Populism Cosmopolitanism and The Reconfi PDF
Populism Cosmopolitanism and The Reconfi PDF
Populism Cosmopolitanism and The Reconfi PDF
103-119
ISSN 1582-2486
http://anale.fspub.unibuc.ro/
CAMIL-ALEXANDRU PÂRVU
Abstract: The present paper questions one of the widespread diagnostics of European
and North-American politics, according to which the emerging political cleavage – in the wake of
the dissolution of the classical left-right distinction – pitches different declinations of sovereignty-
focused populism versus various forms of cosmopolitan transnationalism. In the European case,
this form of political cleavage is deemed to explain some of the current reconfigurations of
member states’ policies and political parties in relation to immigration, as well as an increasingly
popular contestation of the EU exemplified by Brexit; in the US, it would explain the rise of
political figures such as Donald Trump. Against this popular view, this paper seeks to shed light
on a more nuanced understanding of the dichotomy, grounded on Robert Dahl’s original
distinction between the scope and the domain of democratic politics. Whereas the opposition
holds when it refers to their incompatible notions of legitimate political membership, it becomes
much less coherent when viewed as pertaining to political agency.
Keywords: populism, cosmopolitanism, democracy, inclusion, Europe.
1
For an in-depth analysis of the conceptual ambiguities of populism, see (Pârvu, 2015) and
(Pârvu, 2012).
CAMIL-ALEXANDRU PÂRVU
104
hammered that “We will not allow [Brussels] to force onto us the fruits of its
cosmopolitan migration policy”, which he described as leading to catastrophic
results: “First we allow them to tell us whom we must take in, then they force us
to serve foreigners in our own country. In the end we find ourselves being told
to pack up and leave our own land.”3 Still in Hungary, in a 2013 interview
published by Jobbik’s English language website under the perceptive title “The
background of real conflict in the world”, the far-right party’s leader Gabor
Vona insists on delineating the basic cotemporary political cleavage as he sees
it: “the real distinction is not between different religions, countries and cultures,
but between communities attempting to preserve traditions and anti-traditional,
global liberalism.”4 In Jobbik’s parlance, global liberalism is a generic term that
refers to an amorphous group of entities, including various cosmopolitan
sensibilities but also the threat of the international finance. For all these parties,
the crucial opposition is, then, one between what they describe as a morally and
politically corrupt cosmopolitanism, on the one side, and nationalist, nativist
appeals to preserving or restoring national sovereignty, on the other. And
migration – especially in the wake of the refugee crisis of 2015 – operates as
both a catalyst and an accelerator of the political cleavage that opposes
cosmopolitanism and sovereignty-focused populism.
A number of recent studies have focused on this dichotomy, describing it
as essentially centered on the problem of migration and its capacity to almost
singlehandedly reshape the European political system (Lazaridis & Wadia, 2015).
To be sure, there is also a parallel evolution in the wake of the global financial
crisis of 2007, where the more egalitarian demands that press for economic
justice and greater redistribution are also present, revitalizing an important
segment of the more traditional left in Europe and the US. Indeed, the rise of
Jeremy Corbyn and Bernie Sanders, with their unambiguous appeals for economic
equality and rejection of the third-way policies of the New Labour and of the
mainstream US Democratic party, have captured the hopes and imagination of
this re-energized left. The intellectual effervescence around Thomas Piketty’s
book Capital in the Twenty-First Century (Piketty, 2014) is also a testament of
this evolution. But the equally relevant phenomenon that has seen the electoral
rise of the populist political parties and movements of the far-right, is itself as
much a consequence of the financial crisis and the regulatory choices in favor
policies of austerity, as it is of the increased migratory trends following the
collapse into civil war of countries such as Syria and Libya after 2011 (Otjes &
Louwerse, 2015).
For Cas Mudde, however, writing in 2012, the rise of ‘populist radical
right parties (PRRPs)’ is misdiagnosed, and although their electoral trend is
3
See more at: http://www.kormany.hu/en/the-prime-minister/the-prime-minister-s-speech
es/speech-by-prime-minister-viktor-orban-on-15-march
4
http://www.jobbik.com/background_real_conflict_world
CAMIL-ALEXANDRU PÂRVU
106
On July 1st, 2016, the Austrian Constitutional Court invalidated the second
round of the country’s presidential elections and decided that a rerun of the electoral
contest opposing far-right candidate Norbert Hofer and the independent
Alexander van der Bellen should be scheduled over the coming months. This
decision was based on the fact that the Court considered that vote counting in
several counties was fraught with irregularities. At the same time, the decision
provoked renewed anguish across Europe since the nullified elections had been
very narrowly won by Alexander van der Bellen with the slimmest difference of
votes: 30 863, or 0,6%. Norbert Hofer, who lost on May 22nd, was the candidate
running on behalf of the Freedom Party of Austria (FPÖ), a party with a
strongly anti-immigrant and a radically euro-sceptic platform. Van der Bellen
was supported primarily by The Green Alternative – GRÜNE, and while he
won with 50.3 of the votes, it was rather the rapid rise of his opponent that
marked the gravity of the elections.
Equally significant as the surprising electoral score of the FPÖ candidate
was, however, the total collapse of the traditional mainstream political parties – the
Social-Democratic Party and the Popular Party. The SPÖ and the ÖVP had
dominated for decades after WWII the political life in Austria, including in recent
5
For Mudde, the idea that populist radical right political parties are now reshaping the
mainstream politics in Europe is akin to mistaking correlation for causation, as their
relative electoral scores and political influence has not been greater, for instance, than that
of the green political parties – which have, in fact, a greater capacity to enter coalition
governments than the populist radical right parties (Mudde, 2013).
POPULISM, COSMOPOLITANISM AND THE RECONFIGURATION OF CONTEMPORARY POLITICS
107
grand coalitions, yet this time they only managed to collectively garner 22% of the
votes – a remarkable slide into the fourth and fifth positions for their candidates
during the first round of the presidential elections. This trajectory is still
unprecedented in European politics and, for that reason, mustered the academic
and journalistic attention as a first case in Europe where the far-right populist party
is not only close to winning the presidency, but also while being in competition with
another hitherto marginal candidate, an independent with Green movements support.
Yet the FPÖ is not really a newcomer in the Austrian politics. Indeed, in
the late 1990s it had won more votes than the ÖVP (1999) and thereafter
became its junior partner until 2005, in the coalition government led by
Wolfgang Schüssel. Despite the EU diplomatic sanctions and political boycott,
and despite the major internal strife that saw its founding president Jörg Haider
leave the party in order to create a new one, the FPÖ was rather resilient and
managed to pull a significant comeback during this latest round of elections,
when it garnered a much larger percentage of the votes (27% in 1999; 35% and
then 49,7% in 2016). Norbert Hofer was recorded in the wake of the second
round as saying that “it could well be the case that after counting postal votes
that we’re not quite at the front, but I’d say we’ve won anyway” […] “we’ve
made history. Eleven years ago this party had just 3% ... today every second
Austrian voted for the FPÖ.” (Oltermann & Connolly, 2016)
Migration was the key theme of the electoral campaign in the Austrian
presidential elections. Aside from the size of the migratory flow, the tabloid
press in Wien pressed on the notion that the migrants (that were refused the
status of refugees since they traversed ‘safe countries’ before attempting to cross the
Austrian border) were also criminals of a kind that made them incompatible with
‘European civilization’. Their crimes, widely reported as monstrous on the tabloid
front pages, led to calls for the reconsideration of the Austrian penal code – too
lenient in face of such unbridgeable cultural incompatibility. Chancellor Werner
Faymann (SPÖ) massively contributed to the normalization of an anti-immigrant
rhetoric through his own incongruent political evolution: whereas in the early
months of the refugee crisis he had named Orban’s policies vis-à-vis the refugees as
similar to the Nazi policies of deportation6, he subsequently made a U-turn and
allied himself with the same Orban in condemning the German chancellor Merkel
for her open policies sympathetic to the plight of refugees. This was later followed
by his abrupt resignation as chancellor, just a few days before the election, a move7
that contributed to the moral discredit and political collapse of the centrist parties –
the SPÖ and the ÖVP.
6
Austria’s Faymann Likens Orban’s Refugee Policies to Nazi Deportations | Reuters.
(n.d.). Retrieved May 24, 2016, from http://uk.reuters.com/article/uk-europe-migrants-
idUKKCN0RC0GY20150912
7
Shock as Austrian Chancellor Faymann Quits. (n.d.). Retrieved May 26, 2016, from
http://www.bbc.com/news/world-europe-36245316
CAMIL-ALEXANDRU PÂRVU
108
8
I have written elsewhere extensively on the nature, forms, and implications of Dahl’s
paradoxes of democracy’s domain (Pârvu, 2014).
CAMIL-ALEXANDRU PÂRVU
110
learning to see with the eyes of the respective other, in our context: looking at
migration through the migrant’s eyes” (Beck and Beck-Gernsheim 2014, p. 153).
In a similar vein, Jürgen Habermas, in discussing the criteria for
evaluating the justification of the notion of universal obligations that transcend
the borders of nation-states concerning migration, asserts that “the moral point
of view obligates us to assess this problem impartially, and thus not only from
the one-sided perspective of an inhabitant of an affluent region but also from the
perspective of immigrants who are seeking their well-being there” (Habermas,
1996, p. 511). This condition does not appear, to Habermas, hopelessly remote
from actual practice: on the contrary, in fact, he deems the cosmopolitan
condition itself to be within reach: “Even if we still have a long way to go
before fully achieving it, the cosmopolitan condition is no longer merely a
mirage. State citizenship and world citizenship form a continuum whose
contours, at least, are already becoming visible.” (Habermas, 1996, p. 515)
However, for David Miller, such arguments lack a certain condition of
determinacy: in his view, even in the morally straightforward case of refugees
(who have anyway a stronger argument for immigration than economic
migrants), it is not very clear what particular obligation states have: “Refugees
have very strong claims to be admitted somewhere, based on their human rights,
but may not have strong claims against this particular state” (Miller, 2015, p. 403).
Similarly, this focus on criteria of inclusion and exclusion is a central part
of most reputable definitions of populism. A constant part of populist
movements and populist rhetoric is precisely a sharp polarization, namely the
opposition between the people and the elites, or the people vs a certain
antagonistic notion of ‘the other’. For Nadia Urbinati, two essential aspects of
populism are precisely polarization and contestation of representative
institutions. “Polarization as a simplification of social pluralism into two broad
factions – the popolo and the grandi – was since its inception the main character
of populism, its Roman feature.” (Urbinati, 2014, p. 146) Defining the people
becomes, in this sense, the very central rhetorical stake of populism, with an
intensity that distinguishes it from alternative political ideologies and styles
(Canovan, 2005). As such, populism is a radical theory of democracy’s domain,
one that insists on an exclusionary framework for defining it, centered on its
polarization mechanisms.
There are, with respect to democracy’s domain, two important reasons for
the prevalence of the dichotomy populism-cosmopolitanism in the recent years.
One is, as mentioned above, that much of the political discourse of populist
parties and movements is focused, especially in Western Europe and the US, on
the promise of reigning in immigration. As such, these movements put forth
versions of nativist and autochthonist politics in which the promise of a racially
and ethnically homogeneous nation is defended against the groups that are
perceived as essentially different and intruders. Cosmopolitans, by contrast,
CAMIL-ALEXANDRU PÂRVU
112
usually relativize the national bonds and construe a vision of a global community
of fate that endows upon all of us both rights and responsibilities that traverse
the historically contingent political and physical boundaries of the nation-states.
The second reason is that, in many ways, both cosmopolitanism and
populism are construed as theories of political membership, where the matter of
inclusion and exclusion of rightful members and nonmembers is paramount. In
other words, their core normative principles and political positions are seen as
ultimately boiling down to their suggested criteria of legitimate inclusion.
Whereas populists insist that such criteria should be narrowly, jealously guarded
in order to preserve the homogeneity and primacy of ‘the people’ seen in a
sharply polarized opposition to the elites, cosmopolitans adopt a variety of
positions that delineate the notion of a dual membership, one defined by the
states and one defined as universal; furthermore, typically cosmopolitans may
see the latter as normatively more relevant and as potential ground for judging
the legitimacy and justice of the otherwise historically contingent limits of the
former type of citizenship – defined by nation-states.
liberal democracy. Whereas the latter asserts formal and neutral criteria for
democratic inclusion, the former put forth the notion that formerly marginal or
excluded groups have now a central role in reclaiming their political identity as
well as in contributing to the collective political identity of the political community.
It is not simply a matter of challenging the formal criteria of political
membership – but also, on a deeper level, the claim for a right to define the
central political identity (as well as the formal membership criteria) of the wider
polis – by including in that (now, plural) identity, the new types of political
identity that were at the same time challenging the traditional political terms. As
such, the politics of recognition may aim to alter the formal, legal policies and
mechanisms of inclusion – for instance, though affirmative action policies; but the
wider stakes of this perspective reside in the capacity to transform the vocabularies
of political identity and membership, as these have been articulated through the
demands for recognition (and claims against misrecognition).
Distinct from the claims for redistribution that informed the main
political cleavages of the post-war social-democracy in Europe, the claims for
recognition are less concerned with class, social and economic regulation and
taxation policy; rather, these are focused on the importance of cultural
recognition: in the word of Axel Honneth, “a great many contemporary social
movements can only be properly understood from a normative point of view if
their motivating demands are interpreted along the lines of a ‘politics of
identity’ – a demand for the cultural recognition of their collective identity”
(Fraser & Honneth, 2003, p. 111).
Difference and identity are the key terms of the politics of recognition –
and they can be read, I claim, fundamentally as claims for revising the criteria
of membership – in either symbolic or formal terms – of the relevant political
community. As such, they are part of the larger, ongoing debate on democracy’s
domain, as defined by Dahl.
Recent debates on the nature and limits of political representation – and
the oft-mentioned contrast between participation and political representation
that is mobilized within more radical theories and social movements – also
focus especially on matters of inclusion. In a sense, the crucial questions in
many recent studies on political representation – such as Andrew Rehfeld’s The
Concept of Constituency (Rehfeld, 2005) take as their primary normative task
that of re-defining the key notions of constituency, delegation, or accountability –
in order to make the resulting representative arrangements more inclusive. The
widening literature on ‘mini-publics’ as ‘mini-populus’ (Goodin & Dryzek,
2006; Niemeyer, 2011) similarly debates the statistical relevance for large-scale
deliberative democracy from small-scale experiments where controlled
sampling and notions of representativity operate as an indirect mechanism of
democratic inclusion.
CAMIL-ALEXANDRU PÂRVU
114
9
For a rebuttal, see (David Miller, 2010).
POPULISM, COSMOPOLITANISM AND THE RECONFIGURATION OF CONTEMPORARY POLITICS
115
Conclusion
The idea that populism and cosmopolitanism are the two polar opposite
elements of an emerging political cleavage is a promising idea and one that
already structures much of the theoretical premises of recent literature. Yet upon
closer inspection, the opposition is shown to rely mostly on their antagonistic
10
Core Europe To The Rescue: A Conversation With Jürgen Habermas about Brexit and the EU
Crisis. 2016. Retrieved from https://www.socialeurope.eu/2016/07/core-europe-to-the-rescue/
POPULISM, COSMOPOLITANISM AND THE RECONFIGURATION OF CONTEMPORARY POLITICS
117
REFERENCES
ABIZADEH, A. 2008. Democratic Theory and Border Coercion No Right to Unilaterally Control
Your Own Borders. Political Theory, 36 (1), 37-65. http://doi.org/10.1177/009059170
7310090
ABIZADEH, A. 2012. On the Demos and Its Kin: Nationalism, Democracy, and the Boundary
Problem. American Political Science Review, 106(4): 867-882. http://doi.org/10.1017/
S0003055412000421
ARRHENIUS, G. 2005. The Boundary Problem in Democratic Theory. Democracy Unbound:
Basic Explorations, I: 14-19.
BECK, U. 2006. Cosmopolitan Vision. Cambridge: Polity Press.
BENHABIB, S. 1996. Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy. Democracy and
Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, 67-94.
BENHABIB, S. 2006. Another Cosmopolitanism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
BOHMAN, J., & W. REHG. 1997. Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics.
Cambridge: The MIT Press.
BROCK, G., & H. BRIGHOUSE. 2005. The Political Philosophy of Cosmopolitanism. Cambridge,
UK; New York: Cambridge University Press.
CANOVAN, M. 1999. Trust The People! Populism and the Two Faces of Democracy. Political
Studies, 47 (1), 2-16.
CANOVAN, M. 2004. Populism for Political Theorists? Journal of Political Ideologies, 9: 241-252.
CANOVAN, M. 2005. The People. Cambridge:Polity Press.
CĂRĂUȘ, T., & C.A. PÂRVU. 2014. Cosmopolitanism and the Legacies of Dissent (1 edition).
New York: Routledge.
DAHL, R.A. 1989. Democracy and Its Critics. New Haven: Yale University Press.
DELANTY, G. 2009. The Cosmopolitan Imagination: The Renewal of Critical Social Theory.
Cambridge, UK, New York: Cambridge University Press.
ESPEJO, P.O. 2014. People, Territory, and Legitimacy in Democratic States. American Journal
of Political Science, 58(2), 466-478. http://doi.org/10.1111/ajps.12064
FRASER, N., & A. HONNETH, A. 2003. Redistribution or Recognition?: A Political-Philosophical
Exchange. London, New York:Verso.
GHERGHINA, S., S. MIŞCOIU & S. SOARE. 2013. Contemporary Populism: A Controversial
Concept and Its Diverse Forms. Cambridge: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.
GOODIN, R.E., & J.S. DRYZEK. 2006. Deliberative Impacts: the Macro-Political Uptake of
Mini-Publics. Politics & Society, 34 (2): 219-244.
HABERMAS, J. 1996. Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law
and Democracy. Cambridge: MIT Press.
HABERMAS, J. 1998. The Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory (first edition).
Cambridge, Mass: The MIT Press.
CAMIL-ALEXANDRU PÂRVU
118
TAGGART, P. 2002. Populism and the Pathology of Representative Politics. In Democracies and
the Populist Challenge (pp. 62-80). Springer.
TAGGART, P.A. 2000. Populism. Vol. 3. Open University Press Buckingham.
TAGGART, P., & C.R. KALTWASSER. 2016. Dealing With Populists in Government: some
Comparative Conclusions. Democratization, 23 (2), 345-365. http://doi.org/10.1080/13
510347.2015.1076230
URBINATI, N. 2014. Democracy Disfigured: Opinion, Truth, and the People. Cambridge,
Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.