On Immanuel Kant's Concept of Duty
On Immanuel Kant's Concept of Duty
Abstract
Central to the philosophical discourse on duty is its ontology, the
sanctioning entity, and what legitimises an act to assume the status
of duty. Kant conceives of duty to involve the recognition of, and
submission to the moral law. The focus of this work is to critically
interrogate the Kantian conception of duty normatively and the
veracity of its application when the conceptualisation assumes
practical posture. This is to understand as to whether acting from
duty on the one hand, and the universalizability of a moral law
according to which a moral agent ought to act on the other hand,
guarantees that one acts without any consideration, but for duty.
The import is to offer a pragmatic perspective to understanding
Kant’s conception and to realign his metaphysical
conceptualisation of duty within human capabilities. We do this
with the position that duty must be within the practical capabilities
of humans in moral decision-making.
Introduction
The concept of duty is seen as one of the pillars in Kant‟s ethics.
In fact, Kant‟s exposition on duty clearly defines why his ethics is
deontological. After carefully laying bare what he meant by the
good will which is conceived as the highest good in his
deontology, Kant moves to explain how this good will is to be
used in the light of what duty is. In his Groundwork of the
27
UJAH Volume 20 No 2, 2019
28
Abraham: On Immanuel Kant’s Concept of Duty
sees duty and obligation as the necessity for acting out of respect
for the moral law. He further asserted that, the motive of the will,
in Kant‟s ethics, is good only if this motive necessarily emanates
from acting from duty.
In his contribution, Cooke (1974) is of the view that an
exclusive concentration on the Groundwork or the Critique can
easily lead to a misunderstanding of the basic thrust of Kantian
deontology. This is because while it is certainly true that Kant
emphasised the categorical character of moral obligation as no one
had previously, still, Kantian ethics is in a fundamental sense, a
teleological ethic, concerned above all with ends of action, human
fulfilment and happiness. Cooke, thus, avers that;
While Kant held that moral effort is of supreme worth and
while he believed that particular duties were sometime
derivable from a purely formal principle, he always held
that the pursuit of morality would be senseless if it was not
aimed at the realisation of one‟s natural perfections in a
harmonious community. His main ethical concern was with
human fulfilment and the condition of its attainment
(Cooke, 1974:48).
Analysing Kant‟s ethics this way, Cooke (1974) stresses
that Kant‟s deontology has affinities with a natural law view of
morality. In principle, the arguments he puts across, directly
speaks with the position Kant espouses, we however think that
Kant‟s deontology will be more appealing if we look at it from the
perspective of the way humans behave and the influences of
human choices.
Field (1966) also argues that Kant‟s ethics started with
several assumptions about what is right or wrong. For instance,
there was the assumption that if there is a moral law at all then it
29
UJAH Volume 20 No 2, 2019
30
Abraham: On Immanuel Kant’s Concept of Duty
31
UJAH Volume 20 No 2, 2019
32
Abraham: On Immanuel Kant’s Concept of Duty
33
UJAH Volume 20 No 2, 2019
34
Abraham: On Immanuel Kant’s Concept of Duty
35
UJAH Volume 20 No 2, 2019
respect for the moral law. This seems to be in line with the
ordinary conception of what duty is. Thus, in our ordinary moral
lives, there is no distinction between acting from duty and acting
in conformity with duty. We generally accept, sometimes
consciously, an action that merely conforms to duty. Kant (2013),
however, focuses on actions that emanate from duty and considers
only those ones as moral.
We can, however, readily distinguish whether an action
that agrees with duty is actually done from duty or from a selfish
view. It must be noted that there is always the difficulty in making
some of those distinctions when an action accords with duty. For
instance, to use Kant‟s own example, it is always a matter of duty
that a dealer should not over-charge an inexperienced purchaser
and whenever there is much commerce the prudent tradesman does
not overcharge but keeps a fixed price for everyone so that even a
child might be able to buy from him just like any other. The
implication is that people must be honestly served, but this is not
enough to make us believe that the tradesman has acted from duty
and from the principles of honesty. This is because his own
advantage required it and it would not be out of the question, in
this case, to suppose that he might, rather have a direct inclination
in favour of the buyers; so that from love he should give no
advantage to one over another. In this case, Kant (2013) would
say that the dealer did not act from duty or from inclination to act
from what duty requires but merely with a selfish interest.
In furtherance, Kant (2013) claims that only actions done
from duty have moral worth or moral content. The moral worth of
an action, however, goes beyond the value that would merit moral
approval.It is more than its compatibility with the requirements of
duty and also consists in its being motivated in the right sort of
way (Shirk, 1965). Specifically, an action only has moral worth if
36
Abraham: On Immanuel Kant’s Concept of Duty
37
UJAH Volume 20 No 2, 2019
38
Abraham: On Immanuel Kant’s Concept of Duty
39
UJAH Volume 20 No 2, 2019
40
Abraham: On Immanuel Kant’s Concept of Duty
41
UJAH Volume 20 No 2, 2019
42
Abraham: On Immanuel Kant’s Concept of Duty
43
UJAH Volume 20 No 2, 2019
44
Abraham: On Immanuel Kant’s Concept of Duty
45
UJAH Volume 20 No 2, 2019
the motive of duty alone at all times but sometimes act with the aid
of desire. Here, we ascribe the property of intrinsic value to some
forms of desires just as Kant (1959) ascribed to duty.
Duty in morality, therefore, is a matter of necessity. Moral
agents, so far as we are imperfect need to be compelled by reason
to act in accordance with the moral law. The question of what is
my duty and who sanctions duty gives a different form to the
argument. Duty is a moral demand which are sometimes
instinctively innate but sanctioned by society and the individual.
Its origin has been an issue of diverse views. For some moral
philosophers, it is a God-given command to act in a certain way,
an instinctive feeling embedded in man since the day of his birth.
Some, however, ascribe what counts as duty solely on what the
society commands as well as what the individual adheres to. It is
observed that, the use of conscience is a guiding principle to what
duty is. That is, when we fail to perform what duty requires, our
conscience sometimes becomes the best assessor of the morality or
otherwise of that action. This force drives men to perform their
duty in as far as they are rational.
We see of Kant (1959) that he was concerned with setting
up a framework that would operate against plurality of values and
maxims. This strict mission also accounts for the non-simplistic
and rigid interpretation of what is moral. We sometimes allow for
plurality of moral values that have the tendency of moral
praiseworthiness. There are duties like preservation of one‟s life,
development of one‟s talent, etc, which count as duty to oneself. A
possible inference is that there are instances when a person‟s duty
to develop his talent is a duty he has towards his family, friends
and society other than himself. But this view generally defeats the
critics‟ claim that Kant (1959)does not pay attention to the division
of duty to oneself and duty to others.
46
Abraham: On Immanuel Kant’s Concept of Duty
47
UJAH Volume 20 No 2, 2019
Conclusion
Kant‟s idea of acting in accordance with duty emanates from his
idea of the good will. He emphasises on the good will which
according to him must control every action. As a result we might
act in accordance with what duty requires but if it is not from the
good will, the action might not be moral. In this sense, the pivot of
Kant‟s deontological ethics is on duty and its reflection on the
good will. Thus, a moral act is one that is done in accordance with
the good will. The difficulty, then, arises when we ask how we
know an action arises out of the good will. It is possible for one to
act in a good way but not out of the good will, and we seldom can
know the motivating force behind the action. Kant talks about
acting on the good will out of duty and for no other reason.
The satisfaction of the reasoning or thinking side oh
humans is when our action is based on the good will and duty.
When the moral law applied in a legalistic and formalistic manner,
it satisfies the thinking and rational composition of humans. Kant
gave primacy to reason alone, negating the possibility of desires in
deciding what is moral, but we wish to say that desires play a role
in deciding what is good. We recognise the superiority of reason
when deciding which action is right, but desire‟s role is primary.
By man‟s nature we sometimes perform our moral duty out of the
desire to do so. We desire to be generous, honest, etc. This does
not rule out the fact that we also act out of duty for its own sake,
but even when acting out of duty, man does not neglect the role of
desire and consequences. Many people give alms out of pity for
48
Abraham: On Immanuel Kant’s Concept of Duty
the sick, others look after their children out of love, some choose a
career and work dedicatedly out of interest, and people choose to
lecture because they feel the joy to do so. Practically, man acts,
chooses certain careers or takes certain decisions out of desire.
This does not leave out the role reason plays. Acceptance of
anchoring moral assessment on duty and as a result a priori does
not negate the additional recognition of desire or reward which can
be considered as a posteriori.
49
UJAH Volume 20 No 2, 2019
References
Birsch, D. (2002): Philosophical issues: A brief introduction. New
York: McGraw-Hill.
Bordum, A. (2002). The Categorical Imperative Analyzing
Immanuel Kant‟s Grounding for A Metaphysics of Morals
(No. 4/2002).
Cooke, V.M. S.J. (1974): The development of Kant‟s view of
ethics. International philosophical quarterly. Vol. XIV, No.
1
Field, G.C. (1966): Moral theory. London: Methuen Co. Ltd.
Gaus, G. F. (2001). What is deontology? Part two: Reasons to act.
The Journal of Value Inquiry, 35(2), 179-193.
Guyer, P. (2002). The Derivation of the Categorical Imperative:
Kant‟s Correction for a Fatal Flaw. The Harvard Review of
Philosophy, 10(1), 64-80.
Hazlitt, H. (1964): The Foundations of morality. London: D. Van
Nostrand Company, Inc.
Kant, I. (1959): Critique of practical reason. Abbott (trans.).
London: Longmans, Green and Co. Ltd.
Kant, I. (1959): Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals. T. K.
Abbott (trans.). London: Longmans, Green and Co. Ltd.
Kant, I. (1994). The metaphics of morals. Hackett,
Indianapolis/Cambridge (trans. James Ellington).
Kant, I. (1998). Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785)
Cambridge.
Kant, I. (2013). Moral Law: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of
Morals. Routledge.
Kant, I., & Schneewind, J. B. (2002). Groundwork for the
Metaphysics of Morals.Yale University Press.
Kempt, J. (1968): The philosophy of Kant. London: Oxford
University Press.
50
Abraham: On Immanuel Kant’s Concept of Duty
51
UJAH Volume 20 No 2, 2019
52