational variables
that increase the accessibility of comprehension-relevant concepts in mem-
ory should increase the humor elicited by difficult-to-comprehend stimulus
experiences but should decrease the humor elicited by easy-to-compre-
hend experiences. On the other hand, factors that distract recipients from
comprehending the information in terms of these concepts should have the
opposite effects.
Two studies provide indirect support for this possibility. In a study by
Schick, McGlynn, and Woolam (1972), participants were exposed to two sets
of cartoon strips. All strips were originally from the “Peanuts” series and so
the characters and their personalities were well known. However, half of
the strips were redrawn to make the characters unfamiliar. Participants
were exposed to several strips in succession and asked to indicate how
208 CHAPTER 8

amused they were by each. People are likely to have some difficulty com-
prehending strips containing unfamiliar characters as they do not have a
previously formed body of knowledge to draw upon for use in construing
the implications of the strips and their situational context. However, com-
prehension difficulty should decrease as the characters become more fa-
miliar, and so the humor the strips elicit should increase. On the other
hand, suppose the characters in the strips are already familiar. Then, in-
creases in the number of strips should not have this effect. In fact, humor
judgments of the redrawn cartoon strips increased as a function of the num-
ber of exposures to the strips. In contrast, the humor elicited by the origi-
nal “Peanuts” strips was high at the outset and did not change as a function
of the number of exposures.
A perhaps more interesting finding surrounds the combined effects of fa-
miliarity and participants’ chronic anxiety (as inferred from the Taylor Man-
ifest Anxiety Scale). Chronic anxiety might function as internal noise that in-
creases participants’ difficulty in comprehending the stimuli. If so, it should
increase the humor elicited by familiar-character cartoon strips, which in
the absence of this noise are below the optimal level of comprehension dif-
ficulty. However, anxiety might decrease the humor elicited by unfamiliar-
character strips, which may be above the optimal level of difficulty in the
absence of distraction. This was in fact the case.
It can be difficult to interpret the effects of situational manipulations of
comprehension difficulty without an a priori understanding of the difficulty
level of the stimuli to be comprehended independently of these manipula-
tions. A study by Goldstein, Suls, and Anthony (1972) provides an example.
Subjects were initially shown photographs of either aggressive stimuli or
automobiles as part of an aesthetic preference task, thereby activating con-
cepts that were associated with the domain to which the pictures per-
tained. Later, in an ostensibly unrelated experiment, participants judged
the funniness of cartoons in either the same domain to which the pictures
they saw were relevant or in the other, unrelated domain. Cartoons elicited
more amusement in the former condition than the latter. This could suggest
that the concepts activated by the photographs facilitated the comprehen-
sion of the cartoons that participants encountered later and, therefore, in-
creased the ease of identifying their humor-eliciting features. According to
Postulate 8.4, however, this increase should only occur if the cartoons are
fairly difficult to comprehend in the absence of this facilitating influence. If
the cartoons were very easy to comprehend in the absence of priming, ex-
periences that further increase the ease of comprehending them should
have precisely the opposite effect. Thus, Goldstein et al.’s finding would
only be consistent with the conceptualization we propose if the stimuli
were of the first variety.
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 209

COGNITIVE ELABORATION PROCESSES

The humor that people experience in the course of identifying a communi-


cation’s diminishing reinterpretation theoretically occurs automatically.
However, their spontaneous amusement may be increased or decreased as
a result of deliberate cognitive elaboration that the individuals perform
subsequently. If the individuals have constructed an event or episode
model in the course of comprehending the situation described, for exam-
ple, they may elaborate the mental image they have formed of the situation
and the unmentioned events that occur subsequently. Their cognitive elab-
oration of the humor-eliciting aspects of the situation is likely to increase
the amusement that the story elicits.
On the other hand, some stories are considered offensive by the persons
who encounter them. This could occur because the jokes are tasteless, are
socially inappropriate in the situation in which they are told, or cast asper-
sions on a person or group that the recipients hold in high regard. In such
cases, recipients’ postcomprehension cognitive activities may not pertain
to the humor-eliciting reinterpretation per se. Rather, recipients may think
about the motives of the person who conveyed the story and, if the story is
disparaging, the storyteller’s attitude toward the protagonists. This humor-
irrelevant cognitive elaboration is likely to decrease the amusement the
story elicits. These possibilities are formalized in the following postulate:

Postulate 8.6. The amount of humor that is elicited as a result of reinterpreting


a stimulus event is a monotonic function of the amount of cognitive elaboration
of the event and its implications that occurs subsequent to its reinterpretation.
1. If recipients’ processing objective at the time is simply to comprehend and
enjoy experiencing the event, cognitive elaboration of the event will typi-
cally increase the humor it elicits.
2. If recipients’ goal is more restricted, the event is elaborated in terms of its
implications for this more specific objective. In this case, cognitive elabora-
tion could either increase, decrease, or have no effect on the amount of hu-
mor elicited, depending on whether the humor-eliciting reinterpretation of
the event is relevant to the attainment of this objective.

There is a qualification on the applicability of this postulate, however. The


humor-eliciting aspects of some jokes are easy to elaborate. For example:

A Texas Aggie and two friends are marooned on a desert island without food or
water. Suddenly, the sky opens and a voice says, “Each of you may have one
wish.”
One friend says, “I wish I were in the arms of my loved one.” Immediately, he
is gone.
210 CHAPTER 8

The second friend says, “I wish I were in the bosom of my family.” Immedi-
ately, he is also gone.
The Texas Aggie thinks for a moment and says, “Gee, I wish my friends were
with me now.”

The humor elicited by this story presumably results from the realization
that the Aggie’s wish essentially negates the effects of the friends’ wishes,
returning them to the same abysmal situation they had been in before.
Once readers of the story identify these implications, they are likely to form
a mental image of the friends’ reactions to finding themselves back on the
island again. To this extent, the opportunity to think about the joke is likely
to increase the amusement it elicits. In contrast, consider the following:

Q. Why did the Texas Aggie want people to save their burned-out light
bulbs?
A. He needed them for the darkroom he was building.

Although this joke might be mildly amusing, it has little elaboration poten-
tial and so thinking about the joke after comprehending it should have little
impact on amusement. (Moreover, note that both jokes might be seen as
disparaging the intelligence of Texas A&M University students, to whom the
name “Texas Aggie” is typically applied. Students from this university might
be inclined to elaborate the nonhumorous implications of both jokes, and
this could decrease their amusement.)

Effects of Repetition

Some jokes continue to elicit amusement even when they are repeated one
or more times. This can be true despite the fact that the punch line is well
remembered and, therefore, no longer elicits a new interpretation of the
stimulus events being described. Other jokes, however, are less likely to
bear repeating, even though they might have been considered funny at the
time they were first heard. Suls (1972) conjectured that repetition effects re-
flect a general tendency for novel stimuli to become better liked as they be-
come more familiar (Zajonc, 1968; but see McClelland et al., 1953). If this
were so, however, repetition should have similar effects on all jokes. Thus,
this conceptualization cannot easily explain why some repeated jokes con-
tinue to elicit humor but others do not.
It seems more reasonable to interpret repetition effect in terms of Postu-
late 8.6. If a joke has high elaboration potential, all possible implications of
it are unlikely to be considered at the time the joke is first encountered. To
this extent, repeating the joke might stimulate a different subset of implica-
tions than it did the first time, and these new implications could elicit hu-
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 211

mor. Thus, the “desert island” joke described earlier is likely to elicit some-
what different mental images and elaborations each time it is told or
thought about. Eventually, with still further repetitions, no new elabora-
tions are likely to come to mind and so humor is no longer elicited. (All
jokes become stale eventually.) However, jokes that have low elaboration
potential to begin with (e. g., the “burned out light bulb” joke) may elicit lit-
tle humor when they are repeated even once.
Cognitive elaborations may be aided by external stimulation. In fact,
much of the humor that is generated by professional comedians results
from their ability to stimulate their audience to elaborate the implications
of a humor-eliciting event with which they are already familiar. Moreover,
many movies and stories concern protagonists whose humor-eliciting be-
havior, although initially unexpected, is repeated in one form or another
throughout. Don Quixote, for example, repeatedly behaves in foolish ways
while appearing to be distinguished and chivalrous. Inspector Clouseau, the
French detective created by Peter Sellers in the Pink Panther movies ap-
pears sophisticated but is actually a buffoon. In such cases, the audience
soon becomes aware of the protagonist’s actual characteristics, and so his
or her later behavior is not unexpected. Yet, the behavior continues to pro-
vide amusement. For example, the first Pink Panther movie one sees leads
the ostensibly sophisticated Inspector Clouseau to be reinterpreted as an
inept detective who only appears sophisticated. Once this is established,
new elaborations of the reinterpretation are encountered as the film pre-
sents further instances of Clouseau appearing sophisticated but being in
reality a buffoon. The repeated instances of Clouseau’s humor-eliciting be-
havior constitute externally generated elaborations of one’s initial reinter-
pretation of the character and situation and function in much the same way
as self-generated elaborations. These elaborations elicit humor for much
the same reasons that self-generated elaborations do.
These considerations help to conceptualize the humor elicited in a large
number of situations in which the comprehension processes we postulate
might otherwise seem irrelevant. That is, many everyday situations appear
to elicit amusement although they do not require a reinterpretation. A col-
league who is already known to be incompetent but who (perhaps like In-
spector Clouseau) behaves in a pompous fashion elicits humor whenever
he or she inadvertently says or does something that betrays this incompe-
tence. Neither the new event nor the colleague’s attributes are reinter-
preted. However, the colleague’s behavior essentially constitutes an exter-
nally generated elaboration of the implications of a past event (an earlier
instance of the colleague’s buffoonery that occurred in the context of his or
her pomposity) that did stimulate a diminishing reinterpretation at the time
it occurred.
212 CHAPTER 8

Situational Influences on Cognitive Elaboration


and Humor Elicitation

Individual differences undoubtedly exist in the disposition to be offended


by jokes that are considered socially inappropriate in the circumstances in
which they are told, or that perpetuate a negative stereotype. These differ-
ences may be reflected in the humor the jokes elicit. However, these differ-
ences, which presumably result from differences in the type of cognitive
elaboration that people perform after the implications of the jokes have
been comprehended, should only be apparent when recipients are moti-
vated or able to think about the jokes after their humor-eliciting interpreta-
tion has been identified. In the absence of this postcomprehension cogni-
tive activity, people should be amused regardless of their disposition to be
offended by them.
A study with Linda Isbell (reported in Isbell, Wyer, & Collins, 2002) sug-
gested this possibility. In this experiment, we obtained participants’ reac-
tions to jokes that we expected to be more offensive to women than to men
and, therefore, to produce different types of cognitive elaboration. Two
jokes, which described explicit sexual activity (specifically, fellatio and mas-
turbation), were ones that men typically find amusing but women find em-
barrassing or offensive. A third joke was scatological:

Q. Why do farts smell?


A. For the deaf.

Sex differences in reactions to the latter joke were less clear a priori. Females
might find the joke more embarrassing than men. On the other hand, both
men and women might consider the joke to disparage people with disabili-
ties. Moreover, cognitive elaboration of the joke could stimulate unpleasant
olfactory images and might decrease humor for this reason as well.
Be that as it may, we reasoned that if people are encouraged to think
about the implications of these jokes, they should judge a joke to be more
amusing if they elaborate its humor-eliciting aspects than if they think
about its humor-irrelevant aspects. However, suppose participants give
their spontaneous reactions to the joke without engaging in this post-
comprehension elaboration. Then, they should be equally amused by the
joke regardless of the sort of elaboration they might otherwise be disposed
to perform.

1. Method
We told participants we were interested in reactions to stories of the
sort they encounter in daily life, and that to study this, we would like them
to react to a number of stories of the sort they might hear in situations out-
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 213

side the laboratory. With this preamble, participants in spontaneous-reaction


conditions were told we were particularly interested in people’s spontane-
ous responses to stories, and that after reading each story, they should re-
port their immediate reactions to it without thinking about it carefully. In
contrast, participants in thought conditions were told we were interested in
how people respond to a story after they have had time to think about it,
and were urged to think carefully about the stories before reporting their
reactions.
Participants in each condition read a series of eight stories that included
the three jokes described earlier, two jokes that were void of content that
participants were likely to consider offensive, and two stories describing
situations that were not expected to be amusing. Participants read each
story/joke and then rated it along four 0–10 scales pertaining to their emo-
tional reactions: sad, angry, amused, and offended.

2. Results
The amusement elicited by inoffensive jokes was similar regardless of par-
ticipants’ sex or instructional conditions (M = 5.10). Moreover, encouraging
participants to think about these jokes did not appreciably increase their
amusement. This could indicate that the innocuous jokes we selected were
not sufficiently high in elaboration potential for an increase to be detected.
Reactions to the sexual and scatological jokes are of greater interest.
The amusement elicited by these jokes is shown in the left half of Table 8.4
as a function of participant sex and presentation conditions. As we ex-
pected, men were more amused by sexual jokes when they thought about
them than when they did not (7.08 vs. 4.94, respectively), whereas women
were less so (2.62 vs. 4.64, respectively). Therefore, although men were
more amused by the jokes than women under thought conditions (7.02 vs.
2.62, respectively), this difference was not at all apparent under spontane-

TABLE 8.4
Mean Ratings of Inoffensive, Scatological, and Sexual Jokes
as a Function of Instructional Conditions and Distraction

Amusement Ratings Offensiveness Ratings

Spontaneous Thought Spontaneous Thought


Reaction Conditions Conditions Reaction Conditions Conditions

Sexual jokes
Males 4.94 7.08 1.87 2.07
Females 4.64 2.62 1.12 5.44
Scatological joke
Males 5.16 2.87 2.62 1.29
Females 5.63 3.00 1.62 4.78
214 CHAPTER 8

ous-reaction conditions (4.94 vs. 4.64). The interaction of participant sex


and instructional conditions was significant, F(1,42) = 4.55, p < .05.
Gender differences in reactions to the scatological joke were not evident.
In fact, both men and women reported being less amused by the joke when
they were told to think about it (M = 2.94) than when they were told to give
their spontaneous reactions to it (M = 5.40), F(1,42) = 3.97, p < .05, and this
difference did not depend on participant sex (F < 1). Thus, both groups of
participants appeared to elaborate humor-irrelevant implications of the
joke under thought conditions.
The humor-irrelevant cognitive elaboration that occurred when partici-
pants had a chance to think about the jokes was presumably stimulated in
part by their perception that the jokes violated social standards of taste or
portrayed activities they considered undesirable. However, the jokes’ offen-
siveness was apparently not the only determinant of the elaboration they
performed. Participants’ offensiveness ratings of the offensiveness of the
three types of jokes are summarized in the right half of Table 8.4. Partici-
pants judged both sexual and scatological jokes to be inoffensive when they
were asked to report their spontaneous reactions. However, whereas men
continued to consider these jokes to be inoffensive when they were told to
think about them, women increased their judgments of the jokes’ offensive-
ness in these conditions. These conclusions are confirmed by marginally
significant interactions of instructional conditions and participant sex in
analyses of reactions to both sexual jokes and the scatological joke (in each
case, p < .07). However, the fact that men were less amused by the scatolog-
ical joke under thought conditions despite not being offended by it suggests
that the humor-irrelevant elaboration they performed in this condition was
not a result of the joke’s offensiveness per se. Correlational analyses con-
firmed these conclusions. That is, the correlation between amusement rat-
ings and offensiveness ratings, computed separately for each experimental
condition, was generally low (between -.16 and -.45) and was significant in
only one case.

3. Effects of Distraction

If the different effects of instructions on reported amusement are medi-


ated by differences in the cognitive elaboration that participants performed
when they were told to think about them, distracting participants from en-
gaging in this cognitive activity should decrease the magnitude of these ef-
fects. To examine this possibility, we constructed an additional condition in
which participants received instructions similar to those administered un-
der thought conditions of the main experiment. In addition, however, par-
ticipants were told that we wished to simulate conditions outside the labo-
ratory in which people hear stories when they are preoccupied with other
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 215

things, and so we would like them to listen to a tape-recorded conversation


while reading the stories. (The conversation was an intrinsically inter-
change between a man and a woman that was taken from the opening
scenes of Edward Albee’s Who’s Afraid of Virginia Woolf?).
Results were consistent with expectations. Specifically, distracting par-
ticipants from thinking about sexual jokes reduced the sex difference in
amusement that occurred under thought conditions (7.08 vs. 2.62 for men
and women, respectively; see Table 8.4) to a level (5.12 vs. 3.94, respec-
tively) that did not significantly differ from the level we observed under
spontaneous reaction conditions (4.94 vs. 4.64, respectively). Correspond-
ingly, distracting both men and women from thinking about the scatological
joke, which they reported as unamusing under thought conditions (M =
2.93) increased their amusement to a level (M = 4.25) similar to that ob-
served when participants gave their spontaneous reactions (M = 5.38). It
therefore seems reasonable to conclude that distraction disrupted the cog-
nitive elaboration that participants performed when they were told to think
about the jokes and, as a result, it decreased the effect of this elaboration
on their amusement.

Sexual Humor in Social Interaction

The preceding experiment provides evidence that both situational and indi-
vidual difference factors combine to influence the type of cognitive elabora-
tion that people perform in response to a joke and the amusement they ex-
perience as a result of this elaboration. The conclusions drawn from the
study are nonetheless limited by the failure to take into account the social
context in which the jokes are conveyed. People may respond quite differ-
ently to sexual jokes that are told by members of their own sex than to
those that are told by members of the opposite sex. This could be particu-
larly true of females, who may interpret a man’s spontaneous relating of
such a joke to be rather boorish and insensitive.
An experiment by James Collins (reported in Isbell, Wyer, & Collins, 2002)
provided evidence concerning this contingency and, moreover, gave insight
into the cognitive processes that underlie reactions to the jokes. The study is
particularly provocative as the jokes were ostensibly conveyed spontane-
ously under conditions that were not part of the experiment itself.
Specifically, participants were male and female undergraduates who
took part in the experiment in mixed sex groups. The experiment was con-
ducted by either a male or female undergraduate who was ostensibly help-
ing the faculty member obtain reactions to some humor materials he was
preparing for a future experiment. At this point, however, the experimenter
spontaneously remarked, “Say, that reminds me. I just heard a new joke.
Maybe he (Dr. Collins) would like this one. Let me try it out on you . . .” The
216 CHAPTER 8

experimenter then proceeded to convey one of two jokes. One, sexual joke,
was the “Adam and Eve” joke described earlier in this chapter (see Table
8.3). The other was irrelevant to sexuality.
After this aside, the experimenter indicated that before going on with Dr.
Collins’ experiment (s)he would like the participant to perform two unre-
lated task. One was a filler task that was intended to disguise the related-
ness of the studies. The second was a word association task in which partic-
ipants were asked to select one of three words that was most similar to a
fourth. One alternative in each set had sexual overtones. For example:

Feeling: touch tingle stimulate


Oral: eating sex communication
Excited: winning aroused horny

Finally, ostensibly as part of the main study, participants were asked to


report the amusement elicited by approximately 45 humorous passages, 12
of which had sexual content.
Collins assumed that the sexual joke told by the experimenter would
stimulate male participants to engage in humor-relevant cognitive elabora-
tions regardless of whether the joke was told by a man or a woman. How-
ever, females were expected to engage in these elaborations when the joke
was told by another woman, but to engage in humor-irrelevant elaboration
when the joke was told by a man. The nature of these elaborations is likely
to be reflected in the type of concepts that were accessible in memory at
the time participants performed the word association task and, therefore,
the frequency of sexuality-related words they would select. Data bearing on
this possibility are shown in the top half of Table 8.5. Both male and female
participants made a greater number of sexuality-related word associations

TABLE 8.5
Mean Sexuality-Related Word Associations and Amusement Elicited
by Sexual Jokes as a Function Participant Sex, the Experimenter’s Sex,
and the Type of Joke the Experimenter Told

Sexual Joke Told Nonsexual Joke Told


by Experimenter by Experimenter

Male Female Male Female


Experimenter Experimenter Experimenter Experimenter

Sexuality-related word associations


Male participants 3.75 5.40 3.00 1.89
Female participants 1.00 4.86 2.00 1.92
Amusement elicited by sexual jokes
Male participants 5.78 6.28 5.13 4.42
Female participants 4.40 6.96 5.52 3.96
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 217

when they had heard a female tell a sexual joke than when they had heard
her tell a nonsexual joke, indicating that the female’s joke activated sexual-
ity-relevant concepts. Correspondingly, as shown in the bottom half of Ta-
ble 8.5, they were more amused by the sexual jokes they encountered in
these conditions. In contrast, male participants’ sexuality-related word as-
sociations increased only slightly when a male experimenter told a sexual
joke, and female participants’ sexuality-related associations actually de-
creased in these conditions. As a result, the male experimenter’s telling of a
sexual joke only slightly increased males’ amusement in response to the
sexual jokes they encountered later, and decreased women’s amusement.18

Combined Effects of Elaboration


and Comprehension Difficulty

Although we have considered the effects of comprehension difficulty and


cognitive elaboration separately, these effects are actually interdependent.
For one thing, people cannot elaborate the implications of information they
are unable to interpret. Moreover, the experience of difficulty in compre-
hending the information could itself stimulate cognitive elaborations. For
example, if recipients believe they have had more difficulty understanding
a joke than they should, they might be stimulated to think about them-
selves and their competence rather than about the humor-eliciting aspect
of the information. Such humor-irrelevant elaborations could offset any
amusement that the joke would otherwise elicit.
A third consideration arises from the fact that people are typically nei-
ther willing nor able to devote an unlimited amount of time to the process-
ing of any given stimulus event (Sperber & Wilson, 1986; Taylor & Fiske,
1978). This is particularly true in a social interaction in which a continuous
stream of events commands attention. Suppose people are unwilling to
spend more than a given amount of time thinking about a stimulus event.
To this extent, the more time and effort they devote to comprehending a
stimulus event, the less time they will devote to a subsequent elaboration
of its implications.
If this is so, the combined effects of comprehension difficulty and cogni-
tive elaboration on humor elicitation can be described more precisely.
Suppose the total time that people are willing to devote to (a) the compre-
hension of an experience and (b) the cognitive elaboration of its humor-

18
18 Our interpretation of these results of course assumes that participants’ cognitive elabora-
tions of the experimenter’s joke activated concepts that influenced their interpretation of the
sexual jokes they encountered later, thus increasing the humor the jokes elicited. This assump-
tion is supported by a significant correlation between the amusement they reported in response
to these jokes and the number of sexuality-related word associations that participants made (r =
.39, p < .05).
218 CHAPTER 8

eliciting implications is a constant. Wyer and Collins (1992) showed that


under these conditions, the elaboration potential of a stimulus not only
has a direct effect on the humor elicited but also influences the relation
between humor elicitation and comprehension difficulty. Specifically, less
comprehension time is required to maximize the humor an experience
elicits when the elaboration potential of the experience is high than when
it is low.

REACTIONS TO DISPARAGING HUMOR

Jokes and stories often perpetuate a negative stereotype or for other rea-
sons disparage the persons or groups to which they pertain. Some people
are amused by such jokes and others are not. Substantial research has
been devoted to the identification of personality and individual difference
factors that account for these differences. Much of this research has been
stimulated by the assumption that laughing at others’ deficiencies is a mani-
festation of displaced hostility or aggression (Freud, 1905/1960). Alterna-
tively, it may reflect a desire to maintain a feeling of superiority by derogat-
ing others or by otherwise calling attention to their flaws (Wills, 1981;
Zillman, 1983; Zillman & Cantor, 1976). One obvious implication of this as-
sumption is that people are more amused by jokes that disparage individu-
als who are particularly threatening to their self-esteem. Thus, for example,
jokes that disparage minority group members are more likely to elicit
amusement in persons who feel their economic or social status is being
threatened by these groups than in individuals who feel more secure.
The possibility that humor is elicited by disparagement per se cannot be
entirely discounted (see Footnote 18). According to the conceptualization
we propose, however, the humor elicited by a joke or story is a joint func-
tion of the identification of its humor-eliciting implications in the course of
comprehending it, and the amount and type of cognitive elaboration that
occurs subsequently. To this extent, individual differences in responses to
disparaging humor are potentially traceable to (a) the type of previously
formed concepts and knowledge that people bring to bear on their compre-
hension of a joke and (b) their motivation to engage in humor-eliciting or
humor-irrelevant cognitive elaboration, assuming they have an opportunity
to do so.

Effects of Comprehension Difficulty

People are usually less amused by a joke that disparages a stereotyped


group to which they personally belong than a group to which they are indif-
ferent. This difference could be due in part to the type of cognitive elabora-
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 219

tion that people perform in the two conditions. However, it could be local-
ized at the comprehension stage as well. For example, jokes often mention
the ethnic group to which they pertain at the outset. People who do not ex-
pect to be offended by a disparaging joke about this group may spontane-
ously activate a body of knowledge about attributes that are stereotypically
associated with the group and use this knowledge to comprehend the rest
of the joke or story. In such cases, activating the stereotype may facilitate
comprehension of the joke and, perhaps, increase the humor that it elicits.
On the other hand, people who identify with the group may anticipate that
the joke is going to offend them, and may think about the motives of its
source. This humor-irrelevant activity could interfere with the identification
of the joke’s humor-eliciting interpretation. Whether or not this interference
increases or decreases amusement, however, depends on the difficulty of
comprehending the joke more generally.
The extent to which mentioning a stereotyped group activates humor-
irrelevant cognitive activity can also depend on characteristics of the story-
teller. A joke that pertains to Jews is more likely to stimulate this activity in a
Jewish listener than in a Ku Klux Klan member. On the other hand, it is less
likely to do so if the joke-teller is Jewish than if (s)he belongs to the KKK.
However, not all jokes that refer to members of a stereotyped group are
disparaging. If people who anticipate that a joke will perpetuate a negative
stereotype engage in cognitive activity that interferes with comprehension, it
could affect the amusement the joke elicits even if the joke turns out not to
perpetuate the stereotype at all. Consider the following joke, for example:

A bus passenger notices that the woman sitting beside him is staring at him.
“I’m sorry to bother you,” she says, “but I wonder if you would mind my ask-
ing you a personal question. Are you by any chance Jewish?”
“I certainly don’t mind your asking,” replies the man good-naturedly, “but
no, I don’t happen to be Jewish.”
The woman continues to stare at him, however, and asks again, “Are you
sure you’re not Jewish?”
“Yes, I’m sure,” says the man, now somewhat irritated. “My mother is Ro-
man Catholic, and my father is Japanese. There’s really no chance that I am
Jewish.”
This still doesn’t satisfy her, and as the trip continues, she becomes even
more insistent. “Now, I know that you’re Jewish. Tell me you’re Jewish. Admit
it!”
Finally, after repeated denials, the man, only to keep from being pestered
further, says, “Okay. Have it your way, I’m Jewish.”
“Well,” the woman responds, “you certainly don’t look Jewish.”

Thus, the joke does not disparage Jews, but rather, disparages the stereo-
type. However, this does not become clear until the punch line. The allusion
220 CHAPTER 8

to the ethnic group in the material preceding the punch line could stimulate
Jewish recipients to engage in cognitive activity that interferes with their
later comprehension. To this extent, they might consider the joke to be less
funny than non-Jewish recipients would, even though the joke’s implica-
tions are consistent with their a priori values. (This conjecture assumes
that the joke is already moderately difficult to understand. If it were very
easy to understand, the increases in comprehension difficulty resulting
from this activity could increase Jewish individuals’ appreciation of the
joke rather than decreasing it.)

Effects of Cognitive Elaboration

Although individual differences in attitudes and values undoubtedly influ-


ence the comprehension of a joke or story, their primary effects are likely
to result from their impact on the cognitive elaboration that occurs subse-
quently. Suppose individuals encounter the following joke:

Q. What is the difference between a Jew and a canoe?


A. A canoe tips.

This joke is extremely easy to understand. Its humor derives from the
different meanings of “tips,” coupled with knowledge of the stereotype of
Jews as being tight with money. Thus, differences in the humor the joke
elicits are likely to be due largely to differences in the type of cognitive
elaboration that recipients perform subsequent to its comprehension. That
is, people who are generally offended by the perpetuation of the stereotype
may think about why the joke is told and may question the attitudes and
motives of the storyteller. However, people who personally believe the ste-
reotype, or are not concerned with perpetuating it, might not engage in this
humor-irrelevant elaboration.
There are two qualifications on this prediction, however. First, differ-
ences in reactions to the joke should only be evident when people have an
opportunity to elaborate its implications after comprehending it. When this
opportunity does not exist, recipients may be equally amused by the joke
regardless of their feelings about the group being disparaged. (This could
explain why people often laugh at jokes they hear at a party that they
would find unamusing in a less cognitively demanding situation in which
they had more opportunity to think about the jokes’ implications.)
A second contingency surrounds the elaboration potential of a joke.
When a joke’s humor-eliciting reinterpretation evokes visual images, or if
the situation it implies can be elaborated, individuals who are not offended
by the joke may elaborate its humor-eliciting implications and, therefore,
may be more amused by the joke than they might otherwise be. However,
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 221

jokes of the sort provided in our example, which are simply plays on words,
have low elaboration potential. The amusement elicited by these jokes is
unlikely to increase with the opportunity to engage in elaboration regard-
less of recipients’ attitudes toward the stereotyped group. In fact, if individ-
uals have nothing to distract them, any additional postcomprehension
thoughts they might have about the joke could pertain to the source of the
joke, and perhaps the validity of the stereotype, and these thoughts could
occur even if these individuals do not identify with the group being dispar-
aged. As a result, the amusement experienced by these individuals, like per-
sons who are disposed a priori to elaborate the humor-irrelevant implica-
tions of the joke, might decrease when they have an opportunity to think
about the joke more extensively.
A second study with Linda Isbell (see Isbell et al., 2002) examined this
possibility. Participants under thought and spontaneous reaction condi-
tions similar to those in Isbell’s earlier study were asked to read and give
their reactions to six stories. Four of the stories were nonhumorous, but
two others were jokes that had negative implications for the protagonist’s
intelligence. One of these jokes (e.g., the “desert island” joke described ear-
lier) had high elaboration potential, whereas the other (e.g., the “burned-
out light bulb” joke) had low elaboration potential. Moreover, the protago-
nist in one joke was described as Polish and in the other was described as a
Texas Aggie. (The type of protagonist associated with each joke was of
course counterbalanced.)
The midwestern college students who participated in this study were un-
doubtedly aware of the stereotype of Polish as unintelligent. However, they
were typically not of Polish extraction themselves, and were unlikely to be
offended by the jokes. (Participants’ reactions to the jokes in the experi-
ment confirmed this assumption; 65% of the participants reported being
“not at all” offended by these jokes, or 0 along the 0–10 scale used to report
their judgments.) Although Texas Aggies are sometimes stereotyped as un-
intelligent as well, this stereotype was generally unknown in the student
population from which participants were drawn. Based on the assumptions
outlined earlier, we expected that encouraging participants to think about
when Polish jokes with high elaboration potential would stimulate them to
elaborate the humor-eliciting aspects of the jokes, leading them to be more
amused by the jokes than they would otherwise be. In contrast, encourag-
ing participants to think about Polish jokes with low elaboration potential
should stimulate them to elaborate the jokes’ negative implications for the
stereotyped group to which the jokes refer, and thus should lead them to
be less amused by the jokes than they would otherwise be.
Results were consistent with these assumptions. Participants reported
being equally amused by Texas Aggie jokes regardless of whether they
were told to think about them (M = 4.16) or to give their spontaneous reac-
222 CHAPTER 8

tions (M = 4.52). In contrast, thinking about Polish jokes with high elabora-
tion potential increased the amusement the jokes elicited from 4.04 (under
spontaneous reaction conditions) to 5.13 (under thought conditions),
whereas thinking about Polish jokes with low elaboration potential de-
creased amusement from 4.96 to 3.86. These differences were reflected in an
interaction of elaboration potential and instructional conditions in an analy-
sis of reactions to Polish jokes alone, F(1,40) = 4.27, p < .05.
Thus, the results provide insight into people’s reactions to jokes that
perpetuate a negative stereotype. Thinking about a joke that perpetuates a
negative stereotype can obviously decrease the amusement experienced
by persons who are offended by the joke. However, thinking about such a
joke can also decrease the amusement experienced by persons who are not
offended by the joke, provided the joke’s humor-eliciting implications can-
not easily be elaborated.

The Effects of Social Context on Responses


to Sexist Humor

Humor-irrelevant cognitive elaborations are particularly likely when partici-


pants themselves belong to the stereotyped social category and, therefore,
are apt to be offended by it. However, this is not the only factor that can in-
fluence humor-irrelevant elaboration. In some cases, recipients might per-
ceive that a joke-teller is motivated by a desire to ingratiate his or her audi-
ence, or alternatively, to convey hostility toward the person or group that
the joke disparages. They might think about the implications of these mo-
tives regardless of whether or not they are personally offended by the joke.
Consequently, they might be relatively less amused by the joke than they
would be if the joke-teller were simply trying to be funny. In other cases,
people might be aware of the motives that lead a joke to be told and still
elaborate its humor-eliciting implications. (This is particularly true if the
joke’s elaboration potential is high, as suggested by the results of Isbell’s
experiment described earlier.)
The effects of these contextual factors may be particularly evident (at
least, among college students) when jokes exploit a negative stereotype of
men or women. Consider the following joke:

A man and a woman are in the elevator together. The woman suddenly starts
taking off her clothes and says, “Make me feel like a woman.” The man takes
off his clothes, throws them on the floor, and says, “Here, fold these.”

Women’s reactions to this joke, which perpetuates a negative stereotype


of women, are likely to differ from men’s reactions to it. However, the na-
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 223

ture of these reactions may depend on both the sex of the communicator
and the social context in which the joke was originally told. The effects of
these factors may be mediated by their influence on recipients’ assump-
tions about the speaker’s motives and, therefore, on the amount and type
of cognitive elaboration that they perform.

1. Perception of the Motives for Telling Sexist Jokes

The motives that people perceive to underlie the communication of sex-


ist jokes were investigated by Isbell et al. (2002). Male and female college
students were introduced to the study with instructions that we were par-
ticularly interested in the motives that people attribute to individuals who
tell jokes that convey negative stereotypes of men and women. With this
preamble, we gave participants a short questionnaire containing four (fe-
male-bashing) jokes that perpetuated a negative stereotype of women and
four other (male-bashing) jokes that conveyed a negative stereotype of men.
Each joke was preceded by an indication of the sex of both the person who
told the joke and the individual to whom it was told. (Each joke was associ-
ated an equal proportion of times with each of the four speaker–audience
configurations.)
Participants were asked to imagine that each joke had been told in the
situational context described and to estimate the likelihood that the joke-
teller was (a) just trying to be funny, (b) trying to gain social approval, or
(c) being intentionally hostile or aggressive. They also estimated the likeli-
hood that the joke-teller personally believed in the stereotype being con-
veyed. These estimates, reported along scales from 0 (not at all) to 10 (ex-
tremely), are shown in Table 8.6. as a function of the joke-teller’s sex, the sex
of the audience, and the type of joke that was told. Between-cell compari-
sons, shown in the table, suggest the following conclusions:

1. Participants in all cases inferred that the joke-teller’s primary motive


was to be funny (M = 7.30). However, they perceived this motive to be partic-
ularly strong (M = 8.08) when someone told a joke that disparaged the oppo-
site sex to a member of his or her own sex (i.e., when a man told a female-
bashing joke to another man, or a woman told a male-bashing joke to another
woman).
2. Joke-tellers were perceived to have less strong personal beliefs in the
stereotype implied by a joke when the joke disparaged members of their
own sex (M = 3.16) than when it disparaged members of the opposite sex (M =
5.10). However, this difference was evident both when men told a male-
bashing joke (2.28 vs. 4.97) and when women told a female-bashing joke (4.09
vs. 5.23).
224 CHAPTER 8

3. Joke-tellers were judged more likely to be seeking approval when they


either told a male-bashing joke to a female or told a female-bashing joke to a
male (M = 5.81) than when they told these jokes to members of the sex that
was being disparaged (M = 3.19). This was true regardless of whether the
joke disparaged males (5.75 vs. 3.37) or females (5.87 vs. 3.00).
4. Persons who told male-bashing jokes were attributed less hostility if
they were male (M = 1.37) than if they were female (M = 3.97). In contrast, per-
sons who told female-bashing jokes were seen as hostile regardless of their
sex (3.27 vs. 3.05 when the jokes were told by men and women, respectively).
In addition, joke-tellers were attributed greater hostility if they told a joke to
members of the sex being demeaned (M = 3.32) than if they told it to mem-
bers of the opposite sex (M = 2.51). This difference was evident regardless of
whether the joke disparaged men (3.07 vs. 2.26) or women (3.56 vs. 2.75).

2. Context Effects on Amusement and Offensiveness

If the motivational attributions described in Table 8.6 stimulate humor-


irrelevant elaboration, they should decrease the humor the sexist jokes
elicit. As our earlier experiments indicate, however, this elaboration may
not always occur.
To understand the effects of contextual factors on humor elicitation, it is
necessary to distinguish between the audience to whom a speaker intends
to communicate and the actual recipient. To this end, Isbell et al. (2002)
constructed stimulus materials using the same eight jokes employed in the
previous study (Table 8.6). One stimulus replication comprised four filler

TABLE 8.6
Motives Attributed to Tellers of Sexist Jokes as a Function of the
Joke-Teller’s Sex, the Sex of the Audience, and Joke Type

Male Joke-Teller Female Joke-Teller

Male Female Male Female


Audience Audience Audience Audience M

Motivation for telling male-bashing jokes


To be funny 7.67ab 7.47ab 6.59b 8.12a 7.46
Belief in stereotype 2.72b 1.84b 5.53a 4.41a 3.62
Social approval 3.69b 6.75a 3.06b 4.75b 4.56
Hostility 1.66b 1.09b 4.47a 3.44a 2.66
Motivation for telling female-bashing joke
To be funny 8.04a 7.00ab 7.08ab 6.46b 7.14
Belief in stereotype 4.58ab 5.88a 4.17b 3.92b 4.63
Social approval 6.46a 2.62b 5.29a 3.38b 4.43
Hostility 2.79 3.75 2.71 3.38 3.16

Note. Means in each row with unlike superscripts differ at p < .05.
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 225

jokes had nothing to do with sex-role stereotypes, two male-bashing jokes


and two female-bashing jokes. The second replication was composed of the
same filler jokes and the remaining four stereotype-related jokes.
Participants were told we were interested in how people respond to
jokes that were conveyed in social contexts outside the laboratory, and
that to study this, we had collected jokes in a number of informal conversa-
tions that had taken place on campus. On this pretense, we asked partici-
pants to give their reactions to eight jokes, preceded in each case by a de-
scription of the context in which the joke had ostensibly been told. (For
example, one joke had ostensibly been told by a male graduate student to
two female students at a coffee house, another had been told by a female
undergraduate to three undergraduate men at a fraternity party, etc.) Par-
ticipants were told to imagine they had actually overheard the joke being
told conveyed in this context, and to indicate both how amused they would
be by the joke and how offended they would be. These ratings were made
along scales from 0 (not at all) to 10 (extremely).
Each of the four filler jokes was ostensibly told to a mixed audience. The
joke-teller and audience assigned to the four target jokes were varied in a
partial latin square design so that pooled over participants and stimulus
replications, each target joke was told about the same number of times in
situations that represented each possible combination of speaker sex and
audience sex.
The top half of Table 8.7 shows the amusement elicited by each type of
joke as a function of the sex of the joke-teller, the sex of the audience, and
the sex of the participants. The bottom half of the table conveys the offen-
siveness of the jokes. The implications of these data are conveyed most
easily by considering separately participants’ reactions to (a) jokes that dis-
paraged their own sex and (b) jokes that disparaged the opposite sex.

Reactions to Jokes That Disparaged Participants’ Own Sex. First con-


sider jokes that perpetuate a negative stereotype of males. Men were less
amused by these jokes when they were told by a woman to a group of men
(M = 2.43) than they were in any of the other three joke-teller/audience
conditions (M = 4.19). Moreover, they were nonsignificantly more offended
by the jokes in this condition (M = 3.00) than in the other three conditions
(M = 1.86).
The data summarized in Table 8.6 suggest why this might be so. That is,
male-bashing jokes are perceived to convey greater hostility when women
tell them to a man (M = 4.47) than they are under other conditions (M =
2.06). In addition, joke-tellers are attributed stronger beliefs in the stereo-
type in the former condition than in others (5.53 vs. 2.99). It seems reason-
able to suppose that men who encounter a woman telling a male-bashing
joke to men are offended by the joke as a result of these attributions and
226 CHAPTER 8

cognitively elaborate its humor-irrelevant implications. Consequently, they


are less amused by the joke than they would otherwise be.
Note, however, that male-bashing jokes are also perceived to reflect hos-
tility, and a strong belief in a negative male stereotype, when a woman tells
these jokes to other women (see Table 8.6). Despite this fact, men were not
offended by the jokes in this condition (M = 1.63). Moreover, they were
more amused by the jokes in this condition than they were in other
speaker–audience conditions. Thus, men may have attributed hostility to a
woman who told a male-bashing joke, and may have thought that she per-
sonally believed in the stereotype she was perpetuating. Nevertheless, they
were only offended when she told the joke to men and, therefore, appeared
to be intentionally insulting.
Women’s reactions to jokes that disparaged females showed a different
pattern. As shown in Table 8.7, women were not very amused by female-
bashing jokes in any condition (M = 3.64). Moreover, although women were
somewhat less amused when joke-tellers told these jokes to someone of
their own sex than they told them to someone of the opposite sex, this dif-
ference was not reliable (p > .10). Perhaps women are generally threatened
by the perpetuation of a female stereotype and, therefore, are not amused
by female-bashing jokes regardless of the context in which the jokes are

TABLE 8.7
Males’ and Females’ Ratings of Jokes as Amusing and Offensive
as a Function of Joke Type, the Sex of the Joke Teller,
and the Sex of the Intended Audience

Male Joke-Teller Female Joke-Teller

Male Female Male Female


Audience Audience Audience Audience

Amusement Ratings

Male participants
Male-bashing joke 4.21 4.03 2.43 4.33
Female-bashing joke 4.18 4.72 3.51 5.07
Female participants
Male-bashing jokes 6.17 6.80 5.96 6.89
Female-bashing jokes 3.37 3.77 4.04 3.39

Offensiveness Ratings

Male participants
Male-bashing jokes 1.46 2.50 3.00 1.63
Female-bashing jokes 1.00 1.98 1.93 1.43
Female participants
Male-bashing jokes 0.90 0.87 1.57 0.39
Female-bashing jokes 2.43 3.70 3.54 3.23
DYNAMICS OF HUMOR ELICITATION 227

told. In contrast, men are not particularly threatened by the perpetuation of


a male stereotype. Therefore, they only fail to be amused by male-bashing
jokes when the joke-teller is intentionally insulting.

Jokes That Disparaged the Opposite Sex. Men (but not women) were
less amused by female-bashing jokes when the jokes were told to women
(M = 3.84) than when they were told to men (M = 4.90), and this was true re-
gardless of the joke-teller’s sex. Correspondingly, women (but not men)
were less amused by male-bashing jokes when these jokes were told to men
than when they were told to women (6.06 vs. 6.85). Thus, participants ap-
peared to be more amused when they perceived the joke-teller to be seek-
ing social approval (see Table 8.6). Conceivably both men and women rec-
ognized this motivation in all conditions. However, they only elaborated the
humor-irrelevant implications of the jokes when the jokes disparaged mem-
bers of their own sex.

3. Conclusions
The results of Isbell et al.’s studies are complex in detail. They never-
theless confirm the general conclusion that the social context in which a
stereotype-perpetuating joke is told can influence the amount of humor-
irrelevant cognitive elaboration that occurs in response to it and, there-
fore, the amount of humor that the joke elicits. Moreover, although this
elaboration is likely to concern the reason why the joke was conveyed, it
does not necessarily result from perceptions that the joke is particularly
offensive. In some instances, jokes were reported as funny despite being
offensive. In other cases, jokes were not considered very funny despite be-
ing perceived as relatively inoffensive. Perhaps the offensiveness of the
jokes was not a determinant of the humor-unrelated cognitive elaboration
that occurred, but instead, was a consequence of this elaboration. That is,
the social context in which a joke is told might create expectations for the
joke’s content, and a violation of these expectations might stimulate at-
tempts to construe the speaker’s motives. This cognitive activity could de-
crease the humor the joke elicits independently of the motive that the
speaker is ultimately attributed.

CONCLUDING REMARKS

Humor is a fundamental ingredient of social communication in everyday


life. A specification of the conditions in which it is elicited is therefore a nec-
essary component of any theory of real-world information processing. We
have argued that the experience of amusement is partly a result of the ba-
228 CHAPTER 8

sic processes of comprehension outlined in previous chapters of this book.


That is, it occurs when the episode models that have been formed sponta-
neously in the course of comprehending a sequence of events must be
modified in order to understand the sequence as a whole, thereby stimulat-
ing higher order, goal-directed information processing in order to perform
this modification.
However, although the reinterpretation of information that results from
this processing is a necessary antecedent of humor elicitation, it is not suffi-
cient. In addition, the reinterpretation that occurs must generally diminish
the value or importance of either the events described in the information
being processed, the participants in these events, the situational context in
which the information is conveyed or, in some cases, the information itself.
Moreover, the humor that is elicited by a social experience is also a func-
tion of the cognitive elaboration that occurs after its humor-eliciting reinter-
pretation has been identified. The amount and type of this elaboration,
which depends on both the stimulus information itself and the prior knowl-
edge and values of the recipient, can either add to or offset the amusement
that might otherwise be experienced.
The formulation we have proposed in this chapter does not intend to be
the final word. However, it provides a framework within which future
research and theorizing on humor elicitation can be conceptualized and in-
vestigated. At the same time, the comprehension and elaboration proc-
esses that underlie humor elicitation can also come into play in responding
to social information more generally and in making judgments and deci-
sions on the basis of this information. The last section of this volume is de-
voted to a discussion of these processes.
Although our discussion in this chapter has focused on the antecedents
of humor, we have ignored a consideration of its consequences. This con-
cern, which is obviously important, is beyond the scope of this book. One
obvious by-product of amusement, however, is the experience of positive
affect. To this extent, it could have an impact on information processing
similar to that of positive feelings more generally. These effects are also dis-
cussed in the final section of this volume.
P A R T

III
INFERENCE PROCESSES
C H A P T E R

9
Crimes, Vacations, and Political
Candidates: The Construction and
Use of Narratives in Social Judgments

The discussion of comprehension processes in the preceding chapters was


focused largely on the construction of narrative representations of social
experience. To the extent that these representations occupy the bulk of our
social knowledge (Schank & Abelson, 1995), they are correspondingly the
primary basis for judgments and decision to which this knowledge is rele-
vant. In this section, we consider the conditions in which narrative repre-
sentations are brought to bear on judgments and decisions and the proc-
esses that underlie their use.
Narrative representations can enter into inference processes in several
ways. As suggested in chapter 3, some inferences occur spontaneously
when comprehending a sequence of events in terms of a previously formed
narrative representation (Spiro, 1977; see also Graesser, Singer, & Trabasso,
1994). However, narrative-based inferences can also be the result of con-
scious goal-directed activity. In some cases, a narrative account of real and
imagined events might be particularly relevant to the objective at hand
(e.g., planning how to behave in order to please a date, construing the
events that lead up to a murder in a detective novel, or predicting the con-
sequences of taking a new job). In other cases, a narrative representation is
not essential. Nevertheless, information that is conveyed in a form that fa-
cilitates the construction and use of a narrative may be easy to compre-
hend in terms of previously acquired knowledge, and so inferences may be
based on this type of representation rather than other types.
The next two chapters discuss narrative-based inference processes in
some detail. In the present chapter, we consider the conditions in which
narrative representations of new information are constructed and used to

231
232 CHAPTER 9

make inferences about their referents. However, the construction of these


representations often requires the activation and use of previously formed
knowledge structures, many of which constitute implicit theories about the
causes and consequences of social events. The use of these implicit theo-
ries, and of previously formed narrative representations more generally,
are discussed in chapter 10.

THE IMPACT OF NARRATIVES


ON JURY DECISION MAKING

One of the first systematic explorations of narrative-based inference proc-


esses was conducted by Pennington and Hastie (1986, 1988, 1992) in re-
search on jury decision making. Jurors are presumably motivated to deter-
mine whether a person is guilty or innocent of a crime. (This situation is not
one that normally occurs in daily life. However, similar motives are likely to
operate when reading a news story, watching a movie, or reading an Agatha
Christie mystery novel.) To make this determination, people may attempt
to reconstruct the sequence of events that led up to the crime as well as the
crime itself and its aftermath.
This reconstruction can sometimes be difficult. For one thing, the events
are not always described in the order they occurred. In movies and mys-
tery novels, for example, events that occurred early in the sequence are of-
ten not revealed until near the end. Courtroom testimony is typically orga-
nized according the witnesses who provide it, and is not conveyed in the
order in which the events described are likely to occur. In such cases, peo-
ple are likely to find it cognitively taxing to fit the various pieces of evi-
dence into a scenario that permits their temporal and causal relatedness to
be evaluated. As a result, they may be inclined to use other strategies to
evaluate the evidence. In a jury trial, for example, they might attach more
importance to the credibility of witnesses who provide individual pieces of
evidence rather than considering how well the evidence fits into a coherent
account of the crime.
Pennington and Hastie (1986, 1988, 1992) provided compelling evidence
of narrative-based decision processes and the factors that influence them.
Participants in one study (Pennington & Hastie, 1988) read the transcript of
a murder trial and were asked to think aloud as they arrived at a decision
about the defendant’s guilt. Content analyses revealed that participants’
thought protocols were more likely to have a “story” structure than to have
other possible (e.g., categorical) structures. A further study confirmed this
conclusion. That is, participants who had read the testimony and reported
CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 233

their verdict were given a recognition memory test containing some state-
ments that had actually been made in the course of the testimony and oth-
ers that had not. Participants were more likely to report a statement as hav-
ing been mentioned in the story if its implications were consistent with the
narrative-based causal scenario on which they based their verdict than if
its implications were inconsistent with this scenario.
A second series of studies (Pennington & Hastie, 1988) examined these
inference processes more directly. Participants listened to the transcript of
an actual murder trial containing testimony for both the prosecution and
the defense. In witness-order conditions, the evidence favoring a given ver-
dict was organized according to the witness who provided it, as in the origi-
nal trial. In story-order conditions, the evidence for a given side was pre-
sented in the order it became relevant in the sequence of events that had
allegedly occurred. (That is, testimony about events that preceded the inci-
dent was presented first, followed by testimony about the incident itself,
the arrest, the autopsy, etc.). This was done in a 2 ´ 2 design so that the or-
der of presenting the prosecution testimony and the order of presenting
the defense testimony were varied independently. Participants after receiv-
ing the testimony reported both their verdict and their confidence that
their decision was correct.
When the defense and prosecution testimonies were presented in differ-
ent orders, 73% of the participants recommended the verdict implied by the
evidence that was conveyed in story order. When the evidence favoring
both verdicts was presented in the same way, the percentage of partici-
pants who favored a guilty verdict did not depend on how the evidence was
ordered. However, participants were much more confident of their judg-
ments when the evidence was in story order. In short, evidence that was
conveyed in an order that facilitated the construction of a narrative ac-
count of the crime was apparently easier to comprehend, and so recipients
were more confident of its implications. Consequently, they were more
likely to base their judgments on this evidence than on evidence conveyed
in other ways.
This conclusion has further implications. For example, if people have
formed a narrative of the sequence of events that occur, they may be more
receptive to additional information that is consistent with the implications
of the narrative as a whole than to information that conflicts with these im-
plications. Moreover, this could be true regardless of the credibility of the
information’s source. In contrast, if people are unable to construct a coher-
ent narrative representation of the information, they may construe the im-
plications of each piece separately. In this case, the credibility of source of
this additional information should be given more weight.
234 CHAPTER 9

A COMPARISON OF NARRATIVE-BASED
VERSUS NONNARRATIVE-BASED
INFORMATION PROCESSING

General Considerations

A narrative account of a crime is of particular relevance in assessing the


likelihood that the defendant was motivated or able to commit it. Partici-
pants in Pennington and Hastie’s studies may conceivably have tried to
construct a narrative account of the events that occurred regardless of how
the information was presented, but simply found it easier to attain this ob-
jective when the information was conveyed in temporal order. As these au-
thors point out, however (Hastie & Pennington, 1995), many of the decisions
we are called upon to make in daily life are not typically based on narra-
tives. Rather, they are based on spatial, functional, hierarchical, and argu-
mentative criteria. The mental representations that are formed in the
course of applying these criteria may be quite different. Thus, for example,
computer commands might be cognitively organized on the basis of func-
tional considerations, and the arguments bearing on a particular issue
might be organized according to the alternative points of view they sup-
port. Goal-related differences in the representations that people form of in-
formation, which were discussed in chapter 6, are considered more gener-
ally by Pennington and Hastie (1993).
Even within a knowledge domain, a number of alternative strategies
might be used to compute a judgment or decision. For example, the evalua-
tion of a consumer product could be based on either an imagined sequence
of events that surround the use of the product and its consequences or a
piecemeal analysis of the product’s individual features (cf. Fiske &
Pavelchak, 1986). In such cases, the strategy that people use, and the men-
tal representation they construct in the course of applying it, may depend
on situational or informational factors that exist at the time the information
is received. Two factors—the format in which the information is presented
and the presence or absence of pictures—are of particular interest.

1. Effects of Presentation Format


on Processing Strategies
When information describes a temporally ordered sequence of events
that are situationally constrained, people may spontaneously construct an
episode model of this sequence in the course of comprehending it (Postu-
late 4.1). Under these conditions, people are likely to base their judgments
on the implications of the model as a whole without analyzing its individual
features. In contrast, suppose individuals receive the same information in
an ostensibly unordered list. In this case, they may not attempt to assess
CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 235

the temporal or thematic relatedness of the events unless this relatedness


is particularly relevant to the goal they are pursuing. Instead, they may
adopt a piecemeal processing strategy. That is, they may assess the
evaluative implications of each piece of information independently and in-
tegrate these implications using a mechanistic procedure similar to that de-
scribed by algebraic models of information integration (cf. Anderson, 1971,
1981; Fishbein & Hunter, 1964).
Both holistic and piecemeal processing strategies may become very well
learned as a result of numerous past experiences in which they have been
applied. Personal experiences are inherently in the form of a narrative, and
people have undoubtedly acquired procedures for construing their implica-
tions that they activate and apply automatically to new experiences that
are similar in form. Verbal descriptions of temporally related events of the
sort that compose a personal experience could likewise stimulate a holistic
inference process. However, people also learn procedures for aggregating a
number of unrelated items. This learning could occur in both formal situa-
tions (e.g., solving arithmetic problems in school) and informal ones (e.g.,
making a decision on the basis of a consideration of its possible conse-
quences, or estimating whether one has enough money to pay for the gro-
ceries one wishes to purchase). Once learned, these procedures could be
used to construe the implications of information that is conveyed in a man-
ner similar to that in which the procedures have typically been applied in
the past. To this extent, the procedures could function as “if [X], then [Y]”
productions of the sort proposed by Anderson (1983; see also Smith, 1984,
1990), which are activated and applied spontaneously whenever the elicit-
ing conditions for their application [X] are met. The format in which infor-
mation is received could be one of these eliciting conditions.

2. The Role of Visual Imagery


The mental representations that people form in the course of using these
procedures are likely to differ in an important respect. Event and episode
models consist in part of visual images (Postulate 4.2). Pictures of the
events to which these models refer are likely to facilitate the construction
of the models and to increase the detail with which their referents are en-
coded into memory. To this extent, the pictures should increase the ex-
tremity of the evaluations that are based on these models. In contrast, the
information that is conveyed in a list, which is not temporally related, may
be represented only semantically, as a network of features. Moreover, the
piecemeal integration procedure that people activate and use to integrate
the implications of these semantic features may not normally involve a con-
sideration of mental images. To this extent, pictures might not facilitate a
computation of evaluations on the basis of this strategy. In fact, they could
even interfere.
236 CHAPTER 9

The role of pictures and visual images in the computation of evaluations


is surprisingly unclear. Lampel and Anderson (1968) applied an information
integration model in assessing the way in which pictures and personality
trait descriptions combined to influence female participants’ judgments of a
man’s datability. Their data were consistent with an averaging model in
which the weight attached to the man’s physical appearance was inversely
related to its favorableness. (More generally, women appeared to perceive
the man’s physical attractiveness to be a necessary but not sufficient condi-
tion for dating him.)
In Lampel and Anderson’s study, however, pictures were an independent
source of information about the person being rated and, therefore, were
used in addition to the verbal information provided. When pictures simply
elaborate the same attributes that are described verbally, their impact is
not as clear. Studies of consumer behavior suggest that when pictures ac-
company nonnarrative text (e.g., product attribute descriptions), they often
have little impact on judgments over and above the effect of the text infor-
mation alone (Edell & Staelin, 1983; see also Costley & Brucks, 1992). In fact,
this impact may only be appreciable when recipients have little personal in-
terest in the verbal information they receive about the products they evalu-
ate (Miniard et al., 1991). (In these latter conditions, recipients might tend
to base their judgments on pictures alone without bothering to assess the
implications of the verbal information at all.)
Two series of experiments by Adaval and her colleagues examined the
interactive effects of pictures and information presentation format in some
detail. In one set of studies (Adaval & Wyer, 1998), participants evaluated
vacations of the sort they might personally experience. In a second set
(Adaval, Isbell, & Wyer, 2003), participants evaluated politicians on the ba-
sis of information about events that occurred over the course of their lives.
Thus, the two sets of studies differed in the extent to which situation-
specific episode models were likely to be formed in the course of compre-
hending the event descriptions and, therefore, in the likelihood that the
events would elicit visual images spontaneously.

The Role of Narratives in Judgments


of Imagined Personal Experiences

In the studies by Adaval and Wyer (1998), participants read two travel bro-
chures. One brochure described a vacation in India and the other, a vaca-
tion in Thailand. Each brochure began with a general overview of the vaca-
tion, followed by descriptions of 12 places that the vacationers would visit.
These events were always conveyed in the same order. In one brochure,
however, the events were described in a narrative, and in the other, they
CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 237

were conveyed in an ostensibly unordered list. In narrative-format condi-


tions, for example, the India vacation brochure began:

On your vacation, you will start out from the capital of India, Delhi, and move
on to see the Taj Mahal. Later, you will go west and see the palaces and tem-
ples in the colorful deserts of Rajasthan . . . before heading south. Further
south, you will visit the beaches of Goa, the tropical forests and backwaters of
Kerala, and . . . complete your trip at the southernmost tip of India.

This was followed by written narrative descriptions of the places to be vis-


ited. For example:

Only a short trip from Delhi is Agra, the home of the Taj Mahal. A mausoleum
built by Shah Jahan for his empress, the Taj is widely regarded as the most
beautiful man-made structure in the world. Remarkable at all times of the day,
you will visit as the sun rises above the early morning mists and return on a
moon-lit night when the Taj seems to float unattached above the blue-green
pools in front of it.

In contrast, the India brochure under list-format conditions described as-


pects of the vacation without indicating the order in which the events de-
scribed would occur. This brochure began with a simple listing of high-
lights:

Some features of your vacation experience are:


· a visit to the capital, Delhi
· the cool mystery of the forests
· the forest tribes
· the Taj Mahal at Agra
· palaces and temples in Rajasthan, etc.

Moreover, the individual places and situations were described in a simi-


lar manner:
· Agra, home to one of the most beautiful man-made structures in the world.
· the Taj Mahal—a mausoleum built by Shah Jahan for his empress.
· a beautiful spectacle both when the sun rises above the early morning mists
and on moonlit nights when the Taj seems to float above the blue-green
pools in front of it.
238 CHAPTER 9

1. Experiment 1
In the first study, an attractive picture accompanied the verbal descrip-
tion of each event. However, the relative dominance of the pictures and ver-
bal descriptions varied. In some cases, the pictures were large and the ver-
bal descriptions were in small (10-point) font. In other cases, the pictures
were relatively small and the verbal descriptions were in large (18-point)
font. To ensure that format and picture-word dominance were not con-
founded with information content, the particular vacation representing
each combination of these variables was counterbalanced. Participants af-
ter reading both brochures evaluated the extent to which the brochure per-
taining to each vacation made them want to go there. Then, they reported
the difficulty they had had in imagining each of the two vacations and fi-
nally, recalled the events contained in each brochure.

Processing Efficiency. The ease of processing the information under


each presentation format condition was inferred from both participants’
self-reported ease of imagining each vacation and their memory for events
that would occur in it. Data pertaining to these indices are shown in the
first two sections of Table 9.1. When the text information was dominant,
participants found it fairly easy to imagine the vacation regardless of for-
mat, and had relatively better recall of the places they would visit when the
information was conveyed in a list. When the information was conveyed in
a narrative, however, increasing the dominance of the picture decreased
the difficulty of imagining the vacation and increased recall of the places to
be visited. When the same information was presented in a list, on the other
hand, increasing the dominance of the pictures had the opposite effects. In
other words, pictures appeared to facilitate the processing of information
that was presented in a narrative. However, they interfered with the seman-
tic, piecemeal processing of this information when it was conveyed in a list.

Effects on Judgments. The combined effects of format and pictures in


evaluations of the vacations are consistent with the processing differences
just described. The bottom section of Table 9.1 shows evaluations of the
first vacation that participants considered.19 When the text was dominant,
participants rated the vacation somewhat less favorably when the informa-
tion about it was conveyed in a narrative than when it was described in a
list. However, increasing the dominance of pictures increased evaluations

19
19 Participants appeared to use the same criteria to judge the second vacation they consid-
ered that they used to judge the first one, even though the information was conveyed in a differ-
ent format. Thus, the effects of format on judgments of the second vacation were the mirror im-
age of its effects on judgments of the first. (This was true in the second experiment to be
reported as well.)
CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 239

TABLE 9.1
Effects of Information Presentation Format and
Picture-Text Dominance on Recall and Judgments

Narrative Format List Format

Difficulty of imagining vacation


Pictures dominant 3.2 6.3
Text dominant 4.5 4.7
Proportion of places recalled
Pictures dominant .52 .37
Text dominant .48 .55
Evaluations of first vacation presented
Pictures dominant 7.3 4.1
Text dominant 6.5 7.9

Note. Adapted from Adaval and Wyer (1998).

of the vacation in the first case and decreased it in the second. As a result,
evaluations of a vacation when pictures were dominant were much more fa-
vorable when the vacation was described in a narrative than when it was
described in a list.

2. Experiment 2

A second experiment confirmed these conclusions. In this study, the


text-dominant condition was replaced by one in which participants re-
ceived only text information and no pictures were presented at all. In addi-
tion, some participants were explicitly told to imagine themselves actually
having the experience described on each page of the brochure. We rea-
soned that if the effects of picture results from the mental images they stim-
ulate explicitly telling participants to form their own mental images of the
events might have similar effects.
Results confirmed this reasoning. Participants’ evaluations of the first va-
cation they considered are shown in Table 9.2 as a function of presentation
format, the presence of pictures and imagination instructions (see Footnote
20). When the vacation was described in a narrative, participants evaluated
it more favorably when both pictures were presented and they were told to
imagine the events described (M = 8.1) than they did under other condi-
tions (M = 6.4). When the vacation was described in a list, however, partici-
pants evaluated it somewhat less favorably in the first condition than in
other conditions (5.8 vs. 6.1). Thus, both studies converge on the conclu-
sion that people form mental images of events that are conveyed in a narra-
tive, and that situational conditions that encourage the construction of
these images increase the extremity of their judgments. On the other hand,
these same conditions interfere with the piecemeal processing that under-
240 CHAPTER 9

TABLE 9.2
Evaluations of Vacations as a Function of Presentation Format,
Presence of Pictures and Imagination Instructions

Narrative Format List Format

Imagination instructions
Pictures presented 8.1 5.8
No pictures 6.3 6.8
No imagination instructions
Pictures presented 6.4 6.1
No pictures 6.5 5.5

Note. Adapted from Adaval and Wyer (1998).

lies people’s computation of evaluations on the basis of listed information


and, therefore, decrease the extremity of these evaluations.

3. Effects of Information Inconsistency


Research in other domains suggests that people who are asked to judge
a stimulus give greater weight to unfavorable information about the stimu-
lus than to favorable information about it (Birnbaum, 1974; Skowronski &
Carlston, 1989; Wyer, 1973, 1974). However, this may only be true when each
piece of information is considered in isolation. If the information is con-
veyed in a narrative, people presumably base their evaluations on the im-
plications of the sequence of events as a whole, and so unfavorable infor-
mation that is embedded in otherwise favorable information is likely to
have less impact. Supplementary data obtained in Adaval and Wyer’s first
experiment confirmed this speculation. In some conditions, descriptions of
two relatively unpleasant aspects of the vacation (e.g., poor living accom-
modations, an arduous bus ride, etc.) were included among the favorable
event descriptions. Although adding these undesirable features decreased
participants’ evaluations of the vacation, this decrease was much greater
when the information was listed (from 6.0 to. 4.7) than when it was con-
veyed in a narrative (from 6.9 to 6.4).

THE INFLUENCE OF NARRATIVES


ON POLITICAL IMPRESSION FORMATION

We speculated that the format in which information is presented could acti-


vate a cognitive “production” that is applied automatically, with little
awareness. On the other hand, it could also induce an implicit expectation
for the type of processing strategy that should be applied, and participants
might consciously attempt to comply with this expectation. In Adaval and
CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 241

Wyer’s studies, it is unclear which was the case. It was also unclear whether
the facilitating effects of pictures are restricted to conditions in which epi-
sode models are likely to be formed from the information presented or
whether their effects generalize to conditions in which the narrative infor-
mation is unlikely to activate these models (e.g., abstract descriptions of
events that are not temporally or situationally constrained).
Adaval, Isbell, and Wyer (2003) provided evidence of this generaliz-
ability. Some of the more important judgments that people are called upon
to make outside the laboratory are their evaluations of candidates for pub-
lic office. These judgments are presumably based in part on the candidates’
stands on social and political issues. Ever since the 1960 Kennedy–Nixon de-
bates, however, it has been widely recognized that voters’ evaluations of
politicians are influenced at least as much by the global images of the can-
didates that are largely unrelated to the candidates’ political ideology or
specific issue positions (Englis, 1994). These images are undoubtedly stimu-
lated in part by a candidate’s physical appearance, as conveyed in a maga-
zine or on television. However, they can also be influenced by descriptions
of the individual’s activities over the course of his or her lifetime that have
implications for intelligence, morality, or steadfastness. Thus, information
that a candidate had smoked marijuana in college, or performed a heroic
deed in World War II, can have an impact on inferences about the candi-
date’s character and, therefore, judgments of his or her suitability for office
at a much later point in time.
Adaval et al. (2003) examined the processes that underlie the construc-
tion of the images that people form of politicians using procedures similar
to those employed in the vacation studies. The first two studies confirmed
Adaval and Wyer’s earlier findings and, in doing so, provided evidence that
the processing strategies that participants employed under different pre-
sentation format conditions were activated and applied automatically, with
little awareness. Two other studies used recognition response times to un-
derstand more specifically the cognitive representations that were formed
of information under conditions in which the strategies were employed. A
final study explored the role of both pictures and mental imagery in politi-
cal information processing and clarified further the processes that contrib-
uted to judgments in the earlier experiments.
Participants in an initial study were told we were interested in the im-
pressions people form of famous personalities. On this pretense, they
read brochures about two political figures who had been well known dur-
ing the period they held office. Each brochure began with an overview of
the major events in the politician’s life, followed by 12 additional pages
each describing an event or situation in more detail. As in the vacation
studies, the information in one brochure was conveyed in a narrative and
the information in the other was conveyed in the form of a list. In narra-
242 CHAPTER 9

tive-format conditions, for example, the brochure describing one politi-


cian (Thomas Winters) began:

Thomas Winters was a well-known political figure between 1950 and 1975. He
was a veteran of World War II and served as an executive of General Motors
before becoming Governor of Michigan. He then served two years as a U. S.
Senator, and ended his career as a special envoy to China.

This paragraph was followed by a series of paragraphs, each describing a


different event that occurred during the politician’s career and the point at
which it occurred. For example:

He left General Motors to become Governor of Michigan. There, he showed


sensitivity to public interests. Upon assuming office, for example, he went on
television to oppose the construction of a nuclear waste processing plant
near Detroit that would contaminate the city’s water supply.

Other activities included urging the government to halt the bombing in Viet-
nam, donating his summer home for use by a charitable organization, host-
ing the Pope during his visit to America, and helping to revise the state bud-
get to provide support for crime prevention.
In contrast, the brochure under list-format conditions described the
events in the politician’s life in bullet form and did not indicate their tempo-
ral relatedness. Thus, the brochure pertaining to Winters began:

Thomas Winters was a well-known political figure between 1950 and 1970. He
was:

· a member of the U. S. Senate


· a World War II veteran
· a General Motors executive
· Governor of Michigan
· special envoy to China

Although the individual events were conveyed in the same order they were
presented in narrative-format conditions, they were also conveyed in bul-
lets that had no temporal implications:

· Was sensitive to the interests of the public while Governor of Michigan.


· Went on television to oppose the construction of a nuclear waste processing
plant that would contaminate the city’s water supply.

Information about each life event was presented on a different page of


the brochure. In picture conditions, the information was accompanied by a
black-and-white photograph. In some cases, the picture showed the politi-
CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 243

cian engaged in an activity related to the event (giving a speech, talking to


someone, etc.) whereas in other cases, it portrayed an event-related situa-
tion in which the individual was not involved. (Thus, for example, a state-
ment that the politician had headed a committee to investigate how to de-
crease violent crime was accompanied by a policeman at the scene of a
murder.) The pictures were taken from books and magazines. (Pictures of
Henry Kissinger were used for one of the two politicians, and pictures of
Robert McNamara were used for the other. Pretesting indicated that neither
politician’s face was familiar to the college student population from which
participants were drawn.)
Participants after reading the brochures reported the favorableness of
their impressions of each politician along a scale from -5 (very unfavorable)
to +5 (very favorable) and estimated the difficulty of imagining the sequence
of events that occurred in the person’s life. Finally, they were asked to re-
call the events they had read about.
As the aforementioned examples indicate, many of the events described
in the information were not situationally and temporally constrained. More-
over, they were widely separated in time and occurred in unrelated situa-
tions. Therefore, the events were unlikely to be integrated into a single epi-
sode model. Nevertheless, our results were similar to those observed by
Adaval and Wyer (1998). As shown in the top half of Table 9.3, participants
in the absence of pictures evaluated politicians less favorably when the in-
formation about them was conveyed in a narrative than when it was listed.
However, introducing pictures increased evaluations in the former condi-
tion and decreased it in the latter. As a result, evaluations of the politicians
when pictures were presented were more favorable when the information
was conveyed in a narrative than when it was listed. Although these differ-
ences were small in magnitude, the interaction of format and pictures was
reliable (p < .05). Recall data, shown in the bottom half of the table, had a
similar pattern. That is, pictures increased the recall of events that were de-
scribed in a narrative but not when they were listed, suggesting that they

TABLE 9.3
Impressions of Politicians and Number of Events Recalled as a Function
of Format, the Presence of Pictures, and Presentation Order

Narrative Format List Format

Impressions of politician
Pictures 3.98 3.63
No pictures 3.58 3.95
Number of items recalled
Pictures 5.79 4.92
No pictures 5.04 4.98

Note. Adapted from Adaval et al. (2002, Experiment 1).


244 CHAPTER 9

facilitated memory for the events in the former case but not the latter. In
contrast to Adaval and Wyer’s studies (see Footnote 20), these effects were
evident for both the first politician that participants considered and the
second.

Deliberative Versus Spontaneous Influences of Format


on Information Processing Strategies

If participants intentionally use a holistic or piecemeal strategy when they


encounter information in a narrative or a list, respectively, explicit instruc-
tions to employ the strategies should override the effects of format. On the
other hand, suppose the strategies have the status of cognitive productions
that are activated and applied automatically when information to which
they are applicable is encountered. Then, they may have an influence re-
gardless of participants’ conscious attempts to employ other criteria.
To evaluate these possibilities, participants in a second experiment were
exposed to stimulus materials identical to those in the first study. In this
case, however, we told participants explicitly which processing strategy we
would like them to use. Under piecemeal-instruction conditions, we indi-
cated:

Sometimes people form impressions of a person by focusing on specific


events in a person’s life (e.g., winning a lottery). At other times, however, they
try to think about the person’s life as a whole and whether it was admirable,
successful, happy, etc. In this study, we would like you to use the first strat-
egy. That is, when reading about the political figures described in the brochures,
try to imagine the specific events that occurred in each politician’s life and their
implications for your impression of the politician. Use these individual events as a
basis for your impression.

Under holistic-instruction conditions, participants were told:

Sometimes people. . . . happy, etc. In this study, we would like you to use the
second strategy. That is, when reading about the political figures described in the
brochure, try to imagine each politician’s life as a whole and use this as a basis for
your impression.

1. Judgments and Recall


In fact, telling participants what processing strategy they should use had
little impact on the judgments they made. Table 9.4 shows participants’
evaluations as a function of instructions, presentation format, and the pres-
ence of pictures. Results replicated those of the first experiment. That is,
CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 245

TABLE 9.4
Impressions of Politician as a Function of Format, Task Demands,
the Presence of Pictures, and Presentation Order

Narrative Format List Format

Schematic instructions
Pictures 3.94 3.61
No pictures 3.46 4.03
Piecemeal instructions
Pictures 3.76 3.12
No pictures 4.00 4.02
Mean
Pictures 3.85 3.37
No pictures 3.73 4.03

Note. Adapted from Adaval et al. (2002, Experiment 2).

adding pictures slightly increased evaluations of politicians who were de-


scribed in a narrative and decreased evaluations of politicians based on in-
formation conveyed in a list. As a result, the advantage of a narrative over a
list format was significantly greater when pictures were presented (3.85 vs.
3.37) than when they were not (3.73 vs. 4.02), F(1,56) = 7.49, p < .01. These ef-
fects did not significantly depend on the instructions that participants were
given concerning the strategy they should use (p > .10).
The effects of task demands cannot be ruled out entirely, however. Note
that pictures facilitated impressions to the greatest extent when the informa-
tion was conveyed in a narrative and participants were told to apply a sche-
matic criterion (3.94 vs. 3.46 under picture and no-picture conditions, respec-
tively). Correspondingly, they interfered with impressions to the greatest
extent when participants were told to base their judgments on specific
events and the information as conveyed in a list (3.12 vs. 4.02, respectively).
These data therefore suggest that participants did attempt to apply the crite-
ria they were told to use, and these conscious efforts added slightly to the
spontaneous effects that were induced by the format of the information.
However, neither the effect of task demands nor its interaction with pictures
was statistically significant. Thus, the impact of these demands was very
small in relation to the effects of presentation format per se.
Recall data also confirmed the results of the first experiment. That is,
participants recalled a significantly greater number of events when the in-
formation was conveyed in a narrative than when it was conveyed in a list
(4.91 vs. 4.22), and this effect was greater when pictures were presented
(4.99 vs. 3.85) than when they were not (4.82 vs. 4.58). However, these ef-
fects also did not depend on instructional set.
246 CHAPTER 9

2. Self-Report Data
The failure for participants’ judgments to be appreciably influenced by
explicit instructions concerning the criteria they should use suggests that
the strategies that are elicited by different presentation formats were ap-
plied unintentionally. In fact, the use of these strategies, and the impact of
pictures on their effectiveness, may occur without awareness. Several as-
pects of the supplementary data we collected suggest this conclusion. For
one thing, participants’ self-reports indicated they attempted to apply the
same strategy in evaluating the second politician they saw that they had ap-
plied in judging the first one, even though the information about the second
politician was conveyed in a different format. In fact, however, their actual
judgments of the two politicians were quite dependent on format in much
the same way.
Second, the effect of format on participants’ actual evaluations of the
politicians depended on whether pictures were presented but did not de-
pend significantly on task demands (see Table 9.4). In contrast, its effect on
the criteria that participants reported using as a basis for these evaluations
depended on task demands but not on the presence of pictures. Moreover,
analyses of participants’ estimates of the extent to which pictures facili-
tated the impressions they formed did not significantly depend on either
task demands or presentation format.
These results therefore argue against the possibility that the effects of
presentation format reflect a conscious attempt to comply with implicit for-
mat-based expectations concerning the criteria to be used in making judg-
ments. Rather, different presentation formats appear to activate different
processing strategies that participants apply automatically, and that have
effects independently of the strategies they actively try to use. The pres-
ence of pictures may nevertheless facilitate or interfere, depending on the
particular strategy that participants actually employ.

The Role of Pictures in Narrative-Based Processing:


A Reconceptualization

Although the interactive effects of pictures and presentation format in the


preceding studies were very similar to those observed by Adaval and Wyer
(1998), they nevertheless raise questions about the content and structure of
the mental representations that underlie these effects. The assumption that
the event descriptions conveyed under narrative-format conditions were
stored in memory as a sequence of temporally related events was con-
firmed by Adaval et al. (2003) in a study of recognition memory. Partici-
pants were exposed to stimuli under conditions comparable to those con-
structed in the first experiment by Adaval et al. (2003). Rather than judging
the politicians, however, they were given a timed recognition memory test
CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 247

for the verbal descriptions of the events presented. The order in which the
recognition items were presented was systematically varied. We assumed
that if two presentation items were associated in memory, exposure to one
of these items would spontaneously activate the second, and so the speed
with which the second item could be identified would be increased. When
the original information had been conveyed in a narrative, participants
were quicker to identify an event if it was preceded by a description of the
event that had come before it in the presentation sequence (M = 3.68 s) than
if it was preceded by a different item (M = 4.16 s). When the items had been
conveyed in a list, however, this difference was negligible (4.21 s vs. 4.18 s).
These data suggest that the events were organized in memory in a tempo-
ral sequence when they were conveyed in a narrative, but that this was not
the case when the events were presented in a list.
The influence of pictures on the representations that participants
formed is less clear. We assumed that when information was conveyed in a
narrative, participants would form mental images of the events and that
these images would become part of the representations of these events
that they stored in memory. Unlike Adaval and Wyer’s (1998) studies, how-
ever, many of the pictures used in the present experiment were only indi-
rectly connected to the event descriptions they accompanied. (E.g., the ver-
bal description of Harrison as displaying courage under enemy gunfire in
World War II was accompanied by a picture that showed him in an army
uniform but did not portray him as actually engaged in combat. Similarly,
the verbal description of him as showing sensitivity to the needs of the
poor and disabled, and as initiating legislation to provide assistance to
homeless children, was accompanied by a picture of him seated a desk
rather than as actively involved in this behavior.) Thus, although the pic-
tures may have facilitated the construction of mental images of the events
presented, their specific content may not itself have been part of the repre-
sentation that was formed and stored in memory.
A second recognition memory study confirmed this speculation. In this
study, both pictures and verbal event descriptions were used as test stim-
uli. Participants did not recognize an event description any more quickly if
it had been preceded in the recognition series by the picture that had ac-
companied it in the original stimulus materials than if it had been preceded
by a novel picture, and this was true regardless of whether the events had
been conveyed in a narrative (1.84 s vs. 1.81 s) or in a list (1.66 s vs. 1.60 s).20
In other words, the specific picture that accompanied the event description

20
20 The generally shorter recognition times in this study than the preceding one is attributable
to the fact that American students participated in this study and Hong Kong Chinese students in
the earlier one. The latter students generally took longer to read the English phrases than Amer-
icans did.
248 CHAPTER 9

was not associated with the description in memory under either format
condition.
These data therefore suggest that pictures played a somewhat different
role in the representations formed under these conditions than they played
in Adaval and Wyer’s (1998) research. The nature of this role is suggested
by a conceptualization of visual information processing by Barsalou (1993).
That is, a photograph of a person might stimulate the formation of a “per-
ceptual symbol” that people mentally manipulate along with other symbols
to construct a visual image of the person’s activities in not only the situa-
tion to which the picture pertains but other situations as well. (This could
occur in much the same way that a previously formed mental picture of a
colleague’s physical appearance stimulates an image of his or her actions in
a story that someone tells.) Moreover, this perceptual symbol may be ap-
plied across situations, establishing a stronger connection between the
events that occur in a narrative than would otherwise exist. Pictures of a
person could create such a symbol and, therefore, could facilitate the con-
struction of a visual image of events in which the individual is involved
even if they are not themselves directly related to these events.
If this is the case, however, pictures of the person should facilitate the
construction of a coherent image-based narrative representation of the per-
son’s life even when the pictures do not become associated with the spe-
cific events that accompany them. For that matter, pictures of the politician
should have similar effects even if they do not accompany the written event
descriptions at all, but are presented at the outset, before any of these de-
scriptions are provided.
These speculations were confirmed in an additional study described in
the next section. In this study, pictures did not accompany the verbal de-
scriptions of the politicians’ life events. In some cases, however, four photo-
graphs of the politician were provided at the outset, before the event de-
scriptions were presented. Each picture provided a clear image of the
politician’s physical appearance but contained few other indications of the
context in which the pictures were taken.
Relative to conditions in which no pictures at all were presented, intro-
ducing pictures at the outset increased the favorableness of participants’
evaluations of the politicians, and this was true both when the information
was conveyed in a narrative (3.56 vs. 2.88) and when it was listed (3.35 vs.
2.56). Thus, pictures that were presented at the outset had the same influ-
ence under narrative-format conditions that they had when they were con-
veyed in the context of the event descriptions. Furthermore, presenting pic-
tures before the event descriptions in list-format conditions eliminated the
interference effects that occurred when the pictures accompanied these de-
scriptions, leading the pictures to have a positive influence on judgments
under these conditions as well.
CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 249

These results indicate that the influence of pictures in Adaval et al.’s


(2003) other studies did not derive from the information they provided about
the events themselves. Nor did it result from the evaluative implications of
the pictures per se; considered out of context, the pictures were evaluatively
neutral and conveyed very little information about the politicians they de-
picted. Rather, the pictures stimulated the formation of “perceptual symbols”
(Barsalou, 1993) that people used to construct mental images of the politi-
cians engaging in the events they later read about, in much the same way
that the picture of a character in a novel helps the reader to imagine verbal
descriptions of the character’s actions in the text. This facilitation can occur
both when the events are conveyed in a narrative and when they are not. On
the other hand, accompanying listed events with pictures appears to inter-
fere with the piecemeal integration processes that are activated by this pre-
sentation format and occur on-line, as the information is presented and a
judgment is computed. The adverse effects of this interference override the
beneficial effects that the pictures might otherwise have.

THE ROLE OF VISUAL IMAGERY ON VERBAL


INFORMATION PROCESSING: ADDITIONAL
CONSIDERATIONS

The conclusions drawn from the results just described call attention to the
need to examine more closely the impact of visual images on the process-
ing of verbal information. Two quite different studies in the political domain
bear on this impact. The first identifies the influence of individual and situa-
tional differences in the tendency to form visual images on the impact of
verbal event descriptions. The second shows the way in which visual im-
ages can influence the implications that people extract from other types of
verbal information.

Individual and Situational Differences in Visual Imagery


and Its Effects on Information Processing

To reiterate, the influence of pictures on judgments appears to occur be-


cause the pictures facilitate the construction of mental images of events
that are described verbally. If this is so, other factors that influence the con-
struction of images should have similar effects. Some evidence of this was
obtained in the vacation study we described earlier (Adaval & Wyer, 1998,
Experiment 2). That is, the effects of instructions to imagine the events
were similar to the effects of presenting pictures. This possibility was exam-
ined in additional conditions of the experiment described at the end of the
previous section. In these conditions, we took into account by both instruc-
tional demands to form mental images of the events and chronic individual
differences in the disposition to construct them spontaneously.
250 CHAPTER 9

To reiterate, participants made judgments of politicians on the basis of


verbal materials identical to those we employed in the earlier studies. In
this case, however, pictures of the politicians were either presented at the
outset, before participants read verbal descriptions of the politician’s life
events, or not at all. In addition, participants in imagination conditions were
explicitly told to “imagine what the person must have looked like and what
he must have done at each stage of his life. . . In other words, try to imagine
that you are watching a movie . . . and form a picture in your mind of the
events described.” In contrast, participants under no-imagination conditions
received instructions similar to those in the earlier experiment, without fur-
ther elaboration.
Finally, participants after making judgments of the politicians were ad-
ministered a questionnaire developed by Sheehan (1967) to assess individ-
ual differences in information-processing style several items of which as-
sessed the disposition to use visual images in responding to information
(e.g., “I like to picture future events or situations in my mind,” “When I think
of someone I know, I often picture in my mind what they look like,” “My
thinking often consists of mental pictures or images,” etc.). Participants
whose scores were above and below the mean response to these items
were classified as visualizers and nonvisualizers, respectively.
Participants’ impressions of each politician were analyzed as a function
of picture conditions, imagination instructions, presentation format, and
the disposition to form visual images. No effects of format were significant
(p > .10). However, the effects of pictures, imagination instructions, and
chronic dispositions to form images were highly interactive, F(1,47) = 5.11, p
< .03. These effects are summarized in Table 9.5. Visualizers evaluated a pol-
itician more favorably when they were told to imagine the events that oc-

TABLE 9.5
Evaluations of Politicians as a Function of Imagination Instructions,
the Presence of Pictures, and Disposition to Form Visual Images

Visualizers Nonvisualizers

Imagination No Imagination Imagination No Imagination


Instructions Instructions Instructions Instructions

Pictures
Narrative format 3.33 3.08 2.73 4.04
List format 3.50 2.83 3.07 3.87
Mean 3.42 2.96 2.90 3.96
No pictures
Narrative format 3.08 3.10 3.83 2.67
List format 3.71 2.67 3.54 2.46
Mean 3.40 2.88 3.68 2.56

Note. Adapted from Adaval et al. (2002, Experiment 4).


CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 251

curred in his life than when they were not, and this was true regardless of
the format in which the information was conveyed. Moreover, pictures had
no effect whatsoever on these participants’ evaluations. That is, visualizers
apparently formed clear images of the events even in the absence of pic-
tures, and so making the pictures available had little additional effect.
In contrast, pictures had a positive influence on nonvisualizers’ evalua-
tions when these participants were not explicitly told to imagine the politi-
cian’s life events. Furthermore, imagination instructions had a positive ef-
fect provided no pictures were presented. When nonvisualizers were asked
to imagine the politician’s life events and pictures were presented, how-
ever, the two sources of mental images appeared to interfere with one an-
other, thus eliminating the positive effect that each factor had in isolation.
As noted earlier, the verbal information we presented typically de-
scribed abstract events that were unlikely to elicit visual images spontane-
ously. Nevertheless, chronic visualizers found it easy to construct images
when they were asked to do so, and the presence of pictures neither helped
nor hindered them. Therefore, the images that these participants formed in-
creased the extremity of their judgments regardless of whether or not pic-
tures were presented. Nonvisualizers, who do not normally form visual im-
ages on the basis of verbal information, were also benefited by doing so
provided no pictures were presented. When pictures were presented, how-
ever, these individuals apparently found it difficult to integrate their impli-
cations into the images they formed, and this led them to form less clear im-
pressions of the politicians than they might otherwise have done.

Effects of Image-Based Representations


on the Processing of New Information

The preceding series of studies focused on how visual and verbal informa-
tion about a politician combined to affect his “image.” Once this image is
formed, however, it can have an impact on the way other information is proc-
essed and consequently on the implications drawn from this information. A
study by Wyer, Budesheim, Shavitt, Riggle, Melton, and Kuklinski (1991) is of
interest in this regard. Nonacademic employees were recruited for a study of
the way people make judgments of political candidates on the basis of infor-
mation of the sort they receive during an election campaign. On this pre-
tense, they received two types of information about a member of the U.S.
House of Representatives who had recently run for the Senate in a neighbor-
ing state. First, participants were shown a videotaped nonpolitical speech of
the candidate’s remarks at a bicentennial celebration at which he was asked
to present an award to a local dignitary. The speech, delivered by an accom-
plished character actor, was identical in content in all conditions but was de-
livered in either a forceful, articulate manner that conveyed a favorable im-
252 CHAPTER 9

age or in a bumbling manner, with inappropriate pauses, fidgeting, and other


mannerisms that conveyed an unfavorable image.
The second type of information was conveyed in an audiotaped portion
of a radio program that had ostensibly been sponsored by the League of
Women Voters. In this program, commentators reported the candidate’s
votes on ten bills that had recently come before the House. Votes on six of
these bills (e.g., a proposal to increase military spending by 15%, a proposal
to allow prayer in public schools) conveyed either a consistently conserva-
tive or consistently liberal ideology. (Votes on the remaining four bills had
no ideological significance.)
This information was conveyed in three conditions. In no-delay condi-
tions, participants listened to the radio program describing the candidate’s
issue stands immediately after they watched the videotape of his speech.
Then, after doing so, they reported their impression of the candidate along
a 100-point “feeling thermometer.” The procedure in two other conditions
was similar. In delayed-information conditions, however, a 24-hour delay was
introduced between the videotaped speech and exposure to the candi-
date’s issue positions, with judgments being made immediately after expo-
sure to the issue positions. In delayed-judgment conditions, participants lis-
tened to the candidate’s issue stands immediately after seeing the speech,
as they did under no-delay conditions. However, a 24-hour delay was in-
duced between this information and judgments.
In all conditions, participants after evaluating the candidate reported
their personal positions on each of the issues to which the candidate’s
votes pertained. Finally, they indicated their party affiliation and ideologi-
cal orientation. These latter data, in combination with the candidate’s issue
stands, were used to define two independent variables. First, participants’
reported ideology was coded as either similar or dissimilar to the candi-
date’s, as implied by the liberal or conservative orientation of his issue
stands. Second, participants were classified as either generally in agree-
ment or generally in disagreement with the candidate’s specific issue posi-
tions, based on the proportion of ideologically relevant issue stands with
which they agreed. (Each participant agreed with at least one liberal and
one conservative issue position, regardless of his or her general ideology.
Therefore, ideological similarity and agreement level were relatively inde-
pendent.)
Evaluations of the candidate are shown in Table 9.6 as a function of each
informational variable and delay conditions. These evaluations were obvi-
ously affected by the favorableness of the candidate’s image as conveyed in
the videotape. Moreover, this effect was greater when the image was salient
at the time of judgment (i.e., under no-delay conditions) than when it was not.
The effects of agreement and ideological similarity are of greater interest,
however. When the candidate’s image was not salient at the time information
CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 253

TABLE 9.6
Candidate Evaluations as a Function of Delay Conditions, Image,
Agreement With Candidate’s Issue Stands, and Ideological Similarity

No-Delay Delayed-Information Delayed-Judgment


Conditions Conditions Conditions

Candidate’s image
Favorable 51.0 53.8 47.7
Unfavorable 35.6 44.6 42.9
Participants’ agreement with issue stands
Agree 42.3 64.5 48.1
Disagree 33.2 30.9 40.1
Ideological similarity to candidate
Similar 49.6 48.1 57.3
Dissimilar 26.0 47.3 31.0

Note. Adapted from Wyer et al. (1991).

about his issue stands were presented (i.e., under delayed-information condi-
tions), participants based their evaluations of the candidate on their agree-
ment with his issue positions, and the candidate’s similarity to them in ideol-
ogy had virtually no effect. However, when participants learned of the
candidate’s issue stands immediately after they viewed his image-inducing
speech (i.e., under no-delay and delayed-judgment conditions), they based
their evaluations on the candidate’s general ideology, and their agreement
with him on specific issues had little influence. This was true under both no-
delay and delayed-judgment conditions. Thus, unlike the direct effects of the
candidate’s image on judgments, the indirect effects of image on the process-
ing of issue information were not a function of its salience at the time of judg-
ment. Rather, they depended on the salience of the candidate’s image at the
time the issue stand information was conveyed.
In short, the salience of the candidate’s image at the time his issue
stands were learned altered the way in which the implications of these is-
sue stands were construed. When a global image of the candidate was not
salient to them, participants assessed their agreement with his stands on
specific issues and based their judgments on this criterion independently of
the ideological implications of the candidate’s positions. When the candi-
date’s image was salient to participants at the time they heard about his is-
sue positions, however, they applied a global criterion in assessing the im-
plications of his issue positions as well. Consequently, their agreement with
the candidate on specific issues had relatively little effect.21

21
21 An alternative interpretation of these results might be that participants experienced over-
load when the candidate’s videotaped speech and his issue stands were conveyed in temporal
proximity and, therefore, they devoted less cognitive effort to an assessment of the candidate’s
254 CHAPTER 9

Summary and Conclusions

The research described in the preceding sections provides several insights


into the impact of narrative descriptions of a person or object and the influ-
ence of visual images on the processes that underlie this impact. At the
same time, it places constraints on the conditions in which these processes
operate. To summarize:

1. When people’s processing objectives require knowledge of the tempo-


ral sequence of events that occurred in a particular situation (e.g., the events
surrounding a crime), presenting information in a narrative facilitates the
construction of this sequence. Consequently, it increases recipients’ confi-
dence in the conclusions they draw from the information and, therefore, in-
creases the impact of this information on judgments.
2. When an evaluation does not require the construction of a temporal se-
quence of events, this sequence may only be constructed if the events are
described in a narrative that conveys their temporal relatedness. Otherwise,
recipients may employ other strategies for combining the implications of the
information that can often be equally effective (e.g., they may make a piece-
meal assessment and integration of the individual pieces of information).
3. Pictures increase the impact of verbally described events when the
events are conveyed in a narrative. This is true regardless of whether the
events are situationally and temporally constrained (i.e., if they stimulate
the construction of an episode model) or refer to more general experiences
that take place over a period of time. However, pictures interfere with the
piecemeal integration of the implications of events that are conveyed in a
list, and consequently decrease the impact of these events on judgments.
4. Pictures can increase the impact of verbal event descriptions when
they are conveyed at the outset as well as when they accompany these de-
scriptions. Furthermore, this increase can occur regardless of the format in
which the descriptions are presented.
5. The information-processing strategies that are stimulated by different
presentation formats may be activated and applied spontaneously, with lit-
tle conscious awareness. Therefore, their effects are independent of explicit
instructions or situational demands to employ alternative strategies. The in-
fluence of pictures on the use of these strategies also appears to occur with-
out awareness.

issue positions. If this were so, however, they would presumably have been inclined to use the
candidate’s image as a heuristic, leading it to have greater effect on judgments than it otherwise
would. In fact, however, the candidate’s image had no greater effect under delayed-judgment
conditions (when the two types of information were presented together) than under delayed-
information conditions. Therefore, this alternative interpretation does not seem viable.
CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 255

6. Instructions to imagine the events that are described verbally can influ-
ence the impact of these events in much the same way as pictures. However,
when pictures and imagination instructions are both provided, people who
are not normally disposed to form visual images may have difficulty integrat-
ing pictures into the images they form when they are explicitly asked to do
so. In this case, therefore, pictures can decrease the impact of the informa-
tion relative to conditions in which the pictures are not presented.
7. Narrative representations that are formed on the basis of observed
events can induce a holistic processing strategy that, once activated, influ-
ences the processing of verbal information that is conveyed subsequently. In
particular, it stimulates the use of more global criteria for judgments, and
correspondingly decreases the use of criteria that require more analytic,
piecemeal processing.

These conclusions may have more general implications. For example, in-
formation is likely to have greater impact on judgments and decisions if it
stimulates individuals to form a narrative-based account of an experience,
and to form mental images of the events that occurred, than if it does not.
This possibility, which was suggested by results of the study by Reyes et al.
(1980), was also recognized by Nisbett and Ross (1980). To borrow their ex-
ample, a person who is considering the purchase of a particular brand of
dishwasher may be less influenced by statistical evidence of its superior
maintenance and repair record than by a neighbor’s vivid description of her
unique experience with the machine, which broke down 2 weeks after she
purchased it, flooded her kitchen and dining room, and ruined a valuable
rug. As noted earlier, narrative-based information processing may not always
generate more extreme evaluations than other well-learned processing strat-
egies. Nevertheless, as this anecdotal example suggests, when narrative-
based representations are easy to construct and are likely to elicit visual im-
ages, they are generally more likely to have an impact than abstract informa-
tion whose implications are more difficult to assimilate and interpret.

GENERAL EFFECTS OF NARRATIVE-BASED


PROCESSING ON EXPLANATION AND
PREDICTION

As Pennington and Hastie’s research exemplifies, narratives are often con-


structed in the service of both prediction and explanation. Many examples
of this possibility can be drawn from research in traditional areas of psy-
chology, including (a) the impact of constructing explanatory narratives on
predictions of future events, (b) counterfactual reasoning, and (c) attribu-
tion phenomena. Much of this research was not conducted for the purpose
256 CHAPTER 9

of delineating the role of narratives in judgment. Nevertheless, a conceptu-


alization of the research from the perspective proposed in this chapter has
implications for the situational and informational factors that determine
which of several alternative narrative representations are likely to be con-
structed and used.

The Impact of Constructing Explanatory Narratives


on the Prediction of Future Events

People are likely to predict that an event is likely to occur if they can con-
struct a plausible narrative of the events that might lead up to it. This im-
plies that increasing the accessibility in memory of a plausible narrative ac-
count of the event should increase beliefs that the event will occur. Several
studies bear on this possibility. Ross, Lepper, Strack, and Steinmetz (1977)
asked some participants to read a clinical case study with instructions to
explain why the individual might have committed suicide after leaving ther-
apy. Others read the same passage with instructions to explain why the
protagonist might have donated a sizable sum of money to the Peace
Corps. Participants after generating their explanations were asked to pre-
dict the likelihood that the protagonist had engaged in a number of behav-
iors after leaving therapy, one of which was the event they had explained.
Participants were told that the case study had been taken from a textbook
and that neither the experimenters nor anyone else had any knowledge of
what had actually happened to the individual. Nevertheless, participants
typically predicted that the event they had explained was more likely to
have occurred than the events they had not explained. Participants who
were asked to explain an occurrence presumably constructed a plausible
narrative of the sequence of events that led up to it and then, having done
so, used this narrative as a basis for their later predictions.
Results of other studies are consistent with this interpretation. Sherman,
Skov, Hervitz, and Stock (1981), for example, arbitrarily asked participants
to explain why they might either succeed or fail on an anagrams task and
then, after generating their explanation, asked them to predict their actual
performance on the task. Participants predicted the occurrence of the out-
come they had arbitrarily been asked to explain. Moreover, their actual
task performance confirmed their prophecy. (That is, participants who had
been asked to explain why they might succeed, and predicted success, per-
formed better than those who had been asked to explain why they might
fail.) Participants apparently used the implications of their narrative-based
prediction as a standard at the time they actually performed the task, moti-
vating them to attain the performance level it implied.
Narrative-based explanations are likely to be generated spontaneously
when individuals receive information that is inconsistent with expectations.
CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 257

In a study by Ross, Lepper, and Hubbard (1975), participants were asked to


distinguish between true and false suicide notes. They were given bogus
feedback on each trial concerning whether they were correct or incorrect.
Some participants were led to believe they had been correct on 12 of 15 tri-
als, whereas others were told they had been correct only three times. Later,
however, participants were debriefed, being told that the feedback they re-
ceived bore no resemblance to their actual performance. The debriefing
was quite compelling, with participants being shown the preprepared
schedule the experimenter had used to deliver the trial-by-trial feedback. It
was therefore impossible for participants to believe that the feedback they
had received was contingent on their actual performance. Nevertheless,
participants were more likely to predict they would do well on a similar
task in the future if they had been led to believe that they had performed
well on the first task than if they had been led to believe they had done
poorly.
Direct evidence of the cognitive processes that produced these effects
was not obtained in this study. It nevertheless seems reasonable to sup-
pose that participants who received feedback that deviated from their ex-
pectations spontaneously attempted to explain it and, in doing so, selec-
tively retrieved a body of self-knowledge about their past experiences that
provided a plausible narrative-based causal account of it. Later, they used
this representation as a basis for their predictions without considering the
validity of the feedback that stimulated its construction.

The Influence of the Ease of Constructing


a Narrative on Its Impact

The use of a narrative as a basis for judgment may depend on not only its
accessibility in memory but also the ease with which it can be applied. Ex-
amples of this contingency are suggested by research on the impact of
counterfactual reasoning. People who have a negative experience are par-
ticularly likely to ponder the reasons for its occurrence. In doing so, they
may construct a scenario of how the event might have been avoided. If the
story they construct permits them to conclude that the event occurred for
circumstances beyond their control, they may be inclined to dismiss the
event without further ado. However, if they can easily construct a scenario
whereby they could have avoided the unpleasant experience, they may ru-
minate about their failure to have done so, and may experience upset and
regret.
A well-known experiment by Kahneman and Tversky (1982) provided an
example. Suppose Al and Bob are scheduled for different flights that leave
at the same time. They travel from town in the same taxi, are caught in a
traffic jam and arrive 30 minutes after the scheduled departure. Upon
258 CHAPTER 9

reaching the terminal, Al learns that his fight left on time. However, Bob
finds that his flight was delayed by 25 minutes and left only 5 minutes be-
fore he got there. Who is more upset? Ninety-six percent of the participants
who are asked this question agree that Bob would be more upset than Al.
Presumably, the reason is that Bob can easily construct a scenario whereby
he could have saved 5 minutes and caught the plane, whereas Al is less eas-
ily able to do so.
For similar reasons, people are more likely to be bothered by a mishap if it
results from an atypical behavior than if it results from a typical one. For ex-
ample, people imagine being more upset by having a traffic accident while
driving home on a route they take infrequently than by having an accident
while driving home on their normal route. Moreover, people may be more
upset by getting robbed by a hitchhiker if they only rarely pick up hitchhik-
ers than if they regularly do so (Kahneman & Tversky, 1982). In each case,
the difference results from the fact that it is easier to imagine how the event
could have been avoided in the first instance than it is in the second.
The ease of constructing a narrative can also come into play in other
judgments and decision phenomena. Research by Miller (1977) provided an
example. That is, it is easier to imagine how one’s donation of money would
help a particular family whose home has been destroyed by fire than to
imagine how it would help to alleviate the suffering of thousands of people
whose homes have been destroyed in Bosnia. Therefore, people are more
likely to contribute money in the first case than the latter. Miller’s (1977) re-
search provided evidence that this is the case. Evidence that this contin-
gency is recognized outside the laboratory is suggested by the appeals of
charitable organizations to “adopt” a child, a whale, or even a highway.
This strategy presumably stimulates the construction of a narrative in
which one’s own behavior helps an individual person, animal, or highway
maintenance project. Because this narrative is easy to construct, it may in-
crease the willingness to provide assistance.
When two or more alternative narratives are equally easy to construct,
the one that is generated may depend on a number of factors that affect the
relative accessibility of the knowledge that enters into their construction.
Several of these factors, which could be informational, situational, or moti-
vational, are discussed in the sections that follow.

Informational Determinants of Narrative Construction

1. Framing Effects

The narrative that is constructed from information for use in making an


inference can depend to a large extent on features of the information itself
that make different sets of concepts accessible in memory. Examples of this
CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 259

contingency abound. To give a well-known example from research on deci-


sion making, consider the following two choice situations:

1. One thousand people are in danger of being infected by a deadly virus.


You have the choice of administering two serums. One serum, A, is ef-
fective but in short supply. If you administer A, 350 persons will be
saved. If you choose B, there is a probability of .65 that everyone will be
saved but a probability of .35 that no one will be saved.
2. One thousand people are in danger of being infected . . . If you adminis-
ter A, 650 persons will die. If you choose B, there is a probability of .35
that everyone will die but a probability of .65 that no one will die.

The choice alternatives are actually identical in each case. In the first
case, however, the description of the alternatives activates concepts associ-
ated with saving lives, and so people are likely to construct scenarios in
terms of these concepts. As a result, they are more likely to prefer A, which
guarantees that lives will be saved, than B. In the second case, on the other
hand, the descriptions emphasize the loss of life and activate concepts as-
sociated with the avoidance of this negative outcome. In this case, there-
fore, people typically prefer B, which describes a situation in which no one
will die, than A.
The implications of the narratives that people use to make inferences on
the basis of verbal information can also depend on the perspective from
which the narrative is formed. (For evidence of perspective differences in
the mental representations of verbal information, see Black, Turner, &
Bower, 1979, described in chap. 4.) A study by Read (1985) provides an ex-
ample. Consider the following vignette:

Helen was driving to work along a three-lane road, where the middle lane is
used for passing by traffic from both directions. She changed lanes to pass a
slow-moving truck, and quickly realized that she was headed directly for an-
other car coming in the opposite direction. For a moment, it looked as if a col-
lision was inevitable. However, this did not occur. Please indicate in one sen-
tence how you think the accident was avoided.

The situation is objectively similar for both cars. However, the story as writ-
ten focuses the reader’s attention on Helen, leading a narrative to be con-
structed in which she is the central figure. Therefore, people who are called
upon to explain how the accident was avoided typically attribute the re-
sponsibility of avoiding the accident to Helen rather than the other driver.
If the story had been written from a different perspective, this tendency
would presumably have been less likely.
260 CHAPTER 9

2. Effects of Conversational Norms


on Narrative Construction
A quite different informational influence arises from considerations elabo-
rated in chapter 7. That is, the representation that participants construct of a
social interaction is likely to be guided in part by normative expectations
concerning the type of information they expect to be exchanged (Grice, 1975;
Higgins, 1981; Sperber & Wilson, 1986). These expectations can influence the
concepts and knowledge that listeners use to interpret not only the state-
ments a person asks during a conversation but also the responses to these
statements. This interpretation can often require the construction of a narra-
tive. Kahneman and Miller (1986) recognized this possibility in the context of
norm theory. For example, consider the following example:

Q. Why did Joan pass the history examination?


A. She went to bed early the night before.

People who overhear this conversation are likely to assume that the
questioner is seeking new information. That is, they may infer that Joan’s
passing the exam is somewhat unexpected and, therefore, requires an ex-
planation. They may further assume that the explanation is informative;
that is, it describes behaviors or situational factors that do not normally ex-
ist. In interpreting the answer, therefore, they may construct a narrative of
Joan as someone who typically stays out late before exams and is usually
too tired to perform adequately, but who in the present instance went to
bed at a reasonable hour and was sufficiently rested the next morning to do
well. In contrast, consider the conversation:

Q. Why did Joan pass the history examination?


A. She stayed up late the night before.

This conversation might stimulate the construction of a scenario of Joan as


someone who normally doesn’t study much but, in this particular instance,
decided to burn the midnight oil and consequently performed well. These
narrative-based explanations, which are generated in an attempt to com-
prehend the situation, are likely to influence judgments of the protagonist
as well as predictions of her behavior in other situations.

Situational Determinants of Narrative Construction

1. Effects of Perspective on Attributions


of Responsibility
The differences in narrative construction suggested by the preceding ex-
amples result from the way in which events are described verbally. How-
ever, situational variables may have analogous differences when narrative
CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 261

representations are formed on the basis of direct observation. Early studies


of social attribution phenomena (Regan & Totten, 1975; Storms, 1973) pro-
vide examples. In Storms’ (1973) study, some participants watched a video-
tape of a get-acquainted conversation between themselves (the target) and
another person. The tape was also watched by persons who were not them-
selves involved in the conversation. The videotape was made from a van-
tage point that focused attention on either the target or the other. Partici-
pants after viewing the tape were asked whether the target’s behavior was
attributable to characteristics of the target (personality, mood, etc.) or the
situation (e.g., the other participant). Participants were more likely to at-
tribute the target’s behavior to dispositional factors when the target was vi-
sually prominent in the tape than when (s)he was not. This was true regard-
less of whether the participants were themselves in the role of the target.
Analogous conclusions can be drawn from a study by Regan and Totten
(1975). In this case, participants observed a videotape of a conversation in-
volving two other persons with instructions either to observe the target
person or to empathize with this person. Thus, the same information was
available to all participants. Nonetheless, participants who were told to ob-
serve the target presumably constructed a representation of the interaction
in which the target was the focus of attention. In contrast, observers who
were told to empathize with the target were likely to imagine interaction
from the target’s perspective and, therefore, to construct a narrative that
was focused on the conversation partner. The content of these narratives
then provided the basis for their attributions. Thus, the former participants
attributed the target’s behavior to dispositional characteristics, whereas
the latter participants attributed his behavior to situational factors.
Motivational factors can also influence the perspective from which a nar-
rative is constructed. In a study by Wolfson and Salancik (1977), observers
watched an actor perform an achievement task. Some observers expected
to engage in the task themselves at a later time, whereas others did not.
The first group of participants presumably formed a representation of the
situation that focused on the task, whereas the second group formed a rep-
resentation that focused on the actor. Consistent with this possibility, the
first group of participants was more inclined than the second group to at-
tribute the actor’s behavior to the task, and were less inclined than the sec-
ond group to attribute it to the actor himself.

2. Contextual Influences on Narrative-Based


Explanations

The type and implications of narratives that individuals use as a basis


for explanation and prediction can be influenced in part by situational fac-
tors that activate different sets of concepts and knowledge for use in con-
262 CHAPTER 9

structing these narratives. Norenzayan and Schwarz (1999) provided pro-


vocative evidence of these differences in an analysis of the expectations
that participants generate in psychology experiments. Participants read a
New York Times article about either (a) a disgruntled postal employee who
went on a mass murder rampage or (b) a man who was accused of murder
for bombing a federal office building. The letterhead of the questionnaire
being administered suggested that the study was being conducted by either
the “Institute of Personality Research” or the “Institute of Social Research.”
In each case, participants after reading the story listed five reasons why the
protagonist might have committed the crime.
It seems reasonable to suppose that people who believed that the study
was sponsored by a personality research institute would activate concepts
associated with characteristics of the actor and, therefore, would construct
a narrative account of the individual in terms of these characteristics. In
contrast, persons who were told that the study was being conducted by a
social research institute are more likely to activate concepts about social
(i.e., situational) factors and to construct a narrative in terms of these
features. These narratives should then influence the explanations that par-
ticipants generate. This was in fact the case. Participants gave more dis-
positional explanations when they believed that the study was conducted
by a personality research institute (M = 4.4) than when they believed it was
conducted by a social research institute (M = 2.6), and gave fewer situa-
tional explanations in the former case than the latter (5.8 vs. 9.4).
It is important to mention these differences occurred not only when the
nature of the research institute was identified before participants read the
story but also when it was identified afterwards. As the authors point out,
this could indicate that the differences in attributions reflected a tendency
for participants to tailor their responses to the apparent interests of the in-
dividuals to whom they were communicating, and might not reflect a differ-
ence in the underlying representation they formed of the interaction. This
possibility cannot be discounted. However, it seems equally likely that par-
ticipants mentally reviewed and reconstructed the crime after they had
read the story, and that they based their explanations on this reconstruc-
tion rather than the representation they had formed earlier.
Be that as it may, these considerations have implications for the inter-
pretation of numerous psychology experiments in which experimenters im-
plicitly or explicitly induce expectations for the criteria that should be
applied in providing information and, therefore, the narrative-based repre-
sentations they are likely to construct for use as a basis for their responses.
As Schwarz, Strack, Hilton, and Naderer (1991) argued, studies that are os-
tensibly conducted by psychologists can dispose participants to construct
explanations in terms of personality characteristics of the protagonists
rather than employing other criteria that are less relevant to psychology. If
CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 263

the studies were conducted in a different situational context, this might not
be the case. To demonstrate this, Schwarz et al. introduced some partici-
pants to a judgment task with instructions similar to those employed in an
earlier experiment by Kahneman and Tversky (1973):

A panel of psychologists have interviewed and administered personality tests


to 30 engineers and 70 lawyers . . . On the basis of these interviews, thumbnail
descriptions of the [100 individuals] have been written. In your form, you will
find 5 descriptions, chosen at random. . . . For each description, please indi-
cate the probability that the person described is an engineer. . . . the same
task has been performed by a panel of experts who were highly accurate in
assigning probabilities . . .

A second condition was similar except that the first line of the instruc-
tions referred to “researchers” rather than to “psychologists,” and the last
line referred to “statisticians” rather than “experts.” Following these in-
structions, participants read a sketch of the following type;

Hans K. is 45 years old. He is married and has four children. He is generally


conservative, careful and ambitious. He shows no interest in social and politi-
cal issues. He spends most of his time on his many hobbies, which include . . .
solving mathematical puzzles.

The authors speculated that participants who believed that the story was
associated with psychologists would construct an account of the individual
in terms of personality and life style characteristics and would use this ac-
count as a basis for predicting his vocation. In contrast, associating the task
with statistics was expected to lead participants to use a statistical criterion
(e.g., base rates) as a basis for prediction. This was in fact the case. That is,
.76 of the participants predicted that the individual was an engineer when the
study referred to psychologists, whereas only .55 of the participants made
this prediction when the instructions referred to statisticians.
These data obviously do not provide evidence that a narrative represen-
tation of the target person was constructed in one case but not the other.
The results nevertheless provide a general indication that contextual fac-
tors can play an important role in the criteria that underlie judgments and,
to this extent, the likelihood that narrative-based explanations are used.

Motivational Influences on Explanation-Based


Narrative Constructions

The scenarios that people construct in the course of explaining events may
not be entirely dispassionate. This is particularly true when the events are
ones in which people are personally involved in the events and the explana-
264 CHAPTER 9

tions they give could reflect positively or negatively on themselves. Individ-


uals in Western cultures typically make defensive attributions. That is, they
take responsibility for their own success but attribute their failures to other
factors that have relatively few negative implications for their self-esteem
(Harvey & Weary, 1984; Zuckerman, 1975). These factors may determine the
narratives that people construct.
The self-serving motives that underlie the construction of scenarios
about oneself may be attributed to others as well. To give yet another ex-
ample from Tversky and Kahneman (1982):

Tom and Jim were both eliminated from a tennis tournament. Both were elimi-
nated on a tiebreaker. Tom lost when his opponent served an ace. Jim lost on
his own unforced error. Who will spend more time thinking about the match
that night?

Tom can presumably explain his loss in terms of consequences beyond


his control. Jim, on the other hand, may continue to rehearse his error and
to generate alternative ways in which it could have been avoided. There-
fore, as Tversky and Kahneman’s findings imply, participants expect Jim to
be more likely to think about the match than Tom.
The assumption that people are more motivated to generate scenarios
that reflect positively on themselves, and avoid constructing narratives
that reflect negatively, is indirectly confirmed by Arkin, Gleason, and
Johnston (1976). Participants in this study were induced to administer ther-
apy to another person to eliminate a mild phobic reaction. The therapy was
actually the same in all conditions. However, some participants were led to
believe that the treatment they would use was the only one available
whereas others were ostensibly given several alternatives from which they
could choose. In all cases, participants were told that the treatment they
would use had been typically used successfully or unsuccessfully by oth-
ers. However, participants after administering the treatment themselves
were told they had either succeeded or failed. After receiving this feedback,
they estimated the extent to which they were personally responsible for the
outcome.
In principle, participants should believe they are more responsible for
the outcome if they personally chose the therapy they use than if they are
required to use it, and more responsible if their outcome differs from oth-
ers’ (e.g., if they succeed when others fail, or fail when others succeed) than
when it does not. As shown in Table 9.7, however, this was only true when
participants were told they had failed. Participants took responsibility for
success regardless of whether they had freedom of choice over the therapy
they used and regardless of the outcomes that others had attained.
CONSTRUCTION AND USE OF NARRATIVES 265

TABLE 9.7
Mean Attributions of Responsibility for Success and Failure
in Administering Therapy as a Function of Freedom
of Choice and Others’ Outcomes

Personally Succeeded Personally Failed

Others Succeeded Others Failed Others Succeeded Others Failed

Choice over therapy


To be administered 6.63 6.13 7.13 4.25
No choice 6.38 6.75 4.13 4.63

Note. High scores indicate greater attributions of responsibility to oneself. Adapted from
Arkin, Gleason, and Johnston (1976).

This study obviously does not provide direct evidence that participants’
attributions were mediated by a narrative representation that they con-
structed of the situation. It is nevertheless plausible to assume that partici-
pants who did well spontaneously activated a scenario of themselves as
competent individuals who typically succeed in achievement activity and
considered this scenario to be a sufficient explanation for the outcome.
Therefore, because the scenario reflected positively on themselves, they
used it as a basis for judgments without searching for alternative explana-
tions. In contrast, participants were reluctant to construct a scenario that
suggested they were responsible for failure if a plausible alternative could
be generated. Therefore, they only accepted responsibility for their failure
when they had personally chosen the therapy and had failed when others
had done well.
Arkin et al.’s study provides only one example of a more pervasive ten-
dency for individuals to construct representations of themselves and oth-
ers that confirm a perception of themselves as admirable individuals and of
the world as a place in which they can be happy and successful. This ten-
dency, which has been documented in detail by Kunda (1990), is discussed
more fully in the next chapter.

CONCLUDING REMARKS

The studies reviewed in this chapter confirm the assumption that people of-
ten attempt to construct a narrative representation of events on the basis
of information they receive about them, and that their judgments are based
on implications of this representation. The events may be ones they imag-
ine themselves or another person experiencing, events they either read
about, or ones they directly observe. It would obviously be wrong to as-
sume that all social inferences are based on these representations. At the
266 CHAPTER 9

same time, the influence of narrative constructions of social experiences on


judgments is incontrovertible.
However, narrative accounts of a new experience, and the inferences
that are made on the basis of these narratives, do not occur in a cognitive
vacuum. These accounts are constructed, and implications are drawn
from them, on the basis of previously formed representations that specify
the temporal and causal relations among events of the sort under consid-
eration. The use of these representations, which may often constitute im-
plicit theories about the world in which one lives, is discussed in the next
chapter.
C H A P T E R

10
The Impact of Implicational Molecules
and Implicit Theories on Inferences
About Oneself and Others

The construction of narrative representations from new information obvi-


ously requires prior knowledge about the type of persons, objects, and
events to which the information refers. This knowledge, which often has im-
plications for features that are not specified in the information presented,
can sometimes include episode models of specific past experiences that have
features in common with the new one. However, it can also consist of gener-
alized narrative representations that are composed of object and event con-
cepts that the new information exemplifies. As noted in chapter 1, these lat-
ter representations often function as implicit theories that individuals apply in
comprehending new experiences and construing their implications.
This chapter reviews theory and research in a number of areas in which
implicit theories are likely to play a role, including reconstructions of the
past, the use of judgmental heuristics, perceptions of social support, the
correlates of marital satisfaction, and the effects of stereotypes on overt be-
havior. Before embarking on a discussion of specific inference phenomena,
however, it may be useful to provide a simplified conceptualization of the
processes we assume to underlie the use of previous acquired knowledge
representations in making inferences.

GENERAL CONSIDERATIONS

The generalized narrative representations that function as implicit theories


may be abstractions of a number of specific instances of the sequence of
events they characterize (although, as we indicated in chap. 6, these repre-

267
268 CHAPTER 10

sentations may be formed less often than one might intuitively expect). Oth-
ers may be formed in the course of goal-directed cognitive activity that
leads the events that compose them to be associated. Many theory-related
narrative representations may be similar to “story skeletons” of the sort
proposed by Schank and Abelson (1995). Other, simpler theories may be
conceptualized as implicational molecules of the sort described earlier in
this volume. These molecules theoretically consist of two or more verbally
coded segments that combine to describe a temporally and causally related
sequence of events or states of affairs. Although the nature of implicational
molecules has been discussed in earlier chapters, their centrality to the is-
sues of concern in the present chapter arranges a brief recapitulation of
their structure and use in making judgments and decisions.
In combination, the segments of a molecule often exemplify a generaliza-
tion about the world in which we live. To reiterate an earlier example, the
generalization that smoking causes lung cancer might be represented in the
two-segment molecule:

[P smokes; P has (will get) lung cancer].

Similarly, the generalization that people get what they deserve might be
conveyed in a “just-deserts” molecule; i.e.:

[P does a bad thing; P encounters misfortune]

or, alternatively,

[P does a good thing; P has good fortune].

The use of such molecules to make inferences is theoretically governed


by a completion principle. This principle, which is consistent with our previ-
ous discussion of narrative-based comprehension processes, can be con-
veyed as a postulate:

Postulate 10.1. If the information available about a specific situation instan-


tiates all but one of the propositions that compose a molecule, an instantia-
tion of the remaining proposition will be spontaneously inferred.

The completion principle theoretically holds regardless of which propo-


sitions are instantiated by the information available and which must be in-
ferred. Thus, in the previous example, people who learn that a person has
committed a nefarious act might use a just-deserts molecule to infer that
the person will be punished or will otherwise experience misfortune. How-
ever, they might also use this molecule to infer that a person who has expe-
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 269

rienced misfortune has done a bad thing or is reprehensible for other rea-
sons. This possibility is consistent with the just world hypothesis (Lerner et
al., 1976; Lerner & Simmons, 1966). In support of this hypothesis, Walster
(1966) found that people evaluate the innocent victim of an automobile acci-
dent more unfavorably if the individual was seriously injured than if he or
she was only slightly harmed. Research with similar implications was re-
ported by Lerner and Simmons (1966) and also by Wyer, Bodenhausen, and
Gorman (1985) in a study described in chapter 3.
A study by Spiro (1977) also suggested an application of the completion
principle. Protagonists read a story about an engaged couple with instruc-
tions that the experiment concerned “reactions to situations involving in-
terpersonal relations.” In some versions of the story, the man informed the
woman that he didn’t want children, whereupon the woman expressed con-
siderable upset and a bitter argument ensued. After reading the story, par-
ticipants engaged in routine activities unrelated to the experimental task.
During this period, the experimenter, who ostensibly knew the couple inci-
dentally noted that they eventually married and were still happily together.
Participants who are motivated to comprehend the couple’s relationship
are likely to construct a scenario of how this unexpected outcome might
have occurred. In doing so, they might invoke a previously formed “kiss-
and-make-up” molecule of the form:

[People love one another; people fight; people resolve conflict; people make
up].

To this extent, they may infer an instantiation of the proposition “people re-
solve conflict,” which is not implied by the information available. For exam-
ple, they might speculate that one of the partners had a change of heart,
that the woman found she couldn’t have children, or that some other un-
foreseen event occurred that stimulated the couple to resolve their conflict.
The inferred event might then be added to the mental representation that
participants construct of the couple’s relationship and store in memory.
Participants after completing the activities they were asked to perform
were dismissed. However, they returned for a second experimental session
a few days or several weeks later, at which time they were asked to recall
the story they had read. They were explicitly told to report only things that
were mentioned in the story and not to include any personal reactions or
inferences they might have made. Nonetheless, participants made frequent
errors, the number of which increased over time. These errors were typi-
cally of the sort one might expect as a result of attempts to reconcile the ex-
perimenter’s “incidental” comment with the original information. For exam-
ple, one person recalled that “the problem was resolved when they found
that [the woman] could not have children anyway.” Another reported that
270 CHAPTER 10

although one person thought the matter was important, the other did not
(see Spiro, 1977, for additional examples).
The completion principle has potentially broad applicability. However,
additional considerations arise in applying it to the inference phenomena of
concern in this chapter. For one thing, more than one implicit theory can
potentially be brought to bear on a particular observation. Or, in terms of
our present discussion, a proposition may be contained in more than one
molecule. This is particularly likely when an event has more than one possi-
ble cause. For example, people’s theories about poor academic perform-
ance might be reflected in the molecules:

[P doesn’t study; P gets poor grades]

and

[P is stupid; P gets poor grades].

In such instances, the information that a particular person received a poor


grade could activate either of these molecules. Assuming that each mole-
cule is equally applicable, the molecule that comes to mind first is most
likely to be applied.
A second consideration is that the inferences made on the basis of an im-
plicit theory may often be probabilistic. In some cases, the information
available may not be sufficient to determine a theory’s applicability. (In the
case of an implicational molecule, for example, more than one segment
might be uninstantiated.) In other cases, the information to which a theory
is applied might not necessarily be valid. People who hear that an acquain-
tance did not study for an exam could use the molecule described earlier to
predict that the person will get a bad grade. At the same time, they are un-
doubtedly aware that a failure to study does not always lead to bad grades.
Moreover, they might not be completely convinced that the information
they have received about the individual’s study behavior is valid. There-
fore, although they might use an implicational molecule to generate a pre-
diction, they may not be completely certain their prediction is correct.
When an implicational molecule consists of only two propositions, a for-
mal model of probabilistic inference proposed by Wyer and Hartwick (1980;
see also Wyer, 1974; Wyer & Goldberg, 1970) takes this possibility into ac-
count. The conceptualization, which is essentially an extension of
McGuire’s (1960) probabilogical model, provides a quantitative description
of the relations among beliefs in causally related propositions. Suppose an
implicational molecule has been formed as a result of associating two prop-
ositions, A (e.g., “war is good for the economy”) and B (“America is likely to
go to war within the next 5 years”). If this molecule is accessible in memory
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 271

at the time an individual is asked to predict the likelihood of B, the individ-


ual is likely to identify and use A as a basis for this inference. Suppose, how-
ever, that the individual is uncertain that A is true. Then, the person is
likely to consider not only the likelihood that B would occur not only if A is
true but also if A is not true. Thus, in our example, people who are asked the
likelihood that American will go to war might base their belief on not only
the likelihood that this will occur if war is good for the economy, but might
also take into account the possibility that America would go to war even if
war were not good for the economy. The relative weight attached to these
two conditional beliefs may be a function of the relative likelihood that A is
or is not true (i.e., that war is or is not good for the economy, respectively).
The quantification of this process proposed by Wyer (1974; Wyer &
Goldberg, 1970) assumes that if beliefs are defined in units of probability,
then the belief in the event described by one proposition, B, is related to be-
liefs in a possible cause of this event, A, according to the equation:

P(B) = P(A)*P(B/A) + P(~A)*P(B/~A), [10.1]

where P(B) is the belief that A is true, P(A) and P(~A) [= 1 - P(A)] are beliefs
that A is and is not true, respectively, and P(B/A) and P(B/~A) are beliefs
that B is true if A is and is not true, respectively.
This equation provides a remarkably accurate quantitative description
of the relations among these beliefs and, therefore, the influence of beliefs
in one proposition on beliefs in a second (for summaries of this evidence,
see Wyer & Carlston, 1979; Wyer & Hartwick, 1980). In one study, for exam-
ple (Wyer, 1970), participants read scenarios composed of two parts. The
first part led participants to believe that a particular event (A) was unlikely
to occur and, in addition, implicitly conveyed the likelihood that a second
event, B, would occur if A did and did not occur. The second part of the
story provided additional information that increased beliefs that A would
occur without changing its implications for B. In neither part of the story,
however, was the target event itself explicitly mentioned. One story, for ex-
ample, concerned the likelihood that a student riot will occur at a particular
university (A), and the likelihood that the university president would be
fired (B). The first part of the story described the president as coercive, es-
tablishing a low initial belief that a riot would occur. However, the second
part provided information that substantially increased the belief that a riot
would occur without affecting perceptions of whether the president would
remain in office.
After reading each part of the story, participants reported their belief
that B would occur, followed by their belief in A and the two conditional be-
liefs defined in Equation 10.1. These estimates, along a scale from 0 (not at
all likely) to 10 (extremely likely), were divided by 10 to convert them to
272 CHAPTER 10

units of probability. The predicted belief in B, P(B), was then computed for
each participant separately by combining his or her beliefs in the manner
described by the right side of Equation 10.1. Mean obtained values of P(B)
are plotted as a function of mean predicted values in Fig. 10.1. Changes in
beliefs in B after reading the second part of the story are also shown in this
figure. In each case, the standard error of the difference between mean pre-
dicted and mean obtained values was less than .05 (half a scale unit). This
accuracy was obtained without the use of any ad hoc curve-fitting parame-
ters.
Further evidence bearing on the validity of Equation 10.1 as a description
of the relations among beliefs in causally related propositions is provided
by research on the “Socratic effect” (McGuire, 1960; Rosen & Wyer, 1972).
That is, people’s a priori beliefs in a set of propositions may not conform to
the relations specified in Equation 10.1 because the propositions have not
recently been thought about in relation to one another. However, if peo-
ple’s beliefs in the propositions are called to their attention in close tempo-
ral contiguity, they may recognize their inconsistency and, consequently,
may modify one or more of the beliefs to eliminate this inconsistency. This
should be indicated by an increase in the quantitative accuracy of Equation
10.1. Rosen and Wyer (1972) found evidence that this is the case. That is,
participants reported their beliefs in causally related propositions in two
experimental sessions 1 week apart. The accuracy of Equation 10.1 in de-
scribing the relations among these beliefs was significantly greater in the
second session than it was at first, suggesting that the consistency of the
beliefs increased over time.
A later study (Henninger & Wyer, 1976) is potentially more relevant to
the concerns of this chapter. Participants in some conditions were asked to
report their belief in a proposition occupying the position of A in Equation
10.1 (i.e., an antecedent) before reporting their belief in B (the consequent).
These participants appeared to use A as a basis for their belief in B when
they encountered it later in the questionnaire (as inferred from the accu-
racy of Equation 10.1 in describing their relationship). Other participants,
however, reported their belief in B at the outset, when A was not salient to
them. These participants typically used a different criterion for evaluating
the validity of B, and so their belief in this proposition was inconsistent
with the belief in A that they reported later.
Henninger and Wyer’s findings suggest that Equation 10.1 might be used
to determine empirically the criteria that people bring to bear on their be-
liefs in a proposition they are asked to evaluate. Suppose two or more
implicational molecules could potentially provide the basis for an infer-
ence. A comparison of the quantitative accuracy of Equation 10.1 in describ-
ing the relations among the beliefs in the propositions composing each mol-
ecule could provide an indication of which molecule was actually activated
FIG. 10.1. Beliefs in a Proposition B, and changes in these beliefs, as a function of predicted val-
ues based on Equation 10.1. Based on data reported by Wyer (1970).

273
274 CHAPTER 10

and used. The utility of the equation is obviously restricted to theories that
concern only two causally related events or states. Many implicit theories
are more complex. However, if these theories can be broken down into sub-
sets of causally related propositions, the conceptualization could be useful
in evaluating the assumptions underlying the application of these theories
as well.

EFFECTS OF IMPLICIT THEORIES


ON RECONSTRUCTIVE MEMORY

Implicit theories may sometimes be more accessible in memory than the


actual events that led them to be formed. To this extent, they may often be
retrieved and used as a basis for reconstructing the events that occurred in
a particular instance without consulting the original memory trace of the
events at all. That is, suppose people are asked to recall a specific event to
which an implicit theory is relevant. They may find it easier to employ the
theory to reconstruct the event than to retrieve the event itself, which may
be relatively less accessible in memory. (This speculation is consistent with
the effect of generalized representations of an observed experience on
memory for the experience; see Adaval & Wyer, 2003, discussed in chap. 6.)

Reconstructing the Past

Several intriguing demonstrations of the role of implicit theories in memory


have been reported by Michael Ross (1989) in the context of discussing the
impact of these theories on the recall of personal experiences. Two studies
are particularly provocative. In one study, female participants who had pre-
viously reported their typical emotional reactions during the period of their
menstrual cycle were asked to keep a daily diary of their moods over the
course of a month. At the end of the month, they were asked to recall the
moods they had experienced during this period. Participants’ recall was
better predicted by their implicit theories about their emotional reactions
during the time of their menstrual cycle than by the actual feelings they had
reported experiencing at this time.
Students in a second study (Conway & Ross, 1984) participated in a pro-
gram that they believed would increase their study skills. After participat-
ing, they were asked to recall their preprogram estimates of their skills.
Their recall was governed primarily by their implicit theories that the pro-
gram would be effective. Thus, participants whose skills after participating
did not actually change over the course of the program recalled their pre-
program skills as lower than they actually were, consistent with their the-
ory that they had improved.
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 275

In a study by Goethals and Reckman (1973), students participated in a


group discussion of bussing. The discussion was dominated by a confeder-
ate whose opinion contrasted with the attitudes that participants had re-
ported in an earlier session. The confederate’s view had a substantial influ-
ence on not only participants’ postdiscussion attitudes but also their recall
of the attitudes they had reported earlier. Thus, participants apparently
employed an implicit theory that their attitudes were stable over time, and
therefore used their postdiscussion attitudes to infer what their attitude
must have been before the discussion took place. This interpretation was
confirmed by Ross (1989). Specifically, participants after reporting their atti-
tudes toward the position advocated in a persuasive message were asked
to list the thoughts they had had while recalling the attitude they had re-
ported 1 month earlier. Responses of more than 50% of the participants sug-
gested the use of an implicit “temporal consistency” theory (e.g., “I an-
swered the question now and assumed that my opinion probably hadn’t
changed in a month or so.”).

Self-Perception Theory

Ross (1989) was among the first to elaborate the role of implicit theories in
reconstructive memory and judgment. However, Bem’s (1972) well-known
theory of self-perception is based on very similar assumptions. Bem argued
that people who are asked to report their attributes, or alternatively, their
attitude toward a social issue, do not perform an exhaustive review of the
large amount of self-knowledge they have stored in memory that bears on
this characteristic. Rather, they retrieve the most recent judgment-relevant
information that comes to mind and base their judgments on the implica-
tions of this information alone. In many instances, the most accessible judg-
ment-relevant information is a recent behavior they have performed. Under
these circumstances, people construe the implications of this behavior for
the judgment they are asked to make, and resort to additional information
only if they consider its implications to be unclear or unreliable.
Bem further assumes that people use the same principles to infer their
own attributes that they use to infer others’. Or, in terms of the conceptual-
ization we are proposing, both inferences about oneself and inferences
about others may be based on the same implicit theory about the reasons
people engage in attribute-relevant activity. For example, suppose one per-
son agrees to write an essay in favor of capital punishment even though he
is given the opportunity to write about something else. In contrast, a sec-
ond person is told to write the essay without being given the chance to re-
fuse. An observer of the events is likely to activate an implicit theory that
people voluntarily advocate positions with which they agree, as reflected in
the molecule:
276 CHAPTER 10

[P believes X; P chooses to advocate X].

In the second case, the observer may activate an implicit theory that peo-
ple do things because they have to; e.g.,

[A controls P; A desires X; P advocates X].

The first theory has implications for the actor’s belief, but the second the-
ory does not. Consequently, the observer may infer that the first person is
more likely to believe in capital punishment than the second.
However, now suppose the two individuals in our example are asked to
report their own beliefs in capital punishment. If people use similar implicit
theories to infer their own attributes from their behavior, the first person
should report a stronger belief in capital punishment than the second. Al-
though there are obviously alternative interpretations of this difference
(Festinger, 1957), Bem’s conception is certainly plausible.
Bem and McConnell (1970) constructed an intriguing empirical demon-
stration of self-perception processes that also has implications for the role
of implicational molecules in reconstructive memory. Some participants
wrote a counterattitudinal essay under conditions in which they were given
the right to refuse, whereas others were told to write the essay without be-
ing given a choice. Then, some participants in each condition were asked to
report their attitude toward the position they had advocated. These partici-
pants reported more favorable attitudes toward the position under free-
choice conditions than under no-choice conditions, consistent with numer-
ous other studies.
Other participants, however, were asked to recall the attitude they had
reported in an earlier experimental session. These participants’ recall of
their prebehavior attitudes was affected in the same way that postbehavior
attitudes of the first group of participants were influenced. That is, partici-
pants under free-choice conditions recalled their prebehavior attitudes as
similar to the position they advocated in the essay they had written subse-
quently. This was not the case under forced-choice conditions. Participants
in this study, like those in Ross’s studies and the research by Goethals and
Reckman (1973), may have invoked an implicit theory about the attitudinal
antecedents of their behavior and used this theory to infer not only their
postbehavior attitudes but also what their attitudes must have been before
engaging in this behavior.

Further Considerations

The interpretation of research on the effects of behavior on attitudes is of-


ten equivocal. That is, it is often difficult to know whether these effects oc-
cur after the behavior has been performed or in the course of deciding to
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 277

engage in it. In the latter case, the results would not indicate an effect of the
behavior per se, but rather, would simply reflect the results of cognitive de-
liberations that were involved in deciding whether or not to engage in it.
A study by Albarracin and Wyer (2000) circumvented this ambiguity. Par-
ticipants were told that the experiment was designed to test a new comput-
erized procedure for identifying “unconscious behavioral tendencies.” The
procedure ostensibly consisted of presenting statements about social is-
sues subliminally and having participants respond to them without being
consciously aware of their content. Participants were told that although the
stimulus statements would appear to be only flashes of light, they would
elicit unconscious feelings that would give rise to a more conscious “intu-
ition.” They were informed that to provide a measure of their behavior,
they should “follow their intuition” and generate a “yes” or “no” response
to each statement, which would then be interpreted by the computer as a
vote either in favor of or against the issue to which it pertained.
With this preamble, participants were ostensibly exposed to 14 state-
ments that ostensibly concerned seven different university policies. They
were told that the statements might express either support for or opposi-
tion to a policy and that the computer program would take this into ac-
count in determining the implications of their votes. After the 14 “state-
ments” had been judged, participants received computerized feedback
about both the policies to which they were subliminally exposed and their
responses to these policies. Participants’ a priori positions on six of the pol-
icies (e.g., “maintaining civil liberties on campus,” “receiving free tickets to
sports events,” “raising tuition,” etc.) were self-evident. Participants were
told that they had voted in favor of or in opposition to each of these poli-
cies, depending on which vote was normative. (This established the credi-
bility of the assessment procedure.) The seventh policy, “instituting com-
prehensive examinations on campus,” was one on which participants held
varying opinions. Independently of these opinions, however, some partici-
pants were told they had voted in favor of instituting the exams and others
were told they had voted against it.
Participants after receiving the feedback were told that to understand
their unconscious decisions, we needed to know their personal feelings
about the policies and, on this pretext, asked them to report their attitudes
toward instituting the exams. In addition, they estimated the likelihood and
desirability of a number of possible consequences of instituting the exams.
Finally, we indicated that because participants had an opportunity to think
about comprehensive examinations during the experiment, we wanted to
see how students might actually vote in a referendum that was likely to be
held later in the semester. Participants were then left alone with instruc-
tions to select a slip of paper that represented their choice and to place it in
a secured ballot box. (The box appeared to be partially full. In fact, how-
278 CHAPTER 10

ever, it contained only blank slips of paper, and so we could determine after
the experiment how the participants had voted.)
Thus, the procedure ensured that participants had not thought about
comprehensive examinations before they received feedback about their os-
tensible voting behavior. Nevertheless, participants reported more favor-
able attitudes toward the institution of the exams if they had ostensibly
voted in favor of instituting them than if they had voted against. Further-
more, this difference was evident regardless of the attitudes that partici-
pants had reported before to the experiment. Finally, their postbehavior at-
titudes, once formed, were used as bases for their actual voting decisions
that they made at the end of the experiment. (Path analyses indicated that
behavior feedback did not have an effect on participants’ judgments of spe-
cific behavioral consequences, nor did it have direct influence on partici-
pants’ voting behavior. Rather, this latter influence was mediated by the im-
pact of the feedback on participants’ attitudes.)
This study provided no direct evidence of the cognitive mediators of the
effects we observed. It nevertheless seems reasonable to assume that par-
ticipants invoked an implicit theory that people publicly advocate positions
they favor, as embodied in the implicational molecule:

[P favors X; P votes in favor of X].

Participants may have used this molecule not only to infer their attitude to-
ward comprehensive examinations from their “unconscious” behavior, but
also, once their attitude was inferred, as a basis for the overt behavioral de-
cision they made at the end of the experiment.

MOTIVATIONAL INFLUENCES ON IMPLICIT


THEORY CONSTRUCTION AND USE

As we have suggested, the associated cognitions that compose the theories


that people form and use can often result from the experience of these
cognitions, or their referents, in temporal proximity. However, this is cer-
tainly not the whole story. As Arkin et al.’s (1976) study indicated, people
are often motivated to interpret their experiences in a way that reflects fa-
vorably on themselves and their ability to be successful in the world in
which they live. This may be a manifestation of a more general tendency to
construct and apply implicit theories about oneself and the world that con-
firm the desire to have a happy and successful life.
Kunda (1990) summarized substantial evidence in support of this possi-
bility. For example, although college students know that 50% of all first mar-
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 279

riages end in divorce, they nevertheless are convinced that they personally
will remain married to their first spouse for life (Kunda, 1987). This suggests
that individuals who are motivated to believe that they will be successful in
marriage, construct implicit self-theories that support this belief. To demon-
strate this, Kunda (1987) gave participants information about a target per-
son who was either happily married or divorced and whose demographic
and personality characteristics either matched or did not match those of
the participants themselves. After receiving this information, participants
indicated which of the target’s attributes were most likely to contribute to
his or her marital status. Participants were more inclined to attribute the
success of happily married targets to characteristics that matched their
own than to characteristics that did not. Correspondingly, they were less
likely to attribute the failure of divorced targets to the former characteris-
tics. Thus, they constructed theories about themselves that were consis-
tent with the outcome they wished to attain.
People who are motivated to construct and maintain a self-serving the-
ory may selectively search memory for information that supports it. In a
study by Santioso, Kunda, and Fong (1990), some participants were told
that extroversion was conducive to success after leaving college, whereas
others were told that introversion was more conducive to success. Then, in
an ostensibly unrelated study, they were asked to list all of the behaviors
they had performed in the past along a related trait dimension (shy vs. out-
going). Participants listed more behaviors that were congruent with the
trait they were told was conducive to success than behaviors that were in-
congruent with this trait. In a second study, participants after exposure to
the first task were shown a series of behaviors and were asked in each case
to press a button as soon as they thought of a personal experience that ex-
emplified it. Participants responded more quickly to behaviors that exem-
plified the success-related trait than to behaviors that exemplified the op-
posite. Thus, people who are told that a particular trait is associated with
success selectively searched memory for personal experiences that con-
firmed their possession of this trait. Consequently, these experiences came
to mind more easily when they were called upon to report instances of
their behavior at a later point in time.
Research in other paradigms has similar implications. For example, peo-
ple are more likely to report engaging in a particular activity (drinking cof-
fee, brushing one’s teeth, etc.) if they are told that the activity is healthy
than if they are told it is not (Ross, McFarland, & Fletcher, 1986; B. Sherman
& Kunda, 1989). These studies do not provide direct evidence that these re-
sponses were mediated by the construction of an implicit theory. However,
it seems reasonable to suppose that the construction of self-serving theo-
ries is a result of similar processes.
280 CHAPTER 10

THE ROLE OF IMPLICIT THEORIES


IN HEURISTIC-BASED JUDGMENTS

The use of heuristics in making inferences is well established (for reviews,


see Kahneman, Slovic, & Tversky, 1982; Nisbett & Ross, 1980; Sherman &
Corty, 1984). As Wyer and Srull (1989) noted, many of these heuristics may
reflect a general tendency to treat conditional relationships as bicondi-
tionals. That is, people assume that if A implies B, then B implies A (for evi-
dence, see Wyer, 1977). Thus, for example, if people believe that members
of a certain category have a certain cluster of attributes, they infer that indi-
viduals with this cluster of attributes belong to the category. Alternatively,
if they believe that events that are likely to occur are easy to imagine, they
infer that events that are easy to imagine are likely to occur.
The latter, “availability” heuristic (Tversky & Kahneman, 1973) is of par-
ticular interest in the present context. This heuristic can be conceptualized
as an implicit theory in the form of an ease-of-retrieval molecule; specifically:

[X has occurred frequently (infrequently); instances of X are easy (difficult) to


recall].

Thus, people may use this molecule not only to infer the ease of recalling in-
stances of an event from knowledge of how often it has occurred, but also
to infer the frequency of an event’s occurrence from the difficulty of recall-
ing instances of it.
Two quite different sets of phenomena can be conceptualized as result-
ing from an application of this molecule. One concerns the effects of televi-
sion on perceptions of social reality. The other concerns the effects of ease
of retrieving knowledge about oneself and others on judgments of the at-
tributes to which this knowledge is relevant. Research on each set of phe-
nomena is discussed in turn.

Perceptions of Social Reality

Americans watch an average of more than 4 hours of television each day


(Nielsen, 1995). As a result, television is a major source of the episode mod-
els that people form. On the other hand, people often fail to distinguish
clearly between the sources of the knowledge they acquire (Hasher, Gold-
stein, & Toppin, 1977; Jacoby, Kelly, Brown, & Jasechko, 1989; Johnson,
Hastroudi, & Lindsay, 1993). As a result, they are likely to use the episode
models they form while watching television as a basis for judgments with-
out considering the context in which these models were constructed.
L. J. Shrum and his colleagues (O’Guinn & Shrum, 1997; Shrum, O’Guinn,
Semenik, & Faber, 1998; Shrum, Wyer, & O’Guinn, 1998) have examined im-
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 281

plications of this possibility in the context of their research on the “cultiva-


tion effect” (Gerbner, Gross, Morgan, & Signorielli, 1994). That is, people
tend to overestimate the occurrence of events in the real world that are dis-
proportionately represented on television. Moreover, the magnitude of
their overestimation increases with the amount of television they watch. In-
stances of events that occur frequently on television are easily accessible in
memory, and this is particularly true for heavy viewers. Therefore, if indi-
viduals are asked to infer the frequency of occurrence of these events, and
if they apply the ease-of-retrieval molecule, heavy users are likely to make
higher estimates than light viewers do. Thus, for example, heavy viewers
are relatively more likely than light viewers to overestimate the proportion
of Americans who belong to a country club or have a swimming pool in
their back yard (O’Guinn & Shrum, 1997). On the other hand, they are also
more likely to overestimate the incidence of violent crime and the size of
the police force.
Several studies by Shrum and his colleagues support this interpretation.
In one study (O’Guinn & Shrum, 1997), frequent and infrequent viewers of
soap operas were asked to estimate the incidence of characteristics that
are associated with an affluent life style (belonging to a country club, own-
ing a luxury car, having a swimming pool, etc.). Frequent viewers not only
estimated the incidence of these characteristics to be higher than infre-
quent viewers did, but also made their estimates more quickly. These find-
ings are consistent with the hypothesis that frequent television viewers find
instances of these characteristics easier to retrieve from memory and esti-
mate their incidence to be greater as a result.
Other interpretations of these effects should of course be considered.
For example, a third variable, such as education level or socioeconomic
class, could have independent effects on both television watching and fre-
quency estimates, producing an artifactual relation between these vari-
ables that would not otherwise exist. However, O’Guinn and Shrum (1997;
see also Shrum, Wyer, & O’Guinn, 1998) found that the relation between fre-
quency estimates and television viewing was evident even when the poten-
tially confounding effects of these variables were controlled. Moreover,
Shrum et al. (1998) found that when participants were asked to report their
television viewing habits before making frequency estimates (thus calling
their television watching to their attention), the impact of television view-
ing on frequency estimates was significantly reduced. The effects of watch-
ing television on frequency estimates can also be reduced or eliminated by
increasing participants’ motivation to make correct judgments (Shrum,
1999). Thus, people appear able to distinguish between events they see on
television and those they learn about from other sources, and thus can
avoid the bias produced by television when they are motivated to do so.
Normally, however, this motivation does not exist.
282 CHAPTER 10

Although the effects of television on perceptions of social reality are well


established, a qualification on these effects might be noted. Hamilton and
Gifford (1976) found that the incidence of infrequently occurring events is
overestimated to a greater extent than the incidence of more common
ones. This is presumably due in part to the fact that rare events are thought
about more extensively (for evidence that the recall of information in-
creases with amount of processing, see Craik & Lockhart, 1972). In some
cases, this effect could override the effects identified by Shrum and his col-
leagues. On the other hand, people are typically passive viewers of televi-
sion, and are likely to encode and store the information they receive with
minimal cognitive elaboration. To this extent, the effects identified by Ham-
ilton and Gifford (1976) may not be pronounced.
The effects of television on perceptions of social reality have potentially
important implications. For example, individuals who are frequently ex-
posed to television violence may come to view violence and aggression as
normal aspects of life and, therefore, may have more tolerance of aggres-
sion than they otherwise would. Zillman and Bryant (1982) found that ex-
posing naïve college students to heavy doses of sadomasochistic pornogra-
phy over a period of several weeks increased their tolerance of rape.
Moreover, these effects were still evident several months after the main
study had been completed. Other effects of the media on attitudes and val-
ues are worth examining from this perspective.

Effects of Ease of Retrieval on Perceptions


of Self and Others

Shrum et al.’s research suggests that the ease of recalling instances of an


event increases estimates of its frequency. To the extent people apply the
ease-of-retrieval molecule, difficulty in retrieving instances should have the
opposite effect. An intriguing demonstration of this effect was constructed
by Norbert Schwarz and his colleagues (for a review, see Schwarz, 1998). In
a typical study (Schwarz et al., 1991), participants were asked to recall ei-
ther 6 or 12 instances of assertive behavior. After doing so, they rated their
assertiveness.
Participants obviously recalled more behaviors when they were asked to
recall 12 than when they were asked to recall 6. Therefore, one might ex-
pect participants to judge themselves to be more assertive in the former
condition than the latter. On the other hand, it is much more difficult to gen-
erate 12 instances of the attribute than 6 instances. Therefore, to the extent
individuals base their judgments on the ease-of-retrieval molecule, they
should infer that they engage in assertive behavior less frequently in the
former condition than the latter. Thus, they should infer that they are less
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 283

assertive when they have been asked to recall 12 instances than when they
were asked to recall only 6. This was in fact the case.
The use of an ease-of-retrieval heuristic as a basis for judgment is quite
pervasive (for a review, see Schwarz, 1998). Further examples are de-
scribed later in this chapter. Its implications can be quite ironic. For exam-
ple, people may be less likely to believe that a proposition is true if they
have attempted to generate a large number of reasons for its validity than
if they have thought about only a few. Research by Wänke, Bless, and
Biller (1996) supported this speculation. Some participants were asked to
generate either 3 or 7 arguments that either favored or opposed a specific
issue, after which they were asked to report their own position on the is-
sue. Other, yoked participants read the arguments that individuals in the
first group had written. The latter participants reported themselves to be
more in favor of the position advocated when they had read 7-argument
responses than when they had read 3-argument responses, confirming the
assumption that the substantive implications of the 7-argument sets were
relatively more persuasive. Nevertheless, the participants who had actu-
ally generated the arguments judged themselves to be less in favor of the
position when they had generated 7 arguments than when they had gener-
ated only 3. Thus, the effects of ease of retrieval overrode the effects of ac-
tual knowledge.
People do not always ignore the implications of their past knowledge, of
course. However, their computation of a belief on the basis of these implica-
tions is cognitively effortful. Consequently, they may only do so when ease
of retrieval is likely to be an unreliable criterion. In other conditions of
Schwarz et al.’s (1991) research, for example, participants generated in-
stances of assertiveness in the presence of distracting background music.
In this case, participants apparently attributed their difficulty of generating
instances to the distraction and to their lack of knowledge. In these condi-
tions, therefore, they judged themselves more assertive when they had gen-
erated 12 instances rather than 6.

1. Effects of Information About Others’ Ease


of Retrieving Information

As suggested in our discussion of self-perception processes, people can


use implicit theories to construe the implications of others’ behavior as
well as their own. Support for this assumption in the present paradigm was
obtained by Menon and Raghubir (1998) in a study of consumer judgment.
Participants read an advertisement that described the attractive features of
a computer. Later, they were asked to recall either 2 or 8 of these features.
Either before or after the recall task, however, they were given information
about the difficulty that others had in recalling the product’s attributes. If
284 CHAPTER 10

participants use the ease-of-retrieval molecule to infer the implications of


this information, they should infer that the computer has more attractive
features when others find it easy to recall these features than when they
did not, and should judge the product more favorably in the former condi-
tion. Support for this prediction is conveyed in Table 10.1, which summa-
rizes participants’ product evaluations as a function of the number of fea-
tures they were personally asked to recall, the difficulty that others
ostensibly had in recalling attributes, and the point at which the latter infor-
mation was provided. Participants generally evaluated the product more fa-
vorably when others ostensibly found it easy to recall features than when
they found it difficult. However, participants’ use of the ease-of-retrieval
molecule to construe the implications of their own behavior was evident
only when they recalled the product’s features before learning about the
difficulty that others had. In this condition, they evaluated the product
more favorably when they had recalled 2 attributes than when they re-
called 8. When they were told about others’ difficulty at the outset, how-
ever, they appeared to ignore the difficulty they personally experienced
and based their judgments on the number of features they could recall,
thus reporting more favorable evaluations when they were asked to recall 8
features rather than 2.
In summary, people appear to use the ease-of-retrieval molecule to infer
the incidence of information in memory when (a) alternative bases for judg-
ment are not easily accessible in memory and (b) the difficulty they have in
recalling the information is unlikely to be due to extraneous situational fac-
tors. However, when alternative reasons for their subjective feelings are
called to their attention, or when other bases for judgment (e.g., the diffi-
culty that others have had recalling attributes) are easily available, people
apply other criteria instead.

TABLE 10.1
Effects of Subjective Difficulty of Recalling Product Attributes,
and Perceptions of Others’ Difficulty, on Product Evaluations

Two Attributes Eight Attributes


Recalled Recalled M

Others’ difficulty mentioned after recall


Others find recall easy 5.9 4.9 5.4
Others find recall difficult 5.4 4.4 4.9
M 5.6 4.9
Others’ difficulty mentioned before recall
Others find recall easy 5.3 5.9 5.6
Others find recall difficult 4.3 4.9 4.6
M 4.8 5.4

Note. Adapted from Menon and Raghubir (1998).


THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 285

2. The Role of Ease of Retrieval in Hindsight Bias

The role of ease of retrieval in the construction and use of implicit theo-
ries is demonstrated in a series of studies by Sanna and Schwarz (2003;
Sanna, Schwarz, & Small, 2003; Sanna, Schwarz, & Stocker, 2002). People
who know that an event has occurred often overestimate the likelihood
that they would have predicted it (Fischoff, 1975, 1982; for a review, see
Hawkins & Hastie, 1990). This “hindsight” bias presumably occurs for rea-
sons similar to that we assumed to underlie the effects reported by L. Ross
et al. (1975). That is, individuals who are told that an event has occurred at-
tempt to generate a plausible explanation for it and, if this can be done eas-
ily, may conclude that the occurrence of the event was foreordained. In do-
ing so, they ignore the possibility that if the event had not occurred, they
might have generated an explanation of its nonoccurrence just as easily.
If this is the case, however, stimulating individuals to generate additional
explanations for the event, which could be difficult, might decrease or re-
verse the effects observed by Fischoff (1975). Correspondingly, stimulating
people to generate explanations of why the event might not have occurred
could increase the magnitude of the hindsight bias. Sanna and Schwarz
(2003) found this to be the case. Participants in one series of studies read a
story about a military conflict and were arbitrarily told that one of the two
antagonists had been victorious. Participants were then told to generate ei-
ther 2 or 10 thoughts about how this outcome might have been averted.
Participants who generated thoughts about the alternative outcome of the
conflict decreased their belief that this outcome could have occurred. How-
ever, this effect was much greater when they had generated 10 thoughts
(which was difficult to do) than when they had generated only 2. Thus, gen-
erating explanations for how the alternative outcome could have occurred
increased beliefs that the actual outcome was inevitable, thus magnifying
the hindsight bias that participants manifested. In a second series of stud-
ies (Sanna, Schwarz, & Small, 2003), however, participants thought about
why the outcome they were given should have occurred. In this case, par-
ticipants who generated many thoughts decreased their belief that the out-
come was inevitable, thus eliminating the hindsight bias that was otherwise
evident.
In summary, people may often spontaneously generate an implicit the-
ory for why an outcome will occur, and this theory may underlie their belief
that the outcome was foreordained (Fischoff, 1975, 1982). However, generat-
ing additional explanations for the outcome, which is difficult, can decrease
their belief that the outcome was inevitable, whereas generating reasons
why the outcome might not have occurred is likely to strengthen this belief.
Thus, as also implied by Wänke et al.’s (1996) findings noted earlier, the
greater the number of thoughts that individuals generate in support of a po-
sition actually weakens their belief that the position is valid.
286 CHAPTER 10

INDIVIDUAL DIFFERENCES IN IMPLICIT THEORIES

To reiterate, more than one implicit theory can often be used to account for
a given social experience. In such instances, individual and situational dif-
ferences may arise in the theory that people happen to apply and, there-
fore, in the conclusions they draw from the experience. These differences
are likely to be reflected in their judgments and behavioral decisions.

Implicit Theories of Personal Achievement

Individual differences in implicit theories of social judgment and behavior


were suggested by Carol Dweck and her colleagues (Dweck, 1991; Dweck &
Leggett, 1988; Erdley & Dweck, 1993) in an analysis of individuals’ responses
to success and failure. Based on Dweck’s earlier work on learned helpless-
ness (for a summary, see Dweck & Leggett, 1988), they postulated that some
individuals believe that performance on an achievement task can typically
be increased by exerting effort, whereas others are disposed to belief that
performance is largely a reflection of abilities that are fixed and unable to
change. The first belief might be captured by an implicit theory of the form:

[P performs task; P fails; P tries harder; P succeeds].

The second, however, could reflect the theory:

[P has low ability; P performs task; P fails; P tries harder; P fails again].

Thus, suppose people perform a task and fail. This event (“P fails”)
instantiates a segment of each of these theories. Individuals who activate
and use the first theory to interpret the event may infer that they did not
work hard enough and that if they exert more effort, they might ultimately
succeed. As a result, they may be stimulated to try the task again. However,
suppose individuals activate the second theory instead. Then, they are
likely to infer that their failure reflects low ability and that repeating the
task will have the same outcome. Therefore, they may be disinclined to try
a second time. Individual differences in the chronic accessibility of these
theories, and their effects on responses to failure, have been elaborated by
Dweck and Leggett (1988).

Incremental Versus Entity Theories


of Personality and Ability

Dweck (1991; Dweck & Leggett, 1988) suggest that the aforementioned per-
formance-related theories exemplify two more general theories of personal-
ity and behavior. Incremental theories imply that people’s attributes and
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 287

abilities are malleable and can be modified, whereas entity theories imply
that attributes are fixed and resistant to change. These different theories
have numerous implications for judgment and behavior, many of which
have been examined by Dweck, Chiu, and Hong (1995a, 1995b; Dweck, Hong,
& Chiu, 1993; Chiu, Dweck, Tong, & Fu, 1997; Chiu, Hong, & Dweck, 1997;
Hong, Chiu, Dweck, & Sacks, 1997).
Hong et al. (1997), for example, found evidence that people who were
classified as entity theorists on the basis of an independent measure were
more influenced by a target person’s personality and ability test scores
than incremental theorists were, suggesting that they attached relatively
more significance to measures that ostensibly assess stable attributes and
abilities. People may also have incremental vs. entity theories of morality
(implying that individual’s moral character can or cannot be easily modi-
fied) and of the world in which they live. A series of studies by Chiu et al.
(1997) provided evidence that individuals with entity theories of morality
and the world are more inclined than individuals with incremental theo-
ries to evaluate others’ behavior in terms of its fulfillment of obligations
rather than in terms of individual rights. Thus, for example, participants in
one study were asked to give open-ended descriptions of how they would
handle hypothetical classroom situations. Some scenarios described so-
cially desirable behavior (e.g., “The teacher asked Jerry to remove old pa-
pers and notices on the students’ notice boards, and Jerry does what she
requested as soon as possible.”). Others described undesirable actions
(e.g., “The teacher asked Peter to remove old papers and notices. . . . A
week has passed and Peter does not do it.”). Entity theorists, who believe
that the fulfillment of responsibilities is normative, were less inclined than
incremental theorists to indicate that Jerry should be rewarded for fulfill-
ing his obligations. Correspondingly, they were more inclined than incre-
mental theorists to recommend that Peter be punished for not meeting his
responsibilities.
As Dweck et al. (1995a, 1995b) pointed out, the implicit theories that in-
dividuals apply may often be domain specific. Moreover, several alterna-
tive theories may coexist, the implications of which can conflict. The indi-
vidual differences in implicit theories that Dweck and her colleagues
identified in the aforementioned studies could reflect differences in the
chronic accessibility of these theories. To this extent, situational factors
that make one or another theory more accessible in memory might some-
times override these chronic differences. Although this possibility was
not examined in the studies cited in this section, evidence that the effects
of transitory situational factors can often dominate the effects of chronic
accessibility (at least in the short run) is provided by other research de-
scribed presently.
288 CHAPTER 10

IMPLICIT THEORIES OF SOCIAL SUPPORT:


THE EFFECT OF PERSPECTIVE
ON THEORY ACTIVATION

The implicit theories that people acquire are often the result of accumu-
lated past experiences in a particular type of situation that have been suffi-
ciently involving to stimulate the construction of a generalized event repre-
sentation of the sequence of events that take place. Individuals are
therefore likely to differ in the nature of these theories, depending on the
past experiences they have typically had. However, the implications of
their theories can also depend on the perspective from which the experi-
ences in question were viewed. An interesting example of these contingen-
cies is provided by Eric Mankowski’s research on perceptions of social sup-
port (Mankowski & Wyer, 1996). Imagine the following situation:

Russell has learned he got a D on the psychology midterm. He is near tears


when he gets back to his room where his roommate, Chris, is studying. He
tells Chris the bad news. “If I don’t get good grades, I’ll have to drop out of
school. . . . I can’t seem to do well here.”
“Wow,” Chris replies, “What do you say we go out for a pizza and beer? I
haven’t had a good day, either.”
They go out for pizza. . . . Russell tells Chris, “Remember that girl I met at
your party? She’s right over there. . . . We were supposed to go to a movie to-
gether, but she never showed up. . . . I really thought she was interested in
me. . . . I don’t know if I can eat with her sitting there.”
“Oh, she won’t even notice us here,” Chris says. “You should get fixed up
with someone. . . . Mark might have a suggestion. He sure seems to have no
problem getting dates.”

This story is ambiguous in terms of the social support it describes.


Chris’s suggestion to get a pizza, for example, could be viewed as either a
desire to distract Russell from thinking about his bad grade or, alterna-
tively, as insensitivity to Russell’s need for sympathy and reassurance.
Readers’ perception of the story’s implications could therefore depend in
part on the semantic concepts that they bring to bear on its interpretation.
However, their construal of the story’s implications could also depend on
the similarity of the situation it describes to their own past experiences.
For example, people could use a theory about their own experiences as a
standard of comparison in evaluating others. Thus, they might perceive
Chris’s behavior to be relatively more supportive if they have often expe-
rienced rejection themselves than if they have not. This tendency, on the
other hand, is likely to depend on the whether the new experience is
viewed from the perspective of the potential support provider or the
point of view of the recipient.
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 289

These contingencies were identified by Mankowski and Wyer (1996). Par-


ticipants were told that the study was concerned with person impression
formation. On this pretense, they were asked to read a story similar to the
one just described, in which one person was in need of support and the
other was in a position to provide it. In third-person perspective conditions,
the story was written from the perspective of a disinterested observer. In
provider-perspective conditions, however, the provider was referred to as
“you” and the recipient was identified by a name that was ambiguous with
respect to gender (Chris or Terry). In recipient-perspective conditions, the re-
cipient was referred to as “you” and the potential provider was identified
by name. After reading the story, participants in each perspective condition
wrote down three adjectives that they would use to describe the provider
and then rated the provider with respect to several traits that were rele-
vant to social support (supportive, warm, rejecting, accepting, sensitive,
etc.). Finally, participants were completed a general index of the support
they perceived to be personally available (Cutrona & Russell, 1987).
Participants’ perceptions of support availability could reflect two
things. First, it could indicate the frequency with which participants had
personally encountered support-relevant situations in the past and, there-
fore, the likelihood that semantic concepts associated with social support
were chronically accessible in memory. To this extent, participants’ per-
ceptions of support availability should have a positive impact on their use
of support-related concepts to interpret the provider’s ambiguous behav-
ior, and this should be true in all three perspective conditions. On the
other hand, participants’ perceptions of support availability could also in-
dicate the likelihood that they have constructed an implicit theory of
themselves as recipients of support. If participants who read the story
from the recipient’s perspective activate and use this theory as a standard
of comparison in construing the story’s implications, they should perceive
the situation o be less supportive when their self-referent theory implies
that they typically receive support than when it does not. This contrast ef-
fect of the story’s implications on judgments could offset the positive ef-
fect of semantic concepts on its interpretation that occurs at an earlier
stage of processing.
Results were consistent with this analysis. Table 10.2 shows the suppor-
tiveness implied by both participants’ open-ended trait descriptions of the
support provider and their ratings of the provider’s supportiveness. When
participants took the perspective of either the provider or third person,
their perceptions of the provider’s supportiveness increased with their per-
ception of their own support availability. When they took the role of the re-
cipient, however, this was not the case. In these latter conditions, the con-
trast effect that resulted from using an implicit theory of their personal
experiences as a standard of comparison appeared to offset the positive ef-
290 CHAPTER 10

TABLE 10.2
Perceptions of the Provider’s Supportiveness as a Function
of Perspective and Social Support Availability

Perspective

Provider Third Person Recipient

Supportiveness of trait descriptions


High support availability 0.39a 0.14 –0.44
Low support availability 0.18 –0.26 –0.26
Difference 0.21 0.40 –0.18
Supportiveness of trait ratings
High support availability 0.81b 0.26 –1.07
Low support availability 0.35 –0.44 –1.16
Difference 0.46 0.70 0.09

Note. Adapted from Mankowski and Wyer (1996).


aScores reflect the mean difference between the number of trait descriptions that implied

support and the number that implied lack of support.


bScores reflect the mean difference in ratings of traits implying support (reported along a

0–10 scale) and ratings of traits implying rejection.

fects of semantic concepts on the interpretation of the scenario that was ev-
ident in other perspective conditions.

CULTURAL DIFFERENCES IN IMPLICIT THEORIES

Individual differences in the chronic accessibility of implicit theories are


likely to result in part from differences in the socialization practices to
which individuals have been exposed (cf. Miller, 1994; Nelson, 1993; see
chap. 6) and, therefore, the frequency with which the theories have been
applied in the past. To this extent, differences may exist in the theories that
are typically applied by members of different subgroups within a society
(e.g., men vs. women, Blacks vs. Whites, etc.). More general cultural differ-
ences may exist as well. The precise nature of this difference is somewhat
controversial (cf. Briley & Wyer, 2001; Heine, Lehman, Markus, & Kitayama,
1999; Markus & Kitayama, 1991; Triandis, 1995). However, certain general
differences appear to exist.
For example, members of Western and Asian cultures are typically char-
acterized as differing in terms of individualism and collectivism (Hofstede,
1991; Triandis, 1995). Individualism is characterized by a focus on individual
freedom and independence, a concern with personal goals with little con-
sideration of others, independently of others, and competitiveness. In con-
trast, collectivism is typified by a focus on oneself in relation to the groups
to which one belongs, and a concern with group well-being rather than per-
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 291

sonal goals. As Briley and Wyer (2001) pointed out (see also Ho & Chiu,
1994; Rhee, Uleman, & Lee, 1996; Triandis & Gelfand, 1998), the individual-
ism–collectivism construct is multidimensional, and the dimensions that
are often assumed to distinguish individualists and collectivists (i.e., indi-
viduality, cooperation, competitiveness, self-sacrifice, etc.) are not strongly
related (Briley & Wyer, 2001). Nevertheless, a general cultural difference in
the tendency to think of oneself as an independent individual vs. a member
of a group is fairly pervasive (Markus & Kitayama, 1994).
However, the implicit theories that reflect these different cultural orien-
tations are not the only ones that people acquire. As Hong et al. (2000) sug-
gested, representatives of a given culture are often exposed to norms and
values that pervade other cultures as well. Moreover, many individuals are
bicultural, having lived for many years in more than one country, or being
residing in a country (e.g., Hong Kong) in which both Western and Asian
norms and values are pervasive. Hong et al. (2000) conceptualize culture as
a dynamic construct, the effects of which can depend on situational factors
that influence the extent to which cultural norms and values are accessible
in memory. Several studies provide evidence of this dependence.

Attributions of Causality

Hong et al. (2000) showed that the implicit theories that Hong Kong partici-
pants bring to bear on the interpretation of information and the inferences
they draw from this information can be induced by exposing participants to
cultural symbols of Western and Asian cultures prior to the judgment task.
For example, Westerners (individualists) typically acquire an implicit the-
ory of causality that places responsibility on the individual, whereas Asians
(collectivists) acquire theories that place responsibility on the society or
social context in which the behavior occurs. Evidence supporting this dif-
ference was reported by Morris and Peng (1994; see also, Choi, Nisbett, &
Norenzayan, 1999). Nevertheless, both implicit theories are likely to exist in
memory, and the theory that is activated and applied may be influenced by
situational factors that affect its accessibility.
To demonstrate this, Hong et al. constructed stimulus materials consist-
ing of a school of fish in which one fish was swimming ahead of the others.
Thus, the situation could be interpreted as an indication that either the first
fish was leading the others (implying a dispositional cause of the fish’s be-
havior) or, alternatively, that the first fish was being chased by the others
(a situational cause of its behavior). Hong Kong Chinese undergraduates
were exposed to these pictures with instructions to explain why the one
fish was swimming ahead of the others. Before doing so, however, they
were exposed to either a series of American cultural icons or a series of
Chinese icons as part of an ostensibly different experiment. Exposure to
292 CHAPTER 10

American icons increased the tendency to assign a disposition cause to the


fish’s behavior relative to control conditions, and correspondingly de-
creased the tendency to assign a situational cause to it. However, exposure
to Chinese cultural icons had the opposite effects.

Theories of Personal Causality

A series of studies by Oishi, Wyer, and Colcombe (2000) identified cultural


differences in the situational factors that activate implicit theories about
the determinants of one’s own behavior, and demonstrated that these dif-
ferences are reflected in people’s use of their current life satisfaction to pre-
dict the future. People are likely to use this criterion if they activate a per-
son-focused theory of causality (i.e., a theory that life experiences are
determined by stable personal characteristics that persist over time). How-
ever, they are less likely to do so if they apply a situation-focused theory
(i.e., the theory that life experiences are influenced by unforeseen situa-
tional factors). Like Hong et al., we reasoned that people are likely to have
both implicit theories in memory regardless of their cultural background.
However, we expected that the situational factors that activate these theo-
ries would differ.
Specifically, Heine and Lehman (1997; Heine et al., 1999) noted that repre-
sentatives of individualistic cultures exhibit strong self-enhancement mo-
tives, as evidenced by a desire to take responsibility for positive experi-
ences but to attribute negative experiences to transitory situational factors
(Harvey & Weary, 1984; Zuckerman, 1975; see also the study by Arkin et al.,
1976, described in chap. 9). If this is so, calling European Americans’ atten-
tion to positive experiences they have had in the past (for which they pre-
sumably take responsibility) should activate a theory that people are per-
sonally responsible for the events that befall them. Therefore, it should
increase the likelihood that these individuals see themselves as responsible
for both their current and future life situation, and should increase their
tendency to use their current life satisfaction to predict the future. How-
ever, calling these individuals’ attention to negative life events (which they
attribute to situational factors) should activate a theory that life events are
the result of unpredictable factors over which they have little control, and
so it should decrease their tendency to use current life satisfaction to pre-
dict the future.
These predictions should not hold for Asians, however. Members of
Asian societies tend to be self-effacing, and to take responsibility for per-
sonal failure but attribute success to external circumstances (Fry & Ghosh,
1980; Yamauchi, 1988). If this is so, calling Asians’ attention to positive and
negative life experiences should have the opposite effects that it has on
Americans. That is, thinking about positive life events should activate a sit-
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 293

uation-based theory, whereas thinking about negative life events should ac-
tivate a person-based theory. Consequently, Asians should be less inclined
to use their current life satisfaction to predict their future in the former con-
dition than the latter.
Oishi et al. (2000) confirmed these predictions. Participants were Euro-
pean Americans and Asian Americans whose life satisfaction was assessed
in an ostensibly unrelated experiment. Participants first completed a life-
event inventory in which they were asked to write about either a positive
life experience they had had or a negative one. Then, after doing so, they
were given a list of 10 positive and 10 negative events (getting the best
grade on an exam, finding that your friends were talking about you behind
your back, etc.), and estimated the likelihood that each event would occur
to them in the near future.
Multiple regression procedures were used to analyze the favorableness
of participants’ predictions of the future as a function of a number of or-
thogonal contrasts corresponding to the main and interactive effects of life
satisfaction (a continuous variable), cultural background and the valence of
the life experience that participants recalled. This analysis yielded a signifi-
cant interaction of all three variables. The implications of this interaction
can be seen in the left half of Table 10.3, which shows estimated values of
the favorableness of participants’ future outlook as a function of culture,
the valence of the stories that participants wrote about themselves, and
current life satisfaction. European Americans’ life satisfaction had a greater
effect on their future outlook when they had written about a positive life ex-
perience than when they had written about a negative one. In contrast,
Asian Americans’ life satisfaction had more influence on their future out-

TABLE 10.3
Regression-Based Estimates of Future Outlook as a Function
of Current Life Satisfaction, Cultural Background, and the
Valence of Stories About Self and Other

Valence of Stories Valence of Stories


About Self About Others

Favorable Unfavorable Favorable Unfavorable

European Americans
High current life satisfaction 0.36 1.26 1.44 1.84
Low current life satisfaction –2.04 –0.26 1.18 –0.38
Difference 2.40 1.52 0.26 2.22
Asian Americans
High current life satisfaction 0.80 1.54 1.74 0.98
Low current life satisfaction –0.32 –1.10 0.56 0.24
Difference 1.12 2.64 1.18 0.74

Note. Adapted from Oishi et al. (2000).


294 CHAPTER 10

look when they had written about a negative experience than when they
had written about a positive one.
A second study was analogous to the first but focused on the effects of
activating concepts about others. If European Americans are motivated by
a desire to be superior to others, they may tend to attribute others’ suc-
cesses to situational factors but others’ negative outcomes to dispositional
factors (Snyder, Stephan, & Rosenfield, 1976). In contrast, if Asians are typi-
cally self-effacing and tend to promote others’ interests at their own ex-
pense, they may be inclined to attribute others’ successes to dispositional
causes (Yamauchi, 1988). To this extent, a person-based theory of causality
should be activated in European Americans by stimulating them to think
about others’ failures, but should be activated in Asian Americans by induc-
ing them to think about others’ successes.
To explore this possibility, participants participated in a study that was
very similar to the first. Rather than writing about a personal experience,
however, they read a newspaper story describing either positive or nega-
tive job prospects for the current year’s college graduates. (Participants
were freshmen, and so the story was not personally relevant.) Regression
analyses of these participants’ future outlook as a function of experimental
variables yielded a three-way interaction of cultural background, life satis-
faction, and the valence of others’ experiences, the implications of which
are shown in the right half of Table 10.3. The pattern of these data is exactly
the opposite of the first set of data. That is, European Americans’ future out-
look was most strongly influenced by their current life satisfaction when
they had read about others’ negative experiences, but Asians’ future out-
look was most strongly influenced by life satisfaction when they had read
about others’ positive experiences.

Cultural Differences in Inference Strategies

The preceding discussion suggests cultural differences in the content of the


implicit theories that are applied by members of different cultures. However,
more general differences may exist in the conditions in which these theories
are used. Choi et al. (1998) suggested that general cultural differences be-
tween Western and Asian cultures exist in the tendency to use analytic rea-
soning in generating explanations for social events. To this extent, the infer-
ence processes that are implicitly assumed in much of our discussion of the
use of implicational molecules might not generalize over cultures.
Some support for this possibility was obtained in a study by Norenzayan
and Kim (2000) in research on the Socratic effect (McGuire, 1960). In an ini-
tial experimental session, European Americans and Asians completed a be-
lief questionnaire containing causally related propositions of the sort to
which Equation 10.1 is applicable. They then returned 1 week later and com-
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 295

pleted the questionnaire a second time. Based on research and theorizing


by McGuire (1960; Rosen & Wyer, 1972), Norenzayan and Kim assumed that
participants might show inconsistencies in their beliefs initially, but that
making the beliefs salient in temporal proximity would lead them to revise
these beliefs to make them more consistent. Thus, their beliefs should be
more consistent in the second session than they were at first, based on
Equation 10.1. This was true of European Americans, thus replicating find-
ings by Rosen and Wyer (1972). However, Asians’ beliefs were just as incon-
sistent in the second session as they were at the outset. This suggests that
Asians, unlike Westerners, either did not perceive their beliefs in the propo-
sitions to be inconsistent or, alternatively, employed inference processes
that differed from those described by Equation 10.1.

THE ROLE OF IMPLICIT THEORIES


IN MARITAL SATISFACTION

The theories we construct and apply in evaluating our life experiences can
often have social consequences. For example, people often have narrative-
based theories about close relationships. However, substantial individuals
exist in the nature of these theories. Some people, for example, may believe
that marriage partners fall in love quickly but that these feelings inevitably
deteriorate over time, ultimately leading to separation or divorce. Others
may believe that love takes a long time to develop but that once estab-
lished, it is maintained. Still others may believe that people’s feelings
change nonmonotonically. For example, partners’ affection for one another
decreases over the early years of a relationship as romantic love dissipates
but then increases again in later years as the relationship matures.
Several theorists have conceptualized the role that narrative representa-
tions can play in the dynamics of close relationships (Forgas, 1991; Holmes
& Murray, 1995; Miller & Read, 1991; Schank & Abelson, 1995). Murray and
Holmes (1996), for example, found that marriage partners often reconstruct
stories about their personal relationships in order to make them consistent
with the implications of their narrative-based theories about relationships
in general (see also Holmberg & Holmes, 1994). However, it seems likely
that if partners have different theory-based expectations for the typical
progress of close relationships, they may differ in how they evaluate their
own relationship. These differences could create marital conflict and dissat-
isfaction.
Research by Gohm and Wyer (1998) bears indirectly on this possibility.
We assumed that individuals’ theories about the prognosis of relationships
over time could be inferred from their perceptions of change in the feelings
that characterize these relationships, and that differences in marital satis-
296 CHAPTER 10

faction might be related to these theories. To this end, we identified 32 mar-


ried couples who had been in their relationship for an average of 9 years,
and whose marital satisfaction (based on the Locke–Wallace, 1959, scale of
marital adjustment) had been determined in an earlier study. In 16 of these
couples, both partners expressed satisfaction with their relationship, and in
the other 16, both partners reported being dissatisfied. Participants were
told that the study’s purpose was to understand people’s perceptions of
how interpersonal relationships were likely to change over time. On this
pretense, participants plotted six graphs showing the changes that typi-
cally occurred in marriage partners’ feelings toward one another during the
first 10 years of their relationship. Three graphs described the typical
man’s feelings of romantic love, commitment to the marriage, and affection
for his partner. Three others described the typical woman’s feelings along
the same dimensions. To aid them in constructing their graphs, participants
were given axes in which the x-coordinate pertained to the year of the rela-
tionship and the y-coordinate referred to the attribute being rated along a
scale from 0 (none) to 10 (very much). Partners were told to place an “x”
above the number denoting each year of the relationship to indicate their
perception of the partner’s feelings during that year.
Satisfied partners’ theories about the prognosis of marital relationships
were expected to be more similar to one another than dissatisfied partners’
theories. Data pertaining to this hypothesis are conveyed in Figs. 10.2 and
10.3, which show the composite graphs drawn by satisfied and dissatisfied
partners along each dimension. Analyses of these data revealed an interac-
tion of relationship satisfaction, the partner being rated, and attribute di-
mension, F(2, 60) = 4.29, p < .05 and an higher order interaction involving
these variables, participant sex, and time, F(18, 540) = 1.88, p < .01. These in-
teractions are most clearly interpretable by considering data for satisfied
and dissatisfied couples separately.
As expected, satisfied husbands and wives had generally similar theories
about how a typical marriage partner’s feelings were likely to change. For
example, they agreed that the typical partner’s feelings of romantic love de-
creased to a much greater extent over time than his or her feelings of affec-
tion. Moreover, they agreed that the typical man’s feelings of love would
tend to increase during the later years of the relationship without a corre-
sponding increase in affection, whereas the typical woman’s feelings of af-
fection were likely to increase in later years without a corresponding in-
crease in feelings of romantic love.
In contrast, dissatisfied partners’ perceptions of the typical marriage dif-
fered much more dramatically. These differences were reflected in an inter-
action of respondent sex, the sex of the partner being rated, attribute di-
mension, and time, F(18, 270) = 2.80, p < .01, in an analysis of judgments by
dissatisfied partners alone. Three aspects of these data are noteworthy.
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 297

FIG. 10.2. Satisfied partners’ perceptions of the typical husband’s and typical
wife’s feelings over the first 10 years of a relationship.

1. Dissatisfied husbands and wives both perceived the typical marriage


partner’s feelings of romantic love to decrease substantially over the first 8
years of the relationship. However, whereas dissatisfied wives expected
these feelings to increase in later years, dissatisfied husbands did not.
2. Dissatisfied husbands perceived the typical man’s commitment dur-
ing early years of the relationship to correspond more closely to his feel-
ings of romantic love than to his feelings of affection. In contrast, dissatis-
fied wives perceived the typical man’s feelings of commitment to parallel
his feelings of affection, and to be maintained despite a decrease in his feel-
ings of romantic love.
298 CHAPTER 10

FIG. 10.3. Dissatisfied partners’ perceptions of the typical husband’s and typi-
cal wife’s feelings over the first 10 years of a relationship.

3. Dissatisfied husbands believed that the typical woman’s commitment


to her relationship corresponded more closely to her feelings of romantic
love than to her feelings of affection. In contrast, dissatisfied wives perceived
the typical woman’s commitment to parallel her feelings of affection and to
differ markedly from her feelings of romantic love.

The implications of these findings for an understanding of marital rela-


tionships are necessarily equivocal. It is unclear, for example, whether the
differences in dissatisfied partners’ perceptions are a cause or an effect of
their feelings about their own relationship. Be that as it may, however, the
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 299

results demonstrate the utility of comparing the implicit theories that are
likely to characterize happy and unhappy couples. Differences in these the-
ories may be worth more careful attention in future research.

EFFECTS OF IMPLICIT THEORIES


ON BEHAVIORAL DECISIONS

The preceding sections discuss the impact of people’s implicit theories on


their judgments of self and others. Perhaps the most important influences
of these theories, however, are on behavioral decisions. This influence is
evident in Dweck’s work on learned helplessness, noted earlier. That is,
people who apply an incremental theory of ability are likely to conclude
that they can improve their performance on a task by exerting more effort
and, therefore, they may persist. In contrast, people who invoke an entity
theory may attribute their failure to an inherent lack of ability and conclude
that they are likely to fail again regardless of their effort. Therefore, they
may not bother trying (Dweck, 1975; Dweck & Leggett, 1988).
We have already noted that when two or more implicit theories can po-
tentially be brought to bear on judgments, the theory that is applied may
be determined not only by its chronic accessibility but also by transitory
situational factors that activate concepts and knowledge with which they
are associated. This is true of theories that have implications for behavior
as well. Many situational influences on behavior can be conceptualized in
terms of the mediating effects of situational variables on the activation of
different implicit theories. In this section, we restrict consideration to three
quite different areas in which implicit theories potentially come into play in
behavioral decisions. Although the research reported in each case does not
unequivocally demonstrate the mediating influence of these theories, a con-
sideration of the research from this perspective often raises additional is-
sues that might not otherwise be identified.

Helping Behavior

Several factors that underlie decisions to provide help have already been
noted in our discussion of the just world hypothesis. That is, people are
more likely to provide help if they can construct an image-based episode
model of how their behavior might benefit the recipient than if they cannot
(Miller, 1977). However, other factors also enter into the picture. As noted
by Hong et al. (2000), people may have implicit theories about not only the
dispositional antecedents of their behavior but also situational influences,
and both type of theories could affect their own behavioral decisions as
well as their perceptions of others. These theories can have different impli-
300 CHAPTER 10

cations. For example, if people are asked to help another person, two types
of theories could influence their decision to help. One, person-focused the-
ory might be captured by the molecule:

[P is a kind person; O asks P for assistance; P helps].

A second, recipient-focused theory might have the form:

[O requests assistance; O’s request is (is not) legitimate; P helps (does not
help)].

Note that if people who are asked to help activate the first theory and con-
sider themselves to be kind, they are likely to provide help independently
of other considerations. If they activate the second theory, however, their
decision to help may depend on his or her perception of the request’s
legitimacy.
An imaginative study by Langer and Abelson (1972) can be conceptual-
ized in terms of these considerations. Shoppers were approached outside a
supermarket by a woman who had ostensibly hurt her leg. In some cases,
the woman asked the shopper to call her husband to come and pick her up.
This request was likely to be considered legitimate under the circum-
stances. In other cases, she asked the shopper to call her boss and tell him
she would be late—something that was not sufficiently important to justify
asking a stranger. The second variable manipulated in this study was the
order in which the woman (a) described her adversity and (b) made her re-
quest. Specifically, under request-first conditions, the woman said: “Would
you do something for me? Please do me a favor and call my husband to ask
him to pick me up. My knee is killing me. I think I sprained it.” Under need-
first conditions, however, the woman’s words were: “My knee is killing me. I
think I sprained it. Would you do something for me? Please call my husband
and ask him to pick me up.”
Thus, the descriptive content of the woman’s statements was identical in
the two cases. Under request-first conditions, however, the victim’s initial
statement (“Would you do something or me . . .”) focuses attention on the
recipient and, therefore, is likely to activate a person-focused theory of the
sort described earlier. To this extent, shoppers who typically consider
themselves to be kind are likely to grant the request regardless of other
considerations. In contrast, the woman’s initial statement under need-first
conditions (“My leg is killing me . . .”) focuses attention on the victim and,
therefore, is likely to activate the second theory, in which the legitimacy of
the request comes into play. In this case, therefore, shoppers should com-
ply with the request only when the request appears legitimate. Langer and
Abelson’s findings are consistent with this analysis. That is, the likelihood
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 301

of helping the victim increased with the request’s legitimacy under need-
first conditions but not under request-first conditions.

Effects of Anticipated Outcomes on Decisions

People who are confronted with a decision are likely to base it on an im-
plicit theory about the consequences of the alternative courses of action
available. These theories are often domain specific. People’s theories about
the consequences of betting on a horse race are likely to differ from their
theories about the consequences of studying for a final examination. How-
ever, more general theories can exist as well. As we discussed in chapter 3,
Higgins (1997) postulates two general motivational orientations that can un-
derlie goal-directed information processing. One, promotion focus, is charac-
terized by an emphasis on the rewards that can potentially result from a be-
havioral decision irrespective of the costs that might be incurred. The
other, prevention focus, is characterized by a concern with avoiding nega-
tive consequences of one’s behavior independently of its potential benefits.
These different orientations could be embodied in two implicit theories,
each of which has implications for a different behavioral objective:

[P performs A; A has positive consequences; P attains benefits],

and

[P performs B; B avoids negative outcomes; P avoids misfortune].

In many instances, the behavior that maximizes the likelihood of positive


outcomes also increases the risk of negative ones. (E.g., Investing in stocks
can potentially reap substantial benefits but runs the risk of a substantial
loss as well.) In these instances, the two theories can have different implica-
tions. For example, suppose an individual is confronted with a choice be-
tween (a) a vacation in which one is likely to have new and exciting cultural
experiences but will require living in sleazy hotels and eating poor food, and
(b) a vacation that is much less exotic but where the accommodations are
not elegant but are adequate. A person who uses the promotion-focus mole-
cule to predict the individual’s behavior should infer that the vacationer will
choose the first option. However, a person who activates the prevention mol-
ecule should predict the vacationer to choose the second alternative.
This possibility becomes of particular interest when people apply the
theories to their own behavioral decisions. That is, the decision of an indi-
vidual who is personally confronted with the two vacations just described
might depend on which of the two alternative theories happens to be ap-
plied. Several situational and individual difference factors could influence
302 CHAPTER 10

the relative accessibility of the theories and, therefore, the likelihood they
are applied. One factor, discussed in chapter 3, can be the salience of one’s
group membership. That is, consciousness of belonging to a group appears
to activate feelings of responsibility to others and, therefore, to increase at-
tention to negative consequences of behavior. Thus, it may increase the rel-
ative accessibility of a prevention-focus molecule that, once activated, influ-
ences decisions in both interpersonal and individual choice situations
(Briley & Wyer, 2002). Situational factors that emphasize the importance of
success as opposed to the importance of avoiding failure could have a simi-
lar influence. Finally, chronic individual differences in the accessibility of
the two theories can also exist (Aaker & Lee, 2001; Briley et al., 2000). (This
research is also discussed in chapter 3.)
However, the implicit theories on which decisions are based can pertain
to not only the objective consequences that are likely to occur but also the
emotional reactions that occur in response to these consequences. People
may anticipate feeling happy if their decision has positive consequences
but disappointed if it has negative consequences. In addition, they might
anticipate experiencing regret if they decide against an option that would
have benefited them and might expect to feel relief if they decide to avoid
an option that would have turned out badly if they had taken it. The deci-
sion they make might depend to a greater extent on their implicit theories
about the occurrence of these reactions than by the outcomes that elicit
them (cf. Bell, 1982; Loomes & Sugden, 1986; Mellers, Schwartz, & Ritov,
1999). However, both situational and individual differences undoubtedly oc-
cur in the conditions in which these theories are invoked.
Fong and Wyer (2003) examined these differences in simulated choice
situations similar to those that participants were likely to encounter in daily
life. Both North American and Hong Kong Chinese students participated. In
one study, participants imagined a financial situation in which they could
decide either (a) to make an investment that could potentially yield a con-
siderable profit but also ran the risk of taking a substantial loss, or (b) to
make a bank deposit that would yield a low rate of interest but would avoid
the risk of loss. In a second study, they imagined an academic situation in
which they could decide whether (a) to study a particular topic that would
ensure a high grade on an exam if the topic actually appeared but a low
grade if it did not, or (b) to study other topics, guaranteeing an average
grade regardless of whether or not the special topic was on the exam. In
each experiment, the magnitude of the gain or loss that might occur as a re-
sult of taking the risk, and information about the decisions that others had
typically made, were varied over conditions.
Participants after reading the scenario reported the likelihood that they
would choose the risky option and estimated the risk of doing so. Then,
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 303

they estimated the emotional reactions they would experience if they (a)
took the risk and benefited, (b) took the risk and incurred misfortune, (c)
did not take the risk and avoided misfortune, or (d) did not take the risk
and missed out on an opportunity to benefit. These emotional reactions
were analogous to happiness, disappointment, relief and regret, respectively.
Participants’ decisions in each study were typically influenced by their
perception of the risk involved in doing so, the importance of the conse-
quences, and the decisions that others ostensibly made. However, the ef-
fects of these variables were largely mediated by their influence on partici-
pants anticipated emotional reactions. Regression analyses indicated that
participants’ anticipated reactions accounted for a sizable proportion of
variance in decisions over and above the effects of situational variables,
whereas the latter variables contributed only a small and often nonsig-
nificant proportion of variance in decisions over and above the effects of
anticipated emotional reactions. In other words, participants’ implicit theo-
ries about the emotional reactions they would experience in response to al-
ternative decision outcomes were the primary determinant of their choices.
However, the relative impact of the four anticipated reactions varied
over both scenarios and cultural groups. For example, decisions in the fi-
nancial situation were based primarily on the consequences of taking the
risk (i.e., happiness and disappointment), whereas decisions in the aca-
demic situation were influenced by anticipated relief and regret as well.
Moreover, Americans’ decisions in the latter situation were influenced to
the greatest extent by the happiness they anticipated if they benefited as a
result of taking the risk, and to the least extent by the relief they anticipated
if they avoided a negative outcome by not taking the risk. In contrast, Chi-
nese participants’ decisions were influenced least by the happiness they an-
ticipated as a result of receiving a positive outcome and most by the relief
they anticipated as a result of avoiding a negative one. These results sug-
gest that chronic cultural differences exist in the tendency to invoke theo-
ries that focus on positive versus negative decision outcomes. To this ex-
tent, they confirm conclusions drawn by Briley et al. (2000; see also Aaker &
Lee, 2001).

Effects of Stereotypes on Social Behavior

One of the most heavily researched areas in social psychological research


surrounds the determinants and effects of social stereotypes (for reviews
of theory theoretical analyses, see Bodenhausen & Macrae, 1998; Fiske,
1998; Hamilton & Sherman, 1994). In most of this research, a stereotype has
been conceptualized as a cluster of traits and behavioral dispositions that
are associated with a social or ethnic category (women, African Americans,
304 CHAPTER 10

fraternity members, etc.). Generalized representations of this sort presum-


ably influence persons’ attitudes toward individual members of the cate-
gory and the attributes they assign to these members (Hamilton & Sher-
man, 1994). Moreover, a trait-based stereotype that is activated in one
situation can later influence the interpretation of information about other
individuals to whom the stereotype is objectively inapplicable (Devine,
1989; Lepore & Brown, 1997). Finally, active attempts to suppress the use of
the stereotype can have boomerang effects, actually increasing the use of
the stereotype as a basis for judgment once these conscious suppression
mechanisms are deactivated (Bodenhausen & Macrae, 1998).
An understanding of the impact of trait-based stereotypes on social judg-
ments, and the conditions in which they are applied, is of obvious impor-
tance. As Reid and Wyer (1998) noted, however, there is surprisingly little
evidence that these stereotypes directly influence individuals’ actual be-
havior toward members of the stereotyped group. The classic study by
LaPiere (1934) provides an example of a situation in which individuals’ be-
havioral decisions in a social context do not correspond to the attitudes
and behavioral dispositions they express outside of this context. In fact, it
seems somewhat implausible that people who encounter a member of a ste-
reotype group would expend the cognitive energy required to activate a
trait-based stereotype and construe its implications in anticipation of decid-
ing how to behave toward members of the group. Instead, they are likely to
activate a situation stereotype of the events that are likely to occur in the
situation at hand, and to base their decision on the implications of this
event representation.
A situation stereotype is likely to be activated by a configuration of fea-
tures that exist in the situation rather than by individual attributes. Thus,
its activation can depend on features of persons involved in a situation and
features of the situation in combination, rather than on either set of features
in isolation. For example, suppose a woman sees an African-American man
approaching her late at night on an empty Chicago street. She is unlikely to
activate a trait-based stereotype of African Americans as aggressive or hos-
tile before deciding to cross the street. Rather, she is more likely to activate
a prototypic event representation of the events that occur in this particular
situation (i.e., “People who see a woman walking alone late at night are
likely to mug or rape them, and so it is best to avoid contact with them if
possible.”) This stereotypic event representation may function as an im-
plicit theory that is activated and applied in the particular situation at hand.
If the woman encountered this same individual in a university library she
would be far less likely to engage in avoidance behavior. This is because a
different situation stereotype is activated that has quite different implica-
tions for behavior.
THE IMPACT OF IMPLICATIONAL MOLECULES 305

FINAL COMMENT

The research reviewed in this chapter has cut across a very wide variety of
concerns, ranging from counterfactual reasoning and reconstructive mem-
ory to perceptions of social reality, cultural differences in future outlook,
perceptions of social support, marital satisfaction, and stereotyping. The
role of implicit theories in these phenomena is admittedly somewhat con-
jectural. That is, few studies provide direct evidence of the cognitive basis
of the judgments and decisions that were made. To the extent these theo-
ries exist, however, they are a useful construct in integrating a diversity of
empirical findings within a common conceptual framework.
Much of our discussion was guided by the assumption that many differ-
ent theories can often be brought to bear on a judgment or decision, and
that the theory that is activated and applied is determined by its relative ac-
cessibility. The determinants of knowledge accessibility summarized in
chapter 3 obviously come into play in predicting the conditions in which
these theories are used.
Although the phenomena discussed in this and the preceding chapter do
not pretend to be exhaustive, they are representative of those in which nar-
rative representations are likely to be constructed and used as a basis for
judgments and decisions in daily life. However, an obvious and important
factor that influences judgments and behavior in social situations has been
totally ignored, both in these chapters and elsewhere in this volume. We
now turn to a consideration of this factor.
C H A P T E R

11
The Role of Affect
in Information Processing

Our focus throughout this volume has been on the way we comprehend in-
formation about people, objects, and events of the sort we encounter in
daily life. In our discussion, we have emphasized the role of narrative repre-
sentations of knowledge in conceptualizing new information and in making
judgments of the people and events to which the representations refer. We
have also considered the role of pictures and visual images in the compre-
hension and use of information. In doing so, however, we have virtually ig-
nored an obvious but important factor that pervades information process-
ing outside the laboratory.
Specifically, many situations we encounter in daily life elicit affective re-
actions. These reactions can be stimulated by direct experiences with a
person, object, or event with which they are associated. However, imagin-
ing these stimuli, recalling past experiences in which they occurred, or writ-
ing stories about them can also elicit these reactions. When these affective
reactions are experienced, they can influence judgments and overt behav-
ior toward the stimuli that gave rise to them. Thus, we behave antagonisti-
cally to a person who makes us angry, and attempt to increase our contact
with someone who makes us feel happy.
The cognitive determinants and consequences of affect and emotion have
been a major concern of social psychological research and theorizing for
more than 25 years. The issues investigated have ranged from the influence
of affect on the encoding and organization of new information in memory
(Bower, 1981, 1991) to its impact on the retrieval of previously acquired con-
cepts and knowledge (Blaney, 1986; Niedenthal & Setterlund, 1994), its use as
a basis for judgments and decisions (Clore, 1992; Schwarz & Clore, 1983,
1988), and its influence on the strategies that individuals use when perform-

306
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 307

ing cognitive tasks (Isen, 1987; Mackie & Worth, 1989; Nisbett, Schwarz, &
Bless, 1991). These issues have been investigated in research on not only
judgment and decision making but also creativity (Isen, Daubman, & Nowicki,
1987; Isen, Johnson, Mertz, & Robinson, 1985), communication and persua-
sion (Albarracin & Wyer, 2001; Bless, Bohner, Schwarz, & Strack, 1990; Mackie
& Worth, 1989l; Wegener, Petty, & Smith, 1995); stereotyping (Bodenhausen,
1993; Bodenhausen, Sheppard, & Kramer, 1994), self-evaluations (Levine,
Wyer, & Schwarz, 1994); political judgment (Abelson, Kinder, Peters, & Fiske,
1982; Ottati & Isbell, 1996; Ottati & Wyer, 1993), and consumer behavior
(Adaval, 2001; Pham, 1998; Pham, Cohen, Pracejus, & Hughes, 2001).
Despite the diverse conditions in which affect has been shown to influ-
ence information processing, the cognitive mechanisms through which it
exerts this influence may be more limited than is often assumed. These
mechanisms have been difficult to isolate. However, the research reported
to date converges on two general conclusions:
1. Positive and negative affect can be preconditions for cognitive opera-
tions for cognitive productions of the sort that compose procedural knowl-
edge (J. Anderson, 1983; E. R. Smith, 1990) and that govern behavior in spe-
cific types of situations to which they are relevant. Once activated, these
productions can influence responses to new information without conscious
awareness.
2. The affective reactions that one experiences at a given moment can be
used as information about one’s attitude toward oneself, other people, situa-
tions with which one is confronted, the outcomes of behavior, or the appro-
priateness of certain strategies for attaining behavioral outcomes. It can also
influence perceptions of the validity of other affect-eliciting information and,
therefore, can influence the weight that is attached to this information in
making judgments.

The validity of these conclusions is discussed with reference to research


and theory in several different areas, with particular emphasis on the im-
pact of affect on behavioral decisions. In this context, a performance feed-
back model is proposed that accounts for the influence of affect on behav-
ior and judgment in a number of different situations that occur in both the
laboratory and daily life.

GENERAL CONSIDERATIONS

Definition

Wyer, Clore, and Isbell (1999) conceptualized affect as a configuration of


positively or negatively valenced subjective reactions that a person experi-
ences at a given point in time and perceives as either pleasant or unpleas-
308 CHAPTER 11

ant feelings. These feelings can be elicited by proprioceptive cues (e.g., fa-
cial expressions; see Strack, Martin, & Stepper, 1988; Zajonc, Murray, &
Inglehart, 1989), physical stimulation, or drugs. More commonly, however,
they are internal responses to a set of new or previously formed cognitions.
Several general classes of affective reactions can be distinguished (for a de-
tailed discussion of these distinctions, see Clore, Schwarz, & Conway, 1994;
Ortony, Clore, & Collins, 1988; Wyer et al., 1999).

1. Moods and Emotions

Wyer et al. (1999) assumed that emotions are affective states that occur
in response to cognitions about persons, objects, and events, and that are
consciously attributed to a specified source. In contrast, moods are typi-
cally experienced in the absence of specific cognitions about their source
and are not attributed to any particular cause unless one is called upon to
do so. Thus, the clusters of subjective reactions that exemplify emotions
and moods are similar except that one is consciously attributed to a given
source and the other is not. As Wyer et al. (1999) suggested, feelings that
are elicited by a stimulus event take time to dissipate. Therefore, feelings
that are initially experienced as an emotion can become a mood once their
source is no longer considered.
The preceding remarks suggest an important distinction between emo-
tions and affect per se. That is, emotions, unlike moods or affective reac-
tions more generally, have a strong cognitive component. Forgas (2002), for
example, assumed that emotions are defined in terms of a cognitive ap-
praisal of a situation, and that “physiological and autonomic reactions char-
acteristic of that emotion” are responses to this appraisal (p. 104). Thus,
emotions, unlike other affective states, are necessarily accompanied by
cognitions about the situational factors that give rise to them. To this ex-
tent, there may be concepts in memory whose features include a represen-
tation of one’s affective reactions as well as alternative names of both the
emotion and its behavioral manifestations.
The concept angry, for example, might be metaphorically represented as
shown in Fig. 11.1. The concept itself is denoted by a central node to which
the features that define and characterize it (a cognitive appraisal of the con-
ditions that elicit the emotion, a mental representation of the affective reac-
tions that are experienced, names, behaviors, etc.) are associatively linked.
The concept of a mood might be similar to that shown in the figure except
that a characterization of its eliciting conditions would not be included
among its features. In each case, thinking about one or more of the features
associated with it could presumably activate the mood or emotion concept.
Thus, consciousness of the cluster of physiological reactions that define an
emotion concept might activate it, in much the same way as the features of
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 309

FIG. 11.1. Metaphorical mental representation of the emotion concept “angry.”

any concept can activate this concept. Note, however, that these physiolog-
ical reactions per se do not activate the concept. This activation occurs
only if the physiological reactions are thought about or otherwise cog-
nitively represented.

2. Affect Versus Evaluation

It is important to distinguish between affective reactions to a stimulus


and evaluations of the stimulus along a good–bad dimension (e.g., attitudes;
see Eagly & Chaiken, 1993, 1998). Although one’s feelings about a person or
object can often be the basis of such an evaluation, not all evaluative judg-
ments are based on this criterion (cf. Adaval, 2001; Wyer et al., 1999; Zanna
& Rempel, 1988). The distinction between affect and evaluation is not al-
ways made in theories of affect-based information processing (cf. Abelson
et al., 1982; Bargh, Chaiken, Govender, & Pratto, 1992; Fiske & Pavelchak,
1986). In the present context, however, this distinction is important to keep
in mind. For one thing, evaluations are cognitions and, as such, can be fea-
tures of the mental representations of the entities to which they refer. Affec-
tive reactions, however, may not be.

3. Affect Versus Cognition

As implied by our discussion of moods and emotions, people have con-


cepts of different types of affect, and cognitions about different configura-
tions of subjective reactions can be features of these concepts (see Fig.
11.1). These latter cognitions, however, may not always have verbal labels.
Moreover, it is important to distinguish between cognitions about one’s af-
fective reactions and the affective reactions per se. Although affective reac-
tions may sometimes be learned responses to cognitions, they are not part
310 CHAPTER 11

of the cognitive system. This distinction is made by LeDoux (1994) in con-


ceptualizing the relation of emotion and memory:

It is important to distinguish emotional memory [the learned or conditioned


emotional significance of an object that automatically triggers an emotion]
and memory for emotion. The latter is a declarative, conscious memory of an
emotional experience. It is stored as a fact about an emotional episode. Emo-
tional memory (mediated by the amygdala) and memory for emotion (medi-
ated by the hippocampus) can be reactivated in parallel on later occasions,
thereby giving new declarative memories an emotional flavor. . . . Because
emotional memory and memory for emotion are stored through different
brain systems, it is possible that the information stored will not always coin-
cide. (p. 312)

Thus, experiencing affect is not the same thing as conceptualizing it. In


fact, we often have subjective affective reactions that we do not con-
sciously identify at all. And even if we are aware of the reactions, we might
not attempt to explain their occurrence unless the reactions are intense or
there is some particular reason to do so. Put another way, affective reac-
tions may be responses to cognitions, but are not themselves cognitions.
Because specific clusters of affective reactions are experienced as feel-
ings, a cognitive representation of these feelings can often be a feature of a
more general concept of an emotion or mood state (angry, happy, etc.), as
shown in Fig. 11.1. Once such a concept is activated, it could theoretically
be used by the Parser to interpret a new experience to which it is applica-
ble, depending on whether features of the experience instantiate it. Thus,
an emotion concept could be used to interpret the feelings one is person-
ally experiencing. As suggested by Fig. 11.1, however, the concept could
also be activated by other features, including those of the situational con-
text in which these reactions occur (cf. Schachter & Singer, 1962).
Nevertheless, these considerations do not imply that affective reactions
themselves are part of an associative network of cognitions that compose se-
mantic and episodic knowledge. Affective reactions can be responses to con-
cepts and cognitions that are formed of a new stimulus event, to previously
formed cognitions about a past event, or to thoughts about an imagined (e.g.,
future) event (LeDoux, 1994). Moreover, affective reactions can be the refer-
ent of concepts and cognitions about one’s own internal state, and these
cognitions, once activated, can enter into subsequent information process-
ing. However, the reactions themselves are no more part of the cognitive sys-
tem than the referent of the concept “chair.” This means that if a mental rep-
resentation is not formed of the affective reactions one experiences, the
influence of these reactions on information processing may be quite limited.
These distinctions might seem self-evident. However, they appear to be
ignored in much of the theory and research on the impact of affect on infor-
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 311

mation processing. Several theories of affect and cognition (e.g., Bower,


1981; Forgas, 1995; Isen, Shalker, Clark, & Karp, 1978), as well as introduc-
tory textbooks (e.g., Baron & Byrne, 2000), appear to assume that affect
functions as a concept in an associative network whose role in information
processing is similar to that of other concepts. That is, affect can increase
the accessibility of other concepts and knowledge that are directly or indi-
rectly associated with it (i.e., concepts that are similar to it in valence). As a
consequence, it can influence the interpretation of new information to
which these concepts apply. For similar reasons, affective reactions can
cue the retrieval of previously acquired knowledge representations whose
features are similar in valence. Thus, the impact of affective reactions on in-
formation processing is far reaching.
In contrast, if affective reactions are not themselves part of the cognitive
system, their influence may be more limited. If these reactions are repre-
sented cognitively, they might increase the accessibility of the specific con-
cepts they exemplify. However, they would not necessarily influence the ac-
tivation and use of concepts and knowledge to which they are not directly
related. Moreover, affective reactions should not even have this effect un-
less persons are conscious of the reactions and are stimulated to interpret
them in cognitive terms (see Fig. 11.1).
There are two ways, however, in which affective reactions per se are
likely to play a role. First, affective reactions can be part of the precondition
of an “If [X], then [Y]” production. That is, the precondition [X] could in-
clude not only cognitions but also proprioceptive stimuli that, in combina-
tion, could activate a behavioral sequence that is performed with minimal
conscious awareness.
Second, many judgments or decisions are based on feelings. For exam-
ple, if we experience positive or negative affective reactions when we en-
counter or think about a particular person, we might attribute these reac-
tions to our feelings about this person and must use these feelings as a
basis for estimating how much we like this individual. More generally, sub-
jective reactions can often be used as a source of information about the
person, object, or event that ostensibly elicits them. This assumption,
which is implicit in early research and theory on attitude assessment
(Thurstone, 1959) and interpersonal attraction (Byrne, 1971; Clore & Byrne,
1974), has been stated more formally in a theory of affect as information
proposed by Schwarz and Clore (1983, 1988, 1996; for an early version of the
theory, see Wyer & Carlston, 1979). There are several contingencies on the
use of affect as a basis for judgment that are noted later in this chapter. For
example, affective reactions are only likely influence judgments for which
they are considered on a priori grounds to be relevant. The informational
influence of affective reactions is nonetheless pervasive, having been dem-
onstrated to occur in judging life satisfaction and self-esteem, jokes and car-
312 CHAPTER 11

toons, task performance, consumer products, and political candidates.


These effects are discussed in some detail later in this chapter.

Methodological Considerations

Before discussing the implications of research and theory on the influence of


affect in information processing, a methodological problem is worth noting.
In much of this research, the affective reactions that people experience have
been manipulated experimentally. This is done in several ways. That is, peo-
ple might be asked to write about a past experience that had elicited positive
or negative feelings at the time it occurred and that re-elicits these feelings
when thinking about it (Schwarz & Clore, 1983), to watch a movie that elicits
positive or negative emotions (Martin, Achee, Ward, & Wyer, 1993), or to read
aloud statements that reflect strong emotions (e.g., “This is the greatest day
of my life!”, “I wish I could go to bed and never get up,” etc.; see Velten, 1968).
Alternatively, participants might be given positive or negative feedback
about their performance on a test (Forgas & Bower, 1987).
These procedures are typically successful in inducing the affective reac-
tions they are intended to stimulate. As the aforementioned examples indi-
cate, however, the procedures activate semantic concepts and knowledge
that could also have an influence on judgments and behavior. Conse-
quently, the interpretation of research that employs these procedures is of-
ten equivocal. This contention is elaborated in the following discussion.

AFFECT AND CONCEPT ACCESSIBILITY

The influence of affective reactions (or, more accurately, a mental represen-


tation of these reactions) on the accessibility of concepts and knowledge in
memory is presumably governed by the processes described in chapters 2
and 3. In particular, the representation of a particular configuration of reac-
tions should only activate concepts and thoughts that the configuration ex-
emplifies. There is no reason to suppose that the reactions will influence
the accessibility of concepts and knowledge to which they are not directly
related. Two quite different bodies of research bear on this matter, each of
which is discussed in turn.

Effects of Priming Affect on Semantic


Concept Accessibility

Research by Niedenthal and her colleagues (Niedenthal, Halberstadt, &


Setterlund, 1997; Niedenthal & Setterlund, 1994) is consistent with this con-
clusion. In these studies, participants were induced to feel either happy or
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 313

sad by having them listen to upbeat or gloomy music for 12 to 15 minutes.


Pretesting established that the music elicited specific feelings of happiness
and sadness rather than positive or negative affect more generally. In the
main experiments, however, participants were led to believe that the music
was being played to study the relation between auditory and visual percep-
tion, and were given no indication of the type of affect that the music was
intended to induce. Thus, the procedure avoided the interpretative ambigu-
ities described in the preceding section.
If participants who hear the music are aware of the feelings it elicits, they
may form a mental representation of these feelings, and this representation
could increase the accessibility of the specific mood or emotion concept
the feelings exemplify. However, it should not influence the accessibility of
concepts pertaining to other types of feelings, or to positively or negatively
valenced concepts more generally. Results confirmed these predictions. Af-
ter listening to the music, participants performed a word recognition task in
which a number of positively and negatively valenced words were pre-
sented. However, some of these words (e.g., “delight,” “joy,” “weep,” “de-
spair,” etc.) pertained to happiness and sadness whereas others (e.g., wis-
dom, luck, crime, injury, etc.) did not. Participants quickly identified words
that described the particular type of affective reactions they were experi-
encing. However, the time they took to identify words that described other
types of positive or negative affect (Niedenthal et al., 1997), or to identify
positively or negatively valenced words that were not directly related to af-
fective reactions (Niedenthal & Setterlund, 1994), was unaffected by their
reactions.
In short, Niedenthal’s research suggested that if people experience affec-
tive reactions that exemplify a particular mood or emotion concept of the
sort described in Fig. 11.1, these reactions can increase the accessibility of
other features of this concept (e.g., the name of the mood or emotion, or of
behaviors that exemplify it). However, these reactions do not increase the
accessibility of other concepts and knowledge to which the emotion con-
cept is descriptively unrelated.
In fact, even the effects that Niedenthal et al. observed could be of lim-
ited generality. In these studies, both participants’ affective reactions and
the words they were given to identify in the lexical decision task may have
combined to activate the mood or emotion concept they exemplified. In Fig.
11.1, for example, both the representation of the physiological reactions
that define the concept “angry” and the name of this concept may resonate
with the concept, and the resonance from these two sources in combina-
tion may activate it. In the absence of the activation produced by the con-
cept’s name, however, it is conceivable that participants’ representation of
their affective reactions might not produce sufficient resonance to activate
the concept. As we noted earlier, people may often experience feelings
314 CHAPTER 11

without necessarily labeling or interpreting them. This labeling may only


occur spontaneously when the feelings are sufficiently intense that people
are motivated to understand and explain them.

Automatic Evaluation Effects

Niedenthal et al.’s findings are consistent with the conceptualization we


propose. At the same time, they conflict with conclusions drawn by Forgas
(1995, 2002). Forgas proposed that priming a particular affect-related con-
cept should increase the accessibility of other concepts with which simi-
larly valenced affective reactions are associated. Research on the “auto-
matic evaluation effect” (cf. Bargh, Chaiken, Govender, & Pratto, 1992;
Bargh, Chaiken, Raymond, & Hymes, 1996; Fazio, Sanbonmatsu, Powell, &
Kardes, 1986) might appear consistent with this possibility. In this research,
participants are typically exposed to a positively or negatively valenced
word (e. g., lovely, putrid, etc.) at below recognition threshold. Immediately
afterwards, participants in some studies are asked to categorize a second
word as either favorable or unfavorable (Bargh et al., 1992). Participants in
other studies are simply asked to pronounce the second word, without be-
ing given any indication that its valence was of concern (Bargh et al., 1996).
In each case, participants typically respond more quickly to the second
word when its evaluative implications are similar to those of the word that
preceded it than when its evaluative implications are dissimilar (Bargh et
al., 1992, 1996). These findings could be interpreted as evidence that the
first word elicits an affective reaction and that this reaction cues the re-
trieval of other words that are associated with similar reactions. Thus, par-
ticipants identify the second word more quickly or more slowly, depending
on whether the affective reactions the word elicits are similar to or different
from the reactions elicited by the word that preceded it.
As noted earlier, however, a distinction should be made between the af-
fective reactions that a stimulus elicits and its evaluative implications. If af-
fective reactions were involved in the processes identified by Bargh and his
colleagues, observed effects should increase in magnitude with the extrem-
ity of the evaluative implications of the words involved and, therefore, the
intensity of the affect they elicit. In fact, this is true under very limited con-
ditions (Bargh et al., 1992; Chaiken & Bargh, 1993). Moreover, responses to
valenced semantic concepts are influenced by exposure to normatively
positive and negative stimuli that participants have never before seen
(Duckworth, Bargh, Garcia, & Chaiken, 2002). This finding indicates that the
effects do not reflect a previously learned association between the con-
cepts and the affect they elicit.
Wyer, Clore, and Isbell (1999) argued that the effects obtained by Bargh
et al. are likely to reflect a categorization process that people spontaneously
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 315

perform at the time they encounter stimuli that is not affect eliciting in and
of itself. That is, people may spontaneously categorize stimuli as either
good or bad. (This automatic categorization process could reflect an un-
learned, evolution-based disposition to identify stimuli as potentially harm-
ful or not harmful in order to survive.) However, affective reactions might
not provide the basis for this categorization. In fact, these reactions might
only be elicited by a cognitive appraisal of the stimulus and its implications
that occurs after the stimulus has been categorized. If this is so, the effects
observed by Bargh et al. (1992; see also Fazio et al., 1986) would not conflict
with the implications of Niedenthal et al.’s (1997) findings.
This conclusion can be summarized in the following postulate:

Postulate 11.1. Affective reactions may activate a specific affect-relevant con-


cept that can be used to interpret them. However, affective reactions do not
spontaneously influence the accessibility in memory of other similarly
valenced semantic concepts and declarative knowledge.

This postulate, however, runs counter to claims that affective reactions do


have an influence on the recall and interpretation of information that is
evaluatively congruent with it (Bower, 1981; Forgas, 1995). In the following
section, we review research that is often cited in support of these claims.
Although the review is not exhaustive, it is sufficiently representative to
convey the ambiguities that generally exist in the literature bearing on this
matter.

THE INFLUENCE OF AFFECT ON THE RECALL


AND INTERPRETATION OF INFORMATION

The Recall of Previously Acquired Knowledge

If affective reactions are features of a mental representation that people


have formed and stored in memory, the experience of similar reactions at
some later time should cue the retrieval of this representation. This effect
should occur for the same reasons that linguistically and perceptually
coded stimuli cue the retrieval of previously formed cognitions (see chap.
2). If affective reactions are not represented in memory, however, the expe-
rience of these reactions per se would not have this effect. Rather, these re-
actions should influence the recall of information only if the experience of
these reactions is accompanied by perceptually or linguistically coded fea-
tures similar to those of the knowledge representations to be retrieved.
Thus, for example, a person who experiences a certain cluster of affective
reactions might be stimulated to interpret this configuration in terms of an
affect-related semantic concept such as “sad,” or “down in the dumps.” This
316 CHAPTER 11

concept, once activated, could cue the retrieval of a past experience to


which the concept had been applied. In the absence of this mediating cogni-
tive activity, however, the experience is unlikely to be recalled.
This conclusion is not widely accepted. In fact, the assumption that af-
fect does indeed cue the retrieval of valenced concepts and knowledge
from memory is quite pervasive (cf. Bower, 1981; Forgas, 1992, 1995, 2002;
Isen, 1984). However, empirical support for this assumption is very limited
(Blaney, 1986). In a study by Bower, Gilligan, and Monteiro (1981), partici-
pants in some conditions read a story that described both positively
valenced and negatively valenced events that occurred to the protagonists.
Then, they were induced to feel either happy or sad by describing a life
event that had elicited these emotions. If affective reactions per se cue the
retrieval of previously acquired knowledge that is similar in valence, partic-
ipants should recall aspects of the story that are evaluatively congruent
with their feelings at the time of recall. In fact, however, the affect they were
experiencing had no influence on the type of information they recalled.
Mueller, Grove, and Thompson (1991) induced participants to feel either
happy or sad after exposing them to a list of positively and negatively
valenced words. This study also found no evidence that the affect that par-
ticipants were experiencing influenced the valence of the information they
recalled.
In contrast, participants in a study by Bower (1981) were asked to recall
childhood experiences after having been induced hypnotically to feel
happy or sad. Participants recalled experiences that were evaluatively con-
gruent with their mood. At the time of mood induction, however, partici-
pants were explicitly told what feelings they should try to experience.
These instructions presumably activated semantic concepts of the feelings
being induced, and these concepts, rather than the affective reactions to
which they referred, could have cued the recall of experiences whose fea-
tures had been encoded in terms of them.
Our interpretation of these findings gains plausibility in light of a series
of experiments by Parrott and Sabini (1990). In one study, participants lis-
tened to either upbeat or depressing music with explicit instructions to use
the music to get into a happy or sad mood, respectively. They were then
asked to recall an experience they had in high school. In these conditions,
they were more likely to recall a pleasant high school experience when
they were happy than when they were sad, consistent with Bower’s (1981)
earlier findings. In a second study, however, participants were told that the
music was being played to investigate aesthetic preferences, and no men-
tion was made of the feelings it would elicit. In this case, however, the effect
of participants’ feelings on recall was not only eliminated but reversed; that
is, the first event that participants recalled was less pleasant when the mu-
sic had made them feel happy than when it had not. Moreover, this effect
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 317

was replicated in nonlaboratory settings in which participants’ feelings


were induced by naturally occurring events. For example, participants re-
called less pleasant high school experiences on sunny days than on rainy
ones, and less pleasant experiences after learning they had done well on an
examination than after learning they had done poorly.
Parrott and Sabini’s (1990) results should be evaluated in the context of
Niedenthal et al.’s (1997) finding that listening to music increased the acces-
sibility of mood-related words in a lexical-decision task even when explicit
references to the mood or emotion being induced by the music were not
made. As noted earlier, words that denote an emotion concept may activate
this concept more quickly when the feelings that define the concept are
also being experienced. In the absence of semantic labels, however, the
feelings may not be sufficiently intense to activate the concept, as Parrot
and Sabini’s (1990) findings indicate.
This does not explain why the influence of induced affect on recall was
actually reversed under conditions in which the affect was not labeled. The
reason for this reversal can only be speculated. Unhappy individuals’ recall
of positive events could result in part from a desire to distract themselves
from their negative mood state by thinking about something that makes
them happy (Parrott & Sabini, 1990; Rusting & DeHart, 2000). However, this
would not explain the relatively better recall of negative events by persons
who feel happy. Wyer and Srull (1989) suggested that when people are
asked to recall an experience they have had at an earlier point in time (e.g.,
high school), they spontaneously activate a global concept of this period in
their lives. This concept might spontaneously elicit affective reactions that
differ from those they happen to be experiencing for other reasons, and
this discrepancy may stimulate thoughts about the implications of this dif-
ference. In the conditions considered by Parrott and Sabini (1990), for ex-
ample, the affect elicited by the “high school” might on average be less pos-
itive than the feelings that happy persons were typically experiencing at
the time and, therefore, might spontaneously stimulate thoughts such as “I
felt less happy in high school than I do now.” This thought, in turn, could
cue the retrieval of a negative experience that confirms it. Similarly, “high
school” might stimulate unhappy individuals to think, “I felt happier in high
school than I do now,” and this cognition may cue the retrieval of a positive
experience.
Be that as it may, however, Parrott and Sabini’s (1990) results clearly in-
dicated that affective reactions per se do not increase the recall of evalu-
atively congruent knowledge representations. This influence occurs only
when the reactions are accompanied by affect-related semantic concepts
that serve as retrieval cues for descriptive knowledge representations that
contain them. In the laboratory, these concepts are often activated by the
procedures that are used to induce different affective reactions. However,
318 CHAPTER 11

affect-related semantic concepts could also be activated spontaneously if


the affect is intense and persons are stimulated to think about why they are
experiencing it. In this regard, Bower and Mayer (1985) suggested that the
affect induced in the laboratory is often not sufficiently intense to stimulate
affect-congruent retrieval. Thus, the effects are often not detected (cf.
Mueller et al., 1991). This speculation is consistent with our own contention
that affective reactions are often not represented in memory, and that even
if a representation is formed of these reactions, it might not be encoded in
terms of a mood or emotion concept. This encoding might only be made if
the feelings are intense or, alternatively, other features of the emotion con-
cept are present as well.

Selective Attention and Encoding

If affect increases the accessibility in memory of semantic concepts and


knowledge representations that are similar to it in valence (cf. Bower, 1981;
Forgas, 1995, 2002), it should also increase the likelihood of comprehending
and thinking about information that can be interpreted in terms of these
concepts. This increased attention might be reflected in (a) longer time
spent reading and thinking about the information, (b) better memory for
the information, and (c) greater influence of the information on judgments
to which it is relevant (Forgas, 2001). Evidence bearing on each of these fac-
tors is discussed in turn.

1. Effects on Processing Time


In a study by Forgas and Bower (1987), participants were induced to feel
either happy or unhappy by giving them positive or negative feedback
about their performance on a measure of social adjustment. Then, they
were told to form an impression of someone on the basis of both favorable
and unfavorable behaviors pertaining to competence, intelligence, likeable-
ness, and happiness. Participants spent more time reading and thinking
about behaviors if the behaviors were evaluatively congruent with their
feelings than if they were incongruent. Although data for behaviors pertain-
ing to each attribute separately were not reported, the effects apparently
generalized to behaviors that had nothing to do with affect per se but were
only evaluatively consistent with participants’ affective state (e.g., behav-
iors concerning competence, intelligence, etc.).
If Postulate 11.1 and the implications of Niedenthal et al.’s (1997) re-
search are valid, Forgas and Bower’s findings must be due to factors other
than the affect that participants were experiencing per se. In retrospect,
these factors seem fairly obvious. That is, feedback about one’s social ad-
justment is likely to activate concepts about attributes that reflect this ad-
justment. As noted earlier, many of the behaviors that participants encoun-
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 319

tered in the later impression formation task were descriptively related to


such attributes (likeableness, competence, etc.). It seems likely that these
concepts increased participants’ attention to behaviors that exemplified
them independently of the affect they were experiencing. To this extent,
this increased attention could also facilitate the later recall of the behav-
iors. Forgas and Bower’s findings support this prediction as well.

2. Effects on Selective Encoding


The best-known demonstration of the role of affect in the selective en-
coding of information was performed by Bower et al. (1981) in a study men-
tioned earlier. In other conditions of this study, participants were induced
under hypnosis to feel happy or sad by recalling a past experience, and
were given a posthypnotic suggestion to retain these feelings while they
read a story. (Thus, unlike the conditions described earlier, participants
were induced to feel happy or sad before reading the story rather than af-
terwards.) The story concerned one or two characters who experienced a
series of both positive and negative life events. Participants had better re-
call of events that were evaluatively congruent with their feelings than
events that were incongruent.
The authors did not distinguish between events that were descriptively
related to the affect participants were experiencing and events that were
only similar in valence. Consequently, the consistency of their results with
Postulate 11.1 cannot be directly evaluated. One aspect of their methodol-
ogy is noteworthy, however. To induce affect, participants were explicitly
told to experience the particular feeling state to which they were assigned
(i.e., to be happy or sad) and to continue to do so once they were no longer
hypnotized. Therefore, semantic concepts of these feeling states were
clearly activated by the instructions. Semantic concepts that are activated
during hypnosis remain accessible in memory despite instructions to “for-
get” the experiences that led to their activation (Kihlstrom, 1980). It is there-
fore likely that the semantic concepts associated with participants’ feelings,
rather than the feelings themselves, produced the selective encoding effect
that Bower et al. observed.
Even when the induction of affect explicitly requires the activation and
use of affect-related semantic concepts, it does not always influence the se-
lective encoding of information. In a series of six experiments, Mueller et
al.(1991) induced participants to feel happy or sad by having them utter
statements that express these feelings (Velton, 1968). Then, they asked the
participants to learn positively and negatively valenced words and, finally
to recall the words. The statements that were used to induce different feel-
ing states undoubtedly activated semantic concepts pertaining to these
states. Nevertheless, the manipulation had weak and inconsistent effects on
participants’ later recall of the words they were asked to learn.
320 CHAPTER 11

The Interpretation of Ambiguous Information

As Postulate 2.4 implies and research summarized in chapter 3 indicates,


concepts that have recently been activated in memory as a result of using
them in one context can influence the interpretation of information pre-
sented in a later, ostensibly unrelated context. Therefore, if the affect that
people experience spontaneously activates semantic concepts with similar
evaluative implications, it should influence people’s interpretation of infor-
mation through its mediating impact on the accessibility of these concepts.
According to Postulate 11.1, however, affective reactions only influence the
accessibility of the particular mood or emotion that the reactions exem-
plify. To this extent, the effects of inducing these reactions should be quite
restricted if they occur at all.
To examine these possibilities, Forgas, Bower, and Krantz (1984) induced
participants under hypnosis to feel either happy or sad by having them re-
call a past experience that elicited these feelings. Then, participants ob-
served a previously videotaped interaction between themselves and an-
other person with instructions to identify behaviors that exemplified either
social skill or the lack of it. Happy participants interpreted more behaviors
as socially skilled, and fewer behaviors as unskilled, than unhappy partici-
pants did. However, the affect-induction task explicitly referred to the feel-
ings that participants were to experience, creating interpretative ambigu-
ities similar to those surrounding the study by Bower et al. (1981) noted
earlier. Moreover, many of the experiences that participants recalled were
likely to have concerned interpersonal relations, and consequently to acti-
vate concepts that had implications for social skills. These concepts could
also have influenced participants’ interpretation of the behaviors they ob-
served.
A study by Innes-Ker and Niedenthal (2002) avoided this ambiguity. Sup-
pose affective reactions influence the interpretation of information through
their mediating effect on the accessibility of concepts to which the informa-
tion is relevant. Then, similar effects should result from activating these
concepts directly without inducing affective reactions. To examine this pos-
sibility, some participants were induced to feel either happy or sad as a
result of listening to music. Others, however, were required to use emotion-
relevant semantic concepts in the course of performing a sentence-con-
struction task similar to that used to prime trait concepts in other studies
(e.g., Srull & Wyer, 1979, 1980). Then, as part of an ostensibly unrelated ex-
periment, participants read about a person whose behaviors could be inter-
preted as conveying either happiness or sadness; specifically:

The sound of rain on the street was relentless. She thought that maybe it was
a day to stay inside and read a novel, or chat on the phone with friends. . . .
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 321

The cat still had not come back from his night on the prowl, and M wondered
where he was. Then the phone rang. . . . It was an old friend . . . who had re-
cently left town. He was calling to say that things were going fine and that he
liked his new job. . . . He would not be back in town over Thanksgiving but
would probably be back over Christmas break. he said he had a great gift for
her in mind.

As expected, participants who personally experienced an emotion judged


the protagonist’s feelings as consistent with this emotion. However, when
participants were exposed to emotion-related semantic concepts without
actually experiencing the emotions themselves, these concepts had no in-
fluence on their judgments of the protagonist’s feelings.
Taken at face value, these results are quite provocative. That is, they
seem to suggest that the feelings people personally experience influence
the interpretation of other persons’ emotional experiences, whereas the se-
mantic concepts that are activated by these feelings do not. This conclu-
sion would directly contradict Postulate 11.1. However, the interpretation of
Innes-Ker and Niedenthal’s findings is not unequivocal. For one thing, the
failure for primed semantic concepts to influence the interpretation of the
information must be reconciled with the abundant evidence in other re-
search that concepts activated through similar procedures do influence the
interpretation of information (see Higgins, 1996, and chap. 3 of this volume).
Note that primed semantic concepts normally influence the interpretation
of information only if these concepts are descriptively applicable (Higgins,
Rholes, & Jones, 1977; but see Stapel & Koomen, 2000, for an exception). In
Innes-Ker and Niedenthal’s study, this condition might not have been met.
For example, the emotion words employed in the priming stimuli were “ec-
static,” “pleasure,” “exuberance,” and “peaceful” on one hand, and “lonely,”
“dejected,” “melancholy, “sorrow,” and “despondent” on the other. Al-
though the concepts defined by these adjectives are not incompatible with
the thoughts and behaviors of the protagonist in the story participants
read, they are not so clearly applicable that readers are likely to use them
spontaneously, even if these concepts are accessible in memory. This could
account for the failure of the semantic task to have an impact.
If this interpretation is correct, however, why did the feelings that partic-
ipants personally experienced have an impact on their interpretations? It is
conceivable that participants’ judgments were not mediated by their inter-
pretation of the target information at all. Rather, their judgments may have
been based directly on the feelings they were experiencing independently
of the information in the story. That is, participants may have projected the
feelings they were experiencing onto the target independently of the story
content. This “informational” influence of affect is elaborated in the next
section of this chapter.
322 CHAPTER 11

THE USE OF AFFECT AS INFORMATION

Preliminary Considerations

The research summarized in the previous sections calls into question the
assumption that affective reactions per se exert an influence on judgments
and behavior through its mediating influence on the accessibility of previ-
ously acquired concepts and knowledge in memory. These effects are re-
stricted to concepts that are descriptively applicable to the specific emo-
tion or mood that participants are experiencing, and do not extend to
positively or negatively valenced concepts and knowledge in general. To
this extent, the impact of affective reactions on judgments and decisions
may occur for other reasons.
Perhaps the most widely accepted influence of affective reactions is in
one sense the most obvious. Many evaluations of a person, object, or event
are based largely on our feelings about this referent. Thurstone’s (1959) at-
titude scaling procedures were an attempt to assess individuals’ affective
reactions to stimuli independently of their specific beliefs about its attri-
butes. The assumption that attitudes toward an object reflect one’s affec-
tive reactions toward it also underlies Fishbein’s (1967) theory of attitude
formation. More generally, our liking for something is often an expression
of the feelings we experience when encountering it.
In this regard, Schwarz and Clore (1988) postulated that people’s evalu-
ations of a stimulus are often based on a “how-do-I-feel-about-it?” heuris-
tic. They suggest that affect is used as a basis for judgment in order to
simplify an otherwise difficult task (see also Forgas, 1995). As Wyer et al.
(1999) pointed out, however, affect can often be the primary basis for an
evaluation rather than only being used when other relevant information is
unavailable.
People’s affective reactions can be used as information about a wide va-
riety of things and, as such, can have a broad impact on information proc-
essing. For example:

1. Affect can be used as a basis for evaluating a particular person, object,


or event.
2. Affect can provide the basis for an initial impression of an object that
guides the attitude toward and processing of other available informa-
tion about the object.
3. Affective reactions can often influence one’s perceptions of whether
one is successful in attaining a goal one is seeking and, therefore, can
influence the likelihood of persisting in goal-directed activity.

The remainder of this chapter discusses these possibilities in detail.


THE ROLE OF AFFECT 323

An Initial Test

An initial demonstration of the use of affect as information was performed


by Schwarz and Clore (1983, Experiment 1). This study not only established
a methodology for identifying the impact of affective reactions on judg-
ments, but also identified conditions in which the reactions were likely to
be employed.
Schwarz and Clore (1983) recognized that the affect people experience at
any given time can come from different sources. However, people often can-
not distinguish easily between the affect elicited by one source and the af-
fect elicited by another. Consequently, if they base their judgments of a
stimulus on their affective reactions to it, they are likely to confuse these re-
actions with affect they are experiencing for other, irrelevant reasons, and
so the latter affect can have an influence on these judgments. On the other
hand, suppose people do not base their judgment on affect. Then, extrane-
ous affect should have no impact in any condition.
To examine these possibilities, Schwarz and Clore asked participants to
write about a happy or sad past experience while they were seated in a
strange-looking soundproof booth. Some participants were told that people
often found that the booth made them feel mildly elated after they had been
in it for a while. Others were told that the booth made people feel mildly de-
pressed, and others were given no information about the booth’s effects.
Participants after writing their essays were then asked to judge their satis-
faction with their life as a whole. These judgments are summarized in Table
11.1 as a function of the type of experience participants wrote about and
the ostensible effects of the booth.
Participants who were given no information about the booth’s effects re-
ported greater life satisfaction when they had written about a happy experi-
ence than when they had written about an unhappy experience. Considered
in isolation, this difference might be attributed to the content of the story
that participants wrote rather than the affect they were experiencing. If this
were the case, however, the alleged effects of the booth on their feelings
should have had no impact on their judgments. In fact, with participants who

TABLE 11.1
Judgments of Life Satisfaction as a Function of the Affective Quality of a
Recalled Personal Experience and Ostensible Characteristics of the Booth

Ostensible Effect of Booth

Depressing No Effect Elating

Happy recalled experience 9.6 8.6 9.7


Sad recalled experience 8.6 5.7 4.4

Note. Adapted from Schwarz and Clore (1983).


324 CHAPTER 11

had written about a sad experience, telling them that the booth would make
them feel sad eliminated the negative impact of the story on their judgments
of life satisfaction, whereas telling them that the booth would make them
happy increased these judgments relative to no-information conditions. In
other words, participants who were told that the booth made them unhappy
attributed their feelings to the booth and did not use it as a basis for judg-
ment. In contrast, participants who experienced unhappiness despite being
told that the booth would make them happy believed that they must be par-
ticularly unhappy about their life as a whole and, therefore, judged them-
selves to be even less satisfied than they would otherwise.
It is interesting to note that the effects of the booth were not apparent
when participants had written about a positive life experience and, therefore,
were feeling happy. These participants appeared to base their judgments of
life satisfaction on their feelings regardless of the information they were
given about the booth. The asymmetric effects observed in the two affect-
induction condition could be due to factors similar to those underlying Arkin
et al.’s (1976) research described in chapter 9. That is, participants whose af-
fect had favorable implications for themselves were inclined to accept these
implications and use them as a basis for judgment without seeking alterna-
tive explanations for their feelings. In contrast, people whose affect had un-
desirable implications resisted using it as a basis for judging themselves un-
less no alternative explanation for their feelings was available.

The Role of Narratives in Affect Elicitation

Affective reactions can be elicited in many ways, as noted earlier. Affect


that is induced by proprioceptive feedback (cf. Strack, Martin, & Stepper,
1988; Zajonc, Murray, & Inglehart, 1989) can also influence judgments to
which it is relevant (e.g., the amusement elicited by cartoons). The role of
narratives in affect elicitation was confirmed in a series of studies by Strack,
Schwarz, and Gschneidinger (1985). They found that when people listed
past experiences in abstract terms that were unlikely to elicit affect, they
used these experiences as standards of comparison in judging their current
life satisfaction, reporting themselves to be less satisfied when the past ex-
periences were favorable than when they were unfavorable. When partici-
pants wrote detailed narratives of their past experiences, however, this ac-
tivity elicited affect, and this affect had a positive influence on satisfaction
judgments.
In a particularly provocative study (Strack et al., 1985, Experiment 3),
participants were either asked to explain why a particular experience oc-
curred or to describe how it occurred. Writing explanations for happy and
sad events did not elicit affect, and the favorableness of the experiences
that participants explained had contrast effects on the life satisfaction they
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 325

reported later. However, writing descriptions of how the experience oc-


curred did elicit affect and consequently had effects on judgments similar
to those reported by Schwarz and Clore (1983).

AFFECTIVE VERSUS DESCRIPTIVE BASES


FOR JUDGMENT

As noted, not all evaluations that people make are based on affective reac-
tions (Zanna & Rempel, 1988). Many judgments are based on purely descrip-
tive considerations. Thus, although we might like a pair of jeans because
they feel good when wearing them, we might like a computer because it is
fast and has a lot of storage. Similarly, we might evaluate a dinner partner
favorably because her physical attractiveness and effervescent personality
elicit positive affect, we might evaluate a research assistant favorably be-
cause she gets work done on time and records data accurately. Other judg-
ments can be based on either affective or descriptive criteria, depending on
which happen to be more accessible (Postulate 3.1). This latter contingency
has been identified in research in quite different areas, concerning judg-
ments of personal competence in one case and evaluations of commercial
products in the other.

Judgments of Personal Competence


and Global Self-Esteem

General characteristics such as life satisfaction or global self-esteem are


typically not based on a single event, but rather, on more global feelings
that reflected the accumulated influence of many experiences. Conse-
quently, affective reactions may be a primary basis for judging these char-
acteristics. In many cases, however, descriptive criteria are potentially ap-
plicable as well. In such instances, whether descriptive or affective criteria
are used can depend on the relative accessibility of these criteria in mem-
ory. If the content of a narrative has direct implications for a judgment and
if these implications are accessible in memory, the effects of these implica-
tions can override the influence of affect.
Levine, Wyer, and Schwarz (1994) provided an example. Participants
wrote about a happy or an unhappy past experience they had had in either
an achievement situation or a social situation. After doing so, they esti-
mated their competence in both types of situations and their social compe-
tence as well as their global self-esteem. We reasoned that judgments of
competence in the domain to which their story directly pertained would be
based on the descriptive implications of the story, as these implications
were highly accessible in memory. However, their competence in the do-
326 CHAPTER 11

main to which their narrative was descriptively irrelevant should be based


on the affect they were experiencing.
This hypothesis is difficult to evaluate when descriptive and affective cri-
teria for judgment have similar implications. However, a content analysis of
participants’ narratives showed that although participants typically took re-
sponsibility for both positive and negative achievement experiences they
wrote about, they attributed responsibility for both good and bad social
experiences to situational factors (e.g., the other persons involved in the
situation). Based on these differences, we predicted that participants’ judg-
ments of their achievement competence would be influenced by the favor-
ableness of the achievement experience they wrote about, but that their
judgments of social competence would not be influenced by the type of so-
cial experience they described. On the other hand, participants’ judgments
of both achievement competence and social competence should be influ-
enced by the affect that was generated by writing about an experience in a
domain to which the competence being judged was unrelated.
Results shown in Table 11.2 confirm these predictions. That is, partici-
pants’ judgments of their achievement competence were influenced by the
favorableness of the achievement experience they had written about,
whereas their judgments of their social competence was not influenced by
the favorableness of the interpersonal situation they had described. On the
other hand, participants’ judgments of both achievement competence and
social competence were influenced by writing about an affect-eliciting expe-
rience in the domain to which the competence they were judging was irrele-
vant. (Thus, somewhat ironically, judgments of social competence were
more influenced by writing about an objectively irrelevant affect-eliciting
experience than about a relevant one.) Finally, participants’ overall judg-
ments of their self-esteem were influenced by the favorableness of the de-
scription they had written about regardless of the domain, suggesting that
these global judgments were based on affect in all cases.

TABLE 11.2
Judgments of Competence as a Function of the Domain
and Affective Quality of Participants’ Recalled Experiences

Judgment of Judgment of
Achievement Competence Social Competence

Recalled experience in same domain


Happy experience 4.77 4.38
Unhappy experience 4.37 4.38
Recalled experience in different domain
Happy experience 4.87 4.46
Unhappy experience 4.67 3.46

Note. Adapted from Levine, Wyer, and Schwarz (1994).


THE ROLE OF AFFECT 327

Consumer Judgment

Judgments of competence can often be based on either descriptive or affec-


tive criteria, and so participants are likely to use whichever criterion comes
to mind most easily at the time judgments are made. This may also be true
in the consumer domain. Evaluations of commercial products, for example,
are often based on utilitarian considerations as well as hedonic or affective
criteria. A refrigerator, for example, is likely to be evaluated on the basis of
its ability to perform the functions for which it is designed. On the other
hand, a cashmere sweater, or strawberry shortcake, could be judged on the
basis of either affective criteria (how it feels or tastes) or utilitarian consid-
erations (durability, healthfulness, etc.). In the latter case, people are most
likely to base their evaluations on affect if (a) the stimulus is one that is typ-
ically judged on the basis of affective (hedonic) criteria, (b) the information
about the stimulus is conveyed in a way that spontaneously elicits positive
or negative feelings, or (c) people’s objectives at the time of judgment re-
quire the use of affective criteria.
The latter contingency was demonstrated by Pham (1998). Participants
who had been induced to feel happy or unhappy by recalling a past experi-
ence were asked to read a description of a new movie and indicate if they
would like to attend a preview of it. Before reading the description, some
participants were given instructions that emphasized hedonic criteria for a
decision (e.g., having a good time, enjoying life, etc.), whereas others were
given a utilitarian reason for seeing it (its relevance to participating in a
subsequent study for pay). Participants in the first condition expressed
stronger intentions to see the movie if they were feeling happy than if they
were not, suggesting that they used the affect they were experiencing as a
basis for their judgment. In contrast, participants’ intentions in the second
condition were unaffected by the affect they were experiencing.
The use of hedonic or utilitarian criteria can also depend on their rela-
tive accessibility at the time of judgment. However, unless situational fac-
tors make descriptive criteria particularly relevant (as in Levine et al.’s 1994
study), these criteria may be relatively inaccessible. In contrast, the affec-
tive reactions can be activated very quickly, before a detailed cognitive
analysis of the utilitarian features of the description is performed. (For a
more general argument that affective responses to a stimulus as a whole oc-
cur more quickly than responses to its individual features, see Zajonc,
1980.) One implication of this is that if a stimulus can potentially be evalu-
ated on the basis of both hedonic and utilitarian criteria, hedonic criteria
may often take priority. That is, utilitarian considerations may come into
play only when people have both the motivation to evaluate these criteria
and the ability to do so.
A study by Shiv and Fedorikhin (1999) supported this contention. Partici-
pants were given a choice between a chocolate cake and a fruit salad as a
328 CHAPTER 11

reward for participating in the study. The authors assumed that the sight of
the chocolate cake would elicit positive affect, and that the choice of this
option would reflect the use of these reactions as a basis for their decision.
In contrast, the choice of a fruit salad was more likely to reflect the use of
utilitarian (health-related) criteria. The authors further speculated that the
latter criteria would come into play only if participants had the motivation
and ability to think carefully about their decision.
To evaluate this possibility, some participants were placed under high
cognitive load at the time they made their choice by being asked to remem-
ber a multiple-digit number for use in a later part of the study. Others were
put under low load. Participants in the latter condition tended to choose the
fruit salad, suggesting that they based their decision on utilitarian (i.e.,
health-related) criteria. Participants who were distracted from thinking about
their decision, however, were more inclined to choose the chocolate cake.
The implications of these findings may extend beyond the domain of
consumer judgment. For example, a faculty member who wishes to hire a
research assistant may consider utilitarian criteria (background, experi-
ence, etc.) to be particularly relevant. In a personal interview, however, a
candidate’s personality and physical attractiveness might elicit affective re-
actions that are used as a basis for judgment in addition to other consider-
ations. Moreover, if the interviewer meets the candidate before receiving
descriptive information about his or her qualifications, these affective crite-
ria may predominate, and descriptive criteria may be taken into account
only if the interviewer has the motivation and ability to think more carefully
about the candidate’s credentials.

Effects of Initial Appraisals on the Use


of Affective Versus Descriptive Criteria

In most research on the use of affect as a basis for judgment (for reviews,
see Clore, Schwarz, & Conway, 1994; Schwarz & Clore, 1996; Wyer, Clore, &
Isbell, 1999), the influence of affect is assumed to occur at the time of judg-
ment. If people make a spontaneous appraisal of a stimulus at the time they
first encounter it (Lazarus, 1982), and if this appraisal elicits affective reac-
tions, these reactions can give rise to an affect-based initial impression of
the stimulus that influences participants’ later judgments over and above
the effects of more specific information they receive later.
This possibility was confirmed by Catherine Yeung (2003; Yeung & Wyer,
in press). She noted that people’s first encounter with a product often oc-
curs when they notice it in a store window or see a picture of it in a maga-
zine, and that they spontaneously appraise the product on the basis of this
encounter. If this appraisal elicits affect, it not only can have an impact on
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 329

evaluations of the product but also can bias the search for additional infor-
mation about it.

1. Experiment 1
To examine these possibilities, participants in one experiment took part
in three conditions. In no-picture conditions, participants who had been in-
duced to feel either happy or unhappy as a result of writing about a life ex-
perience were given verbal descriptions of a pair of sports shoes consisting
of three favorable and three unfavorable features. Some participants were
told to base their judgment on hedonic criteria (how it would feel to wear
the shoes), and others were told to use utilitarian criteria (durability, work-
manship, etc.). Participants’ evaluations of the products in these condi-
tions, shown in the top left panel of Table 11.3, indicate that the extraneous
affect that participants were experiencing influenced their evaluations
when they were told to use hedonic criteria but had little effect when they
were told to use utilitarian criteria. These data, which are consistent with
those reported by Pham (1998), confirmed the assumption that when partic-
ipants are told to use hedonic criteria as a basis for evaluations, they imag-
ine the feelings they would experience when using the product, and the af-
fect they were experiencing for other reasons influence their assessment of
these feelings. When participants were told to use utilitarian criteria, how-
ever, they did not consult their feelings and so the extraneous affect they
were experiencing had little effect.
In two other conditions of this study, however, participants were
shown an attractive picture of the product before they received descrip-

TABLE 11.3
Product Evaluations and Recall of Attribution Information
as a Function of Induced Affect, Judgment Criterion,
and Information Presentation Conditions

Affect Induced Affect Induced After


No Picture Before Picture Picture

Positive Negative Positive Negative Positive Negative


Affect Affect Affect Affect Affect Affect

Product evaluation (Experiment 1)


Hedonic criterion 6.50 4.10 5.25 3.75 3.46 3.50
Utilitarian criterion 4.00 4.12 5.25 3.78 3.89 4.33
Product evaluation (Experiment 2)
Hedonic product 7.11 4.67 6.38 4.38 5.78 5.30
Utilitarian product 3.41 3.78 4.88 3.63 4.11 4.48
Number of positive attributes recalled (Experiment 2)
Hedonic product 2.55 1.32 2.13 1.32 1.68 1.59
Utilitarian product 1.14 1.80 1.62 1.29 1.32 1.26

Note. Adapted from Yeung and Wyer (in press).


330 CHAPTER 11

tions of its attributes. Moreover, the pictures in affect-picture conditions


were shown after participants had been induced to feel happy or unhap-
pily, whereas in picture-affect conditions, the pictures was conveyed at the
outset. We assumed that the picture would stimulate participants to make
a spontaneous appraisal of the product that elicits affective reactions, and
that these reactions would then provide the basis for an initial impression
of the product that they would use as a basis for their evaluation of the
product they reported later. Moreover, this should be true regardless of
the specific criteria they would apply in the absence of this affect-eliciting
appraisal. Therefore, if participants are experiencing affect for other rea-
sons at the time they made this appraisal, this affect should also influence
the impression they form and the judgments they ultimately make on the
basis of it. On the other hand, suppose extraneous affect is not induced
until after participants have made an appraisal of the product and formed
an impression on the basis of it. Then, this affect should have no impact
on their initial impression and, therefore, should not influence the evalua-
tion they report later.
Data in the last two sections of Table 11.3 (top) confirm these predic-
tions. That is, the extraneous affect that participants were experiencing had
a positive impact on judgments when it was induced before pictures were
presented, and this was true regardless of the criteria they were told to use.
When extraneous affect was not induced until after participants saw the
product, however, it had no influence on judgments whatsoever.

2. Experiment 2

A second experiment confirmed these findings and, in doing so, pro-


vided further evidence bearing on the assumptions underlying their inter-
pretation. The design of this study was similar to the first with two excep-
tions. First, rather than explicitly instructing participants as to which
criterion they should use, we asked them to evaluate products that they
were likely to evaluate spontaneously on the basis of either hedonic criteria
(salad dressing) or utilitarian criteria (backpacks). Second, participants af-
ter receiving the product information were told to recall all of the product’s
features they could remember. (Because most participants could recall all
six pieces, we considered only the first three features they recalled, and
used the number of these features that were favorable as an index of the
relative attention paid to these features in relation to unfavorable ones.)
Product evaluations, shown in the middle third of Table 11.3, confirm
conclusions drawn from the first study. That is, when a picture of the prod-
uct was not presented, participants judged the hedonic product more favor-
ably when they were feeling happy than when they were feeling unhappy,
whereas they evaluated utilitarian products similarly regardless of the ex-
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 331

traneous affect they were experiencing. When participants had received a


picture of the product, however, the extraneous affect they were experienc-
ing at the time they saw the picture had an impact on their judgments of
both types of products, whereas affect that was not induced until after they
saw the picture had no impact. Note that this same pattern of effects was
reflected in the favorableness of the attribute information that participants
recalled, as shown in the bottom third of Table 11.3.
The parallel effects of experimental variables on recall and judgments
has two possible interpretations. First, participants who formed affect-
based impressions selectively attended to attributes of the product that
confirmed the evaluative implications of these impressions, and then used
this attribute information as a basis for judgments. Second, participants
who formed an initial impression of the product based their judgments di-
rectly on this impression independently of the specific attribute informa-
tion presented. However, they thought more about information they re-
ceived that was consistent with this impression in order to confirm its
validity (for evidence of such confirmatory information seeking, see
Bodenhausen & Wyer, 1985; Chernev, 2001; Snyder & Cantor, 1979). Al-
though these alternative possibilities cannot be clearly distinguished on
the basis of the data available, the correlation between product evaluations
and the favorableness of the attribute information recalled was very low (r
= .14), suggesting that in fact, the two measures are relatively independent.
In any event, the two studies in combination clearly suggest that when
participants read verbal descriptions of a product’s attributes without hav-
ing seen a picture of it, they only based their evaluation of the product on
their affective reactions if they believed that hedonic criteria were relevant
to this evaluation. When they saw a picture of the product, however, the
picture stimulated a spontaneous appraisal of the product that elicited af-
fective reactions, and participants formed an initial impression of the prod-
uct on the basis of these reactions. Then, they used this affect-based im-
pression as a basis for their later evaluations of the product regardless of
the criteria they would otherwise have applied.

3. A Contingency
Yeung and Wyer’s (in press) results suggested that affect can exert its
impact on judgments of a stimulus through its influence on the spontane-
ous appraisal that people make of the stimulus at the time they first en-
counter it. Not all initial appraisals elicit affect, however. Whether this is so
could depend in part on previously learned associations of affect with fea-
tures of the stimulus on which appraisals are based. When an appraisal
does not elicit affect, subsequent judgments could still be determined by
the initial impression that is formed on the basis of it. However, affective re-
actions may not have much influence.
332 CHAPTER 11

Yeung (2003) obtained evidence of this contingency in a study that paral-


leled the experiments described in the previous paragraphs. Rather than
giving participants a picture of the product, however, she told them that
the product they would judge was being produced by a company that was
well known for either hedonic products (Pepsi) or utilitarian ones (Bona-
qua, a brand of distilled water). Either before or after conveying this infor-
mation, participants were induced to feel happy or unhappy by writing
about a past experience. Finally, they were given information about a pair
of sports shoes that were ostensibly about to be produced by the company
whose name had been provided earlier.
When the brand was associated with a product that was judged on the
basis of affective criteria, results paralleled those obtained under compara-
ble conditions of the earlier studies. That is, extraneous affect had a posi-
tive influence on participants’ evaluations of the brand extension when it
was induced before participants learned of the brand, but not when it was
induced afterward. When the brand was associated with a product that was
judged on the basis of utilitarian criteria, however, the extraneous affect
that participants were experiencing had no influence regardless of when it
was induced.
These results further strengthen the conclusion that judgments of a stim-
ulus are often induced by an initial appraisal that is made at the time the
stimulus is first encountered independently of more specific information
about the stimulus that is conveyed afterwards. In these conditions, how-
ever, affective reactions only enter into this process when the appraisal
elicits affect. Moreover, extraneous affect that participants happen to be ex-
periencing only has an impact when it is experienced at the time the ap-
praisal is made and, therefore, becomes confused with the affect that is au-
tomatically elicited by the appraisal-inducing stimulus.

AFFECT-CONFIRMATION PROCESSES

In the research by Yeung (2003; Yeung & Wyer, in press) affect was presum-
ably elicited by a spontaneous global appraisal of the product as a whole
that was independent of any specific product features. However, affect can
obviously be elicited by specific features of a stimulus as well. A politician’s
position on a particular issue, for example, could elicit positive or negative
affective reactions in someone who favors or opposes this position. In the
product domain, a sweater’s material can convey how nice it would feel to
wear it, and could elicit affect for this reason. Individuals who wish to evalu-
ate such stimuli on the basis of affective considerations are likely to pay at-
tention to features that elicit affect and use these features rather than oth-
ers as a basis for judgment. If the individuals are also experiencing affect
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 333

for other reasons, however, this affect could have two effects. First, they
might confuse their affective reactions to these features with the affect they
are experiencing for other reasons, and consequently could interpret these
features as more or less favorable. On the other hand, their extraneous feel-
ings could influence the importance that they attach to the affect-eliciting
features and, therefore, the weight they attach to these features when com-
puting a judgment.
This latter possibility is formalized in the affect-confirmation theory pro-
posed by Adaval (2001). According to this theory, participants who base
their judgments of a stimulus on hedonic considerations assess not only
their affective reactions to the stimulus’s individual features but also the ex-
tent to which their perceptions of these reactions are valid. If extraneous af-
fect that they happen to be experiencing is similar to the affect that is elic-
ited by a stimulus feature, it may appear to confirm their reactions to this
feature and, therefore, may give them more confidence in the implications
of these reactions. On the other hand, if extraneous affect they are experi-
encing differs from that elicited by a stimulus feature, they might interpret
this difference as ambivalence and thus might decrease their confidence in
the validity of their assessment of the feature’s affective implications. Con-
sequently, if individuals base their judgments of the stimulus on their affec-
tive reactions to it, they should attach greater weight to features that elicit
affect similar to the feelings they are experiencing for other, unrelated rea-
sons than to features that elicit different reactions.

Empirical Evidence

Two studies by Adaval (2001) evaluated these hypotheses. In one, partici-


pants who had been induced to feel either happy or unhappy received in-
formation about a pair of jeans consisting of either a favorable or an unfa-
vorable brand name (Levis vs. Rustler) and either a favorable or an
unfavorable attribute (preshrunk vs. not preshrunk). In some cases, partici-
pants were told to base their evaluations of the jeans on hedonic criteria
(how it would feel to wear them) and the attribute was described in a way
that emphasized its implications for comfort. In other cases, they were told
to base their judgments on utilitarian criteria, and the attribute description
emphasized its implications for the quality of construction. Participants af-
ter reading the product description evaluated the product and then re-
ported their confidence that this evaluation was correct.
Note that differences in the impact of the attribute information on prod-
uct evaluations under different affect-induction conditions could indicate ei-
ther that the attribute information was weighted more heavily in making
their judgments or, alternatively, that the attribute information was inter-
preted differently (i.e., as more or less extreme) under these conditions. To
334 CHAPTER 11

avoid this ambiguity, Adaval inferred the relative weight attached to the at-
tribute information from the impact of the brand information that accompa-
nied it. If affect information receives relatively greater weight when its
evaluative implications are consistent with the extraneous affect that par-
ticipants were experiencing, the relative influence of the brand information
that accompanies it should be relatively less.22
Data summarized in the top half of Table 11.4 confirm this hypothesis.
That is, when participants were told to evaluate the product on the basis of
hedonic criteria, brand information had less impact on their judgments
when the attribute description was evaluatively consistent with the extra-
neous affect that participants were experiencing than when it was inconsis-
tent, indicating that the attribute information received greater weight in the
former condition. When participants were told to use utilitarian criteria,
however, brand had greater influence in the former condition than the lat-
ter. This reversal suggests that participants in this condition may have in-
tentionally avoided basing their judgments on affective criteria and, in fact,
overcompensated for its influence, attaching less weight to the attribute in-
formation than they otherwise would. Interestingly, participants reported
greater confidence in their judgments when the evaluative implications of
the attribute information and those of the extraneous affect they were expe-
riencing were consistent, and this was true regardless of the objective they
were pursuing. Thus, participants were not only more confident about us-
ing their affective reactions to the attribute information as a basis for judg-
ments when their evaluations were based on hedonic criteria but were also
more confident about avoiding its use when the basis for their judgment
was utilitarian.
A second experiment confirmed these predictions under conditions in
which the criterion that participants used was activated spontaneously by
the type of product that participants were asked to consider. Normative
data suggested that in the absence of explicit instructions, participants
were likely to evaluate jeans on the basis of hedonic criteria and backpacks
on the basis of utilitarian criteria. A second experiment was conducted us-
ing these two product categories but without instructing participants about
the criteria they should employ. The bottom half of Table 11.4 shows that as
expected, brand had less impact on evaluations of jeans when the
evaluative implications of the attribute information were consistent with
the extraneous affect that participants were experiencing, whereas it had
greater impact on evaluations of backpacks in this condition.

22
22 The use of this criterion assumes that judgments are a weighted average of the implica-
tions of the two pieces of information considered separately (cf. N. Anderson, 1971, 1981). Al-
though this assumption is often questionable (cf. Wyer & Carlston, 1979), the validity of the as-
sumption in product evaluation situations is viable (cf. Bettman, Capon, & Lutz, 1975; Troutman
& Shanteau, 1976).
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 335

TABLE 11.4
Effects of Brand Favorableness on Product Evaluations as a
Function of Processing Criterion and Attribute-Affect Consistency

Attribute Consistent Attribute Inconsistent


With Induced Affect With Induced Affect

Experimentally-induced judgment criterion (Experiment 1)


Hedonic 2.21a 2.56
Utilitarian 2.83 1.85
Spontaneously activated judgment criterion (Experiment 2)
Jeans (hedonic) 3.0 4.2
Backpacks (utilitarian) 2.0 1.3

Note. Adapted from Adaval (2001).


aEffect of brand favorableness is inferred from the difference in product evaluations when

the brand was favorable and evaluations when the brand was unfavorable.

Implications for Political Judgment

Adaval’s (2001) findings, and her affect-confirmation theory more generally,


are noteworthy in the context of considerations raised earlier in this chap-
ter. That is, the greater weight of affect-consistent information in judgments
has often been attributed to the greater accessibility of affect-consistent se-
mantic concepts and knowledge in memory and, therefore, the greater like-
lihood of encoding this information into memory (cf. Forgas & Bower, 1987).
However, only two pieces of product information were presented in
Adaval’s studies, and this information was available at the time of judg-
ment. In other words, the differential accessibility of the information in
memory cannot plausibly account for the effects. Moreover, the effects are
unlikely to result from the encoding of the information in terms of eval-
uatively consistent semantic concepts at the time it was received (Nieden-
thal & Setterlund, 1994).
To the extent affect-confirmation processes account for the results of
Adaval’s studies, it seems likely that the influence of affect-consistent infor-
mation observed in other research studies are influenced by similar pro-
cesses. A study by Isbell and Wyer (1999) is worth considering in this re-
gard. Happy and sad participants were asked to evaluate a political
candidate on the basis of a news article that described his stands on a num-
ber of social issues. In addition, their intrinsic and extrinsic motivation to
think carefully about the candidate’s issue positions was varied.23 Partici-

23
23 Intrinsic motivation was inferred from responses to a self-report index of the strength of
participants’ partisanship (i.e., their party identification). To induce extrinsic motivation, partic-
ipants were told that the individual they would evaluate was a current candidate for office in
their area, and that we were consequently interested in whether they would vote for him. In con-
trast, low motivation was induced by telling participants we were primarily interested in
whether the article was clearly written, independently of its specific content.
336 CHAPTER 11

pants after reading the news article reported their impressions of the candi-
date and then indicated their personal agreement with each of the issue
stands he had espoused, along with an equal number of positions on which
the candidate’s stands were unknown.
When participants were neither intrinsically nor extrinsically motivated
to evaluate the candidate, they judged him more favorably when they were
feeling happy than when they were not. Moreover, they reported stronger
agreement with the candidate’s issue stands in the former case than the lat-
ter. (In contrast, their agreement with issue positions that were not associ-
ated with the candidate were not influenced by the affect they were experi-
encing.) Thus, participants’ mood influenced their perceptions of the
favorableness of the candidate’s issue stands and these perceptions, in
turn, determined their liking for the candidate. This conclusion was con-
firmed by covariance analyses. Specifically, the effects of experimental vari-
ables on candidate evaluations were eliminated when their effects on issue
agreement were covaried, whereas the effects of these variables on issue
agreement remained significant when evaluations of the candidate were
covaried.
Isbell and Wyer (1999) concluded that participants interpreted their re-
actions to the candidate’s issue stands as generally more favorable when
they were feeling happy than when they were not. However, affect-
confirmation processes could also underlie these findings. For example,
happy participants may have had more confidence in the validity of their
reactions to issue stands that elicited positive affect (i.e., stands with which
they agreed) than in the validity of their reactions to issue stands that elic-
ited negative affect (stands with which they disagreed). Unhappy partici-
pants, on the other hand, may have had less confidence in their reactions
to the former statements than their reactions to the latter. The differential
weighting of the issue stands that resulted from these differences in confi-
dence could have influenced candidate evaluations for much the same rea-
sons suggested by Adaval (2001). Isbell and Wyer’s study does not distin-
guish between these interpretations.

ADJUSTMENTS FOR BIAS

The aforementioned results by Isbell and Wyer (1999) were evident only
among participants who were neither intrinsically nor extrinsically moti-
vated to make accurate judgments. When people are more motivated to be
correct, they may attempt to distinguish between the various sources of af-
fect they are experiencing. Furthermore, if they believe their perception of
their feelings toward the stimulus they are judging to be contaminated by
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 337

extraneous sources of affect, they might try to adjust for this biasing influ-
ence. As noted in chapter 10, however, people are often unclear how much
adjustment is necessary. If people do not adjust enough, the extraneous af-
fect they are experiencing would continue to have a positive influence on
their judgments. If they adjust too much, on the other hand, it would appear
to have a contrast effect.
The latter appeared to be the case in Isbell and Wyer’s study. That is, al-
though the extraneous affect that participants were experiencing had a pos-
itive impact on their judgments when they were unmotivated to make accu-
rate evaluations, it had precisely the opposite effect on judgments by
individuals who were either intrinsically or extrinsically motivated to be
correct (see footnote 24).

Effects of Ability

Even if people are motivated to adjust for the biasing influence of extrane-
ous affect, they may be unable to do so. Ottati and Isbell (1996), for exam-
ple, found that extraneous affect had a positive influence on evaluations of
a candidate by participants with relatively little knowledge about politics,
but had a contrast effect on evaluations by participants with high political
expertise. Perhaps both groups of participants adjusted for the biasing in-
fluence of the extraneous affect they were experiencing. However, partici-
pants with little expertise had difficulty evaluating the implications of the
candidate’s issue positions and the cognitive resources they had to devote
to this activity prevented them from adjusting sufficiently. On the other
hand, experts found it easy to evaluate the implications of the candidate’s
issue positions and so they could devote more effort to distinguishing their
reactions to these stands from other sources of affect. However, these par-
ticipants adjusted too much, resulting in a contrast effect of extraneous af-
fect on their evaluations.

Adjustment Versus Discounting

Adjustments for bias are most likely to occur when people consider their af-
fective reactions to the primary basis for their judgments of an object but
cannot distinguish clearly between these reactions and affect from other
sources. In many instances, however, nonaffective criteria for judgment
may be as or more appropriate bases for judgment. In these instances, peo-
ple who believe that the affective reactions are biased by extraneous fac-
tors might ignore their feelings entirely and default to other, nonaffective
criteria. In this case, the affect they are experiencing would not have a con-
trast effect on judgments. Rather, it would have no influence at all.
338 CHAPTER 11

One example of discounting was obtained by Schwarz and Clore (1983,


Experiment 2). In this study, residents of downstate Illinois were contacted
by telephone on either a sunny or a rainy day and asked to participate in a
short telephone interview in which they reported their general life satisfac-
tion. Participants judged themselves to be more satisfied with their life on
sunny days than on rainy ones, suggesting they based their judgments in
part on the affective reactions activated by the weather. In other condi-
tions, however, the interviewer, who was ostensibly calling from Chicago,
incidentally asked participants, “By the way, how’s the weather down
there?”, thereby calling participants’ attention to an extraneous source of
their affect. In this condition, participants apparently ignored the affect
they were experiencing and based their judgments on other criteria (e.g.,
their knowledge about life events that they retrieved from memory). Conse-
quently, weather-induced affect had no impact on their judgments at all.
Calling participants’ attention to an extraneous source of affect does not
always lead participants to discount their feelings, however. When partici-
pants in Schwarz and Clore’s (1983, Experiment 1) study had written about
an unhappy life event in a booth they believed would make them happy,
they apparently inferred that they must be feeling even more negatively
about themselves than did participants who were not given information
about the booth. Consequently, they reported lower life satisfaction than
other participants did. A study by Gasper and Clore (1998) found that
chronically anxious individuals do not discount the influence of situational
factors on the negative affect they are experiencing. Calling these individu-
als’ attention to extraneous sources of negative affect apparently made sa-
lient to them that their feelings were not due to transitory factors alone.
Consequently, it increased the influence of the negative affect they were ex-
periencing rather than decreasing it.
In this regard, it is undoubtedly an oversimplification to assume that
when both affective and nonaffective criteria for judgment are available,
people may use one set of criteria or the other but not both. More gener-
ally, people use both types of criteria, with the relative weight attached to
each depending on perceptions of its relative validity and also the time and
effort that are required to construe its implications. As noted earlier, affec-
tive reactions to a stimulus can often occur spontaneously upon exposure
to it, and so this criterion is likely to be weighted heavily when participants’
motivation or ability to think about other available criteria are low. How-
ever, if participants have the time and motivation to apply other relevant
criteria, they may use these criteria as well. The impact of situational fac-
tors on the relative use of alternative criteria for judgment was identified by
Shiv and Fedorikhin (1999) and also by Albarracin and Wyer (2001) in a
study of communication and persuasion. The latter study is described in
more detail presently.
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 339

AUTOMATIC INFLUENCES OF AFFECT


ON INFORMATION PROCESSING

People’s affective reactions can influence not only their judgments but also
their overt behavior and decisions. These effects could be either delibera-
tive or automatic. In the first regard, people are sometimes motivated to be-
have in a way that will maintain a positive mood or, alternatively, will rid
themselves of negative feelings. As noted earlier, however, the affective re-
actions one experiences, like other internally generated stimuli, can acti-
vate a production of the sort described in chapter 1 (J. Anderson, 1983; E. R.
Smith, 1984, 1990). That is, they can form part of the configuration of stimuli
[X] in a production of the form “if [X], then [Y],” where [Y] is a sequence of
responses that are elicited automatically once the preconditions are met.
These effects may be captured in a postulate:

Postulate 11.2. The affective reactions that one experiences, along with con-
cepts and cognitions that are stimulated by an appraisal of a stimulus situation,
can compose a precondition for a previously learned sequence of responses
(i.e., a cognitive production). This response sequence may be activated spon-
taneously, with little conscious cognitive mediation, under conditions in
which the precondition is met.

Despite the vagueness of Postulate 11.2, some general predictions seem


tenable. One particularly interesting hypothesis concerns the use of holistic
vs. piecemeal processing strategies to interpret information and make judg-
ments. The impact of affect on the use of these strategies is described in the
pages that follow.

The Influence of Affect on the Use


of Categorical Criteria

Bless (2001; Bless et al., 1996) postulated that positive affect is associated
with a disposition to use broad concepts and general knowledge structures
to perform experimental tasks, whereas negative affect is associated with at-
tention to situational details. These differences could result from social learn-
ing. That is, positive affect may become associated with conditions in which
success has not required a careful scrutiny of the situation or task to be per-
formed. In contrast, negative affect could become associated with failure and
negative events that can only be avoided by attention to situational details
(cf. Schwarz, 1990). As a result of these learned associations, the experience
of positive affect can often stimulate a production that involves the use of
general (e.g., categorical) criteria in responding to an achievement task,
whereas negative affect may activate a production that involves a more de-
tailed analysis of the task requirements and the information bearing on them.
340 CHAPTER 11

Furthermore, these alternative productions might be activated spontane-


ously when the affect-based preconditions for their occurrence are met, and
might guide behavior with little if any conscious cognitive mediation.
The different productions that are activated by positive and negative af-
fect require different types of knowledge. The procedures activated by posi-
tive affect involve the use of general concepts and knowledge structures. In
contrast, the procedures activated by negative affect may require more
specific concepts that can be used to interpret informational details. This
difference should be reflected in the type of concepts and knowledge that
are used to interpret and organize new information. At least two studies
support this possibility.
Bless et al. (1996) reasoned that if people who experience positive affect
spontaneously activate general knowledge structures to use in processing in-
formation, they should be able to process this information more efficiently.
Moreover, their use of these knowledge structures should free cognitive re-
sources for use in other, unrelated cognitive activity. To evaluate this possi-
bility, participants who were induced experimentally to feel happy or un-
happy listened to two tape-recorded stories about daily life events (e.g.,
making a telephone call from a public phone booth) while they performed a
clerical task. Both recognition memory for the events mentioned in the au-
diotapes and accuracy in performing the clerical task were recorded.
As expected, happy participants were more likely than unhappy ones to
use a prototypic script (Schank & Abelson, 1977) to comprehend the taped
information. That is, happy participants were more likely than unhappy
ones to report prototype-consistent events as having been mentioned, but
were less likely than unhappy participants to report atypical events. To the
extent that participants apply a general prototype in comprehending the
tape-recorded information, however, they should be able to devote more
cognitive resources to the clerical task. This was also the case. Happy par-
ticipants performed better on the secondary, clerical task than unhappy
participants did.
A quite different study by Dienes (1996) has similar implications. In this
study, happy and unhappy participants were asked to learn a list of words
that exemplified either easily identifiable concepts (animals, countries, etc.)
or obscure ones (e.g., things made of wood). Learning the list could be facil-
itated by (a) attending to the details of the individual words, (b) mentally
organizing the words in terms of the concepts they exemplify, or (c) both.
(For evidence that the organization of information items into categories im-
proves learning, see Hunt & Einstein, 1981.) Dienes reasoned that when the
concepts exemplified by the stimulus words were obvious, both happy and
unhappy participants would spontaneously identify and use these concepts
to organize the stimuli. When the concepts were more obscure, however,
only happy participants should identify them spontaneously, so only these
participants’ learning of the stimulus words should be facilitated. Consis-
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 341

tent with this reasoning, happy participants had better memory than un-
happy participants for the hard-to-categorize words but not for the easy-to-
categorize words.
The conclusions that persons who experience positive affect bring cate-
gorical and general knowledge structures to bear on tasks they perform
does not imply that affective reactions per se cue the retrieval of these
knowledge structures. Rather, this retrieval is mediated by cognitive pro-
ductions that require different types of declarative knowledge. The precon-
ditions for activating a production include situational features as well as
affective reactions. In some cases, the cognitive productions that are acti-
vated by situation-specific features might not require the types of knowl-
edge of concern in the studies by Dienes and Bless et al. In other cases, af-
fective reactions might not be a feature of the preconditions that elicit goal-
relevant productions. Consequently, there are many instances in which af-
fect is likely to have little influence on the strategies that people use in re-
sponding to information.
In this regard, Murray, Sujan, Hirt, and Sujan (1990) found that although
happy participants used fewer categories to classify stimuli than control par-
ticipants when they were told to focus on similarities, they used relatively
more categories to classify the stimuli when they were told to focus on differ-
ences. These latter findings qualify the conclusion that happy persons typi-
cally use broader categories to classify stimuli than unhappy persons. Fur-
ther experiments by Murray et al. (1990) indicated that differences in
categorization observed in both task conditions were likely to result from a
more general tendency for positive affect to increase the number of attribute
dimensions that participants brought to bear on the particular task they
were asked to perform. Thus, it increased their ability to make distinctions
among the stimuli they were considering as well as to identify similarities. As
Murray et al. suggest, these results could reflect mood-induced differences in
the motivation to perform the task at hand rather than differences in the cog-
nitive productions that participants spontaneously apply under the condi-
tions being investigated. We consider this possibility in more detail shortly.

Implications for Judgment

If positive affect increases the disposition to rely on categorical criteria for


comprehending and responding to stimuli, this disposition should be re-
flected in judgments to which the criteria are relevant. However, this influ-
ence could be localized at two stages of processing. First, if the information
that is available for judging a stimulus consists of both categorical descrip-
tions and more detailed features, positive affect might increase the relative
weight that is attached to the categorical information at the time the implica-
tions of the two types of information are combined to form a judgment. An al-
342 CHAPTER 11

ternative possibility, however, is that positive affect influences the attention


that is paid to categorical information at the initial, comprehension stage.
That is, if individuals who experience positive affect think more extensively
about the implications of categorical information at the time the information
is received, they may interpret the implications of this information as more
extreme, and this could also lead the information to have more effect on
judgments that individuals report later. (For more general evidence that
thought increases the extremity of judgments, see Tesser, 1978.)
These two alternative possibilities are difficult to separate. That is, both
effects imply that positive affect will increase the apparent influence of cat-
egorical information on judgments. However, a series of studies by Adaval
(2003) suggested that, in fact, the effect is localized at the initial comprehen-
sion stage. In two studies, happy and unhappy participants evaluated a
product on the basis of an unfavorable or unfavorable brand name (a cate-
gorical criterion) and a favorable or unfavorable specific attribute descrip-
tion. Judgments were also obtained of products described by each attribute
feature separately. Brand information had more influence when partici-
pants were feeling happy than when they were not. To determine the rea-
son for this difference, Adaval assumed a weighted averaging model of in-
formation integration of the sort proposed by Anderson (1971, 1981; see
Footnote 23), and applied a parameter-estimation procedure to identify
both the absolute weight attached to each piece of product information and
its scale value (i.e., its evaluative implications). Analyses of these parame-
ters, computed for each participant separately, showed that positive affect
had no impact on the weight attached to brand information. However, it in-
creased the extremity of the scale value assigned to it (That is, happy par-
ticipants interpreted favorable brands as more favorable, and unfavorable
brands as more unfavorable, than unhappy participants did.) Further stud-
ies provided confirming evidence of this conclusion using different criteria.
These results are consistent with the results obtained by Bless et al.
(1996), that people attend more to categorical bases for interpreting the
stimuli they encounter. Moreover, the effects of this attention occur at the
time the information is first received and interpreted and not at the time
the information is used to make a judgment.

MOTIVATIONAL INFLUENCES OF AFFECT


ON INFORMATION PROCESSING

One body of phenomena to which Postulate 11.2 is applicable has been


identified in research on communication and persuasion. Much of this re-
search suggests that people who feel happy are less influenced by the qual-
ity of the arguments contained in a persuasive message than unhappy peo-
ple are (cf. Bless, Bohner, Schwarz, & Strack, 1990; Mackie & Worth, 1989).
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 343

Several factors could have been hypothesized to account for this differ-
ence. Mackie and Worth (1989), for example, proposed that positive affect is
likely to activate a large number of concepts and knowledge representations
in memory, taxing participants’ capacity to provide new information and
making them less able to attend to details of the information available. This
interpretation, however, is called into question by Niedenthal and Setter-
lund’s (1994) finding that affective reactions activate only those concepts that
the specific type of reactions being experienced exemplify, and do not in-
crease the accessibility of valenced concepts and knowledge in general.
A somewhat more viable conceptualization is consistent with the use of
affect as information. Specifically, Schwarz (1990; Schwarz, Bless, & Bohner,
1991) argued that because positive affect is typically associated with pleas-
ant states of affairs, people who experience these feelings in a new situation
may appraise the situation as benign and, therefore, may not pay careful at-
tention to details. In contrast, negative affect is associated with aversive
states of affairs and so the experience of it stimulates an interpretation of a
new situation as potentially problematic. Although these associations could
give rise to cognitive productions that are applied automatically, as noted
in a previous section, they could potentially stimulate deliberative cogni-
tive activity as well. Consequently, people may be less motivated to pay at-
tention to the details of a message they receive when they feel happy than
when they feel unhappy, and so the quality of the arguments contained in
the message has less impact on their judgments.
Although this interpretation seems plausible, it is contradicted by evi-
dence that people engage in as much cognitive activity in responding to a
persuasive message when they are in a good mood as when they are in a
bad mood. In Bless et al.’s (1990) study, for example, thought listing data in-
dicated that the overall amount of this activity did not depend on the mood
that participants were in. That is, participants in a good mood tended to
counterargue both weak and strong arguments (and thus were equally in-
fluenced by both),whereas participants in a bad mood elaborated strong ar-
guments and counterargued weak ones, thus being differently persuaded
by them. The total number of thoughts generated in the two mood condi-
tions was the same in both cases, however. Research on impression forma-
tion by Isbell (2000) also suggested that happy and sad individuals do not
differ in the amount of cognitive activity they perform in response to infor-
mation, but differ only in the nature of this activity.
A third conceptualization is based on the notion that people who are feel-
ing happy are motivated to maintain their mood and, consequently, avoid ac-
tivities that are likely to bring them down. Unhappy individuals, on the other
hand, are motivated to divest themselves of the negative feelings they are ex-
periencing, and engage in activities that distract themselves from thinking
about these feelings and the events that gave rise to them. Because persua-
344 CHAPTER 11

sive messages are typically counterattitudinal, thinking about them is partic-


ularly likely to destroy one’s good mood. Consequently, people who feel
happy tend to avoid this cognitive activity and, as a result, are insensitive to
differences in the quality of arguments contained in the messages.
If this interpretation is correct, processing differences should be elimi-
nated or even reversed by leading happy persons to believe that thinking
about the information they receive will be enjoyable and, therefore, will
maintain or enhance their positive mood state. Wegener, Petty, and Smith
(1995) showed this to be the case. Participants listened to one of two com-
munications. One message advocated a position with which participants
were inclined to disagree and was introduced with instructions that it was
likely to make them unhappy. The quality of arguments contained in this
message had less impact on participants’ attitudes when they were happy
than when they were not. The other message advocated a position that par-
ticipants typically favored and was introduced with a comment that reading
it was likely to be enjoyable. In this case, the quality of the arguments had
greater effect on participants’ attitudes when they were happy.
Wegener et al.’s (1995) results therefore qualified the conclusion that peo-
ple who experience positive affect are generally unmotivated to engage in ex-
tensive cognitive processing. There are also qualifications on the assumption
that people who experience negative affect are motivated to process new in-
formation extensively. Cognitive activity may only help to eliminate negative
affect if the affect is mild and nothing can be done about the events that pro-
duced it. Extremely unhappy individuals are likely to ruminate about the
events that created their unhappiness instead of distracting themselves by
engaging in irrelevant activity (Ellis & Ashbrook, 1988; Klinger, 1975; Martin &
Tesser, 1996). To this extent, these individuals may be just as insensitive to
details of affect-irrelevant information as happy people are.
The information processing implied by this interpretation is deliberative.
To this extent, it would not contradict the possibility that affective reac-
tions can stimulate cognitive procedures of the sort noted in the previous
section, which are performed automatically in situations in which they ap-
ply. However, the deliberative processes that are suggested by mood-
maintenance and mood-repair motives have an alternative interpretation.
That is, these processes could be the byproduct of a more general ten-
dency to use affect as information. We now turn to this possibility.

A PERFORMANCE-FEEDBACK MODEL
OF AFFECT AS INFORMATION

In most research that has been performed to evaluate the use of affect as in-
formation, people are assumed to make judgments of a particular person,
object, or event, and the affect they experience at the time of judgment is
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 345

used as information about their reaction to the stimulus they are judging.
However, people’s affective reactions can provide information about other
things as well. In situations outside the laboratory, people may use their af-
fect as a basis for behavioral decisions. For example, they may decide to en-
gage in a behavior that gives them pleasure, while avoiding activities they
consider to be aversive. In achievement situations, on the other hand, peo-
ple’s decisions to continue on a task can also be influenced by their feelings
about the quality of their performance. A woman who is writing a term pa-
per, for example, might have little objective basis for deciding whether her
output is sufficient to attain the grade she is seeking. Therefore, her deci-
sion to continue working on the paper may be based on her subjective feel-
ings about the work she has done. The extraneous affect she happens to be
experiencing at this time could influence her perceptions of these feelings
and, as a consequence, her decision to stop working or continue.
These possibilities were formalized by Wyer et al. (1999) in a perform-
ance-feedback model of affect. This conceptualization, which was stimu-
lated in large part by Martin, Achee, Ward, and Wyer’s (1993) previous
work, assumes that people spontaneously monitor their behavior and the
outputs it generates to determine if they have satisfactorily attained the
goal they are pursuing. If they conclude that this is the case, they terminate
their goal-directed activity. Otherwise, they continue processing, using the
same or a different strategy, until they generate an output they consider to
be satisfactory.
When objective criteria exist for deciding whether a goal has been at-
tained, the decision to engage in goal-directed activity is obviously based
on these criteria. More often than not, however, the criteria for goal attain-
ment are ambiguous. When this is the case, people may base their decision
on the affect they happen to be experiencing and attribute to their feelings
about their attainment of the goal they are pursuing.
The most interesting implications of this analysis derive from the fact
that people’s perceptions of their affective reactions depend on the particu-
lar goal they happen to be pursuing. In the preceding example, the woman’s
goal was to write a paper of high quality. In this case, she may ask herself if
she feels the paper meets this standard and is more likely to stop work if
her feelings are positive than if they are negative. On the other hand, sup-
pose the woman focuses her attention on whether she is having fun rather
than the quality of the paper she is writing. Then, her feelings are likely to
have precisely the opposite effect. That is, she may be more inclined to
stop writing if her feelings are negative than if they are positive.
Two studies by Martin et al. (1993) provided direct support for these pos-
sibilities. In one, happy or sad participants were asked to form an impres-
sion of someone on the basis of a series of behaviors. Each behavior was
printed on a separate card of a deck that participants were given. Partici-
346 CHAPTER 11

pants under performance-criterion conditions were told to continue turning


the cards and reading the behaviors until they had enough information to
form an impression. In contrast, participants under enjoyment-criterion con-
ditions were told to continue as long as they were enjoying what they were
doing. The first group of participants should implicitly ask themselves as
they read the behaviors if they feel they have enough information. There-
fore, they should be more likely to answer this question affirmatively, and
to stop reading sooner, if they are happy than if they are sad. The second
group of participants, however, should ask themselves if they are enjoying
the task, again responding more affirmatively if they are happy than if they
are sad. In this case, therefore, happy participants should continue reading
behaviors longer than sad participants. Results confirmed these predic-
tions. That is, happy participants read fewer behaviors than sad partici-
pants in performance-criterion conditions (24 vs. 43, respectively), but
more behaviors than sad participants in enjoyment-criterion conditions (47
vs. 36, respectively).
A second study replicated these findings using a different task. In this
case, participants were asked to generate a list of birds. Some participants
were told to continue until they thought it was a good time to stop, whereas
others were told to continue as long as they were enjoying themselves.
Happy participants persevered less long on the task than unhappy partici-
pants when they were told to use a performance criterion (140 s vs. 218 s,
respectively), but longer than unhappy participants when they were en-
couraged to employ an enjoyment criterion (240 s vs. 145 s, respectively).

Individual and Situational Differences


in Goal Orientation

In the conditions just described, the criterion for stopping or continuing


was explicitly stated by the experimenter. When the criterion is unspeci-
fied, both individual and situational differences could influence the criteria
that participants use. Persons with high need for cognition (Cacioppo &
Petty, 1982), for example, typically find intellectual activity to be intrinsi-
cally enjoyable. They may therefore be likely to adopt an enjoyment crite-
rion, whereas persons with low need for cognition may be guided to a
greater extent by performance criteria. If this is so, the experience of posi-
tive affect might increase the persistence of high need-for-cognition individ-
uals on response-generation tasks, but might decrease the persistence of
low need-for-cognition individuals on such tasks. In fact, additional data ob-
tained by Martin et al. (1993) confirmed this prediction.
The relative emphasis on performance and enjoyment is also likely to
vary with the nature of the task and the context in which it is performed. In
laboratory studies, participants are often given a particular task objective
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 347

by the experimenter. Under these conditions, participants may spontane-


ously employ a performance criterion. That is, they may base their decision
to persevere on whether they feel that their responses fulfill these exter-
nally imposed task requirements. This hypothesis was supported in a third
condition of Martin et al.’s second experiment in which participants were
simply told to stop generating birds when “they wanted to.” The results in
this condition were very similar to those obtained when participants were
given an explicit performance criterion; that is, happy participants stopped
sooner than unhappy ones. These results confirm the speculation that par-
ticipants in many experimental situations spontaneously focus their atten-
tion on whether they have fulfilled the implicit task objectives they are
given. Nevertheless, when an experimental task is particularly interesting,
or when achievement goals are de-emphasized, an enjoyment criterion
might be applied as well.
Some evidence in support of the latter possibility was reported by
Murray et al. (1990) in a study mentioned earlier in this chapter. Some par-
ticipants were asked to list similarities between two popular television pro-
grams, whereas others were asked to list differences between the pro-
grams. The task was intrinsically interesting to college-age participants and,
therefore, was likely to stimulate them to use an enjoyment criterion in de-
ciding how much effort they should expend. To this extent, participants
should use the affect they were experiencing as a basis for inferring their
enjoyment. Consistent with this assumption, happy participants reported
enjoying the task more than control participants did. Correspondingly,
happy participants listed more similarities between the television pro-
grams when they were asked to focus on similarities, and listed more differ-
ences between the programs when they were focused on differences, than
control participants did. These results would be hard to explain on the ba-
sis of either the assumption that positive affect generally increases the ac-
cessibility of global concepts in memory. Nor is it consistent with the as-
sumption that positive affect reduces cognitive resources. It seems more
reasonable to suppose that happy participants inferred from the affect they
were experiencing that they were enjoying the task, and therefore devoted
more effort to an identification of both similarities and differences in the
stimuli they were judging than other participants did.
Murray et al.’s finding that happy participants reported greater enjoy-
ment of the task than other participants raises an additional consideration.
That is, when several goals are available in a situation, the affect that per-
sons happen to be experiencing could influence the goal they choose to
pursue as well as their inference that they have or have not attained it (for
a discussion of this possibility, see Schwarz & Clore, 1996). For example,
suppose happy individuals are generally more inclined to adopt an enjoy-
ment objective than unhappy individuals are (Isen, 1987). If this is so, happy
348 CHAPTER 11

persons may persist on a task because they infer they are enjoying it,
whereas unhappy persons, who adopt a performance criterion, may persist
because they feel they have not yet attained an adequate level of achieve-
ment. To this extent, happy and unhappy persons might persist to an equal
extent, albeit for different reasons.
Despite this ambiguity, the influence of affect on behavior in a large num-
ber of situations both in and outside the laboratory can be conceptualized
in terms of its mediating influence on the answers to questions that persons
implicitly ask themselves about how they feel about their behavior and its
outcomes. The broader implications of this conceptualization can be sum-
marized in two postulates:

Postulate 11.3. When people engage in behavior for the purpose of attaining
an external goal and objective criteria for inferring the attainment of this goal
do not exist, they use the affect they are experiencing to infer whether they feel
the strategy they have used in pursuit of this goal, and the outputs they have
generated by employing it, are appropriate. Therefore, they are more likely to
infer they have met the criterion for satisfactory performance if they are expe-
riencing positive affect than if they are not.

Postulate 11.4. When people’s primary reason for engaging in behavior is en-
joyment, they use the affect they are experiencing as a basis for inferring this
enjoyment. Therefore, they will continue the activity longer if they are experi-
encing positive affect than if they are not.

An application of these postulates calls attention to several contingen-


cies in the impact of affect that have not been investigated in the research
performed to date. Several areas of research are worth reviewing from this
perspective.

Creativity

A creativity task often employed in the laboratory requires participants to


generate instances of a concept. This task is similar to that constructed by
Martin et al. (1993, Experiment 2) except that the concept involved has un-
clear boundaries, thus allowing participants to generate novel responses.
Thus, for example, participants might be asked to generate uses of a brick
or things they could use to sit on. In this situation, like that constructed by
Martin et al., participants might assume they should stop when they have
generated enough good responses to fulfill the demands of the task. How-
ever, the task itself might often be intrinsically enjoyable, as it requires a
degree of imaginativeness. Thus, many participants might spontaneously
apply an enjoyment criterion as well. Consistent with this speculation, Isen
and Daubman (1984) found that happy participants generated more re-
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 349

sponses when performing such a task than control participants did. This
suggests that an enjoyment criterion predominated in their study.
A somewhat different interpretation of Isen and Daubman’s results is
suggested by the fact that happy participants also tend to generate more
novel responses than other participants do. When the criterion for an ap-
propriate response is unclear, participants may inhibit reporting responses
they feel are poor exemplars of the concept they are considering. Spe-
cifically, they may subjectively generate a response (e.g., a potential use for
a brick), ask themselves if they feel their response is a good one, and only
report it if they answer this question affirmatively. Thus, they are more
likely to record their response if they are happy than if they are not. Evi-
dence that happy persons perform better then others on the Remote Asso-
ciates Test (Isen, Daubman, & Nowicki, 1987) is consistent with this inter-
pretation. Furthermore, the interpretation could explain the different
results obtained by Isen and Daubman’s (1984) study and those reported by
Martin et al. (1993). That is, the criterion for membership in the category
that participants considered in Martin et al.’s experiment (birds) was
clearly defined, and so the use of affect to evaluate the appropriateness of
individual exemplars was less likely.

Impression Formation

In impression-formation research (for a review, see Wyer & Carlston, 1994),


participants typically receive information about several behaviors a person
has performed with instructions to form an impression of the person. A large
amount of information is typically presented (e.g., 25–30 items; see Wyer &
Martin, 1986), and so it is difficult to form an impression that takes all of it
into account. Consequently, participants in these experiments may often ask
themselves at various points if the information they have received is a suffi-
cient basis for a concept of what the individual is like. If they answer this self-
generated question affirmatively, they may base their concept of the person
on this information without taking into account the implications of the infor-
mation they receive later (see Postulate 3.1). If this is so, and if happy partici-
pants are more likely than unhappy participants to respond affirmatively to
such a question, they should use relatively less information to form their im-
pressions. Moreover, the information they use should typically occur at the
beginning of the sequence rather than at the end.
Martin et al.’s (1993, Experiment 1) results confirmed the assumption
that happy participants with an impression-formation objective use less in-
formation to form an impression than sad participants do. The prediction
that happy persons are more likely than unhappy ones to base their im-
pression on the first information they receive was confirmed in research by
Isbell (2000; Isbell, Clore, and Wyer (1998). Participants who were feeling ei-
350 CHAPTER 11

ther happy or sad were asked to form an impression of someone who was
described at the outset as either extraverted or introverted. This general
description was followed by a series of behaviors, an equal number of
which exemplified each of these traits. After receiving the information, par-
ticipants judged the target’s extraversion and then recalled the behaviors
they had received.
Isbell expected that the general description of the target that partici-
pants received at the outset would activate a concept of either an extravert
or an introvert, and that participants would implicitly ask themselves if
they felt this concept was an appropriate basis for their impression. Happy
participants, who should answer this question affirmatively, should be
more inclined than unhappy participants to apply the concept to the target
and to base the judgments they report later on this concept. This was in
fact the case, as indicated earlier. That is, the initial target description had a
substantial effect on happy participants’ judgments of the target’s extra-
version but had very little impact on unhappy participants’ judgments.
The fact that happy participants based their judgments on the initial de-
scription of the target does not mean that they failed to think about the be-
havioral information they received later. To the contrary, persons who
apply this concept to the target should think about the behavioral informa-
tion they receive with reference to it (Srull & Wyer, 1989). Moreover, they
should think more extensively about behaviors that are inconsistent with
the concept in order to reconcile their occurrence (Hastie, 1980; Srull &
Wyer, 1989; Wyer & Srull, 1989). As implied by this reasoning, these partici-
pants recalled more inconsistent behaviors than consistent ones. Un-
happy participants, who did not apply the concept activated by the initial
trait description to the target, did not engage in this inconsistency resolu-
tion. Consequently, they recalled behaviors equally well regardless of their
consistency with the initial trait description.
In many cases, people’s initial impressions of someone are based largely
on their feelings toward this person. This is particularly likely if their first
encounter with the person elicits a spontaneous appraisal on the basis of
his or her physical appearance (cf. Yeung & Wyer, in press). In such cases,
the affect they experience at the time they judge the person could poten-
tially have a dual function. First, it may convey judgment-relevant informa-
tion about the individual being judged (Schwarz & Clore, 1983). Second, it
could be used as an indication of whether this affect is a sufficient basis for
making the judgment. Thus, people who experience positive affect at the
time they are asked to judge someone might not only infer they feel favor-
ably toward the target, but also that these feelings are a sufficient basis for
the judgment they are asked to make. In contrast, people who experience
negative affect may infer they feel negatively toward the target but also
may conclude that these feelings are not a sufficient basis for the judgment.
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 351

This implies that the effects of positive affect on impression judgments may
often be greater than the effects of negative effect.
There is a contingency in these predictions. That is, the contention that
happy people are inclined to decide that the initial information they receive
is a sufficient basis for judgment assumes that the implications of this initial
information, considered in isolation, are unambiguous. If these implications
are mixed or unclear, they may not be considered sufficient bases for judg-
ments by either happy or unhappy individuals. A recent study by Isbell
(2003) bears on this contingency. She found that happy participants were
more likely than unhappy participants to base their evaluations of the tar-
get on a general trait characterization of him even when this characteriza-
tion was presented after the target’s behaviors were described. In this
study, however, the behavior descriptions were both favorable and unfa-
vorable, and so a clear initial impression of the target was difficult to form
on the basis of these descriptions alone. Therefore, participants were un-
likely to consider the behaviors to be a sufficient basis for judgment regard-
less of their affective state. The greater use of categorical information by
happy participants under these conditions could reflect their generally
greater tendency to apply broad categories in interpreting information, as
suggested by Adaval (2003) and Bless et al. (1996) and noted earlier.

Stereotyping

Our interpretation of Isbell et al.’s (1998) findings also has implications for
the effects of affect on the use of stereotypes. In a study by Bodenhausen
(1993; see also Bodenhausen et al., 1994), for example, happy and sad partic-
ipants were asked to judge the culpability of a defendant on the basis of in-
formation about the defendant’s background and the conditions surround-
ing the crime. The description of the crime was preceded by the target’s
name and hometown, which either identified him as Hispanic or provided
no clue as to his ethnicity. It seems reasonable to suppose that the defen-
dant’s ethnicity spontaneously activated a stereotype, and that participants
implicitly asked themselves if they felt this was an appropriate basis for
their judgment, answering affirmatively if they were happy and negatively if
they were sad. Consistent with this reasoning, the stereotype had more im-
pact on happy participants’ judgments than on unhappy participants’. Note
that if the stereotype had not been activated until after the detailed crime-
related information was presented, participants would not be in a position
to ask themselves at the outset whether the stereotype was a sufficient ba-
sis for judgment. If anything, they should ask themselves if they felt the
crime-related information was sufficient. To this latter extent, happy partici-
pants in this condition might be more influenced by the crime-related infor-
352 CHAPTER 11

mation, and less influenced by the stereotype, than sad participants are. To
my knowledge, this possibility has not been examined.

Self-Evaluation Processes

The determinants and effects of self-judgments have been a major focus of


social-psychological research for many years (cf. Greenwald & Pratkanis,
1984; Klein & Loftus, 1993; McGuire & McGuire, 1988). Because of the general
interest in these matters, the implications of the performance-feedback
model for self-judgment processes are worth considering in some detail.
The influence of affect on four different types of self-judgments—judgments
of global life satisfaction, self-worth, specific trait judgments, and estimates
of personal risk—are therefore considered from the perspective of this
model.
Several alternative cognitive processes could underlie these judgments,
each of which can involve the use of a different type of self-knowledge. The
effects of these procedures can be conceptualized in terms of the general
processing model outlined at the beginning of this volume. Specifically,
when a self-judgment is required, the goal specification may resonate with a
number of different cognitive procedures for generating this judgment.
These processes could include (a) the search for a previously formed judg-
ment-relevant trait description, (b) the identification of a judgment-related
past experience and a construal of its implications for the judgment to be
made, and (c) an assessment of the implications of the affective reactions
one is experiencing. Situational or individual difference factors that make
one process easier to use than another will increase the likelihood that this
process is applied. An additional consideration, however, is implied by the
performance-feedback conceptualization. That is, participants who have
generated a response on the basis of the “winning” procedure may sponta-
neously ask themselves if they feel that this response is a sufficient basis
for judgment. participants who are experiencing positive affect may answer
this question affirmatively, whereas those who are experiencing negative
affect may not. Therefore, happy persons are more likely than unhappy per-
sons to accept and apply the first criterion they are able to generate. The
following discussion is based on this assumption.

1. Judgments of Life Satisfaction


A request to judge one’s life satisfaction could activate three different
processes. First, respondents might search for a previously formed concept
of their life as a whole that is directly applicable to the judgment. Second,
they might recall one or more previous life events that are relevant to the
judgment and base their response on the affect elicited by these memories.
Finally, they might assess the affect they happen to be experiencing at the
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 353

FIG. 11.2. Processing stages involved in making (A) global judgments of life
satisfaction and self-esteem, and (b) specific trait judgments. Based on Wyer et
al. (1999).

time and use this as an indication of their feelings about life in general with-
out conducting a search of memory at all. These processes, which could oc-
cur simultaneously, are summarized in Fig. 11.2a.
On a priori grounds, it is unclear which of these processes will predomi-
nate. For example, if participants in an experiment have a previously
354 CHAPTER 11

formed concept of their life as a whole, a request to estimate their life satis-
faction might spontaneously activate this concept and so a judgment can
be quickly computed on the basis of the affect it elicits. On the other hand,
people are infrequently called upon to make this type of judgment in daily
life. Consequently, they usually do not have a previously formed concept of
their life as a whole stored in memory, and must compute a judgment at the
time they are asked to report it. In this case, it would normally take less
time to compute a judgment on the basis of the transitory affect one is ex-
periencing at the time of judgment than to do so on the basis of other, less
easily accessible criteria, and so judgments are more likely to be based on
the former computation. Evidence that people use transitory affect as a ba-
sis for life satisfaction judgments independently of any specific self-knowl-
edge they have available (Schwarz & Clore, 1983; Strack, Schwarz, &
Gschneidinger, 1985) is consistent with this hypothesis.
However, the performance-feedback model we have proposed raises a
further consideration. People who experience positive affect for reasons
that are objectively unrelated to their life situation might not only use these
feelings as a basis for judgment but also consider this criterion to be suffi-
cient. In contrast, people who experience negative affect might be disposed
to question the sufficiency of this criterion. Therefore, they might either
seek other judgment-relevant information or, if no alternative criteria are
readily available, might adjust for the bias that results from their use of feel-
ings as information.
Schwarz and Clore’s (1983, Experiment 1) findings support this conjec-
ture. To reiterate, happy persons appeared to use their feelings as a basis
for judging their life satisfaction regardless of the situational factors that
had implications for their validity as a basis for judgment. In contrast, un-
happy participants adjusted their judgments to compensate for the effects
of these factors. Perhaps both happy and unhappy participants spontane-
ously considered the affect they were experiencing as a potential basis for
judgment. However, whereas happy participants concluded that these feel-
ings were a sufficient basis for judging without thinking about situational
factors that might have influenced them, unhappy participants considered
that an assessment of their feelings per se was insufficient and took situa-
tional factors into account as well.

2. Judgments of Self-Worth

Estimates of self-worth, like estimates of life satisfaction, may typi-


cally be based on feelings. These feelings are likely to be estimated by
either (a) retrieving a previously formed concept of oneself with which af-
fective reactions have become associated through learning, (b) recalling
descriptive self-knowledge to which affective reactions have become condi-
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 355

tioned and combining the implications of these reactions to arrive at an


overall estimate of one’s feelings; and (c) assessing the implications of the
transitory affect one happens to be experiencing for reasons that may or
may not actually be relevant. If a previously formed concept of “self” exists
and is activated by the request to evaluate one’s self-worth, the affective re-
actions elicited by this concept might be used as a basis for judgment. If
such a concept has not previously been formed, however, and if the affec-
tive reactions based on descriptive self-knowledge take time to compute,
the transitory affect one happens to be experiencing for other reasons
should normally be activated more quickly and, therefore, is more likely to
be used.
The aforementioned study by Levine et al. (1994) bears on this possibil-
ity. In this study, the descriptive implications of participants’ recalled expe-
riences only affected their judgments of competence in the domain to
which these experiences were relevant. However, participants’ estimates of
their global self-esteem were influenced by the affect elicited by the life
events they had recalled regardless of its descriptive implications. In terms
of our conceptualization, this suggests that participants in Levine et al.’s
study did not have a previously formed concept of themselves easily acces-
sible in memory. Therefore, they based their judgments on the affect they
were experiencing at the time, regardless of whether or not the event that
elicited the affect was self relevant.

3. Trait Judgments
Judgments of the specific traits one possesses are more likely to be
based on descriptive rather than affective criteria. The processes that un-
derlie these judgments are summarized in Fig. 11.3b. Specifically, people
who are asked if they have a specific trait may recall and report a previ-
ously formed concept of themselves with respect to this trait. Alternatively,
they may infer the trait from the descriptive implications of trait-relevant
self-knowledge that they have acquired (e.g., behaviors that exemplify the
trait, descriptions of oneself by others, etc.)
For affective reactions to have an informational influence on trait judg-
ments, mediating computations must be performed in order to transform
these reactions into descriptive terms. For example, people who experience
negative affect might judge themselves to be incompetent based on the
implicational molecule

[I am incompetent; I feel badly about myself].

The retrieval and use of this molecule, however, is likely to take longer than
computations based on descriptive criteria. This is particularly true if a
trait-relevant experience is easily accessible in memory at the time of judg-
356 CHAPTER 11

ment. Levine et al.’s (1994) findings, described earlier, are consistent with
this hypothesis. That is, the descriptive implications of participants’ re-
called life experiences were used as a basis for judgments of attributes to
which they were relevant. The affective implications of recalled experi-
ences only influenced judgments of attributes in a domain to which the ex-
periences were unrelated.
The implications of the performance-feedback model become of interest
in this context. If trait judgments are computed more quickly on the basis of
descriptive criteria than on the basis of affective criteria, people who expe-
rience positive affect should be likely to infer that these criteria are suffi-
cient, whereas people who experience negative effect are likely to consider
additional (e.g., affective) criteria. Thus, in contrast to judgments of life sat-
isfaction and self-worth, trait inferences are more likely to be influenced by
negative affect than by positive affect.

Communication and Persuasion

Suppose people read a persuasive communication for the purpose of decid-


ing if the position it advocates is valid. They are likely to have an initial im-
pression of the position’s validity position before they evaluate the commu-
nication’s contents. This impression could be based on the source of the
message, on surface features of the communication itself (e.g., writing
style), or on a previously formed attitude toward the position in question. If
people who have made formed this impression ask themselves if it is an ap-
propriate basis for accepting the position advocated, they should be more
inclined to answer this question affirmatively if they are happy than if they
are sad. This has two implications. First, happy persons are more likely
than unhappy persons to rely on the source of a message as a basis for ac-
cepting the position advocated. Second, happy persons are less inclined
than sad persons to make a careful evaluation of the arguments contained
in a message. Consequently, their acceptance of the position advocated is
less likely to be influenced by the quality of these arguments. Support for
the first hypothesis has been obtained by Roselli (1995), and the second hy-
pothesis is consistent with results of several studies described previously
(Bless et al., 1990; Mackie &Worth, 1989).
A performance-feedback conceptualization of these results suggests two
contingencies, however. First, the different cognitive activities performed
by happy and unhappy persons should only occur if these persons per-
ceive their feelings to have implications for the validity of their initial im-
pression. If participants attribute their feelings to other, impression-irrel-
evant factors, the difference in processing should theoretically not occur.
Results reported by Sinclair, Mark, and Clore (1994) confirmed this predic-
tion. They found that the effect of argument strength on participants’ accep-
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 357

tance of a persuasive message was less on sunny days (when participants


were happy) than on rainy days (when they were unhappy). However, call-
ing participants’ attention to the weather (thereby making salient the true
source of their feelings) eliminated this difference.
Second, our analysis assumes that recipients’ objective at the time they
read the message is to evaluate the validity of the position being advo-
cated. In contrast, suppose persons have an enjoyment objective. Then,
precisely the opposite influence of affect might occur. The aforementioned
study by Wegener et al. (1995), suggesting that happy persons are more in-
fluenced by the quality of arguments in a message than other participants
when they are led to believe that the message will be enjoyable, confirms
this possibility.

Accuracy

The performance-feedback conceptualization can apply to judgments of


physical stimuli as well as social ones. People who are called upon to judge
a stimulus may spontaneously make a holistic appraisal of the stimulus at
the time they are first exposed to it before they scrutinize its individual fea-
tures. They may then ask themselves if this appraisal provides a sufficient
basis for judgments. To this extent, happy individuals should be more likely
than unhappy ones to base their judgments on this initial appraisal alone.
One implication of this is that when accurate judgments are likely to re-
quire a careful analysis of the individual stimulus features happy partici-
pants are less likely to be accurate than unhappy ones. Evidence reported
by Sinclair and Mark (1992), showing that happy participants were less ac-
curate than sad participants in estimating the correlation between two vari-
ables on the basis of scatter plots, confirms this speculation.

Behavior in Nonlaboratory Situations

Many situations arise outside the laboratory in which persons’ behavioral


decisions are likely to be mediated by their feelings about the behavior and
its implications. Students who prepare for an exam must decide if they have
studied long enough. A person who wants to ask someone for a date must
decide if it is the right time to do so. Or, a person who wishes to buy a car
must decide if he or she has enough information about it to make a deci-
sion. In such instances, people should stop studying earlier, ask persons for
a date sooner, and make a purchasing decision more quickly, if they feel
happy than if they do not.
For similar reasons, happy persons may be more inclined to behave im-
pulsively, or in ways that upon reflection they might consider undesirable.
A series of studies by Forgas (1998) are interesting to consider in this con-
358 CHAPTER 11

text. In three studies, participants were asked to indicate how they would
phrase a verbal request in a hypothetical social interaction. It seems rea-
sonable to suppose that people who want another person to do something
(e.g., to repay a loan) will spontaneously generate a verbal phrasing of the
request that corresponds directly to the desired action (e.g., “Give me the
money you owe me”) and may implicitly ask themselves if it is appropriate
to express the request in these terms. If they answer this question posi-
tively, they are likely to alter the phrasing in a way that corresponds to nor-
mative standards of politeness. Otherwise, they might not. If this is so, the
performance-feedback conceptualization we propose suggests that happy
persons are more likely to express their requests impolitely than unhappy
persons are. This, in fact, is what Forgas (1998) found. Although his studies
were performed in the laboratory, they seem likely to generalize to other
situations as well.
It would nevertheless be hazardous to conclude that happy persons are
generally less likely to engage in extensive information processing than un-
happy persons are. This difference should theoretically exist only when in-
dividuals have an implicit performance objective. In nonlaboratory situa-
tions, information processing is often performed for enjoyment. In these
circumstances, the performance-feedback implies that happy persons will
persevere longer, and will process information more analytically, than sad
persons will. Thus, for example, happy individuals might work harder than
sad individuals on crossword puzzles, and may read news articles in rela-
tively greater depth. Moreover, they might make less hasty decisions about
other persons on the basis of their initial impressions of these persons, in
contrast to results observed in the laboratory (Isbell et al., 1998). The possi-
bilities, which are not implied by other conceptualizations of the influence
of affect on performance, should be kept in mind when drawing conclusions
on the basis of experimental research in which performance objectives are
implicitly emphasized.

AFFECT, ATTITUDES, AND BEHAVIOR

As Thurstone (1959) assumed, attitudes are often expressions of the affec-


tive reactions we experience toward a person, object, event, or social pol-
icy. To this extent, the situational and informational factors that influence
the use of affect as information have direct implications for the determi-
nants of attitude formation and change. However, much of the theoretical
and empirical interest in this topic derives from the assumption that atti-
tudes provide the basis for behavioral decisions. In fact, there are many
contingencies on the validity of this assumption (cf. Fazio, 1986; Fishbein &
Ajzen, 1975; Miniard & Cohen, 1981). In light of the centrality of the attitude
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 359

construct in social psychological research, however, the influence of affect


in attitude formation and change deserves special attention.
In fact, the role of affect in attitude formation and change has already
been discussed in several earlier sections of this chapter, and does not re-
quire reiteration. Here, we attempt to outline more formally the processes
that underlie the construction of an attitude and the situational and infor-
mational factors that influence it. Empirical evidence bearing on this analy-
sis is then described.

General Considerations

The ultimate objective of most persuasive communications is to influence


recipients to behave in a way that the communicator considers to be desir-
able (to purchase a particular product, to endorse a social policy, or to stop
smoking, etc.). However, it is useful to distinguish between two types of
communications that could be constructed for this purpose. One type at-
tempts to alter a person’s beliefs, or estimates of the likelihood that an
event will occur, or that a particular proposition is true (e.g., that Ameri-
can’s bombing of Afghanistan has resulted in the deaths of thousands of in-
nocent victims, or that air and water pollution will extinguish life on earth
by the end of the 21st century). As suggested in chapter 5 (Wyer &
Hartwick, 1984), communications that are intended to focus on beliefs in a
proposition are likely to emphasize antecedents, that is, propositions about
events that, if they are true, have implications for the truth of the target
proposition. Affective reactions are likely to influence the impact of such a
communication only indirectly, through the extent to which they influence
the ability or motivation to evaluate the arguments conveyed in the com-
munication or their implications for the validity of the target proposition
(for evidence that affect can have this influence, see Fiedler, 1988.)
The other type of message, which is of primary concern in the present
context, is intended to influence an attitude, or evaluation of a person, ob-
ject, or event (Americas bombing of Afghanistan, recycling, etc.). These
messages are likely to focus on consequences of the event or state of affairs
toward which the attitude is directed. The cognitions that typically underlie
the construction of an attitude are captured by the model proposed by
Fishbein (1963) or, more recently, Fishbein and Ajzen (1975). One’s attitude
toward a behavior, for example (Ab), is captured by the equation

Ab = Sbi ei , [11.1]

Where bi is the belief that the behavior will have a consequence i, and ei is
the evaluation of this consequence. (Not all possible consequences of the
behavior are taken into account, of course, but only a subset that is most
360 CHAPTER 11

“salient” at the time the attitude is formed.) To this extent, a communica-


tion should be effective in changing an attitude if it either increases beliefs
that the behavior has consequences that the recipient considers to be de-
sirable or, alternatively, increases the evaluation of consequences that the
recipient already believes are likely to occur.
Affective reactions are likely to play a quite different role in the process-
ing of attitude-focused communications than in the processing of belief-
focused messages. Moreover, this role may depend in part on whether the
attitude in question is based on hedonic or utilitarian criteria (Zanna &
Rempel, 1988). When the criterion is hedonic, the role of affect could de-
pend on whether (a) recipients think sufficiently about the consequences
described in a message for the affect associated with these consequences
to be elicited, (b) whether they can effectively combine the implications of
these consequences into a single attitudinal response in the manner speci-
fied in Equation 11.1, and (c) whether they can distinguish this affect from
the feelings they are experiencing for other, unrelated reasons. Once an at-
titude is formed in this manner it may be reactivated at the time the course
of action is actually contemplated (see Fazio, 1986, for a discussion of the
factors that influence this activation).
As noted earlier, however, the specific consequences of the position ad-
vocated in a communication may not be the only determinants of the atti-
tude that recipients report. Affect could also be stimulated by the intrinsic
pleasantness or unpleasantness of the behavior being advocated, inde-
pendently of any specific information about it. (The thought of taking com-
prehensive examinations, for example, might spontaneously elicit negative
affect independently of any specific consequences the activity might have.)
Finally, extraneous affect that recipients happen to be experiencing may be
misattributed to their feelings about this activity. Affect from all of these
sources could contribute to people’s perceptions of their attitude toward
the behavior being advocated.

Experimental Evidence

The role of affect in responses to attitude-focused persuasive messages was


evaluated in a series of studies by Albarracin and Wyer (2001). We told par-
ticipants we were concerned with how people process information in natu-
ral settings, and that to do this, we would like them both to transmit and re-
ceive information in a simulated coffee shop situation. On this pretense, we
induced them to feel happy or unhappy by asking them to write a letter to a
friend describing a positive or negative life experience. Then, we asked par-
ticipants to read a communication, ostensibly taken from a local newspa-
per, which summarized either strong or weak arguments in support of insti-
tuting comprehensive examinations and urging recipients to vote in favor
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 361

of the exams in a forthcoming referendum. Participants read the message in


the presence of background noise similar to that encountered in a coffee
shop. In low-distraction conditions, the noise was of low volume and not par-
ticularly disturbing. In high-distraction conditions, however, it consisted of a
high volume get-acquainted conversation between two students of the sort
that might take place in a coffee shop situation. Participants after reading
the message reported their attitudes toward instituting the exams and their
intentions to vote for them. Then, they reported their beliefs that the vari-
ous consequences described in the message would occur and the desirabil-
ity of these consequences.

1. Effects of Distraction on the Processing


of Message Content
We expected that the influence of the persuasive message would result
from cognitive activities at four different stages of processing: the computa-
tion of beliefs that the consequences specified in the message would occur,
evaluations of the desirability of these consequences, an integration of
these beliefs and evaluations to form an attitude in the manner described
by Equation 11.2, and the transformation of this attitude into a behavioral
intention. We further expected that the effects of distraction would be more
evident at later stages of processing (e.g., the computation of an attitude or
behavior intention) than at earlier ones. This was in fact the case.
The effect of argument strength on judgments was inferred from the dif-
ference between judgments when arguments were strong and judgments
when arguments were weak. These differences are shown in the top half of
Table 11.5 for judgments that were presumably formed at each stage of
processing. Distraction had a significant effect on the impact of argument
strength on both attitudes and behavioral intentions, which were formed at
later stages of processing. However, it had a much smaller effect on the im-
pact of argument strength on evaluations of individual consequences (ei ),
and had no effect at all on its impact of argument strength on beliefs that
the consequences would occur (bi ).

2. Impact of Distraction on the Influence


of Extraneous Affect
If participants’ evaluations of the consequences mentioned in the mes-
sage are based on the affective reactions that were elicited by thinking
about them, Equation 11.1 should describe the results of integrating the im-
plications of these reactions. However, distraction could not only prevent
participants from performing this integration but could also prevent them
from distinguishing between their affective reactions to the consequences
and the affect they are experiencing for other reasons. If this is, so, the ex-
362 CHAPTER 11

TABLE 11.5
Effects of Argument Strength and Extraneous Affect on Behavioral
Intentions, Attitudes, and Beliefs and Evaluations of Specific
Behavioral Outcomes as a Function of Distraction

Outcome Outcome Attitudes Behavior


Beliefs (bi ) Evaluations (ei ) (Ab) Intentions

Effect of argument Strength


High distraction 2.10a 3.22 0.62 1.77
Low distraction 2.08 4.37 2.61 3.91
F(1, 73) <1 2.23 5.82* 3.69*
Effect of affect
High distraction 0.75b 1.48 1.79 2.09
Low distraction –0.92 –0.52 –0.73 –0.60
F(1, 73) 4.87* 6.80* 9.39* 5.79*

Note. Adapted from Albarracin and Wyer (2001).


aThe effect of argument strength is inferred from the difference between judgments when ar-

guments were strong and judgments when arguments were weak.


bThe effect of affect is inferred from the difference between judgments when participants

were feeling happy and judgments when they were not.

traneous affect that participants were experiencing should have greater ef-
fect. This was also the case, as shown in the bottom half of Table 11.5. When
distraction was high, extraneous affect had an positive influence on not
only participants’ attitudes and intentions but also their estimates of the
likelihood and desirability of individual consequences. When distraction
was low, however, extraneous affect had slight contrast effects on these
measures.

3. Reciprocal Effects of Attitudes


on Outcome Beliefs and Evaluations

When participants were not distracted, they presumably computed be-


liefs and evaluations associated with each consequence described in the
persuasive message and then integrated these estimates to form an attitude
in the manner implied by Equation 11.1. To this extent, their outcome be-
liefs and evaluations should have multiplicative effects on their attitudes.
Under high-distraction conditions, however, participants presumably based
their attitudes on the extraneous affect they were experiencing rather than
the content of the persuasive message. Having done so, they may have at-
tempted to justify the affect-based attitude they have formed using proc-
esses suggested by McGuire and McGuire (1991; see also Janis & King,
1954). For example, they may engage in rationalization (evaluating the de-
sirability of the consequences in a manner that is evaluatively consistent
with their attitude) and wishful thinking (increasing their beliefs that these
THE ROLE OF AFFECT 363

consequences would occur). These latter effects, however, should be inde-


pendent.
These speculations were supported by supplementary regression analy-
ses of attitudes as a function of predicted values based on Equation 11.1
(i.e., Sbi ei ) and indices of beliefs and evaluations considered separately (Sbi
and Sei ). Under low-distraction conditions, the multiplicative effects of be-
liefs and evaluations implied by Equation 11.1 accounted for 6% of the vari-
ance in attitudes over and above the effects of beliefs and evaluations con-
sidered independently. Under high-distraction conditions, however, the
multiplicative effects contributed only a trivial amount (.01%) of the vari-
ance over and above the component measures.
In summary, Albarracin and Wyer’s (2001) research suggested that when
participants have ample time and motivation to think carefully about the
content of an attitude-focused persuasive communication, they may assess
its implications for the likelihood and desirability of alternative conse-
quences of the position advocated in the message, and then may integrate
them in a manner suggested by Fishbein and Ajzen (1975). When they are
distracted, however, they are more likely to base their attitudes on their
affective reactions to the position advocated independently of the commu-
nication content. Moreover, these attitudes, once formed, can have recipro-
cal effects on the beliefs and evaluations associated with specific conse-
quences of the position being advocated in order to justify this attitude,
engaging in wishful thinking and rationalization of a sort similar to that sug-
gested by McGuire and McGuire (1991).

FINAL COMMENTS

As noted at the outset, people’s affective reactions can come into play in
judgments and behavioral decisions in virtually every domain of social ex-
perience, both in and outside the laboratory. The inordinate length of this
chapter testifies to the diversity of its possible effects and the conditions in
which they occur. We have argued, however, that affective reactions per se
exert their influence primarily through the information they provide about
persons, objects, and events to which these reactions are directed, and the
likelihood that one’s information-processing objectives have been satisfac-
torily attained.
The performance-feedback conceptualization suggested by Martin et
al.’s (1993) findings can account for many effects of affect on judgments and
behavior. It therefore seems worthy of continued consideration in future re-
search. Its ultimately utility is nonetheless something of a promissory note.
That is, a rigorous application of the conceptualization requires a task anal-
ysis of the cognitive processing steps that underlie a judgment or behav-
364 CHAPTER 11

ioral decision and the mental operations that are performed at each step.
An example of this analysis was provided in our analysis of the impact of af-
fect on self-judgments. Similar analyses of other information processing sit-
uations may be fruitful.
Our analysis of the influence of affect on judgments and behavior has
largely been independent of our discussion in previous chapters. As noted,
however, the stories that people write about themselves, as well as stories
they encounter in conversations or in the media, are very likely to elicit af-
fective reactions. To this extent, many of the inference process that are
based on narrative representations of knowledge (see chaps. 9 and 10)
could be based in large part on affect rather than the substantive implica-
tions of the information per se. The impact of pictures and visual images on
narrative-based processing could likewise be mediated by their influences
on people’s affective reactions and the use of these reactions as bases for
judgment. Therefore, although we have not explicated these possibilities in
this chapter, the relevance of the phenomena we have described to issues
raised elsewhere in this volume is hopefully apparent.
C H A P T E R

12
Epilogue: The Book, the Author,
and Philosophical Ruminations

The Book

The information we acquire in daily life can come from many sources: di-
rect observation, conversations with friends and acquaintances, movies
and television, newspapers, and books. Some of this information is about
unknown or fictitious people and events. In many cases, however, we al-
ready know a lot about the things that are described, and we spontane-
ously recognize the information as either true or false. When information is
conveyed in pictures or is acquired through observation, we often form vi-
sual images and retain them in memory as part of our knowledge about
their referents. However, verbal descriptions of events can stimulate the
construction of visual images as well. Finally, the information we receive
can often elicit affective reactions both at the time it is acquired and when
we are later reminded of the events to which it refers, and these reactions
can be used as a basis for evaluating the events and the people or objects
involved in them. The information from all of these sources, and in all of
these modalities, combines to form our accumulated knowledge about the
world in which we live, and serves as a basis for our judgments and behav-
ioral decisions.
This volume has provided a conceptualization of the way in which this
information is comprehended and stored in memory and how it is later re-
trieved and used. Much of our discussion has focused on the construction
and use of narratives (that is, temporally and thematically organized se-
quences of events that are stored in memory as a unit). These mental repre-
sentations include episode models of specific events that we happen to en-

365
366 CHAPTER 12

counter, linguistic representations of these events that we form in the


course of communicating about them, and implicit theories that we use to
understand our experiences and to construe their antecedents and conse-
quences. In conceptualizing the role of narrative representations in com-
prehension and judgment, however, two other ingredients of real-world
knowledge were taken into account: the visual images that people con-
struct on the basis of their experiences and the affective reactions that the
experiences elicit.
Although my concern has been with the way in which information about
real people and events is comprehended and used in daily life, the research I
have brought to bear on these matters has largely been conducted in the lab-
oratory. Nevertheless, the processes identified in the research seem likely to
generalize to daily life situations. The comprehension and validation proc-
esses described in chapter 4 were confirmed empirically using statements
about actual people and events with which participants were already quite
familiar. The conceptualization of episode models was applied in understand-
ing not only people’s comprehension of information about hypothetical indi-
viduals (chap. 5) but also their representations of their own experiences and
those of close acquaintances (chap. 6). Our discussion of the comprehension
of information in a social context (chap. 7) emphasized the processes of iden-
tifying the pragmatic implications of information of the sort one encounters
in newspapers or acquires in informal conversation. It also examined the cog-
nitive processes that underlie reactions to jokes and other humor-eliciting
experiences of the sort we encounter in social situations outside the labora-
tory (see chap. 8). In discussing inference processes, I examined the role of
both visual images and narrative forms of information in judgments (chap. 9),
and also explored the impact of implicit theories that people construct about
themselves and the world in which they live (chap. 10). This latter discussion
covered research on a wide variety of topics including counterfactual reason-
ing, cultural influences on judgments and behavior, marital satisfaction, and
perceptions of social support.
At the same time, I attempted to place the discussion of these matters in
the context of a general theoretical analysis of social information process-
ing that permits comprehension and judgment phenomena to be inter-
preted within a common conceptual framework. This formulation, which is
captured by a series of formal postulates (for a summary, see Appendix),
has several features in common with the earlier theory proposed by Wyer
and Srull (1989). However, it differs from this theory in ways that increase
its potential applicability to real-world information processing without com-
promising its ability to account for a wide range of phenomena to which the
1989 formulation was applicable.
The formulation I have proposed is broader in scope than most other
theories of social information processing. In fact, theories that focus on
EPILOGUE 367

more circumscribed sets of phenomena can often be viewed as compo-


nents of this formulation. (That is, they specify the operations that are per-
formed by one or another special purpose processing unit and represented
either in a goal schema or in a processing unit’s library.) In this regard,
many recent conceptualizations of social cognition have recognized that
different cognitive processes can underlie responses to information (e.g.,
see Chaiken & Trope, 1999). However, the assumption that several alterna-
tive processes can be brought to bear on a judgment or decision, depend-
ing on social, informational, and individual difference variables that deter-
mine their applicability and relative accessibility, is also a central feature of
both the Wyer and Srull (1989) formulation and the present one.
The proposed conceptualization is not without flaws. For one thing, it is
metaphorical, and does not pretend to be an exact depiction of the physiol-
ogy of the brain. As noted in chapter 1, however, most formulations of infor-
mation processing are inherently metaphorical, and should be judged on
the basis of their utility and not their validity. The present formulation ap-
pears to be a useful one, and establishes directions for future research in
social information processing. If this book stimulates even a few research-
ers to pursue these directions, its objectives will be accomplished.

The Author

In the concluding remarks of his recent book, Constructing social psychology,


Bill McGuire (1999) commented: “It may be best if each of us . . . makes his
or her own way . . . but one’s own way should be taken deliberatively and
egosyntonically, not stumbled into by chance” (p. 432). I wish that I could
say that my own career exemplifies this sage advice. I have, undoubtedly,
made my own way. But this way was hardly deliberative. Even my decision
to become a psychologist was determined by largely fortuitous events. Al-
though my reflections about these events is perhaps less out of place in a
volume that emphasizes the role of narratives than it might otherwise be,
they are likely to be of little interest to anyone but myself. At the risk of
abusing a privilege, however, I would like to take advantage of this opportu-
nity to indulge myself in these reflections.
When I was in high school, I wanted to be either a jazz musician or a
sportswriter. I was discouraged from both pursuits by my father. On one
hand, he pointed out that my skills as a clarinet and saxophone player
would probably qualify me for no better than third chair in a mediocre
dance band. He further argued that to be a sportswriter, I would inevitably
have to start off as a copy boy at a city newspaper and would have to work
my way up gradually over a period of many years. Moreover, he claimed
that this would be true regardless of whether I went to college or not.
Therefore, he argued that if I decided to go to college at all, I should major
368 CHAPTER 12

in something more useful. So, having had my primary options dashed, and
having received a scholarship to Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute, I became
an electrical engineer.
Four years in engineering school did little to stimulate my interest in the
field. Nevertheless, I took a job at Bell Laboratories, which offered me full
salary for going to school 3 days a week and working only 2. Although wind-
ing up 2 years later with a Masters degree, I spent most of my time improv-
ing my table tennis skills and imbibing in the intellectual atmosphere that
pervaded Greenwich Village in the late 1950s. These activities convinced
me that I should get a liberal arts education.
I took a battery of ability and interest tests, which indicated that the only
things for which I was suited were architecture and psychology. I hardly
knew what “psychology” was, having barely escaped a D in my single un-
dergraduate course in the area. I nevertheless decided to apply to graduate
schools in psychology in physical locations I might enjoy, without knowing
anything at all about the schools themselves, and not really thinking that I
might actually go. Inevitably, one school that met my “enjoyment” criterion
was the University of Colorado. The application form, however, listed three
areas that were completely foreign to me: experimental (which sounded
like engineering), clinical (which sounded like medicine) and social–person-
ality. Because I thought I understood what “social” and “personality”
meant, I checked the third area as my preference. By chance, this was the
one area at Colorado in which Public Health Service fellowships were avail-
able, and I was offered one. My bluff being called, I accepted it, knowing
nothing at all about what I was getting into and not really caring, but assum-
ing that I would have the opportunity to expose myself to liberal arts in gen-
eral.
This was in fact the case. The graduate program at Colorado in 1960 was
hardly rigorous, and I was able to get through the program in 3 years with a
total of only 27 hours of psychology (most of which was for thesis and inde-
pendent study). I actually audited more courses in humanities, sociology,
history, and philosophy than I took in psychology. What Colorado lacked in
substance, however, it made up for in stimulation, due largely to OJ Harvey
(one of the most inspirational individuals I had ever met) and Bill Scott (my
dissertation advisor, who gave me an appreciation for the need to think rig-
orously as well as innovatively). In general, Colorado’s reactions to my
graduate school career were probably exemplified by one faculty member’s
prediction that unless I was always right, I would never succeed as a psy-
chologist because I never listened to anything that anyone else was saying.
I obviously haven’t always been right. Whether that reflects a change in my
chronic disposition, however, is debatable.
I spent an additional year at Colorado in 1962 with Glenn Terrell, a devel-
opmental psychologist and Associate Dean, on research on nonintellective
EPILOGUE 369

correlates of scholastic achievement. This was a year of political upheaval


in Colorado, leading to the election of an ultra-conservative Board of
Trustees and, consequently, the resignation of the entire University admin-
istration. Terrell moved to the University of Illinois at Chicago Circle to be-
come Dean of Arts and Sciences (later Dean of Faculties). I had never seri-
ously thought of an academic career, assuming that I would wind up back in
industry doing human factors research. However, I was offered a job at
the University of Iowa Institute for Child Behavior and Development, which
didn’t seem to care whether I knew anything about children, either person-
ally or professionally. So, I accepted it.
At that time, Spence learning theory dominated psychology at Iowa.
“Mental representations” of knowledge were not in vogue. After 2 years of
indoctrination, I escaped to rejoin Terrell at Chicago Circle to complete the
research on academic achievement and to teach part time in Psychology.
Three years past my PhD, I was still woefully ignorant of theory and re-
search in social psychology. However, I had the good fortunate to have an
office next to Harry Upshaw, who blended the charisma of OJ Harvey with
the rigor of Bill Scott, and who perhaps as much as anyone gave me an ap-
preciation of what social psychology was really all about. Despite this cha-
otic start, and despite being an active participant in the anti-war movement
of the 1960s, I somehow developed a program of research. The four books I
have published over the past three decades are the result.

The Philosophical Ruminations

The four books I have written over the course of the past 30 years have all
concerned one or another aspect of social information processing. This
might give the impression of a deliberative, single-minded approach to psy-
chological research and theorizing. This impression would be misleading,
however. Both theoretically and methodologically, I have throughout my ca-
reer simply explored the things I have found intellectually exciting without
giving much thought to the reason for this excitement and how my explora-
tions might fit into the general scheme of things. The fact that they have
turned out to fit such a scheme has been as surprising to me as to anyone.
The specific areas of research in which I’ve been involved have con-
cerned the nonintellective determinants of scholastic achievement, persis-
tence in goal-directed activity, conformity, two-person games, algebraic
models of impression formation, stereotyping, belief organization and
change, response language effects on judgments along category scales,
emotional communication, knowledge accessibility, the mental representa-
tion of persons and social events, pragmatic factors in social communica-
tion, humor elicitation, communication and persuasion, country of origin ef-
fects on consumer judgments, affect and cognition, and cross-cultural
370 CHAPTER 12

influences on decision making. Much of this work was inspired by students


whose diverse interests and ideas captured my imagination. It probably
takes a lot of imagination to identify the conceptual and methodological un-
derpinnings of this work.
However, there is usually a reason why something seems “interesting,”
even if one is not aware of why this is the case. The reason may only be
identified after the fact, on reflection. This is certainly the case with me.
The common thread that connects my interests is a concern with the men-
tal processes that mediate judgments and behavior. These processes oper-
ate at several stages: attention, comprehension, the organization and stor-
age of information in memory, inference, and response generation. Almost
all social phenomena implicate one or another of these stages. Correspond-
ingly, I have found myself interested in almost everything. However, the re-
alization that this is what brings it all together has been a personal discov-
ery to me, and was not the result of a premeditated approach or carefully
thought out research paradigm.
Having said this, I have had a desire to develop comprehensive concep-
tualizations of social phenomena that not only integrate a lot of diverse em-
pirical findings but are sufficiently rigorous to permit the derivation of new,
empirically testable hypotheses. This motive has led me to think both
broadly and formally about the cognitive underpinnings of memory, judg-
ment, and behavior. This penchant for formalism as well as breadth has
sometimes led to overly grandiose conceptualizations, composed of mind-
boggling sets of postulates and assumptions that few colleagues have had
the stamina to digest. But I’ve found it hard to think in any other way.
Three somewhat diverging comments I encountered early in my profes-
sional life have remained with me over the years and have had a major im-
pact. In an informal graduate seminar at Colorado, Nan Wertheimer, an epi-
demiologist, observed that people should attempt to avoid becoming
committed to any particular theory for as long as possible, because once
that commitment was made, their contribution to psychology was over.
That is, they would spend the rest of their lives defending their theory and
would blind themselves to new ideas and approaches.
The second, which seems contradictory on the surface, comes from a
chapter by McGuire in 1972. He likened the search for knowledge to that of
a boy who is lost in the woods:

If the boy strikes out in any one direction and keeps making progress in that
direction, it is likely that he will eventually find his way out of the woods. It
might be that if he had pursued a different line of progress, he would have
gotten out even sooner, but almost any line of advance will suffice if pursued
sufficiently long. The only real danger is that one will not persist in any direc-
tion but will wander around at random and never get out of the woods. Analo-
gously, if the empirical scientist is lost in a complex area, his pursuing the im-
EPILOGUE 371

plications of any reasonable paradigm in a steady direction will probably led


him to some ultimate clarification of the area. If in stead he drops each theory
as soon as the slightest negative evidence crops up, there results the danger
that he will wander around in circles and not obtain any clarification. The re-
searcher who keeps the faith and pursues his paradigm to ultimate enlighten-
ment may find that there is a much better theory he could have chosen ini-
tially. But his persistence will also have demonstrated the truth of Blake’s
proverb that “if the fool would persist in his folly, he would become wise.
(p. 138).

Finally, I read an article in graduate school by Edward Tolman, one of the


foremost animal learning theorists of his era, whose views, radical at the
time, have since been implicitly vindicated by both cognitive and social
psychologists. In reviewing his career, he noted that he, like McGuire’s boy
in the woods, might not have taken the most direct route to understanding,
and that if he had it to do over again, he might have taken a different path.
However, he had had fun along the way, and that was what mattered.
All three of these comments have had an impact on my philosophy of
life, both professionally and personally. Following McGuire, I have tried to
develop a conceptual perspective on social phenomena to guide my theo-
retical and empirical understanding of both new and old information. At the
same time, I have tried to follow Nan Wertheimer’s advice not to identify
too closely with this perspective, not to take myself too seriously, to take
my theories with a grain of salt and to challenge them as harshly as I chal-
lenge others’, and to be receptive to new and better ways of viewing the
world. Finally, I, like Tolman, might do things differently if I had them to do
over. (Indeed, I might choose to ignore my father’s advice and try my hand
at sports writing or clarinet playing.) However, I have also had fun along the
way, and I, again like Tolman, think that this is what really matters.

A Debt of Gratitude

Many individuals have had a major influence on my career. Some are


more obvious than others. Unquestionably one of the major influences
has been Bill McGuire. His empirical and theoretical work in both cogni-
tive organization and persuasion was among the most exciting I have ever
encountered, and captivated me at an early stage in my career. Moreover,
his encouragement to me while serving as the editor of JPSP instilled the
confidence I needed at a time when I was conflicted with many self-doubts.
Although I have personally met McGuire less than a half dozen times in
my life (two of which came from festschrifts in one another’s honor that
we attended), I consider him to be my primary mentor, whose influence
on me over the years has extended far beyond the specific research and
theorizing I have done.
372 CHAPTER 12

I am also in debt to Norman Anderson, who also encouraged me at this


early point in my career. Although my approach to understanding informa-
tion processing ultimately diverged from Norman’s, his work as well as
McGuire’s stimulated my interest in the underpinnings of social judgment.
Anderson’s most enduring influence on my career was rather fortuitous,
however. He conducted a 3-week workshop at La Jolla in 1973. During the
course of this workshop, Tom Ostrom, Dave Hamilton, Reid Hastie, Ebbe
Ebbesen and I, none of whom had ever before met, became good friends as
well as admirers of one another’s work. Stimulated by our intellectual ex-
changes during the workshop, we began to meet informally at irregular in-
tervals over the next several years (usually in Ostrom’s gigantic house), to
discuss alternative approaches to understanding person impression forma-
tion. (This group, along with Don Carlston and Thom Srull who joined later,
were the original nucleus of the Person Memory Interest Group, now over
70 members strong, which continues to flourish.) These weekend-long dis-
cussions established a new direction to my theorizing and my research on
the mental representation of social information.
During the same period, I had occasion to serve as a journal editor and,
in this capacity, became a fan of both Tory Higgins and Jim Sherman. The
first stimulated my interest in input processes (e.g., the role of knowledge
accessibility) and the second stimulated my interest in output processes
(the cognitive determinants of overt behavior). More recently, Jerry Clore
provided similar stimulation to my interest in affect. Their influence, as well
as the influence of Ostrom et al., is readily apparent in my work over the
past two decades.
However, the major influences on my work over the past 25 years have
been the graduate and postdoctoral students with whom I had contact at
the University of Illinois. Don Carlston and John Lynch, early sources of
stimulation, both have become outstanding researchers in psychology and
consumer behavior, respectively. In 1980, a small group of students consist-
ing of Thom Srull, Sallie Gordon, and Jon Hartwick began meeting weekly to
exchange ongoing research they were conducting in various areas related
to social cognition. This group grew over the years to become the Univer-
sity of Illinois Social Cognition Group, a consortium of faculty, postdoctoral
students, and graduate students who met informally each week to ex-
change theoretical ideas and empirical findings in social cognition. My par-
ticipation in this group, and my collaboration with its individual members,
has unquestionably been the most personally rewarding experience of my
professional life.
Although all of the members of this group over the 20 years of its exis-
tence are too numerous to mention, there are several to whom I am particu-
larly indebted. Lenny Martin, Norbert Schwarz, and Fritz Strack, who visited
Illinois as postdoctoral students, have since become leaders in the field. I
EPILOGUE 373

continue to be profoundly influenced by their work. Thom Srull, first as stu-


dent and then as colleague, was a major collaborator for many years. Other
students whose contributions to my career are particularly noteworthy in-
clude Galen Bodenhausen, Lee Budesheim, Bob Fuhrman, Alan Lambert,
Victor Ottati, and Dave Trafimow. Dolores Albarracin, Deborah Gruenfeld,
Linda Isbell, and L. J. Shrum were also major collaborators. Their research
on communication and persuasion, the pragmatic implications of informa-
tion, affect, and perceptions of social reality, respectively, has had an obvi-
ous impact on my own. Rashmi Adaval, Stan Colcombe, and Eric Man-
kowski, in quite different ways, stimulated my interest in the role of
narratives in information processing. Most of these individuals have been
close friends as well as stimulating colleagues, making our collaboration
doubly rewarding.
It has been a long trip, and the journey is not quite ended. However,
these individuals and others too numerous to mention have made the trip
exciting and enjoyable beyond belief, and I will always be in their debt.
A P P E N D I X

Summary of Postulates

Retrieval Postulates (chap. 2)

Postulate 2.1. Each knowledge representation that is formed, either in


the course of comprehension or in the course of higher level, goal-directed
processing, constitutes a separate unit of knowledge that is stored inde-
pendently of other knowledge units.

Postulate 2.2. The activation of a set of stimulus features causes all


knowledge representations that contain these features to resonate. The res-
onance of a given representation, k, increases with (a) the similarity of its
features to those in the stimulus set and (b) the length of time the stimulus
set has been activated. The subjective similarity of the stimulus features to
the representation, and thus the rate at which its resonance increases, is
estimated by the quantity:

n( pI k)
Res(k) = ,
n( k)

where n(k) is the number of features in the representation and n( pI k) is


the number of features that are common to both the representation and the
stimulus set. If the resonance reaches a threshold value, T(k), the represen-
tation is activated.

374
SUMMARY OF POSTULATES 375

Postulate 2.3. (a) If two or more representations resonate with a given


set of probe cues, the one that reaches threshold most quickly is identified.
(b) If several representations reach threshold simultaneously, a composite
of the features is activated. The weight of each feature in the composite is a
positive function of the proportion of times it occurs in the set of represen-
tations involved.

Postulate 2.4. If a knowledge representation has resonated with a set of


probe cues, this resonance does not dissipate immediately but rather, de-
cays gradually over time.

Postulate 2.5. The activation threshold of a knowledge representation


in memory, T(k), is an increasing function of the number of times the repre-
sentation has been activated in the past.

Sufficiency Postulate (chap. 3)

Postulate 3.1. People retrieve and use only the amount of information
that they consider to be sufficient for attaining the processing objective
they are pursuing at the time. The information they use is likely to be the
first goal-relevant information that comes to mind or, alternatively, permits
their objective to be attained most quickly and easily.

Comprehension and Verification Postulates (chap. 4)

Postulate 4.1. Event and episode models are mental simulations of an


event, or sequence of events, that are temporally and spatially constrained.
These models are constructed spontaneously in the course of comprehend-
ing events that occur at a specifiable (although not necessarily specified)
time and place.

Postulate 4.2. An event model can consist of both a mental image and a
linguistically coded description of the event or state of affairs to which it re-
fers. Although the image component of the model is obligatory, the linguis-
tic component is optional.

Postulate 4.3. The subject and predicate identified by the Parser are in-
dependently used as probe cues of memory, resonating with all of the men-
tal representations that contain them (see Postulate 2.2). In each case, the
representation whose resonance level reaches threshold most quickly is
most likely to be identified.
376 APPENDIX

Postulate 4.4. If a memory search activates a previously formed knowl-


edge representation whose features include both the subject probe cues
and the predicate probe cues, the new information is spontaneously recog-
nized as redundant with prior knowledge and a new representation is not
formed.

Postulate 4.5. If no previously formed model (i.e., knowledge unit) re-


fers to both the subject and predicate of a target statement, the features
that are activated by the target’s subject are compared to a weighted com-
posite of the features associated with the target’s predicate. This compari-
son yields a global estimate of similarity, S. A new situation model is formed
if either (a) S is greater than a minimum threshold value, TC, or (b) the tar-
get’s subject contains a subset of features that are common to the subject
of all models activated by the probe. In the latter case, the new model is
constructed by combining the composite of features activated by the sub-
ject and the composite of features activated by the predicate. In all cases,
however, only the features that are weighted heavily in the composite are in-
cluded in the new model that is constructed.

Postulate 4.6. A statement is comprehended spontaneously if it is re-


dundant with prior knowledge or if a new model is constructed of it. If nei-
ther is the case, comprehension of the statement is not spontaneous, but
requires (Executor-controlled) goal-directed processing.

Postulate 4.7. A statement is spontaneously recognized as true in the


course of comprehending it if (a) a situation model of the event or state de-
scribed already exists in memory and (b) no tag has been attached to the
model that designates it as false.

Postulate 4.8. A statement about an event is recognized as true in the


course of comprehending it if the similarity of its subject to those of previ-
ously formed models of the event (S) exceeds an upper threshold, TT . The
statement is identified as false if S is below a lower threshold, TF . If S falls
between TT and TF , the statement is comprehended but its validity is not
spontaneously evaluated.

Postulate 4.9. Spontaneous inferences that a statement is true or false


are transferred to the Work Space along with a representation of the state-
ment that has been formed in the course of comprehending it.
SUMMARY OF POSTULATES 377

Construction of Episode Models (chap. 5)

Postulate 5.1. Once a situation model has been formed, subsequent in-
formation is integrated into the model if and only if this information con-
cerns the same situation as the model or a thematically related one.

Postulate 5.2. When new information requires a modification of an


event or episode model that had been constructed on the basis of prior in-
formation, the original model is retained in memory. However, a second
representation is constructed consisting of a modified version of the first
model along with the implications of the new information.

Humor Elicitation Postulates (chap. 8)

Postulate 8.1. New experiences are spontaneously interpreted in terms


of previously formed event representations (e.g., situation models) with
which they have common features. When more than one alternative knowl-
edge representation is applicable for interpreting an experience, the repre-
sentation that is most easily accessible in memory is typically applied. The
result of this cognitive activity is a newly formed situation model of the
event being comprehended.

Postulate 8.2. Once a mental representation has been formed of an ex-


perience, this representation, along with the concepts and knowledge that
were activated in the course of constructing it, is used to comprehend the-
matically related experiences that occur subsequently.

Postulate 8.3. When information about an event cannot be interpreted


in terms of concepts drawn from the same domain of knowledge that was
applied to previous events, recipients attempt to identify concepts and
knowledge in a different domain that is applicable to both the new event
and the preceding ones. If these concepts can be found, the previously
learned events are reinterpreted in terms of them.

Postulate 8.4. Humor is elicited by a reinterpretation of a stimulus


event only if the features of one or more features of the event are dimin-
ished in value or importance relative to that implied by the original inter-
pretation.

Postulate 8.5. The amount of amusement that is potentially elicited as a


result of reinterpreting a stimulus event is a nonmonotonic (inverted-U)
function of the time and effort that is required to make this interpretation.
378 APPENDIX

Postulate 8.6. The amount of humor that is elicited as a result of rein-


terpreting a stimulus event is a monotonic function of the amount of cogni-
tive elaboration of the event and its implications that occurs subsequent to
its reinterpretation.

1. If recipients’ processing objective at the time is simply to comprehend


and enjoy experiencing the event, cognitive elaboration of the event will typ-
ically increase the humor it elicits.
2. If recipients’ goal is more restricted, the event is elaborated in terms of
its implications for this more specific objective. In this case, cognitive elabo-
ration could either increase, decrease, or have no effect on the amount of hu-
mor elicited, depending on whether the humor-eliciting reinterpretation of
the event is relevant to the attainment of this objective.

Inference Postulate (“Completion Principle”; chap. 10)

Postulate 10.1. If the information available about a specific situation


instantiates all but one of the propositions that compose a molecule, an
instantiation of the remaining proposition will be spontaneously inferred.

Affect Postulates (chap. 11)

Postulate 11.1. Affective reactions may activate a specific affect-


relevant concept that can be used to interpret them. However, affective re-
actions do not spontaneously influence the accessibility in memory of other
similarly valenced semantic concepts and declarative knowledge.

Postulate 11.2. The affective reactions that one experiences, along with
concepts and cognitions that are stimulated by an appraisal of a stimulus
situation, can compose a precondition for a previously learned sequence of
responses (i.e., a cognitive production). This response sequence may be ac-
tivated spontaneously, with little conscious cognitive mediation, under con-
ditions in which the precondition is met.

Postulate 11.3. When people engage in behavior for the purpose of at-
taining an external goal and objective criteria for inferring the attainment of
this goal do not exist, they use the affect they are experiencing to infer
whether they feel that the strategy they have used in pursuit of this goal,
and the outputs they have generated by employing it, are appropriate.
Therefore, they are more likely to infer that they have met the criterion for
satisfactory performance if they are experiencing positive affect than if they
are not.
SUMMARY OF POSTULATES 379

Postulate 11.4. When people’s primary reason for engaging in behavior


is enjoyment, they use the affect they are experiencing as a basis for infer-
ring this enjoyment. Therefore, they will continue the activity longer if they
are experiencing positive affect than if they are not.
References

Aaker, J. L., & Lee, A. (2001). I seek pleasures, we avoid pains: The role of self-regulatory goals in
information processing and persuasion. Journal of Consumer Research, 27, 33–49.
Abelson, R. P. (1959). Modes of resolution of belief dilemmas. Conflict Resolution, 3, 343–352.
Abelson, R. P. (1976). Script processing in attitude formation and decision making. In J. S. Carroll
& J. W. Payne (Eds.), Cognition and social behavior (pp. 33–46). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.
Abelson, R. P., Kinder, D. R., Peters, M. D., & Fiske, S. T. (1982). Affective and semantic compo-
nents in political person perception. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 42, 619–630.
Abelson, R. P., & Reich, C. M. (1969). Implicational molecules: A method for extracting meaning
from input sentences. In D. E. Walker & L. M. Norton (Eds.), Proceedings of the International
Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence.
Adaval, R. (2001). Sometimes it just feels right: The differential weighting of affect-consistent and
affect-inconsistent product information. Journal of Consumer Research, 7, 207–245.
Adaval, R. (2003). How good gets better and bad gets worse: Understanding the impact of affect
on evaluations of known brands. Journal of Consumer Research.
Adaval, R., Isbell, L. M., & Wyer, R. S. (2003). Political impression formation: The role of pictures and
information presentation format on evaluations of politicians. Unpublished manuscript, Hong
Kong University of Science and Technology.
Adaval, R., & Monroe, K. B. (2002). Automatic construction and use of contextual information for
product and price evaluations. Journal of Consumer Research, 28, 572–588.
Adaval, R., & Wyer, R. S. (1998). The role of narratives in consumer information processing. Jour-
nal of Consumer Psychology, 7, 207–245.
Adaval, R., & Wyer, R. S. (2003). Memory for social interactions: Effects of post-information processing
objectives on the recognition of protagonists’ statements and nonverbal behaviors. Unpublished
manuscript, Hong Kong University of Science and Technology.
Albarracin, D., & Wyer, R. S. (2000). The cognitive impact of past behavior: Influences on beliefs,
attitudes, and future behavioral decisions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79,
5–22.
Albarracin, D., & Wyer, R. S. (2001). Elaborative and nonelaborative processing of a behavior-
related persuasive communication. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 27, 691–705.

380
REFERENCES 381

Albrecht, J. E., & Myers, J. L. (1995). Updating a mental model: Maintaining both local and global
coherence. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 19,
1061–1070.
Anderson, A., Garrod, S. C., & Sanford, A. J. (1983). The accessibility of pronominal antecedents
as a function of episode shifts in narrative text. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology,
35A, 427–440.
Anderson, J. R. (1978). Arguments concerning representations for mental imagery. Psychological
Review, 85, 249–277.
Anderson, J. R. (1982). Acquisition of cognitive skill. Psychological Review, 89, 369–406.
Anderson, J. R. (1983). The architecture of cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Anderson, J. R., & Bower, G. H. (1973). Human associative memory. Washington, DC: V. H. Winston.
Anderson, N. H. (1971). Integration theory and attitude change. Psychological Review, 78, 171–206.
Anderson, N. H. (1981). Foundations of information integration theory. New York: Academic Press.
Anderson, R. C., Reynolds, R. E., Schallert, D. L., & Goetz, F. T. (1977). Frameworks for comprehend-
ing discourse (Tech. Rep. No. 12). Urbana, IL: Laboratory for Cognitive Studies in Education,
University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign.
Apter, M. J. (1982). The experience of motivation: The theory of psychological reversals. San Diego,
CA: Academic Press.
Arkin, R. M., Gleason, J. M., & Johnston, S. (1976). Effect of perceived choice, expected outcome
and observed outcome of an action on the causal attributions of actors. Journal of Experimen-
tal Social Psychology, 12, 151–158.
Banks, W. P. (1977). Encoding and processing of symbolic information in comparative judg-
ments. In G. H. Bower (Ed.), The psychology of learning and motivation (Vol. 11). New York: Aca-
demic Press.
Barclay, J. R. (1973). The role of comprehension in remembering sentences. Cognitive Psychology,
4, 229–254.
Bargh, J. A. (1994). The four horsemen of automaticity: Awareness, intention, efficiency, and con-
trol in social cognition. In R. S. Wyer & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Handbook of social cognition (2nd ed.,
Vol. 1, pp. 1–40). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Bargh, J. A. (1997). The automaticity of everyday life. In R. S. Wyer (Ed.), Advances in social cogni-
tion (Vol. 10, pp. 1–62). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Bargh, J. A., Bond, R. N., Lombardi, W., & Tota, M. E. (1986). The additive nature of chronic and
temporary sources of construct accessibility. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 50,
869–878.
Bargh, J. A., Chaiken, S., Govender, R., & Pratto, F. (1992). The generality of the automatic atti-
tude activation effect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 62, 893–912.
Bargh, J. A., Chaiken, S., Raymond, P., & Hymes, C. (1996). The automatic evaluation effect: Un-
conditionally automatic attitude activation in a pronunciation task. Journal of Experimental
Social Psychology, 32, 104–120.
Bargh, J. A., Chen, M., & Burrows, L. (1996). Automaticity of social behavior: Direct effects of trait
construct and stereotype activation on action. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
71, 230–244.
Bargh, J. A., & Pietromonaco, P. (1982). Automatic information processing and social perception:
The influence of trait information presented outside of conscious awareness on impression
formation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 43, 437–449.
Baron, R. A., & Byrne, D. (2000). Social psychology (9th ed.). Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon.
Barsalou, L. W. (1990). On the indistinguishability of exemplar memory and abstraction in cate-
gory representations. In T. K. Srull & R. S. Wyer (Eds.), Content and process specificity in the ef-
fects of prior experiences: Advances in social cognition (Vol. 3, pp. 61–88). Hillsdale, NJ: Law-
rence Erlbaum Associates.
Barsalou, L. W. (1993). Flexibility, structure, and linguistic vagary in concepts: Manifestations of
a compositional system of perceptual symbols. In A. F. Collins, S. E. Gathercole, M. A.
382 REFERENCES

Conway, & P. E. Morris (Eds.), Theories of memory (pp. 29–102). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.
Baumeister, R. F., & Newman, L. S. (1994). How stories make sense of personal experience: Mo-
tives that shape autobiographical memories. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 20,
676–690.
Bell, D. E. (1982). Regret in decision making under uncertainty. Operations Research, 30, 961–981.
Bem, D. J. (1972). Self-perception theory. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social
psychology (Vol. 6, pp. 1–62). New York: Academic Press.
Bem, D. J., & McConnell, H. K. (1970). Testing the self-perception explanation of dissonance phe-
nomena: On the salience of premanipulation attitudes. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
chology, 14, 23–31.
Bergson, H. (1911). Laughter: An essay on the meaning of the comic. New York: Macmillan.
Berlyne, D. E. (1969). Laughter, humor and play. In G. Lindzey & E. Aronson (Eds.), Handbook of
social psychology (Vol. 3, pp. 795–852). Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Berlyne, D. E. (1971). Aesthetics and psychology. New York: Appleton-Century.
Bettman, J. R., Capon, N., & Lutz, R. J. (1975). Multiattribute measurement models and
multiattribute attitude theory: A test of construct validity. Journal of Consumer Research, 1,
1–15.
Birnbaum, M. H. (1974). The nonadditivity of personality impressions. Journal of Experimental
Psychology, 102, 543–561.
Black, J. B., Galambos, J. A., & Read, S. (1984). Comprehending stories and social situations. In
R. S. Wyer & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Handbook of social cognition (Vol. 3, pp. 45–86). Hillsdale, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Black, J. B., Turner, T., & Bower, G. H. (1979). Point of view in narrative comprehension, memory,
and production. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 11, 717–726.
Blaney, P. H. (1986). Affect and memory: A review. Psychological Bulletin, 99, 229–246.
Bless, H. (2001). Mood and the use of general knowledge structures. In L. L. Martin & G. L. Clore
(Eds.), Theories of mood and cognition: A user’s guidebook (pp. 9–26). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.
Bless, H., Bohner, G., Schwarz, H., & Strack, F. (1990). Mood and persuasion: A cognitive re-
sponse analysis. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 16, 331–345.
Bless, H., Clore, G. L., Schwarz, N., Golisano, V., Rabe, C., & Woelke, M. (1996). Mood and the use
of scripts: Does being in a happy mood really lead to mindlessness? Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 71, 665–679.
Bodenhausen, G. V. (1993). Emotions, arousal, and stereotypic judgments: A heuristic model of
affect and stereotyping. In D. M. Mackie & D. L. Hamilton (Eds.), Affect, cognition and stereotyp-
ing: Interactive processes in group perception (pp. 13–37). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Bodenhausen, G. V., & Macrae, C. N. (1998). Stereotype activation and inhibition. In R. S. Wyer
(Ed.), Advances in social cognition (Vol. 11, pp. 1–52). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associ-
ates.
Bodenhausen, G. V., Sheppard, L. A., & Kramer, G. P. (1994). Negative affect and social judgment:
The differential impact of anger and sadness. European Journal of Social Psychology, 24, 45–62.
Bodenhausen, G. V., & Wyer, R. S. (1985). Effects of stereotypes on decision-making and informa-
tion-processing strategies. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 52, 871–880.
Boorstin, D. (1973). The Americans: The national experience. New York: Random House.
Bower, G. H. (1981). Emotional mood and memory. American Psychologist, 36, 129–148.
Bower, G. H. (1991). Mood congruity of social judgments. In J. P. Forgas (Ed.), Emotion and social
judgments (pp. 31–53). Oxford, England: Pergamon.
Bower, G. H., Black, J. B., & Turner, T. J. (1979). Scripts in memory for texts. Cognitive Psychology,
11, 177–220.
Bower, G. H., Gilligan, S. G., & Monteiro, K. P. (1981). Selectivity of learning caused by affective
states. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 110, 451–473.
REFERENCES 383

Bower, G. H., & Mayer, J. D. (1985). Failure to replicate mood-dependent retrieval. Bulletin of the
Psychonomic Society, 23, 39–42.
Bransford, J. D., Barclay, J. R., & Franks, J. J. (1972). Sentence memory: A constructive versus in-
terpretative approach. Cognitive Psychology, 3, 193–209.
Bransford, J. D., & Johnson, M. K. (1972). Contextual prerequisites for understanding: Some in-
vestigations of comprehension and recall. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 11,
717–726.
Bransford, J. D., & Stein, B. S. (1984). The ideal problem solver: A guide to improving thinking, learn-
ing, and creativity. New York: Freeman.
Brewer, M. (1988). A dual process model of impression formation. In T. K. Srull & R. S. Wyer
(Eds.), Advances in social cognition: A dual process model of impression formation (Vol. 1, pp.
1–36). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Brewer, W. F. (1995). To assert that essentially all human knowledge and memory is represented
in terms of stories is certainly wrong. In R. S. Wyer (Ed.), Advances in social cognition (Vol. 8,
pp. 109–119). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Brewer, W. H., & Lichtenstein, E. H. (1981). Event schemas, story schemas, and story grammars.
In J. Long & A. Baddeley (Eds.), Attention and Performance, IX (pp. 363–379). Hillsdale, NJ: Law-
rence Erlbaum Associates.
Briley, D. A., Morris, M., & Simonson, I. (2000). Reasons as carriers of culture: Dynamic versus
dispositional models of cultural influence on decision making. Journal of Consumer Research,
27, 157–178.
Briley, D. A., & Wyer, R. S. (2001). Transitory determinants of values and decisions: The utility (or
nonutility) of individualism and collectivism in understanding cultural differences. Social
Cognition, 19, 198–229.
Briley, D. A., & Wyer, R. S. (2002). The effect of group membership salience on the avoidance of
negative outcomes: Implications for social and consumer decisions. Journal of Consumer Re-
search, 29, 400–415.
Brown, N. R., Rips, L. J., & Shevell, S. K. (1985). The subjective dates of natural events in very-
long-term memory. Cognitive Psychology, 17, 139–177.
Byrne, D. (1971). The attraction paradigm. New York: Academic Press.
Cacioppo, J. T., & Petty, R. E. (1982). The need for cognition. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
chology, 42, 116–131.
Carlston, D. E. (1980). Events, inferences and impression formation. In R. Hastie, T. Ostrom, E.
Ebbesen, R. Wyer, D. Hamilton, & D. Carlston (Eds.), Person memory: The cognitive basis of so-
cial perception (pp. 89–119). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Carlston, D. E. (1994). Associated Systems Theory: A systematic approach to cognitive represen-
tations of persons. In R. S. Wyer (Ed.), Advances in social cognition (Vol. 7, pp. 1–78). Hillsdale,
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Carlston, D. E., & Smith, E. R. (1996). Principles of mental representation. In E. T. Higgins & A. W.
Kruglanski (Eds.), Social psychology: Handbook of basic principles (pp. 184–210). New York:
Guilford Press.
Ceci, S. J., & Bruck, M. (1993). Suggestibility of the child witness: A historical review and synthe-
sis. Psychological Bulletin, 113, 403–439.
Chaiken, S. (1980). Heuristic versus systematic information processing in the use of source ver-
sus message cues in persuasion. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 39, 752–766.
Chaiken, S. (1987). The heuristic model of persuasion. In M. P. Zanna, J. M. Olson, & C. P. Herman
(Eds.), Social influence: The Ontario Symposium (Vol. 5, pp. 3–39). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.
Chaiken, S., & Bargh, J. A. (1993). Occurrence versus moderation of the automatic attitude acti-
vation effect: Reply to Fazio. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 64, 759–765.
Chaiken, S., Liberman, A., & Eagly, A. H. (1989). Heuristic and systematic information processing
within and beyond the persuasion context. In J. S. Uleman & J. A. Bargh (Eds.), Unintended
thought (pp. 212–252). New York: Guilford Press.
384 REFERENCES

Chaiken, S., & Trope, Y. (1999). Dual-process theories in social psychology. New York: Guilford
Press.
Chaiken, S., Wood, W., & Eagly, A. H. (1996). Principles of persuasion. In E. T. Higgins & A. W.
Kruglanski (Eds.), Social psychology: Handbook of basic principles (pp. 702–742). New York:
Guilford Press.
Chapman, A. J., & Foot, H. C. (Eds.). (1976). Humor and laughter: Theory, research and application.
New York: Wiley.
Chapman, A. J., & Foot, H. C. (Eds.). (1977). It’s a funny thing, humor. Elmsford, NY: Pergamon
Press.
Chartrand, T. L., & Bargh, J. A. (1996). Automatic activation of impression formation and memori-
zation goals: Nonconscious goal priming reproduces effects of explicit task instructions.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71, 464–478.
Chartrand, T. L., & Bargh, J. A. (2002). Nonconscious motivations: Their activation, operation
and consequences. In A. Tesser & D. Stapel (Eds.), Self and motivation: Emerging psychological
perspectives (pp. 13–41). Washington DC: American Psychological Association.
Chernev, A. (2001). The impact of common features on consumer preferences: A case of confir-
matory reasoning. Journal of Consumer Research, 27, 475–488.
Chiu, C., Dweck, C. S., Tong, J. Y., & Fu, J. H. (1997). Implicit theories and conceptions of morality.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 73, 923–940.
Chiu, C., Hong, Y., & Dweck, C. S. (1997). Lay dispositionism and implicit theories of personality.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 73, 19–30.
Chodorow, N. (1979). Feminism and difference: Gender, relation and difference in psychoana-
lytic perspective. Socialist Review, 46, 42–64.
Choi, I., Nisbett, R. E., & Norenzayan, A. (1999). Causal attribution across cultures: Variation and
universality. Psychological Bulletin, 125, 47–63.
Clore, G. L. (1992). Cognitive phenomenology: Feelings and the construction of judgment. In L. L.
Martin & A. Tesser (Eds.), The construction of social judgments (pp. 133–163). Hillsdale, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Clore, G. L., & Byrne, D. (1974). A reinforcement affect model of attraction. In T. L. Huston (Ed.),
Foundations of interpersonal attraction (pp. 143–170). New York: Academic Press.
Clore, G. L., Schwarz, N., & Conway, M. (1994). Affective causes and consequences of social infor-
mation processing. In R. S. Wyer & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Handbook of social cognition (2nd ed., Vol.
1, pp. 323–417). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Colcombe, S. J., & Wyer, R. S. (2001). The effects of image-based priming on lexical access, concep-
tual activation, and behavior. Unpublished manuscript, University of Illinois at Urbana-
Champaign.
Colcombe, S. J., & Wyer, R. S. (2002). The role of prototypes in the mental representation of tem-
porally-related events. Cognitive Psychology, 44, 67–103.
Collins, A. M., & Loftus, E. F. (1975). A spreading-activation theory of semantic processing. Psy-
chological Review, 82, 407–428.
Conway, M., & Ross, M. (1984). Getting what you want by revising what you had. Journal of Per-
sonality and Social Psychology, 47, 738–748.
Costley, C. L., & Brucks, M. (1992). Selective recall and information use in consumer preferences.
Journal of Consumer Research, 11, 464–474.
Craik, F. I. M., & Lockhart, R. S. (1972). Levels of processing: A framework for memory research.
Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 11, 671–684.
Cutrona, C., & Russell, D. (1987). The provisions of social relationships and adaptation to stress.
In W. H. Jones & D. Perlman (Eds.), Advances in personal relationships (Vol. 1, pp. 37–67).
Greenwich, CT: JAI.
DePaulo, B. M., & Friedman, H. S. (1998). Nonverbal communication. In D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, &
G. Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of social psychology (4th ed., Vol. 2, pp. 3–40). New York: McGraw-
Hill.
REFERENCES 385

DePaulo, B. M., & Kirkendol, S. E. (1989). The motivational impairment effect in the communica-
tion of deception. In J. Yuille (Ed.), Credibility assessment (pp. 51–70). Belgium: Kluwer.
Devine, P. G. (1989). Stereotypes and prejudice: Their automatic and controlled components.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 56, 5–18.
Dienes, B. P. A. (1996). Mood as information: Affective cues for cognitive processing styles. Unpub-
lished doctoral dissertation, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign.
Dijksterhuis, A., & van Knippenberg, A. (1998). The relation between perception and behavior, or
how to win a game of Trivial Pursuit. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 74, 865–877.
Duckworth, K. L., Bargh, J. A., Garcia, M., & Chaiken, S. (2002). The automatic evaluation of novel
stimuli. Psychological Science, 13, 514–520.
Dweck, C. S. (1975). The role of expectations and attributions in the alleviation of learned help-
lessness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 31, 674–685.
Dweck, C. S. (1991). Self-theories and goals: Their role in motivation, personality, and develop-
ment. In R. Dienstbier (Ed.), Nebraska Symposium on Motivation: Vol. 38. Perspectives on moti-
vation (pp. 199–235). Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.
Dweck, C. S., Chiu, C., & Hong, Y. (1995a). Implicit theories and their role in judgments and reac-
tions: A world from two perspectives. Psychological Inquiry, 6, 267–285.
Dweck, C. S., Chiu, C., & Hong, Y. (1995b). Implicit theories: Elaboration and extension of the
model. Psychological Inquiry, 6, 322–333.
Dweck, C. S., Hong, Y., & Chiu, C. (1993). Implicit theories: Individual differences in the likelihood
and meaning of dispositional inference. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 19, 644–656.
Dweck, C. S., & Leggett, E. L. (1988). A social-cognitive approach to motivation and personality.
Psychological Review, 25, 109–116.
Eagly, A. H., & Chaiken, S. (1993). The psychology of attitudes. Fort Worth, TX: Harcourt Brace
Jovanovich.
Eagly, A. H., & Chaiken, S. (1998). Attitude structure and function. In D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, & G.
Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of social psychology (4th ed., Vol. 1, pp. 269–322). Boston, MA:
McGraw-Hill.
Ebbesen, E. B. (1980). Cognitive processes in understanding ongoing behavior. In R. Hastie, T.
Ostrom, E. Ebbesen, R. Wyer, D. Hamilton, & D. Carlston (Eds.), Person memory: Cognitive ba-
sis of social perception (pp. 179–226). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Edell, J. A., & Staelin, R. (1983). The information processing of pictures in print advertisements.
Journal of Consumer Research, 10, 45–61.
Ellis, H. C., & Ashbrook, P. W. (1988). Resource allocation model of the effects of depressed mood
states on memory. In K. Fiedler, & J. Forgas (Eds.), Affect, cognition, and social behavior (pp.
25–43). Toronto: C. J. Hofgrefe.
Ellsworth, P. C., & Carlsmith, M. (1968). Effects of eye contact and verbal content on affective re-
sponse to a dyadic interaction. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 10, 15–20.
Emler, N., Renwick, S., & Malone, B. (1983). The relationship between moral reasoning and politi-
cal orientation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 45, 1073–1080.
Englis, B. G. (1994). The role of affect in political advertising: Voter emotional responses to the
nonverbal behavior of politicians. In E. M. Clark et al. (Eds.), Attention, attitude, and affect in re-
sponse to advertising (pp. 223–247). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Erdley, C. A., & Dweck, C. S. (1993). Children’s implicit personality theories as predictors of their
social judgments. Child Development, 64, 863–878.
Fazio, R. H. (1986). How do attitudes guide behavior? In R. M. Sorrentino & E. T. Higgins (Eds.),
Handbook of motivation and cognition (pp. 204–243). New York: Guilford.
Fazio, R. H. (1990). Multiple processes by which attitudes guide behavior: The MODE model as
an integrative framework. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology
(Vol. 23, pp. 75–109). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Fazio, R. H., Sanbonmatsu, D. M., Powell, M. C., & Kardes, F. R. (1986). On the automatic activation
of attitudes. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 50, 229–238.
386 REFERENCES

Festinger, L. (1957). A theory of cognitive dissonance. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press.
Fiedler, K. (1988). Emotional mood, cognitive style, and behavior regulation. In K. Fiedler & J.
Forgas (Eds.), Affect, cognition and social behavior (pp. 100–119). Toronto: Hofgrefe Interna-
tional.
Fischoff, B. (1975). Hindsight ¹ foresight: The effect of outcome knowledge on judgment under
uncertainty. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 1,
288–299.
Fischoff, B. (1982). For those condemned to study the past: Heuristics and biases in hindsight. In
D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, & A. Tversky (Eds.), Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases
(pp. 332–351). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Fishbein, M. (1963). An investigation of the relationships between beliefs about an object and at-
titude toward that object. Human Relations, 16, 233–239.
Fishbein, M. (1967). A behavior theory approach to the relations between beliefs about an object
and the attitude toward the object. In M. Fishbein (Ed.), Readings in attitude theory and meas-
urement (pp. 389–400). New York: Wiley.
Fishbein, M., & Ajzen, I. (1975). Belief, attitude, intention, and behavior: An introduction to theory
and research. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Fishbein, M., & Hunter, R. (1964). Summation versus balance in attitude organization and
change. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 69, 505–510.
Fishkin, J., Keniston, K., & MacKinnon, C. (1973). Moral reasoning and political ideology. Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, 27, 109–119.
Fiske, S. T. (1998). Stereotyping, prejudice, and discrimination. In D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, & G.
Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of social psychology (4th ed., Vol. 2, pp. 357–414). New York: McGraw
Hill.
Fiske, S. T., & Pavelchak, M. A. (1986). Category-based versus piecemeal-based affective re-
sponses: Developments in schema-triggered affect. In R. M. Sorrentino & E. T. Higgins (Eds.),
Handbook of motivation and cognition (pp. 167–203). New York: Guilford.
Fletcher, G. J. O., Danilovics, P., Fernandez, G., Peterson, D., & Reeder, G. D. (1986). Attributional
complexity: An individual differences measure. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
51, 875–884.
Fong, C. P. S., & Wyer, R. S. (2003). Cultural, social and emotional determinants of decisions un-
der uncertainty. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes,
Forgas, J. P. (1991). Affect and cognition in close relationships. In G. J. O. Fletcher & F. D. Fincham
(Eds.), Cognition in close relationships (pp. 7–35). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Forgas, J. P. (1992). Affect in social judgments and decisions: a multiprocess model. In M. P.
Zanna (Ed.), Advances in Experimental Social Psychology (Vol. 25, pp. 227–275). San Diego, CA:
Academic Press.
Forgas, J. P. (1995). Mood and judgment: The affect infusion model (AIM). Psychological Bulletin,
117, 39–66.
Forgas, J. P. (1998). Asking nicely? The effects of mood on responding to more or less polite re-
quests. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 2, 173–185.
Forgas, J. P. (2001). Feeling and doing: Affective influences on interpersonal behavior. Psychologi-
cal Inquiry, 13, 1–28.
Forgas, J. P. (2002). Feeling and doing: Affective influences on interpersonal behavior. Psychologi-
cal Inquiry, 13, 1–28.
Forgas, J. P., & Bower, G. H. (1987). Mood effects on person perception judgments. Journal of Per-
sonality and Social Psychology, 53, 53–60.
Forgas, J. P., Bower, G. H., & Krantz, S. (1984). The influence of mood on perceptions of social in-
teractions. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 20, 497–513.
Freud, S. (1928). Humor. International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 9, 1–6.
Freud, S. (1960/1905). Jokes and their relation to the unconscious. New York: Norton.
REFERENCES 387

Fry, P. S., & Ghosh, R. (1980). Attributions of success and failure: Comparison of cultural differ-
ences between Asian and Caucasian children. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 11,
343–363.
Gaelick, L., Bodenhausen, G. V., & Wyer, R. S. (1985). Emotional communication in close relation-
ships. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 49, 1246–1265.
Garnham, A. (1981). Mental models as representations of text. Memory & Cognition, 9, 560–565.
Gasper, K., & Clore, G. L. (1998). The persistent use of negative affect by anxious individuals to
estimate risk. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 74, 1350–1363.
Gerbner, G., Gross, L., Morgan, M., & Signorielli, N. (1994). Growing up with television: the culti-
vation perspective. In J. Bryant & D. Zillmann (Eds.), Media effects: Advances in theory and re-
search (pp. 17–41). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Gick, M., L., & Holyoak, K. J. (1983). Schema induction and analogical transfer. Cognitive Psychol-
ogy, 15, 1–38.
Gilbert, D. T. (1991). How mental systems believe. American Psychologist, 46, 107–119.
Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice: Psychological theory and women’s development. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Giner-Sorolla, R., & Chaiken, S. (1997). Selective use of heuristic and systematic processing un-
der defense motivation. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 23, 84–97.
Glenberg, A. M. (1997). What memory is for. Behavioral & Brain Sciences, 20, 1–55.
Glenberg, A. M., Kruley, P., & Langston, W. E. (1994). Analogical processes in comprehension:
Simulation of a mental model. In M. A. Gernsbacher (Ed.), Handbook of psycholinguistics (pp.
609–640). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Glenberg, A. M., Meyer, M., & Lindem, K. (1987). Mental models contribute to foregrounding dur-
ing text comprehension. Journal of Memory and Language, 26, 69–83.
Goethals, G. R., & Reckman, R. F. (1973). The perception of consistency in attitudes. Journal of Ex-
perimental Social Psychology, 9, 491–501.
Gohm, C. L., & Wyer, R. S. (1998). Narrative representations of long-term relationships: An evaluation
of assessment procedures and implications for marital satisfaction. Unpublished manuscript,
University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign.
Goldstein, J. H., & McGhee, P. (Eds.). (1972). The psychology of humor. New York: Springer-Verlag.
Goldstein, J. H., Suls, J. M., & Anthony, S. (1972). Enjoyment of specific types of humor content:
Motivation or salience. In J. Goldstein & P. McGhee (Eds.), It’s a funny thing, humor (pp.
159–171). New York: Springer-Verlag.
Gordon, S. E., & Wyer, R. S. (1987). Person memory: Category-set-size effects on the recall of a
person’s behaviors. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 53, 648–662.
Graesser, A. C. (1981). Prose comprehension beyond the word. New York: Springer-Verlag.
Graesser, A. C., Gordon, S. E., & Sawyer, J. D. (1979). Memory for typical and atypical actions in
scripted activities: Test of a script pointer + tag hypothesis. Journal of Verbal Learning and
Verbal Behavior, 18, 319–322.
Graesser, A. C., & Nakamura, G. V. (1982). The impact of a schema on comprehension and mem-
ory. In G. H. Bower (Ed.), The psychology of learning and motivation: Advances in research and
theory (Vol. 16, pp. 66–109). New York: Academic Press.
Graesser, A. C., Singer, M., & Trabasso, T. (1994). Constructing inferences during narrative text
comprehension. Psychological Review, 101, 371–395.
Green, G. M. (1989). Pragmatics and natural language understanding. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Green, M. C., & Brock, T. C. (2000). The role of transportation in the persuasiveness of public nar-
ratives. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79, 701–721.
Greenwald, A. G. (1968). Cognitive learning, cognitive responses to persuasion and attitude
change. In A. G. Greenwald, T. C. Brock, & T. M. Ostrom (Eds.), Psychological foundations of at-
titudes (pp. 147–170). New York: Academic Press.
Greenwald, A. G., & Banaji, M. R. (1995). Implicit social cognition: Attitudes, self-esteem, and ste-
reotypes. Psychological Review, 102, 4–27.
388 REFERENCES

Greenwald, A. G., & Pratkanis, A. R. (1984). The self. In R. S. Wyer & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Handbook of
social cognition (Vol. 3, pp. 129–178). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P. Cole & J. L. Morgan (Eds.), Syntax and semantics:
Speech acts (pp. 41–58). New York: Academic Press.
Gruenfeld, D. H., & Wyer, R. S. (1992). Semantics and pragmatics of social influence: How affirma-
tions and denials affect beliefs in referent propositions. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
chology, 62, 38–49.
Gruenfeld, D., & Wyer, R. S. (1993). A two-set flow model of social communication: The influence of
information source and communication objectives on memory, message content and delivery,
and recipients’ beliefs. Unpublished manuscript, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign.
Hamilton, D. L., & Gifford, R. K. (1976). Illusory correlation in interpersonal perception: A cogni-
tive basis of stereotypic judgment. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 13, 392–407.
Hamilton, D. H., Katz, L. B., & Leirer, V. O. (1980). Organizational processes in impression forma-
tion. In R. Hastie, T. Ostrom, E. Ebbesen, R. Wyer, D. Hamilton, & D. Carlston (Eds.), Person
memory: The cognitive basis of social perception (pp. 121–153). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.
Hamilton, D. L., & Sherman, J. W. (1994). Stereotypes. In R. S. Wyer & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Handbook
of social cognition (2nd ed., Vol. 2, pp. 1–68). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Harkins, S. G., Latane, B., & Williams, K. (1980). Social loafing: Allocating effort or taking it easy?
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 16, 457–465.
Harvey, J. H., & Weary, G. (1984). Current issues in attribution theory and research. Annual Re-
view of Psychology, 35, 427–459.
Harvey, J. H., Weber, A. L., & Orbuch, T. L. (1990). Interpersonal accounts. Cambridge, MA: Basil
Blackwell.
Hasher, L., Goldstein, D., & Toppin, T. (1977). Frequency and the conference of referential valid-
ity. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 16, 107–112.
Hastie, R. (1980). Memory for behavioral information that confirms or contradicts a personality
impression. In R. Hastie, T. Ostrom, E. Ebbesen, R. Wyer, D. Hamilton, & D. Carlston (Eds.),
Person memory: The cognitive basis of social perception (pp. 141–172). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.
Hastie, R., & Kumar, P. A. (1979). Person memory: Personality traits as organizing principles in
memory for behaviors. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 37, 25–38.
Hastie, R., & Pennington, N. (1995). The big picture: Is it a story? In R. S. Wyer (Ed.), Advances in
social cognition (Vol. 8, pp. 133–138). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Hawkins, S. A., & Hastie, R. (1990). Hindsight: Biased judgment of past events after the outcomes
are known. Psychological Bulletin, 107, 311–327.
Heider, F. (1958). The psychology of interpersonal relations. New York: Wiley.
Heine, S. J., & Lehman, D. R. (1997). Culture, dissonance, and self-affirmation. Personality and So-
cial Psychology Bulletin, 23, 389–400.
Heine, S., Lehman, D., Markus, H., & Kitayama, S. (1999). Is there a universal need for positive
self-regard? Psychological Review, 106, 766–794.
Henninger, M., & Wyer, R. S. (1976). The recognition and elimination of inconsistencies among
syllogistically-related beliefs: Some new light on the “Socratic effect.” Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology, 34, 680–693.
Herr, P. M. (1986). Consequences of priming: Judgment and behavior. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 51, 1106–1115.
Higgins, E. T. (1981). The “communication game”: Implications for social cognition and persua-
sion. In E. T. Higgins, C. P. Herman, & M. P. Zanna (Eds.), Social cognition: The Ontario Sympo-
sium (Vol. 1, pp. 342–392). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Higgins, E. T. (1996). Knowledge activation: Accessibility, applicability, and salience. In E. T. Hig-
gins & A. Kruglanski (Eds.), Social psychology: Handbook of basic principles (pp. 133–168). New
York: Guilford.
REFERENCES 389

Higgins, E. T. (1997). Beyond pleasure and pain. American Psychologist, 55, 1217–1233.
Higgins, E. T. (1998). Promotion and prevention: Regulatory focus as a motivational principle. In
M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 30, pp. 1–46). San Diego,
CA: Academic Press.
Higgins, E. T., Bargh, J. A., & Lombardi, W. (1985). The nature of priming effects on categoriza-
tion. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 11, 59–69.
Higgins, E. T., & Lurie, L. (1983). Context, categorization and recall: The “change-of-standard” ef-
fect. Cognitive Psychology, 15, 525–547.
Higgins, E. T., & Rholes, W. S. (1978). “Saying is believing”: Effects of message modification on
memory and liking for the person described. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 14,
363–378.
Higgins, E. T., Rholes, W. S., & Jones, C. R. (1977). Category accessibility and impression forma-
tion. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 13, 141–154.
Hilgard, E. R. (1951). Methods and procedures in the study of learning. In S. S. Stevens (Ed.),
Handbook of experimental psychology. New York: Wiley.
Hintzman, D. L. (1986). “Schema abstraction” in a multiple-trace model. Psychological Review, 93,
411–428.
Ho, D. Y. F., & Chiu, C. Y. (1994). Component ideas of individualism, collectivism, and social orga-
nization: An application in the study of Chinese culture. In U. Kim, C. Kagitcibasi, S. C. Choi, &
G. Yoon (Eds.), Individualism and collectivism: theory, method and applications (pp. 137–156).
Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Hofstede, G. H. (1991). Empirical models of cultural differences. In N. Bleichrodt & P. J. D. Drenth
(Eds.), Contemporary issues in cross-cultural psychology (pp. 4–20). Amsterdam, Netherlands:
Swets & Zeitlinger.
Holmberg, D., & Holmes, J. G. (1994). Reconstruction of relationship memories: A mental models
approach. In N. Schwarz & S. Sudman (Eds.), Autobiographical memory and the validity of retro-
spective reports (pp. 267–288). New York: Springer-Verlag.
Holmes, J. G., & Murray, S. L. (1995). Memory for events in close relationships: Applying Schank
and Abelson’s story skeleton model. In R. S. Wyer (Ed.), Advances in social cognition (Vol. 8,
pp. 193–210). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Hong, Y., Chiu, C., Dweck, C. S., & Sacks, R. (1997). Implicit theories and evaluative processes in
person cognition. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 33, 296–303.
Hong, Y., Morris, M. W., Chiu, C., & Benet-Martinez, V. (2000). Multicultural minds: A dynamic
constructivist approach to culture and cognition. American Psychologist, 55, 709–720.
Humphreys, M. S., & Kashima, Y. (2002). Connectionism and self: Distributed representational
systems and their implications for self and identity. In Y. Kashima, M. Foddy, & M. Platow
(Eds.), Self and identity: Personal, social and symbolic (pp. 27–54). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.
Hunt, R. R., & Einstein, G. O. (1981). Relational and item-specific information in memory. Journal
of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 20, 497–514.
Hyman, I. E., & Loftus, E. F. (2002). False childhood memories and eyewitness memory errors. In
M. Eisen & J. Quas (Eds.), Memory and suggestibility in the forensic interview (pp. 63–84).
Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Innes-Ker, A., & Niedenthal, P. M. (2002). Emotion concepts and emotional states in social judg-
ment and categorization. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 83, 804–816.
Isbell, L. M. (2000). Beyond heuristic information processing: Systematic processing in happy and sad
moods. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign.
Isbell, L. M., Clore, G. L., & Wyer, R. S. (1998). Mood-mediated uses of stereotyping in impression for-
mation. Unpublished manuscript, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign.
Isbell, L. M., & Wyer, R. S. (1999). Correcting for mood-induced bias in the evaluation of political
candidates. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 25, 237–249.
390 REFERENCES

Isbell, L. M., Wyer, R. S., & Collins, J. E. (2002). The cognitive dynamics of humor elicitation: The role
of diminishment, disparagement and cognitive elaboration in responses to jokes and witticisms.
Unpublished manuscript, Hong Kong University of Science and Technology, Hong Kong.
Isen, A. M. (1984). Toward understanding the role of affect in cognition. In R. S. Wyer & T. K. Srull
(Eds.), Handbook of social cognition (Vol. 3, pp. 179–236). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum As-
sociates.
Isen, A. M. (1987). Positive affect, cognitive processes, and social behavior. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.),
Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 20, pp. 203–253). New York: Academic Press.
Isen, A. M., & Daubman, L. A. (1984). The influence of affect on categorization. Journal of Personal-
ity and Social Psychology, 47, 1206–1217.
Isen, A. M., Daubman, L. A., & Nowicki, G. P. (1987). Positive affect facilitates creative problem
solving. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 52, 1122–1131.
Isen, A. M., Johnson, M., Mertz, E., & Robinson, G. (1985). Positive affect and the uniqueness of
word association. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 48, 1413–1426.
Isen, A. M., Shalker, T. E., Clark, M. S., & Karp, L. (1978). Affect, accessibility of material in mem-
ory and behavior: A cognitive loop? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 36, 1–12.
Jacoby, L. L., Kelley, C. M., Brown, J., & Jasechko, J. (1989). Becoming famous overnight: Limits
on the ability to avoid unconscious influences of the past. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 56, 326–338.
Janis, I. L., & King, B. T. (1954). The influence of role playing on opinion change. Journal of Abnor-
mal and Social Psychology, 49, 211–218.
Johnson, M., Hashtroudi, S., & Lindsay, D. S. (1993). Source monitoring. Psychological Bulletin,
114, 3–28.
Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1983). Mental models: Towards a cognitive science of language, inference and
consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1989). Mental models. In M. I. Posner (Ed.), Foundations of cognitive science
(pp. 469–500). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Jones, E. E., & Davis, K. J. (1965). From acts to dispositions: The attributional process in person
perception. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 2, pp.
220–266). New York: Academic Press.
Kahneman, D., & Miller, D. T. (1986). Norm theory: Comparing reality to its alternatives. Psycho-
logical Review, 93, 136–153.
Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (Eds.). (1982). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and
biases. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1982). The simulation heuristic. In D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, & A.
Tversky (Eds.), Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases (pp. 201–208). New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Kane, T. R., Suls, J., & Tedeschi, J. T. (1977). Humor as a tool of social interaction. In A. J. Chap-
man & H. C. foot (Eds.), It’s a funny thing, humor. Elmsford, NY: Pergamon Press.
Kelley, C. M., & Lindsay, D. S. (1993). Remembering mistaken for knowing: Ease of retrieval as a
basis for confidence in answers to general knowledge questions. Journal of Memory and Lan-
guage, 32, 1–24.
Kelley, H. H. (1967). Attribution theory in social psychology. In D. Levine (Ed.), Nebraska sympo-
sium on motivation, 15, 192–238.
Kelley, H. H. (1987). Causal schemata and the attribution process. In E. Jones, D. Kanouse, H.
Kelley, R. Nisbett, S. Valins, & B. Winer (Eds.), Attribution: Perceiving the causes of behavior.
Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. (Originally published 1971).
Kihlstrom, J. F. (1980). Posthypnotic amnesia for recently learned material: Interactions with
“episodic” and “semantic” memory. Cognitive Psychology, 12, 227–251.
Kintsch, W. (1998). Comprehension: A paradigm for cognition. Cambridge, England: Cambridge
University Press.
REFERENCES 391

Klein, S. B., & Loftus, J. (1993). Behavioral experience and trait judgments about the self. Person-
ality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 19, 740–745.
Klein, S. B., Loftus, J., Trafton, J. G., & Fuhrman, R. W. (1992). Use of exemplars and abstractions
in trait judgments: A model of trait knowledge about the self and others. Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology, 63, 739–753.
Klinger, E. (1975). Consequences of commitment to and disengagement from incentives. Psycho-
logical Bulletin, 82, 223–231.
Koestler, A. (1964). The act of creation. New York: Macmillan.
Kohlberg, L. (1976). Moral stages and moralization: The cognitive-developmental approach. In T.
Lickona (Ed.), Moral development and behavior: Theory, research and social issues. New York:
Holt, Rinehart, & Winston.
Kosslyn, S. M. (1980). Image and mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Kunda, Z. (1987). Motivated inference: Self-serving generation and evaluation of causal theories.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 53, 636–647.
Kunda, Z. (1990). The case for motivated reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 108, 480–498.
LaFave, L., Haddad, J., & Maesen, W. A. (1976). Superiority, enhanced self-esteem and perceived
incongruity humor theory. In A. J. Chapman & H. C. Foot (Eds.), Humor and laughter: Theory,
research and applications (pp. 63–91). New York: Wiley.
Lampel, A. K., & Anderson, N. H. (1968). Combining visual and verbal information in an impres-
sion-formation task. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 9, 1–6.
Langer, E. J., & Abelson, R. P. (1972). The semantics of asking a favor: How to succeed in getting
help without really dying. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 24, 26–32.
LaPiere, R. T. (1934). Attitudes vs. actions. Social Forces, 13, 230–237.
Lazarus, R. S. (1982). Thoughts on the relations between emotion and cognition. American Psy-
chologist, 37, 1019–1024.
Lazarus, R. S. (1991). Emotion and adaptation. New York: Oxford University Press.
LeDoux, J. E. (1994). Memory vs. emotional memory in the brain. in P. Ekman & R. J. Davidson
(Eds.), The nature of emotion: Fundamental questions (pp. 311–312). New York: Oxford Univer-
sity Press.
Lefcourt, H. M., & Martin, R. A. (1986). Humor and life stress: Anecdote to adversity. New York:
Springer-Verlag.
Lepore, L., & Brown, R. (1997). Category and stereotype activation: Is prejudice inevitable? Jour-
nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 72, 275–287.
Lerner, M. J. (1970). The desire for justice and reactions to victims. In J. Macaulay & L. Berkowitz
(Eds.), Altruism and helping behavior (pp. 205–229). New York: Academic Press.
Lerner, M. J., & Miller, D. T. (1978). Just world research and the attribution process: Looking
back and ahead. Psychological Bulletin, 85, 1030–1051.
Lerner, M. J., Miller, D. T., & Holmes, J. G. (1976). Deserving and the emergence of forms of jus-
tice. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 9). New York: Aca-
demic Press.
Lerner, M. J., & Simmons, C. H. (1966). Observer’s reaction to the “innocent victim”: Compassion
or rejection? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 4, 203–210.
Levine, S. R., Wyer, R. S., & Schwarz, N. (1994). Are you what you feel? The affective and cognitive
determinants of self-judgments. Experimental Journal of Social Psychology, 24, 63–77.
Locke, H. L., & Wallace, K. (1959). Short marital adjustment and prediction tests: Their reliability
and validity. Marriage and Family Living, 21, 251–255.
Loftus, E. F. (1975). Leading questions and the eyewitness report. Cognitive Psychology, 7, 560–
572.
Loftus, E. F. (2000). Remembering what never happened. In E. Tulving (Ed.), Memory, conscious-
ness and the brain: The Tallinn conference (pp. 106–118). Philadelphia, PA: Taylor & Francis.
392 REFERENCES

Loftus, E. F., & Marburger, W. (1983). Since the eruption of Mt. St. Helens, has anyone beaten you
up? Improving the accuracy of retrospective reports with landmark events. Memory & Cogni-
tion, 11, 114–120.
Loftus, E. F., & Palmer, S. J. (1974). Reconstruction of automobile destruction. Journal of Verbal
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 2, 467–471.
Logan, G. L. (1988). Toward an instance theory of automatization. Psychological Review, 95,
492–527.
Loken, B. A. (1984). Attitude processing strategies. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 20,
272–296.
Loken, B. A., & Wyer, R. S. (1983). Effects of reporting beliefs in syllogistically related proposi-
tions on the recognition of unmentioned propositions. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
chology, 45, 306–322.
Lombardi, W. J., Higgins, E. T., & Bargh, J. A. (1987). The role of consciousness in priming effects
on categorization. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 13, 411–429.
Long, D. L., & Graesser, A. C. (1988). Wit and humor in discourse processing. Discourse Processes,
11, 35–60.
Loomes, G., & Sugden, R. (1986). Disappointment and dynamic consistency in choice under un-
certainty. Review of Economic Studies, 53, 271–282.
Lynch, J. G., Chakravarti, D., & Mitra, A. (1991). Contrast effects in consumer judgments: Changes
in mental representations or in the anchoring of rating scales? Journal of Consumer Research,
18, 284–297.
Mackie, D. M., & Worth, L. T. (1989). Cognitive deficits and the mediation of positive affect in per-
suasion. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57, 27–40.
Macrae, C. N., Bodenhausen, G. V., Milne, A. B., & Jetten, J. (1994). Out of mind but back in sight:
Stereotypes on the rebound. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 808–817.
Magliano, J. P., Dijkstra, K., & Zwaan, R. A. (1996). Generating predictive inferences while viewing
a movie. Discourse Processes, 22, 199–224.
Maheswaran, D., Mackie, D. M., & Chaiken, S. (1992). Brand name as a heuristic cue: The effects of
task importance and expectancy confirmation on consumer judgments. Journal of Consumer
Psychology, 1, 317–336.
Mandler, J. (1979). Categorical and schematic organization in memory. In C. R. Puff (Ed.), Mem-
ory, organization and structure. New York: Academic Press.
Mandler, J., & Johnson, N. S. (1977). Remembrance of things parsed: Story structure and recall.
Cognitive Psychology, 9, 111–151.
Mankowski, E., & Rappaport, J. (1995). Stories, identity, and the psychological sense of commu-
nity. In R. S. Wyer (Ed.), Advances in social cognition (Vol. 8, pp. 211–226). Hillsdale, NJ: Law-
rence Erlbaum Associates.
Mankowski, E. S., & Wyer, R. S. (1996). Cognitive processes in perceptions of social support. Per-
sonality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 22, 894–905.
Markus, H., & Kitayama, S. (1991). Culture and the self: Implications for cognition, emotion and
motivation. Psychological Review, 98, 224–253.
Martin, L. L., Achee, J. W., Ward, D. W., & Wyer, R. S. (1993). Mood as input: People have to inter-
pret the motivational implications of their moods. Journal of Personality and Social Psychol-
ogy, 64, 317–326.
Martin, L. L., Seta, J. J., & Crelia, R. A. (1990). Assimilation and contrast as a function of people’s
willingness and ability to expend effort in forming an impression. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 59, 27–37.
Martin, L. L., & Tesser, A. (1996). Some ruminative thoughts. In R. S. Wyer (Ed.), Ruminative
thoughts: Advances in social cognition (Vol. 9, pp. 1–48). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Asso-
ciates.
McAdams, D. (1988). Power, intimacy and the life story: Personalogical inquiries into identity. New
York: Guilford Press.
REFERENCES 393

McClelland, D. C., Atkinson, J. W., Clark, R. A., & Lowell, E. L. (1953). The achievement motive. New
York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
McGhee, P., & Goldstein, J. (Eds.). (1983). Handbook of humor research: Basic issues. New York:
Springer-Verlag.
McGuire, W. J. (1960). A syllogistic analysis of cognitive relationships. In M. J. Rosenberg & C. I.
Hovland (Eds.), Attitude organization and change (pp. 140–162). New Haven, CT: Yale Univer-
sity Press.
McGuire, W. J. (1972). Attitude change: An information processing paradigm. In C. G. McClintock
(Ed.), Experimental social psychology (pp. 108–141). New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.
McGuire, W. J. (1981). The probabilogical model of cognitive structure and attitude change. In
R. E. Petty, T. M. Ostrom, & T. C. Brock (Eds.), Cognitive responses in persuasion (pp. 291–307).
Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
McGuire, W. J. (1999). Constructing social psychology: Creative and critical processes. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
McGuire, W. J., & McGuire, C. V. (1988). Content and process in the experience of self. In L.
Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 21, pp. 97–144). San Diego,
CA: Academic Press.
McGuire, W. J., & McGuire, C. V. (1991). The content, structure and operation of thought systems.
In R. S. Wyer & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Advances in social cognition (Vol. 4, pp. 1–78). Hillsdale, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Mellers, B., Schwartz, A., & Ritov, I. (1999). Emotion-based choice. Journal of Experimental Psy-
chology: General, 128, 332–345.
Menon, G., & Raghubir, P. (1998). When automatic accessibility meets conscious content: Implica-
tions for judgment formation. Unpublished manuscript, New York University.
Miller, D. T. (1977). Altruism and threat to a belief in a just world. Journal of Experimental Social
Psychology, 13, 113–124.
Miller, L. C., & Read, S. R. (1991). On the coherence of mental models of persons and relation-
ships: A knowledge structure approach. In G. J. O. Fletcher & F. D. Fincham (Eds.), Cognition
in close relationships (pp. 69–99). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Miller, P. J. (1994). Narrative practices: Their role in socialization and self-construction. In U.
Neisser & R. Fivush (Eds.), The remembering self: Construction and accuracy in the self-narra-
tive. Emory symposia in cognition (Vol. 6, pp. 158–179). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Miller, P. J. (1995). Personal storytelling in everyday life: Social and cultural perspectives. In R. S.
Wyer (Ed.), Advances in social cognition: Knowledge and memory (Vol. 8, pp. 177–184). Mah-
wah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Miller, P. J., Fung, H., & Mintz, J. (1996). Self-construction through narrative practices: A Chinese
and American comparison of early socialization. Ethos, 24, 237–280.
Miller, P. J., Sandel, T. L., Liang, C.-H., & Fung, H. (2001). Narrating transgressions in Longwood:
The discourses, meanings and paradoxes of an American socializing practice. Ethos, 29,
159–186.
Miller, P. J., Wiley, A. R., Fung, H., & Liang, C. H. (1997). Personal storytelling as a medium of so-
cialization in Chinese and American families. Child Development, 68, 557–568.
Mindess, H., Miller, C., Turek, J., Bender, A., & Corbin, S. (1985). The Antioch Humor test: Making
sense of humor. New York: Avon Books.
Miniard, P. W., Bhatla, S., Lord, K. R., Dickson, P. R., & Unnava, H. R. (1991). Picture-based persua-
sion processes and the moderating role of involvement. Journal of Consumer Research, 18,
82–107.
Miniard, P. W., & Cohen, J. B. (1981). An examination of the Fishbein-Ajzen behavioral intentions
model’s concepts and measures. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 17, 309–339.
Morris, M. W., & Peng, K. (1994). Culture and cause: American and Chinese attributions for social
and physical events. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 949–971.
394 REFERENCES

Moskowitz, G. B., & Skurnik, I. W. (1999). Contrast effects as determined by the type of prime:
Trait versus exemplar primes initiate processing strategies that differ in how accessible con-
structs are used. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 76, 911–927.
Mueller, J. H., Grove, T. R., & Thompson, W. B. (1991). Mood-dependent retrieval and mood
awareness. Cognition and Emotion, 5, 331–349.
Murray, N., Sujan, H., Hirt, E. R., & Sujan, M. (1990). The influence of mood on categorization: A
cognitive flexibility interpretation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 59, 411–425.
Murray, S. L., & Holmes, J. G. (1996). The construction of relationship realities. In G. J. O. Fletcher
& J. Fitness (Eds.), Knowledge structures in close relationships: A social psychological approach
(pp. 91–120). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Mussweiler, T. (2003). Comparison processes in social judgment: Mechanisms and conse-
quences. Psychological Review,
Mussweiler, T., & Strack, F. (1999a). Hypothesis-consistent testing and semantic priming in the
anchoring paradigm: A selective accessibility model. Journal of Experimental Social Psychol-
ogy, 35, 136–164.
Mussweiler, T., & Strack, F. (1999b). Comparing is believing: A selective accessibility model of
judgmental anchoring. In W. Stroebe & M. Hewstone (Eds.), European review of social psychol-
ogy (Vol. 10, pp. 135–167). Chichester, England: Wiley.
Mussweiler, T., & Strack, F. (2000a). The use of category and exemplar knowledge in the solution
of anchoring tasks. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78, 1038–1052.
Mussweiler, T., & Strack, F. (2000b). The “relative self”: Informational and judgmental conse-
quences of comparative self-evaluation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79,
23–38.
Nassi, A. J., Abramowitz, S. I., & Youmans, J. E. (1983). Moral development and politics a decade
later: A replication and extension. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 45, 1127–1135.
Nehrhardt, G. (1976). Incongruity and funniness: Toward a new descriptive model. In A. J. Chap-
man & H. C. Foot (Eds.), Humor and laughter: Theory, research and application (pp. 55–62). New
York: Wiley.
Nelson, K. (Ed.). (1989). Stories from the crib. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Nelson, K. (1993). The psychological and social origins of autobiographical memory. Psychologi-
cal Science, 4, 7–14.
Nelson, K., & Greundel, J. (1981). Generalized event representations: Building blocks of cognitive
development. In M. Lamb & A. Brown (Eds.), Advances in developmental psychology (Vol. 1,
pp. 131–158). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Newtson, D. A. (1973). Attribution and the unit of perception of ongoing behavior. Journal of Per-
sonality and Social Psychology, 28, 28–38.
Newtson, D. A. (1976). Foundations of attribution: The perception of ongoing behavior. In J.
Harvey, W. Ickes, & R. Kidd (Eds.), New directions in attribution research (Vol. 1, pp. 223–247).
Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Niedenthal, P. M., Halberstadt, J. B., & Setterlund, M. B. (1997). Being happy and seeing “happy”:
Emotional state mediates visual word recognition. Cognition and Emotion, 11, 403–432.
Niedenthal, P. M., & Setterlund, M. B. (1994). Emotion congruence in perception. Personality and
Social Psychology Bulletin, 20, 401–411.
Nielsen, A. C. (1995). Nielsen report on television. Northbrook, IL: A.C. Nielsen.
Nisbett, R. E., & Ross, L. (1980). Human inference: Strategies and shortcomings of social judgments.
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Norenzayan, A., & Kim, B. (2000). Unpublished data.
Norenzayan, A., & Schwarz, N. (1999). Telling what they want to know: Participants tailor causal
attributions to researchers’ interests. European Journal of Social Psychology, 29, 1011–1020.
Norman, D. A., & Bobrow, D. G. (1979). Descriptions: An intermediate stage in memory retrieval.
Cognitive Psychology, 11, 107–123.
REFERENCES 395

Nottenburg, G., & Shoben, E. J. (1980). Scripts as linear orders. Journal of Experimental Social Psy-
chology, 16, 329–347.
O’Guinn, T. C., & Shrum, L. J. (1997). The role of television in the construction of social reality.
Journal of Consumer Research, 23, 278–294.
Oishi, S., Wyer, R. S., & Colcombe, S. (2000). Cultural variation in the use of current life satisfac-
tion to predict the future. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78, 434–445.
Ortony, A., Clore, G. L., & Collins, A. (1988). The cognitive structure of emotions. New York: Cam-
bridge University Press.
Ostrom, T. M., & Upshaw, H. S. (1968). Psychological perspective and attitude change. In A. G.
Greenwald, T. M. Ostrom, & T. C. Brock (Eds.), Psychological foundations of attitudes. New
York: Academic Press.
Ottati, V. C., & Isbell, L. M. (1996). Effects of mood during exposure to target information on sub-
sequently reported judgments: An on-line model of misattribution and correction. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 71, 39–53.
Ottati, V. C., & Wyer, R., S. (1993). Affect and political judgment. In S. Iyengar & W. J. McGuire
(Eds.), Current approaches to political psychology (pp. 296–320). Durham, NC: Duke University
Press.
Parducci, A. (1965). Category judgment: A range-frequency model. Psychological Review, 72,
407–418.
Park, J. W., & Wyer, R. S. (1993). The cognitive organization of product information: Effects of at-
tribute category set size on information recall. Journal of Consumer Psychology, 2, 329–357.
Park, J. W., Yoon, S. O., Kim, K. H., & Wyer, R. S. (2001). Effects of priming a bipolar attribute con-
cept on dimension versus concept-specific accessibility of semantic memory. Journal of Per-
sonality and Social Psychology, 81, 405–420.
Parrott, G., & Sabini, J. (1990). Mood and memory under natural conditions: Evidence for mood
and incongruent recall. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 59, 321–336.
Pennington, N., & Hastie, R. (1986). Evidence evaluation in complex decision making. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 51, 242–258.
Pennington, N., & Hastie, R. (1988). Explanation-based decision making: Effects of memory struc-
ture on judgment. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 14,
521–533.
Pennington, N., & Hastie, R. (1992). Explaining the evidence: Tests of the Story Model for juror
decision making. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 62, 189–206.
Pennington, N., & Hastie, R. (1993). A theory of explanation-based decision making. In G. Klein, J.
Orasanu, R. Calderwood, & C. E. Zsambok (Eds.), Decision making in action: Models and meth-
ods (pp. 188–204). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Petty, R. E., & Cacioppo, J. T. (1986). Communication and persuasion: Central and peripheral routes
to attitude change. New York: Springer-Verlag.
Pham, M. T. (1998). Representativeness, relevance and the use of feelings in decision making.
Journal of Consumer Research, 25, 144–159.
Pham, M. T., Cohen, J. B., Pracejus, J., & Hughes, G. D. (2001). Affect monitoring and the primacy
of feelings in judgment. Journal of Consumer Research, 28, 167–188.
Picek, J. S., Sherman, S. J., & Shiffrin, R. M. (1975). Cognitive organization and coding of social
structures. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 31, 758–768.
Prinz, W. (1990). On dynamic pertinence models. In H. G. Geissler & M. H. Miller (Eds.), Psycho-
physical explorations of mental structures (pp. 411–421). Kirkland, WA: Hofgrefe & Huber.
Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1973). What the mind’s eye tells the mind’s brain: A critique of mental imagery.
Psychological Bulletin, 80, 1–24.
Pyszczynski, T. A., & Greenberg, J. (1987). Toward an integration of cognitive and motivational
perspectives on social inference: A biased hypothesis-testing model. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.),
Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 20, pp. 297–340). San Diego, CA: Academic
Press.
396 REFERENCES

Radvansky, G. A., Gerard, L. D., Zacks, R. T., & Hasher, L. (1990). Younger and older adults’ use of
mental models as representations for text material. Psychology and Aging, 5, 209–214.
Radvansky, G. A., Wyer, R. S., Curiel, J. M., & Lutz, M. F. (1997). Mental models and abstract rela-
tions. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 23, 1233–1246.
Radvansky, G. A., & Zacks, R. T. (1991). Mental models and the fan effect. Journal of Experimental
Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 17, 940–953.
Ratcliff, R. (1978). A theory of memory retrieval. Psychological Review, 85, 59–108.
Read, D. (1985). Determinants of relative mutability. Unpublished research, University of British
Columbia, Vancouver, Canada.
Regan, D., & Totten, J. (1975). Empathy and attribution: Turning observers into actors. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 32, 850–856.
Reid, L. D., & Wyer, R. S. (1998). Stereotype suppression in a social context. In R. S. Wyer (Ed.),
Advances in social cognition (Vol. 11, pp. 177–192). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associ-
ates.
Reyes, R. M., Thompson, W. C., & Bower, G. H. (1980). Judgmental biases resulting from differing
availabilities of arguments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 39, 2–12.
Rhee, E., Uleman, J., & Lee, H. K. (1996). Variations in collectivism and individualism by ingroup
and culture: Confirmatory factor analysis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71,
1037–1054.
Roselli, F. (1995, August). Positive affect and heuristic cues in persuasion. Poster presented at the
American Psychological Society Convention, New York.
Rosen, N. A., & Wyer, R. S. (1972). Some further evidence for the “Socratic effect” using a subjec-
tive probability model of cognitive organization. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
24, 420–424.
Ross, L. D., Greene, D., & House, P. (1977). The “false consensus effect”: An egocentric bias in so-
cial perception and attribution processes. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 13,
279–301.
Ross, L., Lepper, M. R., & Hubbard, M. (1975). Perseverance in self-perception and social percep-
tion: Biased attributional processes in the debriefing paradigm. Journal of Personality and So-
cial Psychology, 32, 880–892.
Ross, L., Lepper, M. R., Strack, F., & Steinmetz, J. (1977). Social explanation and social expecta-
tion: Effects of real and hypothetical explanations on subjective likelihood. Journal of Person-
ality and Social Psychology, 35, 817–829.
Ross, M. (1989). Relation of implicit theories to the construction of personal histories. Psychologi-
cal Review, 96, 341–357.
Ross, M., McFarland, C., & Fletcher, G. J. O. (1981). The effect of attitude on recall of past histo-
ries. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 10, 627–634.
Rubin, D. C. (1995). Stories about stories. In R. S. Wyer (Ed.), Advances in social cognition (Vol. 8,
pp. 153–164). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Rusting, C. L., & DeHart, T. (2000). Retrieving positive memories to regulate negative mood:
Consequences for mood-congruent memory. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78,
737–752.
Sanitioso, R., Kunda, Z., & Fong, G. T. (1990). Motivated recruitment of autobiographical memo-
ries. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 59, 229–241.
Sanna, L. J., & Schwarz, N. (2003). Debiasing the hindsight bias: The role of accessibility experi-
ences and (mis)attributions. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology.
Sanna, L. J., Schwarz, N., & Small, E. M. (2003). Accessibility experiences and the hindsight bias: I
knew it all along versus it could never have happened. Memory & Cognition.
Sanna, L. J., Schwarz, N., & Stocker, S. L. (2002). What debiasing backfires: Accessible content
and accessibility experiences in debiasing hindsight. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 28, 497–502.
REFERENCES 397

Schachter, S., & Singer, J. (1962). Cognitive, social and physiological determinants of emotional
state. Psychological Review, 69, 379–399.
Schaeken, W., Johnson-Laird, P. N., & d’Ydewalle, G. (1996). Mental models and temporal reason-
ing. Cognition, 60, 205–234.
Schank, R. C., & Abelson, R. P. (1977). Scripts, plans, goals and understanding. Hillsdale, NJ: Law-
rence Erlbaum Associates.
Schank, R. C., & Abelson, R. P. (1995). Knowledge and memory: The real story. In R. S. Wyer (Ed.),
Advances in social cognition (Vol. 8, pp. 1–85). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Schick, C., McGlynn, R. P., & Woolam, D. (1972). Perception of cartoon humor as a function of fa-
miliarity and anxiety level. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 24, 22–25.
Schneider, W., & Shiffrin, R. M. (1977). Controlled and automatic human information processing:
I. Detection, research and attention. Psychological Review, 84, 1–66.
Schooler, J. W., & Engstler-Schooler, T. Y. (1990). Verbal overshadowing of visual memories:
Some things are better left unsaid. Cognitive Psychology, 22, 36–71.
Schwarz, N. (1990). Feelings as information: Informational and motivational functions of affec-
tive states. In E. T. Higgins & R. M. Sorrentino (Eds.), Handbook of motivation and cognition:
Foundations of social behavior (Vol. 2, pp. 527–561). New York: Guilford Press.
Schwarz, N. (1998). Accessible content and accessibility experiences: The interplay of declara-
tive and experiential information in judgment. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 2,
87–99.
Schwarz, N. (1994). Judgment in a social context: Biases, shortcomings, and the logic of conver-
sation. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 24, pp. 123–162).
San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Schwarz, N., & Bless, H. (1991). Emotion and social judgments. In J. Forgas (Ed.), Emotion and so-
cial judgments (pp. 55–71). Elmsford, NJ: Pergamon Press.
Schwarz, N., Bless, H., & Bohner, G. (1991). Mood and persuasion: Affective states influence the
processing of persuasive communications. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental so-
cial psychology (Vol. 24, pp. 161–199). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Schwarz, N., Bless, H., Strack, F., Klumpp, G., Rittenauer-Schatka, H., & Simons, A. (1991). Ease of
retrieval as information: Another look at the availability heuristic. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 61, 195–202.
Schwarz, N., & Clore, G. L. (1983). Mood, misattribution, and judgments of well-being: Informative
and directive functions of affective states. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 45,
513–523.
Schwarz, N., & Clore, G. L. (1988). How do I feel about it? Informative functions of affective states.
In K. Fiedler & J. Forgas (Eds.), Affect, cognition, and social behavior (pp. 44–62). Toronto:
Hofgrefe International.
Schwarz, N., & Clore, G. L. (1996). Feelings and phenomenal experiences. In E. T. Higgins & A.
Kruglanski (Eds.), Social psychology: A handbook of basic principles (pp. 433–465). New York:
Guilford Press.
Schwarz, N., Strack, F., Hilton, D., & Naderer, G. (1991). Base rates, representativeness, and the
logic of conversation: The contextual relevance of “irrelevant” information. Social Cognition,
9, 67–84.
Schwarz, N., & Wyer, R. S. (1985). Effects of rank ordering stimuli on magnitude ratings of these
and other stimuli. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 21, 30–46.
Scott, C. K., Fuhrman, R. W., & Wyer, R. S. (1991). Information processing in close relationships. In
G. J. O. Fletcher & F. D. Fincham (Eds.), Cognition in close relationships (pp. 37–68). Hillsdale,
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Sentis, K. P., & Burnstein, E. (1979). Remembering schema-consistent information: Effects of a
balance schema on recognition memory. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 37,
2200–2212.
398 REFERENCES

Sheehan, P. W. (1967). A shortened form of Betts’ Questionnaire on Mental Imagery. Journal of


Clinical Psychology, 23, 386–389.
Shepard, R. N., & Metzler, J. (1971). Mental rotation of three-dimensional objects. Science, 171,
701–703.
Sherman, B. R., & Kunda, Z. (1989). Motivated evaluation of scientific evidence. Paper presented at
the American Psychological Society convention, Arlington.
Sherman, S. J., & Corty, E. (1984). Cognitive heuristics. In R. S. Wyer & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Handbook
of social cognition (Vol. 1, pp. 189–286). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Sherman, J. W., & Klein, S. B. (1994). Development and representation of personality impres-
sions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 972–983.
Sherman, S. J., Ahlm, K., Berman, L., & Lynn, S. (1978). Contrast effects and the relationship to
subsequent behavior. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 14, 340–350.
Sherman, S. J., Skov, R. B., Hervitz, E. F., & Stock, C. B. (1981). The effects of explaining hypotheti-
cal future events: From possibility to probability to actuality and beyond. Journal of Experi-
mental Social Psychology, 17, 142–158.
Shiv, B., & Fedorikhin, A. (1999). Heart and mind in conflict: The interplay of affect and cognition
in consumer decision making. Journal of Consumer Research, 26, 278–292.
Shrum, L. J. (1999). Television and persuasion: Effects of the programs between the ads. Psychol-
ogy & Marketing, 16, 119–140.
Shrum, L. J., O’Guinn, T. C., Semenik, R. J., & Faber, R. J. (1998). Process and effects in the con-
struction of normative consumer beliefs: The role of television. In R. H. Holman & M. R. Solo-
mon (Eds.), Advances in consumer research (Vol. 18, pp. 755–763). Provo, UT: Association for
Consumer Research.
Shrum, L. J., Wyer, R. S., & O’Guinn, T. (1998). The effects of watching television on perceptions of
social reality. Journal of Consumer Research, 24, 447–458.
Shurcliff, A. (1968). Judged humor, arousal, and the relief theory. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 8, 300–363.
Sinclair, R. S., & Mark, M. M. (1992). The influence of mood state on judgment and action: Effects
on persuasion, categorization, social justice, person perception and judgmental accuracy. In
A. Tesser & L. L. Martin (Eds.), The construction of social judgments (pp. 165–194). Hillsdale, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Sinclair, R. C., Mark, M. M., & Clore, G. L. (1994). Mood-related persuasion depends on (mis)attri-
butions. Social Cognition, 12, 309–326.
Skowronski, J. J., & Carlston, D. (1989). Negativity and extremity biases in impression formation:
A review of explanations. Psychological Bulletin, 195, 131–142.
Smith, E. R. (1984). Model of social inference processes. Psychological Review, 91, 392–413.
Smith, E. R. (1990). Content and process specificity in the effects of prior experiences. In T. K.
Srull & R. S. Wyer (Eds.), Advances in social cognition (Vol. 3, pp. 1–59). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.
Smith, E. R. (1994). Procedural knowledge and processing strategies in social cognition. In R. S.
Wyer & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Handbook of social cognition (2nd ed., Vol. 1, pp. 99–151). Hillsdale,
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Smith, E. R. (1998). Mental representation and memory. In D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, & G. Lindzey
(Eds.), Handbook of social psychology (4th ed., Vol. 2, pp. 391–445). New York: McGraw Hill.
Smith, E. R., & DeCoster, J. (1998). Knowledge acquisition, accessibility, and use in person per-
ception and stereotyping: Simulation with a recurrent connectionist network. Journal of Per-
sonality and Social Psychology, 74, 21–35.
Smith, E. R., & DeCoster, J. (1999). Associative and rule-based processing: A connectionist inter-
pretation of dual-processing models. In S. Chaiken & Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-process theories in
social psychology (pp. 323–336). New York: Guilford Press.
Snyder, M., & Cantor, N. (1979). Testing hypotheses about other people: The use of historical
knowledge. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 15, 330–342.
REFERENCES 399

Snyder, M. L., Stephan, W. G., & Rosenfield, D. (1976). Egotism and attribution. Journal of Person-
ality and Social Psychology, 33, 435–441.
Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance: Communication and cognition. Oxford, England: Basil
Blackwell.
Sperling, G. (1960). The information available in brief visual presentations. Psychological Mono-
graphs, 74, 1–29.
Spiro, R. J. (1977). Remembering information from text: The “state of schema” approach. In R. C.
Anderson, R. J. Spiro, & W. E. Montague (Eds.), Schooling and the acquisition of knowledge.
Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Srull, T. K. (1981). Person memory: Some tests of associative storage and retrieval models. Jour-
nal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 7, 440–463.
Srull, T. K., & Brand, J. F. (1983). Memory for information about persons: The effect of encoding
operations on subsequent retrieval. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 22,
219–230.
Srull, T. K., Lichtenstein, M., & Rothbart, M. (1985). Associative storage and retrieval processes
in person memory. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 11,
316–345.
Srull, T. K., & Wyer, R. S. (1979). The role of category accessibility in the interpretation of infor-
mation about persons: Some determinants and implications. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 37, 1660–1672.
Srull, T. K., & Wyer, R. S. (1980). Category accessibility and social perception: Some implications
for the study of person memory and interpersonal judgments. Journal of Personality and So-
cial Psychology, 38, 841–856.
Srull, T. K., & Wyer, R. S. (1983). The role of control processes and structural constraints in mod-
els of memory and social judgment. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 19, 497–521.
Srull, T. K., & Wyer, R. S. (1989). Person memory and judgment. Psychological Review, 96, 58–63.
Stapel, D. A., & Koomen, W. (2000). How far do we go beyond the information given? The impact
of knowledge activation on interpretation and inference. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
chology, 78, 19–37.
Stapel, D. A., Koomen, W., & van der Plight, J. (1997). Categories of category accessibility: The im-
pact of trait concept versus exemplar priming on person judgments. Journal of Experimental
Social Psychology, 33, 47–76.
Stein, N. L. (1982). The definition of a story. Journal of Pragmatics, 6, 487–507.
Stein, N. L., & Glenn, C. G. (1979). An analysis of story comprehension in elementary school chil-
dren. In R. O. Freedle (Ed.), New directions in discourse processing. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Storms, M. (1973). Videotape and the attribution process: Reversing actors’ and observers’ point
of view. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 27, 165–175.
Strack, F. (1994). Response processes in social judgment. In R. S. Wyer & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Hand-
book of social cognition (2nd ed., Vol. 1, pp. 287–322). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associ-
ates.
Strack, F., & Deutsch, R. (2002). Reflective and impulsive determinants of social behavior. Unpub-
lished manuscript, University of Würzburg, Germany.
Strack, F., Martin, L. L., & Stepper, S. (1988). Inhibiting and facilitating conditions of the human
smile: A nonobtrusive test of the facial feedback hypothesis. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 54, 768–777.
Strack, F., Schwarz, N., & Gschneidinger, E. E. (1985). Happiness and reminiscing: The role of time
perspective, affect and mode of thinking. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 49,
1460–1469.
Strack, F., Schwarz, N., Bless, H., & Kuebler, A. 1993). Awareness of the influence as a determi-
nant of assimilation versus contrast. European Journal of Social Psychology, 23, 53–62.
Suls, J. M. (1972). Two-stage model for the appreciation of jokes and cartoons: Information-
processing analysis. In J. H. Goldstein & P. E. McGhee (Eds.), The psychology of humor (pp.
81–100). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
400 REFERENCES

Suls, J. M. (1977). Cognitive processes in humor appreciation. In P. E. McGhee & J. H. Goldstein


(Eds.), It’s a funny thing, humor (pp. 41–45). Elmsford, NY: Pergamon Press.
Suls, J. M. (1983). Cognitive processes in humor appreciation. In P. E. McGhee & J. H. Goldstein
(Eds.), Handbook of humor research: Basic issues (Vol. 1, pp. 39–57). New York: Springer-
Verlag.
Tannen, D. (1990). You just don’t understand: Women and men in conversation. New York: William
Morrow.
Taylor, H. A., & Tversky, B. (1992). Spatial situation models derived from survey and route de-
scriptions. Journal of Memory and Language, 31, 261–292.
Taylor, S. E., & Fiske, S. T. (1978). Salience, attention and attribution: Top of the head phenom-
ena. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 11, pp. 249–288).
New York: Academic Press.
Tesser, A. (1978). Self-generated attitude change. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental
social psychology (Vol. 11, pp. 289–338). New York: Academic Press.
Thurstone, L. L. (1959). The measurement of values. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Trafimow, D. A., & Wyer, R. S. (1993). Cognitive representation of mundane social events. Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, 64, 365–376.
Triandis, H. C. (1995). Individualism and collectivism. Boulder, CO: Westview.
Triandis, H. C., & Gelfand, M. J. (1998). Converging measurement of horizontal and vertical indi-
vidualism and collectivism. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 74, 118–128.
Trope, Y. (1986). Identification and inferential processes in dispositional attribution. Psychologi-
cal Review, 93, 239–257.
Troutman, M. C., & Shanteau, J. A. (1976). Do consumers evaluate products by adding or averag-
ing attribute information? Journal of Consumer Research, 3, 101–106.
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1973). Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and probabil-
ity. Cognitive Psychology, 5, 207–232.
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science,
185, 1124–1131.
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1982). Causal schemas in judgments under uncertainty. In D.
Kahneman, P. Slovic, & A. Tversky (Eds.), Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases
(pp. 117–128). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Upshaw, H. S. (1969). The personal reference scale: An approach to social judgment. In L.
Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 4). New York: Academic
Press.
Velton, E. (1968). A laboratory task for the induction of mood states. Behavior Research and Ther-
apy, 6, 473–482.
Walster, E. (1996). Assignment of responsibility for an accident. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 3, 73–79.
Wänke, M., Bless, H., & Biller, B. (1996). Subjective experience versus content of information in
the construction of attitude judgments. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 11, 1105–
1113.
Wänke, M., & Wyer, R. S. (1996). Individual differences in person memory: The role of socio-
political ideology and in-group versus out-group membership in responses to socially rele-
vant behavior. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 22, 742–754.
Watzlawick, P., Beavin, J. H., & Jackson, D. D. (1967). Pragmatics of human communication. New
York: Norton.
Weber, E., Hsee, C., & Sokolowska, J. (1998). What folklore tells us about risk and risk taking:
Cross-cultural comparisons of American, German and Chinese proverbs. Organizational Be-
havior and Human Decision Processes, 75, 170–186.
Wegener, D. T., Petty, R. E., & Smith, S. M. (1995). Positive mood can increase or decrease mes-
sage scrutiny: The hedonic contingency view of mood and message processing. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 69, 5–15.
REFERENCES 401

Wegner, D. M. (1994). Ironic processes of mental control. Psychological Review, 101, 34–52.
White, R. W. (1959). Motivation reconsidered: the concept of competence. Psychological Review,
66, 297–333.
Wills, T. A. (1981). Downward comparison principles in social psychology. Psychological Bulletin,
90, 245–271.
Wolfson, M. R., & Salancik, G. R. (1977). Observer orientation and actor-observer differences in
attributions for failure. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 13, 441–451.
Wyer, R. S. (1970). The quantitative prediction of belief and opinion change: A further test of a
subjective probability model. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 16, 559–571.
Wyer, R. S. (1973). Category ratings as “subjective expected values”: Implications for attitude for-
mation and change. Psychological Review, 80, 446–467.
Wyer, R. S. (1974). Cognitive organization and change: An information-processing approach. Hills-
dale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Wyer, R. S. (1977). The role of logical and nonlogical factors in making inferences about category
membership. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 13, 577–595.
Wyer, R. S., & Adaval, R. (2003). Message reception skills in social communication. In J. O. Greene
& B. Burleson (Eds.), Handbook of communication and social interaction skills (pp. 291–354).
Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Wyer, R. S., Adaval, R., & Colcombe, S. J. (2002). Narrative-based representations of social knowl-
edge: Their construction and use in comprehension, memory and judgment. In M. P. Zanna
(Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 34, pp. 131–197). San Diego, CA: Aca-
demic Press.
Wyer, R. S., & Bodenhausen, G. V. (1985). Event memory: The effects of processing objectives
and time delay on memory for action sequences. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
49, 304–316.
Wyer, R. S., Bodenhausen, G. V., & Gorman, T. F. (1985). Cognitive mediators of reactions to rape.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 48, 324–338.
Wyer, R. S., Bodenhausen, G. V., & Srull, T. K. (1984). The cognitive representation of persons and
groups and its effect on recall and recognition memory. Journal of Experimental Social Psy-
chology, 20, 445–469.
Wyer, R. S., & Budesheim, T. L. (1987). Person memory and judgment: The impact of information
that one is told to disregard. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 53, 14–29.
Wyer, R. S., Budesheim, T. L., & Lambert, A. J. (1990). Person memory and judgment: The cogni-
tive representation of informal conversations. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 58,
218–238.
Wyer, R. S., Budesheim, T. L., Lambert, A. J., & Martin, L. L. (1989). Person memory: The priorities
that govern the cognitive activities involved in person impression formation. Unpublished manu-
script, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign.
Wyer, R. S., Budesheim, T. L., Lambert, A. J., & Swan, S. (1994). Person memory and judgment:
Pragmatic influences on impressions formed in a social context. Journal of Personality and So-
cial Psychology, 66, 254–267.
Wyer, R. S., Budesheim, T. L., Shavitt, S., Riggle, E. J., Melton, R. J., & Kuklinski, J. H. (1991). Image,
issues and ideology: The processing of information about political candidates. Journal of Per-
sonality and Social Psychology, 61, 533–545.
Wyer, R. S., & Carlston, D. E. (1979). Social cognition, inference and attribution. Hillsdale, NJ: Law-
rence Erlbaum Associates.
Wyer, R. S., & Carlston, D. E. (1994). The cognitive representation of persons and events. In R. S.
Wyer & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Handbook of social cognition (2nd ed., Vol. 1, pp. 41–98). Hillsdale, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Wyer, R. S., Clore, G. L., & Isbell, L. M. (1999). Affect and information processing. In M. P. Zanna
(Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (vol. 31, pp. 1–77). San Diego: Academic
Press.
402 REFERENCES

Wyer, R. S., & Collins, J. E. (1992). A theory of humor elicitation. Psychological Review, 99, 663–688.
Wyer, R. S., & Goldberg, L. (1970). A probabilistic analysis of the relationships among beliefs and
attitudes. Psychological Review, 77, 100–120.
Wyer, R. S., & Gordon, S. E. (1982). The recall of information about persons and groups. Journal of
Experimental Social Psychology, 18, 128–164.
Wyer, R. S., & Gruenfeld, D. H. (1995). Information processing in social contexts: Implications for
social memory and judgment. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology
(Vol. 27, pp. 49–91). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Wyer, R. S., & Hartwick, J. (1980). The role of information retrieval and conditional inference
processes in belief formation and change. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental so-
cial psychology (Vol. 13, pp. 241–284). New York: Academic Press.
Wyer, R. S., & Hartwick, J. (1984). The recall and use of belief statements as bases for judgments:
Some determinants and implications. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 20, 65–85.
Wyer, R. S., Lambert, A. J., Budesheim, T. L., & Gruenfeld, D. (1992). Theory and research on per-
son impression formation: A look to the future. In L. Martin & A. Tesser (Eds.), The construc-
tion of social judgment (pp. 3–36). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Wyer, R. S., & Martin, L. L. (1986). Person memory: The role of traits, group stereotypes, and spe-
cific behaviors in the cognitive representation of persons. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 50, 661–675.
Wyer, R. S., & Radvansky, G. A. (1999). The comprehension and validation of social information.
Psychological Review, 106, 89–118.
Wyer, R. S., Shoben, E. J., Fuhrman, R. F., & Bodenhausen, G. V. (1985). Event memory: The cogni-
tive representation of social action sequences. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
49, 857–877.
Wyer, R. S., & Srull, T. K. (1989). Memory and cognition in its social context. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.
Wyer, R. S., Swan, S., & Gruenfeld, D. H. (1995). Impression formation in informal conversations.
Social Cognition, 13, 243–272.
Wyer, R. S., & Unverzagt, W. H. (1985). The effects of instructions to disregard information on its
subsequent recall and use in making judgments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
48, 533–549.
Yamauchi, H. (1988). Effects of actor’s and observer’s roles on causal attributions by Japanese
subjects for success and failure in competitive situations. Psychological Reports, 63, 619–626.
Yeung, C. W. M. (2003). Unpublished data.
Yeung, C. W. M., & Wyer, R. S. (in press). Affect, appraisal, and consumer judgment. Journal of
Consumer Research.
Zajonc, R. B. (1968). Attitudinal effects of mere exposure. Journal of Personality and Social Psychol-
ogy, 9, 1–27.
Zajonc, R. B. (1980). Feeling and thinking. Preferences need no inferences. American Psychologist,
35, 151–175.
Zajonc, R. B., Murray, S. T., & Inglehart, M. (1989). Feeling and facial efference: Implication of the
vascular theory of emotion. Psychological Review, 96, 395–416.
Zanna, M. P., & Cooper, J. (1976). Dissonance and the attribution process. In J. Harvey, W. Ickes,
& R. Kidd (Eds.), New directions in attribution research (Vol. 1, pp. 199–217). Hillsdale, NJ: Law-
rence Erlbaum Associates.
Zanna, M., & Rempel, J. K. (1988). Attitudes: a new look at an old concept. In D. Bar-Tal & A.
Kruglanski (Eds.), The social psychology of knowledge (pp. 315–334). Cambridge, England:
Cambridge University Press.
Zigler, E., Levine, J., & Gould, L. (1967). Cognitive challenge as a factor in children’s humor appre-
ciation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 6, 332–336.
Zillman, D. (1983). Connections between sex and aggression. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Asso-
ciates.
REFERENCES 403

Zillmann, D., & Bryant, J. (1982). Pornography, sexual callousness, and the trivialization of rape.
Journal of Communication, 32, 10–21.
Zillman, D., & Cantor, J. R. (1976). A disposition theory of humor and mirth. In A. J. Chapman &
H. C. Foot (Eds.), Humor and laughter: Theory, research and application (pp. 93–116). New York:
Wiley.
Zinn, H. (1980). A people’s history of the United States. New York: Harper-Collins.
Zuckerman, M. (1975). Belief in a just world and altruistic behavior. Journal of Personality and So-
cial Psychology, 31, 972–976.
Zwaan, R. A., Magliano, J. P., & Graesser, A. C. (1995). Dimensions of situation model construction
in narrative comprehension. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cogni-
tion, 21, 386–397.
Zwaan, R. A., & Radvansky, G. A. (1998). Situation models in language comprehension and mem-
ory. Psychological Bulletin, 123, 162–185.
Author Index

Baron, R. A., 311, 381


A
Barsalou, L. W., 130, 248, 249, 381
Baumeister, R. F., 66, 382
Aaker, J. L., 70, 148, 302, 303, 380 Beavin, J. H., 160, 186, 400
Abramowitz, S. I., 164, 394 Bell, D. E., 303, 382
Achee, J. W., 312, 345-349, 363, 392 Bem, D. J., 35, 62, 275, 276, 382
Abelson, R. P., 3, 16, 18, 21, 28, 116, Bender, A., 191, 194, 393
122, 126, 146, 149, 168, 293, 300, Benet-Martinez, V., 47, 291, 299,
307, 309, 340, 380, 391, 397 389
Adaval, R., 29, 34, 47, 63, 86-88, 115, Bergson, H., 193, 382
139, 142-144, 151, 236, 239-241, Berlyne, D. E., 192, 193, 382
243-250, 274, 307, 309, 333, 335, Bettman, J. R.,334, 382
342, 351, 386, 401 Bhatla, S., 236, 397
Ajzen, I., 358, 359, 363, 386 Birnbaum, M. H., 240, 382
Albarracin, D., 62, 121, 277, 307, Black, J. B., 18, 19, 85, 126, 259, 382
338, 360, 362, 363, 380 Blaney, P.H. 306, 316, 382
Albrecht, J. E., 39. 381 Bless, H., 55, 282, 283, 285, 307, 339,
Anderson, A., 28, 381 340, 342, 343, 351, 356, 382, 397,
Anderson, J. R., 6, 9, 39, 49, 73, 128, 399
133 Bobrow, D. G., 42, 394
Anderson, N. H., 35, 165, 235, 236, Bodenhausen, G. V., 10, 28, 31, 32,
334, 342, 381, 391. 47, 56, 67-69, 110,. 113, 114, 168,
Anderson, R. C., 51, 381 169, 186, 187, 269 , 303, 304, 307,
Anthony, S., 208, 387 331, 351, 382, 387, 392, 401, 402
Apter, M. J., 191, 193, 195, 196, 198, Bohner, G., 307, 342, 243, 356, 382,
200, 381 397
Arkin, R. M., 66, 264, 265, 278, 292, Bond, R. N., 51, 52, 381
324, 381 Boorstin, D., 149, 382
Ashbrook, P. W., 344, 385 Bower, G. H., 9, 18, 29, 85, 126, 128,
Atkinson, J. W., 204, 210, 393 255, 259, 306, 311, 312, 315, 316,
318-320, 381-383, 386, 396
B Brand, J. F., 128, 399
Bransford, J. D., 29, 84, 108, 151, 383
Banaji, M., 13, 387 Brewer, M., 26, 383
Banks, W. P., 114, 381 Brewer, W. F., 3, 19, 383
Barclay, J. R.10, 29, 84, 151, 381 Briley, D. A., 47, 69-72, 148, 290,
Bargh, J. A., 7, 13, 23, 41, 47, 50-53, 291, 302, 303, 383
55, 57, 62, 69, 73-75, 101, 136, 199, Brock, T. C., 101, 387
309, 314, 315, 381, 383-385, 389, Brown, J., 54, 280, 390
392 Brown, N. R., 113, 383

405
406 AUTHOR INDEX

Brown, R., 304, 391 Collins, J. E., 161, 198, 201-203, 205-
Brucks, M., 146, 236, 383, 384 207, 212, 215, 216, 218, 221, 223,
Bryant, J., 282, 402 224, 390, 401
Budesheim, T. L., 13, 28, 32,163, Conway, M., 274, 308, 328, 384
167-169, 172, 176, 178, 251, 253, 401, Cooper, J., 66, 402
402 Corbin, S., 191, 194, 393
Burnstein, E., 122, 397 Corty, E., 280, 398
Burrows, L., 47, 73-75, 104, 381 Costley, C. L., 236, 384
Byrne, D., 311, 381, 383, 384 Craik, F. I. M., 162, 282, 384
Crelia, R. A., 55, 392
Curiel, J. M., 17, 109-111, 396
C Cutrona, C., 289, 384

Cacioppo, J. T., 55, 346, 383, 395


Cantor, J. R., 191, 193, 201, 203, 218, D
403 Danilovics, P., 163, 386
Cantor, N., 331, 398 Daubman, L. A., 307, 348, 349,
Capon, N., 334, 382 390
Carlsmith, M., 179, 385 Davis, K. E., 35, 187, 390
Carlston, D. E., 8, 10, 12, 21, 22, 24, DeCoster, J., 39, 398
26, 28, 39, 63, 122, 166, 240, 271, DeHart, T., 317, 397
311, 334, 383, 398, 401 DePaulo, B. M., 179, 384
Ceci, S. J., 146, 383 Deutsch, R., 8, 399
Chaiken, S., 36, 48, 66, 138, 188, Devine, P. G., 304, 385
309, 314, 315, 367, 381, 383-385, Dickson, P. R., 236, 393
387 Dienes, B. P. A., 340, 385
Chakravarti, D., 35, 392 Dijksterhuis, A., 47, 385
Chapman, A. J., 191, 384 Dijkstra, K., 81, 392
Chartrand, T. L., 23, 384 Duckworth, K. L., 314, 385
Chen, M., 47, 73-75,104, 381 Dweck, C. S., 4, 286, 287, 299, 384,
Chernev, A., 331, 384 385, 389
Chiu, C., 47, 287, 291, 299, 384, 385, d'Ydewalle, G., 81, 397
389
Chodorow, N., 183, 384
Choi, I., 291, 294, 384 E
Clark, M. S., 311, 390
Clark, R. A., 204, 210, 393 Eagly, A. H., 48, 188, 309, 383-385
Clore, G. L., 8, 9, 306-309, 311, 312, Ebbesen, E. B., 103, 385
314, 322, 325, 328, 338-340, 342, Edell, J. A., 235, 385
345, 347, 349-351, 353, 354, 356, Einstein, G. O., 340, 389
382, 384, 387, 389, 395, 397, 398, 401 Ellis, H. C., 344, 385
Cohen, J. B., 307, 358, 393, 395 Ellsworth, P. C., 179, 385
Colcombe, S. J., 4,19, 29, 74, 75, 86- Emler, N., 164, 385
88, 104, 115-117, 124, 129, 130, Englis, B. G., 241, 385
132-136, 292, 293, 384, 385, 401 Engstler-Schooler, T. Y., 138, 397
Collins, A. M., 24, 39, 308, 384, 395 Erdley, C. A., 286, 385
AUTHOR INDEX 407

F Giner-Sorolla, R., 66, 387


Gleason, J. M., 66, 264, 278, 292,
Faber, R. J., 280, 398 324, 381
Fazio, R. H., 83, 314, 315, 358, 385 Glenberg, A. M., 81, 85, 387
Fedorikhin, A., 66, 327, 338, 398 Glenn, C. G., 4, 19, 399
Fernandez, G., 163, 386 Goethals, G. R., 275, 276, 387
Festinger, L., 66, 276, 386 Goetz, F. T., 51, 381
Fiedler, K., 386 Gohm, C. L., 295, 387
Fischoff, B., 285, 386 Goldberg, L., 60, 270, 271, 401
Fishbein, M., 235, 322, 358, 363, 386 Goldstein, D., 54, 101, 208, 280, 388
Fishkin, J., 164, 386 Goldstein, J. H., 191, 387, 393
Fiske, S. T., 36, 47, 217, 303, 307, Golisano, V., 339, 340, 342, 350, 382
309, 380, 386, 400 Gordon, S. E., 27, 126, 127, 167, 169,
Fletcher, G. J. O., 163, 279, 386, 396 387, 402
Fong, C. P. S., 302, 386 Gorman, T. F., 67-69, 269, 401
Fong, G. T., 279, 396 Gould, L., 205, 402
Foot, H. C., 191, 384 Govender, R., 309, 314, 315, 381
Forgas, J. P., 295, 308, 312, 314-316, Graesser, A. C., 4, 18, 28, 81, 117,
318-320, 322, 357, 358, 386 124, 126, 127, 149, 191, 194, 387,
Franks, J. J., 29, 84, 151, 383 392, 403
Freud, S., 191, 193, 204, 218, 386 Green, G. M., 153, 387
Friedman, H. S., 179, 384 Green, M. C., 101, 387
Fry, P. S., 292, 387 Greenberg, J., 66, 395
Fu, J. H., 287, 384 Greene, D., 133,396
Fuhrman, R. W., 28, 113, 114, 132, Greenwald, A. G., 11, 13, 352, 387,
391, 387, 402 388
Fung, H., 145-147, 385 Greundel, J., 145, 394
Grice, H. P., 79, 153, 260, 388
G Gross, L., 281, 387
Grove, T. R., 316, 318, 319, 394
Gaelick, L., 28, 186, 187, 387 Gruenfeld, D. H., 28, 153, 157-159,
Galambos, J. A., 19, 382 163, 176, 179-181, 183, 185, 186,
Garcia, M., 314, 385 388, 402
Garnham, A., 29, 84, 387 Gschneidinger, E., 324, 354, 399
Garrod, S. C., 28, 381
Gasper, K., 338, 387 H
Gelfand, M. J., 291, 400 Haddad, J., 191. 193. 391
Gerard, L. D., 29, 396 Halberstadt, J. B., 312, 313, 317, 318,
Gerbner, G., 281, 387 394
Gerrod, S. C., 28, 381 Hamilton, D. L., 10, 282, 303, 304,
Ghosh, R., 292, 387 388
Gick, M. L., 130, 387 Harkins, S. G., 55, 388
Gifford, R. K., 282, 388 Hartwick, J., 60, 61, 118, 120, 162,
Gilbert, D. T., 102, 387 271, 359, 402
Gilligan, C., 183, 387 Harvey, J. H., 264, 292, 388
Gilligan, S. G., 316, 318, 320, 382 Hasher, L., 29, 54, 101, 280, 388, 396
408 AUTHOR INDEX

Hashtroudi, S., 280, 390 J


Hastie, R., 4, 27, 163, 166, 168, 232-
235, 285, 350, 388, 395 Jackson, D. D., 160, 186, 400
Hawkins, S. A., 285, 388 Jacoby, L. L., 54, 280, 390
Heider, F., 122, 388 Janis, I. L., 362, 390
Heine, S. J., 290, 292, 388 Jasechko, J., 54, 280, 390
Henninger, M., 60, 119, 272, 388 Jetten, J., 56, 392
Herr, P. M., 62, 388 Johnson, M., 307, 390
Hervitz, E. F., 256, 398 Johnson, M. K., 84, 280, 383, 390
Higgins, E. T., 10, 12, 41, 47, 49, 50, Johnson, N. S., 4, 19, 392
51, 52, 55, 57, 66, 69, 144, 148, Johnson-Laird, P. N., 16, 80, 81, 390,
153, 199, 260, 301, 321, 388, 389, 397
392 Johnston, S., 66, 264, 265, 278, 292,
Hilgard, E. R., 142, 389 324, 381
Hilton, D., 262, 263, 282, 283, 397 Jones, C. R., 47, 49, 52, 321, 389
Hintzman, D. L., 40, 126, 389 Jones, E. E., 35, 187, 390
Hirt, E. R., 341, 347, 394
Ho, D. Y. F., 291, 389 K
Hofstede, G. H., 290, 389
Holmberg, D., 295, 389 Kahneman, D., 35, 64, 257, 258, 260,
Holmes, J. G., 4, 66, 269, 295, 389, 263, 264, 280, 390, 400
391, 394 Kane, T. R., 191, 300
Holyoak, K. J., 130, 387 Kardes, F. R., 314, 315, 385
Hong, Y., 47, 287, 291, 299, 384, 385, Karp, L., 311, 390
389 Kashima, Y.,39, 389
House, P., 133, 396 Katz, L. B., 10, 388
Hsee, C., 70, 400 Kelley, C. M.,54, 280, 390
Hubbard, M., 257, 285, 396 Kelley, H. H., 187, 390
Hughes, G. D., 307, 395 Keniston, K., 164, 386
Humphreys, M. S., 39, 389 Kihlstrom, J. F., 318, 390
Hunt, R. R., 340, 389 Kim, B., 294, 295, 394
Hunter, R., 235, 386 Kim, K. H., 24, 58, 59, 395
Hyman, I. E., 146, 389 Kinder, D. R., 307, 309, 380
Hymes, C., 314, 381 King, B. T., 362, 390
Kintsch, W., 16, 39, 81, 390
I Kirkendol, S. E., 385
Kitayama, S., 290-292, 388, 392
Inglehart, M., 308, 324, 402 Klein, S. B., 38, 132, 352, 391, 398
Innes-Ker, A., 320, 389 Klinger, E., 344, 391
Isbell, L. M., 9, 161, 203, 212, 215, Klumpp, G., 282, 397
221, 223, 224, 236, 241, 243, 245, Koestler, A., 193, 196, 391
246, 249, 250, 307-309, 314, 322, Kohlberg, L., 164, 391
328, 335-337, 343, 345, 349-351, Koomen, W., 52, 63, 321, 399
353, 380,389, 390,395,401 Kosslyn, S. M., 9, 81, 391
Isen, A. M., 307, 311, 316, 347-349, Kramer, G. P., 307, 351, 382
390 Krantz, S., 320, 386
AUTHOR INDEX 409

Kruley, P., 81, 387 Long, D. L., 191, 392


Kuebler, A., 55, 399 Loomes, G., 302, 392
Kuklinski, J. H., 251, 253, 401 Lord, K. R., 236, 393
Kumar, P.A., 27, 163, 166, 168, 388 Lowell, E. L., 204, 210, 393
Kunda, Z., 123, 265, 278, 279, 391, Lurie, L., 12, 389
396, 398 Lutz, M. F., 17, 109-111, 396
Lutz, R. J., 334, 382
L Lynch, J. G., 35, 392

LaFave, L., 191, 193, 391 M


Lambert, A. J., 28, 163, 168, 169,
172, 176, 178, 401, 402 Mackie, D. M., 307, 342, 343, 356,
Lampel, A. K., 236, 391 392
Langer, E. J., 300, 391 MacKinnon, C., 164, 386
Langston, W. E., 81, 387 Macrae, C. N., 31, 47, 56, 303, 304,
LaPiere, R. T., 304, 391 382, 392
Latane, B., 55, 388 Maeson, W. A., 191, 193, 391
Lazarus, R. S., 82, 154, 328, 391 Magliano, J. P., 28, 81, 392, 403
LeDoux, J. E., 310, 391 Malone, B., 164, 385
Lee, A. Y., 70, 148, 302, 303, 380 Mandler, J., 4, 19, 392
Lee, H. K., 291, 393 Mankowski, E., 4, 144, 148, 288-290,
Lefcourt, H. M., 191, 391 392
Leggett, E. L., 4, 286, 299, 385 Marburger, W., 113, 392
Lehman, D. R., 290, 292, 388 Mark, M. M., 356, 357, 398
Leirer, V. O., 10, 388 Markus, H., 290-292, 388, 392
Lepore, L., 304, 391 Martin, L. L., 55, 166, 168, 169, 308,
Lepper, M. R., 102, 256, 257, 285, 312, 324, 344-349, 363, 392, 399,
396 401, 402
Lerner, M. J., 66, 269, 391 Martin, R. A., 191, 391
Levine, J., 205, 402 Mayer, J. D., 318, 383
Levine, S. R., 307, 325-327, 355, 391 McAdams, D. 4, 144, 149, 392
Liang, C. H., 146, 147, 393 McClelland, D. C., 204, 210, 343
Liberman, A., 48, 383 McConnell, H. K., 276, 382
Lichtenstein, E. H., 19, 383 McFarland, C., 279, 396
Lichtenstein, M., 168, 399 McGhee, P., 191, 387, 393
Lindem, K., 85, 387 McGlynn, R. P., 207, 397
Lindsay, D. S., 54, 280, 390 McGuire, C. V., 118, 120, 270, 352,
Locke,H. L., 296, 391 362, 393
Lockhart, R. S., 162, 282, 384 McGuire, W. J., 60, 118, 119, 272,
Loftus, E. F., 10, 24, 39, 113, 138, 294, 295, 352, 362, 367, 370, 373,
146, 384, 389, 391, 392 393
Loftus, J., 38, 132, 352, 391 Mellers, B., 302, 393
Logan, G. L., 36, 40, 392 Melton, R. J. 251, 253, 401
Loken, B. A., 11, 122, 392 Menon, G., 283, 284, 393
Lombardi, W., 41, 50-52, 55, 69, 199, Mertz, E., 307, 390
381, 389, 392 Metzler, J., 81, 398
410 AUTHOR INDEX

Meyer, M., 85, 387 O


Miller, C., 191, 194, 393
Miller, D. T., 66, 258, 260, 269, 299, O’Guinn, T. C., 54, 101, 280, 281,
390, 391, 393 395, 398
Miller, L. C., 295, 393 Oishi, S., 4, 292, 293, 385
Miller, P. J., 4, 145-147, 290, 393 Ortony, A., 308, 395
Milne, A. B., 56, 392 Ostrom, T. M., 35, 65, 395
Mindess, H., 191, 194, 393 Ottati, V. C., 307, 337, 395
Miniard, P. W., 236, 358, 393
Mintz, J., 145, 146, 393 P
Mitra, A., 35, 392
Monroe, K. B., 47, 63, 380 Palmer, S. J., 138, 392
Monteiro, K. P., 316, 318, 320, 382 Parducci, A., 35, 65, 395
Morgan, M., 281, 387 Park, J. W., 24, 58, 59, 167, 395
Morris, M. W., 47, 69, 70, 72, 148, Parrott, G., 316, 317, 395
291, 299, 302, 303, 383, 389, 393 Pavelchak, M.A., 36, 309, 386
Moskowitz, G. B., 63, 394 Peng, K., 291, 393
Mueller, J. H., 316, 318, 319, 394 Pennington, N., 4, 232-234, 255,
Murray, N., 341, 347, 394 388, 395
Murray, S. L., 4, 295, 389, 394 Peters, M. D., 307, 309, 380
Murray, S. T., 308, 324, 402 Peterson, D., 163, 386
Mussweiler, T., 64, 65, 394 Petty, R. E., 55, 307, 344, 346, 357,
Myers, J. L., 39, 381 383, 395, 400
Pham, M. T., 307, 327, 395
Picek, J. S., 122, 395
N Pietromonaco, P., 53, 57, 62, 381
Powell, M. C., 314, 315, 385
Naderer, G., 262, 263, 282, 283, Pracejus, J., 307, 395
397 Pratkanis, A. R., 352, 308
Nakamura, G. V., 117, 124, 126, Pratto, F., 309, 314, 315, 381
387 Prinz, W., 75, 395
Nassi, A. J., 164, 394 Pylyshyn, Z. W., 9, 81, 395
Nehrhardt, G., 197, 394 Pyszczynski, T. A., 66, 395
Nelson, K., 4, 145, 290, 394
Newman, L. S., 66, 382 R
Newtson, D. A., 103, 115, 394
Niedenthal, P. M., 306, 312, 313, Rabe, C., 339, 340, 342, 351, 382
317, 318, 320, 335, 343, 389, 394 Radvansky, G. A., 17, 29, 81, 95, 98,
Nielsen, A. C., 280, 394 100, 108-111, 136, 396, 402, 403
Nisbett, R. E., 255, 280, 291, 294, Raghubir, P., 283, 284, 393
307, 384, 394 Rappoport, J., 4, 144, 148, 392
Norenzayan, A., 262, 291, 294, 295, Ratcliff, R., 39, 396
384, 394 Raymond, P., 314, 381
Norman, D. A., 42, 394 Read, D., 396
Nottenburg, G., 18, 114, 395 Read, S., 19, 259, 295, 382, 393
Nowicki, G. P., 307, 349, 390 Reckman, R. F., 275, 276, 387
AUTHOR INDEX 411

Reeder, G. D., 163, 386 Scott, C. K., 28, 397


Regan, D., 261, 396 Schwartz, A., 302, 393
Reich, C. M., 21, 122, 380 Schwarz, N., 8, 35, 55, 64, 262, 263,
Reid, L. D., 304, 396 280, 282, 283, 285, 304, 307, 308,
Rempel, J. K., 309, 325, 360, 402 311, 312, 322-328, 338-340, 342,
Renwick, S., 164, 385 343, 347, 350, 351, 354-356, 382,
Reyes, R. M., 29, 255, 396 384, 391, 394, 396, 397,399
Reynolds, R. E., 51, 381 Semenik, R. J., 280, 398
Rhee, E., 291, 396 Sentis, K. P., 122, 397
Rholes, W. S., 47, 49, 52, 144, 321, Seta, J. J., 55, 392
389 Setterlund, M. B., 306, 312, 313, 317,
Riggle, E. J., 251, 253, 401 318, 335, 343, 394
Rips, L. J., 113, 383 Shalker, T. E., 311, 390
Ritov, I., 302, 393 Shanteau, J. A., 334, 400
Rittenauer-Schatka, H., 282, 397 Shavitt, S., 251, 253, 401
Robinson, G., 307, 390 Sheehan, P. W., 250, 398
Roselli, F., 356, 396 Shepard, R. N., 81, 398
Rosen, N. A., 272, 295, 396 Sheppard, L. A., 307, 351, 382
Rosenfield, D., 294, 399 Sherman, B. R., 279, 398
Ross, L. 102, 133, 255-257, 280, 285, Sherman, J. W., 132, 303, 304, 388,
394, 396 398
Ross, M., 4, 274, 275, 279, 384, 396 Sherman, S. J., 122, 256, 280, 395,
Rothbart, M., 168, 399 398
Rubin, D. C., 3, 396 Shevell, S. K., 113, 393
Russell, D., 289, 384 Shiffrin, R. M., 7, 122, 395, 397
Rusting, C. L., 317, 397 Shiv, B., 66, 327, 338, 398
Shoben, E. J., 18, 113, 114, 395, 402
S Shurcliff, A., 201, 398
Shrum, L. J., 54, 101, 280, 281, 395,
Sabini, J., 316, 317, 395 398
Sacks, R., 287, 389 Signorielli, N., 281, 387
Salancik, G. R., 261, 401 Simmons, C. H., 66, 269, 391
Sanbonmatsu, D. M., 314, 315, 387 Simons, A., 282, 397
Sandel, T. L., 146, 393 Simonson, I., 69, 70, 72, 148, 302,
Sanford, A. J., 28, 381 303, 383
Sanna, L. J., 285, 396 Sinclair, R. S., 356, 357, 398
Santioso, R., 279, 396 Singer, J., 310, 397
Sawyer, J. D., 126, 127, 387 Singer, M., 28, 81, 231, 387
Schachter, S., 310, 397 Skowronski, J. J., 240, 398
Schaeken, W., 81, 397 Skov, R. B., 256, 398
Schallert, D. L., 51, 381 Skurnik, I. W., 63, 394
Schank, R. C., 3, 18, 28, 116, 126, Slovic, P., 280, 390
146, 149, 293, 340, 397 Small, E. M., 284, 396
Schick, C., 267, 397 Smith, E. R., 6, 22, 26, 39, 166, 235,
Schneider, W., 7, 397 307, 339, 383, 398
Schooler, J. W., 138, 397 Smith, S. M., 307, 344, 357, 400
412 AUTHOR INDEX

Snyder, M., 331, 398 Trabasso, T., 28, 81, 231, 387
Snyder, M. L., 294, 331, 399 Trafimow, D. A., 18, 126-130, 135,
Sokolowska, J., 70, 400 199, 400
Sperber, D., 153, 217, 260, 399 Trafton, J. G., 132, 391
Sperling, G., 29, 399 Triandis, H. C., 290, 291, 400
Spiro, R. J., 231, 269, 270, 399 Trope, Y., 36, 52, 367, 384, 400
Srull, T. K., 5, 8-10,12, 26-29, 31, 32, Troutman, M. C., 334, 400
34, 36, 37, 40-43, 47, 50, 52, 57, 61, Turek, J., 191, 194, 393
62, 65, 69, 89, 91, 103, 117, 128, Turner, T. J., 18, 85, 126, 259, 382
163, 166-169, 173, 280, 317, 320, Tversky, A., 35, 64, 257, 258, 263,
350, 366, 367, 399, 401, 402 264, 280, 390, 400
Staelin, R., 236, 385 Tversky, B., 81, 400
Stapel, D. A., 52, 63, 321, 399
Stein, B. S., 108, 383 U
Stein, N. L., 4, 19, 383, 399
Steinmetz, J., 102, 256, 396 Uleman, J., 291, 396
Stephan, W. G., 294, 399 Unnava, H. R., 236, 393
Stepper, S., 308, 324, 399 Unverzagt, W. H., 13, 32, 167, 169,
Stock, C. B., 256, 398 402
Stocker, S. L., 285, 396 Upshaw, H. S., 35, 65, 395, 400
Storms, M., 261, 399
Strack, F., 8, 35, 55, 64, 65, 102, 262, V
263, 282, 283, 307, 308, 324, 342,
343, 354, 382, 394, 396, 397, 399 Van der Plight, J., 63, 399
Sugden, R., 302, 392 Van Knippenberg, A., 47, 385
Sujan, H., 341, 347, 394 Velton, E., 319, 400
Sujan, M., 341, 347, 394
Suls, J. M., 191, 193-195, 200, 204, W
208, 210, 387, 390, 399, 400
Swan, S., 153, 175, 178, 181, 183,
Wänke, M., 28, 163, 165, 283, 285,
185, 196, 401, 402
400
T Wallace, K., 296, 391
Walster, E., 66, 400
Ward, D. W., 312, 345-349, 363, 392
Tannen, D., 183, 400 Watzlawick, P., 160, 186, 400
Taylor, H. A., 81, 400 Weary, G., 264, 292, 388
Taylor, S. E., 47, 217, 400 Weber, E., 70, 400
Tedeschi, J. T., 191, 390 Wegener, D. T., 307, 344, 357, 400
Tesser, A., 342, 344, 392, 400 Wegner, D. M., 31, 56, 400
Thompson, W. B., 316, 318, 319, 394 White, R. W., 205, 400
Thompson, W. C., 29, 255, 396 Wiley, A. R., 146, 393
Thurstone, L. L., 322, 358, 400 Williams, K., 55, 388
Tong, J. Y., 287, 384 Wills, T. A., 218, 401
Toppin, T., 54, 101, 280, 388 Wilson, D., 153, 217, 260, 399
Tota, M. E., 51, 52, 381 Woelke, M., 339, 340, 34 2, 351, 382
Totten, J., 261, 396 Wolfson, M. R., 261, 401
AUTHOR INDEX 413

Wood, W., 48, 384 Y


Woolam, D., 207, 396
Worth, L. T., 307, 342, 343, 356, 392 Yamauchi, H., 292, 294, 402
Wyer, R. S., 4, 5, 8-10, 12, 13, 16-19, Yeung, C. W. M., 328, 329, 331, 332,
21, 22, 24, 26-29, 31, 32, 34-37, 39- 350, 402
43, 47, 50, 52, 54, 57-62, 64, 65, 67- Yoon, S. O., 24, 58, 59, 395
72, 74, 75, 86-89, 91, 95, 98, 100, Youmans, J. E., 164, 394
101, 103, 104, 109, 111, 113-122,
124, 126-130, 132-136, 139, 142- Z
144, 151, 153, 157-159, 161-163,
165-167, 172, 173, 176, 178-181, Zacks, R. T., 29, 108-110, 396,
183, 185-187, 198, 199, 201-203, Zajonc, R. B., 210, 308, 324, 327, 402
205-207, 212, 215, 218, 221, 223, Zanna, M. P., 66, 309, 325, 360, 402
224, 236, 239-241, 243-251, 253, Zigler, E., 205, 402
269-274, 277, 280, 281, 288-293, Zillman, D., 191, 193, 201, 203, 218,
295, 302, 304, 307-309, 311, 312, 282, 402, 403
314, 317, 320, 322, 325-329, 331, Zinn, H., 148, 403
332, 335-338, 345-351, 353, 355, Zuckerman, M., 264, 292, 403
359, 360, 362, 363, 366, 367, 380, Zwaan, R. A., 28, 81, 392, 403
382-384, 386-392, 395-401
Subject Index

automatic influence of,


A on use of categorical criteria,
339-343
Accessibility of knowledge in definition of, 307-312
memory vs. cognitions, 309-310
determinants of, 41, 48-49 vs. emotions, 308-309
frequency of use, 49-52 vs. evaluations, 309
recency of use, 49-52 vs. descriptive bases for judg-
effects on, ment, 325-332
of group membership effects of,
salience, 69-72 on appraisals, 328-332
of prior judgments, 63-64 on interpretation of ambiguous
of thought suppression, 56-57 information, 320-321, 332-337
effects of, on political judgment, 335-336
on activation of bipolar on recall of previously acquired
concepts, 57-60 knowledge, 315-318
on assimilation and contrast, on selective attention and
57-60, 62-63, 65 encoding, 318-319
on avoidance of negative on semantic concept accessi-
outcomes, 69-72 bility, 312-314
on belief formation, 60-62 influence of,
on beliefs in a just world, 66- on attitudes and behavior, 359-
69 363
on comprehension time, 97-98 on behavior in nonlaboratory
on goals and motives, 65-72 situations, 357-358
on interpretation of informa- on communication and
tion, 57-60 persuasion, 356
on own behavior, 72-75 on creativity, 348-349
on perceptions of social reality, on impression formation, 349-
280-282 351
on reactions to rape, 66-69 on life satisfaction, 352-354
on selective attention, 57-60 on self-evaluation, 352, 354-356
on use of stereotypes, 70-72 on use of stereotypes, 351-352
on verification, 98-100 motivational influences of, 342-344
generalizeability of effects, 52-53 performance-feedback model of,
nonconscious vs. conscious 344-348
effects of, 53-56 and procedural knowledge, 311
Adjustment for bias, 55-56, 336-338 as reactions to cognitions, 310
Affect role of narratives in, 324-325
adjustments for influences of, use as informational basis for
336-338 judgment

415
416 SUBJECT INDEX

of competence and self-esteem, Comprehension; see also Episode


325-327 models
of consumer products, 327-332 effect of social context on, 151-188
Affect-confirmation processes, 332- pragmatic influences on, 151-188
335 priming effects on, 97-98
Amusement; see Humor elicitation of observed events, 106-116
Assimilation and contrast role in humor elicitation, 161-
and activation of bipolar 162, 198-209
concepts, 57-60 role of visual imagery in, 81, 83-88
and comparative judgment, 63-65 of situation specific events, 106-116
in interpretation of information, spontaneous,
57-60 theoretical formulation of, 88-95
and use of comparative standards, of verbal statements, 92-97
62-65 and validation, 98-103
Associative processes Conscious vs. nonconscious
in construction of event repre- processes
sentations, 116-123 conceptualization of, 36-37
Attribution processes, in knowledge accessibility, 53-56
effects of perspective on, 260-261 Conversational norm violations
Automatic evaluation effect, 314-315 effects of,
Automaticity; see Conscious vs. on attitudes, 158-159
nonconscious processes on belief formation, 155-158
Awareness; see also Conscious vs. on construction of narratives,
nonconscious processes 260
effect on avoidance of bias, 55-56 in communication and
of group identity, 70-72 persuasion, 159
on humor elicitation, 161-162
B on impression formation, 178-
186
Belief formation and change on information seeking, 162-
formal models of, 60-63 165, 184-186
role of knowledge accessibility on interpretation of emotions,
on, 60-63 186-188
on liking for the communicator,
C 178-186
on memory, 175-178
Communication goals on responses to news, 157-159
effects on memory, 137-143 in informal conversation, 165-186
pre- vs. post-information, 137-143 normative influences on, 178-186
Comparative judgments in social interaction, 178-188
effects of, on absolute judgments, spontaneous identification of,
63-65 153-157
Completion principle of spontan- types of,
eous inference, 268-270 conversational style, 178-186
Comprehender, functions of, 89-92, informativeness, 155-160
106-110 modesty, 175-178
SUBJECT INDEX 417

politeness, 175-178 construction of, 106-116


truthfulness, 160-165 effects of familiarity on, 115-116
Conversational style, effects of effect of thematic relatedness
on information seeking, 184-186 on, 110-112
on liking for the speaker, 180-186 vs. generalized event representa-
on perception of message impli- tions, 116-123
cations, 179-180 number formed of, 106-112
Cultural identity, effects of temporal coding of, 112-115
on avoidance of negative out- Event prototypes; see Generalized
comes, 72 event representations
Cultural norms and values Event representations; see
activation of, 66-67, 72 Generalized event representa-
effect of, tions; see Episode models
on avoidance of negative out- Expectation, deviations from; see
comes, 72 also Conversational norm
on implicit theories, 290-295 violations
on representation of self in role in humor elicitation, 161-
memory, 144-147 162, 198-211
on prediction of future out- Explanation and prediction
comes, 292-294 contextual influences on, 161-263
on regulatory focus, 72 motivational influences on, 263-
on self-identity, 144-149 265
on socialization practices, 144- role of narratives in, 255-258,
149 261-265
on theories of personal caus-
ality, 292-294 G

D Generalized entity representations


conceptualization of, 22-24
Dual-processing models, 35-36 construction of, 23-25, 166-168
Generalized event representations
E conceptualization of, 17-21
construction of, 116-123, 130-133
Ease of retrieval, role of socialization influences on,
in hindsight bias, 285 144-149
in perception of self and others, effect of,
282-284 on comprehension of others’
in perception of social reality, experiences, 125-130, 135-137
280-282 on comprehension of own
Emotions; see also Affect experiences, 133-135
communication of, in close rela- on memory for specific experi-
tionships, 186-188 ences, 137-144
anticipation of, in decision- Group membership salience
making, 301-303 effects on behavioral decisions,
Episode models; see also Situation 69-72
models effects on regulatory focus, 69-72
418 SUBJECT INDEX

H Implicational molecules
conceptualization of, 20-21
Humor elicitation construction of, 121-122
comprehension processes in, 198- examples of, 267-270
204 Implicit theories
comprehension difficulty, cultural differences in, 290-295
effects of, 204-207, 218-220 effects of, on causal attribu-
situational and individual tions, 291-292
differences in, 207-208 effects of, on predictions of the
diminishment, role in, 195-198 future, 292-294
effects of disparagement on, 218- of ease of retrieval, 280-285
227 effects of perspective on, 288-290
effects of distraction on, 210-211 incremental vs. entity, 286-288
effects of repetition on, 210-211 motivational influences on, 278-
elaboration processes in, 279
and responses to sexist humor, of personal achievement, 286-287
215-217 of personal causality, 292-294
situational influences on, 212- role of,
215, 220-227 in anticipated emotional
theoretical effects of, 209-211, reactions, 301-303
220-222 in behavioral decision making,
role of stereotypes in, 218-227 301-303
by sexist jokes, 222-227 in helping decisions, 299-301
source effects on, 218-227 in hindsight, 285
attributions of motivation and, in marital satisfaction, 295-299
223-224 in perception of social reality,
theories of, 192-209 280-282
Apter’s reversal theory, 195-199 in perception of social support,
arousal reduction theories, 288-290
192-193 in personal achievement, 286-
comprehension-elaboration 288
theory, 198-209 in prevention and promotion
incongruity resolution focus, 301-303
theories, 193-194 in reconstructing the past, 274-
superiority and disparage- 275
ment theories, 193 in self perception, 275-276
in stereotype-based behavior,
I 303-305
Impression formation
Imagery; see Visual imagery of communicators, 168-175
Images of politicians effect of social context on, 165-
influence of, 174
on information processing, in get-acquainted conversations,
240-250 180-186
on interpretation of issue in nonsocial situations, 166-167
stands, 251-250 of politicians, 248-254
SUBJECT INDEX 419

role of affect in, 349-351 satisfaction with, 295-299


role of conversational norms in, Memory; see also Reminding
165-186 effect of communication on, 137-
role of visual imagery in, 140-254 143
Information processing models effect of story-telling on, 144-149
conceptualization of for observed experience, 137-143
comprehension, 89-92 retrieval processes, 39-41
conscious vs. nonconscious goal-directed, 42
processes, 36-37 resonance metaphor, 39-40
dual processing, 35-36 storage of information in, 37-39
free flow of thought, 43-45
knowledge accessibility, 41 N
reminding, 41-45
storage and retrieval proces- Narratives; see also Episode Models
ses, 37-41 construction of,
Wyer-Srull (1989) theory, 26-37 framing effects on, 258-259
limitations of, 26-29 informational influences on,
modifications of, 22, 89-92 258-260
role of consciousness in, 36-37 motivational influences on,
Information processing strategies 263-265
piecemeal vs. holistic, 234-253 perspective effects on, 260-263
effect of presentation format on, situational influences on, 144-
234-235 149, 260-263
effect of visual images on, 236- socialization influences on,
253 144-149
Informativeness principle ease of constructing, 257-258
in emotional communication, effects of,
186-188 on social identity, 144-150
in responses to news, 157-159 vs. implicational molecules, 121-
in social communication, 155- 123
160, 180-196 representation in memory of,
Innuendo effects, 157-159 116-123, 144-149
associative processes in, 116-
J 123
cultural influences on, 144-149
Just world, belief in social interaction processes in,
as an implicational molecule, 144-149
122, 268 role in affect elicitation, 324
role, in reactions to rape, 66-69 role in daily life, 3-4
types of,
M histories, 20
stories, 19-20
Marital relationships implicational molecules, 20-21,
communication of emotions in, 121-123
186-188 implicit theories, 20
role of implicit theories in, 295-299 use of,
420 SUBJECT INDEX

in explanation and prediction, S


255-258, 261-265
in jury decision making, 232-234 Self and self-knowledge
in political impression formation, cultural differences in, 144-149
240-251 representation in memory of,
in social judgment, 231-266 133-136
Narrative vs. list-based processing, and social identity, 144-149
232-251 socialization influences on, 144-
149
P and story-telling, 144-145
Self-perception,
Parent-child interaction theory of, 275-276
effects on narrative construction, role of affect in, 352-356
144-149 Self-referent statements,
Perception of social reality, 54, 280- effects on person impressions,
282 175-178
Perspective, effects of Self-serving bias,
on attribution of responsibility, in implicit theories, 178-179
260-261 Situation models; see also Episode
Pragmatic influences on compre- models
hension; see Conversational conceptualization of, 16-17
norms content and structure of, 80-83
Probabilistic inference, of events, 81-83
formal model of, 270-274 role of visual imagery in, 81, 83-88
Procedural knowledge, Social knowledge
conceptualization of, 6-7 approach to investigating, 14-16
in affect-based information generalized entity representa-
processing, 311-312 tions of, 22-24
generalized event representa-
R tions of, 17-21, 116-123
histories, 20
Regulatory focus, stories, 19-20
chronic differences in, 69-70 implicational molecules, 20-21,
cultural influences on, 69-70, 72- 121-123
73 implicit theories, 20
effects of, on anticipated decision independent storage of, in
outcomes, 301-303 memory, 37-39
effects of group membership modalities of, 9
salience on, 70-72 representation in memory of, 10-
situational influences on, 70-72 14
Reminding, referents of, 7-8
effects on later memory, 142-143 situation models of, 16-17
goal directed, 42-43 types of, 6-7
spontaneous, 43-45 validation of, 98-103
Resonance metaphor, Social support, perceptions of, 288-
in retrieval of information, 39-40 290
SUBJECT INDEX 421

Socialization, influence of Validation of information, 98-103


on content of self-narratives, 144- Visual imagery
149 effects of,
on social identity, 144-145, 148- on information processing
149 strategies, 251-254
Stereotypes, on interpretation of informa-
nonconscious activation of, 73- tion, 251-254
75 on processing of new informa-
role in behavioral decision tion, 251-253
making, 303-305 on verbal information proces-
role in humor elicitation, 218-227 sing, 236-244
suppression of, 56-57 individual and situational
Sufficiency principle, differences in, 249-251
Role in comprehension and interfering vs. facilitative effects
judgment, 48 of, 236-244, 246-249
role of,
T in construction of situation
models, 81
Thought suppression, effects of, 56- in narrative-based vs. list-
57 based inferences, 235-244,
Truthfulness, perception of, 98-104, 246-251
153-154 in text comprehension, 84-85
Truthfulness principle, effects of
violating W
on humor elicitation, 161-162
on information seeking, 163-165 Witticisms, comprehension of, 161-
163

You might also like