Source of Ethics Reading
Source of Ethics Reading
1. Introduction – Scope
Ethics is one of the most controversial subjects of philosophy, mainly because of its
immediate relation to our everyday lives. You can hardly find a person who has not postulated
on what is “good” or “bad”, on what is “right” or “wrong”, “ethical” or “immoral”. The goal of
this paper is not to present a full analysis of moral theories or to give any advice. The purpose
of this article is to present the basic principles of ethics philosophy, so as to show the reader
what are the main possible explanations of why we want to be good (or bad)… Or in other
words: to present a list of potential “sources of ethics”. At the end, the conclusions are more
than astounding. What seems to be important is not the answer to the question “What is the
source of ethics?” but ethics itself! And the answer to this question can only come from
outside the realm in which the answer is born…
2. Definitions of Ethics
Ethics (Gr. ta ethika, <= ethos), also referred to as moral philosophy, is that study or
discipline which concerns itself with judgments of approval and disapproval, judgments as to
the rightness or wrongness, goodness or badness, virtue or vice, desirability or wisdom of
actions, dispositions, ends, objects, or states of affairs. There are two main directions which
this study may take. It may concern itself with a psychological or sociological analysis and
explanation of our ethical judgments, showing what our approvals and disapprovals consist of
and why we approve or disapprove what we do. Or it may concern itself with establishing or
recommending certain courses of action, ends, or ways of life as to be taken or pursued,
either as right or as good or as virtuous or as wise, as over against others which are wrong,
bad, vicious, or foolish. Here the interest is more in action than in approval, and more in the
guidance of action than in its explanation, the purpose being to find or set up some ideal or
standard of conduct or character, some good or end or sum mum bonum, some ethical
criterion or first principle. In many philosophers these two approaches are combined. The first
is dominant or nearly so in the ethics of Hume, Schopenhauer, the evolutionists,
Westermarck, and of M. Schlick and other recent positivists, while the latter is dominant in
the ethics of most other moralists. [1]
One of the greatest philosophers, Socrates, posited that people will naturally do what is
good, if they know what is right. Evil or bad actions, are the result of ignorance. If a criminal
were truly aware of the mental and spiritual consequences of his actions, he would neither
commit nor even consider committing them. Any person who knows what is truly right will
automatically do it, according to Socrates. While he correlated knowledge with virtue, he
similarly equated virtue with happiness. The truly wise man will know what is right, do what is
good and therefore be happy. [2]The tool towards that “good” was self-knowledge. Socrates
insisted that every person must reach into himself and learn himself (the infamous “Know
thyself” <= Greek “Γνώθι σ’ εαυτόν”). We must all turn our attention from the outside world
to our inner “world” because this is the only way to know what is really “good” for us.
He insists that ethics is not a theoretical discipline: we are asking what the good for
human beings is not simply because we want to have knowledge, but because we will be
better able to achieve our good if we develop a fuller understanding of what it is to flourish.
In raising this question—what is the good?—Aristotle is not looking for a list of items that are
good. He assumes that such a list can be compiled rather easily; most would agree, for
example, that it is good to have friends, to experience pleasure, to be healthy, to be honored,
and to have such virtues as courage at least to some degree. The difficult and controversial
question arises when we ask whether certain of these goods are more desirable than other.
Aristotle’s search for the good is a search for the highest good. The great philosopher
assumes that the highest good, whatever it turns out to be, has three main characteristics: it
is desirable for itself, it is not desirable for the sake of some other good, and all other goods
are desirable for its sake.
In summary, for Aristotle eudaimonia was all about practicing your virtues to the greatest
possible extent. Everything for Aristotle has a telos (goal), so doing your best towards
achieving this goal is your goal!
Aristotle’s conclusion about the nature of happiness is in a sense uniquely his own. No other
writer or thinker had said precisely what he says about what it is to live well.
But at the same time his view is not too distant from a common idea… [3]
Morality, like art, means drawing a line someplace. Oscar Wilde
In particular, many claim that there is a massive unanimity of the ethics practical reason in
man and that this indicates the inherent (a priori) nature of ethics in us. From the Babylonian
Hymn to Samos, the laws of Manu, from the Book of the Dead to the Analects, from the
Stoics to the Platonists, from Australian Aborigines to Redskins, one sees the same
monotonous denunciations of oppression, murder, treachery and falsehood; the same
injunctions of kindness to the aged, the young and the weak. In some unusual cultures the
law takes on surprising trapping (e.g. witch burning) – yet when surveyed closely these
apparent aberrations can be seen to arise from strongly held but misguided conclusions about
who is good or evil. [6][7]
Ethics NOT based on the judgement of a higher ‘judge’ is not ethics at all; it is just personal
opinion. Some people do some things simply because they feel like doing them, others do not
do the same things simply because they do not feel like doing them. This is what humans do,
in the same way they select what they like to eat in the morning or what they want to wear.
Ethical laws which are not “laws” (i.e. set and imposed by something of ‘higher essence’) are
not… laws at all. This is almost tautological in nature and should be self-evident, but for most
people it is not. If we accept the atheistic opinion that no ethical laws are written by the hand
of the God, then there are no no solid ethics whatsoever. In that case where a non-human
lawmaker of morality does not exist, we just have human laws which simply change all the
time based on the human will. Anything which is built on continuously shifting foundations is
subject to collapse. As simple as that. In the old days, human laws stated that is was legal to
have slaves, that it was legal to kill Jews, that it was legal to segregate between white and
black people. Human laws seem to be arbitrarily selected truths, changing all the time as per
our taste of good.
There are many philosophers who postulated ideas about how society does formulate or
should formulate ethics…
§ Locke spoke about how humans have some inherent rights, which they manage to
cultivate and protect through a social contract, which in turns gives the state power to
create laws to which we must abide.
§ Rousseau also spoke about this social contract, which makes us all come together under
the umbrella of a society which then in turn defines what is ethical and what is not.
§ Kelsen spoke about the hierarchical nature of laws, which gives laws their… lawfulness.
Hart attributed the validity of the highest law to the real event that some people where
organized in a state.
§ Hobbes spoke about the Leviathan – the state – which is what keeps people safe from
dying. The state which of course then defines ethics.
§ Hume as an empiricist, talked about how justice was in fact an artificial idea and that our
logos is essentially bound to the path of our emotions. He thought we cannot deduce what
is justice by reason alone. (so by denying this ability, he simply gave up the definition of
what is just to the society)
§ Even many ancient Greeks adhered to the idea that justice is simply something decided
and imposed by the powerful (Threaymachous, Gr. Θρασύµαχος).
Again, even though this type of solution to the problem seems logical, it leads to dead-ends
as the atheistic opinion that no “lawmaker” of ethics exists (see above). What seems logically
moral for a society, might seem totally immoral for another! Basing morality to the likes of
society is like basing good taste to the likes of fashion…
At the end, it is up to the individual to decide whether he/ she accepts the rules of society or
not. But besides the astounding philosophical shortcomings of such a proposal (which reduces
everything to the subjectivity of a person and to the potential shallowness of a society), there
are also many practical implications: Can a society founded on the rules it imposes on itself
ever be stable? A valid question to which an equally valid answer may exist: Can any society
based on rules it does not impose on itself ever be stable enough?
For example such a model could ask the following questions to help you decide the “ethical”
decision:
Are you treating others as you would want to be treated? Would you be comfortable if your
reasoning and decision were to be publicized? Would you be comfortable if your children were
observing you? [9]
Others have postulated “rules” that could be applied in order to reach an ethical decision. One
of these rules is the utility principle (also known as the “greatest happiness principle”)
which favors actions that produce “the greatest good for the greatest number of people”.
Ethical reasoning, consequently, consists of attempting to quantify happiness, and choosing
actions that maximize it. [10]This rule is a result of social impulses that have been
crystallized into a phrase that puts what society “wants” (as a unified set) above what a
person might view as “ethical” or “good”. Another very wellknown society-based rule is the
“do not do to others what you don’t want others do to you” rule.
Some of these models and rules are indeed useful guides. But one should remember that a
simple model cannot tell you how to behave correctly in all situations. Human judgement and
self-awareness is required. The more you attempt to analyze something the more you lose its
meaning and significance as a whole. No matter how much you analyze hydrogen and
oxygen, you will never understand the wetness of water…
Human reality is messy and ambiguous – and so moral decisions, unlike abstract ethical
principles, are ambivalent. It is in this sort of world that we must live. Knowing that to be the
truth is to be postmodern. Post-modernity, one may say, is modernity without illusions (the
obverse of which is that modernity is post-modernity refusing to accept its own truth). The
illusions in question boil down to the belief that the “messiness” of the human world is but a
temporary and repairable state, sooner or later to be replaced by the orderly and systematic
rule of reason. The truth in question is that the “messiness” will stay whatever we do or
know, that the little orders and “systems” we carve out in the world are as arbitrary and in
the end contingent as their alternatives. [11] Post-modernism surely gives a new perspective
in ethics…
4. Conclusion
The conclusion is that from a philosophical point of view, unfortunately… there is no
conclusion! Philosophers have not agreed on the source of ethics and neither have people.
Even though the notions of good and bad are so close to us, they are still the hardest to
define… And that is why perhaps the extensive analysis of the matter draws us more and
more away from the source of ethics. There are many reasons for a person to do good to his
fellow humans. But philosophy cannot help us substantiate or justify any of them. Only
through self-knowledge can someone begin understanding why he might want to be good
instead of evil. If someone wants to start dealing with ethics, philosophy is the best place to
initialize his search, but not the place to end his quest. Ethics was and still is the most
important subject for our everyday lives and one can only approach it via the irrationality of
realms of knowledge beyond the inherent limitations of philosophy. The wisdom of doing the
right thing passes through the dark alleys of knowledge available only to those who accept
that they possess no knowledge. What is ethical is comprehensible only from those who
believe in ethics without the need to (philosophically) understand ethics and justify their
actions.
Be a good person!
Does it matter why?