AND Sciences: Hegel THE
AND Sciences: Hegel THE
AND Sciences: Hegel THE
VOLUME 64
HEGEL
AND THE SCIENCES
Edited by
ROBERT S. COHEN
and
MARX W. WARTOFSKY
DORDRECHT/BOSTON/LANCASTER
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
PREFACE vii
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ix
PETER BERTOCCI / The Scholar, the Liberal Ideal, and the Philos-
ophy of Science 3
1. THE SCIENCES
To the scientists and philosophers of our time, Hegel has been either a ne-
glected or a provocative thinker, a source of irrelevant dark metaphysics or
of complex but insightful analysis. His influence upon the work of natural
scientists has seemed minimal, in the main; and his stimulus to the nascent
sciences of society and to psychology has seemed to be as often an obstacle
as an encouragement. Nevertheless his philosophical analysis of knowledge
and the knowing process, of concepts and their evolutionary formation, of
rationality in its forms and histories, of the stages of empirical awareness and
human practice, all set within his endless inquiries into cultural formations
from the entire sweep of human experience, must, we believe, be confronted
by anyone who wants to understand the scientific consciousness. Indeed, we
may wish to situate the changing theories of nature, and of humankind in
nature, within a philosophical account of men and women as social practi-
tioners and as sensing, thinking, feeling centers of privacy; and then we will
see the work of Hegel as a major effort to mediate between the purest of
epistemological investigations and the most practical of the political and the
religious.
This book, long delayed to our deep regret, derives from a Symposium on
Hegel and the Sciences which was sponsored jointly by the Hegel Society of
America and the Boston University Center for Philosophy and History of
Science a decade ago. To the Symposium papers we have added several
others, and we are grateful to Dietrich von Engelhardt of the University of
Heidelberg and Hermann Ley of the Humboldt University of Berlin for their
agreement to contribute. We are also grateful to Carolyn Fawcett for her
help with the difficult tasks of editing and for the beautifully organized and
detailed bibliographical apparatus.
Where shall the philosopher of science see Hegel's contributions most
clearly? To some, this question must lead to his dialectical logic; to others,
it must suggest the methodology of the social sciences, especially via the
philosophical analysis of history; yet another approach will look to his
theory of knowledge; another his critical epistemology of religious claims;
another his metaphysics of nature, particularly in its analysis of incom-
pleteness and creativity; another his early apen;us concerning labor and
vii
viii PREFACE
cognition; yet others his inspiration for the historical dialectic of science,
technology and society in the thought of Karl Marx. Some of these ways to
Hegel will be found in this book. Perhaps there is no direct entry to Hegel,
and perhaps there will never be a supplementary Section to Hegel's
Phenomenology devoted to the stage of scientific consciousness, that extra-
ordinary stage of Western, and now universal, civilization. We are pleased
that the authors of these essays have so intelligently, lucidly, judiciously
given us their signposts on the way.
October 1983
ix
INTRODUCTORY REMARKS TO THE
SYMPOSIUM ON HEGEL AND THE SCIENCES
PETER BERTOCCI
Benedetto Croce was to live much of his life during the turbulent period in
the history of Italy which had far-reaching consequences for the history of
Europe and the world. At the end of World War II, this Senator of the
Kingdom of Italy and Minister of Public Instruction, owing to his age, refused
the request of Albert Einstein and others to offer himself for the leadership
of a war-weary, war-tom Italy. Croce's whole life might be seen as an
attempt, in the midst of the authoritarianism of the right and of the left, to
discover what is living and what is dead in the philosophy of Hegel. Writing in
1940 on 'The Roots of Liberty' , he said:
The liberal ideal is a moral ideal, expressing an aspiration toward a better humanity and
a higher civilization. The new ideal that is to triumph should therefore present itself with
the promise of a newer, richer, deeper humanity and civilization. 1
And he adds:
As regards our scholars and thinkers of the present time, it is their task to keep the
concept of freedom precise and clear, to broaden it and work out its foundations.
The act of thought, he urged, '''is at the same time the act of willing." 2
This theme is at the heart of Croce's famous statement: "History is the
history of freedom." History is the effort of human beings to create political,
religious, scientific, social and artistic modes of being that allow persons
themselves to define the forms in which the different dimensions (distinzioni)
of their lives will fmd fulfillment.
I happen to think that Croce saw, even more clearly than Hegel, what the
dialectic of freedom involves. He saw, if I may put it this way, that even the
dictum: " ... Ye shall know the truth, and the truth shall make you free",
can destroy the free search for truth, goodness, beauty, and social organiza-
tion. There is not one of us in this gathering tonight who has not seen the
search for truth cramped by some orthodoxy whose purpose was to protect
the truth. In the name of humanity, in the name of the true God, in the name
of a particular ethical code, of a specific aesthetic style, and of the true
3
R. S. Cohen and M W. Wartofsky (eds.), Hegel and the Sciences, 3-10.
© 1984 by D. Reidel Publishing Company.
4 PETER BERTOCCI
II
The French Revolution broke out while Hegel was a student at Ttibingen
University; the singing of the 'Marseillaise', the anti-establishment speeches,
were not events that were taking place in France alone; the new ferment
expressed and inspired Rousseau's Emile and the Social Contract. "It is
Rousseau," Hegel was to write in his History of Philosophy, "who has
inaugurated the Absolute as Uberty.,,3 But as he was to say in The Pheno-
menology of Spirit, "Universal Freedom can produce neither a positive
achievement nor a deed ... it is merely the rage and fury of disappearance
and destruction." Freedom was no unmixed blessing, and for Hegel, the
6 PETER BERTOCCI
educational ideal that will assure men that their freedom will be self-
fulfilling.
III
But, I suggest, even this formulation of the solution is inadequate. For once
men think they have found the way to keep men really free, be it in religion,
in philosophy, or in science, they invite the alternative vice offorgetting that
freedom and reason live in persons who are never complete either in their
vision of truth or their own self-fulfillment. Thus I fmd Croce more accurate
when he says:
But the Jiberal mind ... does what the heart of mankind cannot do: [it] regards the
withdrawing of liberty and the times of reaction as illnesses and critical stages of growth,
as incidents and means in the eternal life of liberty. 6
And, in Kantian vein, I find Croce closer to the truth than Hegel when, in
another context, he says:
Liberty is not dependent on any particular economic systems [and I add political,
theological, or scholarly structures] .... It calls all systems to the bar of judgment. 1
May I, then, finally suggest that as philosophers of science - and not the
least as scholars and as persons - we keep the Kant-Hegel (the MoralWit-
Sittlichkeit) tension before us as a struggle that does not have a or the historic
solution? Can we avoid the great seduction, the belief that there is some
specific system that will solve the dialectic opposition between formal and
qualitative freedom? Is it not our task to keep the tension between formal
and qualitative freedom alive? As Heraclitus said, "Strife is justice", a justice
that never allows the opposition between formal and qualitative freedom to
fade out.
As persons and scholars we conscientiously continue to confront each
other in the search for truth and goodness. We know that every Eden will
have its serpent, that every specific ideal of fulfillment may endanger the
freedom to say yes or no. On the other hand, we must insist that, if persons
are to be free to find full freedom, they must be free to be wrong in so doing.
At the same time we must insist that every claim to actual freedom, actual
truth, face the bar of reasoned judgment. Indeed, must we as scholars not be
aware that the guide of reason is indeed at work in the realm of freedom?
To be free is to seek qualitative freedom in some method or mode of life.
Since every ideal, personal or communal, will be inadequate, persons will be
10 PETER BERTOCCI
Boston University
NOTES
1 Anshen, R. (ed.), Freedom, Its Meaning [by Croce and others] (New York, Harcourt
Brace, 1940), p. 24.
2 Ibid., p. 27.
3 lowe this reference to T. N. Munson, Monist 48 (1965), 100.
4 Ibid., p. 105.
S See edition translated by E. S. Haldane and F. H. Simson [1892] (New York,
Humanities Press, 1968).
6 Croce, B., Politics and Morals, tr. S. J. Castiglione (New York, Philosophical Library,
1945), p. 121.
7 Anshen, op. cit., p. 38.
8 Bradley, F. H., Appearance and Reality (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1897), p.7.
PART ONE
THE SCIENCES
GERD BUCHDAHL
The author of our textbook thereupon makes considerable play with the
hostile reaction that this approach received from the men of science in
Hegel's time, which, he says, was part of the cause of "the emotional drive
behind the scorn which the scientific world came to hold for philosophy".3
Now it is true that no greater contrast could be imagined between the poetic
lines quoted above and the down-to-earth procedures of the sober scientist,
with his concern for observations held together by a network of theoretical
conceptions. I think, however, that where we come face-to-face with such a
total intellectual, not to say emotional, clash of temperaments, it is likely
that there is some grave misunderstanding concerning intentions. More
specifically, Hegel's purposes in all probability have here been both mis-
conceived and torn from their natural context.
For what Hegel tells us at the start of the passage from which I quoted is
that he is attempting to provide an 'a priori notional determination
[Begriffsbestimmung] of light'. By this Hegel means a conceptual formulation
which defmes light as a state of matter, instead of as an independent element
13
R. S. Cohen and M. W. Wartofsky (eds.), Hegel and the Sciences, 13-36.
© 1984 by D. Reidel Publishing Company.
14 GERD BUCHDAHL
(as was still done in his day); furthermore, as a formulation which seeks to
furnish an explication in terms of the categories and concepts of Hegelian
dialectical logic .
Assuming here some familiarity with the outlines of Hegel's logic,4 let me,
in order to exemplify the process of notional determination, give a brief
outline of Hegel's progressive elucidation of the concept of light, as it emerges
from the structure of that logic. Let us take for granted an understanding of
the place held in the logic by the overarching index of 'the Notion' [Begriffl .
And singling out some of the details, we fmd, to start with, that the Notion is
determined 'in itself as pure Being, and in particular, as 'Being-for-itself.
Then, when specified further, the latter is conceived both as 'a one' and as
'a many'. This one-many relation, Hegel claims, further can be shown to
involve a 'process' which may be labelled as 'repulsion-attraction', concepts
which characterise Hegel's idea of 'matter'. 5 Now let us also note that all
these logical articulations have their parallel in Hegel's philosophy of nature,
where the logic of Being turns up more concretely interpreted as the subject
of 'Mechanics', and in particular (for the above example of matter), of 'Finite
Mechanics' (PN, § 262, p. 44; more of this in section III).
We cannot (and need not) - at least for the moment - enter into the
details of this account. We only note that we meet here, in a nutshell, the
kind of consideration of a concept - in our case, 'Matter', explicated in terms
of Hegel's logical categories (all specifications or stages in the development of
the so-called 'logical Idea' as 'Nature')6 - which is what Hegel understands by
an 'a priori notional determination'. In a similar way, as we proceed up the
ladder of the logic with our example, where the Logic deals with 'Essence',
and in particular, with the categories of reflection, so in parallel, in the
Philosophy ofNature, we likewise "enter logically into the sphere of Essence"
(PN, § 274, Z, p. 86) which exhibits matter as a kind of 'reflection-into-self,
interpreted by Hegel here as a kind of 'manifestation'. Where matter at first
was purely inert, at best determined gravitationally and only 'externally', it
has now gained a sort of 'independent existence', whereby it manifests itself
as what Hegel calls 'light', but which - considering Hegel's characterisation -
is perhaps on the whole more adequately labelled a field of energy, appearing
only in certain instances as a 'singularity' (Hegel says 'individuality'); for
example, as the stars; and especially, as the sun (PN, § 275, p. 87).
Now I want to claim that the general significance of this procedure
amounts to an attempt to see certain very general scientific concepts
articulated within a logical framework, to which they become thereby tied, in
order to discover how much can be said about a given concept within such a
CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS AND HEGEL'S OPTICS 15
local context. And this is not absurd. We have in our own day become
familiar with the idea that the broad formative concepts of a science govern
its development, and that a considerable part of their intellectual articulation
relates to what we may vaguely call a 'metaphysical dimension'. And we have
learnt that revolutionary changes in science frequently parallel, not to say are
triggered off by, categorial changes. It is in this way we can understand Hegel
when he writes in his Introduction to the Philosophy of Nature:
All revolutions, in the sciences no less than in world history, originate solely from the
fact that Spirit, in order to understand and comprehend itself with a view to possessing
itself, has changed its categories, comprehending itself more truly, more deeply, more
intimately, and more in unity with itself. 7
Similarly, we find that in our own day we have less difficulty with a
typically Hegelian formulation, according to which 'nature is posited by
spirit', though, to be sure, as a natural process the latter emerges from the
former - remembering that a characterisation of this 'process' itself involves
scientific and philosophical theorising. And equally we can say, with Hegel,
that
spirit is not the mere result of nature, but in truth its own result; it produces itself out of
the presuppositions which it creates for itself, - out of the logical idea and external
nature (PG, § 381. Z, p. 23).
II
not only must philosophy be in agreement with our empirical knowledge of Nature, but
the origin and formation of the Philosophy of Nature presupposes and is conditioned by
empirical physics (PN, § 246, Remark, p. 6).
This confusion of contingency ... , this impotence of Nature, [he writes 1, sets limits to
philosophy and it is quite improper to expect the Notion to comprehend - or as it is
said, construe or deduce - these contingent products of Nature (PN, § 250, Remark,
p.23).
the Notion", but even these enter into science in a very complex way, to be
considered presently. This is not to say that notional exploration may not on
occasion yield some astonishing insights and anticipations, for instance those
concerning the relations of energy and space. Thus, in accordance with the
'notional determination' mentioned before, light, Hegel writes, cannot
properly be said to 'fill space', but only to be "present in space, and then not
as something individual". Indeed, since under the Hegelian scheme, space
turns out to be - as he puts it - "only abstract subsistence or virtual being",
whilst 'light' is the "existent being-within-self" [daseyendes Insichseyn],
there is an aspect of light according to which, in its 'abstract manifestation'
it is as such primarily "spatial, an absolute expansion in space". And, Hegel
concludes, "light is infinite spatial dispersion, or rather it is an infmite
generation of space" (PN, § 275,Z, pp. 87-88).
We may interpret this as a conceptual exploration, according to which we
cannot speak of empty space as such, but only of a spatial field of energy, not
unlike ideas of more recent science. In such terms, field and space are more
closely interwoven than in the traditional Newtonian context, though Hegel's
ideas here go back perhaps also to older medieval or Renaissance or seven-
teenth-century ideas.
At any rate, the question of the relationship between such general ideas
and the presence of empirical phenomena is easily misunderstood. For
instance, one of the 'singularities' in our field of energy is a concentration of
'matter' which we call 'the sun'. Now on the one hand, that there is such a
singularity, constitutes a fact which, so Hegel expressly notes, "is empirically
ascertained" (PN, § 275, Z, p. 89). Here, seemingly a complication arises. For
about this fact he expresses himself in an apparently contradictory way. At
first he tells us that the body of the sun is "the primordial, uncreated light"
(PN, § 275, Z, p. 89). However, immediately afterwards, when enquiring into
"the finite causes of the existence of that which shines in this way", the
account which he gives, in terms of 'internal friction' due to rotation of the
sun, seems to clash with this claim to the light being 'uncreated'.
Now his answer to this problem tells us something further about the
relation between scientific theorising and the Notion. The theory, Hegel
implies, simply states the physical conditions incident upon the production
of light in the finite contingent body of the sun. But this says nothing about
the notional status according to which the sun is a singularity in a spatial
field of energy, regarded as a tense-neutral manifestation. It is only this
notional determination with which we are there concerned. And from this,
'matters of empirical fact', such as the account in terms of friction, cannot be
18 GERD BUCHDAHL
deduced (PN, § 275. Z, p. 90). Evidently, the Notion supplies the conceptual
framework; causal investigations at best are only guided by the conceptions
thus explored.
III
Philosophy has to start from the Notion, and even if it does not assert much, we must be
content with this. The Philosophy of Nature is in error when it wants to account for
every phenomenon; this is what happens in the fmite sciences, which try to trace every-
thing back to general conceptions, the hypotheses. In these sciences, the sole verification
of the hypothesis lies in the empirical element and consequently everything has then to
be explained. But what is known through the Notion is clear by itself and stands fIrm;
and philosophy need not feel any embarrassment about this, even if all phenomena are
not yet explained. I have therefore set down here only the rudiments of a rational
procedure in the comprehension of the mathematical and mechanical laws of Nature as
this free realm of measures (PN, § 270, Remark, Z, p. 82).
This passage makes it very clear that Hegel's philosophy of science has a
two-tier structure. We must distinguish, he says, between the science,
including its theoretical formulations, on the one hand, and "the course of its
origin and of its preliminary investigations" (PN, § 246, Remark, p. 6). It is
these preliminaries that a're governed by notional determination, or - as we
might say - conceptual explication. On the other hand, and this raises the
problem, Hegel also maintains, in the same passage, that not only must
experience "name the empirical appearance corresponding" to the result of
conceptual explication; we must also show "that the appearance does, in fact,
correspond to its Notion" (PN, § 246, Remark, pp. 6-7).
Is Hegel saying that there should, and that there should not, be deducibility
between Notion and phenomena? The answer must be that this, for Hegel,
is a matter of degree. The more 'brute' the empirical data, the less grip may
CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS AND HEGEL'S OPTICS 19
be expected from the side of the Notion. But then, scientific theorising itself
already banishes much of the purely qualitative and specific in its investiga-
tions: the more theoretical thought "enters into our representation of things,
the less do they retain their naturalness, their singularity and immediacy ....
The rustle of Nature's life is silenced in the stillness of thought", in one of
Hegel's truly memorable formulations (PN, § 246,Remark, Z, p. 7).
Now the more theoretical our approach - and it is a commonplace for
Hegel, that the purely immediate sensory datum cannot maintain itself intact
as such - the logically 'softer' the constructions. Here, on the one side,
hypothetical and constructive thinking always allow of alternatives. Not only
that, but - and this is important - on the other side, science itself will always
attempt to tie its fundamental constructs back to still more basic experience,
and for Hegel this means: to the categorial determinations of the logical Idea.
So it is here that we may expect Hegel, when confronted by scientific
constructions and positions, usually and quite properly surrounded by much
that is still problematic, to offer alternatives, or to reject hypotheses incon-
sistent with the development of his Logic. The variety of relations, either
agreements or disagreements, between the developing Notion and the
scientific laws and constructs, is however not so simple, and in this section" I
shall attempt to distinguish several different cases. Studying these in tum is
perhaps the best way of coming to grips with Hegel's intentions.
I have elsewhere argued that there are some clearly defmable groups of
criteria for the acceptance of scientific theories, including conceptual or
metaphysical, inductive, systemic, and regulative or architectonic components
of appraisal. 9 Such a stratification seems to me to have had its first clear
expression in the writings of Kant, from whom - as will be found presently -
Hegel, too, appears to have received his prime inspiration. Hegel's develop-
ment of this theme in rather an extreme fashion presents an opportunity to
study at close quarters the range and limits of such a methodology, quite
apart from the incidental gain of offering the modern student of the
philosophy of science an entry to Hegel's philosophical intentions which has
been somewhat overlooked.
realisation (of which Hegel is well aware) that this involves a metaphysics of
mechanism which forever seeks to absorb the realm of the organic into
itself.12
acceleration. Now, Hegel freely agrees, the "a priori proof independent of
empirical methods" of this expression has "been furnished by mathematical
mechanics" (PN, § 267, Remark, p. 57). It simply follows from the Galilean
law that v = ds/dt = gt by integration.
However, contrasted with this there is also another, logically otiose
Newtonian proof, which involves the "conversion of the moments of the
mathematical formula into physical forces", a force of inertia, responsible
for uniform motion of falling, and a force of acceleration which adds
continuous increments, and thus involves the sum of two independent
elements, when the result is a relation of powers. (This is, of course, a
distortion of the Newtonian argument, though not too uncommon in the
period immediately following Newton.) Hegel's basic objections here are,
first, that we introduce the law of inertia as such, a law which he holds to be
an unreal abstraction, and a case that never occurs in nature; a taking in
separation of the principle of identity, and thus simply reducing to the
tautologies that motion is motion, and rest is rest. 16 Secondly, in the
Newtonian proof we make an unreal transition from uniform velocity to
uniformly accelerated velocity.
And it is this, what Hegel considers a confused Newtonian gloss of a proof,
involving a confused 'metaphysics', that requires replacement by something
more in line with his own notional approach. We must therefore, Hegel says,
"against the abstract, uniform velocity of lifeless, external determined
mechanism" , seek a genuine proof for the "law of descent of a falling body" ,
a law which is a "free law of Nature". As such, its basis must involve some-
thing notional, and it follows that "the law must be deducible from this
Notion" (PN, § 267, Remark, p. 58).
The proof that follows is rather bizarre; but in any case, Hegel is con-
cerned only with what he calls "the qualitative relation" of "powers"
[Potenzen]. The argument (which I will put in my own words) seems to
involve the contention that in free motion, space and time form an intrinsic
whole. If we now plot the axes of space and time, we obtain a space-time
diagram in which we can picture time as a second dimension, the diagram
resulting in a plane figure whose simplest representation is a square. ('Raising
to a power', it will be remembered, is the third determination of numbers,
which are a development of 'the quantum'; and here the simplest case,
accoqling to Hegel, is 'the square'. This third determination is regarded as the
"equality of the multiple and the unit [Anzahl und Einheit] ". 'The square'
has thus a definitive place in the development of the logical Idea.)17 And
this is the notional explication or 'proof of why the spaces traversed when
CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS AND HEGEL'S OPTICS 23
4. Probably the prime inspiration for Hegel's approach, which centres on the
need for a notional determination of the elements of natural science, was
Kant's attempt to construct the metaphysical foundations of the basic
conceptions of dynamics, especially of matter and force. It is not too much
to say that, as for Schelling, so for Hegel, this was in all probability the most
important source for his whole approach, with Hegel sticking more respon-
sibly than Schelling to the basic intentions of Kant's procedure. Kant's
metaphysical exposition, Hegel says in the Science of Logic
is noteworthy, ...... because as an experiment with the Notion it at least gave the
impulse to the more recent philosophy of nature, to a philosophy which does not make
nature as given in sense-perception the basis of science, but which goes to the absolute
Notion for its determination (SL [M] , p. 179).
Those who have difficulty in unravelling Hegel's views about the relation
between notional determination and empirical science may therefore hope to
gain some light from Kant's procedure in the Metaphysical Foundations,
provided that has been properly understood.
Let us briefly consider Hegel's treatment of the subject of matter and
force. Here again, Hegel follows the twofold path of empirical and notional
determination. Whilst empirical science operates with the concept of matter
regarded as subject to the twin forces of attraction and repulsion, these
forces, says Hegel,
24 GERD BUCHDAHL
in so far as they are regarded as forces of empirical matter, are also based on the pure
determinations here considered, of the one and the many and their interrelationships,
which, because these names are most obvious [the Encyclopedia describes them as
'metaphorical expressions' - bildliche Ausdrucke), 1 9 I have called repulsion and
attraction (SL [M), p. 179).
Now what is here called 'pure determination' of matter had been described
by Kant as an a priori elucidation of its concept; an elucidation which was
supposed to establish the 'possibility of matter' by 'constructing' the concept
through its reduction to the just-mentioned fundamental forces. The method-
ological approach here followed by Kant involves a sharp distinction between
establishing the 'possibility' of a scientific construct, and the inductive
'probability' of its application. 2o In the present context, it is of course the
establishment of 'the general possibility of the concept of matter,21 with
which we are concerned. Actually, Kant's procedure, 'constructive' from one
point of view, from another was basically 'analytical' (as Hegel rightly points
out (SL [M] , p. 179)); it departs from an analysis of the meaning of matter as
impenetrable, by interpreting this property as repulsive force. He then
proceeds to show that matter cannot be conceived as existing with repulsion
alone without attraction; which completes the exposition.
This, then, is an extremely clear case of conceptual analysis or explication;
it seeks to show how much of the concept of matter is already contained in
our basic modes of categorial thinking; and on the other side, how much of
the fabric employed in empirical science can be shown to answer to this
conceptual explication. There is no attempt to 'deduce' attractive or repulsive
forces, let alone their laws of action.
This looseness of fit is also quite apparent in Hegel's treatment of
repulsion and attraction, emerging as they do from within his own notional
analysis as metaphorical expressions - evidently thus borrowed from the
domain in which they originally have their empirical home.
The details of Hegel's account would take too long to unravel at any
length. Of Kant's analysis he complains that although it has the merit of
making the two forces internal to matter, deriving - unlike in the Newtonian
procedure - matter from the forces, it still leaves them standing side by side,
independent of each other (SL [M], p. 181), instead of treating them as
"moments which pass over into each other" (SL [M] , p. 182), an instance of
the process of the Hegelian dialectical evolution of the logical Idea. The
argument, as already mentioned at the start, is that Being, qua being-for-
itself, is a one; yet as such, at the same time, it relates itself to itself as an
'other'. Hence the one is incompatible with itself; it is "that which thrusts
CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS AND HEGEL'S OPTICS 25
itself off itself; and what it thus posits itself as, is the many. Hence we may
designate this side of the process of being-for-itself through the metaphorical
expression, repulsion" .22
The intention of the argument, if not its logical formulation, at least may
be clear; when reflecting on matter as one, this turns into many; but the
conclusion can maintain itself only via a process which bears similarity to
what in mechanics is called 'repulsion'. Or rather, that concept, in its notional
determination, boils down to this fundamental aspect of the being-for-itself
of anything in respect of its material aspect. Similarly, each of the many is
itself a one, and in this way turns round into its opposite, viz. attraction.
Attraction and repulsion, on this view, are a dual aspect of the one-and-the-
many.
Modern (Le. Newtonian) physics, comments Hegel, still operates, through
its conception of the molecule, with the picture-aspect of the old atom, even
though admittedly - unlike original atomic theory - it has added the force
of attraction to that of repulsion. "But their mutual relation, what
constitutes their concrete and true nature, must be tom from its opaque
confusion, in which even Kant's Metaphysical Foundations of Science has still
left it.,,23 In other words, attraction and repulsion must not be introjected
ab extemo, but need to be explicated as logical aspects of the Notion
involved in the very consideration of matter qua matter, under its aspect of
the one and the many.
Hegel's analysis has thus a dual aspect. On the one hand, it seeks to incor-
porate these forces into the intimate process of the logical Idea, and thus
project what Kant had called 'the possibility' of the concept. On the other
hand, the method is so contrived as to deprive forces of their quasi-
independent reality, or as merely borrowed from the theory of science. At
the same time it is clear that Hegel's derivation is meant also to support his
preference for the use of phenomenological theory-types, as already noted.
For his 'deduction' is incidentally meant to have the effect of de-substantial-
ising the forces of Newtonian physics, and thus to point to the adoption of
the Continental 'mathematical' approach.
IV
With these explanations, we may now hope to gain some understanding of the
significance of Hegel's philosophy of optics for his general philosophy of
science. We shall be prepared for a phenomenological approach to that
theory. We shall expect a rejection of any realist interpretation of the
26 GERD BUCHDAHL
Let us, however, now briefly consider the laws of rectilinear propagation,
reflection and refraction. Since any theory of reflection in terms of the
motion of luminiferous particles or the propagation of waves is rejected, only
notional considerations are left, mixed up in a peculiar manner with a purely
geometrical approach, perhaps somewhat akin to the procedure of Ptolemy's
theory of reflection?8
The law of rectilinear propagation, according to Hegel, is implied by the
fact that the manifestation of objects to each other is a purely spatial
relationship; furthermore, since no other conditions obtain bar this, it must
be "direct or rectilinear". Presumably this conclusion assumes some principle
of simplicity, though Hegel does not make this explicit. Besides, it is not clear
whether 'rectilinearity' has any meaning without the conception of a ray;
but as already remarked, Hegel did not object to the use of this conception,
provided it be treated as a purely geometrical model.
As regards reflection, Hegel's account is extremely brief, implying that we
must not regard it as a form of deductive derivation. All consideration of
material categories of transmission, he tells us, must be excluded. We are in
these considerations simply to confine ourselves to the defmition of light,
"as abstract ideality, as inseparable self-externality", as "intrinsically spatial"
(PN, § 278, p. 96). Once again, use is made of the basic notion ofreflection:
one object can be manifest to another, and that to a third: this is a basic
aspect of light. Hegel now at once concludes - hardly a deductively mediated
inference - that
in these spatial determinations the law of manifestation can only be that of equality -
the equality of the angles of incidence and reflection, and the unity of the plane of these
angles. Nothing whatever is present which could in any way alter the identity of the
relation (PN, § 278, p. 96).
Evidently, the 'can only be' of the text, and the appeal to simplicity con-
sideration, shows that Hegel is not providing a deductive account but a
notional contribution to what he knows is supported on experimental
grounds. But such looseness pays of course its price. For as soon as we turn
to more complex phenomena, e.g. of the polarization of light, the notional
account can get us no further. Hegel, instead of admitting this, however,
simply falls back altogether on to the pure description of a limiting case: the
mere determination of the angle at which a second reflection occurs does not
lead to any diminution of the light intensity.
30 GERD BUCHDAHL
from above ought not seem to be raised. Yet it is! (PN, § 318, Remark, Z,
p.191).
This is a prominent specimen of one of Hegel's 'counter-examples', to
'prove' that even the physicists' own theory leads to a conclusion inconsistent
with observation! I mention this to show that Hegel does not oppose physical
theory merely on ideological grounds. Unfortunately, the counter-example
involves a confusion: since both the eye of the observer and the coin are
objects extended in space, Hegel's assumption of zero-angle of incidence does
not apply. Still, as usual, we should note the intention, and the method-
ological implications, which make good sense.
What of the 'positive', notional 'explanation' of refraction? Let me state
it in brief outline. We need to stick entirely to the phenomenological
situation, employing solely concepts that have emerged in the course of the
increasing specification of the logical Idea. The concepts involved are light,
the transparency of the two media, and one primary property - there are
others, but they have less relevance in the context - viz. 'specific gravity',
or the relative density of the media. Then, Hegel holds, the only property
which has any relevance to the passage of light from one medium to the other
must be the specific gravity.
Hegel now proceeds to a move, very difficult to grasp for any quantitative,
let alone mechanistically orientated approach, although it bears a curious
likeness to one of the many hypothetical accounts of refraction - though
unlike Hegel's, framed in purely quantitative terms - which Kepler con-
jectured in his treatise on optics of 1604, theAd Vitellionem Paralipomena. 30
Whether Hegel, an avid student of Kepler's writings, was influenced by this
work is not known. At any rate, Hegel talks as though the specific gravity of
one medium could be 'active'; as though, for instance, the specific gravity of
the air could become affected by the specific gravity of the water (PN, § 318,
Remark, Z, p. 190); specific gravity being regarded here as a hybrid
quantitative-qualitative concept, defined as 'space-determining form'; as
though it were a kind of activity whose effects can spread?! Suppose now
the eye, starting from the visual medium of the air, to reach a certain volume
of the water, say V w; we may then regard the situation as though a corres-
ponding volume Vw of air had been impregnated with the specific gravity of
water, contained in that volume, the latter resulting in the determination of
a new (apparent) volume. Since the imaginary mass of air in the volume V w
is constant, to the greater specific gravity there must therefore correspond
a smaller volume; the volume of 'air' (i.e. water) will seem diminished, which
was what we tried to explain. (Remember: density = v~a:e.)
32 GERD BUCHDAHL
Perhaps the fascination of the whole story for us is just that it is so vastly
at variance with the methodological constraints of the scientific tradition
which has come down to us these last 300 years. It provides us with a
reductio ad absurdum of that view which I already mentioned when quoting
from the Hegelian introductory passage to the Philosophy of Nature, where
we are told that scientific revolutions originate solely from the change in
categories through which Spirit seeks to comprehend itself more truly (PN,
§ 246,Remark, Z, p. 11).
Light must not be represented as a material propagation: the water, as visible, is ideally
present in the air. This presence is a specific gravity with this specific determinateness
alone, the water preserves and exerts itself in that into which it has been transformed,
and so transforms this its transformation into itself (PN, § 318, Remark, Z, p. 190).
As the hero I imagine is actively present in me, if only in ideal fashion, so too does the
air receive within itself the visual space of the water and dwarf it to itself (PN, § 318,
Remark, Z, p. 191).
Evidently, this is 'a different way of seeing' the physical phenomenon. The
fact that the natural manifold needs interpretation through spiritual articula-
tion has become transformed into a method of envisaging the phenomena
themselves as spiritual. It has become fashionable recently to emphasise that
Hegel's Logic is not the logic of Russell or Frege, but that its roots lie in
the mystical visions of a Jacob Boehme or a Meister Eckhart, and that his
influence must be sought in the direction of the poets, both from whom
34 GERD BUCHDAHL
University of Cambridge
England
NOTES
1 Lloyd William Taylor, Physics. The Pioneer Science (Boston, Houghton Mifflin, 1941),
p. 490. (New York, Dover, 1959,2 vols.)
2 I have occasionally (as here) modified Miller's translation. Taylor himself actually
quotes from the summary given by J. B. Stallo, General Principles of the Philosophy of
Nature (London, 1847).
3 Taylor,loc. cit.
4 I cannot do better than refer the reader to J. N. Findlay's excellent modern introduc-
tion, Hegel. A Re-examination (London, George Allen and Unwin; New York,
Humanities Press, 1958).
5 Cf. Logik, §§ 96-7, pp. 189-92. I have made my own translations of relevant
passages from the Logik, Wallace's rather free translation being often too unreliable
(The Logic of Hegel, second edition (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1892». I have, however,
given the corresponding page references from Wallace, thus here: L [W, 1892], pp.
179-81.
6 PN, § 86,Z, 2, p.166;cf. Logik. § 131,Z, p. 261;L [W, 1892], pp. 159,240.
7 PN. § 246, Remark, p. 11. Cf. also PG, § 381. Z, pp. 21-3, for a summary of Hegel's
position.
S Cf. Logik. § 86, Z, 2, pp. 168-8; L [W, 1982], pp. 159-61. Cf. also Logik. § 160, Z,
p. 315; L [W, 1892], p. 287.
CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS AND HEGEL'S OPTICS 35
9 Cf. Gerd Buchdahl, 'History of Science and Criteria of Choice', in Historical and
Philosophical Perspectives of Science. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science,
vol. 5 (ed. R. Stuewer, Minneapolis, Minnesota University Press, 1970), pp. 204-30. I
have used a similar criterial scheme for a more general characterisation of Hegel's
Philosophy of Nature in 'Hegel's Philosophy of Nature and the Structure of Science',
Ratio 15 (1973), 1-27.
10 Logik, § 136, pp. 269-75;L [W, 1892], pp. 246-51.
11 Logik, § 140, p. 276;L [W, 1892], p. 253;PN, § 246, Renwrk, Z, p. 12.
12 Cf. Hegel's remarks in Logik, § 195, Z, p. 369 (section on 'Mechanism'); L [W,
1892], p. 337.
13 I have paraphrased this, since neither the German text, still less the translation, give
much inkling of what Hegel intended.
14 Logik, § 136, p. 270; L [W, 1892], p. 248.
15 PN, § 267, Remark, p. 58n. Cf. also p. 67, the reference to Francoeur's Traite
elementaire de mecanique (Paris, 1798). Hegel goes on to say that Newton's presentation
is such that 'what have been adduced are not so much propositions as bare facts; and the
requisite reflection is only this, that the distinctions and determinations brought forward
by mathematical analysis, and the course it has to follow in accordance with its method,
are wholly distinct from what is supposed to have physical reality'.
16 PN, § 266, Renwrk, p. 52; cf. SL [M], pp. 379 ff.
17 Cf.Logik, § 102,pp.203-4;L [W, 1892],pp.190-92.
18 PN, § 267, Renwrk, p. 59. For a somewhat fuller development, see my Ratio article,
note 9 above, sect. vii, pp. 17 - 21.
19 Logik, §97,Z,p.I92;L [W,1892],p.181.
20 Cf. Gerd Buchdahl, Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science. The Qassical
Sources: Descartes to Kant (Oxford, Blackwell; Cambridge, Mass., MIT Press, 1969),
ch.8, sect. 4c(iv), pp. 512-16.
21 Cf. Kant's Prolegomena and Metaphysical Foundations of Science (tr. E. B. Bax,
London, Bell, 1883), ch. II: 'General Observation on Dynamics', p. 200; Schriften
(Ak. ed., Berlin, 1911), vol. 4, p. 524, line 24. Also Buchdahl, Metaphysic . ... , pp.567-8.
22 Logik, § 97, Z, p. 192; L [W, 1892], p. 181.
23 Logik, § 98, p. 193;L [W, 1892], p. 182.
24 Logik, § 112,Z, p. 224;L [W, 1892], p. 208.
25 PN, § 275, p. 87; ~ 277, p. 95.
26 Logik, §112,Z,p.224;L [W,1892],p.208.
27 Cf. E. Nagel, The Structure of Science (New York, Harcourt, 1961), ch.6, especially
sect. 4; P. Duhem, The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory (tf. P. P. Wiener, Princeton,
Princeton University Press, 1954), Part I; N. R. Campbell, Foundations of Science (New
York, Dover, 1957), ch.6. For an earlier source, E. Mach, Die Principien der Wiirmelehre
(Leipzig, Barth, 1896): 'The contrast between mechanical and phenomenological
physics', pp. 362-4.
28 For Ptolemy, see M. R. Cohen and I. E. Drabkin, A Source Book in Greek Science
(New York, McGraw Hill, 1948), pp. 268-71.
29 Cf. Buchdahl, Metaphysics . .. ch.3, sect. 2c-d, for Descartes's Optics, and ch.7,
sect. 3b, pp. 425-34, for Leibniz's use of his theory of refraction.
30 Cf. Johannes Kepler. Gesammelte Werke, vol. 2 (ed. W. v. Dyck and Max Caspar,
Munich, Beck, 1938 -), ch.2, pp. 85-86. See my 'Methodological Aspects of Kepler's
36 GERD BUCHDAHL
Theory of Refraction', Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 3 (1972), 265-298, especially pp. 283-86.
31 PN, § 318, Remark, Z, p. 190; cf. § 293, Remark, p.127.
32 Logik, § 107, p. 215; L [W, 1892], p. 201.
33 Logik, § 111, Z, p. 221;L [W, 1892], pp. 205-206.
JOHN J. COMPTON
Now I do not even hint that I am able to answer these questions. I believe
that Buchdahl can do so and I profoundly hope that he will. However, I can
suggest a possible context for an answer - one which is already implicit,
I believe, in Buchdahl's paper, and one which is by now familiar in any case.
Consider, for example, that there are three distinct levels of scientific
thought - and their correlative concepts of nature: (1) The level of observed
and experimentally tested regularities in the behavior of things; (2) The level
of physical constructs or theoretical explanations, hypothetically offered to
account for those regularities - leaving the crucial expression "to account
for" undefined for the moment; and (3) the level of metaphysical or
conceptual models which represent what is thought to be intrinsically
intelligible or self.explanatory in nature, and which function in a regulative
way to suggest hypothetical constructs for possible scientific use.
Now consider further that there are competing master, metaphysical
models - among them one given by the tradition of atomistic materialism,
suitably amended by adding various sorts of forces, and another based on the
notion of a self-alienating and self-fulfilling Absolute Spirit. And suppose, still
further, that while most of the tested and wen-accepted physical constructs
have been suggested by the atomistic-mechanical model, one has convincing
reasons to believe that this model is inferior in systematic coherence to that
of the Absolute Spirit. Then it seems clear that what one should rationally set
out to do is precisely what Hegel did set out to do in the Philosophy of
Nature: One should try so to develop and apply the model of nature based on
the notion of Absolute Spirit that it would give sense to the given phenomena
of level (1) but without using the physical constructs of level (2), which are
based on the competing, atomistic-mechanical picture.
But "give sense" or "account for" in what sense? What precisely should be
the logical relations among the three levels of scientific thought? At this
point, as Buchdahl writes the story, Hegel seems to have failed clearly to
distinguish two quite distinct alternatives or, if he did, he seems to have taken
them both.
from the metaphysical model (3). This is the view that seems to be implicit in
Hegel's analysis of gravitation and of free-fall, where he expresses strong
preference for formal, mathematical laws only and seeks to supplement such
laws with a qualitative demonstration of their inner meaning and basis.
Similarly, he appears willing to allow talk of light rays and of their rectilinear
propagation so long as this is understood to refer to purely geometric,
heuristic representations. On this option scientific agnosticism (d fa Kant)
allows metaphysical fulfillment (d fa Hegel).
II. On the other hand, a second option is a realism of scientific theory. But
this implies a new and more adequate scientific theory, the constructs of
which will be based on the genuinely referential model of the Absolute Spirit.
Here, the philosophical task is not only to criticize materialistic representa-
tions and to re-interpret observed phenomena in notional terms, but more:
it is to use the notional determinations to generate new theoretical hypotheses
which might afford discovery and explanation of new phenomena. While
Hegel never explicitly espouses this view, perhaps it is nascent in his reformu-
lation of the Kantian dynamic theory of matter - which could be used to
suggest a field theory of matter-energy. And it seems obvious in his treatment
of the relations between light and space which, as Buchdahl points out, yields
some astonishing insights such as that of the dependence of space upon the
dispersion of light-energy. Even, and perhaps especially, Hegel's 'excessive'
spiritualization of light in his account of refraction, suggests this more con-
structive role for metaphysical models - for we should not expect a
metaphysical model invariably to yield positive results!
Now let me put my basic puzzlement this way: Why is it that Hegel
held back from this second, more constructive view of the role of
philosophy of nature? Why did he seem to favor the first, more cautious
option - conventionalism and formalism of scientific theory coupled with
metaphysical redescription of the already given empirical data? To be sure,
it is far less risky; but it is also far less dialectical, less open to permitting
new phenomena to bear upon and perhaps force modifications in what we
had thought to be the categorial features of nature, and in being far less
dialectical it is less true to Hegel's own vision. The second option would
have more adequately fulfIlled Hegel's aim to reveal the drama of the Idea
not only as consistent with known phenomena but as requiring new ones -
not deductively, but in the way in which a rich and fundamental model
affords new analogies for examination, quantified formulation and test.
40 JOHN J. COMPTON
Perversely, I suppose, I find myself wishing that Hegel had indulged in some
more 'bizarre' excesses like that of "the ideal presence of water in air"; he
might then have found some more astonishing successes as well.
Vanderbilt University
Nashville, Tennessee
DIETRICH VON ENGELHARDT
In the history of Hegel research his philosophy of nature has been unjustly
neglected. Only some fifty studies of this subject have appeared since 1830;
and the greater part of these are devoted to the philosophy of nature as
a whole. On chemistry as a special domain of physical nature no more than
perhaps five treatises are to be found. Academic concern with Hegel's
philosophy of nature has not been less insignificant. In the years from 1945
to 1970, 15,500 seminars and lectures were held at the universities of the
Federal Republic of Germany. Of these only twelve treated Hegel's philo-
sophy of nature, only two exclusively so. This low esteem seems strange if we
consider that the second part of Hegel's system is formed entirely by the
philosophy of nature and recall furthermore how much attention the
philosopher had devoted to the natural sciences throughout his life. Indeed,
the treatment of philosophy of nature was so important for Hegel that he did
not hold back from polemical commentaries dealing with the entire formal-
analogical speculation about nature of his time, and he did not shrink from
allowing his friendship with Schelling to be broken off because of these.
The rejection which his philosophy of nature has met, is based above all on
Hegel's alleged contempt for and neglect of both empirical work and modern
research. The general indifference displayed toward the philosophy of nature
after 1830, however, cannot adequately be explained by these objections, be·
cause they were raised only among natural scientists and by few of them even
though with a vehement and offensive tone; and they found but meager reso-
nance. The reason for the indifference lies rather in the polarization of the
sciences of nature and the sciences of the mind [Geisteswissenschaften] during
the nineteenth century, which Hegel had foreseen; indeed he had seen one es-
sentially important significance of philosophizing to be the overcoming of that
polarization. The positivist sciences' understanding of themselves, separating
nature and mind [Geist], and apparently legitimated by impressive technical
achievements ,has become the epitome of the domin?nt attitude toward nature
after the idealist period; it has confirmed a self-centered and self-satisfied
readiness to leave the world of nature to the empirical approach and know-
ledge, and in this way has freed the natural scientist from the philosophic
requirement to establish the grounds for the forms and materials of nature.
41
R. S. Cohen and M. W. Wartofsky (eds.), Hegel and the Sciences, 41-54.
© 1984 by D. Reidel Publishing Company.
42 DIETRICH VON ENGELHARDT
To unite system and empirical work was the general goal of natural science in
the second half of the eighteenth century. To meet the demand of empirical
research and at the same time to proceed systematically, this was to initiate
a new phase of research. In addition, mathematics was declared to be the
model of scientific method, the possibility of mathematization held to be
proof of the scientific (d' Alembert, 1751: Discours preliminaire; Kastner,
1768: p. 2, 5; Erxleben, 1772: Preface; Condillac, 1780). Both parts of
natural science - theoretical knowledge of nature and natural history -
sought to achieve the principle of the empirical combined with the systematic.
In natural history, the description and classification of phenomena of the
three natural kingdoms was required, which meant the development of a
natural order instead of an artificial system or any arbitrary preoccupation
with some specific subject-matter; in the natural sciences explanation of the
causes and effects of phenomena was demanded, the uniting of separate
phenomena and their manifold conditions into a natural order. Theoretical
natural science was subdivided into physics and chemistry, natural history
THE CHEMICAL SYSTEM IN HEGEL'S PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE 43
et al., 1780: vol. 2, Preface; Richter, 1792: vol. 1, pp. 1 fi). This transforma-
tion appeared all the more justified, the more the demonstration of the
constancy of the proportions of substances within compounds succeeded, and
where these proportions were variable, to show them as multiple - which
means to show that they stood in a simple relation to each other. The theory
of forces was questioned at first, before its fmal adoption due ,to the obser-
vation and investigation of such factors as heat, physical conditions, and
mass, which influenced the constant and multiple proportions; but finally
the theory was refmed and extended by these insights (Berthollet, 1803).
But the combination of the theory of attraction with electrochemical theory
(Volta, 1792,1800; Davy, 1807, 1812; Berzelius, 1803,1819) and atomic
theory (Higgins, 1789, 1814; Dalton, 1808-1810) proved much more prob-
lematical. According to the electrochemical view, also called Galvanism,
substances were positive and negative electrically charged matter; the
chemical processes were the uniting and the separating of the two kinds of
electricity. This interpretation reduced the theory of attraction to the two
electrical poles, and beyond that made the validity of atomic theory appear
questionable; for with the tendency then prevailing to regard electricity - as
well as heat, light and magnetism - not as substance, but as force or
manifestation of forces, required that a dynamic view of nature become more
pro bable again. To be sure, the controversy, which was not to be resolved
empirically, was then decided in favor of atomism. The dogmatic and, for the
time, still ambiguous character of the system of chemistry that was linked to
this was certainly noticed by scientists, as in general it had to be admitted
that science and its progress was unthinkable without hypotheses and specula-
tion (Gmelin, 1817: vol. 1, pp. 54ff; Berzelius, 1820, p. 19ff).
Elements, compounds, forces and processes were the constitutive
'moments' of chemistry between 1780 and 1830. A closed system was not,
however, produced from these moments by. the scientists of those decades.
Fundamentally a system of chemistry could have been constructed from two
principles and their combination: first, according to a principle of substances,
and this either in the fonn of a mathematized classification of the elements
and their compounds, those of a simple and a higher order, or in the form of
a natural history taxonomy; the other according to the principle of forces and
processes. Neither of the two possibilities nor their integration into a com-
prehensive unity was realized. The system of chemistry remained disjointed
among the varied presentations because of the irregular connection of the two
fundamental possibilities, as well as due to the special preeminence accorded
to specific substances or forces, as for instance oxygen or electricity. To be
46 DIETRICH VON ENGELHARDT
sure, proceeding logically from its scientific premisses (Condillac, 1780), anti-
phlogiston chemistry had developed an analytic method for the language of
chemistry (de Morveau et al., 1787) and for the system of elements and com-
pounds on various levels, but then, due to the emphasis given to oxygen and
an orientation reflecting the three kingdoms of nature, it had arrived at an
arbitrary claiisification (Lavoisier, 1789). Furthermore, the theory of forces
and the theory of processes on the whole remained excluded from the anti-
phlogiston theory, although they were mentioned here and there. This situa-
tion did not change in the subsequent decades. About 1800 a system began
with a conceptual explanation of the elements, compounds, forces and pro-
cesses, proceeded to the examination of fire, water and air, then went on to
the acids, alkalis, oxides and chlorides, and metals and ended with an account
of the mineral, vegetable and animal substances (Trommsdorff, 1800-1804).
The organization of chemistry reached a certain consistency around 1815,
since after the weightless substances the ponderable elements were presented,
these divided into non-metals and metals; and to the description of the
individual metals, that of the compounds of each was added. However, the
theory of forces and processes was expounded independently of the elements
and compounds (Gmelin, 1817). Around 1830, the non-metallic fundamental
substances and their combinations stood at the beginning of the system; air
and water and the theory of attraction followed; to these finally the acids,
bases and metals were added (Mitscherlich, 1829-1830). All the chemical
systems were characterized by the fact that the theory of forces and processes
had no influence on the order of the substances. The theory was treated quite
arbitrarily, now at the beginning, now at the end or at some point within the
account of the elements and their compounds, and at times not at all or only
in part. Substance, force and process remained apart. Beyond that, the theory
of forces, of atoms and of electrochemistry were not and could not be
brought into correspondence. By proceeding neither from one of the basic
possibilities by themselves nor from their combination was a consistent order
of chemical substances and processes developed. The universal demands
placed upon science during the eighteenth century were not fulfilled.
II
More decisive than the deduced emergence of the living from chemistry is
the real-ideal genesis of chemistry from the phenomena of physics that
precede it. The concept of chemical reality follows immanently from the
processes of magnetism and electricity; the concept of chemistry is the unidn,
conceived in thought, of two aspects of magnetism and electricity, namely
the conceptual indifference of a polar body - that is, magnetism - and the
real indifference of two polar bodies - that is, electricity:
In magnetism, the difference is manifest in one body. In electricity, each difference
belongs to a separate body; each difference is self-subsistent, and the whole shape does
not enter into this process. Chemical process is the totality of the life of inorganic
individuality; for here we have whole, physically determined shapes .... The two sides
into which the form sunders itself are thus whole bodies, such as metals, acids, and
alkalis; their truth is that they enter into relation (PN, § 326, Zusatz, p. 233).
50 DIETRICH VON ENGELHARDT
In empirical chemistry, interest mainly centres in the particularity of the substances and
products grouped together according to superficial, abstract determinations in such
fashion that no order is brought into their particularity. In this grouping, metals, oxygen,
hydrogen, etc., metalloids (formerly called earths), sulphur, and phosphorus, are placed
side by side as simple chemical bodies and on the same level. The great physical diversity
of these bodies is such that it straightway arouses opposition to such grouping; no less
varied, too, is their chemical origin, the process from which these bodies result. But in
equally chaotic fashion, the more abstract processes are put on the same level as those
that have more reality. If scientific form is to be introduced into this sphere, each
product must be defined according to the stage of the concrete, fully developed process
from which it essentially results and from which it has its peculiar significance; for this
purpose it is equally essential to distinguish between the stages of abstraction or reality
of the process.... A further matter is the empirical, quite special particularity of
reaction shown by bodies to all other particular bodies; a knowledge of this involves
going through the same litany of reactions to every re-agent (PN § 334, Remark,
pp. 264-265).
share in determining them, they are not properly chemical substances; the
methods of physics are also transferrable to other domains of nature, but
they do not lose their own proper meaning. Rejecting the intermingling of
the domains of nature and their categories - an identification, which,
according to Hegel, much more deserves a reproach than that which identity
philosophy has received - also forbids inclusion of imponderable substances
such as light, heat, magnetism and electricity within chemistry, since science
has reached agreement concerning their physical character only hesitantly.
Though electricity - like magnetism too - has a part in chemistry, and above
all in the syntheses of metals, for which Hegel also adopts the term
Galvanism, the category of polarity can by no means adequately explain the
qualitative characteristics of substances, their forces and processes:
Let philosophy no more be reproached with 'its ignoring of particularity and its empty
generalities', when all the physical properties just mentioned can be disregarded in
favour of positive and negative electricity. A former style of Philosophy of Nature
'potentialized' - or rather dissipated and attenuated - the system and process of animal
reproduction to magnetism and the vascular system to electricity: such schematism was
not more superficial than this reduction of concrete, corporeal opposition to electricity.
In the former case, such a summary method of dealing with concrete phenomena to the
neglect, by abstraction, of their characteristic features, was rightly rejected. Why not also
in the present instance? (PN § 330, Remark, pp. 248-249).
III
To unite system and empirical work was not the universal goal of science
52 DIETRICH VON ENGELHARDT
alone, for philosophy too took itself to be subject to the demand for a
natural order. An adequate conceptual grasp and explanation of nature is,
however, for Hegel, only possible for a science that does not deny resting on
metaphysical conditions, that does claim to be without presuppositions, but
is conscious of its metaphysics, tests it in its empirical work and orients its
experience by it. The inadequacy with respect to nature, and the incon-
sistency of the chemical system are the result of a lack of metaphysical
reflection, of the admixture of unrecognized speculative presuppositions with
hypotheses and empirical theories; they are the result of the isolated treat-
ment of chemical phenomena that destroys their natural unity, of neglect of
the specific methodologies of individual domains of nature, and especially of
the internal disconnectedness of the chemical substances, forces and processes.
However, several other attempts in the natural sciences to pursue corres-
pondence and lawfulness in the scattered and contingent sensuous world meet
with Hegel's approval: the ordering of plants according to the principle of
mono- and dicotyledons, the conception of the metamorphosis of plants, the
division of animals into those with and without vertebrae, and, more specially,
according to their teeth and claws, these are in accord with nature and not
artificial; for teeth and claws are the instruments with which the animal itself
confronts its environment, and plants too arise in the beginning as the unfold-
ing of one or of two germinating leaves; the leaf is the basic form of the
plant's form, and the vertebra the archetype of the animal bone structure.
However, these attempts, too, are still inadequate for Hegel; they fail to see
the one-sidedness of their category, do not comprehend its conceptual
character, tear apart the unity of nature.
If for the formation of natural order, scient;e must depend on philosophy,
so philosophy must also depend on science. The conceptual categories are
extracted from description and observation, the speculative operations that
make a formal-material derivation of nature have to be verified in experience.
The concept of chemistry is the result of the reality of magnetism and electri-
city - and chemical reality makes a concept emerge whose reality is the
organic. The concept of chemistry and the genesis of a new concept must be
capable of confirmation in empirical research. But, philosophy is not
research, it must presuppose it, it must allow itself to be instructed by it:
"Not only must philosophy be in agreement with our empirical knowledge of
Nature, but the origin and formation of the Philosophy of Nature presupposes
and is conditioned by empirical physics" (PN, § 246, Remark, p. 6).
Hegel refers to about 100 natural scientists; one third of these are
chemists. The observations and insights incorporated in indirect and direct
THE CHEMICAL SYSTEM IN HEGEL'S PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE 53
Ruprecht-Karl-University
Heidelberg
BIBLIOGRAPHY
My object here is, first, to review Hegel's criticism of Newton's 'system of the
world' and then to examine critically the many aspects of it that seem to
anticipate the approach to mathematical physics, which is today associated
with the name of Einstein.
One must emphasize that Hegel's criticism was well informed. Certainly he
knew the Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica and Opticks first hand
and had the requisite training in mathematics to comprehend what he read.
Through hundreds of well-documented pages of his Science of Logic (large
and small) and Philosophy of Nature, Hegel explores the meaning of
Newton's fluxional calculus, his concepts of space, time, mass, inertia, centri-
petal and centrifugal forces, his laws of motion, his gravitational world-
system, and, finally, his theory of light and colors. Particularly under the
headings 'Quantity' and 'Measure' in the Logic and 'Mechanics' in the
Philosophy of Nature, Newton's doctrine provides much of the empirical
datum upon which the Hegelian philosophical dialectic operates. And that
represents no small tribute to the achievement of Newton, especially when we
bear in mind that, according to Hegel, "without the working out of the
empirical sciences on their own account, philosophy could not have reached
further than with the ancients" (HP 3, p. 176V
Dante's phrase (Inf. IV, 131), the "teacher of those who know" -- maestro
di color che sanno. Still, there is no denying that the Newtonian sacramenta
are subject to much abuse in the pages of the German philosopher; and,
despite the reigning relativism of our age, it is a bold scholar who will
presume, as J. N. Findlay has, to qualify it as "much fine abuse.,,3
Admittedly hard to take, on a first reading, is Hegel's comparison of
Newton with Moliere's bourgeois gentilhomme - all to the advantage of the
latter! Moliere's M. Jourdain was "surprised to learn that he had talked prose
all his life, not having had any idea that he was so accomplished"; but he, at
least, learned - Hegel observes - whereas Newton seems never to have
realized "that he thought in and had to deal with notions of the under-
standing, while he imagined he was dealing with physical facts" (HP 3,
pp. 323-324). On the same level is Hegel's discussion of what the English
generally understand by the term Philosophy and why it is that among them
"Newton continues to be celebrated as the greatest of philosophers." In
England, he explains, not only the empirical sciences but also the mechanical
arts are confounded with philosophy; "and the name goes down as far as the
price-lists of instrument-makers." With grudging admiration, as well as irony,
Hegel in the same passage commends the heirs of the tradition of Bacon and
Newton for at least taking the name of philosophy seriously enough to apply
it to the study of matters of the greatest importance to them - like political
economy, free trade, and the imperial administration, as well as chemistry,
mineralogy, natural history, agriculture, and the arts - whereas in most other
lands "the name of philosophy is now generally used only as a nickname and
insult, or as something odious" (L [W, 1975], § 7, pp. 11-12).4
More abusive, from a Newtonian standpoint, is Hegel's rejection of the
Principia's 'proofs' of Kepler's laws - proofs which he characterizes as
"demonstrationaljugglery and counterfeiting" (SL [J/S] 2, p. 290); and most
offensive of all, perhaps, is his assessment of the Opticks, where he speaks not
only of ineptitude, incorrectness, and thoughtless inconsistency, but also of
stupidity, blind prejudice, and dishonesty (PN, § 320, Remark, p. 199). 5
It is no wonder, therefore, that, for longer than a century in Newton's
English-speaking world, most scholars have responded by refusing to take
Hegel's Naturphilosophie seriously, or even to read it at all - as, it is said, the
seventeenth century Aristotelians of Padua refused to take Galileo seriously,
or even to look through his optical tube. The fact is that, whereas the French
and Italians, less sensitive to criticism of Newton, have had translations of the
complete Encyclopedia of Hegel, including the Naturphilosophie, since the
1860s, the English-speaking academic community, on the contrary, has
HEGEL, NEWTON AND EINSTEIN 57
delayed until this bicentennial anniversary of Hegel's birth the labors of filling
the gap between the excellent versions of the Logic and the Philosophy of
Mind, which Professor Wallace provided three generations ago.
But this year is destined evidently to mark a turning point in the fortunes
of Hegel's Philosophy of Nature. Thanks largely to the sustained interest of
Professor Findlay, we now have an excellent translation - that of A. V. Miller
- presented to us by Findlay with a challenge that the Anglo-American
academic community will sooner or later have to accept. Back in 1958,
Professor Findlay had written of the Naturphilosophie:
This part of the system is one that many Hegelians have thought fit to ignore entirely,
mainly on account of the outmoded character of the science on which it reposes.
Nothing can, however, be more unfit than this ignoring, and, in view of Hegel's
undoubted greatness, more impertinent. The Philosophy of Nature is an integral part of
Hegel's system, and one can no more understand that system without taking account of
it, than one can understand Aristotelianism while ignoring the Physics or the History of
Animals, or Cartesianism while ignoring the physical portions of the Principles of
Philosophy. In Hegel's theory of Nature, as in the parallel theories of Aristotle and
Descartes, one sees the philosopher's principles at work, casting their slant upon our talk
and thought about the world around us. The complete misunderstanding of Hegel's
idealism by British philosophers, and its reduction to a refined form of subjectivism, are
probably due to their ignoring of the Naturphilosophie .
. . . Hegel's grasp of contemporary science was, moreover, informed and accurate: the
reading of the Naturphilosophie is made easy by its wealth of experimental illustration,
and by its long citations from contemporary treatises. Hegelgives one the sciences of his
own day, together with the interpretations he puts on them. [His views remain] as
worthy of study, and of detailed scholarly comment, as are the views of Aristotle, or
(in recent times) ofWhitehead. 6
In his foreword to the Miller translation, Professor Findlay says that his
object in publishing it has been primarily utilitarian, to make its thought
accessible "to students and teachers, particularly in regions where prejudiced
simplifications might otherwise be their only route of access to it." The work
itself is proof, he asserts, "that Hegel, like Aristotle and Descartes and
Whitehead, is one of the great philosophical interpreters of nature, as steeped
in its detail as he is audacious in his treatment of it." Praising its "thorough-
going realism," Findlay concludes that what is to be admired most in it is
Hegel's manifest "willingness, unusual in philosophers, to read, digest, and
take full account of so much detailed scientific material, a willingness which
puts him on a pinnacle of scientific information and understanding shared
only by Aristotle" (PN, pp. viii-ix, xxv).
Thus, under unprecedentedly favorable auspices, we now have the
58 HENR Y PAOLUCCI
II
The important point to stress here is that Hegel exhibits this activity of the
understanding as an essential moment in the phenomenological process. What
Newton did had to be done by human consciousness. The idea of universal
gravitation "is therefore of the greatest importance," Hegel concludes,
"because it is directed against the unthinking way of representing reality that
makes everything appear to have happened by accident, and for which
qualitative distinctiveness has the form of merely sensory differentiation"
(Phen [B], p. 197).
Newton thus comes off rather well in the Phenomenology - in marked
contrast with the caustic treatment we get of him in the lectures on the
History of Philosophy. There Hegel calls the author of the Principia an
intellectual "barbarian" for having treated the basic concepts of his natural
science as if they were physical facts - sensuous things, to be dealt with
"as men deal with wood and stone." Especially barbaric, according to Hegel,
was the Newtonian attitude summed up in the maxim, "Physics, beware of
metaphysics," which amounts to saying, "Science, beware of thought." The
worst of it is, Hegel continues, that physical scientists since Newton's time
have for the most part
60 HENRY PAOLUCCI
faithfully observed this precept, inasmuch as they have not entered upon an investigation
of their conceptions, or thought about thoughts .... And this is even now the case. In
the beginnings of physical science we read of the power of inertia, for instance, of the
force of acceleration, of molecules, or centripetal and centrifugal forces, as of facts
which definitely exist; what are really the final results of reflection are represented as
their first grounds (HP 3, p. 323).
Yet here again, Hegel acknowledges the value of Newton's scientific work
in "introducing to physics the determinations respecting forces, which pertain
to reflection." By setting "the laws of forces in the place of the laws of
phenomena," Newton "raised science to the standpoint of reflection," and
for that he deserves high praise. He is to be blamed, according to Hegel, only
for imagining that he is still functioning on the level of sensory perception,
free of metaphysics, when, by undertaking to 'compose' the empirically-
derived laws of phenomena out of the interrelations of 'component' forces,
he has obviously slipped back into metaphysics without knowing it - which
is to say, ignorantly. The harshest part of Hegel's judgment here is his
prophecy that physical science will make no significant advance in the
theoretical sense until it gives up the naive Newtonian dogmatism that con-
founds abstract concepts of the understanding with the reality of nature
(HP 3, pp. 322-324).
That surely was a 'hard saying' in the first decades of the nineteenth
century. Today, however, it has become the prevailing view of the most
expert practitioners in the field. In his Physics and Microphysics, for instance,
the Nobel Prize-winning physicist Louis de Broglie writes:
For scientists, and in particular for the theorists, there is a certain danger in trying to
ignore the efforts of philosophers and especially their work as critics .... Thus many
scientists of the present day, victims of an ingenuous realism, almost without perceiving
it, have adopted a certain metaphysics of a very materialistic and mechanistic character
and have regarded it as the very expression of scientific truth. One of the great services
that the recent evolution of physics has rendered contemporary thought, is that it has
destroyed this simplified metaphysics, and with the same stroke has caused certain
traditional philosophic problems to be considered in an enterely new light .... For the
development of science to continue, we must embark on, or at any rate touch upon,
questions of philosophic import and sometimes consider their new and very original
solutions. 8
On the other hand, it is impossible to overlook the formal right which, in the first place,
entitles the empirical sciences to vindicate the right of thought to know the existent
world in all the speciality of its content, and to seek something further than the mere
abstract faith that God creates and governs the world. When our religious consciousness,
resting upon the authority of the Church, teaches us that God created the world by his
almighty will, that he guides the stars in their courses, and vouchsafes to all his creatures
their existence and their well-being, the question Why? is still left to answer. Now it is
the answer to this question which forms the common task of empirical science and of
philosophy (L [W, 1975], § 136, p. 195).
Defending the practice against the piety of the Newtonians, Hegel asserts that
when religion appeals to the 'unsearchableness' of the decrees of God, it is,
in effect, aping the agnosticism of the enlightenment rationalists. "Such an
appeal," he concludes, "is no better than an arbitrary dogmatism which
contravenes the express command of Christianity, to know God in spirit and
truth, and is prompted by a humility which is not Christian, but born of
ostentatious bigotry" (L [W, 1975], § 136, p. 196).
III
things (as, for instance, Einsteinian and Planckian physics now deals with
qualitatively determined quanta, or measures, of space, time, light, and a host
of electro-magnetic phenomena).
The first explicit reference to Newton comes under the sub-heading
'Quantum' and it consists of singularly high praise. Considering the "chief
determinations which have been offered in mathematics about the infinite,"
Hegel asserts unequivocally that "no correcter determination of the thought
can be made than that offered by Newton." The problem of the mathematical
infinite is ancient. It was first clearly defined by the Eleatics (notably Zeno)
in their efforts to demonstrate the irrationality of the Heraclitean 'flux'; and
Zeno's paradoxes have remained vital paradoxes for mathematical physicists
to this day - Hegel insists - despite all the walking to and fro of old
Diogenes and cynics of more recent times. That Hegel was competent to deal
with the problem in its abstractest geometrical and algebraic as well as logical
aspects, he has amply demonstrated not only in the Science of Logic itself,
but also in the History of Philosophy, where he takes it up as often as it
surfaces in his sources.
Newton tells us that he "invented the methods of series and fluxions in
the year 1665," and his first published treatise on the subject, Methods of
Fluxions and Infinite Sequences, appeared in 1674. But Hegel is concerned,
as he says, with Newton's maturest thought on the subject, which is that of
the Principia. Hinting at what he will later criticize, Hegel writes:
I here set apart the determinations belonging to the idea of motion and velocity (from
which latter chiefly he took the name of fluxions), for there the thought appears not in
its due abstraction, but concrete and mixed with unessential forms.
Newton explains these fluxions (Prine. Mathem. Phil. Nat. L. i. Lemma XI, Schol.) by
saying that he takes them not as indivisibiUa (a form used by earlier mathematicians,
Cavalieri and others; it contains the concept of a Quantum determinate in itself), but as
vanishing divisibilia; and, further, not as the sums and ratios of determinate parts, but as
the limits (Umites) of the sums and ratios. It will be objected, he says, that vanishing
magnitudes have no final ratio, because the ratio before they vanish is not the last, and,
after they have vanished, no longer exists. But by the ratio between vanishing
magnitudes must not be understood the ratio that exists either before or after, but that
with whieh they vanish (quacum evanescunt). And, similarly, the first ratio of becoming
magnitudes is that with which they arise (SL [J/S] 1, pp. 271-272).
After noting that the "magnitudes at the point of vanishing" are understood
by Newton to be "quanta no longer," Hegel makes clear that, in his judgment,
HEGEL, NEWTON AND EINSTEIN 65
Newton has here adequately expressed the notion of transition from quantity
to quality which is so essential an element in the Hegelian dialectic. As much
Newtonian as Hegelian is the statement that: "The limit of the magnitudinal
ratio is that point where it is and it is not - or, more precisely, where the
Quantum has vanished, and the ratio, therefore, is preserved only as qualita-
tive quantity-ratio" (SL [1/S] 1, p. 272).
But while Newton grasped the concept of the qualitative quantity-ratio
and expressed it clearly, in practice - says Hegel - the author of the Principia
let it slip through his fingers. And the same must be said of the other great
mathematicians of the period, including Newton's master Barrow, as well as
Fermat, Leibniz, Lagrange, Landen, Euler, and their successors. It seems,
Hegel writes, that "when mathematicians turn to practice, the finite deter-
minateness of quantity returns, and the operation can no longer do without
the idea of a Quantum which is merely relatively small" (SL [J/S] 1, p. 277).
Indeed, the idea of the relatively small, of increment, of addition, "of growth
of x by dx or i, and so on," Hegel concludes, "must be considered the funda-
mental evil inherent in these methods - as an enduring obstacle which makes
it impossible to disengage the determination of the qualitative moment of
quantity from the idea of ordinary Quantum" (SL [J/S] 1, p. 274). In other
words, the evil is that those "ghosts of departed quantities" (as Bishop
Berkeley called them) are too easily mistaken for never-perishing indivisibilia,
and the transition from quantity to quality is lost to thought.
If mathematicians could take another approach so as to develop a mathe-
matics of qualitative quantity-ratios, Hegel observes, the result would be a
magnificent instrument for the advancement of a truly physical as distinct
from an abstractly mechanical science. Such a mathematics, he writes, would
have to be in essence -
a science of measures - a science for which much has been done empirically, but little
in a truly scientific, that is philosophic, manner. Mathematical principles of Natural
Philosophy - as Newton called his work - if they were to fulfill this determination in a
philosophic and scientific meaning deeper than that which was reached by Newton and
the whole Baconian generation, must contain quite other things in order to bring light
into these regions, dark as yet, but most worthy of contemplation (SL [J/S] 1, p. 361).
Hegel was well aware that Newton had not arrived at the conclusions
demonstrated in Book Three of the Principia (where the universal law of
gravitation is expounded as the System of the World) by means of the
analytical calculus and geometry he uses there. Newton himself says, at the
beginning of that book, that the method of exposition there was an after-
thought, and that he introduced it rather to prevent than to facilitate general
understanding. He had at first, he says, written the entire book in a more
direct, popular way; but afterwards, "considering that such as had not
sufficiently entered into the principles could not easily discern the strength
of the consequences, nor lay aside the prejudices to which they had been
many years accustomed," Newton decided to avoid any direct confrontation
with ignorance and prejudice by choosing "to reduce the substance of this
Book into the form of Propositions (in the mathematical way), which would
be read by those only who had first made themselves masters of the principles
established in the preceding books."!!
What might have become of the great law of universal gravitation of that
Third Book, had Newton not reduced his exposition to the form of Pro-
positions, in a mathematical way, one can hardly guess. But perhaps the Ernst
Machs and Einsteins would have got at its absolute space and time, the
essentially non-empirical character of its laws of motion, and its oddly
HEGEL, NEWTON AND EINSTEIN 67
It will be impossible to deny that in this sphere much has been accepted as proof -
chiefly veiled under the kindly mist of the infinitesimally small - on no other ground
than that the result was already known beforehand, and the proof, which was arranged
in such a manner as to produce the result, at least effected the illusion of a framework of
proof - which illusion was preferred to mere belief or empirical knowledge. But I do not
hesitate to regard this method as no better than demonstrational jugglery and counter-
feiting; and I include even some of Newton's demonstrations, and especially such as
belong to those just mentioned, for which Newton has been extolled to the skies and
above Kepler, because what Kepler had discovered empirically he demonstrated mathe-
matically (SL [J IS 1 1, p. 290).
Hegel then proceeds to explain that, by its very nature, the mathematics
of Newton and his peers is unable to "prove the magnitudinal determinations
of physics in so far as they are laws based upon the qualitative nature of the
moments." The qualitative element is lost in the processes of the calculus;
and it is rather a moral than a scientific question why, to many mathe-
maticians, it has seemed against the honor of their discipline - so Hegel
phrases it - to "acknowledge simply experience as source and sole proof of
empirical propositions" (SL [J/S] 1, p. 290).
Needless to say, Hegel has long since won his point on this score. Modern
mathematicians and the best mathematical physicists of recent years are all
of a mind in acknowledging - and indeed often boasting - that they no
longer hold, with Galileo, Descartes, and Newton, that mathematics of itself,
or mathematically conducted experiments, can lead to true knowledge of the
realities of Nature. As Professor Tobias Dantzig expressed it in his Number:
The Language of Science:
validity of the two methods has been found to be of an anthropomorphic origin, both
have been found to rest on articles of faith.12
IV
What the solar system is as a whole, matter is now to be in detail .... The determina-
tions of form which constitute the solar system are the determinations of matter itself
and they constitute the being of matter. The determination and the being are thus
essentially identical; but this is the nature of the qualitative, for here, if the determina-
tion is removed, the being, too, is destroyed. This is the transition from Mechanics to
Physics (PN, § 271, Z, pp. 83-84).
Hegel was aware that Light - which for him as for Einstein was the first
physical manifestation of matter - united qualitatively the characteristics of
abstract corpuscular and wave motions; he knew also that light, in reflecting,
refracting, and otherwise manifesting itself, shows all the colors of the entire
universe, including those revealed in the dark when a prism is set up, just
right, as a divider between light and dark. But, about the corpuscular and
wave theories, Hegel held that they were both one-sided, and therefore
inadequate approaches to the dialectical notion of light in its qualitative
unity. Hegel writes:
Light is an interesting theme to treat; for we think that in Nature we have only the
individual, this particular reality. But light is the very opposite of this .... In thinking of
light, we must renounce all conceptions of composition and the like .... The expression
'bundles of rays' is merely one of convenience, it means nothing; the bundles are light in
its entirety, which is only outwardly limited; it is no more divided into bundles of rays
than is the Ego or pure self-consciousness. It is the same when I say: in my time or in
Caesar's time. This was also the time of everyone else; but here I am speaking of it in
relation to Caesar, and restrict it to him without meaning that he really had a separate
ray or parcel of time. The Newtonian theory according to which light is propagated in
straight lines, or the wave theory which makes it travel in waves, are, like Euler's aether
or the vibration of sound, materialistic representations quite useless for the compre-
hension of light (PN, § 276, Z, pp. 93-94).
Hegel died, it is to be noted, more than a generation before the birth of the
people who are usually honored in our catechisms of popular science for
having discussed such matters for the first time. Also on the speed of light,
Hegel anticipates the pioneers, writing:
The propagation of light occurs in time, since, being an activity and an alteration, it
cannot dispense with this moment .... The distances which light is supposed to travel
involve time; for illumination, whether through a medium or by reflection, is a modifica-
tion of matter requiring time (PN, § 276, Z, p. 94).
HEGEL, NEWTON AND EINSTEIN 71
But the speed of light is not, according to Hegel, like the speed of other
physically determinate manifestations of matter. In the sphere of qualified
as distinct from abstract matter, light is primary - the first, and therefore
limiting manifestation of matter in motion. The sun, says Hegel, does not
pour out its light incidentally while serving as the central material point of
the solar system. That system's orbital structure is the inner form of matter
itself, as we have noted, and it is that circling about a center that shows itself
physically as light. But, as each particle of matter is a microcosmic solar
system, all matter is - for the eye that can discern its true, centralized orbital
speeds -luminous. Again in a thoroughly Einsteinian vein, Hegel characterizes
Light as the "self-contained totality of matter," explaining that, as an
"existent, space-filling force," it is "absolute velocity, pure materiality which
is everywhere present, real existence which remains within itself, or actuality
as transparent possibility." "Light," he concludes, "brings us into the
universal interrelation; everything exists for us in theoretical, unresistant
fashion because it is in light (PN, § 275, Z, p. 88).
Einstein has told us that it was as a consequence of the labors of Faraday,
Clerk Maxwell, and Hertz, but particularly of Maxwell, in the study of light
and electro-magnetic phenomena, that modern science generally abandoned
the established view that Galilean-Newtonian mechanics could stand as the
"basis of all physics." Attempts to solve the difficulties of application of the
Newtonian principles to the newly-developed spheres led first to formulation
of the field theory of electricity, then to the effort to base all physics upon
the concept of field, and finally to the theory of relativity, which is the
"evolution of the notion of space and time into that of the continuum with
metric structure,,,15 which is in our view then qualitatively determined. "The
general theory of relativity," Einstein has said with his usual respectful regard
for the overthrown Titan of classical mechanics, "formed the last step in the
development of the programme of the field-theory. Quantitatively it modified
Newton's theory only slightly, but for that all the more profoundly
qualitatively.,,16
Already in Hegel's day, the phenomena of magnetism, electricity, and
chemism, together with those of light, were calling into being a unified
science very different in principle from Newtonian mechanics. Scientific 'law'
in the mechanical sense means, he explains, "the combination of two simple
determinations such that merely their simple interconnections constitute the
whole relationship, and yet each must have the show of independence with
regard to the other" (PN, § 270, Z, p. 72). But such a concept of law has, he
insists, a very limited range - that of mathematical abstraction. It will not do
72 HENR Y PAOLUCCI
in the study of bodies as they actually fall, or as they actually orbit around an
energized center; but the inadequacy there may be obscured by assuming that
the bodies in those qualitatively determined relationships are really nothing
more than points in the geometric sense. It is otherwise, however, with the
phenomena of light, magnetism, electricity, and chemism.
In magnetism, for instance, Hegel writes, "the inseparability of the two
determinations is already posited"; consequently there is not a co·relationship
of 'law' in the mechanical sense (PN, § 270, Z, p. 72). Magnetic phenomena,
he explains, are not gravitational phenomena which mathematical analysis
can, for its arbitrary convenience, separate into inertial as well as gravitational
components. "Magnetism," he writes, "differs from gravity in this, that it
forces bodies into a quite different direction from the vertical." Motion in the.
sphere, or 'field' of magnetism is not that of rectilinear attraction; but it is
also "not rotary, not a curve upon itself, like the motion of the heavenly
bodies, which is accordingly neither attractive nor repellent" (PN, § 313, Z,
p.171).
Summing up his case against scientific 'reductionism' in this sphere, Hegel
continues:
In all higher forms [as contrasted with the forms of abstract mechanics 1 the individual-
ized whole constitutes the third in which the determinations are conjoined, and we no
longer have the direct determinations of two things which are in relationship with each
other.
Laws in the mechanical sense are possible for the planetary motions, he says,
because those motions involve two distinct phenomenal elements - not to be
confounded with the non-empirical centripetal and centrifugal forces. Those
two phenomenal elements are "the form of the path and the velocity of the
motion." But if such laws are to be comprehended in a higher principle so as
to embrace the phenomena of light and magnetism as well, the "thing to be
done," he concludes, "is to develop this from the Notion. This would give
rise to a far-reaching science and the difficulty of the task is such that this has
not yet been fully accomplished." (PN, § 270,Z, p. 72).
The men who have undertaken to develop that "far-reaching science"
in our time have all started from the premise that it would have to be
built up from the very bottom - from a rectification of the first
'reductionist' error of classical mechanics, which consisted in its positing
space and time as only externally interrelated in the phenomena of motion.
Identifying the essential element in Einstein's labors of rectification, Bertrand
Russell wrote:
HEGEL, NEWTON AND EINSTEIN 73
The scientific merit of Einstein's theory lies in the explanation, by a uniform principle,
of many facts which are unintelligible in the Newtonian system. The philosophical
interest lies chiefly in the substitution of the single manifold, space-time, for the two
manifolds, space and time.! 7
How the original 'reductionist' error came to be made, Einstein himself has
explained as follows:
The lack of definiteness which, from the point of view of empirical importance, adheres
to the notion of time in classical mechanics was veiled by the axiomatic representation
of space and time as things given independently of our senses. Such a use of notions -
independent of the empirical basis, to which they owe their existence - does not
necessarily damage science. One may however easily be led into the· error of believing
that these notions, whose origin is forgotten, are necessary and unalterable accompani-
ments to our· thinking, and this error may constitute a serious danger to the progress of
science.1 8
Literally billions of words have been written on this theme since Ernst Mach
and then Einstein opened it up for the academic community of mathematical
scientists. Yet in all that literary production, which still floods the markets
today, there is, I am confident, no discussion of the reductionist error as
profound or as philosophically consistent as Hegel's in the opening sections of
his Mechanics, from which point he pursues the process of philosophical
rectification up through the whole range of mechanics into those higher
spheres of nature where to mathematize at all is to commit the gravest sort of
reductionist error - unless one's purpose is avowedly reductionist and
utilitarian.
In reviewing Hegel's approach to Newton in the Philosophy of Nature,
we have started from the 'difficulties' of the phenomena of light and electro-
magnetism only because it has been from that standpoint that our contem-
porary science, always working 'reductionistically', has found its way back
to the beginnings, ironically getting a reductionist satisfaction out of the
effort to rectify the original reductionist error of Newton. Hegel pursued
a 'reductionist' course in his great intellectual voyage of discovery, the
Phenomenology of Mind; but in his systematic exposition of the doctrine of
Mechanics, as in all the philosophical sciences of his Encyclopedia, he reverses
that course, working his way up from the most abstract to the most concrete
conceptions.
v
Although we have the assurances of the greatest practitioners that, in
74 HENRY PAOLUCCI
of its Future and Past. Time gives 'place' to the lines, planes, and volumes of
space. And Hegel dares to conclude that 'moving place' or, as we usually say,
locomotion, is the sole constituent of Matter.
Every time-point is thus a mass-point circling in itself: an essentially
moving place that tends restlessly to circle 'out of place' and back into it.
Thus this universal gravitation of time-points is simultaneously a moving away
and a moving toward, self-repulsion from one center and attraction toward
another. As Hegel expresses it: "Matter is both moments [repulsion as well as
attraction] and their unity, centralized in a point, is gravity." Matter itself is
"tending toward a center, but - and here is its other determination - a
center located outside itself." More precisely: Gravity is not mere attraction,
which is the tendency to negate spatial separateness and produce continuity.
On the contrary, "gravity preserves both separateness and continuity" as
moments of its concept (PN, § 262, pp. 44-47). And these moments,
apprehended abstractly as repulsion and attraction, are destined to be
narrowly determined as independent forces, centrifugal and centripetal
(PN, § 269, pp. 62-65).
Those who take space and time abstractly, who conceive of 'matter' as
'occupying' space and as being 'acted upon' by independent forces of 'inertia'
and 'gravity' have, in other words, taken rectilinear uniform motion as simple,
and accelerated and curvilinear motion as composed. From Hegel's standpoint
these are to be reversed. And in what he has to say on this point, "there is
undoubtedly [as Professor Findlay has said of his concept of light] a flavor
of relativity-physics." 1 9 Hegel says:
That movement in general is movement that returns upon itself may be concluded from
the determinations of particularity and individuality in a body, which give it an internal
focus of separateness together with a tendency to join a center outside itself. These are
the determinations underlying the concepts of centripetal and centrifugal force; these are
then taken abstractly as independent vectors which, brought to bear accidently on the
same inert body, give it the empirically observed motion. Thus you have the transforma-
tion of physical reality into lines that really serve only to facilitate mathematical
expression (PN, § 270, Remark, pp. 68-69).
We have two realities: matter and field . ... But what are the physical criterions distin-
guishing matter and field? Before we learned about the relativity theory we could have
tried to answer the question in the following way: matter has mass, whereas field has
not. Field represents energy, matter represents mass .... From the relativity theory
we know that matter represents vast stores of energy and energy represents matter ....
the division into matter and field is, after the recognition of the equivalence of mass and
energy, something artificial and not clearly defined .... What impresses our senses as
matter is really a great concentration of energy into a comparatively small space. We
could regard matter as the regions in space where the field is extremely strong .... There
would be no place, in our new physics for both field and matter, field [in Hegelian
terms, 'moving place'] being the only reality. This new view is suggested by the great
achievements of field physics, by our success in expressing laws of electricity,
magnetism, gravitation in the form of structure laws, and fmally by the equivalence of
mass and energy. 20
We noted in passing that it was on the basis of the field theory that the
Einsteinians rejected the Newtonian principles of rectilinear inertial and
gravitational motion, adopting a four-dimensional geometry in place of
Newton's calculus to express mathematically their conception of an astrono-
mical order in which inertial and gravitational mass are identified and the
fundamental motion is curvilinear. And, while we cannot dwell on it, we
should at least mention here that, at one point in his larger Science of Logic,
Hegel speaks of the possibility of developing a four-dimensional space-time
geometry to do justice to Kepler's laws. Such a geometry, Hegel says, "might
prove powerful with regard to free movement, wherein one (spatial) side is
governed by geometrical determination (in Kepler's law S3 :t 2), and the other
(temporal) side by arithmetical determination." The mathematics of that
geometry, Hegel suggests, might serve to comprehend the elliptical motions
of planets in their uncomposed naturality, in a manner consistent with the
Hegelian concept of matter and gravity (SL [J/S] 1, p. 324).
VI
Hegel, as we said, places Kepler's laws of planetary motions at the apex of the
grand pyramid of Mechanics. On that apex, looking beyond itself, mechanistic
science transcends the abstract, and the transition is made into the sciences of
qualified matter. Just below that apex Hegel sets the Galilean laws of falling
bodies.
Of these laws, Hegel says: "they are immortal discoveries which redound
to the greatest honour of the analysis of the Understanding." Still, in them-
selves they are not enough. "The next step," he continues, requires "their
78 HENR Y PAOLUCCI
in the conversion of the moments of the mathematical formula into physical forces, into
an accelerating force imparting one and the same impulse in each unit of time, and into
a force of inertia which perpetuates the (greater) velocity acquired in each moment of
time - determinations utterly devoid of empirical sanction and equally inconsistent with
the notion (PN, § 267, Remark, p. 57).
In other words, Hegel indicates that Newton treats a heavy, falling body,
which naturally gravitates toward a center outside itself, as if it were an inert
body responding inertly to an external thrust or force - as if it were not itself
essentially gravitational. "The motion of falling," Hegel writes, "forms the
transition and middle term between inert matter and matter whose Notion is
absolutely realized, that is, absolutely free motion." Inert matter is the
abstraction of a single material point, conceived as having no time in itself.
It will remain at rest, or, if moved, will move inertially as if it were at rest, the
two being equally timeless and therefore not really distinguishable as rest
and motion. On the other hand, "heavy matter in the motion of falling,"
Hegel writes, is at least "partly adequate to its Notion, namely, through the
sublation of the Many, as the effort of matter to reach one definite place, as
center." The next step in the determination of matter is that 'falling toward'
a center must also be seen as 'repulsion from' a center - which is what the
so-<:alled fixed stars manifest in their 'constellational' pattern. Though in
themselves they are matter orbiting about an energized center, with respect to
one another, they are simply held in a rigid equilibrium of attraction and
repulsion. The stars, says Hegel, "belong to the sphere of dead repulsion ....
Matter, in filling space, erupts into an infinite plurality of [luminous] masses,
but this, which may delight the eye, is only the first manifestation of
matter.,,21
Not in abstraction as inert, not in falling, not in the rigid equilibrium of
HEGEL, NEWTON AND EINSTEIN 79
principles, to displace the old Aristotelian double physics with its double set
of principles (celestial and curvilinear, terrestrial and rectilinear). Galileo, as
any serious student of his works must know, opted for unity on the basis
of curvilinear motion, so that all apparent rectilinear motion would be either
an optical illusion (like that of falling bodies, where the rotational movement
of the earth is shared by body and 0 bserver, and therefore cancelled out) or a
resultant compounded of naturally curvilinear motions. Copernicus had
abolished the entire realm of rectilinear motion by assigning celestial motion
to the terrestrial orb. And Kepler, too, while laboring to eliminate the com-
plexities of circles on circles in the Ptolemaic and Copernican systems, was
none the less a champion of curvilinear physics. From Copernicus to Galileo
and Kepler, the triumphant claim of science had been, therefore, that the
physical universe is indeed One, and all celestial. But then came Newton to
bring the whole business down with a Baconian thud: The universe is
physically One, as required, but - according to Newton's doctrine - it is all
earth, all rectilinear - so that all curves are either optical illusions or
resultants of compounded, naturally rectilinear motions.
From Hegel's point of view both positions, the Galilean as well as the
Newtonian, were one-sided abstractions of the Understanding - like the
contradictory corpuscular and wave theories oflight. Against both (and again
in an Einsteinian vein), Hegel argues that the proper scientific course is to
distinguish and preserve qualitative differences. Inert, falling, rigidly-fixed
stellar, and the freely-moving matter of the solar system must be compre-
hended together in their qualitative differences. Altogether, Hegel concludes
after a long discussion of principles,
There exist three motions: (a) mechanical motion which is communicated from outside
and is uniform; (b) the partly conditioned and partly free motion of falling, where the
separation of a body is still posited contingently but where the motion already belongs
to the gravity itself; and (c) the unconditionally free motion, the principal moments of
which have been indicated, the great mechanics of the heavens. This motion is a curve.
In it, the positing of a central body by the particular bodies, and conversely, the positing
of these by the central body, occur simultaneously. The center has no meaning apart
from the periphery nor the periphery apart from the center. This puts to rout those
physical hypotheses which start now with the center and now with the particular bodies,
sometimes making the former and sometimes the latter the original factor. Both points
of view are necessary, but, taken separately, they are one-sided. The diremption into
different bodies, and the positing of the moments of subjectivity, is a simple act, a free
motion, nothing external like pressure and thrust (PN, § 269, Remd1'k Z, p. 64).
we must not speak of forces. If we want to speak of force, then there is but one force,
and its moments do not, as two forces, pull in different directions. The motion of the
celestial bodies is not any such pulling this way and that but is free motion; they go on
their way, as the ancients said, like blessed Gods (!>N, § 269, Remark, Z, p. 65).
That last phrase, it should be noted, was cited by Sir Arthur Eddington in
The Nature of the Physical World to epitomize his own doctrine of the
planetary movements, in the light of the Einsteinian general theory of
relativity.22 Einstein himself has observed that in the "translation of the law
of inertia into the language of the general theory of relativity" we get a new
law of motion which is not rectilinear at all, being the law of "a system of
total differential equations, the system characteristic of the geodetic line"
which curves back on itself. Einstein says further: "In place of Newton's law
of interaction by gravitation, we shall find the system of the simplest
generally covariant differential equations which can be set up for the gllv-
tensor. It is formed by equating to zero the once contracted Riemannian
curvature tensor (RIlV = 0)" - which means that all apparently rectilinear
motion is henceforth to be understood as the segment of a vast curve. 23
But from Hegel's point of view, this Einsteinian development is also one-
sided. All that Hegel says against Newton's 'proofs' would apply also,
mutatis mutandis, to the Einsteinian-Riemannian formulas, were they offered
as 'proofs'. The philosophic virtue of the latter, in comparison with the
Principia, is their philosophic modesty. The Einsteinians acknowledge that
their mathematical analysis, which permits them to speak of non-empirical
clocks slowing down non-empirically and about non-empirical rulers
shrinking, proves nothing. But, if more were claimed for that analysis, it
could hardly expect to fare any better at the hands of another Ernst Mach
than Newton's analysis has fared.
82 HENRY PAOLUCCI
the conditions which make the path of the body a specific conic section are, in the
analytical formula, constants, and their determination is referred to an empirical circum-
stance, namely, to a particular position of the body at a certain point of time, and to the
fortuitous strength of an impulse which it is supposed to have received in the beginning;
so that the circumstance which determines the curve to be an ellipse falls outside the
formula that is supposed to be proved, and no one has ever dreamt of proving this
circumstance (PN, § 270, Remark, p. 66).
VII
Summing up, we may say that the great value of Hegel's criticism of Newton's
celestial mechanics consists in its emphasis on the error of scientific
'reductionism' upon which that mechanics was founded - an error that still
plagues theoretical physics, obstructing its advance, and making impossible
a philosophically-integrated Natural Science. The popularity of Einstein has
HEGEL, NEWTON AND EINSTEIN 83
made this part of Hegel's criticism more acceptable now than ever before. Yet
hardly less impressive than his criticism of Newton is Hegel's sustained
polemic against the pre-Darwinian advocates of an evolutionary origin of
species, which he conducts on the same grounds. Like the Newtonians in
Mechanics, Hegel argues, so the evolutionists in biology are 'reductionist'.
They 'decompose' the self-generative cycle of a species into two constitutive
elements or vectors, one of which is the characteristic actuality of the species
just below it in the unbroken chain of organic forms, while the other is a sort
of fortuitous thrust (chance mutation) acting at right angles, so to speak, and
thus deflecting the old species out of its old generative cycle into a new one.
Summing up the lesson of his entire Philosophy of Nature from this stand-
point, Hegel says:
Now, here is what is really involved in this conception. What, speaking generally, we call
inorganic nature is thought of as having an independent existence, while the organic is
attached to it in an external fashion, so that it is a mere matter of chance whether or not
the organic finds the conditions of existence in what confronts it .... The question is
this: Is that the true concept of the inorganic, and do living things represent what is
dependent? [On the contrary] this is the true relation: man is not an accident added on
to what is first; the organic is itself what is first .... Regarded in this fashion, the
universe is not an aggregate of many accidents existing in a relation of indifference, but
is a system endowed, in its essential character, with life. 25
NOTES
1 The translations cited here from Hegel's Lectures on the History of Philosophy have
sometimes been adapted in accordance with the German text (Michelet, 1840).
2 Inscription on statue in the ante-chapel of Trinity College, Cambridge.
3 John N. Findlay, 'Hegel and the Philosophy of Physics,' in The Legacy of Hegel:
Proceedings of the Marquette Hegel Symposium, 1970, ed. J. J. O'Malley, et al. (The
Hague, Nijhoff, 1973), p. 83.
4 The translations cited here from Hegel's Logic have sometimes been adapted in
accordance with the German text (Henning, 1840, 1955).
5 The translations cited here from Hegel's Philosophy of Nature have sometimes been
adapted in accordance with the German text (Poggeler, 1959; Michelet, 1847).
6 J. N. Findlay, Hegel: A Re-Examination (New York, Humanities Press, 1958,1976),
pp.167-8.
7 The translations from Hegel's Phenomenology of Mind have been adapted in
accordance with the German text (Hoffmeister, 1949).
8 Louis de Broglie, Physics and Microphysics (New York, Grosset and Dunlap, 1966),
pp.238-9.
9 Ibid., p. 75.
10 See V. Cioffari, Fortune and Fate from Democritus to St. Thomas Aquinas (New
York, 1935), passim, for a review of the commentary on Dante's Heisenbergian line
(Inf., IV, 136) epitomizing the doctrine of Democritus.
11 H. D. Anthony, Sir Isaac Newton (New York, Collier, 1961), pp. 140-141.
12 Tobias Dantzig, Number: The Language of Science (New York, Macmillan, 1954),
pp. 234, 335.
13 Bertrand Russell, The Scientific Outlook (New York, Norton, 1932), p. 264.
14 Albert Einstein, Out of My Later Years (New York, Philosophical Library, 1950),
p.l10.
15 Einstein, Later Years, p. 97.
16 Albert Einstein, The World As I See It (New York, Covici Friede, 1934), p. 57.
17 Bertrand Russell, 'Introduction,' in A. V. VasiIiev, Space, Time, and Motion (New
York, Knopf, 1924), pp. xv-xvi.
18 Einstein, Later Years, p. 69.
19 FindlaY,Hegel, p. 279.
20 Albert Einstein and L. Infeld, The Evolution of Physics (New York, Simon and
Schuster, 1961), pp. 256-58.
21 PN, § 267, Z, p. 59; § 268, Remark, Z, pp. 61, 62.
HEGEL, NEWTON AND EINSTEIN 85
seem anthropomorphic, but what they picture is the varied forms of that
distinction-without-separation which analytic thought hates, and which is the
central feature of Hegelianism.
I shall now go over to the treatment of Life and the Life-sciences we
encounter in the Phenomenology. Here Hegel is dealing with Life as an
object of Consciousness which emerges after Consciousness has been dealing
with the world of phenomenal natural things, and seeing it as the theatre in
which unmanifest powers and laws are forever displaying themselves. Con-
templating Nature in this manner, it has gone beyond sundered moments of
the Begriff to the Begriff: it has been the Begriff as a Universality which is
forever specifying itself and individualizing itself, and in which none of the
Begriff's constituent moments, and their living interplay, can be separated
from the others. This living Begriff is, however, as much Consciousness itself
as Consciousness's object, and, in contemplating it, Consciousness, the faculty
of liberated, active Universality, is in a sense only contemplating itself. The
Begriff, qua object of Consciousness, is, however, first invested with traits
reminiscent of the sensuous externality which has belonged to its former
objects, and, seen in this manner, it is Life, the defmiteness which is always
melting into indefiniteness and the out-thereness which has also all the lack
of out-thereness which marks inner-life interpenetration. As Hegel puts it:
The determination of Life as it arises out of the Notion or general result which we
encountered on entering this sphere, is sufficient to characterize it without attempting to
develop its nature further: it is a circle embracing the following moments. Its essence is
infmity as the supersession of all differences, the pure revolution about an axis, the rest
of its own absolutely restless infmity, the very self-sufficiency in which the differences
of motion are dissolved, the simple essence of time which in this inner uniformity has
the solid shape of space. Differences, however, are just as much present as differences in
this simple universal medium, since this universal fluidity only has its negative nature in
so far as it abolishes such differences: differences must be there if differences are to be
abolished. But this fluidity, as self-sufficient uniformity, is itself the subsistence or the
substance of these differences, in which they occur as distinct members and independent
parts. Their being no longer has the meaning of being in the abstract, nor their pure
essence the meaning of abstract universality: their being is just the simple fluid substance
of pure movement in itself (Phdn [H, 1937], pp. 135-136). [Trans. by 1. N. F.].
The word that encapsulates the sense of this paragraph and of several
others that follow it is the word Fliissigkeit, Fluidity: Life is Flux as a pure
concept. It is a flux in which there are differences which assert themselves
against the flux, which mean to be determinate, specific, separately individual.
These self-asserting differences are, however, the mere instruments of a
mightier self-assertion, one which has posited such differences only in order
92 JOHN N. FINDLAY
to abolish them, to make them pass into one another, to be the pure negativity
that it is in the process of negating them all. The many differences involved in
Life do not even pretend to the separateness and self-sufficiency of solid,
inorganic things: they are there only to have their separateness and self-
sufficiency and even clear character denied, to become mere points of passage
in an unbroken motion. The teleology of the living organism simply consists
in its denial of substantial separateness, even of determinate character to its
parts: they are there only to be modified, to be bye-passed, to be swept
through and swept away. Nowhere has anyone put forward so stably unstable
and so purely logical an account of life in which structure rests on funda-
mental structurelessness: beside it the Platonic-Aristotelian accounts of Life
as the Self-moving seem hopelessly gross and inadequate. But they make
sense, for they constitute an image of that being-no-one-in-particular which is
also the possibility of being-anyone-and-everyone which is somehow the
deepest essence of our conscious personal being: life in the more defmite
medium of what exists out there is a monogram, an analogue, of that more
ultimate indefmiteness that we experience as ourselves.
Hegel develops his account of Life at a later stage of the Phenomenology
(Phiin [H, 1937], pp. 193-221) where he is discussing the observation of
organic phenomena. Here he maintains the interesting thesis that the teleology
of life, where it is present, essentially transcends natural law: there is rigorous
law connecting acids with bases, but there is no rigorous law connecting cold
climates with hairy pelts, or fluid media with the shapes of fishes. Organisms
do indeed adapt themselves to the environmental situation in which they
arise, but this does not causally produce their peculiarities, and they evince
their freedom from it by having many non-adaptive characters, some anti-
cipating the adaptations of other types of organisms or harking back to the
same. (Hegel does not believe in organismic evolution in time, but his logical
arrangement of species none the less has an evolutionary cast.) The duck-billed
platypus, which Hegel does not seem to have heard of, is a typical example of
Hegelian freedom. Arid not only are organisms ~ot products of the environ-
ment, but they produce no uniform products but themselves: it is they them-
selves which they alone produce and reproduce. An organism may be stimu-
lated by the environment into doing this or that, but, unless this stimulation
passes over into inorganic violence, what the organism does is solely what
suits its own programme, what is part of its repertoire, what is in short itself.
Organisms in short use the natural objects around them, they incorporate
them and their dead properties to some extent into themselves, they feed on
them, they walk on them, they play with them etc., but in all this they make
HEGELIAN TREATMENT OF BIOLOGY AND LIFE 93
external objects their own: the objects which surround organisms never use
organisms, on the other hand, since they have no programmes, no directed
procedures, into whose service organisms can be impressed. These are
elementary points, but they seem, none the less, to have eluded most contem-
porary philosophers.
Hegel also thinks that, while we may properly distinguish the specific
bodily structures of organisms, their brain-structures, muscular structures
etc., from the universal organic functions which work in and through these
structures, it is quite wrong to think of these as correlated aspects of organic
being somehow connected by laws of nature. The structures of brain,
intestines, muscles are nothing apart from the uses, the indwelling purposes to
which they are put: we can no more study them to throw light on integrated
organic functions than we can throw light on the semantics of sentences by
a mere examination of their syntactical make-up. The uses to which such
structures are put are, however, ineliminably universal, and this means that an
organism can always shift its exploration or reaction or self-maintenance from
one structure to another. It is indifferent, Hegel tells us, to the stream of life
what manner of mills it drives (Phiin [H, 1937], p. 211). The freedom of
organic nature is in fact such as neither to obey the rigours which bind
physical substances in physico-chemical necessity, nor the dialectical laws
which govern the development of conscious spirit. Organic nature reveals only
rudiments of laws, suggestions of order and sequence, amusing and specious
relationships, in which the most serious statement that is ever made is that
something has a 'great influence' on something else (Phiin [H, 1937]
p. 220f). Since Hegel's day there has been a great rlevelopment in the life-
sciences and social sciences, but what he says is as true today as it was in
his time. There is not a single rigorous biological or psychological or psycho-
physical or sociological law on record, only rudiments of all these things,
given undue prominence by those who hope to assimilate the sciences of
life to the sciences of lifeless things. When will scientists and philosophers
give up this vain endeavour, and learn to study life as life and not as a
peculiarly complex case oflifelessness? I believe myself that only a revolution
in thought and life, one that radically demotes experimental science and
manipulative technology will do the trick. We are in need of a radical de-
Baconization of thought and life.
From the more fundamental treatments of Life which occur in the Logic
and the Phenomenology, I pass on to consider Hegel's treatment of Life as a
natural phenomenon. The 'Organics' is the third part of the Naturphilosophie,
and in this work we start dialectically with the Notion, the Principle of
94 JOHN N. FINDLAY
this crystal of Life, the inanimate organism of the earth, which has its notion in the
sidereal connections outside of it, but possesses its own peculiar process as a presupposed
past, is the immediate subject of the meteorological process, through which this subject,
as in itself the totality of life, no longer becomes merely an individual shape but is
fructified into vitality. Land and especially sea, as thus the real possibility of life,
perpetually erupt at every point into punctiform, transitory life-forms, lichens, infusoria,
and, in the sea, countless hosts of phosphorescent points of life. But it is just because
generatio aequivoca has this objective organism outside it, that it is restricted to this
punctiform organization, does not develop internally into a specifically articulated
organism, or reproduce itself ex ovo (PN, § 341).
There are accordingly flashes of life in the earth and the elements surrounding
the earth which do not develop into lasting individuality, or the even longer
lasting life of the species, but represent something more than chemico-
mechanical materiality, having perhaps a spontaneity of origin and a brief
self-maintenance of which inert matter is incapable. It is surely a great pity
that generatio aequivoca, so unequivocally real to Aristotle and Hegel, has
since been rendered so dubious: it should on general principles have been
true. The doctrine that omne vivum ex vivo smells inexpugnably of the
analytic Understanding. Modern science has, however, not failed to find
forms of quasi-life which bridge the gulf between the organic and inorganic.
Viruses are now the front-line candidates for this position, and I do not doubt
that there will be others. But instead of being used to show chemistry and
mechanism transcending themselves, I have no doubt that they will be used
by some as but one more 'proof' ofthe mechanico-chemical nature of life.
From the Geological Organism we proceed to the Plant-Organism. Here it
would appear that we have one of the many cases where the dialectic is best
read backwards, where what comes later is necessary for the understanding of
what comes earlier. We can only understand what Hegel has to say about
plants by going on to what he has to say about animals. The animal organism
is the organism fully actualized, the plant merely approaches animality in an
inadequate manner, and falls short of it in ways that are only significant by
contrast with animality. In the animal the moment of Universality is present
in two fashions: on the one hand in the fluid organization of parts and
functions, which have no fixed, separate character, on the other hand in a
sort of rudimentary subjectivity, involving centralized feeling rather than
cognition, into which all its specific differentiations are taken back. The
animal not only is universal, but after a fashion feels its own universality. In
the plant, on the other hand, there is no such detached, centralized univer-
sality: in so far as plants have a centralized self, this lies not in themselves,
but in the light towards which they tend, and on which they depend for the
96 JOHN N. FINDLAY
the hubris of the diseased function or organ, and makes a cure possible. The
Zoological Idea is, however, powerless against the individual's slow hardening
in habit, which is the essence of growing old: growing less and less responsive
to the environment, living more and more in the past, the organism becomes
more and more like a dead thing. But, as we have said, "the goal of Nature is
to destroy itself and to break through its husk of immediate sensuous exis-
tence, to consume itself like the phoenix in order to come forth from this
externality rejuvenated as spirit" (PN, § 376, Z).
I have now come to the end of Hegel's treatment of Life and the Life-
Sciences. I would comment, not only on the richness of its detail, and of its
application of logical principle to that detail, but also on its general metho-
dology. Hegel is neither a rationalist nor an empiricist: the basic forms of
Life are logical differentiations of a single categorial conception, but he does
not disdain to show us how these basic forms are further specified with
infinitely rich, empirical contingency. Hegel is also neither a mechanist nor a
vitalist. Life for him is led up to by processes which fall short of Life itself
and is at all times dependent on such processes, it is itself a series of stages
which lead up to and depend on one another, and it itself leads up to Spirit
which, while transcending it, never breaks with it nor loses its dependence on
it. Hegel's conceptual presuppositions are arguably those of a truly rational
biology, not those of a biology intent of making nonsense of its own subject-
matter and ultimately of itself.
Boston University
GEORGE DI GIOVANNI
I shall come shortly to Findlay's paper.! First, for reasons that will become
apparent later, I want to broaden somewhat the scope of his discussion. It
must be remembered that the 'organic', before appearing in the Philosophy
of Nature as a form of the natural world, is already present in the Logic
as one of the determinations of thought;2 and the question I now want to
consider is whether, after Hegel's treatment of it as logical category, it can
still have legitimate meaning in the context of the Philosophy of Nature.
Speaking briefly and lucidly about Hegel's Logic always presents, of course,
virtually insurmountable difficulties. But I think that I can make my point
with reasonable clarity using Kant as a point of reference. His Transcendental
Logic had been built on a distinction between the concept of an object in
general, such as would be obtained by reflecting upon the requirements of
intelligibility that thought makes upon its object, and the concept of an
object of experience. 3 The two were by no means identical, for an object of
experience was ex hypothesi sensible; and although it too, in order to make
genuine science possible, would have had to satisfy the general conditions of
intelligibility, in its case these also had to be shown to be facts of experience.
As long as one proceeded along reflective lines to determine what, in principle,
constituted an intelligible object, one had no guarantees that such an object
would in fact be realized in experiences, or that these, as Hume had in fact
denied, were in fact a fitting subject of science. The big problem that thus
faced the critical Kant was precisely to demonstrate that the concept of an
object in general (as reflectively determined) was also a valid determination of
the immediate objects of experience.
Whether Kant in fact resolved the problem, or whether it was even possible
for him to resolve it on his principles, is a question that does not concern us
here. But it is instructive to note how Hegel managed to avoid altogether the
need of demonstrating the legitimacy of a transition from reflection to actual
experience. What had led Kant to differentiate between object in general and
object of experience had been. precisely the immediacy that characterized
experiences and that he thought detracted from their intelligibility. Hegel
realized, instead, that the same immediacy is in fact a necessary condition of
all objectivity; and while one could distinguish between types of objects,
101
R. S. Cohen and M. W. Wartofsky (eds.), Hegel and the Sciences, 101-107.
© 1984 by D. Reidel Publishing Company.
102 GEORGE DI GIOV ANNI
some being more intelligible than others, the difference between them was to
be measured not by the extent they were free from immediacy, but by the
degree to which they explicitly incorporated it as an integral moment of their
being per se. 4 In other words, immediacy is for Hegel just as much a moment
of thought-life as it is of sensible experience: it should be possible, therefore,
to demonstrate from within thought itself, and on reflective terms, that a
constant transition from the immediate to the reflective and vice versa is
both possible and necessary. Once this point has been speculatively
established, and the need to justify the existential relevance of thought is thus
in principle absolved, one is free to consider whatever particular problem the
interplay between immediacy and reflection poses in a given sphere of
experience in terms that are appropriate to such a sphere. The resolution of
the problem no longer calls for the impossible task of 'applying' reflective
categories to the immediate content of experience.
Unless this point is understood, the form that Hegel's Logic assumes does
not make any sense. Its goal is to develop the idea of 'concept' and this goal
is to be realized by means of the highest possible reflection. It is clear, more-
over, that for Hegel this reflection represents the most accomplished case of
a free act; and that, in virtue of its freedom, it encompasses in principle all
things. Like Aristotle's soul, Hegel's self-thinking thought is potentially a
whole world. But precisely for this reason, the Logic opens with the category
of Being, an indeterminate somewhat which is more the intimation of an
object than anything actually recognizable. It is the form the thought itself
must first assume in front of its own reflective glance inasmuch as, since in
the reflection the distinction between itself as subject and itself as object
becomes strictly relative, what its limits as thought actually are becomes a
thoroughly open question. Thought must discover what it itself is: it re-
enacts, albeit in a highly abstract and reflectively controlled conceptual
medium, the same interplay between subject and object at work at any level
of experience. It is difficult not to refer once more back to Kant. He had
been right, after all, in arguing against Descartes that the Cogito does not
offer to philosophical reflection an especially indubitable source of certainty,5
for even thought, in order to know itself, would have to objectify itself. But
it then would have to treat itself as 'other' just like any other object. Kant,
however, had taken this peculiarity of conscious life to mean that logical
reflection is strictly formal, and that in order to be relevant to the rest of
experience, its determinations needed the complement of an extraneous,
empirical material. Hegel interpreted it, instead, in a directly opposite
manner. For him it meant that thought, even at its most reflective level,
ON THE ORGANIC IN HEGEL'S PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE 103
said about the categories of 'life' in the Philosophy of Nature would apply as
well to the rest of it. I find it difficult, in other words, to consider the place
that the 'organic' might have in Hegel's Philosophy of Nature, for I do not
accept the latter as a legitimate piece of philosophical thinking. I do not mean
to say, of course, that after Hegel's Logic there is no room left for a specula-
tive, even philosophical, study of nature.6 My point is that, since the Logic has
vindicated the speculative value of all experiences, even the most immediate
among them, after it we should be ready to explore the sense that emerges
out of our transactions with actual nature in a manner and with conceptual
means that respect the immediacy of such transactions. This is not what Hegel
does in his Philosophy of Nature. At worst, he simply uses logical categories
in order to classify data gathered elsewhere. At best, he manages to throw
upon nature a human proflle: I mean to say, he interprets it as if it were an
extension of the human body, attributing relative value to its many appear-
ances according as they approximate the perfection of existence achieved in
thought. An exercise of this sort might have a proper place and some value.
It does not help us learn, however, about nature itself (something, incident-
ally, that the 'Baconian' concepts which Professor Findlay decries might well
do); and while it might prove instructive about the ways of the spirit, even in
this respect it does not add anything to what the Logic has already taught.
Rudolf Haym said of the Phenomenology of Spirit that it was at once
Transcendental Psychology and History of Culture, and that the mixture of
the two made for a completely imaginary account of the rise of man's spirit. 7
In a similar vein, one could say of Hegel's Philosophy of Nature that it
represents an illegitimate extrapolation of logical reflection. But it must be
noted that Kant too, no less than Hegel, had tried to determine a priori the
properties of nature; and that his Transcendental Logic required, for reasons
inherent to its very conception, that its categories be extended to encompass
an empirical material. Kant needed a Metaphysics of Nature for basically the
same reason he needed a Transcendental Deduction of the categories - viz.,
in order to demonstrate the de facto relevance of his logic to the process of
experience. Hegel's Logic, however, as I have pointed out, circumvented this
need of Kant. The use, therefore, to which Hegel puts the categories of the
Logic in the Philosophy of Nature is specious not only per se, but also from
the point of view of the Logic itself. Of course, saying that Hegel was wrong
when he needed not be and that he was not in the clear with respect to his
own conception of the system, might not appear at all flattering to his
apologists. But it is an important point to make if one wants to adjudicate
the nature and the value of Hegel's contribution to German Idealism. From a
ON THE ORGANIC IN HEGEL'S PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE 105
itself, for it still has to realize its own idea by exhibiting it in the immediacy
of nature and eventually (I presume) in the vicissitudes of history. Hence the
transition to the Philosophy of Nature, which Hegel justifies as the first step
in the process of realization.
Now, Hegel's alleged reason is a highly disturbing one. Philosophically,
it suggests a strange model on his part regarding the nature and the limits of
reflection. Unless one seriously expects one's awareness of oneself, and the
process that has led up to it, to become itself a 'person' (somewhat in the
manner of a Trinitarian procession), it is difficult to see how else such aware-
ness could be realized except as idea, viz., in the medium of abstract con-
ceptualization. Anything else would involve suspending the stance of specula-
tive thought, and becoming engaged instead in the concerns of actual
existence. Historically, Hegel's words evoke issues from past debates between
Fichte and Schelling that he was in fact in a position to silence once and for
all. I am referring to the controversy regarding the possibility of a philosophy
of nature that Schelling upheld and Fichte denied. Schelling had argued that
his speCUlations on nature were needed in order to provide a more concrete
counterpart to the otherwise purely abstract reflections of the Wissen-
schaftslehre; and Fichte had retorted by saying that it was wrong-headed,
perhaps even dangerous, to try to recognize the process of thought in the
appearances of nature, and that Schelling's attempts, in any event, lacked
seriousness for they too were, and could not help being, the products of
reflection.! 0 Now, Hegel could have silenced both Fichte and Schelling by
pointing out to each that his Logic was indeed only an idealization, yet,
because of the continuity of ideal reflection and natural becoming, it
provided the only purely reflective understanding of nature possible.
In brief, exactly when Hegel thought he had found a way of realizing the
System which had been, in one way or other, the ideal of all his predecessors,
he had in fact achieved an understanding of reason that opened it to all
experiences, and made irrelevant the very notion of a systematic reconstruc-
tion of reality. As a response to an apology for Hegel's Philosophy of Nature,
this amounts to saying that Hegel's merit is not to have succeeded where
modern empirical sciences have failed, but on the contrary, to have provided
the conceptual means for understanding the nature of such sciences, and the
speculative value of the knowledge they provide.
McGill University
Montreal
ON THE ORGANIC IN HEGEL'S PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE 107
NOTES
1 This paper was originally prepared, thirteen years ago, as a comment on Professor
Findlay's 'The Place of the Organic in Hegel's Philosophy of Nature'. I have revised it
somewhat and updated it for publication.
2 That is, in the Logic of 1812-16, in the third part of the third book, as the first form
that Idea assumes.
3 This distinction is not usually adverted to by commentators. It is nonetheless crucial
to Kant. Without it, for instance, he could not legitimately claim to be able to think of
the thing-in-itself as affecting the mind, yet disclaim to understand the nature of the
relation involved. As applied to the thing-in-itself and the mind, the cause-effect relation
remains unschematized. It is used in the abstract sense of a determination of an object in
general. Cf., for instance, Critique of Pure Reason, A290/B346-47.
4 Immediacy appears at every stage of the Logic, but has a different meaning in each
depending on the specific form thought assumes. For the way immediacy re-asserts itself
at the end of the Logic, cf. Wissenschaft der Logik, vol. II (Hamburg, Meiner, 1963),
pp. 499 ff. I have tried to illustrate the place of immediacy in Hegel's Logic using some
specific texts as my basis in two papers: 'Reflection and Contradiction: A Commentary
on some Passages of Hegel's Logic', Hegel-Studien 8 (1973),131-61; 'The Category of
Contingency in the Hegelian Logic', in Art and Logic in Hegel's Philosophy, eds. W. E.
Steinkraus and K. L. Schmitz (Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey, Humanities Press; Brigh-
ton, Sussex, Harvester Press, 1980), pp. 179-200.
5 Critique of Pure Reason, A347/B405-A348/B406; A354-55; B423, note.
6 This was Croce's position. Cf. Logica come scienza del concetto puro (Bari, Laterza,
1958; first ed. 1909), pp.13 ff., 21-24.
7 Hegel und seine Zeit [1857] (Hildesheim, Georg Olms, 1962), pp. 240 ff. I am in no
way endorsing Haym's estimation of the Phenomenology of Spirit.
8 I have in mind especially, Otto Poggeler, 'Fragment aus einer Hegelschen Logik, mit
einem Nachwort zur Entwicklungsgeschichte von Hegels Logik', Hegel-Studien 2 (1963),
47-70; 'Hegels Jenaer Systemkonzeption', Philosophisches lahrbuch 71 (1963-64),
286-318; Heinz Kimmerle, 'Zur Entwicklung des Hegelschen Denkens in Jena', Hegel-
Studien 4 (1969), 33-47; Johann H. Trede, 'Hegels fruhe Logik (1801-1803/4)" Hegel-
Studien 7 (1970), 123-68.
9 Logik, Metaphysik, Naturphilosophie, Fragment einer Reinschrift (1804/05), Hegel -
Gesammelte Werke, vol. VII (Hamburg, Meiner, 1971), pp. 176-78.
10 For the controversy, see the following letters: 1800, Nov. 15 - Fichte to Schelling;
Nov. 19 - Schelling to Fichte; Dec. 27 - Fichte to Schelling; 1801, May 29 - Schelling
to Fichte; May 31 - Fichte to Schelling; Oct. 3 - Schelling to Fichte; 1802, Jan. 15 -
Fichte to Schelling. F. W. 1. Schelling, Briefe und Dokumente, ed. H. Fuhrmans (Bonn,
Bouvier, 1973), vol. II, Zusatzband.
MILIC CAPEK
And Hegel adds confidently: "This is the proof of the law of descent of a
falling body derived from the Notion of the thing.,,3 Only one thing is clear
in this obscure passage: Hegel's so-called proof is nothing but a vague and
questionable application of his triadic method - first the thesis, then its
negation, and, finally, the synthesis as a negation of the previous negation.
There are hundreds of similarly obscure 'proofs' in Hegel's writings on nature.
It is not difficult to see that under such circumstances the whole meaning
of Newtonian mechanics completely escaped him. Thus he denies the validity
of Newton's deduction of Kepler's law from the law of gravitation. On the
contrary, he claims that the law of gravitation can be derived from Kepler's
third law and offers another of his 'proofs', based on an elementary confusion
of symbols and the failure to understand the very meaning of mathematical
proof. 4 But does he really believe in the law of gravitation itself when he says
that the motion of the heavenly bodies is not a result of their being pulled
this way or the other, but is a 'free' motion? "They go on, as the ancients
used to say, like the blessed gods" (PN, § 269, Remark, Z, p. 65). As Edding-
ton observed, "this sounds particularly foolish even for a philosopher."s
Perhaps what Hegel was trying to say is that mechanics and astronomy
describe what is a mere external aspect of a process whose intrinsic structure
is akin to human will and to mind in general. This would be consonant with
Hegel's view of nature as the self-externalization of the Absolute Idea; hence
his opposition to Newtonian mechanism and his leaning toward an organic
view of nature. But his own organic philosophy of nature is, at least in this
particular context, of a very crude, hylozoistic kind; of the passage above it
may be said without unfairness that it is on the same level as that of Thales
HEGEL AND THE ORGANIC VIEW OF NATURE 111
talking about the soul of the lodestone. In truth, Hegel's view of magnetism
differs from that of Thales only by its triadic jargon: the magnet with its pair
of poles and a neutral field in between is a sensible manifestation of syllogism
(PN, § 312, pp. 162-163)! No wonder that, as Hegel's disciple and editor,
Karl Ludwig Michelet conceded, Hegel's philosophy of nature was met by
scientists with a shrugging of shoulders and compassionate smiles. No wonder
that Harald Hp[fding called it "une partie honteuse" of Hegel's philosophy, 7
and that Emile Meyerson was rather polite when he confessed that the
resulting impression it leaves in the mind of the reader is that of "profound
bewilderment" (profond ahurissement):
Nothing which would resemble the science of today or the science of his contemporaries
... not even any science in any era such as the Aristotelian physics or the chemistry of
alchemists. It is as if, while expecting to see human faces, we were presented with a series
of absurdly grimacing monsters. Sometimes the reader begins to doubt whether he
understood properly and re-reads the text several times to be sure that the phenomenon
of which the author speaks is really that which is known to science - to such degree
does the interpretation given by the author differ from everything which science knows
or has known. The' examples abound and on this point one is embarrassed which one to
choose. 8
not to be aware of the chemical revolution of his own time. It is even more
odd to see an outstanding nineteenth-century philosopher adhering to the old
Aristotelian doctrine of the four elements (PN, § 281 ).10
As for Hegel's biological views, we have already mentioned his odd theory
of the senses. Obsessed by the dialectical triad, he tried hard to prove that
there are really only three senses. In a similar way he reduced the number of
continents to three: Europe, Asia, and Africa; for America is a mere appendix
of European civilization, and Australia is eliminated. But the most surprising
feature of Hegel's biological views is the denial of biological evolution. It is
true that he lived before Darwin; but Cuvier and Lamarck were his contem-
poraries. Paleontology, founded by Cuvier, was dismissed by him as a
'nebulous' science; and the fossils, according to him, have no evolutionary
significance since they are not the relics of extinct organisms, but mere freaks
of nature. The idea of evolution of plants and animals is explicitly rejected in
§ 249 of Hegel's The Encyclopedia of Sciences. Nature is devoid of history;
history begins with historians. When Hegel speaks of the hierarchy of nature,
he means by it the system of gradations without any' evolutionary significance,
the static scala naturae of the pre-evolutionary thought,u
The only possible conclusion, then, is that if there is any value in Hegel's
philosophy of nature, it must not be looked for in his specific claims, which
are mostly false, often absurd, at best irrelevant. It should be looked for in his
more general, metaphysical ideas; among them the idea of becoming occupies
first place. Yet, what was just said about Hegel's attitude toward evolution
indicates that the status of becoming in Hegel's overall view of reality is
uncertain and ambiguous. This question is of fundamental importance in our
present context. On the way in which it is answered will depend our answer
to another important question: What is the relation of Hegel's philosophy to
the modern organic view of nature? Since the modern organic view of nature
can hardly ignore evolution and the dynamic and historical aspect of reality,
it is obvious how important for us is the status of becoming in Hegel's
thought.
It is frustrating that the question concerning the status of becoming in
Hegel's thOUght cannot be answered in a definite and unambiguous way. The
reason is that the ambiguity is inherent in Hegel's thought, as various texts
clearly indicate_ On the one hand, in his own words, there was not a single
idea of Heraclitus which was not incorporated into his own system (HP 2,
p. 279). On the other hand, Hegel's leaning toward a dynamic view of reality
was counterbalanced by his strong Eleatic emphasis on the timeless character
of the Absolute Idea. The latter tendency was certainly strengthened by the
HEGEL AND THE ORGANIC VIEW OF NATURE 113
if any philosopher is a philosopher of evolution, that philosopher is Hegel ... Had the
Darwinian and later data been available, he would almost certainly have acknowledged
the historical trends in nature that he admits in the realm of Spirit ... 13
I am not so sure of it; in the first place, there were evolutionists prior to
Darwin - lamarck during Hegel's own life, Buffon and Diderot even before
him; to believe that the idea of evolution came into being with Charles
Darwin is a mere 'ethnic' prejudice. Furthermore, it is doubtful that Hegel
114 MILlC CAPEK
II. Becoming appears as the third term of the first and most fundamental
dialectical triad, that is, as the synthesis of Being and Non-Being. It is another
instance of Hegel's dialectical triad, which cannot be understood as a 'dialec-
tical process'; certainly neither Being nor Non-Being are anterior in a
temporal sense to Becoming. Should then the priority of Being and Non·
Being with respect to their synthesis be understood in a logical sense? If so,
should we regard Hegel's attempt to deduce Becoming as successful? As early
as ten years after Hegel's death it was pointed out by one of his critics that
Becoming cannot be obtained by a synthesis of two equally static terms. This
objection was formulated by Trendelenburg and was also raised by Victor
Cousin, by Paul. Janet, and much more recently by Emile Meyerson in his
un translated work De ['explication dans les sciences (1925).14 Meyerson
observed that the predicament in which Hegel found himself was not basically
different from that of Parmenides; but while Parmenides realized that
between two equally static, becomingless terms, no intermediate and non-
static term can be smuggled, Hegel tried to do just that. But his deduction of
becoming was fallacious; the only way that he was able to smuggle it in was
to borrow it surreptitiously from experience, that is, from something
altogether heterogeneous to the couple of static and abstract concepts. In the
light of the history of ideas it was thus not accidental that Eleatism re-
appeared with neo-Hegelian thinkers, in particular in the thought of
McTaggart.
HEGEL AND THE ORGANIC VIEW OF NATURE 115
Harald H~ffding raised basically the same objection, even though super-
ficially it looks different since it is formulated in the language of formal
logic. 15 He pointed out that if each synthesis is a negation of the previous
negation, we should obtain the original term - Being instead of Becoming.
This is the well-known law of double negation, which is closely related to
the law of the excluded middle. It is certainly valid within the two-valued
logic. But is Hegel's thought intelligible within the framework of the tradi-
tional two-valued logic? Does it not transcend it as the thought of Heraclitus
did before him and Bergson's dynamism after him? This, it seems to me, is
hinted by Findlay when he wrote that
Hegel is not wrong in pointing out that our thought hates borderlines or transitional
situations, that it is averse to anything that would now be called a three-value logic, and
that it seeks to break up its subject-matter into mutually exclusive aspects of phases, so
that the conceptual position of anything is immediately clear. 16
idea of "being its own other" ,22 which characterized the way perceptual data
interpenetrate each other. No psychological atomism, no doctrine of external
relations can do justice to the mutual immanence of parts which is character-
istic of immediate experience, sensory as well as introspective. This was
systematically stressed by Gestalt psychology, in opposition to the atomistic
and additive approach of associationistic psychology.
The emphasis on the unitary, Gestalt-like and dynamic character of
organic life is probably the most valuable feature of Hegel's philosophy of
nature. From the mechanistic standpoint, 'life' is a mere collective name for
all living organisms; there is no supraindividuallife in the sense of a concrete
universal present in its different individual manifestations; in the mechanistic
scheme, widely prevalent today in English-speaking countries and in Russia,
life is nothing but a peculiarly complex case of lifelessness. In any organic
view of nature just the opposite is true: life is the primary category and what
we call 'lifeless' or 'inorganic' is merely a very rudimentary form of life or
proto-life. The mechanistic view of life was a logical consequence of the
mechanistic view of the universe; it remained justified as long as no serious
flaws in the classical Newton-Laplacean view appeared. But anybody even
superficially acquainted with the physics of the twentieth century, whose
attention is not diverted to irrelevant problems of methodology, is well aware
that the mechanistic view of the universe belongs to the past. The mechanistic
view of life has been deprived of the basic premises which made it so plausible
in the relatively recent past. But a detailed discussion of this would lead us far
beyond the scope of this article. 23
Hegel's philosophy of nature, together with the whole German Romantic
movement of which Goethe and Schelling were the outstanding representa-
tives, was the first revolt against the classical Newtonian physics. The main
reason for its failure was that it was premature and was to a considerable
degree merely a revolt of imagination and feeling against the depressing
mechanistic view of reality. There were valuable insights in it, and Whitehead,
in the fifth chapter of his Science and the Modem World (1925) did full
justice to the English counterpart of the Romantic reaction, as he called it.
But these valuable insights were fragmentary, and, in Hegel's philosophy of
nature at least, wrapped in confusing jargon and pervaded by hasty general-
izations, superficial and vague analogies, and even by weird and irresponsible
guesses. When the course of time swept away the debris, little was left of
Hegel's philosophy of nature; but what was left resembled, if I may use this
metaphor, a few golden grains found after the mass of sand is washed away.
There is no space left for me to show how Hegel's central idea of the related-
HEGEL AND THE ORGANIC VIEW OF NATURE 119
ness of nature was fruitfully applied by his former disciple, Johannes Bernard
Stallo, in his prophetic criticism of the mechanical theory of nature.
Stallo's criticism of Newton's rotating bucket experiment anticipated both
Mach's criticism and Whitehead's much later criticism of the fallacy of simple
location, as I tried to show some time ago. 24 It is true that Stallo, when he
wrote his Concepts and Theories of Modem Physics (1882), was not a
Hegelian any longer. He referred to his early Hegelianism as "the metaphysical
malady which seems to be one of the unavoidable disorders of intellectual
infancy."25 Yet, an attentive reader of Stallo's intermediate writings as well
as of his final work would find that the most fruitful of his insights - the
inadequacy of the mechanization and fragmentation of nature - can be
traced to Hegel's intuitive anticipation of the organic view of nature.
Boston University
NOTES
others, and indeed are so in the self-same sense in which the absolute is maintained to
be so by Hegel.
Whitehead's view on the combination of self-identity and self-diversity of each actual
occasion has a truly Hegelian ring. Cf. Process and Reality (New York, Macmillan, 1930),
p.38.
23 Cf. my books, The Philosophical Impact of Contemporary Physics, 2nd ed. (Prince'
ton, Van Nostrand, 1969) and Bergson and Modern Physics. A Re-Interpretation and
Re-Evaluation, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 7 (Dordrecht, Boston,
D. Reidel, 1971).
24 Cf. mY'articles, 'Two Critics of Newton Prior to Mach: Boscovich and Stallo' in Actes
du XII congres international de l'histoire des sciences, Paris, 1968 (Paris, Blanchard,
1971), Vol. IV, pp. 35-37; and 'Johann Bernard Stallo' in Dictionary of Scientific
Biography, ed. by C. C. Gillispie (New York, Scribner, 1975), Vol. XII, pp. 607-10.
2S The Concepts and Theories of Modern Physics, ed. Percy W. Bridgman (Cambridge,
Mass., Harvard University Press, 1960), p. 6.
DIETRICH VON ENGELHARDT
II
with both views toward research into nature and medicine, empirical and
romantic. Especially complex is his relation to Schelling. The differences
among the innumerable Romantic proposals on the one hand, and the
difference between these and Hegel's philosophy of nature on the other,
remained unnoticed by the physicians of his time. Hegel's ideas about illness
were basically disregarded,2 his philosophy of nature sharing the general fate
of the Romantic philosophy of nature.
Already.during Hegel's lifetime a pronounced resistance to metaphysical
conceptions of illness was to be found in medicine. According to Hufeland
(1800), for medicine during these years of crisis there was only "the middle
road between fruitless speculation and blind empiricism" 3 ; an enduring and
practice-oriented doctrine of illness will be especially careful not to "impute
to nature some sort of speculative system".4 In 1805, Hecker warns of the
"slippery ice", of the "thorns, cliffs and rushing forest streams of the most
recent philosophies", which "climb at once to the highest viewpoint of all,
while lacking any path to get up there."s On the contrary, it was the task
of empirical medicine to find a path between the "mania for systems, hair-
splitting dogmatism and blind empiricism.,,6 Especially in an age of anarchy
- in political as well as scientific respects - it was essential to have solid
foundations; the imperative of the hour was a "rational scepticism.,,7 Even
if such scepticism also had an eclectic character, the interest of the patient
was to be preferred to any system. In the year 1816, a physician, using the
pseudonym 'Candidus', published a critique of philosophy of nature, under
the title 'Not an Accusation, But a Complaint'.8 According to this Candidus,
philosophy of nature of a Romantic-speculative character led to absurdities;
to be sure it was "famed only in Germany, in France and England it was
either unknown or held in contempt."9 One could only wish that all the
"fantasies and errors of young and old which philosophy of nature had
caused in Germany would be forgiven and as soon as possible forgotten."lO
But not only are erroneous concepts of man and of illness due to this
philosophy of nature, it also makes the individual human beings who follow
it unhappy; the death of Reil is oppressive, as is his melancholy, his despair,
his dreary views of man and the world. Hufeland devoted an Mterword to
Candidus's critique. Above ali, medicine must defend itself against this,
"because it is just the medical world where this view can most easily gain
admission, and the physical world is the enchanted forest through which
the spirit is led to moral eclipse."ll Around 1830, the preceding decades
were condemned by the anatomist Hartmann because during these times
philosophy of nature "subjugated medicine and transformed it to accord with
HEGEL'S UNDERSTANDING OF ILLNESS 125
its basic views" ;12 fortunately this time had now been superseded forever.
Hegel repeatedly separated himself from the empiricist and Romantic
conceptions of his time. Just as he was against the natural scientists, so he
also fmds himself in a dual opposition to medicine: on the one hand against
the Romantic designs for medicine, and on the other against the fact·centered
form of contemporary empirical medicine. Still with this, Hegel considers
a combination of empirical work and speculation as a thinking and compre-
hending [begreiJend] examination of nature to be in principle both possible
and necessary (PN § 246, p. 6). According to him philosophy of nature is
not an alternative to natural science, nor is it to be defended or rejected as
a preparatory stage or a menace to natural science. However, Hegel sees the
medicine of his time surrendering to the effect of the Zeitgeist, making
everything shallow, just like all the other sciences. In a letter of April 11,
1824 he thanks Windischmann for sending him his latest work, "Ober etwas,
das def Heilkunst Noth thut [About something that is needed by medicine] ",
which, according to Windischmann, should fall like "a bomb into the vile
junk and apothecary rubbish of medicine.,,13 In his evaluation of this work
Hegel remarks:
Your attack is disordered at its root, and even if those who are sunk in this morass can
no longer hear, still on the other hand, for those whose confidence cannot attain force
in the face of the universal climate, these words will prove fruitful for their power and
their sentiments, and the courage of knowing will grow in them. To begin with, you have
turned to medicine, and the presentation will be most convincing when it presents the
particular distress and need of a special field. However, other fields deserve equal
attention, especially theology, from which all confidence and intrinsic worth issue for
the others. But the state of this science almost justifies that of the others, for the sacred
realm is not entrusted to them, and if the priests (and among these I also include the
philosophers and in its way also the government) allow the people to fall into such
superficiality, then medicine too will be forced to conceive of their illnesses and
suffering in such an external manner, for then it finds no point of support for an intellec-
tually deep activity that both enters inward and acts from within.1 4
According to Hegel, mind and nature are torn apart by the thought of the
time; but what is required is their combination, to be sure, a specific
combination of concept and reality, which, according to him, the Romantics
(who have turned against the dominant medical science) have by no means
achieved. ls Their conceptions are familiar to him. Hegel criticizes the
formalism in all the Romantic attempts, the external analogizing, the
involution and uncritical application of the concept of metamorphosis.l 6
Hegel also speaks of a "wild forest stream that threatens to sow confusion in
reason and science,,;l? a philosophic critique must decisively oppose these
126 DIETRICH VON ENGELHARDT
tendencies, in order that the attitude toward philosophy of nature, which had
fallen from astonishment into indifference could be changed back again to
respect and recognition. The external manner which had already been at work
in Schelling'S philosophy had been carried still further by Oken, Troxler and
other Romantics, who had lapsed "completely into an empty formalism"
(PN § 359, Zusatz, p. 388); their method of comprehending nature and the
living organisms was "crude and thoroughly unphilosophical" in spirit
(PN § 359, Remark, p. 386), and this because ofa thoroughgoing confusion
of logical categories and the categories of natural science:
... this ignorance and contempt for the Notion which, in general, gives rise to the facile
formalism that, in place of the determinations of the Notion, makes use of sensuous
materials such as chemical substances, as well as relationships belonging to the sphere
of inorganic Nature, such as the north and south poles of the magnet, or even the
difference between magnetism itself and electricity, a formalism which, in its appre-
hension and exposition of the natural universe, attaches externally to its various spheres
and differences a ready-made schema compounded of such material (PN § 359, Remark,
p. 387).
Fine philosophers these, who fancy that in essence they have the truth, and that if only
they keep on saying 'essence', then this makes it the inner truth of the matter! I have not
the slightest respect for their talk of essence, for it is nothing but an abstract reflection.
To explicate essence, however, is to make it appear as a real existence (PN § 371,
Zusatz, p. 430).
system of medicine" (PN § 373, Remark, p. 437) and to try to explain illness
with the categories of sthenia and asthenia [strength and weakness] alone,
cannot convince Hegel: "A theory of medicine built on these arid determina-
tions of the Understanding is complete in a half dozen propositions; it is no
wonder that it spread rapidly and found many adherents" (PN § 359,
Remark, p. 386).
Nor will Hegel accept the historization of illnesses, according to which
the taxonomic system of illness is at the same time supposed to be the law of
their appearance in history. 20 Hegel also does not follow the natural history
approach to illness, which induces Oken to designate "pathology" as the
"physiology of the animal kingdom", and illnesses as the "life-processes of
animals",21 and which leads Hoffmann to the conception that rickets is a
sinking-down to the condition of mollusks, arthritis a regression to animal
regeneration by means of the joints, and epilepsy a coming-to-life again in
human beings of the natural stage of the Oscillatoria [algae].22 Hegel also
does not agree with the religious view of illness as set forth by a Heinroth, a
Windischmann, a Ringseis. 23 With all his interest in illness and its significance
in nature and in the realm of the spirit, the philosopher Hegel cannot agree
with the emphatic judgments of the Romantics about illness and the
pathological. Instead he sees the Romantic preoccupation with illness as
dangerous to the equanimity of soul and mind of human beings; above all
from such confrontations with mental illnesses, psychic damage may result.
He is very eager, Hegel writes to Windischmann on May 27, 1810, to see his
work on magic; he himself does not dare to draw near to "this obscure side
or mode of mental nature or of natural mind", for "health and a merry, and
indeed ruggedly merry, disposition" was needed for this work more than for
any other. Without doubt, the deplorable state of his feelings, of which
Windischmann had reported, was to be blamed on this work:
... this descending into dark regions, where nothing shows itself to be firm, definite
and secure, where shimmering lights flicker everywhere, but beside chasms, still more
obscured by the brightness, misled by the surroundings that cast false reflections rather
than illuminate - where the beginning of every path breaks off again or dwindles away
into the indeterminable, is lost and tears us away from our destiny and our direction. 24
From his own experience he knew that state, where one had steeped one-
self in the "chaos of appearances" and had not yet arrived at "clarity and a
detailed view of the whole"; he himself had "suffered several years from this
hypochondria to the point of debilitation." Probably every human being had
"such a turning point in his life, the dark point of contraction of his being,
128 DIETRICH VON ENGELHARDT
The organism can recover from disease; but disease is in its very nature, and herein lies
the necessity of death, i.e. of this dissolution in which the series of processes becomes
the empty process which does not return to itself (PN § 375, Zusatz, pp. 441-442).
Illness documents the power of nature over the individual; in the sexual
relationship, man relates to nature in another person, in taking nourishment
he relates to external nature; but in becoming ill he has to carry out this
confrontation within himself. Sexuality, as the foundation of the species and
illness are philosophically related phenomena. [In German, gatten means to
mate or to copulate, and Gattung means species - Ed.] In the perspective of
Hegelian philosophy, nature and mind must necessarily fall asunder for a
positive interpretation of reality, man must become estranged from his
material environment and also from his own body.
For Hegel illness is a disturbance of the organism, a falling apart of the
capacities and body systems which are maintained in a unity in a state of
health. At the same time, Hegel rejects Brown's proposal to understand illness
as the consequence of too strong or too weak a stimulus - fundamentally
illness is a discrepancy between the individual as a living ego [Ich] and his
bodily reality:
Disease does not consist in an irritation (Reiz) being too great or too small for the
susceptibility of the organism, rather is its Notion a disproportion of its being and its
self (PN § 371, Zusatz, p. 428).
Appetite, too, the feeling of a lack, is to its own self the negative, relates itself to itself
as a negative: is itself and is also in relation to itself as a being feeling a lack; but with
this difference, that in appetite this lack is something external, that is, the self is not
turned against its structure (Gestalt) as such, whereas in disease the negative thing is the
structure,itself (PN § 371, Zusatz, p. 429).
130 DIETRICH VON ENGELHARDT
clear by the weight carried by the multiplicity of both the concrete and
chance in Hegel's philosophy.26 Hegel by no means claims to deduce all
forms of illness, their causes and their courses, the possibilities of treatment,
therapeutic methods, and the limits of therapy. According to him that cannot
be the task of philosophy.
Typology of Illness
Whereas in health, all the vital functions are held in this ideality, in disease the blood,
e.g., is heated, inflamed; and then it is active on its own account (PN § 371, Zusatz,
p.429).
central activity on its own. According to Hegel these illnesses have two modes
of manifesting themselves: acute and chronic. In acute illnesses, the disease
of one region of the body spreads to the whole organism, while in chronic
illnesses the disease cannot become illness of the whole organism; the
essential vital functions remain unbroken: "In such diseases, appetite and
digestion remain quite unimpaired, and the sexual instinct retains its
strength" (PN § 371, Zusatz, p. 432). Cirrhosis of the liver and consumption
are typical examples of chronic illnesses for Hegel.
The third kind of illness relates to the subject in its subjectivity - these
are the "diseases of the soul (Seele)" (PN § 371, Zusatz, p. 432). Just like the
physical illnesses, these can be so acute that death takes place. In the psychic
illnesses, according to Hegel, the psychic dimensions absolutize themselves
against the unity of the mind and destroy the identity of the individual,
which is now no longer capable of remaining itself through all its different
feelings and affects:
so, too, in the psychical life illness results if the merely psychical side of the organism,
freeing itself from the power of the mental or spiritual consciousness, usurps the latter's
function and mind or spirit, in losing control over the psychical element belonging to it,
no longer retains its self-mastery but itself sinks to the form of psychical life and in
doing so surrenders that relation to the actual which to the sound mind is essential and
objective, that is, the relation resulting from the reduction to a moment of what is
posited as external (PM § 406, Zusatz, p. 106).
Sorrow and fright can be the immediate precondition for the onset of
psychic illness, but also general conditions - above all "religious and political
exaltation". During the war of the Cevennes, such complexes appeared;27
another famous example was Joan of Arc in whom "patriotic enthusiasm ...
and ... a kind of magnetic state" were combined (PM § 406, Zu sa tz , p. 107).
The climate, and also the time of day or year could also have damaging effect,
and could find expression "in morbid states (including insanity) and at
periods when the self-conscious life suffers depression" (PM § 392, p. 37).
Romantic conceptions about a cosmic dependence of life are explicitly
rejected by Hegel: "The history of the world is not bound up with revolutions
in the solar system, any more than the destinies of individuals with the
position of the planets" (PM § 392, pp. 36-37).
Sickness and health, in their origins and their development, are not deter-
mined by the movement of the planets (PM § 392,Zusatz, p. 38); Hegel does
not support any sidereal concept of illness. Animals and plants are bound to
such a common life joined with nature; modem man, however, has freed
himself from these bonds. Psychic illnesses and those of the body according
HEGEL'S UNDERSTANDING OF ILLNESS 133
to Hegel, are linked concretely with each other and dependent on each other,
since in the dissociation of consciousness, the "corporeity which is as
necessary for the empirical existence of mind as it is for that of soul, is
divided between these two separated sides and accordingly is divided within
itself and therefore sick" (PM § 406,Zusatz, p.106).
The division of illnesses in three basic kinds finds its confirmation in
reality, according to Hegel; but this distinction is also justified (onto-)
logically. The philosophic systematization would be legitimized on the one
side by a dialectic of the transition from concept [Begriff] to phenomenon
and phenomenon to concept, which should be capable of being carried out
subsequently in empirical work; but on the other side this mediation of
notions and phenomena has its foundation in logic. From the principle of this
double perspective - empirical research and logic - comes the decisive
methodological difference between Hegel's speculative understanding of
illness and the Romantic conceptions. According to Hegel, the first kind of
illness - epidemics and contagious diseases - are to be traced back to "a
general determinateness lying in the non-organic nature as such" (PN § 371,
Zusatz, p. 430). The second kind is caused by "particular, external harmful
influences" (PN § 371, Zusatz, p. 432); in these illnesses above all, specific
parts of the body are affected. The third kind of illness, fmally, originates
"in the universal subject" (PN § 371, Zusatz, p. 432). In the three kinds of
illness, for Hegel, a transition from the universal to the individual, by way of
the particular, is carried out, a transition that is developed in the logic and
receives its justification there. However, at the same time Hegel's conviction
of the possibility of a logical foundation of reality is combined with insight
into the limits of such a foundation; Hegel considers a deduction of all forms
of illness to be impossible.
1be characteristic manifestation of disease is, therefore, that the identity of the entire
organic process displays itself as the successive course of the vital movement through
its distinct moments: sensibility, irritability, and reproduction, i.e. as fever, which,
however, as process of the totality in opposition to the isolated (vereinzelte) activity,
is just as much the effort towards, and the beginning of, cure (PN § 372, pp. 432-433).
Therapy
But instead of this magnetically induced sleep, a healthy sleep, too, can produce this
turning-point in an illness, i.e. the organism can then spontaneously gather itself
together into its substantiality (PN § 373, Zusatz, p. 440).
This humane treatment, no less benevolent than reasonable ... presupposes the patient's
rationality, and in that assumption has the sound basis for dealing with him on this side
- just as in the case of bodily disease the physician bases his treatment on the vitality
which as such still contains health (PM § 408, p. 124).29
IV
Ruprecht-Karl-University
Heidelberg
138 DIETRICH VON ENGELHARDT
NOTES
1 After completion of work on this manuscript there appeared W. Jacob's brief descrip·
tion 'Der Krankheitsbegriff in der Dialektik von Natur und Geist bei Hegel' in Hegel-
Studien, Beiheft 11 (1974), pp. 165-73; and also T. J. Bole: 'John Brown, Hegel and
Speculative Concepts in Medicine', Texas Reports on Biology and Medicine 32 (1974),
287-97. Previously to that only W. L. Leibbrand had presented Hegel's conception of
illness in quite detailed form (see below Notes 15, Leibbrand (1956),187-90,263-70).
In the comprehensive works on the history and systematics of the concept of illness,
Hegel has not been included: H. Ribbert, Die Lehren vom Wesen der Krankheiten in
ihren geschichtlichen Entwicklung (Bonn, Cohen, 1899); T. Meyer·Steineg, 'Der Gang der
Krankheitslehre in ihren wichtigsten Phasen',peutsche Medizinische Wochenschrift 50
(1924), 31H., 347f., 380f., 412; H. MUller, 'Uber den Krankheitsbegriff im Wandel der
Zeiten, mit besonderer BerUcksichtigung neuerer Anschauungen und Foigerungen',
Diss. Berlin 1939; A. Dietrich, 'Die Entwicklung des Krankheitsbegriffes', Hippokrates
12 (1941), 122·-26; E. Berghoff, Entwicklungsgeschichte des Krankheitsbegriffes, 2nd
ed. (Vienna, Maudrich), 1947 (Here alone a quotation from the Philosophy of the
Subjective Mind is to be found.); W. Riese, The Conception of Disease, Its History, Its
Versions and Its Nature (New York, Philosophical Library, 1953); L. J. Rather, 'Zur
Philo sophie des Begriffes Krankheit', Deutsche Medizinische Wochenschrift 83 (1958),
2012-18; also: 'Towards a Philosophical Study of the Idea of Disease', in The Historical
Development of Physiological Thought, ed. C. C. M. Brooks and P. F. Cranefield (New
York, Hafner, 1959), pp. 351-73; O. Temkin, 'The Scientific Approach to Disease;
Specific Entity and Individual Sickness', in Scientific Change, ed. A. C. Crombie,
(London, Heinemann, 1963), pp. 629-58; P. Diepgen, G. B. Gruber and H. Schadewaldt,
'Der Krankheitsbegriff, seine Geschichte und Problematik', Handbuch der Allgemeinen
Pathologie, (Berlin, Heidelberg, New York, Springer, 1969), vol. I, pp. 1·-50; K. E.
Rothschuh, Zwei Beitrdge zur Allgemeinen Krankheitslehre (Stuttgart, 1973).
2 H. A. Goden published a totally negative account in 1819 in his essay 'Uber Hegel's
Begriff vom Wesen der Krankheit und der Heilung' in Okens Isis, vol. 2 (1819), col.
1127-38; in 1829 K. H. Scheidler reviewed the 'GrundzUge der Hegelschen Philo sophie
in Beziehung auf die Medizin [The Basic Principles of the Hegelian Philosophy in
Relation to Medicine]" within the treatise 'Uber das Verhaltnis der Philo sophie
iiberhaupt and der Psychologie insbesondere zur Medicin', Minerva Medica, 1 (1829),
211-48; he regretted the widespread disinterest in philosophy among physicians;
this disinterest has brought about "that not even the system of Hegel, recently epoch·
making in the focal point of North German scientific culture, and already applied in
many ways to theology, jurisprudence, history in general, as well as to the history of
philosophy especially and to aesthetics, has not been considered or noted by them."
(p.245f.)
3 C. W. Hufeland, System der practischen Heilkunde (Frankfurt and Leibzig, 1800),
vol. 1, p. VIII.
4 Ibid., 1802, vol. 2, p. VIf.
5 A. F. Hecker, Kunst, die Krankheiten der Mensch en zu heilen (Erfurt, Henning, 1804;
4th ed., 1813), p. V.
6 Ibid., p. VI.
7 Ibid., p. 298.
DIETRICH VON ENGELHARDT 139
Ed. by J. Hoffmeister. 4 vols. (Siimtliche Werke. Neue kritische Ausgabe 29, 1959),
Vol. I, p. 314.
25 Ibid.
26 See D. Henrich, 'Hegels Theorie tiber den Zufall', Kantstudien 50 (1958/59), 131-
148; reprinted in Henrich, Hegel im Kontext (Frankfurt, Suhrkamp, 1971).
27 [The Cevennes, a mountain range forming the southern and eastern fringe of the
central plateau of southern France, was the locale of an early eighteenth century uprising
of Huguenot Protestant peasants - the Camisards - against the Church and the King.
The Camisards carried on organized military resistance for some years after 1702,
following nearly two decades of violent repression of their movement after the revoca-
tion of the Edict of Nantes (1685). Their religion was marked by visions, ecstasy,
miracles and other spiritual manifestations, as well as by prophetic and mystical
witnessing, and the leadership of young children. - Ed.]
28 Hegel expressly points to the observations of P. G. van Ghert who studied with him
and who formed a positive judgement of Hegel's philosophy; a 'Tagebuch einer
magnetischen Behandlung' (Diary of a magnetic treatment) (Holland 1814) by van Ghert
appeared in German translation in the Archiv fur den thierischen Magnetismus 2 (1817)
St. 1, pp. 3-24,55-188, St. 2, pp. 3-51; also a 'Sammlung merkwiirdiger Erscheinungen
des thierischen Magnetismus' (Collection of Remarkable Phenomena of Animal
Magnetism) (Holland 1815) appeared in translation in the same journal, vol. 3 (1818)
St. 3, pp. 1-97. Hegel calls van Ghert a "reliable physician who is at the same fertile in
ideas and educated in the most recent philosophy" (see PM § 406, Zusatz, p. 118).
29 In this relation Hegel recalls to mind Pinel and his commitment to a humane, moral
treatment of mental illness (see PM § 408, p. 124; Zusatz, p. 137). Pinel himself is
convinced that "the moral treatment of insanity is one of the most important parts of
observational medical science and one that has till now received little attention." His
residence in the Hospital Bicetre, his communication with the insane patients, his obser-
vation of the "regular order" of their behavior and well as of "changeable and often
bizarre scenes" led him to the insight, how frequently it would be possible in these
"cases of misled reason to restore its use either by means of mild remedies or an energetic
but wise and humane discipline". P. Pinel, Philosophisch-Medizinische Abhandlung
tiber Geistesverirrungen oder Manie. A. de Fr. (1801) tr. by M. Wagner (Vienna 1801),
p. 112. [This is a translation from the original French work: Traite medico-philosophique
sur l'aliimation mentale, au la manie ... (Paris, 1801). The English version is A Treatise
on Insanity, trans. by D. D. Davis (London, 1806; reprinted New York, Hafner, 1962).
- Ed.]
RUDIGER BUBNER
After the breakdown of the Hegelian encyclopedic system, the individual parts
suffered different fates. One set of questions seems to have survived better
than the others: Hegel's social philosophy has continued to incite contro-
versies in the social sciences, the humanities and philosophy from the nine-
teenth century to the present. German sociology with its so-called 'Positivism-
dispute' has been the most recent scene of debate.! This controversy between
Popper's philosophy of science and a Neo-Marxist defence of the dialectic
reiterates motives and prejudices with a long-standing tradition. However, a
true appraisal of Hegel's significance for the social sciences must renounce the
established chain of prejudices on both sides. In my opinion the fecundity of
Hegel's philosophy for fundamental questions of history and society first
becomes clear in the light of a full understanding of the famous thesis in the
Preface to the Philosophy of Right: "Philosophy is its own epoch compre-
hended in thought".2
The recourse to Hegel himself does not arise out of a purely historical
interest in textual exegesis. To the contrary, the attempt to reconstruct
Hegel's original dialectic independently of traditional controversies reveals its
Significance and fruitfulness for dealing with problems of our day. Conse-
quently, my paper traces the contemporary discussion. back into the nine-
teenth century and ultimately to its source in Hegel. The first section reviews
pertinent aspects of the recent Positivism-dispute (1). I then sketch out the
tradition of Hegel's influence on the methodology of the social sciences.
These historical remarks should serve to clarify some commonplace ideas
(II - The impatient reader may skip that section). An analysis of Hegel's view
of the inescapable tension between philosophy and its epoch completes the
argumentation (III). Finally, I draw some general conclusions on the role of
dialectics for social thought (IV).
midst of actual bondage and inequality. The Neo-Marxist position aims not
at true knowledge of existing society, but at knowledge of the falsity of
existing society viewed against the background of a projection of another
truer, though not yet actual, society.
In response to this position Popper's followers simply repeated the old
arguments against the dialectic, detecting again what they call an irrational
myth of totality which Popper had discarded as historicism. The positions
hardened to a kind of stalemate and at the level of this controversy no
satisfactory solution has been reached. This dispute, however, represents
only the most recent phase of the discussion of Hegel's significance for the
social sciences. It will be useful to recall this tradition of Hegel's influence
in order to remove some persistent misunderstandings and to evaluate the
enduring significance of Hegel's legacy.
II
Hegel's dictum implies more than Hegel himself recognized. The "task of
philosophy for its time" means overcoming isolated theory and practically
changing reality.
In contrast to such a critical application of the dialectic Dilthey's
hermeneutical theory of the humanities (Geisteswissenschaften) represents a
more conservative line of Hegelian influence on the social sciences.! 0 This
theory seeks to found the method of the humanities on Hegel's concept of
the objective mind (Geist), in the attempt to circumvent the hubris of an
absolute system of encyclopedic philosophy. Dilthey's central category, 'life'
(Leben), designates the inner connection of historical phenomena, and can
be considered a terminological translation of Hegel's concept of objective
mind. l l
According to Dilthey, the unitary stream of life not only inexhaustibly
manifests itself in innumerable concrete phenomena, but also enables us
to understand these phenomena. If the phenomena of the objective mind are
expressions of the all-embracing stream of life, then these phenomena are
immediately accessible to the understanding, for he who understands, parti-
cipates in that very stream of life. The object of the humanities is historical-
social reality, and if it is to be grasped it must be ontologically distinct from
nature. It must neither be artificially objectivized nor alienated through
analogy with the method of the natural sciences.i2 The appropriate method
of the humanities is the identification of the given object as a manifestation
of life. Thus an act of anamnesis occurs in which the subject recognizes
himself, as it were, in the object. The comprehensive stream of life to which
both the subject and the object essentially belong mediates between the two
sides of one whole. Dilthey calls this process 'Verstehen'P
As a natural consequence of his conception of the humanities, it was
impossible for Dilthey to accept Hegel's idea of an absolute mind, under
which art, religion and philosophy are subsumed. The realm of absolute mind
should be abolished as a metaphysical dogma. Dilthey complains of Hegel's
approach: "The plan of construction of the 'Geisteswissenschaften' is reversed
from the outset. Historical understanding is sacrificed to the metaphysical
schema".!4 In fact, Dilthey is guided by a thoroughly un-Hegelian epistemo-
logical intention which he conceives analogously to Kant as a "critique of
historical reason". His central concern is to clarify the possibilities for know-
ledge of historically limited, fmite reason; in his view this means rectifying
Kant's transcendental abstractions by focusing on the living individuals'
concrete acts of reason, thereby at the same time avoiding the speculative
extravagance of Hegel's absolute system.
HEGEL'S SIGNIFICANCE FOR SOCIAL SCIENCE 147
selects out of the abundance of details the specific individual fact which is
related to a value and therefore is of general significance in the historical-
social realm. As is well known, Rickert's notion of value-reference was
adopted by Weber as a useful tool for sociological understanding. This aspect
of the social sciences continues to remain controversial. 21
Rickert's treatment of historical-social reality as the object of an indivi-
dualizing and value-referring science does not suggest Hegel's speculative
idealism as much as Dilthey's. He spoke of Kulturwissenschaften rather than
Geisteswissenschaften. However, he did admit they and their subject-matter
essentially rested on Hegel's provocative and ambiguous principle stated in
the introduction to the Philosophy of Right that what is rational is real and
what is real is rational. 22
There are yet two further examples of Hegel's influence on the social
sciences which should be considered: the work of Hans Freyer and Karl
Mannheim. Freyer could easily appeal to Hegel when he charged that the
sociology of his day, which was methodologically oriented towards the
Kulturwissenschaften, was too removed from life. He maintained that a
sociology which is primarily concerned with methodological questions tends
to forget its actual duty vis-a-vis history. He reminded the sociologists of the
legacy of Hegel's philosophy and Marx's socio-economics. Sociology should
deal with the reality of changing society and not with the constructs of
Kulturwissenschaften.
Sociology must therefore consciously recognize its ties to its time and
seek to maintain this connection. Only after recognizing the essential
dependence of theory on its time can sociology become aware of its genuine
object. Freyer's formulation of the task confo:-ms completely to the Hegelian
dictum that the epoch must be comprehended in thought. 23 "A sociology is
the scientific self-understanding of a given society. In the nature of its
problems and in the inner form of its thought, a sociology is inescapably
determined by its time .,,24
This program of sociological realism differs from Karl Mannheim's
sociology of knowledge, although it too has roots in Hegelian thOUght.
Mannheim begins as well by postulating the crucial bondage of theory to its
time. But instead of deducing the present duties of sociology from this
postulate, he formulates a thesis which, he believes, rests securely on the
methodological basis of the Kulturwissenschaften. He raises the historical
limitation of all manifestations of mind to the universal principle that all
thought is bound to its time and place. The research of the sociology of
knowledge takes individual, historical phenomena which Hegel described as
HEGEL'S SIGNIFICANCE FOR SOCIAL SCIENCE 149
III
One may ask why such value is placed on the relationship of philosophy to
its age, since, after all, emphasis on the historical epoch seems extrinsic.
However, the problem is embedded within the notion of philosophy itself.
One speaks of philosophy and means something defmite and unitary. But in
reality there are only philosophies, differing systems, alternating tendencies.
Philosophy as such is not a visible entity; one sees only attempts to realize the
essence of philosophy, attempts which have followed upon each other
throughout history.
So considered, the central problem of philosophy's self-understanding
becomes how to grasp the unity of the intended idea of philosophy in con-
junction with the multiplicity of its historical manifestations. Philosophy
cannot begin at all before it has solved the paradox of the single idea and its
many realizations. The paradox is that of philosophy itself and does not
reside somewhere outside of philosophy. He who begins to philosophize and
wants to be clear about what he is doing encounters the difficulty that that
which he intends exists only in multifarious historical forms even though he
does not mean these various forms when he thinks of philosophy. What then
does he mean?
The question cannot be referred to the propaedeutic preliminaries of
philosophy. It is impossible to decide the question before beginning to
philosophize, in order thus to be able to proceed undisturbed with
philosophy itself; for, in order to be able to say what precedes philosophy, it
is necessary to know first what philosophy itself is. Otherwise there is no
criteria to draw the desired boundary. But what philosophy itself is - that
was exactly the question at issue. It is obvious that one cannot begin to
philosophize without knowing what philosophy itself is and that one can
only arrive at a defmition of philosophy through the history of philosophy.
Hence, the task of philosophy is primarily to come to terms with its
own history. The elucidation of that history represents the first step in
philosophizing and, at the same time, philosophy thereby provides its own
secure foundation.
Within the fully developed Hegelian system, the Phenomenology of Mind
takes up this task of a philosophical clarification of the historical constella-
tions of thOUght. As the first part of that system the Phenomenology serves
as a preparatory stage 34 for everything that follows. Today we no longer
believe in the philosophy as emphatically as did Hegel. Nevertheless, the unity
of philosophical thinking still represents a philosophical problem of un-
deniable and fundamental import. One tends to ignore the search for this
unity in favour of an unarticulated aggregate of independent disciplines and
152 RUDIGER BUBNER
highly sophisticated special techniques. And yet, the question remains: What
holds this aggregate together?
Of course, this question can be avoided if one attempts -like the positivist
philosophers - to equate a particular theoretical discipline (i.e. the logic of
scientific research) with philosophy per se. Those who believed in the logic of
scientific research denied the name of philosophy to anything not corres-
ponding to their own tradition. However, this kind of dogmatism has never
been able to survive for the simple reason that its self-assuredness is dependent
upon the denial of its factual relativity in the historical context of a plurality
of existing philosophical orientations. In the long run, the absolutist claim of
a philosophical dogmatism necessarily becomes historically relativized. Its
intentional blindness to its historical position is bound to give way in the
course of philosophical debate. The recent history of the philosophy of
science from the orthodoxy of the Vienna Circle to the pragmatism of the
community of researchers and finally to the quasi-hermeneutic historicism of
paradigm-change it fa Kuhn offers an instructive example of the significance
of this process.
Philosophy cannot abstract from its own historicity. TIlis does not mean,
however, that philosophy is nothing more than an intellectual expression of
given circumstances that change from one epoch to the next. Rather, the
awareness of historical conditions is the only way to escape the dominating
influence of those conditions. Philosophy must continuously insist on its
theoretical autonomy, but such an autonomy cannot be secured by assum-
ing a position high above the relativity of the hic et nunc. A philosophy
that is not jolted out of such a dogmatic slumber is bound to fall prey to the
unexpressed presuppositions of what the actual tendencies in the social and
intellectual world prescribe. It will unconsciously bear the mark of what goes
without saying in the existing paradigm of theoretical activities. Only by
reflecting upon these historical conditions can philosophy defend its legiti-
rna te claim to truth, a claim which reaches beyond historical relativity.
Paradoxically, then, this transhistorical claim is better supported by taking
the undeniable historicity into account than by neglecting it. Cynical fatalism
that believes in nothing but historical change is not the lesson to be derived
from Hegel's perspective on philosophy through history. What can be learned
is that the claim to truth is no inherited privilege, but can only be raised in
a productive critical exchange with those variable conditions that are given in
a broader historical context and that would seem to hinder autonomous
philosophizing. Thus, the main presupposition of the autonomy of philosophy
is the recognition of its limitations.
HEGEL'S SIGNIFICANCE FOR SOCIAL SCIENCE 153
been a mere vogue. Conversely, historical factors that are prima facie held to
be of less importance may, in the course of philosophical reflection, be found
to have a primary significance. The immediate view is not necessarily the
most penetrating one.
The physiognomy of an epoch is in no sense evident and easy to grasp.
Mere involvement in a historical situation is not a sufficient basis for a com-
prehension of that situation. The conceptual articulation of what is truly
substantial in a manifold of historical phenomena presupposes more than
contemporaneous participation in the general consciousness of an epoch.
What is required is the view from a distance, whereby the observer is not
ahistorically removed from the situation but is also not involved in its details.
Only from such a standpoint is one able to uncover what is essential under
that which is commonly held to be real. Only from such a standpoint is it
possible to comprehend the essential traits, the long-range tendencies, in
short, the actual make-up of a given society. Hegel entrusts this task of com-
prehension to philosophy. The question still remains open: Why philosophy?
Since philosophy is interested in its own paradoxical autonomy within the
framework of an historical epoch, it is not interested in that epoch as such.
Although its historical conditions are fetters which philosophy cannot cast
off, they are only seen as contingencies that must be relativized. Of course
the reduction of those factors to the status of mere contingency cannot
dispose of history. It does, however, put an end to the exaggerated role
ascribed to seemingly essential factors that temporarily eclipse other
characteristics before they, too, yield to change. In other words, change,
looked at as mere contingency, no longer has the power to influence the
comprehension of an epoch, since it no longer obscures the fundamental
structures that are of true historical relevance behind the veil of superficial
phenomena.
The result of disinterest in the contingency of the moment over against
the genuine philosophical interest in reason is that those factors in any given
historical situation which resist the activity of rational elucidation prove to be
the fundamental structures of an epoch. What philosophy is unable to
relativize to any greater degree, it must recognize in the name of reason itself.
This is precisely the meaning of Hegel's provocative motto of the actuality of
the rational and the rationality of the actual. 35
IV
I have not undertaken a rigorous philological exegesis of all the texts of Hegel
HEGEL'S SIGNIFICANCE FOR SOCIAL SCIENCE 155
that are relevant to our question. This could easily be carried out and would
provide a coherent picture of the genesis of Hegel's idea of the task of philo-
sophy vis a vis its epoch. 36 Rather, through a reconstruction of the argument
underlying Hegel's claim for philosophy, I have attempted to demonstrate its
plausibility.
We have finally arrived at the point where we can readdress the main
question at issue: What is Hegel's significance for the social sciences? I am
well aware of the difficulties of making Hegel's mode of philosophical
thinking acceptable. A first step in this direction would be to cast doubt upon
the self-assured objectivity of the methods of the social sciences. I have, with
intentional indefmiteness, characterized the prevailing opinions in everyday
consciousness, or the immediate picture of an epoch, as a reality that
philosophy can and has to take into account. Science on the other hand, far
from escaping this reality, is intricately bound to it. Science exerts a strong
influence upon the formation of our everyday opinions, just as common
opinion has an indirect effect upon the general orientation of scientific
research. The process of 'scientification' of common, or public opinion
becomes ever more pervasive, while, reciprocally, the obligation of science to
be 'socially relevant' is increasingly emphasized. It would be simple-minded to
believe that scientific research proceeds according to independent standards
of rationality and methods of self·evident legitimacy.
Especially the social sciences have gained the authority of being a per-
manent and definite source of knowledge concerning all those questions
everybody is interested in. No wonder, therefore, that sociologists, political
scientists, economists, psychologists, psychoanalysts constantly throw them-
selves upon the market of public opinion. Privileged by their reputation as
scientists, they are busy contributing to the picture every epoch constructs
of itself. This symbiosis of the social sciences and common opinion is quite
natural and should by no means be denounced in the name of some false
purism. Instead one must turn, so to speak, to a higher court of appeal. Since
the days of the sophists, philosophy has had to deal with this very problem.
Philosophy has thereby learnt that it does not, in supposed contrast to the
social sciences, enjoy a kind of splendid isolation. That was the impulse
behind my effort to destroy the fiction of a philosophia perennis that
purports to hover above the sphere of common life.
What in fact distinguishes philosophy from the social sciences although
both are entangled in the self-understanding of an epoch is that the philo-
sophical interest of reason is not primarily oriented towards the epoch and
its immediately evident features. Philosophy does not so much aim at a
156 RUDIGER BUBNER
Titbingen University
NOTES
3S PR, Preface.
36 Cf. J. Ritter, Hegel und die franzosische Revolution (Frankfurt, Suhrkamp, 1965);
J. Habermas, 'Nachwort' to: Hegel, Politische Schriften (Frankfurt, Suhrkamp, 1966);
S. Avineri, Hegel's Theory of the Modern State (London, Cambridge University Press,
1972), Chap. VI.
MURRAY GREENE
approach, says Hegel, had not yet "equipped itself" even to grasp truly its
"own deed." In proceeding straightway to criticize and test, it employed
canons that were uncritical and untested - such as its standard of "clear and
distinct," which, says Hegel, is a "psychological" (in the unphilosophic sense)
rather than a "logical" criterion. 3 The fact that one's opinions come from
one's self does not mean that truth has taken the place of error. lacking the
proper method of showing how its certainty becomes truth, Descartes' pro-
ceeding through the inner certainty of the subjective consciousness turns out
to be but a form of external reflection.
The post-Cartesian methods of synthesis and analysis, or composition and
resolution, Hegel maintains, are likewise modes of external reflection.
Analysis dissolves the concretum of experience into lifeless abstractions.
Synthesis presents the universal in defmitions that have no "constraining
necessity" for the content, and is a "purely subjective cognition which is
external to the object" (L [W, 1892], p. 366). The method of demonstration
taken from mathematics is unsuitable to philosophy in general and particularly
inappropriate to a science of mind (Phen [M] , p. 24ff). Spinoza's demonstra-
tion more geometrico, according to Hegel, is the "fundamental defect in the
whole position" (HP 3, p. 283), and Spinoza tells us that substance is the unity
of thought and extension "without demonstrating how he gets to this distinc-
tion, or how he traces it back to the unity of substance" (L [W, 1892],
p. 275). Leibniz was perhaps the only pre-Kantian thinker who put forward
a claim which, as we shall see, is also central to Hegel's own notion of subjec-
tive spirit: namely, that self-consciousness arises as an internal development
of the preconscious subjectivity. But here too, says Hegel, the philosopher
demonstrated no immanent necessity. While the Leibnizian monad evolves its
representations "out of itself," says Hegel, "they arise in the monad like
bubbles; they are indifferent and immediate over against one another and the
same in relation to the monad itself' (SL [M], p. 396). In the so-called
"method of construction" - the method that "construes its notions" - there
is, Hegel grants, a "dim consciousness of the Idea, of the unity of the Notion
and objectivity" insofar as, in demonstration, the subjectivity "shows itself
a modifying and determining principle" (L [W, 1892], p. 371). But in con-
struction the demonstration is "ruled by an external end." The proof is not
truly a "genesis of the relationship that constitutes the content of the
theorem," and therefore it too is "an external reflection" which proceeds
"from without inwards," "infers from external circumstances the inner
constitution of the relationship" (SL [M], p. 812).
While these Hegelian criticisms of external reflection apply to philosophic
164 MURRAY GREENE
of spirit, whose essence as ideality is such that it does not let itself be thus
'found,.4 In its analysis of the 'given', empiricism means to introduce nothing
but its own act of separating. But its breakdown of the concrete object of
experience only leaves it with abstract universal attributes, and thus brings in
again a metaphysic of the "thing and its properties" (See Phen [M] p.77ff).
Yet empiricism remains all the while oblivious to its own metaphysical pre-
suppositions and employs its thought categories in an "utterly thoughtless
and uncritical" fashion. In separating the given into "simple ideas" and the
mind into 'faculties' and 'forces,' empiricism renders the living totality an
aggregate of "parts" and the mind a "skeleton-like mechanical collection"
(PM, p. 189).
In reconstructing the concretum of experience and arriving at the higher
connections of mind, empiricism proceeds essentially by showing a 'natural
evolution' of what happens in "pictorial and phenomenal thinking" (SL [M],
p. 588). But philosophy, says Hegel, is not meant to be a 'narration' of what
happens but a cognition of 'what is true' in happenings. This sort of genetic
method, whether showing an origin of ideas or of faculties, Hegel argues,
carries a built-in limitation of knowledge to sensuous experience. For when
there is a question of history rather than truth, then the "substrate of feelings
and intuitions" from which understanding abstracts its universals need not be
seen as sublated in conceptual thinking but "remains for representation in the
same complete reality with which it first presented itself". 5 In the so-called
laws of association of ideas as employed by empiricism, some principle is
assumed, such as a "force of attraction" of like images. But such 'attraction,'
Hegel points out, would just as well have to be a 'repulsion,' a "negative
power of rubbing off the dissimilar elements against each other" (PM, p. 208).
Hegel also rejects any procedure through the 'facts of consciousness',
whether employed by empiricism or some form of intuitionism, as in Jacobi
or Fichte. If the criteria of truth are to be taken in "the immediacy, or self-
evident way, in which a fact or body of truths is presented in consciousness,"
says Hegel, then "every alleged truth has no other basis than the subjective
certitude and the assertion that we discover a certain fact in our conscious-
ness." What I find in my consciousness, I can exaggerate into a "fact of the
consciousness of all" and even pass off "for the very nature of consciousness"
(L [W, 1892] , p. 134). If indeed we are to examine the nature of conscious-
ness, says Hegel, then we must be able to strip it of its particular and
accidental elements and "by the toilsome operation of reflection" disclose
"the universal in its entirety and purity."
If we are not then, like the old metaphysic of the soul, to speak of the
166 MURRAY GREENE
II
is to investigate itself, says Hegel, the action of the forms of thought must be
their own criticism. The forms of thought must "examine themselves," and
the critical work of thought, "instead of being brought to bear upon the
categories from without," must remain "immanent in their own action."
Hegel's flrst application of this method of immanence - or, as he terms it, the
"speculative" or "absolute" method - was in the Phenomenology of Spirit
of 1807.
The Phenomenology of 1807 was not meant by Hegel - the mature Hegel
at least (see below, p. 175) - to constitute an absolute beginning of
philosophy or indeed of his own system as such. It is not a beginning without
important presuppositions. In commencing with the 'natural consciousness,'
for example, the notion of consciousness is in a sense presupposed. We might
also say the commencement is historical, inasmuch as the very term 'natural'
or 'empirical' consciousness is hardly conceivable prior to the empirical
thinkers and Kant's own distinction of the empirical and the pure conscious-
ness. Kant wanted to go behind the empirical consciousness to its a priori
forms, but his presentation of the forms of the a priori, according to Hegel,
was "solely based upon psychological and historical grounds" (L, [W, 1892],
p. 84). Hegel in the Phenomenology purports at once to take the empirical
consciousness on its own terms and allow it to unfold its pure forms in the
concrete context of its movement of 'experience.' In this way the forms of
thought are seen to "test and examine themselves." Each form of thought, as
a shape of experience, succeeds its predecessor as its "determinate negation,"
while the philosophic observer need only "look on" (Phen [M], p. 54). In
fact the philosopher does more than look on. 7 He assembles and organizes
the shapes of consciousness so as to bring out their necessary movement from
the natural to the philosophic consciousness (Phen [M], p. 55; p. 480). But
insofar as the philosopher thereby demonstrates the necessity of his own
emergence in the movement of consciousness, he may be said to overcome
the standpoint of external reflection.
Through the pathway of experience demonstrated'in the Phenomenology
of 1807, consciousness has purportedly attained to the standpoint of pure
science. In this sense the Phenomenology is an introduction to the system of
philosophic sciences and in the flrst instance to the science of logic. What is
most important for our purposes is to note Hegel's stress on the fact that the
Phenomenology, by traversing the shapes of experience of consciousness, has
made possible that 'liberation' from consciousness which is the precondition
of all philosophic science. 8 The standpoint of consciousness as such, we can
now say, is a standpoint of external reflection. For reasons both historical
168 MURRAY GREENE
sums up the 'false tack' taken by post-Cartesian philosophy even while its
notion of the subjective consciousness marked the great advance of modern
thought.
While, according to Kant, the original identity of self-consciousness is the
highest principle of knowledge, the pure ego or self as it is 'in itself' must
remain for us a 'transcendental x.' All our certain knowledge is a knowledge
of "objects" and requires the possibility of a sensible intuition. Since I can
have no such intuition of myself as pure ego, I can have no knowledge of the
"identity of the subject" whereby it can be "given as object" (CPR, B 408).10
Further, "I cannot know as an object," says Kant, "that which I must pre-
suppose in order to know any object" (CPR, A 402). The pure ego, which
is ever the subject in judgment, cannot make its own self the object of its
judgment without an awkward circularity. For these and other reasons, Kant
says, "the hope of succeeding by a priori methods" in a science of the soul
must be "abandoned" and psychology "banished from the domain of meta-
physics" (CPR, A 849-B 877). Kant relegates psychology to a position within
anthropology, where it can play a role as "the pendant to the empirical
doctrine of nature" (CPR, A 849-B 877). Such a psychology would deal, for
example, with the empirical laws of association in the reproductive imagina-
tion (CPR, B 152). In his own writings and lectures on anthropology, educa-
tion, and applied ethics, Kant offers such empirical psychological material.
But by the critical philosophy's own canons, these treatments do not rank
as theoretical science in the sense of apodictically certain knowledge, and do
not belong to the science of the a priori principles of knowledge. 11
According to Hegel, the Kantian notion of a 'transcendental x' is an
external reflection that derives from a philosophizing from the standpoint of
consciousness as an absolute. The Kantian philosophy, in Hegel's view, is a
phenomenology, since it takes spirit only in its aspect as consciousness (PM,
p. 156). For this reason it does not even do justice to the truth of conscious-
ness. That Kant's restriction of knowledge to sense experience is untenable,
Hegel claims to have demonstrated in the first three chapters of the
Phenomenology of 1807. We shall pass this discussion by in order to focus
on Hegel's critique of the supposed circularity of a knowledge of the
'transcendental x.'
It is ridiculous, says Hegel, to stigmatize as circular - as though it implied
a fallacy - "this nature of self.consciousness, namely, that the 'I' thinks
itself, that the'!' cannot be thought without its being the'!, that thinks"
(SL [M], p. 777). It is not as though, says Hegel, we "must already make
use" of the ego whenever we want to judge about it. The ego does not 'make
HEGEL'S CONCEPTION OF PSYCHOLOGY 171
use' of something like an instrument - even its own self - in judging. Ego is
the subject-object relation (PM, p. 15lff), is judgment. And its actively
performed judgments in the theoretical, practical, and other realms are
precisely what render it concrete and knowable. For its every judgment of
and relation to an other is at the same time a self-relation. It is in just this
self-relation in all relating to other, says Hegel, that ego reveals itself as
Notion, as "the absolute relation-to-self that, as a separating judgment
(Urteil) , makes itself its own object and is solely this process whereby it
makes itself a circle" (SL [M], p. 77). In this statement, I believe, we have
the key to Hegel's organization of the sciences of subjective spirit and the
possibility of a philosophical psychology.
According to Aristotle, the soul attains truth in affirming or denying a
predicate of a subject, that is to say, in judgment. But in Aristotle the
problem of judgment can hardly be said to be viewed in terms of subjectivity
and objectivity in the modern sense. One may measure the Kantian revolution
in philosophy by Kant's defmition of 'objective judgment.' Such a judgment,
Kant says, "is nothing but the manner in which given modes of knowledge are
brought to the objective unity of apperception. This is what is intended by
the copula (Verhiiltniswortchen) 'is'" (CPR, B 142). Hereby Kant makes
'objectivity' a function of the subjective consciousness: apperception. This, as
we shall see more specifically later, may also be said to be the case for Hegel.
In Hegel, however, it has a different sense. In the first place, according to
Hegel, the copula 'is' is not to be understood only as a function of the subjec-
tive consciousness as apperception. "The copula 'is' springs from the nature
of the Notion, to be self-identical even in parting with its own" (in seiner
Entaiisserung) (L [W, 1892], p. 298). It is not only consciousness but 'the
Notion' that distinguishes itself into subject and predicate; and it is the forms
of this distinguishing that provide the logical categories. Hegel makes use of
the German word Urteil. Ordinarily in judgment, says Hegel, we view subject
and predicate as independent extremes which we somehow connect by the
copula 'is.' However, "the etymological meaning of the judgment in German
goes deeper, as it were declaring the unity of the Notion to be primary,
and its distinction to be the original partition." And that, says Hegel, "is
what the judgment really is" (L [W, 1892] ,p. 297).
But while the science of logic demonstrates the pure forms of the
Scheidung in sich of the Notion, it is up to the concrete sciences of subjective
spirit to show that ego is this very Urteil. In the doctrine of subjective spirit,
Hegel demonstrates consciousness itself to be the 'original partition' whereby
subjectivity comes to hold itself 'in relation' to its content as a self-subsistent
172 MURRAY GREENE
III
Anthropology, the first of the three sciences of subjective spirit, deals with
the natural foundation of man, spirit as first arising out of its 'immersion'
in physical nature. A main theme of the anthropology is the soul-body
relationship. The demonstration in the anthropology shows how the soul
(Seele) as preconscious subjectivity comes to power in its corporeality
(Leiblichkeit). Having permeated the latter and rendered it the outer 'sign'
(Zeichen) of the soul's own spiritual inwardness, the psychical subjectivity
'lets go' (entlassen) the pre-objective content of sensation and feeling to
become an objective outer world. This development, according to Hegel, is
the genesis at once of the ego of consciousness and of its content as an
independent externality to which the ego relates itself in its knowing.
In discussing the question of how a soul-body unity is possible, Hegel says
the problem remains unanswerable for any standpoint on which the object as
such already has the shape of a prefound existent standing opposite it (PM,
p. 30). As long as the subjective consciousness is related to its outer object -
or the immaterial to the material - as one particular to another, says Hegel,
the mind-body relation must remain a mystery. But the posing of the
question of a 'community' of two such particulars is an external reflection.
In the Philosophy of Nature, Hegel has purportedly shown how natural
materiality sublates itself to spirit. In the sentient animal soul, which feels
itself a one at every point in its corporeality, and in the sublation of the
singular animal life in the abiding genus, says Hegel, nature has overpassed
itself as self-externality and the realm of the partes extra partes. 12 But in this
spatial and temporal asunderness consists the very essence of materiality in
HEGEL'S CONCEPTION OF PSYCHOLOGY 173
its notion. Spirit, as individual natural soul, has emerged as the 'result' of
nature and at the same time as nature's own 'truth' and 'absolute prius'
(PM, p.8).
The individual soul in its identity with its corporeality, according to Hegel,
is the 'microcosm' in which the macrocosm of universal nature is
'concentrated' and sublated in its asunderness (PM, p. 36). My body, says
Hegel, is the "mean" (Mitte) whereby I "come together with external nature
in general.,,13 This is exhibited in Hegel's treatment of sentience
(Empjindung). Hegel seeks to show that the five senses comprise a system of
specified 'bodiness' (Korperlichkeit) which contains the essential moments
of external body or materiality in its notion. 14 Thus sight reveals materiality
in its moment of "pure ideality," light; touch, the moment of "solid reality."
The transient content of the 'sentient soul' attains a higher form in the
'feeling soul' (fiihlende Seele), whose manifold as a feeling-life comes to it in
the form of dream and presentiment. Hegel here deals with a realm of the
psyche that later came to be explored by depth psychology. The psychical
subjectivity is termed by Hegel a self-enclosed 'monad,' since its content does
not yet come to it in the form of an objectively structured outer world. The
'immediate' knowing of this inner subjectivity is evidenced in forms of trance-
like 'gazing-knowing' (schauendes Wissen) of an inner content not yet
mediated by such objective categories as space and time, cause and effect.
The phenomena of 'animal magnetism' are seen as displaying a psychical
union (Seeleneinheit) of two subjectivities where the passive feeling selfhood
of the patient is permeated by the dominating subjectivity of the hypnotist,
as in a kind of foetus-mother relationship. Sicknesses of insanity are discussed
by Hegel as forms of 'self-feeling' (Selbstgefiihl) where a particular content of
passion has taken on the spurious objectivity of a fixed idea, thus forming a
self-sunderance and 'blocking' (Hemmung) of the psychical subjectivity in its
fluid universality. In 'habit', which is the concluding moment of the feeling
soul, the subjectivity sublates the particular corporeal determination and
comes back to itself in its fluid universality. Here by the soul wins release
from its immediate corporeal affections and frees itself for occupation with
other things. In reducing the corporeality to an 'instrument' of its 'subjective
purpose', the soul has raised itself to 'subjective substance' and developed
itself as the 'foundation' of consciousness.
The soul 'actualizes' itself as ideality of the body by so 'informing'
(einbilden) it with its subjective inwardness that the body is but the soul's
own outer 'sign'. In stance and attitude, in gesture, demeanor, and mobile
play of features, the body has become the soul's own 'work of art.' The
174 MURRAY GREENE
body stands not for itself but is the externality wherein the spiritual inner
"feels itself and makes itself felt," the Dasein of the inner subjectivity. Having
attained to its being·for·self as actual soul, the subjectivity 'separates' itself
from its immediate being, sets itself opposite (gegenuberstellen) its own being
as corporeality while sublating it and determining it to its own. In its very
externality the soul is hereby 'inwardized' (erinnert) within self and infinite
self·relation. This being·for·self of the free universality, says Hegel, is the
'awakening' of the soul to ego: to the "abstract universality insofar as it is for
the abstract universality" (PM, p. 151). Subjectivity is no longer immersed
(versenkt) in the immediacy of 'feeling' but is now 'thinking' and subject
'for itself.' More particularly, says Hegel, it is subject of the Urteil in which
ego excludes its formerly monadic content as an 'object.' To this the subject
now relates itself in such a way that in it, it is directly "reflected within
itself," is consciousness (PM, p. 151).
Thus where modern philosophy from Descartes to Kant began on the level
of consciousness, Hegel demonstrates consciousness as a 'result.' This means
that a deeper principle has been exhibited than that of consciousness and its
subject·object relation. Indeed it is a principle that first makes that relation
possible. In the anthropology the body was 'object,' the soul 'subject'; the
body was the 'in itself,' the soul the 'for itself; the body was substantiality,
the soul subjectivity. In its rendering the body an 'outer' of its own spiritual
'inner,' the subject has posited itself opposite itself and in this its very
opposite is reflected back into itself. It is this that constitutes the subject an
'ego' and its content 'objective.' Thus we can say that for Hegel as for Fichte,
ego is the act of positing itself. But to exhibit this, Fichte called upon an
'intellectual intuition' and needed the Anstoss from without, while Hegel
demonstrates it in the form of an immanent development of the soul's
relation to its corporeality as its natural substantiality. The demonstration of
the emergence of consciousness as an Ur·teil (see above, p. 171), in which each
side is implicitly reflected into itself in its relation to its opposite, provides
the notion of consciousness:
Ego, as this absolute negativity, is implicitly the identity in the otherness: the ego is
itself that other and stretches over the object (as if that object were implicitly cancelled)
~ it is one side of the relationship and the whole relationship ~ the light, which mani·
fests itself and something else too (PM, p. 153).
Intuition, as we shall note shortly, is reserved for psychology, and the reason
why this is so will be an important indication of the nature of organization of
the sciences of subjective spirit.
After these few remarks on the nature of the demonstration in the pheno-
menology as the second science of subjective spirit, we are finally in a position
to view in broad outline Hegel's conception of a philosophical psychology.
IV
Hegel's treatment, is not one 'part' or 'faculty' of the mind, not even 'one
stem' of knowledge that has to be united synthetically with another 'stem.'
For this reason, Hegel experiences no difficulty in linking his meaning of
intuition with the sense we give the word when we speak, for example, of the
deep intuition of a Goethe. Intuition, for Hegel, is conceptual thinking in
germ; intuition is mind, is spirit in its living totality, though as yet in un-
developed or deficient form.
Spirit as intelligence, however, cannot remain immersed in this form of its
immediacy. In the various stages of representation, intelligence inwardizes
the externality of intuition and imagination in memory, and finally over-
comes its last vestige of se1f-externality in conceptual thinking. We can hardly
go beyond a bald summary of Hegel's presentation of theoretical spirit in the
psychology. A few points of special interest must suffice.
As initially 'recollective' of intuition, says Hegel, intelligence posits the
intuited content in its own inwardness, "in its own space and time." Thus
taken up into the universality of the ego, the content becomes an image,
abstracted from the fullness of the original intuition and isolated from the
directly experienced place, time, and context of the intuition. The image thus
seems to be but a residue and a loss from the determinate singularity of the
intuition. But it is not the case for Hegel, as for Hume, that the image is but
a faded copy of the impression. For Hegel, no manifestation of spirit in its
activity can be explained merely in terms of loss. In Hegel the intuition is
eclipsed as Singularity by the actively inwardizing intelligence in transposing
the content into its own universal ideal medium. This greatly extends the
range of the representing, as against the intuiting intelligence, since I no
longer require the immediate presence of the object. Further, in abstracting
the intuition from its original setting, says Hegel, representation divests it of
what are frequently but the contingent connections of time and space.
Of itself the image is transient, and intelligence as inner attention is its
sole 'where and when.' But intelligence is not merely this Dasein as but a
present awareness of this determinate content; and the image, while
inwardized in the intelligence and thus no longer 'existent', has not vanished
into nothingness. The image is "unconsciously retained," says Hegel in the
"night-like pit" (niichtlicher Schacht) of the intelligence. Here are preserved
a "world of infinitely many images and representations without their being in
consciousness." This preservation of the no longer existent can only be
understood, says Hegel, if spirit is grasped in its essence as "ideality" - which
means "negation of the real, but a negation in which the real is aufbewahrt,
retained virtualiter, although it does not exist" (PM, p. 92). The representing
182 MURRAY GREENE
intelligence is the power which, of itself, can bring forth the image to
existence from its 'simple night.' In so doing, the intelligence has 'subsumed'
the singular intuition under the image as 'the universal in point of form.'
Recollection (Erinnenmg) is thus a merging in the form of a 'recognizing.'
In being brought forth from the 'simple night' of the intelligence, the image
acquires a Dasein and the intuition simultaneously a generality. Through such
repeated 'recognitions,' the image obtains the 'liveliness' and 'presentness'
of a Vorstellung, inasmuch as I can 'set it before' myself without the aid of
intuition.
While in imagination I am no longer restricted to the sensuously present,
nevertheless as long as my thinking continues to be in images, according to
Hegel, I am not yet free. To the extent that my imagining is a kind of roving,
I n~main subject to contingencies external to my essential being as intelligence.
But in imagination itself, says Hegel, intelligence proceeds to sublate this
unfreedom and contingency, and the moments of imagination display spirit's
advance toward the freedom of conceptual thinking. This advance is marked
by the movement from (1) the more or less automatic evocation of images by
the 'reproductive' imagination, to (2) the relating of images to one another
through general representations by the 'associative' imagination, and finally
to (3) the positing of general representations by the 'creative' imagination or
Phantasie in the sensuous Dasein of symbols and signs making up the store-
house of memory.
While Kant poses the problem of knowledge as the "subsumption of an
object under a concept," or the "subsumption of intuitions under pure
concepts" (CPR, B 177-A 138), Hegel takes such terms as 'subsumption' and
'synthesis' as indicating an external conjoining (Verkniipfung)19 that plays a
role on the level of representation but is out of place in the notion of pure
conceptual thinking. Here, according to Hegel, the determinations are not
united in 'syntheses' but "produced by the inherent movement of the
moments tending back into this unity" (SL [M], p. 75). But such conceptual
thinking, Hegel endeavors to show, only first arises in an overcoming of the
synthetic connectings of the representing intelligence.
In the reproductive imagination the images are brought forth from the
ego's own interiority, thus providing a universal representation for the asso-
ciative connecting of images. The activity of the associative imagination, says
Hegel, is not to be explained in terms of some "force of attraction" (see above,
p. 165), but as the intelligence's own power of subsuming and synthesizing
its content in its very act of "setting it before" itself in its universality.
Association, says Hegel, is a subsumption of singular representations under a
HEGEL'S CONCEPTION OF PSYCHOLOGY 183
god, the Phantasie has in effect dissolved the intuition in its sensuous con-
creteness and taken one essential attribute which is thus raised to an abstract
universal: Jupiter as strength. But in such pure signs as the cocarde, flag,
gravestone, says Hegel, the intelligence has so infused the intuition with its
own inner purport that the intuition serves as but the incidental occasion for
the intelligence's own self-reminder.
In thus taking the intuition out of its immediate spatio-temporal context
and positing the image in intelligence's own space and time, the signmaking
Phantasie, says Hegel, annuls (tilgen) the immediacy of the intuition and
infuses it with its own soul and meaning, within intelligence's own ideal
space and time. In this way, says Hegel, intelligence's sign-creating activity
becomes the 'productive memory.' In the annulling of the immediacy of its
being, the original intuition now only 'is' as an Aufgehobensein. This subla-
tion of the intuition provides Hegel's deduction of language.
Since the negative power that annuls the intuition in its immediacy is the
intelligence itself - which is responsible for intuition's forms of space and
time in the nrst place - the more determinate shape of the intuition-become-
sign is that of a "being-there in time" which is just as well the "vanishing of
the being-there in that it is." As an external psychical positedness deriving
from the intelligence's own natural being, the sign is now a vocal note (Ton),
"where the inward idea manifests itself in adequate utterance" (PM, p. 214).
Articulated in speech and language, vocalization endows feelings, intuitions,
representations, with a second Dasein, spiritually enhanced and higher than
before - an 'existence' wholly within the realm of representing.
Language, for Hegel, is the highest product of the signmaking intelligence,
the mediator between intuition and pure thinking (SL [M], pp. 31-32). In
sublating the intuition in the verbal sign, the intelligence is the inner spiritual
'time,' which, like time in general, sublates the asunderness of space (PN,
p. 33ff). In its creation and employment of language, the intelligence is
engaged in that going-outwards that is simultaneously a going-inwards: an
investing of its spiritual inner with the form of an outer Dasein whose very
being is straightway a vanishing. Thus, for Hegel, signmaking is not some
specialized function of imagination in 'cognition,' which is mainly the role it
obtains in the Kantian schematism. Its role for Hegel is indeed that of a
mediator - but one that is the ego itself in its totality as a spiritual life.
Language for Hegel is "divine" (Phen [M], p. 66). The sublation of the
spatial intuition to the vanishing temporal Dasein of the vocal sign entails the
whole inner spirituality of the intelligence as negative power over its natural
being as well as its representations.
HEGEL'S CONCEPTION OF PSYCHOLOGY 185
itself and made it its 'own.' In memory it makes itself an externality so that
its 'own' once again appears as a 'found': now, however, the rmding is a
rmding of what is intelligence's express creation. In mechanical memory, says
Hegel, one of the moments of thinking, "objectivity, is here put in intelli-
gence" as the quality of the intelligence itself (PM, p. 222). The movement
here recapitulated may be seen as a movement from space to time and from
time back to space; or, since space and time are, respectively, the abstract
forms of objectivity and subjectivity, from objectivity to subjectivity and
back to objectivity. The spatiality of the original external intuition is subia ted
in the temporal Dasein of the vocal sign; now, going back, the transience and
contingent subjectivity of the name is itself sublated in an objectivity that is
- indeed not that of sensuous space - out the 'inner outerness' of the spirit's
universal spatiality: the mechanical memory. As mechanical memory, intelli-
gence puts the stamp of 'being' on all its productivity of representation.
The objectivity which the name acquires in mechanical memory, however,
is in the first instance but abstract. If the Seiende as name is to be the Sache
as genuine objectivity, says Hegel, it is in need of the 'meaning' coming from
the representing intelligence as the inner. But memory as such, as we have
seen, has fallen heir to the inner of representation with its treasury of names
and meanings; and as mechanical memory the intelligence contains at once
the two moments: outer objectivity and inner meaning. The intelligence, says
Hegel, is now posited as 'existence' of this identity. Spirit is now explicitly
'for itself the identity which it is 'in itself as reason. The inwardness of
intelligence is now 'to itself being' (an ihr selbst seiend), subjectivity explicit-
ly one with objectivity. Hereby, says Hegel, intelligence as memory passes
over into the activity of thought.
The kinship of memory and thought (Gediichtnis and Gedanken) is
recognized even in language, Hegel claims. Memory as such is thinking in its
'existence,' i.e., thinking in its merely outer aspect or onesided moment.
Reason is implicitly identical with this mode of thought's existence, and this
means that reason now exists in the subject, that reason 'is' as the individual
subjectivity's own activity of thinking.
With the attainment of thinking, spirit has completed its development as
theoretical intelligence. Thinking is the explicit and consummated unity of
subjective and objective in the sphere of cognition. The movement in the
psychology began with spirit as implicit identity of 'being' and its 'own,'
and the course of spirit's movement through intuition, representation, and
thought has been to posit this identity as 'for' itself. For this reason, Hegel
tells us, intelligence has proved to be 'recognitive' (wiedererkennend).
188 MURRAY GREENE
Spirit's knowing now means that what it finds in itself it knows both as its
own and as being.
Beginning with the formal determinations of 'category' and 'judgment,'
thought in 'syllogism' discloses the necessity of the content and sublates the
last distinction of content and form. Whereas in understanding the intelli-
gence still deals with a content other than itself, in reason the content as such
derives from the thinking intelligence's own distinctions of form. In concep~
tual thinking (begreifendes Denken) the Notion evidences itself in its own
proper shape. The universal as form is no longer external to the content but
produces the determinations of the latter from itself and is thus the
immanent self-developing notion of the Sache. The entire movement of
subjective spirit has been the demonstration that "the Notion as such can
only be apprehended by spirit, of which it is not only the peculiar property
but the pure self' (SL [M], p. 618).
That the intelligence now knows that "what is thought, is; and what is,
is only insofar as it is a thought," constitutes the transition from the
theoretical to the practical sphere. In knowing itself as the "determinant of
the content" which at the same time is determined as 'being,' the intelligence
is will (PM, p. 227). The development of subjective spirit as will comprises
the second part of the psychology: practical spirit. This division, however, is
not absolute. The will is nothing separate from reason. In man, says Hegel,
"there is only one reason, in feeling, volition and thought" (fM, p. 231).
As will, spirit enters the realm of actuality. Actuality in subjective spirit,
however, has to do with the individuality as fulfilling itself, and will viewed
psychologically is that of the finite subjectivity. The fmitude of will here,
says Hegel, consists in its 'formalism'; its self-fulfilling is in the first instance
an abstract insistence on its own satisfaction that is not yet "identified with
the developed reason."
The pathway of the will in overcoming its formalism consists in its raising
itself to a 'thinking will' that has freed itself of its own narrow particularity
and now posits itself in its free subjectivity as at the same time objective and
universal. The course of the movement displays the three moments of the
Notion. As (1) 'practical feeling' the will 'finds' itself determined by its
manifold - often contradictory - inclinations and passions, whose contin-
gent and isolated content is lacking in the form of universality that would
render it objective and substantial. The would-be harmony of irmer feeling
with the objectively valid is 'posited' in (2) impulse and choice as a harmony
to be established by the will itself through subordination of the manifold
impulses to a universal aim. Initially this is (3) 'happiness,' which, however,
HEGEL'S CONCEPTION OF PSYCHOLOGY 189
NOTES
to do so. See FriedheIm Nicolin, 'HegeIs Arbeiten zur Theorie des subjektiven Geistes'
in J. Derbolav and F. Nicolin, eds., Erkenntnis und Verantwortung. Festschrift fUr
Theodor Litt (DUsseldorf, Schwann, 1960), pp. 356-374.
3 L [W, 1892], p. 296; SL [M], p. 613.
4 "What merely is (das Seiende), without any spiritual activity," says Hegel, is so little
the essence of spirit that consciousness is rather the very opposite of it and is only actual
for itself by "the negation and abolition of such a being" (Phen [M], p. 205).
5 Referring to Condillac's model of the mind, Hegel says, it shows a successive emer-
gence of mental faculties in a "solely affirmative manner" that misses the "negative
aspect" whereby the sensible material is "transmuted into mind and destroyed as a
sensible." (PM, p. 183).
6 Ph en [M], p. 47; L [W, 1892], p. 17.
7 On the question of the role of the philosopher, see Kenley R. Dove, 'Hegel's Pheno-
menological Method', Review of Metaphysics 23 (1970), 627 ff.
8 SL [M] , pp. 51, 60, 63;Phen [M], p. 491.
9 "Psychologists may not expressly speak of parts of the soul or mind, but the mode in
which this subject is treated by the analytic understanding is largely founded on the
analogy of this finite relation." (L [W, 1892], p. 246; see also p. 365).
10 See R. C. Solomon, 'Hegel's Concept of "Geist" " Review of Metaphysics 23 (1970),
642-661.
11 See Kant's Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science, tr. J. Ellington (Indian-
apolis, Bobbs-MerriU, 1970), p. 8; Theodore Mischel, 'Kant and the Possibility of a
Science of Psychology' in Kant Studies Today, ed. L. W. Beck (La Salle, ill., Open Court,
1969) pp. 432-455.
12 PN, p. 442 ff;L [W, 1892], p. 362; PM, p. 9ff.
13 PM, p. 146; see also SL [M], p. 766.
14 PN, p. 382 ff;PM, p. 76 ff.
15 See Ernst Bloch, Subjekt-Objekt: ErltJuterungen zu Hegel, 2d ed. (Frankfurt am
Main, Suhrkamp, 1962), pp. 188-189.
16 Siimtliche Werke, ed. Glockner (Stuttgart, Frommann, 1958), Vol. 6, p. 48.
17 In fact the term 'experience' only occurs thrice, each time in a polemical context
incidental to the main exposition of the conception of the phenomenology. (See PM,
pp. 161, 162).
18 William James, The Principles of Psychology [1918], 2 vols. (New York, Dover,
1950), vol. 1, p. 218 (cited by Aron Gurwitsch, 'Towards a Theory of Intentionality,'
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 30 (1970),359.)
19 SL [M], p. 96; L [W, 1892], p. 344.
20 See Hume's Introduction to his A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge
(Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1964), p. xxi.
PART TWO
and categories which generates itself by the dynamic of its own inherent
principle of activity, from the most vague, abstract and indefmite to the most
complete, articulate and explicit elaboration of absolute reality. Each form,
at every level, is, he asserts, the Absolute in some partial, and in some degree
inadequate, manifestation of itself. Each logical category, which has a place in
the system, is a provisional definition of the Absolute. It is that definition
which is characteristic of a particular phase in the process of dialectical
development. Hence the progression is not simply from the fragmentary to
the complete (though any such progression is one aspect of the process), but
is from the vague and confused to the more precise and discriminate. At every
stage the whole is in some sense, or manner, or degree, present, for at every
stage we have what Kant called a whole of related and connected elements.
But the whole is not at every stage explicitly articulated, and the series of
forms is constituted by the successive stages of explication engendered from
the less to the more adequate self-manifestations of what is ultimately real
and true.
The movement is generated by the very inadequacy of the primitive forms.
For every entity strives to become self-sufficient; and in those which are
finite, incomplete, or in other respects deficient, their very shortcomings give
rise to internal conflicts and oppositions that can be resolved only by further
self-development and explication. Similarly at the level of development at
which consciousness arises and this process becomes explicit as knowledge,
fmite objects are found wanting just so far as they do not satisfy the mind's
demand for, and nisus towards, coherent wholeness; and contradictions arise,
oppositions are generated, and resolutions are achieved by synthesis and
reconciliation. The progression is consequently one that proceeds by the
generation of contradictions and their resolution. It is the continual assertion
of the negative aspect involved in finiteness and insufficiency and its superses-
sion by a more adequate form in which the particular defiCiency is supplied
and the negation is negated.
For this reason Hegel calls the principle of the dialectic one of absolute
negativity; and it is because of the generation of internal contradiction
through inadequacy of the fmite form, the generation of consequent opposi-
tion to an other which is constituted by what is lacking from the original,
that the triadic appearance of the dialectical stages results. 'Thesis, antithesis
and synthesis' was not Hegel's own formula for the dialectical movement, but
it does summarize what results from it, even though it is not always apparent
and by no means always rigidly exemplified in Hegel's exposition.
System, then, is a series or scale of dialectically related forms, each
DIALECTICAL STRUCTURE OF SCIENTIFIC THINKING 197
automatically generating the next, by its inherent nisus to overcome its own
shortcomings and the contradictions to which they give rise. It is system of
this kind that constitutes what Hegel calls 'science' or Wissenschaft, and it is
to this that he is referring when he writes: " ... knowledge is only real and
can only be expounded as a science or system" (Phiin [G] ,p. 27). Each form,
because the whole is implicit in it, is itself a whole of some sort. Thus the
logic of the dialectic is a logic of development and what develops is always a
totality.
The gamut of categories that results from the dialectical process is a scale
of forms in which each is a specific exemplification of the totality which
is developing, but an exemplification at a particular level of adequacy (or
inadequacy) or degree of explicitness. At the same time the successive forms
are I]1utually related as opposites because of the difference in adequacy
between them: the first as relatively false to that which it is its purport to
present, and the other as relatively true. As Hegel puts it, the later is 'the
truth of the earlier. Every category of the Logic is an exemplification of the
Idea at a specific level of explicit thought; every category of Nature-philo-
sophy is a specific natural form at a particular level of realization of integral
wholeness; and every form of sentience, feeling and consciousness is a specific
form of mind (Geist) at a definite level of self-development. Yet each of
them, as well as each major division of philosophical reflection, is in some
respect, or in some sense, opposed to its neighbour, and in some degree to
every other. I believe that this can be demonstrated in detail, but my present
purpose is only to bring out the fact that the dialectical system is a scale of
forms such as R. G. Collingwood describes in his Essay on Philosophical
Method, in which the forms are mutually related in three ways at once, as
degrees of realization of a universal principle, as specifications of that same
universal, and as opposites. Such a logical structure Collingwood finds
characteristic of all philosophical thinking, and typical of every philosophical
system. My object is to show that it is not confmed to philosophy but is also
the form of scientific theory and scientific advance.
II
III
synthetic view will be more important than the analytic. The psychologist
J. J. Gibson is probably nearer the truth when he writes, "The progress of
learning is from indefinite to definite, not from sensation to percept" (where
'sensation' may be correlated with atomic element and 'percept' with struc-
tured object). If the progress of learning is the same as, or analogous to, the
advancement of knowledge, we should then say that it moves from the vaguer
and more confused to the more defmite and integrated, and this is, in fact,
what we fmd.
The most satisfactory accounts of perception that we have, whether
psychological or epistemological, show it to be an activity of structuring
vague and confused sentient elements to form coherent and systematically
ordered objects,4 and these again are recognizable and significant to the
extent to which they fit into a wider context of mutually related objects. Our
awareness of individual entities in our environment develops pari passu with
our comprehension of that environment as a world of objects ordered in
space and time, as well as in other respects. The ordering principles are
concepts without which, as Kant taught, there is no coherent perception of
objects. This presupposition of a conceptually ordered world implicit in the
perception of ordinary material things is prior to, and is involved in, all
scientific observation; so that there is no observation wholly free from
theoretical presupposition. s Science, moreover, is the fruit of an intellectual
effort to render the world of common perception - what we call 'the world
of common sense' more intelligible. It arises out of puzzling experiences and
develops as the resolution of initial problems gives rise to further questions.
Human knowledge, in short, is always a system of some kind, but is never a
fixed system established for all time. It is a constantly developing process -
a continuing activity of discovery and enlightenment.
From what has been said it will follow that the logical character of this
process of discovery will be that characteristic of the development of a whole.
Ordinary perception - the common sense awareness of the world - is already
a whole of related and connected elements. Incoherences in this structure give
rise to problems that stimulate the scientific enterprise; and this consists in
successive efforts to discover the coherent structure underlying the apparent
discrepancies, and generates a series of theories of increasing explanatory
power. Let us look at examples of this process in more detail.
Common sense accepts the familiar fact of motion as natural and un-
problematic, and yet does not reject the conception of a static world as a
possibility. We perceive things at rest and also things in motion and transfer
the resulting ideas of them at will without undue shock. The Biblical poet
DIALECTICAL STRUCTURE OF SCIENTIFIC THINKING 201
speaks of the mountains skipping like lambs and hills like lambkins, and his
reader, while he may be incredulous, does not fmd the image impossible.
Further our own sense of effort in moving both our own bodies and others
gives rise to a conception of a cause of motion. It seems obvious that some-
thing should act on a body at rest in order to move it; for rest seems to be the
more natural condition which calls for no explanation, while motion carries
with it the idea of activity.
Common experience seems to show that to be moved a body must be
pushed or pulled, but falling bodies move without apparent impulsion. Here
is a discrepancy in the manifest behaviour of things which demands explana-
tion. Such an explanation was devised by the Ancients and set out systema-
tically by Aristotle. It was to the effect that all bodies have a natural place in
the universe from which, if they are to be moved, they must be violently
dislodged, and to which, if they are dislodged, they will naturally return. The
motion of falling bodies is, therefore, their natural motion in returning to
the centre, which is the natural place of earth, whereas forcible impulsion is
required to move them from rest in their natural setting. We are all aware
that, far-reaching as it was, Aristotle's theory led to contradictions when
applied to the behaviour of projectiles, and the subsequent efforts to resolve
these conflicts gave rise to the theories, first of impetus and later of inertia
and gravitation. A projectile like a flying arrow apparently moves indepen-
dently of push or pull, so Aristotle's theory provided no explanation of its
continued motion after its initial propulsion. The theory of antiperistasis,
which was proposed to account for this, led to immediate contradiction for it
presumed a rush of air behind the projectile to prevent a vacuum, which,
while it might keep it moving, would provide no cause for its eventual cessa-
tion. This was likewise attributed to air pressure, so that one was committed
to an appeal to the same process and the same force acting in diametrically
opposed directions. To resolve this difficulty Buridan introduced the theory
of impetus - a kind of induced natural motion originated by the original
impulsion, which, like the loss of heat in a glowing body, gradually died out.
This conception was still in use, though in suitably modified form, by Galileo
in his attempts to explain the motion of falling bodies, and it merges, as we
shall see, into that of inertia.
Thus a common sense notion leading to contradi~tion stimulates a theory,
in which, as it is applied, new conflicts arise; and these in tum are resolved
by successive theories, each applying to the same domain of facts, each
ordering the facts by means of laws, but successively doing so more cohe-
rently.
202 ERROL HARRIS
established, and some writers (like Karl Popper) maintain that none can be
established at all, though they may be falsified. So there is good reason for
holding that all scientific theories are in this sense no more than hypotheses.
The function performed by hypothesis, by virtue of which it explains, is
to organize the experienced phenomena into a system, and the degree of its
success depends on the range of phenomena to which it can consistently be
applied and the absence of conflict in the results of its application. The long
hegemony of the Aristotelian system resulted from the eminent success with
which it coherently ordered the common experience of movement, change,
growth, sensation, thinking and moral conduct, in terms of a single principle
of organization: the matter-form relationship. The collapse of Aristotelian
physics resulted, nevertheless, from the contradiction which arose in the
attempt to apply its theory of motion to the flight of projectiles.
Likewise, most of the visible phenomena of movement in the heavens were
very successfully organized by the conception of spheres revolving around a
central earth, except that the aberrations of planetary motion could not be
consistently included. First Eudoxus worked out a model of spheres each
revolving on a different axis, which carried the different heavenly bodies,
each of which communicated its motion to the next. Callipus elaborated this
system, increasing the number of spheres and introducing some revolving in
opposite directions. This system was adopted by Aristotle, and later Ptolemy
modified it still further by introducing epicycles between the spheres to
account for aberrations which still defied explanation. Each successive
correction of the system to overcome the discrepancies was a new effort at
organization, each succeeded in some measure, but none completely, until the
hypothesis of Aristarchus of Sam os that the sun and not the earth be taken as
central was adopted. The heliocentric theory was delayed by fourteen cen-
turies because the Aristotelian system, with which it conflicted, was so
comprehensive and explained so many fields and departments of common
experience, that theorists could not afford to abandon it without a better
alternative. In the Middle Ages it even became the philosophical support for
Christianity so that a challenge to its authority threatened the very dogmata
of the prevailing religion. It was eventually despair of accurate calculation
of the annual occurrence of religious feasts and festivals which prompted
Copernicus to revert to the hypothesis of Aristarchus in the hope of a more
coherent theory.
This change was not prompted by the empirical discovery of new pheno-
mena, either in ancient times or in the fifteenth century, but was the
fruit of an intellectual endeavour to unify and integrate the system. As a
204 ERROL HARRIS
anyone time they fit (more or less loosely) together into one system covering
the entire world and involving definite conceptions of its elementary con-
stituents and substances as well as of the laws that govern their movements,
combinations and changes. The process of scientific advance is thus a succes-
sion of wholes or systems, like the Hegelian dialectical system, and the series
of conceptual schemes that emerge in it are related to one another as the
Hegelian forms and categories are related. Like them each is a conception of
the universe - a provisional definition of the Absolute.
The progress of scientific ideas further conforms to the dialectical pro-
gression in ways we have already listed as typical. In the first place, the
development, despite appearances in some cases, is continuous. Secondly,
the consecutive systems are specifications of a universal - each is an example
of a general type of scientific theory. And thirdly, each system comes to be
in opposition to the one it supersedes. They are thus at once degrees in a scale
of progressively more satisfactory explanations, species of a special kind or
area of explanatory theory, and opposite or rival theories of a certain range of
phenomena. The progress of science thus constitutes a scale of forms in a
manner comparable to that demonstrated by Collingwood in the case of the
history of philosophy. I shall attempt to give some illustrations of this thesis.
(i) Continuity
his Parisian colleagues. The view that the earth rotated on its axis was
anticipated by Nicole Oresme. Even after the heliocentric hypothesis had
been advocated by Copernicus, it took much time and labour to develop
it by stages into a system that could account for all the facts with sufficient
comprehensiveness and coherence to persuade scientists to abandon the
Aristotelian and Ptolemaic system in its favour. Kepler had to work upon the
laws of planetary motion and Galileo on those of falling bodies. Descartes had
to develop the notions of vortical rotation and conceive the idea of inertia,
and Gilbert had to develop the conception of magnetic attraction, before
the genius of Newton could combine all of these discoveries into a single all-
inclusive explanatory system conceptually whole and self-consistent.
Despite superficial appearances, the Einsteinian revolution grew in like
manner from seeds planted long in advance. The introduction into physics, by
the mid-nineteenth century, of the concept of the field, was already the
beginning of revolutionary change. It shifted the focus of attention from
mass-points and forces to the space between charged particles and the time of
propagation of electro-magnetic waves. Thus space, time and velocity became
prior in importance to particles and impressed forces. Philosophers like
Berkeley and Kant had even earlier called in question the absolute character
of space and time, and later difficulties which increasingly beset the notion of
an aether stimulated new theories. Mach, whose influence Einstein acknowl-
edged, had already propounded relativistic concepts, and asserted in particular
the relativity of gravitational, corio lis and centrifugal forces, and the Principle
of Relativity itself was enunciated by Poincare prior to the exposition of the
theory by Einstein.
Similar continuity can be illustrated in the cases of other scientific revolu-
tions - Harvey's in physiology was continuous with Galen's through a series
of stages from Vesalius, who doubted the permeability of the septum,
Colombo, who discovered the lesser circulation from the heart through the
lungs, and Fabricius who first revealed the presence of the valves in the veins;
Lavoisier's in chemistry followed the work of the British pneumatic chemists
and their discoveries of 'fixed air' (C0 2 ), 'dephlogistigated air' (oxygen), and
hydrogen, identified by Cavendish with phlogiston. Darwin's revolution in
biology, likewise, was a continuous growth from the leads of his grandfather,
Erasmus Darwin, of Cuvier, Buffon, Geoffroi St. Hilaire and Lamarck, as well
as from those of von Baer and of Charles Lyell. 8 And Heisenberg's quantum
mechanics has grown from the progressive development of theories put
forward by Max Planck, Niels Bohr, the de Broglies and Schroedinger. 9 Space
does not permit a proliferation of detail here, nor does my present purpose
208 ERROL HARRIS
warrant it. What is important, however, is not just the demonstrable fact of
continuity but its nature and direction.
Each successive hypothesis is an attempt to explain the same range and class
of facts, so that each is an example of the same general type of theory:
(a) one of celestial mechanics: Ptolemy's geocentric theory with circular
orbits, deferents and epicycles; Copernicus' heliocentric theory with circular
orbits and epicycles; Kepler's heliocentric theory with elliptical orbits, and
fmally Newton's gravitational celestial mechanics. (b) one of vascular
physiology: Galen's implied doctrine of oscillating blood flow with the heart
as a cooling mechanism, its main action in diastole; Vesalius'implied modifica-
tion of this in the denial of the permeability of the septum; Colombo's theory
of the lesser circulation; Fabricius' demonstration of the valvular obstruction
in the veins to the flow of blood away from the heart; and then Harvey's
coordination of all these in De motu cordis into a theory of general blood
circulation, with the heart functioning as a pump, its principal action in
systole. (c) one of combustion: Stahl's theory of phlogiston; the theory of
'fixed air' put forward by Hales and Black, Priestley's theory of 'dephlogis-
ticated air', and finally Lavoisier's demonstration, following upon Guyton
de Morveau's of augmentation, of the process of oxidation.
In each case we have progressively more adequate examples of the same
universal type of principle of explanation. Later theories explain (i.e. fit into
the coherent system) facts which in the earlier theories gave rise to conflicts
and remained intractable, and they do so with fewer discrepancies of their
own. They may, therefore, be regarded at the same time as degrees in a scale
and also as specifications of a universal concept.
But because it is from initial contradictions that the new efforts arise, the
successive theories are in mutual opposition, the later being corrections of the
earlier, which by contrast appear as errors. The newer theory embodies a new
principle of order and establishes a new conceptual structure. It is, therefore,
genuinely revolutionary. Moreover, not merely is the new synthesis in opposi-
tion to the old, it reconciles oppositions within the old. Aristotle had argued
that the heavenly bodies must move in a circle because it was the perfect
figure, but to accommodate the motions of the planets Ptolemy had to
DIALECTICAL STRUCTURE OF SCIENTIFIC THINKING 209
IV
specific forms in the development of consciousness and not the actual history
of scientific discovery. He comes nearer to doing this in the Naturphilosophie,
but there he is more concerned with the conception of nature as such; and, of
course, the only reliable source of that is empirical science, viewed now from
the philosophical viewpoint, after reflection upon both the forms of con-
sciousness and the categories of experience (in the Logic).
What I have tried to do in this paper is to show that the methods of dis-
covery, confirmation and advance in the empirical sciences, both of his day
and of our own, are dialectical in the Hegelian manner, rather than cumula-
tive of empirically derived factual information coupled with merely formal
deduction. Philosophy of science, if it is to give a faithful account of its
subject matter as the scientific disciplines are actually pursued and conducted
by practising scientists, must, it seems to me, return to Hegelian notions of
logic and abandon the narrow empiricism to which it has hitherto been
addicted.
NOTES
Chemism, but the organic is opposed to the inorganic and finds synthesis with it in the
psycho-physical.
13 It must, however, be borne in mind that there are no 'facts' independent of, or
neutral with respect to theory.
14 For Hegel 'the natural history' of thinking.
ERNAN McMULLIN
l. SCIENCE AS HISTORICAL
There is a trivial sense in which science, like any other human product, is
historical. It appears in history; it is constructed by historical individuals in
ways that are contingent. Furthermore, it does not remain the same. It
advances, accumulates, progresses, changes, whatever one's favorite verb here
may be. No one has ever denied these claims. Eighteenth-century science
contai!led elements both of earlier deductivist views (which would make
scientific change something like the derivation of new theorems or the dis-
covery of new intuitively necessary axioms) and of inductivism (making
scientific change primarily an addition of new empirical generalizations or an
extension of older ones). In either case, science would proceed in a cumula-
tive manner. Earlier states would be conserved in the later ones. The addition
of new elements (laws or theories) would leave the 'established' earlier ones
untouched.
Hegel's views on how thought and reality develop suggests a much more
radical account of scientific change, one which may be called 'historicist' or
'transformationist'. At the level of what he calls 'understanding', precise and
determinate concepts are developed in order to grasp the structures of
experience. But these are inevitably inadequate; in the overcoming of the
ensuing tensions, revisions of the conceptual system are made. 5 The system is
never defmitive then; no part of it is immune from challenge. Its warrant lies
in its overall coherence, not in the priority of some foundational statements,
whether axiomatic or observational. Its 'scientific' character lies neither in the
intuitive necessity of its principles nor in its empirical basis but in the degree
to which it has attained the status of reason. "The goal is this, that Spirit
came to consciousness of itself or made the world congruent to itself - for
these come to the same thing". 6
In the empiricist climate of eighteenth-century science, it had been
assumed that the concepts corresponding to the primary properties of matter
(length, mass, and so on) were anchored safely in pre-scientific experience
and were thus unproblematic. Since these were the concepts on which
Newtonian mechanics was built, this system seemed to be immune from basic
218 ERNAN McMULLIN
conceptual reVISIOn. It could be added to, of course, and could fmd new
applications in areas like chemistry. But its grasp of the fundamentals of
motion appeared to be completely adequate. A dialectical account of knowl-
edge, on the other hand, would presumably imply that an irrevisable science
of mechanics is not attainable, that contradictions are bound to be generated
at all stages. Thus, Hegel can readily be made to appear the forerunner of the
sort of historicism that has become the accepted view in recent philosophy of
science.
Unfortunately the matter is not so simple. Nowhere in his writings (to the
best of my knowledge) does Hegel explicitly treat the sciences of nature as a
continuously evolving conceptual system. Nowhere does he attack the
empiricist assumption that the basic observational concepts of length and
time are already definitely grasped. Though the implications of his dialectical
logic for the system of the natural sciences are clear to us, he did not (so far
as I can see) think of them himself in the transformationist terms we might
be tempted to attribute to him. Society, yes; organisms, yes; the life of mind,
yes. But the science of nature: no.
It is important to see why this was so. For Hegel was not at all a historicist
in the modern style. The function of dialectic was to reveal the necessary
connections between elements. And once these came to light, no further
contradiction could occur. It is instructive to recall what he has to say about
Newton's laws of motion. They:
are immortal discoveries which redound to the greatest honour of the analysis of the
Understanding. The next step concerns their proof independently of empirical methods;
and this proof has also been furnished by mathematical mechanics, so that even a science
based on empirically ascertained facts is not satisfied with the merely empirical pointing
out (demonstration). The a priori proof in question rests on the presupposition that the
velocity of a falling body is uniformly accelerated; the proof, however, consists in the
conversion of the moments of the mathematical formula into physical forces, into an
accelerating force . . . and a force of inertia ... determinations utterly devoid of
empirical sanction and equally inconsistent with the NotionfPN, p. 57).
So Hegel rejects what he takes to be the a priori proof of Calileo's law given
by 'mathematical mechanics', and goes on to propose his own proof:
The law of descent of a falling body is afree law of Nature, i.e. it involves an element
which is determined by the Notion of body. Since it follows that the law must be
deducible from this Notion, what has to be done is to show the way in which Galileo's
law . . . coheres with the determination of this Notion. This connection lies simply in
this, that because it is the Notion that now determines motion, so time and space (as
determinations of the Notion) become free in regard to each other; that is to say, their
quantitative relationships conform to their notional determinations. Now seeing that
IS PROGRESS OF SCIENCE DIALECTICAL? 219
time is the moment of negation, of being-for-self, the principle of the One, its magnitude
... in relation to space is to be taken as the unit or denominator. Space on the contrary
is asunderness, and its magnitude is no other than that of time ... (PN, pp. 58-59).
The proof continues in this vein and concludes: "This is the proof of the law
of descent of a falling body as derived from the Notion of the Thing." A few
pages later he goes on to give equally conceptualist proofs of Kepler's three
laws, proofs which display his dialectical ingenuity at its furthest extension.
Newton's formulation of mechanics he disregards, since despite its admitted
mathematical convenience, it is without physical meaning, being "steeped in
an unspeakable metaphysics" that runs "contrary to the Notion" (PN, p. 67).
Is Hegel's mechanics an a priori one? Not in the Kantian sense, certainly. It
requires experience; it does not dispense with the work of the experimentalist.
Hegel is not saying that Kepler's laws might have been obtained in advance by
a philosopher reflecting on the Notion of the Thing. Rather he is saying that
once they have been obtained empirically, the philosopher must set out to
show their logical necessi ty (taking 'logical' here in the dialectical sense):
The philosophy of nature takes up the material which physics has prepared for it
empirically, at the point to which physics has brought it, and reconstitutes it so that
experience is not its final warrant and base. Physics must therefore work into the hands
of philosophy, in order that the latter may translate into the Notion the abstract
universal transmitted to it, by showing how this universal, as an intrinsically necessary
whole, proceeds from the Notion (PN, p. 10).
2. SCIENCE AS SYSTEMIC
One theme that appears again and again in Hegel's writings (Harris reminds
us) is that of the interconnectedness which is constitutive of system. An
element of the system is specified by its relations with the other elements.
Thus there cannot be simple concepts since to conceptualize is to interrelate.
IS PROGRESS OF SCIENCE DIALECTICAL? 221
But once again, one has to be careful not to make Hegel too modern in
this regard. Balancing his stress on coherence and integration of disparate
empirical elements is his hostility to explicitly hypothetical reasoning utiliz-
ing atoms, waves, ether, light-rays, or the like. He argues, for example, that
water must not be thought to consist of oxygen and hydrogen; rather these
latter are only "different forms assumed by water". The "greatest contradic-
tion thus appears", he goes on, "when through the abstract thought of
identity, the thing is still held to exist". He rejects the trust in the sciences of
his day to explain the behaviour of a complex entity in terms of the presence
within it of specified real constituents. Further:
It is a similar conception which looks on heat, water of crystallization etc., as reduced to
latency. Heat, for example, is no longer seen, felt, and so forth; yet it is said to be still
there, though not perceptible. But what is not subject to observation does not exist in
this sphere; for to exist is precisely to be for another, to make oneself perc!lptible; and
this sphere is precisely the sphere of existence (PN, § 286, Z, pp. 117-118).11
Hegel goes further than did later positivists in that he opposed the use of
theories employing such elements even as heuristic devices. They are fictions
of the Understanding and cannot but mislead. His preference for phenomeno-
logical or descriptive theories 12 thus leads him to reject Dalton's atomic
hypothesis, notions of latent heat, Newton's theory of color, and so on. He
can see no possibility of Reason's discovering necessity in such postulations,
hence they cannot be regarded as the roots of exteriorization the Notion
could create in its constitution of Nature. Nor do they have a direct empirical
warrant.
Despite the acuteness of his perception of the systemic character of the
sciences, then, Hegel was blocked from an appreciation of the ampliative
power this character bestow.ed on theoretical reasoning. The warrant for the
existence of such entities as atoms, as we know, lies not in the necessity of
the conceptual connections nor in observation directly, but mainly in the
fertility over an extended history of the conceptual system employing
them. 13 The systemic character of science enables it to extend ontology
indefinitely. And this is done, not in terms of constructions that can be made
to take on some sort of necessity after the fact, nor in terms of static
determinations inevitably doomed to be rejected, but by means of tentative
models whose metaphoric power enables them to grow. The organic image
here is one that Hegel could appreciate. But the science of his day still gave
little evidence of the ontological power of retroduction that is so plain in the
structural sciences of the past century. And his idealist standpoint had too
IS PROGRESS OF SCIENCE DIALECTICAL? 223
Continuity: On the face of it, it seems simply false to claim that the develop-
ment of science is continuous. Instances of discontinuity are everywhere: the
Wegener continental drift hypothesis, which, in its plate-tectonic form, has
revolutionized geology in the past decade; the Planck-Einstein quantum
hypothesis; Lavoisier's oxygen hypothesis - the list could be extended
indefinitely. What, then, can Harris mean? He maintains that "despite the
appearances in some cases", scientific change is continuous. But then he goes
on to say that many of the major changes in science "are in a significant sense
revolutionary" (p. 206). So that his criterion (which at first might seem to
lean to Toulmin, say, and away from Kuhn) begins to seem rather elastic.
'Continuous' for him appears to mean (1) that there are hints in advance of
even the most novel-seeming hypotheses, and (2) that "each step leads
naturally to the next" (ibid.). I would want to argue that neither of these
alleged requirements can, in fact, be maintained, in anything other than the
vaguest senses of the key terms.
It would be agreed by all that scientific discoveries do not occur in a
vacuum, that even the most creative thinker makes use of ideas of which he
was not the discoverer. He may modify them or juxtapose them in new ways,
but no system is entirely new, if by that is meant that it makes no use of
elements previously available. Is But surely this is trivial, and is not enough to
constitute continuity in any meaningful sense. There was no hint in advance
of the Planck quantum hypothesis; it did not develop out of some 'more-or-
less' quantum views held before-hand. To describe Aristarchus' heliocentric
hypothesis as an antecedent of Copernicus' is perfectly correct. But to
generalize from this that 'hints' of this explicit sort must always be available
is to misunderstand the creativity of the scientist. Of course, there are
anticipations of Galilean mechanics in earlier thought. But it is risky to say
that Galileo used a 'modified' conception of Buridan's notion of impetus in
his account of falling motion, one that 'merged' into the concept of inertia
(p. 201).16 This is to diminish unduly the basic shifts that occurred in early
mechanics, though there were undoubtedly analogies at work of the sort
Harris suggests. Likewise, to say that "the Einsteinian revolution grew ... from
seeds planted long in advance" (p. 207) is in one sense trivially true, but it is
nonetheless a dangerous formulation if this is taken to imply that there was
nothing in the Einsteinian formulation that did not have a specific antecedent
IS PROGRESS OF SCIENCE DIALECTICAL? 225
become progressively more specific. Harris puts this as follows: "Each succes-
sive hypothesis is an attempt to explain the same range and class of facts, so
that each is an example of the same general type of theory" (p. 208). The
familiar charge: 'vacuous or false' can once again be made. To say that the
progression of theories belongs to the same general 'concept', e.g. mechanics,
is analytically true, since if it counts as a 'successor' of T 1 , T2 would auto-
matically be described by the same very general category; it presumably
explains most (at least) of the facts that Tl explained. But in an important
sense, the supposed requirement cannot be admitted. Very often T2 will
unite classes of 'facts' hitherto seen as disparate; 'interfield' theories (as these
have been called) are of enormous importance in the history of science, and
the manner of their 'linking' to form a new type of theory is significant in
any general account of scientific advance. IS If 'specifying a universal' be
taken to be a gradual process of focussing on a domain whose boundaries are
more or less set from the beginning, then it is an inadmissible requirement.
Yet Harris can scarcely have intended the 'specification' of a universal to
be taken as restrictively as this. He elsewhere counts it a merit of the Hegelian
scheme that it suggests a "progressive integration" in which previously un-
related areas (like optics and electrodynamics, for example) would be brought
together in a single scheme, thus organizing wider and wider sets of observa-
tions (p. 204). It is hard to reconcile this with his statement of the 'specifica-
tion' principle as requiring successive theories each to apply to the "same
domain of facts"; the progression would then (as he says) be one of 'coher-
ence' in the laws by which the domain is organized (p. 201).
Hegel himself has relatively little to say on this topic. But he certainly
does envisage some Rind of progressive integration. He criticizes Berzelius's
unification of the disparate domains of electricity and chemistry, not because
such unifications are misguided in principle, but only because Berzelius's
'electro-chemistry' has (in his view) outrun the facts. He shows himself here,
as elsewhere, fairly knowledgeable about the empirical details of galvanic
electricity and chemical action as they were known in his day. And he
admonishes the chemists not to overlook the distinctions between the
electrical and chemical aspects of the galvanic process:
Perhaps this higher demand, addressed to the instinct of Reason, to grasp the course of
the galvanic and the electrical process as such, conceived as a total of natural activity, is
responsible in part for the fact that the lesser demand, viz., simply to take notice of
empirically demonstrated facts, has up till now met with scant compliance (PN, § 330,
p. 246, see also § 313).
But could the unification of the chemical and electrical aspects of
IS PROGRESS OF SCIENCE DIALECTICAL? 227
nature be brought about under a single universal, a universal that had been
inchoately present from the beginning of the scientific inquiry? Hegel's
system oversimplifies the resources for conceptual innovation that science
possesses. The unification in this case occurs through the postulation of
underlying structures which are characterized by means of newly-developed
complex concepts. These are validated retroductively not primarily by the
internal properties of coherence' and simplicity of the resultant system but
rather by the success of the system in prediction and more especially in the
guidance of research into new areas. The process here simply cannot be
characterized as the specification of a single universal, dimly grasped from the
beginning.
progressed very far by his day? The reasons, to my mind, go deeper than this.
They derive, I would suggest, from two fundamental optimisms in the Hegel-
ian program, both of them based on pervasive ambiguities in his thought.
One is the assumption (rooted in his powerful analysis of political forms) that
a historical dialectic must follow the dialectic of the reconstructive reason.
The other is the assumption that the empirical is the occasion for, and not in
any ultimate way the warrant of, the assertion of the theoretical scientific
reason. He writes:
To the observing consciousness, the truth of the law is found in experience, in the same
way that sensuous being is [an object] for consciousness; is not in and for itself. But if
the law does not have its truth in the Notion, it is a contingency, not a necessity, not in
fact a law. The fact that it is essentially in the form of Notion, not only does not conflict
with its being accessible to observation, but rather for that very reason gives it necessary
existence, and makes it [an object for] observation (phen [M], § 249).
This view of the role of the empirical in the development and warranting
of theory would make it very difficult indeed for him to make sense in
anything other than a very selective and schematic way of the history of the
natural sciences between Calileo's day and his own. This is where Harris
boldly takes the plunge and asserts that the Hegelian dialectic can, in fact,
be successfully applied to the illumination of the history of science, just as it
can to the history of civilizations. "My object is to show that [the dialectic]
is not confined to philosophy but is also the form of scientific theory and
scientific advance" (p. 197). Let us see whether he can bring this off.
How, in his view, does scientific change occur? Each theoretical system
"automatically [generates] the next, by its inherent nisus to overcome its
own shortcomings and the contradictions to which they give rise" (p. 197).
These "internal conflicts and oppositions ... can be resolved only by further
self-development and explication" (ibid.). When scientists continue to explore
a theory, "intolerable contradictions" invariably appear (p. 210) which force
the abandonment of the theory and the formulation of a new and more all-
embraCing hypothesis, the successive theories being "related as opposites"
(p. 197), "related as opposed and revolutionary" (p. 210). This certainly
sounds like Hegel. But how well does it respect the history of science?
Change in science 'can be of many sorts. First it can be nomothetic: a new
empirical law is proposed, an older one extended or sharpened. Such advance
is crucial to science and constitutes by far the largest part of day-to-day
scientific work. Harris himself mentions (p. 204) that the "true empirical
method" involves this kind of patient accumulation of skillfully varied
observational evidence; he alludes to the work of Harvey and Lavoisier as
IS PROGRESS OF SCIENCE DIALECTICAL? 229
examples. What he does not seem to see is that the motive force behind
advances such as these is not contradiction in previously known empirical
law, i.e. something a theorist would recognise as a discrepancy. When the
experimenter extends the gas laws to even lower temperatures or higher
pressures, for example, he is not responding to any sort of perception of
incoherence in these laws as they stand.
Harris adopts two different strategies in the face of this obvious objection
to his thesis. The first is to weaken it by using terms like 'inadequacy' instead
of 'contradiction', and to propose that a change in science can occur only
when some inadequacy is perceived. This is true, but is of course vacuous.
The scientist will presumably not move from stage A to stage B unless he has
some reason to suppose stage A incomplete, inadequate, in need of change or
supplementation. Once again, we are back to the objection of vacuity. But
even apart from the fact that this would deprive the thesis of any interest, it
should be obvious from what we have seen of Hegel's views above that this is
not at all what he was saying. His notion of contradiction had much more
'bite' to it.
Harris' second strategy is to suggest a Kuhnian distinction between 'revolu-
tionary' changes in science and those that occur in the process of 'normal
science', only the former qualifying as properly 'dialectic' (pp. 210-211).
Apart from the fact that this could restrict the scope of the dialectic thesis to
a rather small number of developments in the history of science, the objec-
tion that Kuhn himself would be likely to put is the important role played by
the accumulation of empirical anomaly in such 'revolutions'. But might these
not be called 'contradictions' in only a slightly extended use of the Hegelian
term?
Before answering this, let us look at some other sorts of changes in science.
There can, as we have just seen, be 'revolutionary' ones where a theory that
articulates an entire domain is replaced by a substantially different theory.
Or there can be less shattering changes where a set of empirical laws for the
first time receives some sort of theoretical unification, or where conflict
between a number of competing theories in a relatively restricted domain
(e.g. origin of the moon, nature of capillary attraction) is fmally resolved.
This latter case seems to involve 'contradiction' of a sort; there is surely a
sense in which alternative theories put forward to account for the same set
of empirical regularities 'contradict' each other.
But here again, vacuity lurks nearby. It is perhaps worth saying (sincethe
early empiricists so often missed this point) that the acceptance of a theory
entails in some sense the rejection of the earlier one, if there was an earlier
230 ERNAN McMULLIN
one in regard to roughly the same domain. Harris puts this by saying that
"the successive theories are in mutual opposition, the later being correc-
tions of the earlier, which by contrast appear as errors" (p. 208). But this
notion of a 'rejection' has to be taken carefully here, as critics of Feyera-
bend's use of 'refutation' in this same context have pointed out. Newtonian
physics is still used for the vast majority of physical problems today; to say
that it has· been 'rejected' is to say that as an overall explanatory system it
has been proved to be inadequate. But a relation of inadequ!!cy of a theory
in regard to its successor is, as we have just seen, hardly an interesting sense
of 'contradiction', and is certainly much weaker than the relation claimed by
Hegel.
There is one important type of change in science to which the notion of
dialectic contradiction is peculiarly inapplicable. Sometimes a theory proves
unable to predict some domain of phenomena which the scientist believes it
should be able to predict. Thus, for example, the original Bohr theory of the
H-atom proved unable to explain the fine-structures of the spectroscopic lines
produced when the emitting hydrogen was subjected to a magnetic field
(Zeeman effects). It was not so much that it predicted them wrongly as that
it did not predict this cluster of effects at all. It would be entirely misleading
to describe this as a 'conflict' or 'contradiction' within the theory; it would
also be wrong to describe the relationship between successive theories (or
successive versions of the theory) here as one of conflict or opposition.
Quite the opposite, in fact. A good theoretical model is expected to have
the resources of a good metaphor. That is, it is expected to guide research,
not just by the predictions it makes, but by further conceptual innovations it
may suggest in the face of anomaly or a range of phenomena (like the Zeeman
effects) which ought to prove tractable. The original gene theory of heredity
was quite vague about where and what the gene was. But it provided a
research program within which the gene came to be more and more closely
linked with a location on the chromosome, on the basis of very sophisticated
experimental testing of alternative sub-hypotheses. The primary impetus here
was provided not by contradiction nor even by anomaly but by the imagina-
tive resources of the original model which at each stage pointed the way to
the alternatives that had to be explored in order that the structures of the
model itself might be progressively more sharply defined.
One might want to say with Hegel that in cases like this one a universal is
being progressively specified. But what the Hegelian system does not account
for is just why this happens. It is not contradiction or incoherence in the
original concept that leads to the formulation of an opposed alternative.
IS PROGRESS OF SCIENCE DIALECTICAL? 231
decisive. But by themselves, they are not sufficient to account for the kinds
of change that occur in natural science.
Harris himself appears to recognize this when he says that "the establish-
ment of a new hypothesis ... is achieved by the construction of a body of
varying evidence", leading to "corroboration" from the "diverse phenomena"
(p. 204). Unfortunately, he then goes on to construe the notion of construc-
tion as a means of ordering the facts, "which in large measure, by ordering,
constitutes them, makes them what they are" (p. 205). This enables him to
return to the Hegelian internalist thesis: theories change as their "implications
are developed and their details worked out". What must be done (he con-
tinues) is to "devise a modified conceptual scheme that will organize the
phenomena more coherently" (ibid.). It is as though the set of phenomena is
somehow already there, and the criteria of the successive theories are those of
coherence only. Theory does not simply constitute fact; if it did, empirical
anomalies would never arise. Theory shapes the way in which fact is express-
ed. But that is not nearly enough to allow the primacy of reason that the
Hegelian dialectic demands.
In this connection, it is important to notice that Hegel did not recognize
the importance of retroductive patterns of inference. There were, on the one
hand, the empirical inductions of the inorganic, and on the other the most
general laws of mechanics and the general interrelations of the organic world.
It was only in the latter that he could trace the lineaments of the Idea. The
structural sciences of chemistry and geology were only beginning to display
their power and range. The ability of structural models to stretch out beyond
the necessities of the rationalist or the empirical generalizations of the
inductivist was still not plain. So that Hegel, to the extent that he saw the
inadequacy of the inductivist model, could be forgiven for assuming that his
own rationalist alternative was the only other one which could account for
the onward march of science.
Harris can less easily be pardoned. He rejects the inductivists' account of
scientific change in language sufficiently ambiguous, for the most part, to
count as an endorsement either of rationalist dialectic or of retroductive
inference. But he cannot have it both ways. If empirical anomaly and corro-
boration by the variety of empirical evidence play the role he allows them to
do, he has opted for retroduction. To retain the language of Hegel is at the
very least misleading once the substance of the rationalist metaphysic under-
lying it has been compromised.
IS PROGRESS OF SCIENCE DIALECTICAL? 233
This raises one last issue. On what did Hegel's claim for the dialectic rest?
Taylor has pointed out a fundamental ambiguity at this point in Hegel's
argument between the 'contrastive' sense, in which we cannot have the
shape-concept square without contrasting it with other concepts like round
which 'negate' it, and the 'interactive' sense in which beings struggle to
maintain themselves in the face of others and hence 'negate' each other in an
active way.21 It is essential to Hegel's argument for dialectic as a universal
pattern that he elide the differences between these two senses. A determi-
nate being can only be defined by reference to another with which it is
contrasted. This other is its negation. But Hegel then goes on in a way which
(as Taylor says) "arouses our suspicion", to suppose that this negation is to
be understood not merely in its contrastive sense but also in that of interac-
tion. Thus the determinate being has to struggle against its negation; the
outcome can only be the modification of both.
The confusion here is manifest. It is true that everything does have a
contrastive frontier with others. Its frontier is constitutive of it:
Hence in containing it, each contains what negates it as well as what essentially con-
stitutes it. If we now shift to the other sense of frontier, that of interaction, we can give
this "negation" a concrete as well as just a contrastive logical sense, and it looks as
though each entity essentially contains the seeds of its own destruction. But, of course,
however much we may be tempted to speak of something as "containing its frontier" in
the contrastive sense, when we move to the frontier at which things "negate" each other
by interaction, it is just false to say that each contains its own negation. Quite the
contrary, to the extent that they maintain themselves, they hold their "negations" off. If
they fail to do so, of course, they go under, but they are not essentially determined to
do so by the very way in which they are defined. 22
There is another difficulty, ;tlready alluded to, facing anyone who attempts
to apply the dialectic thesis to the history of science. Hegel assumes that the
historical dialectic follows the same path as the logical (or ontological) one.
This may have some plaUSibility in the politico-social realm. But why should
one expect it to be the case that scientists in their work retrace the lines of
the necessary dialectic of Reason? Hegel makes a sharp distinction between
empirical science (which he identifies with the systematic observation of
nature) and philosophy of nature (which takes empirical science as its
presupposition, reflects on it and shows how nature is an externalization of
the Idea). This distinction is inadequate on several scores, but leaving this
aside, how is Hegel to show that the gradual development of empirical science
itself follows a dialectical pattern? This in no way follows from the logical
234 ERNAN McMULLIN
Thus, moon and comet are both dialectically derived from darkness.
Their "peculiarity as relative central bodies" in the solar system "is based on
the same Notion as their physical peculiarity: they do not rotate on their
axes". They are two logical sides of an opposition, so that their presence in
the solar system is not a chance matter once we have grasped the nature of
the Notion. "They constitute the self-subsistent moments of the dissolving
earth: the moon is the earth's hard interior, the comet is the earth's atmos-
phere which has acquired independent existence, an enduring meteor".
later, he rejects the chemical notion of an element as an 'abstraction' and
proposes instead a four-element theory based on an intricate set of opposi-
tions:
Air corresponds to light; it is passive light which has sunk to the level of a moment. The
elements of opposition are Fire and Water. Rigidity, the lunar principle, is no longer
indifferent, existing by itself alone; but as an element entering into relation with
another, namely the individuality, it is an active unstable being-for-self which is in
ceaseless process, and thus is liberated negativity: Fire. The third element corresponds
to the cometary principle and is Water. The fourth is the earth again ... (PN, § 281,
p. 106).
From oppositions of this imaginative sort, light and darkness, active and
passive, rigid and unstable, magnetisim and electricity of opposite polarities,
and so forth, he constructs an immensely complex logical dialectic. My
purpose here is not to comment on the validity of this dialectic as an explana-
tion of nature. Rather, it is to make the simpler point that it has no bearing
whatever on the manner in which the empirical scientist develops his laws and
theories. The oppositions on which Hegel bases his dialectic of moon, comets,
physical elements, are not reflected in the history of astronomy nor of
chemistry. Nor, indeed, does Hegel claim that they should be. But if the
history of empirical science cannot be represented by the logical dialectic
revealed in the philosophy of nature, what grounds are there for supposing
that this history is in fact dialectical?
We have earlier questioned the validity of Hegel's argument for the
IS PROGRESS OF SCIENCE DIALECTICAL? 235
universality of the dialectical process. The suggestive analogies which carry his
analysis of history and of ontology are not available in the history of science.
Is there any other source of evidence for the dialectical character of this
history? Harris spends much of his time pointing to episodes in the history of
science which he takes to exemplify the dialectical principle. We have argued
at some length above that most of them do not do so unless the notion of
'dialectical' is extended to the point of near-vacuity. But suppose they did
exemplify it. Are they then being presented as the warrant for our accepting
it? Harris nowhere develops Hegel's own argument for the dialectic, and the
impression the reader might easily receive is that the reason for accepting his
thesis is that it does in fact describe the realities of the history of science so
exactly.23
If this is the case, it is of course an a posteriori inference of a rather un-
Hegelian sort. One would then have to ask (which he does not) whether there
might not be other alternative modes of description that might not do the job
better. But perhaps the references to history are intended only as illustration,
not as evidence? It is hard to be sure. But either way, it would seem that the
dialectic thesis is in trouble.
We began this paper with a reference to the Marxist version of the dialectic
thesis, so perhaps it is appropriate to turn once more, very briefly, to this
before ending. What kind of warrant can Marxism-Leninism produce for its
dialectical claim for the history of science? Because it rejects the idealism of
Hegel, it is deprived of the central argument he could call on: that nature is
an externalization of mind and thus the same structures must govern the
processes of both. For Hegel, as Taylor puts it, "the motor force of move-
ment is contradiction, that between the external reality and that which it is
meant to realize".24 But in a materialist metaphysics, this tension does not
exist, since nature is not meant to realize anything. Only a teleology that
verges on the (forbidden) idealist one would seem to justify the reimposition
here of a dialectical scheme on nature.
Marxist-Leninist writers make much of the presence in nature of 'contra-
dictions'. Leaving aside the question of the appositeness of such a term to
describe such polarities as that between electrical attraction and repulsion,25
the more pressing question for us in this context is: how is one to get from
such 'contradictions' to the claim that thought about nature, because of the
inevitable occurrence of internal 'contradictions', must follow a progressive
dialectical pattern? It would be just as much a fallacy to infer from the fact
(if it is a fact) that material nature is dialectical to the dialectical character of
the history of science, as it was for Platonism to argue from the unchanging
236 ERNAN McMULLIN
NOTES
particular, it is not correct to render thus the 'correspondence rules' which played such
a vital role in this proposal: "The interpretation of the calculus is effected by substitut-
ing for its variable elements empirical terms, indicative, or descriptive, of observable
entities". Were this to be the case all reference to unobservable entities would have
to be eliminated, which was very far from Carnap's intention. Harris' conclusion that
"inference in the natural sciences is accordingly reduced by current doctrine to analytic
deduction, which can produce no new knowledge and inductive generalization, which
cannot be validated" (p. 198), is too sweeping. The main fault with this Humean charac-
terization is that it lumps under 'induction' a number of modes of confirmation that have
to be taken separately. But to explore this would lead us too far afield. See E. McMullin,
'Structural Explanation', American Philosophical Quarterly 15 (1978), 139-147.
5 "'The understanding' is the name of the attitude of mind in which notions are regard-
ed as being fully determined, with a precise meaning and with a precise and restricted
range of extension so that they can be applied rigidly and clearly to the differentiation
of experience ... It is part of the abstract and formal function of the Logik to show that
to stick to such fixed notions involves contradictions which can be overcome by the
development of more adequate, less rigid notions. This generation of contradictions
which shows up the inadequacy of the understanding is the process of dialectic" (R.
Plant, Hegel (London, 1973), pp. 140--1).
6 Reason in History, trans!. R. S. Hartman (New York, Liberal Arts Press, 1953), p. 74.
7 M. J. Petry in the introduction to his three-volume translation of the Philosophy of
Nature (London, Allen and Unwin, 1970) asserts both that Hegel seems to suggest that
a science of nature is open to constant revision, and that it also is ultimately rooted in
absolute and unchanging principles (I, pp. 33, 90). He reads perhaps more of the 'infinite
revisability' theme into Hegel than the text will actually bear. See G. Buchdahl, 'Hegel's
Philosophy of Nature', British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 23 (1972), 257-
266; see p. 262.
8 C. Taylor notes that to put it in this way is to give it a more contemporary expression
than is actually found in Hegel's text, but he argues that it is a fair rendering of what
Hegel had in mind (Hegel (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1975), p. 305).
9 For a fuller discussion of this issue, see the Introduction to The Concept of Matter in
Modern Philosophy, ed. E. McMullin (Notre Dame, Ind., Notre Dame University Press,
1978), especially pp. 47-52.
10 See E. McMullin, 'The Ambiguity of 'Historicism' ',New Directions in the Philoso·
phy of Science, ed. P. Asquith and H. Kyburg (E. Lansing: PSA, 1979).
11 SeealsoPetry,op. cit. l,p.l08.
12 The philosopher of nature must 'submerge his freedom' in the content and let it be
moved by its own nature. Though the object of study follows a dialectic movement, the
philosopher (scientist) must stay as close as he can to a purely phenomenological
method, and intrude no purely hypothetical entities. See K. Dove, 'Hegel's Phenomeno-
logical Method', Review of Metaphysics 231970, 615-64L
13 See E. McMullin, 'The Criterion of Fertility and the Unit for Appraisal in Science',
Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science [Lakatos Memorial Volume] VoL 39
(Dordrecht, Reidel, 1976), pp. 395-432.
14 Much historical work remains to be done on the development of philosophy of
science in the fIrst half of the nineteenth century. In Larry Laudan's detailed review of
the sources for this period, it is interesting that Hegel is not even listed among the several
238 ERNAN McMULLIN
score who are counted there as having contributed to the philosophy of science during
this time. See 'Theories of Scientific Method from Plato to Mach', History of Science 7
(1967),1-63.
15 See E. McMullin, 'Creativity and Scientific Discovery', Freedom and Man, ed. J. C.
Murray (New York, Kennedy, 1965), 105-130.
16 This issue is treated by several authors in New Perspectives on Galileo, ed. R. Butts
and J. Pitt (Dordrecht and Boston, Reidel, 1978).
17 P. Feyerabend, 'Explanation, Reduction and Empiricism', Minnesota Studies in the
Philosophy of Science 3 (1962), 28-97.
18 See, for example, 1. Darden and N. Maull, 'Interfield Theories', Philosophy of
Science 44 (1977),43-64.
19 It is incorrect nonetheless to say that "the collapse of Aristotelian physics resulted
... from the contradiction which arose in the attempt to apply its theory of motion to
the flight of projectiles" (p. 203). The matter was far more complex than this. It involved
not merely the inability of Aristotelian physics to handle the phenomena of (relatively)
free fall but also the direct anomalies that were revealed by the telescope.
20 Harris, oddly, goes too far in this direction when he says that "it was eventually
despair of accurate calculation of the annual occurrence of religious feasts and festivals
which prompted Copernicus to revert to the hypothesis of Aristarchus in the hope
of a more coherent theory" (p. 203). All the most recent scholarship in the tangled
Copernican story would indicate that this was one of the cases where the perception of
empirical anomaly did not, in fact, play the crucial role.
21 Taylor,op. cit., p. 234.
22 Ibid., p. 236
23 Elsewhere Harris utilizes an argument of an interestingly different, and more com-
plex, kind. In 'Hegel and the Natural Sciences' (Beyond Epistemology, ed. F. G. Weiss
(The Hague, Nijhoff, 1974), 129-153), he claims that it was Hegel's "conviction of an
immanent dialectic in nature" which enabled him "to see, at times, in the forms and
phenomena of nature, what the science of his day had not yet discovered, but what has
since become sound scientific doctrine" (p. 151). Thus, for example, Harris continues,
he anticipated both the theory of evolution and the theory of relativity in his concep-
tual dialectic of nature. This utility to anticipate later developments furnishes (in
Harris's view) an impressive additional warrant for the validity of his metaphysical
insights.
It could, however, be objected that a great many of the dialectical constructions in
the Philosophy of Nature were not borne out by later developments in science, so that
this is a rather vulnerable strategy of argument. And Hegel's opposition to the theories of
evolution of his own day cannot be explained away by claiming (as Harris does) that it
was because these theories were unduly speculative and that "his faithful adherence to
what in his time was scientifically respectable led him to reject the notion of biological
evolution, convenient though it would have been for him to adopt it", thus leading to a
"discrepancy" between his "metaphysical insights and what he accepts as scientifically
supported fact". Hegel is not slow elsewhere to enter into a critique of the sciences of
his day, on the grounds of their inability to structure the facts along lines that he
considers acceptable.
His objection to evolution came from within his own system, as he makes clear in the
Philosophy of Nature:
IS PROGRESS OF SCIENCE DIALECTICAL? 239
Hegel's dialectic seems to possess the property of provoking again and again
either adherence or vehement rejection. In this the question whether the
philosopher had a troubled relation to the exact sciences, or, on the contrary,
exercised a stimulating influence, remains just as much at issue as the possi-
bility of reaching an adequate understanding of his intentions. At the 15th
World Congress of Philosophy in 1973 at Varna, at least four positions
emerged in the sessions of the Institut Internationa1e de Philo sophie alone.
Mario Bunge assured the meeting, in essence, that science was present only
where the last vestige of dialectics had been eradicated in order that the
principles of exact philosophy might be complied with. Paul Ricoeur related
dialectics solely to human practice, differing in this evaluation from Mihailo
MarkoviC. In an interpretation drawn from Marx and Engels, I. S. Narski
accepted the validity of objective and subjective dialectics, to be interpreted
materialistically. Under these circumstances, it seems advisable to consult
Hegel's texts on the various points in order to recall to memory how his ideas,
which refer mainly polemically to Kant, are to be understood. That it is
worthwhile to seek to complete Hegel's methodological and epistemological
structure at this late date results from a fact that simply cannot be neglected:
in recent times a turning back to Hegel's ideas has begun within predominant-
ly empirical disciplines, which has confirmed an unmistakable relationship
to the most modern problems.
In a controversy by correspondence with William James, Charles S. Peirce
professes to a kind of thinking in which three modes of consciousness are
contained, which he classifies as feeling, experience and awareness of the
future.! The theoreticians, alluded to but not named by Pierce in this corre-
spondence, are characterized as Thomists, Hegelians and intellectualists. In
this connection only the absence of an aversion to Hegelian intentions is of
interest. One of the more recent editors of Pierce, Karl-Otto Apel, places the
'objective logic' of evolution, already postulated in 1868 and worked out
explicitly after 1890, within a framework of influences that extends from
Hegel and Schelling to Darwin and Lamarck?
That an influence of Hegel on Charles S. Peirce definitely exists can
be concluded from, for instance, Peirce's Lectures on Pragmatism. In the
241
R. S. Cohen and M. W. Wartofsky (eds.), Hegel and the Sciences, 241-270.
© 1984 by D. Reidel Publishing Company.
242 HERMAN LEY
relation both to the logic of evolution, and to the categories, which for Lwoff
. retains the constancy contained in the seed throughout the various stages of
existence of ontogenesis. Without actually discussing it, Lwoff seems to sense
the paradox, that the dialectician Hegel finds it necessary to emphasize the
constancy of living organisms more than, say, Kant, who points to a possible
hypothesis of the evolution of animals and plants. In contrast to Kant, the
evolution of nature is absent in Hegel's philosophy, while for society an
evolutionary trend is worked out in consciousness and in the economic-
technical infrastructure, one that does not relate solely to the phenomena of
mind. While nature is considered to be the realization of absolute spirit
without its own immanent evolution, i.e., for nature as a whole, yet Hegel
was able to seize upon the constancy of the determinants and of the simple
forces which condition the individual development of the objects of the
species whose change of form is visible. Even though a not inconsiderable
indefiniteness attaches to the dialectic, this does not hinder Hegel from
emphasizing the constancy of the relation between the seed and the fully
formed object. In the references to Hegel which have become relevant in
more recent times, these opposing sides contained in the dialectic gain in
significance. The relatively constant is related to a process of well-defined
change of form, and belongs in the domain of the phenomena of the empiri-
cally accessible reality within an objectively understood multiplicity; Hegel
conceives of this domain as dialectical.
Perhaps the most enthusiastic advocacy of Hegel's evolutionary thought
comes in more recent times from the biologist Adolf Meyer-Abich, who
designated phylogeny as an essentially historical science indebted to Roman-
ticism, and especially to the historical thought of the Hegelian school. 6 As
a dialectical synthesis he mentions, among others, the vitalism-mechanism
problem. This kind of problem is characterized by Niels Bohr as ideals of
knowledge, as deep truths, of which Bohr says that "their opposite also
contains deep truths.,,7 If Meyer-Abich deals too boldly in some respects
with Hegel's dialectical triad of thesis-antithesis-synthesis, which is hardly
rigidified into woodenness in Hegel, still, in any case the holistic theoretician
is able to link his views to Bohr. The compensations of phylogenetic epochs
are conceived as complementaries in statu nascendi. The emergency of
antinomical states of affairs is seen to be the result; these have their domain
in the history of society, but are extrapolated by Meyer-Abich to the natural
sciences, whose structures as developing sciences he sees as approaching
human history.8 Whereas Helmholtz saw the Hegelian identity philosophy
founding on natural science,9 Meyer-Abich assures us that the natural
244 HERMAN LEY
nature, is carried out in anything but an automatic fashion, but instead has its
precondition in subjective activity, Churchman, to begin with, goes back to
Kant's thesis: data are not movements of nature, but partially our own
movements, created by our judgment. 1 2 In any case, that is how Churchman
formulates the state of affairs, and he emphasizes the objective and subjective
participation in the production of data, which corresponds to Kant's con-
frontation of Platonism and Epicureansim in his Critique of Pure Reason.
Churchman regards the production of data as a creative process. Since he
cannot receive sufficient enlightenment about the inner structure of this
process from either Berkeley or Kant, and also knows that he cannot receive
sufficient information from contemporary philosophy, he falls back to the
point of departure of recent discussion, which he recognizes as the content of
the confrontation between Kant and Hegel. It is astonishing that this resump-
tion of a discussion that is generally assumed to be concluded comes from a
theoretician who, together with others, organizes 'teamwork' through which
applied mathematics and the most modem techniques are placed at the
disposal of processes of management and production. Also to be noted, aside
from this, is the state of controversy in which at least two positions confront
each other: the assumption that future events can be precisely predetermined
and carried through on the basis of a stringent calculus; the other assumption
being the prediction of transitional probabilities, the concrete fulftllment of
which unconditionally involves human activity, and must keep open any
system of human beings or of human beings and machines. 13 Churchman
related his theoretical generalizations to the domain of empirical research,
and confirms that in their effective execution these go in principle beyond
the boundary set by the strict rules of formallogic. 14 The procedure of those
philosophers like Hegel, who subsume under 'logic' the whole process of
developing an understanding of world, as well as of those natural scientists
who use the term 'logic' to cover all the methods by which they reach their
conclusions in empirical research, may be understood as parallel modes of
thOUght. Accordingly, it becomes understandable that Churchman includes
Karl R. Popper's logic as an argument for the validity and justification of
Hegel's logic, although Popper can also be considered as the antipode of the
Hegelian dialectic. In another passage Churchman calls Hegel's result a
dialectical theology. However, it is possible to use the dialectical method
more significantly in order to describe a SOCiological, materialistic process
without God. IS What deserves to be especially noted is that the dialectical
method can be applied to nature and to society, and, as we may see from
Churchman's own account of the state of affairs, actually is being applied
246 HERMAN LEY
thought consists in the limitation imposed on human beings at that time, but
in the sense that thereby there can be actual knowledge corresponding to the
current stage of development. If, for Hegel, the categories and the concepts
of objects are delimited with respect to each other, on the other hand they
are congruent with respect to their reference to contents, the range of which
goes beyond merely formal correctness. Hegel arrives at a formulation which
formally French Structuralism could lay claim to for its use, but which
receives a different evaluation in Hegel's context. 19
So also Francis Bacon's "natura non nisi parendo vincitur" receives a
corresponding modification in Hegel when applied to the process of knowl-
edge. By setting object and subject as approximately equal, it would seem
obvious that the thesis of the domination of nature by man or the purely
instrumental function of concepts should be accepted. But quite the con-
trary: Hegel emphasizes the objectivity of object and subject as confronting
man, whose product is explicitly conceived of as the achievement of con-
cepts. In the categories and concepts of objects, what Hegel calls the universal
presents itself, with which man, for his part, has to comply. It is far removed
from Hegel to conceive this dialectic between man, the products of thought
and the confronting objects in an indefinite manner; the objectivity of the
products of thought achieved by man, even with regard to man himself, is
maintained with all definiteness. 2o Not to go beyond the nature of things
means for Hegel not to be able to elevate oneself above the understanding of
things. If Hegel says the objective concept of a thing constitutes the thing
itself, then philosophically a limit is given which is practically effective, but
which also must be understood historically. With such a term as 'the objective
concept of things', taken by itself, it appears that philosophy is proclaiming
a closure of knowledge in its own time. But just as Hegel sets about the
determination of the categories historically, so the concept of things is no less
historical. Forms of thought and knowledge are conceived as determining and
dominating man, because in them, as it were, the horizon is revealed which
contemporary man of each period has created, and which only he will be
capable of transcending when the forms of thought and the rest of his
cognitive activities have absorbed other contents.
While Kant insists on absolute original 'root' concepts of pure understand-
ing, Hegel insists on their changing character, which appears as a 'moment' of
becoming and therefore signifies a limitation that continually strives to go
beyond itself. The dialectical method seeks to grasp the historical process but
surely not as history, not only because it comes after the fact like the owl
of Minerva and begins its flight in darkness, but because it universalizes
HEGEL'S RELATION TO THE SCIENCES 249
undeveloped material of his time, which only achieved broader validity with
delay, and which suggest modification of the philosophical generalizations
widely held and considered valid until then.
As an identity philosopher and philosophical idealist, Hegel hesitates to
simply accept the 'nature of things' which he considered. He does not
subjectivistically deny the existence of things, but sees in the "object ...
nothing else but our notions of it" (SL [M], p. 36). Even if we reject a
relation of our thoughts to the thing, still Hegel seeks to avoid the suspicion
that the concept present in the subject is in any way made independent and
does not permit any distance between the subject and its objects, which
always act only corresponding to the level of consciousness.
With that Hegel seeks to clarify his own position and that of critical
philosophy. Thoughts should not stand between us and things, nor should the
medium [of thought] shut us off from things.22 Insofar as Hegel thinks of a
mediation, it does not shut consciousness off from things but instead "joins
us with them". In Hegel's understanding the identity is mediated by the
concept of the thing and by the categories, and therefore directed toward
something definite. If thinking, in Hegel, belongs to the abstract form of
labor, yet he also occasionally comes to the more concrete means, to which
externality is explicitly ascribed. As against "our very own, innermost, act"
(SL [M], p. 36) the external means is markedly contrasted; precisely through
this characteristic, the external means reaches a meaningful significance which
at first is negligible to Hegel, as it is his main concern to bring subject and
object more closely together, in order to re-evaluate the constructive form of
thought, as well as to bring theoretical thinking into closer contact with
objects epistemologically. With that, Kant's concern to draw closer methodo-
logically to the active operation of the understanding is given adequate scope
philosophically; but precisely in this way the positive and dialectical form of
mediation is emphasized. In Hegel's understanding, the categories, insofar as
they intervene mediatingly into the process of thought, prove to be the
vehicle which permits us to get at the thing itself. But as, in addition, the
development of knowledge also remains to be treated in terms of its own
mechanism, the external means appear as a complement to the categories,
which also contain, as it were, a measuring function, and aside from that also
interveRe in the overall process.23 Hegel sees them entering into the process
in combination with the goal-setting activity of man.
Without moralizing or going so far as to postulate goal-free activity, as the
Preface asserts at least partially with respect to scientific activity, nevertheless
goals belong within the domain of mediation. Of finite content, it inserts
HEGEL'S RELATION TO THE SCIENCES 251
another object between itself and the result, as Hegel expresses it, whereby
the 'cunning of reason' asserts itself. To characterize the total difference
between it and formal logic, and the merely formal function of its content-
determined categories, Hegel's content-determined logic takes this other
object to be the means of the external middle-term of the inference; and the
middle-term is the carrying out of the goal. Since we are concerned with
finite goals, as Hegel presents it, the objects of the external middle-term of
the inference are also not to be understood in any absolute sense. They
change and turn out to be concrete means, without being something rational
in-and-for-themselves [an und fUr sich]. Themselves 'moments' of mediation,
they mediate something higher. If the categories and concepts of the thing
itself were conceived as limits which would not have to serve as means of
domination by man, then, following Hegel's stylized way of speaking, the
case would be different with respect to objects, which are an 'external
middle' term and should properly be conceived as subordinated, if one were
to understand them within the framework of Hegel's understanding.
As contrived as this train of thOUght may seem, and as mannered as the
composition of Hege1's text may appear, so too, with closer explication or
later completion of the stages of thinking, are we far removed from the
exactitude demanded, say, by Mario Bunge. Since Hegel subsumes structures
of various kinds under what he wants to consider included under 'essence',
these structures can, so to speak, be of internal and external configuration. In
the case before us, where Hegel speaks of that mediation which emerges from
finite purposes, in his view rationality asserts itself in externality.2 4 Given
that Hegel has reduced the thing-in-itself to the concept and sees the cate-
gories arising from this, which fundamentally are not restricted to the number
found either in Aristotle or in Kant, and which in their turn again dominate
consciousness, nevertheless, on the other hand, toward the end of the Science
of Logic, human activity is by no means confined to merely inner activity.
Completely in keeping with the understanding of the seventeenth and
eighteenth-century Enlightenment, from the two Bacons through Diderot,
and including Descartes, it is tools that give men power over external nature.
But in contrast to these aforementioned periods of the Enlightenment, Hegel
analyzes a reciprocal relation that unites the position of the world-outlook
with the methodological position, and utilizes analysis for that purpose. The
relationship of the 'thing itself, the categories and consciousness are con-
strued in terms of the world-outlook, while with respect to a dialectical under-
standing, the dialectical identity, which is not that of formal logic , is brought
forth only methodologically. The goals are, as it were, products of the
252 HERMAN LEY
in the concept, Hegel also points to the contradiction between the means
inserted between man and nature, which alone let becoming come to totality.
Thereby the merely passive concept appears as one side of the contradiction,
which, when without realization and without retraction, remains an empty
and unfulftlled demand; it thus lacks the other side of the contradiction.
Hegel's dialectic is already confronted with the later critics of technology in
that they, just like the theorists of 'post-industrial society' , fixate on only one
side of reality. But as Hegel speaks of becoming, then knowledge does not
mean the exclusion of history, nor does the domain of means signify the
destruction of humanity. Becoming consists in the unity of the diverse
moments, which are formulated as the task of human beings and of society,
and only evading these tasks can represent withdrawal from this historical
process.
How broadly Hegel interprets the term 'concept' is shown when he points
to natural, scientific and mental development, in which the natural, in
contrast to the others, has been moved to first place. When Hegel speaks of
'concept', the material side, and also that side which is in the process of
becoming accessible to consciousness is included in his meaning. However,
since what is involved is always a becoming that includes the negation and
overcoming of the negation, the structures of what is real develop no less
than their images, and refer to each other. Accordingly, merely to be a
concept also means for Hegel a germinating and embryonic existence, which
must yet make its way to the full concept and complex manifestation. But it
is from this too that Hegel's remark comes about the equality of the whole
and its parts. The parts are accepted as representation of the whole, and the
whole as that of the parts, without the other dialectical category thereby
being revoked or overcome [aufgehoben] , namely, that as against its parts
the whole possesses a special quality. Hegel came to the assumption that a
tautology was expressed by this, which only gains its truth through mediation
(SL [M], p. 51St), and thereby receives an additional meaning. It appears
simultaneously as an inner and an external qlovement, which comes to
expression in things [Sachen] and in instinctual activity.
In the 'Preface' Hegel does not let freedom of the mind be dependent
solely on consciousness. The so-called unmediated unity with the subject
serves as the beginning. Freedom of the mind begins when what is conscious
is brought to objective status before the subject, and no longer remains
merely split up among the categories. In the dual Signification of Hegelian
diction, the logical business, as he calls it, is meant, and the transition into
reality, as well as further knowledge made fruitful by this. What is involved
256 HERMAN LEY
here, side by side, is the fundamental determination of the reality of the mind
and of reality itself, which man appropriates. According to this, it is doubly
efficacious categories that concern Hegel. They are only considered to be
appropriated by the understanding, if they have to the same extent passed
through confirmation in reality.32 The fixed points and nodes are considered
to be the life and consciousness of mind; and in the same way they are
considered to be an essential relation, i.e., law. Since becoming and objec-
tivity have a specific function in Hegel's philosophy, a further dialectical
antinomy appears in this, which belongs to the state of affairs to deny which
means a so-called prettifying of things. If law is defined as essential relation,
then it is not to be demanded o fit , that it be valid always and everywhere in
all possible worlds; rather proof of the existence of certain essential relations
suffices, and the domain of their validity will then follow as a possible further
question from this.
What is brought to consciousness can be the state of affairs as such, as well
as the universality of the claim to validity. In the categories of the dialectic
Hegel finds fundamental determinations of the reality of mind; these have
had to emerge and thus are also a product of development. Becoming itself,
however, appears as the inevitable state of affairs, which can never be dis-
pensed with. If the categories are expressly affected by this, then their
development applies to the domain of overarching mediation, in the first
place, for example, society, and then, natural, scientific and intellectual
development, all of them states of affairs in which development is linked to
the emergence of new conditions.
No matter that one or another discipline may have had a more rigorous
conception of modern science than was available for Hegel, for the discovery
of a logic of development is the achievement of this philosopher. Although
both the natural sciences and social theory could already show the beginnings
of a concept of evolution, the generalization of these attempts has not
appeared till then. As the revolutions of the bourgeoisie and the Third Estate
- now brought more or less to a conclusion - had shown there is develop-
ment in society, it was time for a hypothesis about the course of human
history accomplishing itself in this development, whether contingent or
necessary. Hegel sought for a historical understanding of society, and in this
he encountered the historical character of the determinations of thought, the
reciprocal connections of which he treated, in modern technology, synchroni-
cally and diachronically; and by this he sought to represent the truth in
process, but not in the manner of formal logic. If the formal logicians are
shocked by Hegel's application of a sequential algebra of truth, it must be
HEGEL'S RELATION TO THE SCIENCES 257
content and form arouse the suspicion of being stuck in medieval scholas-
ticism - although a hardly appropriate judgment is pronounced upon the
schools of the latter in that way - then the assumption of fluid categories
proves to be suitable to pry the categories of content and form loose from
their mutually unrelated confrontation. If content and form were related
to each other as matter and entelechy, or material substance and configura-
tion [Stoff and Gestalt], then Hegel would seem to want to include various
categories in both traditional determinations of thought. Since content is not
to be debased to empty form, and as 'moments' of content are granted to
form, while at the same time a change of content and form should be grasped
in a formal sense as well as developmentally, Hegel can claim an enrichment
of the empirical material that enters into thinking about objective things.
Content and form no longer confront each other dualistically and cease to
incorporate spiritualistic dualistic elements within themselves. The original
root concepts of the understanding do not remain in the transcendent space
of the a priori, nor settle in the same realm as a collection of performed
possible formations. The Aristotelian separation of content and form meant a
dualism, which, Hegel felt, was contradictory to his identity philosophy in its
approach; for the same reason it had already lost its cogency in the tradition
of the young Schelling.
Hegel seeks to approach content and form in accordance with their
structure, by proceeding from the object of investigation, in which content
and form are conceived as fused, and thus no actual separation occurs. From
this Hegel concludes that the separation of content and form is an activity of
the understanding, something worth reflecting upon, and indeed simple self-
reflection can give rise to notable results. The separation of content and form
by the understanding does not create, so Hegel assumes, any content without
form neither in the absolute unformed Aristotelian matter nor in Spinozistic
substance. Since Hegel, without exception, imputes to things a heuristic
dialectic and process of becoming, and thinking thereby is induced to find
such states of affairs, so form must be found in so-called content, a form
whose inspiration and shape, as Hegel figuratively expresses himself, can
always be found in what can be called content. If the categories, as determin-
ations of thought, are to be distinguished from the 'thing' and to be advanced
before consideration in thought, then the result is the definite concept in
which, in fact, dialectically linked content and form are to be found, and
constitute a substantial unity?4
If the manner of expression seems more or less awkward, still Hegel
explains why it is that scientific concepts are capable of conferring knowledge
HEGEL'S RELA nON TO THE SCIENCES 259
ble to theory and praxis. Along with the emphasis on the determinateness of
concepts, Hegel expressly holds that the indeterminations of the individual
object will not escape thought. Against naked empiricism, Hegel emphasizes
the grasp possible with theoretical thinking. Whether the data and facts
secured by observation or the basic propositions necessary for theoretical
derivation possess absolute validity, or are to be understood as relative,
remains a secondary problem at Hegel's stage of identity philosophy. Deter-
minateness and at least the coming-to-be of the 'means' and of consciousness,
including the categories, are regarded as properties of one thing. As Hegel
subsumes contradiction and [evolutionary] development under dialectic, he
does not come into conflict with his simultaneous respect for freedom of
thinking from contradictions defined by formal logic. In Hegel's under-
standing, the analogical procedure that differentiates various applications of
models already unambiguously signifies the dialectical contradiction within
the same mathematical structure. Hegel sees another dialectical contradiction
in the difference between the individual and the universal, which character-
izes every statement formulated in consciousness, even when it is supposed to
refer expressly to an individual object, but especially when generalized
theoretical discussions are involved, whether these be formalized or not.
Insofar as awareness seems to be intensified, it is seen that methodologically
secured rigor at the same time requires creative imagination, fantasy, within
the domain of fundamentally scientific expertise.
This active experimental approach to concrete objects and domains of
objects, in Hegel's understanding, aims to obtain the corresponding structures
by hard work. How Hegel gets from the multiplicity of empirical objects to
structure is treated with a certain naivete which belongs to a problematic
since then taken up again and again, from time to time. Obviously, for Hegel
the concept stands above the concrete object. If the concepts are what is real,
then Hegel seems to stay completely within classical realism of universals? 5
On the basis of the conception of this identity philosophy, however, the
relation to objects shows itself to have the same import as old conceptual
realism and naive copy -theory [of perception] ? 6
In contrast to the classical conceptual realism, as Hegel sees it, sensuous,
spatial and temporal, palpable existence are just as far from complete as the
concept, because both contain 'moments' that can only be elevated to the
'idea' together. Among these, Hegel understands the unity of the 'concept
and reality'. In connection with this, 'reality' points to that palpable exis-
tence which meanwhile has been conceived as externality, and as far as
Hegel's text is to be understood, contains laws and structures as a field of
HEGEL'S RELATION TO THE SCIENCES 261
internal relations. If, to begin with, Hegel speaks of reality as the external,
he then goes on to relate reality primarily to inner systematic coherence, to
be characterized more or less as the universal, or approximately, say, as a
'white box', as an approach which permits adequate characterization. How
this is to be achieved occupies Hegel because of the obvious denigration in his
time of scientific concept or, as we would say now, of theoretical thought
as against [immediately] palpable existence.
In the opposition of the concrete and the abstract, Hegel offers a quite
simple, but not unimportant delimitation of the two categories. If the
palpable counts as more admirable, as superior to the concept, then the
concept meets with the reproach the "it lacks so much of this kind of
material."37 But Hegel assumes that scientific procedure operates in just that
way. Since concepts are credited with a unified connection with reality, the
various terms utilized at the same time mean something like representation,
or image, but in which the constructive 'moment' of the understanding and
its activity find adequate consideration. Palpable existence is to be found in
the attributes to which reference is made. They do not function under the
criterion of any completeness required by the thing, but only that of being
sufficient. It is assumed that the object or the domain of objects can be
reduced in the multiplicity of its properties and characteristics to a smaller
number, without impairing its worth. Without any particular added specula-
tion, Hegel assumes that scientific thinking omits a greater number of known
properties and characteristics, at least in the formation of concepts, and does
so, indeed, not for subjective reasons, although these can be decisive too, but
for objective reasons which can be derived from the thing itself. It is expressly
attested for the understanding, that it is not a question of its inability to
appropriate the overwhelming multipliCity that confronts it. Rather, it is the
reverse, a property of the understanding to proceed in an appropriate manner,
and thereby just allow that adequacy of thing and concept, which Hegel does
not understand as a literal total mirror-image. Nor is the Aristotelian equality
of thing and concept accepted, for it too is subordinated to the process of
becoming, namely to the development of the scientific concept itself.
Accordingly, which features are of interest is subject to a catalogue of
influences in the Hegelian dialectic, through which the value and dignity of
the object only begin to assert themselves; thereby something is assumed
which is similar to distinguishing the essential from the unessential parameters
in working out structures in systems analysis. As Hegel considers the existence
of things to be given, he does not require any aMitional speculation about
the range of the capacity of the understanding. He considers it sufficient to
262 HERMAN LEY
NOTES
1 Charles Sanders Peirce to William James, Oct. 3,1904: "More or less explicitly, some
writers, namely the Thomists, the Hegelians, and other Intellectualists, together with
some scientific thinkers not too much sophisticated by reading philosophy, recognize
with me (until I shall have studied your views, which I don't believe will carry me
entirely away from this anchorage) three modes of consciousness, that of feeling, that
of EXPERIENCE (experience meaning precisely that which the history of my life has
FORCED me to think; so that the idea of a struggle, of not mere twoness but active
opugnancy is in it), and thirdly, the consciousness of the future (whether veridical or
not is aside from the question) ... " Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. 8 vols.
(Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1931-1958), Vol. VIII. Reviews, Corre·
spondence and Bibliography, ed. by Arthur W. Burks, 1958, p. 202.
2 K.-O. Apel, 'Peirces Denkweg vom Pragmatismus zum Pragmatizismus', in Charles
S. Peirce, Schriften II (Frankfurt a. M., Suhrkamp, 1970), p. 18.
HEGEL'S RELATION TO THE SCIENCES 265
permeate all our ideas - whether these are purely theoretical or contain matter belonging
to feeling, impulse, will - are means for us, rather than that we serve them, that in fact
they have us in their possession; what is there more in us as against them, how shall we,
how shall I, set myself up as more universal than they, which are the universal as such"
(ibid., Preface to the Second Edition, p. 35).
20 "Or again, to speak of things, we call the nature or the essence of things their notion,
and this is only for thought; but still less shall we say of the notions of things that we
dominate them, or that the determinations of thought of which they are the complex
are at our service; on the contrary, it is our thinking that must accommodate itself to
them, and our caprice or freedom ought not to want to mould them to suit itself. Since,
therefore, subjective thought is our very own, innermost, act, and the objective notion of
things constitutes their essential import, we cannot go outside this our act, we cannot
stand above it, and just as little can we go beyond the nature of things" (ibid., p. 35f.).
21 Ibid., p. 32: "The advance of culture generally, and of the sciences in particular,
gradually brings into use higher relationships of thought, or at least raises them to greater
universality, and they have thus attracted increased attention. This applies even to the
empirical and natural sciences which in general employ the commonest categories, for
example, whole and parts, a thing and its properties, and the like)."
22 "The way critical philosophy understands the relationship of these three terms is
that we place our thoughts as a medium between ourselves and the objects, and that
this medium instead of connecting us with the objects rather cuts us off from them. But
this view can be countered by the simple observation, that these very things which are
supposed to stand beyond us and, at the other extreme, beyond the thoughts referring
to them, are themselves figments of subjective thought, and as wholly indeterminate
they are only one single thought-thing - the so-called thing-in-itself of empty abstrac-
tion" (ibid., p. 36).
23 "Further, since the end is f'mite it has a finite content; accordingly, it is not an
absolute, nor simply something that in its own nature is rational" (ibid., p. 747).
24 "But the means is the external middle term of the syllogism which is the realization
of the end; in the means, therefore, the rationality in it manifests itself as such by main-
taining itself in this external other, and precisely through this externality. To this extent
the means is superior to the finite ends of external purposiveness: the plough is more
honourable than are immediately the enjoyments procured by it and which are the ends.
The tool lasts, while the immediate enjoyments pass away and are forgotten. In his tools
man possesses power over external nature, even though in respect of his ends he is, on
the contrary, subject to it" (ibid.).
2S E. Nagel, The Structure of Science, Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation
(New York, Harcourt, Brace and World, 1961), p. 15: "As we shall see, such explana-
tions may be offered for individual occurrences, for recurring processes, or for invariable
as well as statistical regularities."
26 V. I. Lenin, 'Conspectus of Hegel's Book, The Science of Logic' in Philosophical
Notebooks, vol. 38 of Collected Works (London, Lawrence and Wishart; Moscow Foreign
Languages Publishing House, 1961), p. 190.
27 Georg Lukacs, History and Class Consciousness. Studies in Marxist Dialectics. Trans.
Rodney Livingstone (cambridge, Mass., MIT Press, 1971), p. 129f.: "It is important to
realise that if we take action in the sense indicated above to mean changing reality, an
orientation toward the qualitatively essential and the material substratum of action, then
268 HERMAN LEY
the attitude under discussion will appear much more contemplative than, for instance,
the idea of knowledge held by Greek philosophers. For this 'action' consists in predict-
ing, in calculating as far as possible the probable effects of those laws, and the subject
of the 'action' takes up a position in which these effects can be exploited to the best
avantage of his own purposes. It is therefore evident that, on the one hand, the more the
whole of reality is rationalised and the more its manifestations can be integrated into the
system of laws, the more such prediction becomes feasible. On the other hand, it is no
less evident that the more reality and the attitude of the subject 'in action' approximates
to this type, the more the subject will be transformed into a receptive organ ready to
pounce on opportunities created by the system of laws and his 'activity' will narrow
itself down to the adoption of a vantage point from which these laws function in his best
interests (and this without any intervention on his part)."
28 "Non omnino improbabile est, materiam et quantitatem esse realiter idem." See also
SL [M], p. 189f. where Hegel continues: "In fact, the distinction between these two
concepts is simply this, that quantity is a determination of pure thought, whereas matter
is the same determination in outer existence."
29 "But profounder insight into the antinomial, or more truly into the dialectical nature
of reason demonstrates any Notion whatever to be a unity of opposed moments to which,
therefore, the form of antinomial assertions could be given. Becoming, determinate
being, etc. and every other Notion, could thus provide its particular antinomy, and thus
as many antinomies could be constructed as there are Notions. Ancient scepticism did
not spare itself the pains in demonstrating this contradiction or antinomy in every
notion which presented itself in the sciences" (ibid., p. 191).
30 "Thus law is essential relation" (ibid., p. 511).
31 "This makes itself apparent in all natural, scientific and spiritual development
generally and it is essential to recognize that because something is at fIrst only inner or
also in its Notion, the fIrst stage is for that very reason only its immediate, passive
existence" (ibid., p. 526).
32 " ... when the content of the interest in which one is absorbed is drawn out of its
immediate unity with oneself and becomes an independent object of one's thinking,
then it is that spirit begins to be free, whereas when thinking is an instinctive activity,
spirit is enmeshed in the bonds of its categories and is broken up into an infinitely varied
material. Here and there in this mesh there are firm knots which give stability and
direction to the life and consciousness of spirit; these knots or nodes owe their fixity and
power to the simple fact that having been brought before consciousness, they are
independent, self-existent Notions of its essential nature. The most important point for
the nature of spirit is not only the relation of what it is in itself to what it is actually, but
the relation of what it knows itself to be to what it actually is; because spirit is essen-
tially consciousness, this self-knowing is a fundamental determination of its actuality."
33 "The inadequacy of this way of regarding thought which leaves truth on one side
can only be made good by including in our conception of thought not only that which is
usually reckoned as belonging to external form but the content as well. It is soon evident
that what at rust to ordinary reflection is, as content, divorced from form, cannot in fact
be formless, cannot be devoid of inner determination; if it were, then it would be only
vacuity, the abstraction of the thing-in-itself; that, on the contrary, the content in its own
self possesses form, in fact it is through form alone that it has soul and meaning ... "
(ibid., p. 38f.).
HEGEL'S RELATION TO THE SCIENCES 269
vexing since it is one of his very few utterances about the function of the
work as a whole. He there refers to the book as "the deduction of the
concept of science" and assigns the concept, thus deduced, the formidable
role of being the necessary presupposition for his otherwise presupposition-
less Logic. 1 The Logic, on the other hand, takes up in its first chapter a
subject matter which seems to bear no resemblance to that of the second half
of the Phenomenology. It begins with 'pure being'. And if we ask what this
might be, the immediate context does not seem to be very illuminating, for
we are only told what 'pure being' is not: it is not definite and it is not
mediate. It is "das unbestimmte Unmittelbare (WL [1812] 1, p. 22)". In fact,
it is said to be nothing more nor less than Nothing.
This famous and irritating beginning of the Logic has been the object of a
considerable literature. 2 But, as in the case of the Phenomenology, nothing
like a critical consensus has been arrived at. The Logic continues to be read,
but its beginning remains an enigma.
Given this situation, it would be foolhardy simply to assert that the mysteries
of the Logic might be unlocked by referring all difficulties of its beginning to
the Phenomenology, as its presumptive 'deduction'. For, as we have seen,
the Phenomenology itself is no less problematical than the Logic. But perhaps
some light might be cast on the question of the Phenomenology's subject
matter if the question of its argument were focussed by the problem of the
beginning of the Logic. The aim of this paper is to explore the conjecture that
the Phenomenology, when read as a "deduction of the concept of science,"
will reveal more clearly the nature of its subject matter.
As we have seen, the subject matter at the beginning of the second half of
the Phenomenology, 'Geist', is remarkably akin to that of Aristotle's practical
philosophy. It is also strikingly different from the traditional subject matter
of German Idealism, i.e., the 'Ich'. Now when we look at the pages of the
Logic immediately preceding the treatment of 'pure being', we find that
Hegel explicitly contrasts 'Ich' and 'Geist' with respect to the problem of an
absolute beginning in science. An examination of this discussion, "Womit
muss der Anfang der Wissenschaft gemacht werden?" (with special reference
to the recently republished 1812 edition), will suggest an interpretative
conjecture concerning the Phenomenology.
The section begins with the statement of what appears to be a dilemma.
On the one hand, the result of the Phenomenology, 'pure knowing', is said to
HEGEL'S DEDUCTION OF THE CONCEPT OF SCIENCE 273
be presupposed by the Logic, the pure science (WL [1812], p. 6). On the
other hand, an absolute science must itself be an absolute beginning, and as
such it may presuppose nothing (WL [1812], p. 7). If the Logic is taken to
begin as a science of the absolute, it will therefore be incompatible with the
Phenomenology. Since Hegel has explicitly affirmed that the Logic does
require and must presuppose the "deduction of the concept of science," and
that the Phenomenology is this deduction, the implication seems to be that
the Logic does not and cannot have an absolute beginning.
An explication of this, at first sight, impossible dilemma is to be found on
the next page of the 1812 edition. The paragraph in question has been
discussed only rarely in the Hegel literature; and since it is critical to our
problem, it will be well to cite it entire:
In der ersten so eben gegebenen Darstellung des Seyns als des Anfangs ist der Begriff des
Wissens vorausgesetzt. Somit ist dieser Anfang nicht absolut, sondern kommt aus der
vorhergehenden Bewegung des Bewusstseyns her. Die Wissenschaft dieser Bewegung
[i.e., the Phenomenology of Spirit], aus der das Wissen resultirt, miisste nun den
absoluten Anfang haben. Sie macht ihn mit dem unmittelbaren Bewusstseyn, dem
Wissen, dass etwas ist. - Das Seyn macht so hier gleichfalls den Anfang, aber als Bcstim-
mung einer eonereten Gestalt, des Bewusstseyns; ERST DAS REINE WISSEN, DER
GEIST, DER SICH VON SEINER ERSCHEINUNG ALS BEWUSSTSEYN BEFREYT
HAT, HAT AUCH DAS FREYE, REINE SEYN ZU SEINEM ANFANG. - Aber jener
Anfang, das unmittelbare Bewusstseyn, enthiilt das leh als bezogen auf ein schleehthin
Anderes, und umgekehrt, den Gegenstand bezogen auf leh; somit eine Vermittlung. -
Zwar entha:it das Bewusstseyn die beyden Vermittelnden - die aueh wiederum die
Vermittelten sind, - selbst, weist somit nicht tiber sich hinaus, und ist in sich beseh-
lossen. Aber indem die Vermittlung gegenseitig ist, so ist jedes Vermittelnde auch
vermittelt, somit keine wahrhafte Unmittelbarkeit vorhanden. - Aber umgekehrt,
wARE eine solche vorhanden, so ist sie, DA SIE NICHT BEGRUNDET 1ST, etwas
WILLKURLICHES und ZUFALLIGES (WL [1812], p. 8 - emphasis added).
As in the case of Plato's recollection myth, which is said simply to trans-
port the paradox of learning (Meno, 80E) to another level, Hegel's remarks
concerning the beginning of logical science and its derivation from the
Phenomenology have been seen as a dodge. In the light of this paragraph,
however, we see that Hegel clearly distinguishes between two ways of begin-
ning and two types of subject matter in which these beginnings may be made.
The one kind of beginning is absolute, but not immediate. The other is
immediate, but not absolute. In the former, immediate consciousness begins
absolutely, with the knowledge that something is. It is absolute because
consciousness refers to nothing beyond itself. It simply affirms the absolute
identity of what is 'for it', pure being, and what it takes itself to be, the pure
Ich. As the affirmation of a relation, however, consciousness is not immediate
274 KENLEY ROYCE DOVE
but rather the reflective mediation of the Ich, identified with what is for it
(the object), and the object, identified with the Ich. Both terms of this
identity are therefore mediating and mediated. And to affirm the immediacy
of either by itself would be to remove it from the absoluteness of the
identity, to declare it fortuitous, arbitrary, and groundless. C:onsciousness is
therefore the subject of the absolute way of beginning. It begins with an
absolute grounding, the identity of its terms: the Ich and pure being. And this
is the beginning of the Phenomenology, the shape of consciousness called
'Sense Certainty'. .
The other way of beginning, which is immediate but not absolute, first
becomes possible as the result of the movement (Bewegung) which begins
absolutely with consciousness and through which 'Geist' is "liberated from
its appearance as consciousness." As such, it is said to be 'pure knowing' and
to have 'pure being' as its beginning. 'Pure being' was also the beginning,
indeed, the absolute beginning of the 'Ich' in the Phenomenology. But, as we
have seen, it was there a term in a relation of absolute identity, the unity of
consciousness. At the end of the Phenomenology 'pure being' becomes a
beginning, the beginning of 'pure knowing', now conceived as Spirit purified
of all relation to an object, pure spiritual unity (geistige Einheit). Here there
is no absolute beginning because there is no absolute ground; spiritual unity is
pure immediacy, immediacy as the result of a process of purification. And
through this process, consciousness, which began the movement described in
the Phenomenology with an absolute grounding, seems to have become
groundless.
These observations suggest that the key problem for a coherent interpreta-
tion of the Phenomenology will be an understanding of how spiritual unity
emerges through the movement of mediation which begins with the absolute
identity of the 'Ich' and its object. Put in its most concise form, the question
is how Spirit emerges - and is not simply introjected - in the' Wissenschaft
der Erfahrung des Bewusstseins'. Is this Science continuous with the
'Wissenschaft der Phiinomenologie des Geistes'?
To this end it will be important to notice that the absolute identity of
consciousness is absolute only from a standpoint independent of conscious-
ness. Hegel makes this point most clearly in his Jena lectures of 1803-04.
"Aber dies Bewusstseiende, und das, dessen es sich bewusst ist, ist nur fUr
einen Dritten diese Einheit des Bewusstseins, nicht fur sie selbst ... ".3 In
the Phenomenology it is clear that this 'third' is the 'Wir', who observe the
entire development of consciousness from its absolute beginning to its
'Aufbebung' in pure knowing. 4 The absoluteness of the beginning of the
HEGEL'S DEDUCTION OF THE CONCEPT OF SCIENCE 275
Phenomenology must be seen to consist not merely in the identity of the two
terms of consciousness, Ich and object, for this inner reflective unity is an
absolute unity only by means of an 'external reflection', or 'fUr uns' (see
WL [L], 2, p. 18). The 'Wir' is therefore a constitutive element of conscious-
ness from the point of its absolute beginning and because it is an absolute
beginning.
It must be noted, however, that the absolute unity of consciousness with
which the Phenomenology begins is not posited by the 'Wir'. The 'Wir' is
rather pre-thematically posited by consciousness as the necessary condition
of its claim to absoluteness. The development of the argument in the book
may therefore be read as a progressive thematization by consciousness of that
ultimate, but at first abstractly posited ground of its absoluteness: the 'Wir'.
The Ich of consciousness therefore has two objects, the one with which it
identifies itself as a knowing subject, and the other the essential ground on
which its claims of ultimate or absolute identity with its first object are
based. In its relationship to the first object, the Ich takes itself to be absolute-
ly certain of itself. It is absolutely at one with its object. But as the knowing
subject in an absolutely scientific mode of knowing, it must also express the
truth conditions, the grounds, for its certainty. And thus it begins the process
of thematizing its second object. This second object is at first taken to be
simply the Ansich or the essence of the certainty constituting the relation to
the first object. But when consciousness actually expresses what it takes the
absolute ground or essence (Ansich or Wesen) of its certainty to be, the
ground expressed reveals itself to be merely an Ansich or essence for con-
sciousness and not something in itself or absolute. We therefore see that
consciousness, as consciousness, cannot immediately thematize its ground;
it cannot, as Hegel so strikingly puts it, "shoot the absolute out of a pistol."
But it does take the now thematized essence or Ansich to be new ground for
its subsequent truth claims. And this process of mediation in which con-
sciousness progressively thematizes its absolute continues throughout the
Phenomenology.
The movement (Bewegung) of consciousness presented in the Phenomeno-
logy may therefore be understood as a sequence of stages (the 'Gestalten des
Bewusstseins'), each of which is defined by the fundamental truth claim that
consciousness has come to the point of thematizing. But although the
Gestalten are discontinuous, each being defined by a definite Ansich, all share
the form of consciousness as such, all are forms of knowing in which a subject
takes itself to be related to an object. Viewed in this way, we can also see that
this movement will have a terminus, namely, at that stage when knowing no
276 KENLEY ROYCE DOVE
II
NOTE
1 The question whether Hegel later, i.e., after 1812, retracted this interpretation of the
Phenomenology has been the subject of a considerable literature. In addition to the
reminder that Hegel explicitly reaffirmed this view in the last year of his life (see the
second edition of the first book of the Science of Logic), the reader may be recommend-
ed Hans Friedrich Fulda's masterful survey of the critical literature in his book, Das
Problem einer Einleitung in Hegels Wissenschaft der Logik (Frankfurt, Klostermann,
1965).
2 A critical review of nineteenth century attacks and defenses of the beginning of the
Logic may be found in Dieter Hemich's short essay, 'Anfang und Methode der Logik',
Hegel-Studien, Beiheft 1.
3 Jenenser Realphilosophie, ed. 1. Hoffmeister. 2 vols. (Leipzig, Meiner, 1932), Vol. 1,
p. 201. Cf. Phon [H. 1937], p. 74.
4 For a more detailed discussion of the question of the 'Wir' in the Phenomenology, see
my essay, 'Hegel's Phenomenological Method', Review of Metaphysics 23 (1970), 615-
641.
5 See WL [1812], p. xii; WL [L] 1, p. 30;Phiin [H, 1937], p. 549.
6 "Die einfache Unmittelbarkeit ist selbst ein Reflexions-ausdruck, und bezieht sich auf
den Unterschied von dem Vermittelten" (WL [1812], p. 7).
HEGEL'S DEDUCTION OF THE CONCEPT OF SCIENCE 281
. . . there are, in the first place, other ways of approaching Nature which I will
mention, not for the sake of completeness, but because we shall find in them the
elements or moments which are requisite for a knowledge of the Idea and which
individually reach our consciousness earlier in other ways of considering Nature
(PN, p. 4).
Only in this fashion, Hegel concludes, will we really comprehend what truly
characterizes the philosophical or scientific approach to the realm of Nature:
the need, at the outset, to synthesize properly the practical and theoretical
approaches to Nature.!
In this brief paper, I would like to highlight the relation (dialecti-
cal or otherwise) between the practical and theoretical elements in Hegel's
283
simply by so doing transforms it into something human, even though only formally
human, into ideas and purposes (SL [M], pp. 31-32).
Brooklyn
CUNY
NOTES
1 "In so doing [considering other ways of approaching Nature 1, we shall come to the
point where the characteristic feature of our inquiry becomes prominent. Our approach
to Nature is partly practical and partly theoretical. An examination of the theoretical
approach will reveal a contradiction which, thirdly, will lead us to our standpoint; to
resolve the contradiction we must incorporate what is peculiar to the practical approach,
and by this means practical and theoretical will be united and integrated into a totality"
(PN, p. 4).
2 "Die theoretische Arbeit, iiberzeuge ich mich taglich mehr, bringt mehr zustande in
der Welt als die praktische; ist erst das Reich der Vorstellung revolutioniert, so halt die
Wirklichkeit nicht aus." Cited by F. Nicolin and O. Piiggeler, 'Zur Einflihrung' in G. W. F.
Hegel, Enzyklopiidie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830) (Ham-
burg, Meiner, 1959). p. XXII.
L. D. EASTON
Among the Ohio Hegelians - an informal group of writers and social re-
formers who championed Hegel's thought in Cincinnati from 1848 to 1860,
prior to the St. Louis Philosophical Society - John Bernard Stal10 was
outstanding in mastery of philosophy and public influence.! His special
interest was philosophy of science, the underlying principles and assumptions
of physics, chemistry, biology and sociology and the foundations of knowl-
edge in those areas. Pursuing this interest in his teaching and writing, he
concentrated on two main points he found in Hegel: first, the thesis that all
experience and the actualities of nature and society are essentially process,
becoming, development, evolution; secondly, the thesis that the real nature
of things is not to be found in a separate realm, a 'beyond' that transcends
experience, but rather in the phenomena themselves taken concretely in their
verifiable connections and context.
In applying and interpreting these two theses Stallo also criticized Hegel,
thus anticipating his mature philosophy of science that professed to repudiate
Hegel altogether. Stallo's relation to Hegel from the beginning was that of
critical follower. In the preface to his first major writing in 1848, The General
Principles of the Philosophy of Nature, Stallo wrote: "I cheerfully acknowl-
edge that for many of my views I am indebted to the study of Hegel's
philosophy, although, generally, these views are as independent of Hegel as
Hegel is (if it be permitted magnis componere parva) of Schelling."
Stallo absorbed Hegel's views from 1841 to 1848 while he was studying and
teaching mathematics, physics and chemistry at St. Xavier's College in
Cincinnati and St. John's College at Fordham, New York. In his native
Germany his schooling had included mathematics and languages, and at a
teacher's college in Vechta he had been exposed to Kant's view of space and
time and the relation of concepts to sense-impressions. But apparently Hegel's
writings were among the 'forbidden books' in his boyhood home. A few years
after his arrival in Cincinnati in 1839 at the age of sixteen, he began studying
Hegel, Schelling, and Humboldt "with great enthusiasm." These studies came
287
R. S. Cohen and M. W. Wartofsky (eds.), Hegel and the Sciences, 287 -299.
© 1984 by D. Reidel Publishing Company.
288 L. D. EASTON
II
Mind is the absolutely Restless in itself the absolutely Creative, the absolutely Free.
Mind is not the blank abstraction, not the caput mortuum of the External. The Deity,
the absolute Mind, is the absolute intrinsic process - the substance which causes, pro-
duces itself, - gazes into its own eye. 4
"There is," Stallo concluded, "nowhere absolute rest, but motion every-
where." Further, those who hold that there must be some material substance
as a fixed, unchanging substratum behind changing phenomena cannot
possibly square their view with Dalton's law of compression of gases or
Graham's law of diffusion. With such arguments as these Stallo was more
concerned than Hegel to control his conclusions by the empirical data of
natural science.
The fmal and longest section of Stallo's statement of his own philosophy
of science was entitled 'Evolutions.' It provided details on the "phases and
processes" in physical motion, the solar system, light, sound and heat,
chemical combination, electricity, vegetable and animal organisms, recreative
and procreative mind, and the organization of society. This section was the
heart of Stallo's philosophy of science, applying and seeking to confirm his
central thesis concerning process, movement, activity. It also revealed the dis-
tinctive features of his view and thus how he differed from and criticized
Hegel.
Stallo used the word 'evolution' synonymously with 'process,' 'develop-
ment,' 'origination,' and he thought of it as progressive, 'spiral' movement
towards increasing complexity of organization and greater multiplicity of
relations. He was well aware that Hegel had used the term 'Evolution' to
HEGEL IN STALLO'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE 291
refer to the serial progression in nature from the imperfect and formless
liquid element through fishes and land animals to man. But Hegel had dis-
missed this as "a completely empty thought." It explains nothing and in some
respects is inferior to its correlative opposite, the Oriental idea of 'Emanation.'
For Hegel the only 'development' and 'origination' is in the Notion which
"timelessly and in a universal manner posits all particularity in existence." On
this basis he concluded, in spite of his reading in Lamarck and Kant, that
species do not change, that organic fossils never really lived, and that the
"lightning of life" strikes a complete creature into previously lifeless matter
like Minerva from the brow of Jupiter. "The Mosaic story of creation," said
Hegel, "is still the best in its quite naive statement that on this day planets
came into being, on another day the animals, and on another day man"
(PN, pp. 20-22,284).9
Stallo, on the other hand, regarded "generative modification of certain
species" as empirically substantiated and saw organic fossils as evidences of
"the consecutive advance of vegetable and zoological genera." By implica-
tion he dismissed the Mosaic story as a form of occasionalism that is as
external as the purest materialism to the mediated unity of efficient and final
causation. Stallo agreed with Hegel that temporal succession is inapplicable
to the true ground of all nature, absolute Mind or Spirit as "absolute intrinsic
process." Its relation to its phenomenal manifestations is tenseless as in the
relation of whole or part, and Stallo frequently referred to the Absolute,
following Hegel, as 'the Whole.' But the essential nature of the Absolute is to
manifest and realize itself in the phenomenal and material world characteriz-
ed by spatiality and temporality. "Consequently," Stallo concluded,
"whatever is in the Spiritual as unital intensity is likewise found in material
nature, therefore in time and space as succession and co-arrangement.',lO
Apparently, then, Stallo's use of 'evolution' as a synonym for 'process,' 'deve-
lopment,' and 'becoming' was not accidental. It signalized his differences
from Hegel, integrating process more closely with empirical data of natural
science and providing a more coherent position than Hegel had achieved.
Stallo frequently used 'history' as a synonym for 'process,' 'becoming,'
and 'evolution.' It has been suggested that Hegel temporalized the realm of
spirit in history but generally denied the historical development of nature
because of his conservative temperament in a pre-Darwinian age. ll Stallo also
lived in a pre-Darwinian age but had the audacity and originality to try to
resolve the dualism between a non-historical nature and a historical realm of
spirit in a more coherent, thoroughgoing evolutionism. His exposition of
evolutions widely followed Hegel's Naturphilosophie in its sequence or
292 L. D. EASTON
subject matter, and even some of Hegel's subtitles, from mechanics and
motion through the solar system, light, chemical combinations, and organisms
to end in a discussion of sexuality. But then Stallo went on to elaborate
evolutions in what Hegel had separated from nature as subjective and objec-
tive mind, namely, perception, imagination, memory, reasoning, mental
derangements, the organization of society in family, civil society, and state
and finally the major phases of mankind's history.
In sum, Stallo held that Hegel's position on process, becoming, and devel-
opment was abortive. It was not thoroughgoing but was still infected with
static substantialism, an appeal t6 a fIxed entity or 'thing' as the basis of
explanation. Hegel invited this criticism, Stallo felt, in maintaining that every
true philosophy must stand on the platform of Spinozism. Though Hegel saw
clearly that the existence of things is their becoming (Werden) - hence Stallo
could reverently regard him as 'one of the philosophical saviours of nature" -
he was not consistent and thoroughgoing in the application of this insight. His
construction and his method still belonged to the old school that makes 'the
thing' the basis of its deductions and changeless rest the fundamental fact. As
a result, said Stallo,
His consequences are not infrequently fallacious, and his transitions are arbitrary. He is
like a man who has invented gunpowder; now he wishes to shoot but unfortunately with
the old weapon, the lance, and at the same time to keep the lance in his hand. Hence also
the unintelligibility of his language, the jargon of real and ideal "positing," of being at
itself and for itself (an sich and for sich) etc. 12
III
Further interpreting Hegel, Stallo defended a second main thesis for philoso-
phy of science, namely, that the real nature of things is not to be found in a
separate realm, a 'beyond' that transcends experience, but rather in the
phenomena themselves taken concretely in their connections and context. 14
Negatively this thesis involved a rejection of transcendent metaphysics, the
view that 'reality' lies in a separate realm that observed phenomena somehow
copy or reflect. Mfrrrnatively it asserted that reality or truth is to be found in
phenomena, and in this respect it is akin to current philosophies of experi-
ence - empiricism, phenomenalism, positivism - which vigorously criticize
transcendent metaphysics and seek its elimination from responsible thought.
This thesis has already been suggested in the previous discussion of Absolute
Mind or 'the Whole' as process. Such a conception outlaws any fixed,
unchanging substance or entity that might serve as a permanent reality behind
or beneath changing phenomena.
In his General Principles Stallo was especially attracted to the way that
Hegel overcame the dualisms between idea and reality, subjective and objec-
tive, spirit and matter left by Kant's philosophy. By resolutely eschewing
'abstractions' or "some hypostatic notion of universality," Hegel could
provide an effective unification of science and metaphysics. As Stallo put it:
Hegel does not attempt to evolve concrete forms from an abstraction; his "Absolute" is
essentially concrete .... Since truth is apprehended not as something reposing in the
bosom of its own being, but as the "Whole in its development," as the Absolute, not
abstractly taken, but also in its phenomenal existence, in its individual exterioration,
the system of metaphysics, which formerly consisted of nothing but formalities, must
encroach upon the domain of all science. Instead of an establishment of certain forms,
merely for construing the various material, form and material now stand in necessary
relation; the material - nature, etc. - enter as essentially into metaphysical reasoning
as the old formulas. It cannot, therefore, be startling to see that the natural sciences,
history, etc. are an integral part of metaphysics. 1s
Following Hegel in his view of perception and observation, Stallo held that
external objects are not somehow engraved on the mind but rather their
particularities become general qualities and relations. Objects are not some·
thing transcendent to their qualities and properties. Rather, ''the predicates
are the subject; they are not glued, plastered upon it, and torn off when the
subject is idealized. Everything exists in its properties, not beside them."
These properties, moreover, are basically an ensemble of relations. "Objects,"
294 L. D. EASTON
We look into the interior of things only through the phenomenon; the interior itself is
transcendental, a "beyond" for our consciousness. The transcendental interior, however,
reveals nothing whatever to consciousness; no more, to use Hegel's own simile than pure
darkness or pure light reveals anything to the gaze. But the supersensual "beyond"
results from mediation; it proceeds from the phenomenon, and the phenomenon is its
reality. The Supersensual is but the Sensual taken in its truth, taken as phenomenon and
not as a permanent reality, which it has amply proved itself not to be. We behold the
play of forces, a continual shifting of determinate appearances, whose truth consists
merely in the law which manifests itself there. The law is the permanent image of the
fleeting phenomenon. The supersensual world is the quiet realm of laws, indeed beyond
the world of observation, since this exhibits the law only in continuous change; but it is
nevertheless present in the world of observation and its immediate type)7
But even as he praised Hegel for fusing the Absolute and phenomena and
thus advancing what might be called a 'concrete phenomenalism' in opposi-
tion to transcendent metaphysics, Stallo was critical of Hegel in this respect.
There were, Stallo felt, numerous abstractions in Hegel's view, points where
the Absolute did not exist in and through the phenomena but remained
independent of the empirical data of natural science. In short, there were
numerous points where Hegel held to a "hypostatic notion of universality"
as in traditional metaphysics.
We have already noted how Stallo found an element of static substantia-
lism in Hegel's view and criticized his treatment of process in nature as
abortive, as failing to embody the transitions and movement of phenomena.
In developing his own view of evolutions in physics, Stallo widely followed
Hegel but sometimes digressed to criticize him for failing to fuse idea and
phenomena. For example, he noted that Hegel's view of single and double
diffraction of light did not account for certain observed deviations or distor-
tions, and the mutual dependencies of refraction and reflection as well as the
limit of refraction could not be derived from his theory at all. 1S Though
HEGEL IN STALLO'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE 295
The General Principles three decades earlier. The theory of cognition was
fundamental in Concepts and Theories, and Stallo regarded it as the central
point and purpose of the whole book. It undergirded his continuing criticism
of materialism, the "atomo-mechanical view of nature." The atomic theory,
he allowed, was useful in chemistry as an expository device, but for its most
vigorous defenders it was "substantially identical with the cardinal doctrines
of ontological metaphysics" and could not in main features be squared with
data of observation and experiment. Stallo's theory of cognition was also the
basis for detecting 'metaphysical errors' that he illustrated in detail in the last
eight chapters of Concepts and Theories where he criticized the 'absolute
space' of Newton and Euler, the notion of absolutely independent physical
objects, and cosmological speculation about "the origin of the universe as an
absolute whole in the light of physical and dynamical laws."
The first point in Stallo's theory of cognition asserted that thought deals
not with things themselves but with "states of consciousness" and every
object of cognition is a synthesis of subjective and objective elements so
"all knowledge is relative to the cognizing faculty." He had said substantially
the same thing in The General Principles where, following Hegel's Pheno-
menology, he saw perception and observation as involving an interchange
between conscious mind and apparently external objects and the reality of
consciousness in and through them. Secondly, Stallo's theory of cognition
asserted that objects are known through their relations and have no attributes
except through their relations. In 1848 he based this conclusion on Hegel's
view that the 'sense certainty' of objects perceived as 'here' and 'now'
involves grasping them as relationships, but in 1881 it was supported from
Helmholtz's research on vision. Helmholtz, as Stallo may have known, had
attributed the nineteenth century schism between philosophy and science to
Hegel's Naturphilosophie that seemed "absolutely crazy" to the scientists,
an attempt "to construct a priori the results of other sciences.,,23 The third
main point in Stallo's theory of cognition asserted that thought deals only
with a selected class of relations, so our thought of-things is always 'symboli-
cal.' Concepts and Theories identified this point with views of Leibniz and Sir
William Hamilton, but in The Phenomenology of Mind, which Stallo had
summarized three decades earlier, Hegel maintained that abstractions ("things
of the intellect") are indispensable to perception. In wider implications of
this theory of cognition, which Stallo called 'phenomenalism,' there was a
vivid echo of Hegel's coherence theory of truth. "There is no physical reality,"
Stallo held, "which is not phenomenal. The only test of physical reality
is sensible experience." What, then, about the conflicting deliverances of
HEGEL IN STALLO'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE 297
IV
Early and late in his lifetime Stallo saw his philosophy of science as implying
and supporting freedom of inquiry, the fullest freedom of mind. He was
aware that Hegel had supported freedom of inquiry in discussing the relation
of church to state but had grounded it in constitutional monarchy. But Stallo
held that only a democratic republic, not monarchy, is "adequate to the
idea." Only democracy is consonant with Hegel's premise that the substance
of society and history is spirit as reason, and reason, Stallo argued, involves
the unity of system and relationship, not the extraneous unity of a single
man. Universal reason in society is nothing but law reproducing itself in and
from the individual. "The organization of society," he concluded, "is, there-
fore, essentially democratic." Furthermore, social development is a 'dialecti-
cal process' in which partial points of view and particular errors are required
298 L. D. EASTON
for the emergence of truth. Such a process requires freedom of thought and
inquiry as its essential medium. Similarly, but on different grounds, Stallo
saw his mature philosophy of science - his phenomenalism that professed to
repudiate Hegel altogether but actually extended major 'Hegelian lines' -
as a means of freeing intelligence for growth and openness to experience. Of
his Concepts and Theories of Modem Physics he said:
Its tendency is throughout to eliminate from science its latent metaphysical elements, to
foster and not repress the spirit of experimental investigation, and to accredit instead of
discrediting the great endeavor of scientific research to gain a sure foothold on solid
empirical ground, where the real data of experience may be reduced without ontologi-
cal prepossessions. 26
Thus Stallo's philosophy of science in its beginnings and in its maturity was
fully and unswervingly committed to freedom of thought and inquiry, to the
free mind.
NOTES
1 For biographical and historical details see L. D. Easton, Hegel's First American
Followers, The Ohio Hegelians - J. B. Stallo, Peter Kaufmann, Moncure Conway, and
August WilUch (Athens, Ohio University Press, 1967), Chs. I-III presenting the nub of
the main theses in this essay, but here those theses are developed further, with details of
Stallo's criticism of Hegel.
2 Cf. Franz Wiedmann, Hegel, trans. 1. Neugroshel (New York, Pegasus, 1968), pp. 32-
33,36,44.
3 J. B. Stallo, The General Principles of the Philosophy of Nature (Boston, Crosby and
Nichols, 1848), pp. vii-viii. Some sixty pages of this scarce book are reproduced, with
original pagination in square brackets, in an appendix to Easton, op. cit.
4 Ibid., p. 43.
5 Ibid., p. 333, 345.
6 Cf. Stallo, General Principles, pp. 50-51.
7 General Principles, p. 44.
8 Ibid., p. 24; cf.ibid., pp. 51, 345,45-46.
9 Encyclopiidie der Philosophischen Wissenchaften ed. G. Lasson (Leipzig, Felix Meiner,
1930), §§ 249, 339. (Stallo used the Michelet text and Zusiitze of Hegel's 'Natur-
philosophie. ')
10 General Principles, p. 44; cf. ibid., pp. 6-7, 11-12.
11 Cf. J. N. Findlay, 'Foreword,' Hegel, Philosophy of Nature, trans. A. V. Miller
(Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1970), p. xv; Hegel, A Re-examination (New York, Macmillan,
1958), p. 272.
HEGEL IN STALLO'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE 299
12 General Principles, p. SO
13 For further details and specific documentation in Emerson's writings see Easton,
op cit., pp. 45-49 and A. W. Plum stead, and W. H. Gilman, eds., The Journals and
Miscellaneous Notebooks of Ralph Waldo Emerson (Cambridge, Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press, 1975), Vol., XI, p. 200.
14 Cf. 1. N. Findlay, 'Some Merits of Hegelianism,' Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society 56 (1956), pp. 7 -9.
15 General Principles, p. 337.
16 Ibid., pp. 131-34.
17 Ibid., p. 360.
18 Ibid., p. 74.
19 Ibid., p. 72; cf. ibid., pp. 158-62,517-18.
20 Stallo, Reden, Abhandlungen und Briefe (New York, Steiger, 1893), p. 112.
21 Stallo, Concepts and Theories of Modern Physics, ed. P. W. Bridgman (Cambridge,
Mass., Harvard University Press), p. 178; cf. ibid., pp. 6-7.
22 Cf. ibid., pp. 10-11; Stallo, "Speculative Science," Popular Science Monthly 21
(1882), pp. 151-53. In General Principles Stallo did not summarize Hegel's views on
language in Philosophy of Mind (trans. William Wallace from The Encyclopaedia of the
Philosophical Sciences (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1894), § 459), views that resembled his
own mature conclusions at some points. Cf. Easton,op. cit., pp. 215-19.
23 Cf. W. C. Dampier-Whetham, A History of Science (New York, Macmillan, 1929),
p. 313 quoting from Helmholtz, Popular Lectures on Scientific Subjects, trans. E.
Atkinson (London, Longmans, Green, 1873), p. 5.
24 Cf. Stallo, Concepts and Theories, Ch. IX, p. 216; General Principles, pp. 131-35,
354-57;Phen [B], pp. 168-78,80-81.
25 Ernst Mach, 'Vorwort' (1901), J. B. Stallo, Die Begriffe und Theorien der Modernen
Physik, trans. H. Kleinpeter (Leipzig, Barth, 1911), pp. x-xiii.
26 StallO, Concepts and Theories, p. 4; cf. General Principles, pp. 158-67,517-18 and
PR, §§ 270, 275-80.
PART THREE
It is clear that the method in question here is the dialectics. That there are
different forms or models of dialectics is again not to be doubted. I am allud-
ing here not only to Plato's dialectics, but to post-Hegelian dialectics, the
Marxist and the Neo-Marxist models. Even within the restricted range of
Hegelian dialectics, there are many models possible, for instance, the dialecti-
cal models of Well and Kojeve and others.? Leslie Armour has given recently
yet another model of Hegelian dialectics in his Logic and Reality [Assen,
1972] . From the logical point of view many variations of dialectics can be
conceived, for instance the models of GUnther, Asenjo, Kosok and my own
models. It is not surprising then that logicians like Beth s and Lorenzen 9
express a strong scepticism about the interest and the validity of dialectical
logic, notwithstanding the efforts of contemporary Soviet logicians. To put it
bluntly, the dialectical method is not a logical method and Hegel's endeavour
from a logical point of view does not deserve the name 'logic'.
3. How can we escape such a devastating criticism? It will not suffice to say
that most logicians do not know anything about Hegel's logic. If it is objected
that Hegel's logic is at the same time and indissolubly an ontology or a meta-
physics,1O the critics can add to their arsenal the charge of irrelevance.
Hegel's dialectical logic thus seems unsalvable. It would not do either to argue
that Hegel's logic has no similarity at all with classical or orthodox logic and
that is what explains most misunderstandings. There are, to be sure, non-
classical systems of logic, e.g. many-valued systems or intuitionistic logic, but
their spirit of logical revisionism does not affect the foundations themselves,
but specific logical laws, like the law of excluded middle. I do not plead here
for logical exclusivism, I am only dispelling illusory hopes or expectations.
What are we left with, if we still want to pursue a formal approach to
Hegel's logiC? If we exclude non-classical or unorthodox approaches and I
do not see what in Hegel's logic would compel us to abandon classical logic -
the subsequent analysis of Hegelian logic tries to justify that statement -
there is a variety of standard methods that can be used. It seems to me, for
example, that one could do for Hegel's logic what Chomsky has done for
transformational grammars, to propose a recursive treatment. Of course,
natural languages and ontologies or ontologics are subject to algorithmic
limitations that make it difficult to transcend the level of trivial generalities,
but with the help of recursive analysis, one could defme, for example, the
generative structure of the dialectical scheme, the invariance properties of
dialectical determinations or moments, the continuity of dialectical passage
(Uebergehen) from one moment to the others, the formal conditions of the
306 YVON GAUTHIER
circularity of the system, and so on. Another closely related approach is the
combinatory approach. I have made some suggestions in that direction in a
previous paperY Here one concentrates on the logical operations of Hegel's
system and attempts to show their reducibility to some fundamental
constants, their inter-connection, the cyclic permutation oflogical categories.
One could then obtain a relational logical algebra in the sense of Curry.12
Both approaches, the recursive and the combinatory ones, share a common
idea: the algebraic perspective. The general algebraic approach seems to me to
be a fruitful undertaking. Boolean structures, group structures, graph
structures, lattice structures, all could contribute to a better understanding of
Hegel's logiC. The question is how to apply those abstract structures to
Hegel's particular form of logic. Uses and abuses proliferate. One has only to
remember the intricacies of quantum logic. The problem of Hegel's logic is
not without similarity with the situation in quantum logic. However,
quantum logic has to do with a more limited (non-simultaneously measur-
able observables), if not less ambiguous, state of affairs. The solution devised
for quantum logic, the modular lattice, has only a faint affmity with the
logicisation of Hegel's logic. Hegel's logic, as was pointed out above, is
constituted by an interpretation which covers up, supposedly, an axiomatic
skeleton. I indicated how a very close analysis of Hegel's work was necessary
to avoid substituting an alien model to Hegel's model of dialectical logic,
since as Asenjo rightly emphasizes, "But here there are too many existing
applications of dialectic that are far from convergent.,,13
In my opinion, attempts to formalize Hegel's logic all suffer from an
insufficient interpretation of Hegel's writings, mainly Die Wissenschaft der
Logik. Formal treatments of dialectics, despite their intrinsic interest, have to
be judged on their relevance for Hegel's logic and at the same time for their
logical fertility. I have explained earlier that formalisation in the case of
Hegel's logic has a special meaning: formalisation does not exhaust the
content of Hegelian dialectics, it aims at disentangling the structural features
of the dialectics or, as Hegel puts it, the form of the self-movement of the
content from the content itself. In particular full axiomatisation in the usual
sense is excluded. On the other hand, I insist upon that point again, the
mathematical-algebraic-structures used in the formalization must have a
logical meaning. Very often a mathematical structure serves to represent a
logical relation, but it remains an empty representation or an 'analogical'
abstraction; it gives then only a formal image without any real gain as far as
explanation or foundational depth is concerned.
HEGEL'S LOGIC FROM A LOGICAL VIEWPOINT 307
University ofMontreal
NOTES
INTRODUCTION
Hegel then comments, however, that " ... the necessity of connection and the
immanent origination of (these) distinctions must show themselves in the
discussion of the subject matter, for they are part of the self-development of
the concept" (SL [J/S] 1, p. 66). And what is this "necessary connection"?
Hegel goes on to say that "That by means of which the Concept forges ahead
is the ..... Negative which it carries within itself; it is that that constitutes
the genuine dialectical procedure" (SL [J/S] 1, p. 66).
DYNAMICS OF HEGEL'S DIALECTICS 313
Now this all important 'Negative', which the concept carries within itself,
which forges the true dialectical movement, is introduced by the very bold
statement that "The one and only thing for securing scientific progress is
knowledge of the logical precept that Negation is just as much Affirmation as
Negation ... " (SL [J/S] 1, pp. 64-65), and this declaration reappears in the
form that "neither in heaven nor on earth is there anything not containing
both Being and Nothing" . . . because Being and Nothing "are absolutely
distinct and yet ... inseparable" and furthermore "This unity of Being and
Nothing, as being the primary truth, is, once and for all, the basis and element
of all that follows: therefore, besides Becoming itself, all further logical deter-
minations such as Determinate Being, Quality, and in short all philosophical
concepts are examples of this unity" (SL [J/S] 1, pp. 95,97). In summary,
Hegel refers to this both singular and universal paradox of being and nothing
or affirmation and negation (or immediacy and mediation) characterizing at
once his whole science and the dialectic, as the 'aujheben' or transcending
process in which "a thing is transcended only in so far as it has come into
unity with its opposite ... " (SL [J/S] 1, p. 120), a transcendence process
which Hegel in his preface refers to as the 'immanent soul" of the content of
knowledge and the "schema of movement of all concrete knowing" (SL [J/S]
1, p. 37).
Thus, all the various complex identities, divisions and headings Hegel
displays in his system are in themselves not the content: it is the self-develop-
ing Negative as a 'scheme of movement' which is the only content, and as a
schema of movement it must serve as the basis or 'soul' of all concrete know-
ledge. What one must grasp, therefore, is this schema or dialectic movement
in its singular and universal nature if one is to judge the significance and
relevance Hegel has for the sciences of knowledge as we know them today,
and not get lost in an analytic dissection of the various categories or identi-
ties which Hegel clearly dismisses as being besides the point. Indeed this very
distinction that Hegel makes of the categories in-themselves as not being the
content but rather their necessary connection and origination, should warn
the reader that any attempt to hypothesize this movement-of-identities into
a set, sequence, or algebra of well-defined terms is doomed from the start,
and thus should the reader disdainfully display a proof that all sorts of self-
contradictions appear when analyzing the movement of distinct terms as
separate entities in relation, or that the movement of terms can be reduced to
a given pattern of relations, then he would merely be displaying his ignorance
of what the point of the whole dialectics is in the first place.
Grasping directly the essential point being made, however, takes us on a
314 M.KOSOK
voyage totally removed in spirit from what our usual conception of logic or
structure is, if our training and conditioning rests upon a heavy dosage of
what is usually referred to in the sciences as 'linear-thinking' ... and unfor-
tunately our most cherished responses and habits of consciousness are so
weighed down with automatic 'linear-response' that we are not aware most of
the time of the type of assumptions and Simplifications introduced by this
mechanism of linearization . . . . it appears so 'natural' that it disappears as a
problem. And yet, it is precisely this problem of linearity that not only
characterizes the paradoxes and boundaries of all the modern sciences and
humanities, but at the same time becomes the means, when properly resolved,
by which Hegelian dialectic reappears transformed as a revolutionary perspec-
tive of integration and transcendence for the sciences and humanities as they
are developing today.
Both the problem of linearity and Hegel's paradoxical unity of being and
nothing or affirmation and negation can be grasped with the understanding of
what is involved in the activity of 'identification,' or simply put, what one
means by the 'identity' of that which our awareness is concerned with. To
identify means to bring into focus a certain element, quality, fact, condition
... a certain event, state of events or experience in such a way as to be able
to refer to it in some categorical way. Without identification, our awareness is
in a state of immediacy which is not defined in relation to categorization.
This, however, means that a genuine state of immediacy cannot be charac-
terized as either including or excluding any mediation or categorical state lest
this immediacy is 'itself then perceived as an identified state and hence not
immediate. Thus, true immediacy is not an irrational/indeterminate anti-
categorical state of dissolution in opposition to a rational/determinate
categorical state of resolution, since both involve a specification or positing of
specific qualities. Indeed, a state of direct:presence and immediacy presents a
logical paradox right at the beginning for not only cannot it be regarded as a
well-defmed element capable of being identified with a given 'truth value,'
but this very 'lack of value' cannot be regarde4, upon reflection, as its
identity either. Identity of any kind sets limits and boundaries, while a state
of immediacy is a trans-b,ounded 'totality' or 'singularity', meaning that it
cannot be regarded as either determined positively by the presence of a
boundary or negatively by the absence of a boundary, for both presence and
absence, inclusion or exclusion of limits or boundaries are mediations or
modifications delimiting and defining that which it stands in relation to.
Even the notion of trans-bounded, if identified or localized by appearing
in opposition to non-trans-bounded, cannot describe immediacy, yet
DYNAMICS OF HEGEL'S DIALECTICS 315
and all becoming is self-becoming and transformation. Not grasping the e ,e',
e" e-ing state of immediacy within which the + and - functions develop,
reduces dialectics to an absurdity, and makes non-linearity in the sciences a
mystery. Hegel, unfortunately, did not explicitly spell out the whole
dynamics of such a non-linear self-mediation process, and as a result it
became easy to get lost in a myriad of categories instead of becoming free of
them. Thus the boundary-transitional nature of Becoming, resting as it does
on both the distinctness of +e and -e and the inseparability of +e and -e,
was not sufficiently brought out as an immediate transition from Being
appearing simply as e, and here is where a marriage of Hegelian dialectics with
non-linear topology in mathematics would be extremely fruitful, for each is
involved - from a different perspective - with the same problem. Hegel's
triad of Being, Nothing and Becoming, when analysed in detail amounts to
the same logic as presented here (i.e. this is not a sequence of Being, then
Nothing and then Becoming) but the singular dynamics of its origination is
somewhat obscure.
Now the importance of such a dynamics of immediacy, being the unfold-
ment of what-is and revealing the coming-to-be of identities in a non-linear
topology or context-of-relations, is that it does not present one with an
identity structure predicated on a given structure, but rather is totally void
of specificity other than the experience of immediacy. To the degree to
which one does experience himself-in-the-world as a dynamic immediacy,
together with the forming and transforming of his identities and categories
of immediacy, then to what degree will this dynamics reveal itself in and
through the identities appearing and not appear as an external structure or
mold into which to put or place an assortment of categories, if what has been
presented does 'correspond' to the life and structure of immediacy. This in
tum implies that the 'test' of meaningfulness such a dynamics of immediacy
or dialectic has for knowledge in general and for the sciences in particular
initially rests on the degree to which one is capable of regarding his total
being-in-the-world - namely his feeling, ideas, actions and thoughts in terms
of such a dynamic of self-transformation. Otherwise, this scheme of move-
ment merely becomes but a more complex identity structure as linearized
into a pattern of relations as any other system. This means that all the various
identities and boundary conditions continually confronting one's existence
must be grasped in their paradoxical state of transition and levels of transi-
tion, including of course any reflected notions of the dynamics of immediacy
itself when regarded as a structure among other structures in the world of
dynamic appearance. The paradoxical state of dialectic self-becoming is thus
320 M. KOSOK
not only about immediacy, but also, paradoxically, within immediacy, and
one must not therefore conclude that the present form of analysis, using as it
must linear words and symbols historically conditioned, is the /ast-analysis.
However, the beauty - if you will - of a paradoxical dynamic structure, is
that its own transition as a structure of identifiable elements is not a contra-
diction to its power of revelation, but is indeed exactly that which must be
expected if it does indeed reveal the continual self-negating and transforming
nature of any identity! Paradoxical non-linear dialectics is never an end (Le.
an identity finally given), but always a beginning, and hence is a logic of
creativity and revolution whose activity is the revelation in depth of aware-
ness - and thus self-awareness, for as we have seen, all mediation and reflec-
tion is always self-mediation and self-reflection - the world of dynamic
appearance being the content of this awareness.
te' represents the original state of direct relation between being and nothing,
each one posited as itself, -e' would reveal an inverted counter-relation in
opposition to this posited state and this would mean a state in which being
appearing as nothing would be in relation to nothing, appearing as being.
Thus, -e' as 'counter-becoming' would be a relation of terms each one of
which appears as its opposite in order to counter +e' in which each term
appears only as itself. Hence, if +e' represents, for example, an energy
exchange relation between charges (of electricity), -e' would represent an
inverse energy exchange relation between the same charges, tending to
counter-act and stabilize a transition state into two transition states moving
in opposite directions. In terms of a general topological dynamics, whereas
e' in effect appears as a relation due to a simple balance of two opposite
elements as a result of a self-differentiation of e into te and -e, e" now
appears as a balance of two opposite relations, appearing as a result of a
self-differentiation of e' into te' and -e', producing a singular relation-of-a-
relation. This, of course, means that in e", not only must there exist +e and
-e elements, producing a posited relation, but each in turn must also mirror
its opposite in order to manifest a counter-relation between them, which,
at the same time, mirrors the original relation of transition between them,
also within each. Thus, intuitively, a second level two-dimensional relation of
dialectic opposition reveals not only X and Y, let us say, as oppositions, but
also its inverse as X(Y) and Y(X), such that there are four X - Y relations:
the direct relation between X and Y, the counter-relation between (Y) and
(X), the relation within X (between X and (Y)) and the relation within Y
(between Y and (X)). Finally, there is the en tire structure as a whole, which is
nothing but the X - Y relation now taken not as a simple one-dimensional
unity, but as a self-differentiated unity - i.e. a unity of unities, or a unity
between X and Y each of which is also an XY unity. (This nine-term analysis
is an intuitive simplification of the formal two-dimensional, nine-term matrix
appearing on page 322.) Clearly, higher order matrices would then not only
develop further unity within unity within unities, but each quantitatively
higher order dimension would require a higher order topology of relations in
order to grasp all possible relations as a Singular dynamic whole: a three
dimensional reflection would have to spell out 27 terms, simultaneously
related in a three-dimensional space thus displaying qualitatively newer
modalities of existence not previously visible. Thus the dynamics of imme-
diacy not only represents the initial 'triad' of dialectics non-linearly, but
subsequent triadicies continually expand the dimensionality or perspective of
the dynamics present and hence the nature of the terms one is in relation to,
DYNAMICS OF HEGEL'S DIALECTICS 325
of the immediacy of being or e. It is hence only within e' that the negative
makes its first appearance. This means that e" as the development of e' will
now start with both being and negation as positive immediacies in +e', and
only then develop each of these as mediated negative terms in -e', wherein
the original positive and negative immediacies within +e' each now reveal
their complimentary opposites (i.e. being revealing negation and negation
revealing being through mediation). However, since +e' or posited becoming
is also the asymmetric movement of being into negation, -e' is then the
counter asymmetric movement of mediated being into mediated negation -
or negation back into being: -e' is thus the anti-state of counter-becoming
balancing the original state of becoming +e', such that te' or e" is now both
the symmetric balance of becoming and antibecoming, and the asymmetric
movement of being into becoming-its-negative (e into e') which has now in
turn expanded with a return movement of negation back to being, for only in
e" do we first find a double-negative term (--e) representing the return
movement of being from negation. Thus e, e' and e" develop an overall cycle
from immediate being (e), through being-revealing-the-becoming-of-negation
(e') to the becoming-of-negation, re-revealing the presence of being as a
return state (e"). In e" being is revealed as the end-state of all becoming,
because now being reveals itself through negation as self-being or being-for-
self. Quality as the full dynamics of e, e', e" is thus the permanence of being
or immediacy through any determination, limit, negation or becoming. The
nine-term matrix e" is thus the full self-determination of being or e and it is
this matrix of double-transition which is the essential building unit of Hegel's
logic, as much as any triad of single transition is the interconnecting move-
ment or energy which constitutes the component aspects of such units.
Specifically, the details of the dynamic unit of Quality e" can best be re-
vealed by returning to our initial cycle or triad e' where we can see the cycle
itself recycled, first determined as an immediate positive cycle, then as the
mediating negative cycle. (i.e. the cycle e' will be recycled as +e' -e' and te'
all within e", just as e originally appeared as +e, -e and te within e'.) In the
immediate or positive cycle, all the forms present are now in immediate form,
which means that the original selfmediated state of becoming +-e containing
+ and - in mutual identification now collapses as Hegel often puts it, into
only an immediate form of itself: the Being and Nothing or + and - within
Becoming or e' appear' as indifferent immediates or distinctions which have
not yet explicitly developed each opposite within itself (Le. e' is now part of
itself as e" which is to develop). This leaves us now with the mediating or
negative cycle. Here all the forms present become mediated: the positive
DYNAMICS OF HEGEL'S DIALECTICS 327
appears mediated into the negative, and the negative mediated into the
positive, each immediate or apparently indifferent term revealing the other
within and relative to itself. Consequently the identity between the positive
and negative which was originally totally immediate in the cycle e' , and which
in the positive cycle appeared as a paradox of two immediacies in a co-
immediate state, has now become self-separated in the negative or mediating
cycle because each immediacy is now turned to the opposite within it as a
derived opposite, and is not directly or immediately in relation with the
opposite 'itself. Each opposite appears self-bound and not other-bound. In
Hegel this means we have moved from the initial or positive triad of Being
Nothing and Becoming (itself called Being) to the triad of Determinate Being.
Relative to this triad, Being or the positive form of the first cycle appears as a
determined Being called Something or Finitude (mediated self-referral), while
Nothing or the negative appears as a counter-determined Other or Non-finitude
(the bad infinity of open-ended other-referral): the 'Something' is actually
Being acting in a delimited negative way, i.e. it is a bounded system, while
the 'Other' is actually negativity acting in a positive way - i.e. it is the context
or the determinate space within which the system as a something appears
determined: Determinate Being is System in a Context (Diagram, p. 345).
Now the unity of the Something and Other (the two fundamental oppo-
sites on the negative level) is naturally not the state of immediate becoming
or the co-immediacy of Being and Nothing, but rather the mediated state of
Anti-Becoming, or the co-mediated state in which a determined Being and a
determined Negation relate to each other as apparently external elements.
This, however, immediately collapses, for the system and its context in
unity generate a synthesis called True Infinity - each determinate Being (as
a something) in revealing within itself Negation, in turn is but a revelation of
the negative itself qua Other, which relative to its domain in turn is the
revelation of Being: i.e. being externalized within negativity is now a return
to immediate Being. This, hence, leads us to consider the unity of the positive
or immediate cycle of BeCOming and the negative or mediating cycle of
Determinate Being, for not only does a system and its context now ex-ist as
distinguished independent and self-related entities, but each in turn has
revealed the dependency and other-relatedness previously expressed directly
in the pure state of Becoming.
In the self-mediated cycle, then, each opposite, both the positive and
negative, now express a total cycle of return, for each opposite is (1) both
its immediate presence and hence in a direct relation to its opposite as a co-
immediate (2) a revelation of its complementary opposite as a derived or
328 M. KOSaK
mediated presence within itself separating each opposite from its immediate
relation to its actual immediate opposite and now (3) a return to itself
through its own opposite - i.e. a return as a self-mediated immediacy having
explicitly developed within itself its own opposition. This means, however,
that the opposites, as immediates are once more in a direct relation of unity
with each other as in Becoming, but at the same time, each is also a unique
monad of the other within it. Hence each opposite itself is in a state of Self-
Determination and a unity of opposites, while at the same time the opposites
together are also in a state of direct unity: This is the Being For Self stage in
which the unity of being and nothing is also a unity of unities: Being, having
emerged into a determined Something or system, returns to itself as the One
of Attraction; Nothingness - having emerged into a counter-determined
context, also returns to its negativity as the Many of Repulsion. The Unity
of the One and Many, or attraction and repulsion is the overall unity for the
e" cycle. It is a unity in which the original element of immediacy called e or
Being, having become a transition state e' and a revelation of its negative as
Nothingness, has in tum generated a higher order negation, in which both
Being and Nothingness, as two co-immediacies, have each become negated
within themselves, only to reveal a counter-transition to the e', in which Being
not only disappears into Negativity, but any Negativity as an immediate
element itself in turn reveals Being. Hence with e", being or e is in a double
transition state, explicitly returning being to itself through any negation
which has emerged from it. Being as containing all determination and
negation within it is Quality.
Now in mathematics, the movement from e to e' to e" is structurally
similar to the movement from a function to its first derivative, and then to its
second derivative, which is not as such a linear one-dimensional sum of two
derivatives, but a derivative of a derivative, or a state of transition-in-
transition. In physics, position, velocity as the first derivative (like becoming)
and acceleration as the second derivative (the motion itself in movement)
likewise express three states of space-time relation important to describe
fundamental types of movement possible. Position is simple 'being', velocity
is simple 'change-of-position', and hence position vs. velocity merely describes
the simple opposition between non-action and action. However, in order to
describe inter-action, or a state of non-action (like a body at rest) which is
actually in a sub-state of action (like sub-units in movement), then the
acceleration of changing velocities (and hence forces, dynamically speaking)
are required, for now not only is there simple movement in one-direction, but
there is also the movement of this movement changing it into an opposite
DYNAMICS OF HEGEL'S DIALECTICS 329
to the line itself - i.e. to the line of co-relation determining the two end
points or polarities. Thus, the original zero·dimensional space - namely the
singular point - now appears within the one-dimensional space as a double-
term or double sub-space (i.e. as two points) giving expression to a new
singular space - namely the line itself. For 3 2 we obtain the value 9. As
previously pointed out, a two-dimensional dialectic matrix has four opposi-
tion elements «++e, +-e, -+e and --e), four partial transitions (+ +-e,
- +-e; and +- +e, +- -e), and one complete transition (+- +-e). The four
oppositions correspond to the four points of a square-surface, the four partial
transitions correspond to the four lines connecting these points, and the one
total transition corresponds to the two-dimensional square-surface itself
whose boundary is now composed of four one-dimensional lines simul-
teneously in co-relation. (Looking back at the matrix on page 322, together
with its analysis on the pages following, will enable one to intuit the corre-
spondence outlined. Besides the obvious properties mentioned here, there are
others to be considered, e.g. the role of the diagonals, which all give addi-
tional expression to the topology of dialectic relations.) Thus in moving from
one- to two-dimensional dialectic, the elements in relation are no longer
points, but lines (i.e. relations themselves) and furthermore, the Singular space
they generate is not according to the same kind of structure found in the
more simple one dimensional dialectic of a triad. A two-dimensional dialectic
has to be grasped as a singular 9-term relation of relations generating simul-
taneous transitions in a two-dimensional space.
For a three-dimensional dialectic, 33 gives 27 terms. This corresponds to
the cubic volume which has 8 points, 12 lines, 6 planes and one singular
volume - namely the entire space itself as a three-dimension transition space.
We see that the complexity of transition relations jumps qualitatively, each
time the previous space becomes a sub-space or element within a larger
singular space. For a four-dimensional dialectic, 3 4 gives 81 terms. This
corresponds to the 'tesserac' - i.e. a four-dimensional cube having 16 points,
32 lines, 24 surfaces, 8 volumes and one four-dimensional volume that is
bounded by the 8 volumes (as the three-dimensional volume is bounded by
6 planes). Hegel's logic, as a 3 4 or 8l-term dialectic generated through four
major transition states, which function simultaneously in co-relation, is thus
mapped topologically into a 'tesserac' - i.e. a four-dimensional cube, which
gives a singular expression to these 81 elements of transition in a singular
gestalt! Small wonder that it is difficult to imagine as a totality, let alone
higher order spaces into 5,6, ... etc., etc. dimensions not even considered.
Two immediate observations appear. First, the number of singular points
332 M.KOSOK
only cancelled but not preserved or (2) only preserved but not cancelled.
Transcendence is dialectic paradoxical immediacy, so if Nature or objectivity
(Le. sensual, material interaction) is regarded as an altogether other-ness not
already present within Logic or subjectivity, then there indeed is a mysterious
'jump' from one domain into another, with which the idealists feel at odds,
and to which the materialists can rightly point as a flaw. Spirit, as the
mutuality of a pure Logic and an alienated otherness called Nature is then a
diction vs. contradiction polarity and not a paradox, Le. Nature within
subjectivity can either (1) appear only as a vanishing moment - the otherness
cancelled - and hence a mechanical return to the logic of subjectivity·
without being genuinely integrated or (2) remain within the subjectivity -
preserved - as an alienation in the heart of awareness - and most likely
combinations of both. Nature, objectivity, or space time historicity as a
particular determined here-now localization must be the authentic self-
otherness to which subjectivity as a dynamic essence or Logic (an Eros) or
field-ofpresence must have reference, as its form (Le. its Logos of determina-
tion) in the modality of events of existence such that in reality, Spirit or
Geist is a field-event mutuality - a phenomenology of subject and object
in which neither as an identification has any meaning without the other.
Consequently Marx attempted to reintegrate sensual materialism into the
dialectic process of Hegel - and this perspective as a whole is best outlined in
his famous Theses on Feuerbach, where he criticizes both onesided idealism
and materialism as destroying the genuine mutuality between the active
subject and the object-of-action. Unfortunately - and dialectically - this
reintegration of authentic objectivity with the spirituality of Hegel likewise
has tended to become a counter one-sided distortion in the hands of the
materialists.
The genuine content of dialectic is con§equently a dynamic of immediacy
(e, e', e" ... ) which on the one hand is, as-a-totality, ever-present as a trans-
temporal immediacy (Le. the whole dynamics itself expressed as an ever-
present singularity e), while on the other hand, its reflection can take the
Logos or form of a triadic mutuality (+e, -e, +-e), the +e now being the
identifiable or linearizable dynamic of immediacy posited as a given essence
or subjectivity (Le. sheer immediacy now pictured as a Logic of field of
relations); the -e, now the counter-identifiable mediation counter'posited as
negativity, determination, objectivity ('gegenstdndlichkeit') or the events of
existence (Le. mediation as Nature); and +-e as the self-mediated mutuality
of essence and existence, subjectivity and objectivity called reality or Spirit
(Geist). Naturally in this modality, Hegel's Encyclopedia of Logic, Nature and
336 M.KOSOK
Spirit are all three modalities of a higher order dynamic of immediacy whose
three initial mediations (i.e. Logic as +e, Nature as -e and Spirit as the
mutual mediation +-e) are each already the entire dynamic of immediacy -
i.e. each is a reflection of the entire e, e', e" ... relative to one type of
fundamental mediation. Logic regards the entire +, -, ± self-mutuality
process relative to the positive modality of presence (i.e. a field of presence
regarded as a given universe of possibility), Nature the same process relative
to the negative modality of localized events of eXistence and extension, while
Spirit is the same process relative to the transitive modality of mutuality
between the field of presence and its events. Such an interpretation of both
the dynamics of immediacy and Hegel's system requires a detailed investiga-
tion into the dialectic of infinity - for it presupposes that the entire non-
linear totality expressed here as the e, e', e" ... e-ing state or process can
itself be experienced and grasped as a singularity relative to which higher
order e-ing states of immediacy in turn appear. Furthermore, it opens up
the possibility of an infinity of infinities ... ad infinitum of dynamic transi-
tion states, each dimension of infinity opening up newer interpretations
of the fundamental +e, -e, ±e mutuality expressive of any e to e' transition.
Naturally, all such e to e' transitions would represent a form of the original
Being-Nothing-Becoming triadicity. However, if it is permissable to speak
about levels of infinite totalities, then each higher order level would require
a qualitatively more developed presentation of the original triadicity. It is
suggested here 2 that Logic, Nature and Spirit in Hegel's Encyclopedia
represents such a higher order form of Being, Nothing and Becoming - a
form in which the implicit phenomenology of subject-object co-relation
inherent in the first order dynamic of immediacy (expressive of such terms-
of-movement as Being, Becoming, Quality etc.) now becomes an explicit
phenomenology, the subjective aspect seen as Logic, the objective as Nature,
and their co-relativity as Spirit. With such a form of relations, the terms or
elements appearing in all three modalities would be of the same quality: not
only does nature or objectivity appear as a linearizable localization into
definitive determinations appearing in space and time, but logic or the subjec-
tive field of relations likewise appears linearizable into definitive determina-
tions historically conditioned in space and time (and Similarly for Spirit).
The point of such a presentation is to illustrate the following fact of
dynamic immediacy: the dynamic has to be total and singular at any stage,
and should one reflect on this totality as a condition of presence (i.e. as a
field of presence or Logic) in opposition to that which is present (the
particular events), then both the immediacy as a field and its opposite -
DYNAMICS OF HEGEL'S DIALECTICS 337
namely the events of mediation are now co-mediations within a larger totality
and immediacy. Hence one cannot separate out the dynamics of immediacy
as a fixed point of immediacy - Le. as a given logic, relative to which the
world appears as its content without at the same time mediating that
immediacy into a larger and as-yet-unfixed or un-mediated state, within
which it now functions as but a co-relative variable. Hence, once Hegel
decides to localize his Logic of dynamic immediacy by mediating it relative to
Nature, then both are but co-relative sub-mediations within a larger dynamic
- now given as Logic, Nature and Spirit. At no time can one come up with a
particular logic of relations - spelling out a definitive structure that is merely
a subjective thought un-conditioned by objective existence: to specify (Le.
linearize out) a field of presence or 'subjective space' of essences, is to
counter-specify a co-relative state of existential events or 'objective space',
both of which are co-determined. Consequently, logical relations must reflect
their objective conditioning as referring to events-in-a-state-of-interaction, and
natural events must in turn - if specified out as 'facts' - refer to the subjec-
tive field of presence to which they appear as facts. In reality, Geist or Spirit
is then the mutual co-relativity of fact and essence, each only linearizable in
relation to the other.
What has been thus far outlined for a non-linear presentation of dialectic
has only taken into explicit consideration the first aspect of non-linearity
previously mentioned - namely the appearance of all elements within a
dynamic dimensionality or space. We now turn to the second aspect -
namely the infinite nature of such a dimensionality, which has already
appeared in the first aspect as a potentiality - in other words - as a way of
giving expression to orders or levels of dynamic immediacy that give explicit
expression to the dialectic phenomenology of subject-object relation. We can
now justify the usage of such a method of presentation - showing the
actuality or reality of dialectic infmity - not only as a notion within a
dynamic of immediacy but as a quality of that dynamic itself. Just because
there is no final transition state in the e-ing process, and furthermore, because
all of these stages of transition themselves form a Singular inseparable
dynamics (e, e', e" do not form a sequence of separate terms), this dynamics
neither converges to a final limit point, nor diverges into a plurality of
isolated steps or positions. One can say, instead, that it trans-verges, repres-
enting a self-mediating totality whose singularity expresses itself through
mutuality of opposition and vice versa. Rather than ending up in a static
being (Le. a posited Absolute), or not-ending up at all, but merely generative
of an endless state of becoming (Le. an anti-Absolute, Absolute), the dynamic
338 M. KOSOK
problems of identity (the same three Nietzsche points to in Beyond Good and
Evil!): the status of 'the symbol', 'the material object', and 'the ego' or self.
In modern science, the classical atomicity of regarding existence essentially in
terms of a linear composition of identifiable units - such as words, objects
and persons (and thus groups of words, objects and persons giving us language,
nature and society) is precisely what has been put into question by the 'un-
decidability' of symbols, the 'indeterminacy' of objects and the 'ambiguity' of
the ego. From a dynamic of immediacy, however, the paradox of transition
inverts one's 'normalized' (Le. one's linear identity) awareness by becoming
aware of the non-existence of any kind of 'Ding-an-sich' or singular point of
reference such as the symbol, object or ego. 3
Thus, for example, it is Gbdel's theorems themselves which show that any
arithmetizable (linearizable) logic is bound to be either inconsistent or in-
complete and hence 'undecidable'. Furthermore, this undecidability arises
exactly at the boundary between anyone symbol and its context or negation.
Thus, in attempting to give expression to the coupling between a term and its
negation - expressing therefore a boundary condition of co-relation - this
co-relation leads either to an inconsistency if accepted into a logic, or an
incompleteness if excluded. Only by regarding the boundary itself as a
dynamic transition generating its terms, instead of first regarding the terms as
pre-given and then put into co-relation, can one truly transcend the limitation
of Gbdel's theorems. Hence the so-called Liar's Paradox, which prompted
Gbdel's formulations, is seen to be but the immediate state in which all
symbolic terminology must give expression to: transition generates self-
opposition between mutually conditioned elements such as true or false,
present or absent (being or nothing). Any symbol, word, term or designated
element at once presents and denies - it presents itself through denying its
context, and it denies its context through presenting itself, hence condition-
ing the presence of a term by the very de-lineation it has with its context.
Thus if one learns that the truth or presence of a term is conditioned by its
negation, then simply negating the term will not be a transcendence of that
term but only a reference to the 'other-side' of the mutually co-determining
boundary, and hence a negative referral to that identity. (To say that "I am
not going to the movies" is only a reference to the movies as a possible but
lacking content and does not of itself refer to anything else.) Thus all nega-
tion is self-negation, meaning that it expresses the intrinsic paradox between
any mediation and its co-mediation. Rebellion as an act of denial is but the
mirror-image of conformity: revolution or real-transformation must grasp
both what is and what is not as a Singular self-related totality - revolution
DYNAMICS OF HEGEL'S DIALECTICS 341
NOTES
.-t
§ Being - - + Nothing --+
Becoming non-linear in two-dimensions g;
§ ~ Bas B N as N BN as BN From Quality (B*) to Absolute Idea (B**)
.s g;
.~ .Ei ~ ~ ~ (5 ~ in 2 additional dimensions: ~
~ i5 Something Other Determinate ~ '0 3 2 X 3 2 = 3 4 or 9 X 9 = 81 transition- 0
a~ ------+ ------+ Being ] ~ terms of a Dialectic Matrix-of-a-Matrix ;;
.S 'E B as N N as B BN as NB 0 u:: simultaneously emerging, nonlinearly in ~
a e ~ ~ ~ \I 4 dimensions creating the entire Logic: ~
~ The One The Many Being-for-self ~ all Being is, Be-ing: Dialectic as sheer ~
'"d ------+ ------+ II self-reflexive Being
~ B as BN N as NB BN as BNNB ~
(inner unity) (outer unity ) (unity of unities) ~
w
~
V1
CHART - PART II w
-I'>-
0\
BEING ESSENCE NOTION
Presence, Immediacy, Field Reflection, Mediation, Self-Reflection, Self-
~CIl
of Being B* Negating activity N* Mediation, Self-Acting- } .~ g
>-...:i
~
Field of Being B*N*
.§ -I-
j <
Q MEASURE ACTUALITY IDEA
""0 Integrated Presence & Integrated Reflection & Integrated Self-Reflection *co
~ Total Field B* as B*N* Total Activity N* as N*B* & Total Self-Acting-Field *Z
""0
d B*N* as B*N*N*B* .. or *Z
("l
*co
(B* revealing B* through N*:
the Self-Appearing-Field)
tj
-<
Z
);-
w
.j:>.
-J
H. C. SABELLl
In The Science of Logic, Hegel rejects the concept that logic makes abstrac-
tion of the content of thought. Thus, the elements of a mathematical
dialectics, concepts or propositions, must be taken simultaneously in exten-
sion and in intension. Set theory can be used to develop a logic of the
connotation of concepts in which simple attributes can be taken as elements
and compound attributes as sets. The lattice of attributes is not isomorphic
to that of classes (in contradiction to Boole's first law). For instance, there
is an infinite number of attributes corresponding to the extensional empty
set. Moreover, as the definition of a given class is more sharply defined, the
defmition of its connotation becomes less well-defined and vice versa. For
instance, the well-defmed attributes 'liquid' and 'solid', 'acid' and 'base', do
not correspond to well-defmed classes; a given substance can act as an acid if
and only if there are other conditions under which it will act as a base.
Extension and connotation are related by an uncertainty principle equivalent
to the relation between position and momentum in Quantum Mechanics.
Thus, a concept taken both in intension and extension satisfies Kosok's
requirement that an element of a dialectic calculus cannot be well defmed.
Let us then defme a concept as an ordered pair < a, ii> the first element of
which is a connotation (set of attributes) a and the second member in the
corresponding class ii of objects. We now say that concept < a, ii > implies
< b, b > if and only if a < band ii < b. This double implication solves many
of the paradoxes of implication that plague classic Boolean logic and as a
consequence, Hempel's theory of confirmation.
One needs to consider the connotation of concepts to formalize the
Hegelian categories because all such categories are co-extensively universal.
The interpretation of concepts in connotation allows for and requires the
logical interpretation of more powerful mathematical structures than set
COMMENT ON GAUTHIER AND KOSOK 351
One of the advantages implicit in the use of mathematical models is that they
clarify our ideas. There are, in fact, different conceptions of dialectic nega-
tion, but this multiplicity is often obscured by the ambiguity of the language.
In Kosok's conception of dialectics, negation is symmetric. Reflection upon
any immediate unformed element e is not a single element but rather a pair
of elements +e and -e emerging by mutual opposition. In other words, the
initial, immediate term serves as a base for both mediated terms, positive and
negative. The terms are like the three vertices of a triangle standing on one
vertex. Assertion and negation are equally potent. The relation between them
Kosak's system:
symmetric R 5
Relations
non-symmetricR 1 , R 2 ,R3, R4
Sublation
is symmetric and they are both sublated by their synthesis, which is inter-
mediate in quality between the two. This hierarchy of elements does not
imply evolution in time. The immediate inferior term e coexists with the
superior mediated terms +e and -e (Figure 1, top).
In classic mathematical logic, negation .is complementation, that is to say,
absence. Kosok also interprets dialectic negation as an absence; he exemplifies
negation by the pair: "I am going to the movies", "I am not going to the
movies". This is not sublation, which implies a hierarchical order. Moreover,
group inverses may be interpreted to formalize negation as an absence, there-
by introducing one of the most powerful mathematical tools in the formaliza-
tion of dialectics.
Already Gauthier mentioned the use of group theory in the formalization
of Hegelian logic. Group inverses obviously abstract the characteristics of
symmetric negation. Group theory allows many values in addition to an
element and its inverse, thereby eliminating the principle of excluded third,
the excluded middle. Moreover, it allows for contradictory statements
(elements that are their own inverses). Group theory, however, emphasizes the
reversibility of processes, the 'return' of the synthesis to the thesis, by allow-
ing the existence of an identity element. It does not model dialectic negation.
The assertion of both a proposition (a) and its denial (a-I) implies the
assertion of neither in group theory. In contrast, the assertion of a hypothesis
(thesis) and its refutation (antithesis) implies the denial of the former, the
assertion of the latter, and the synthesis of a new hypothesis accounting for
both the former hypothesis and its counterexample.
Symmetric negation emphasizes the mutually exclusive character of the
two terms of a contradiction. Hence, dialectics is described as the need for
two consistent (non-contradictory) but incomplete descriptions of the world.
Kosok proposed a 'principle of non-identity': "It is impossible to have both
the law of contradiction and the law of the excluded middle"; hence, a
description of reality can be consistent but incomplete, complete but in-
consistent. A more essential form of negation is the hierarchical non-
symmetric negation known in dialectics as sublation and in philosophy of
science as refutation or falsification. It implies evolution in time and similarity
between the terms of the contradiction. The opposition of the two terms of
the contradiction is transient, their unity is essential and becomes permanent
in a consistent and complete synthesis. The relation between thesis and
antithesis and in the same manner the antithesis is sublated by the synthesis.
Each term creates new properties by conserving, transcending and super-
seding the other terms.
COMMENT ON GAUTHIER AND KOSOK 353
/\ \/
o VTwo-valued logic
i
o
ri
o
x
o
./~
V
The direct product of two two-element Helicoids corresponds to Kosok's R (e)
Fig. 2.
logic because truth values need not form a totally ordered lattice (as in the
two-valued propositional calculus). Moreover, a Helicoid may have any
number of truth values (including infinite) and such truth values alternate
in two colors; elements of one color are consistent between themselves and
contradictory to those of the other color.
Mathematical logic refers only to the composition of unchanged atomic
propositions into a compound statement. Atomic propositions may be
changed in their meaning as a result of their combination into compound
statements in a similar manner as in nature the interaction of two elementary
particles generates new ones. The synthesis of hypotheses and their refuta-
tions is essential to the formulation of new hypotheses. An example of the
synthesis of two conepts into a new one is the synthesis of rest and motion in
inertia.
A Helix is a Helicoid in which we can define a unitary operation antithesis
and a binary operation synthesis, to model such non-linear combinations of
concepts, and more generally to abstract the dialectic laws of movement. To
present the mathematical theory of helices at this point would require
considerable space. An article describing the model as well as its use in the
interpretation of empirical data has been published (H. C. Sabelli, 'A Pharma-
cological Approach for Modelling Neuronal Nets' in Biocybernetics, Vol. IV,
H. Drischel and P. Dettmar, editors (lena, VEB Gustav Fischer Verlag, 1972)).
Let me now touch some more general points raised by the work of Kosok
and Gauthier.
First, the relation between dialectic and non-dialectic logic: Most modern
logicians have simply ignored dialectics. Conversely many dialecticians have
regarded mathematical logic as sterile. The best description of the worst
conception of the relation between dialectic and formal logic is given by
Zinoviev:
Dialectics by its very essence cannot be subjected to formalization by way of a formal
calculus; it has other tasks than logic, and solves them by oth~r methods .... Dialectics
did actually point to the fact that two-valued logic has limitations, once it excludes
situations of the kind a(x) p (x) and p' (x). But this limitation is one which makes
science viable.
This statement recognizes the actual meaning of the non-formalization of
dialectics: science is outside the domain of dialectics. I conceive dialectics as
a set of heuristic rules which guide us to search for probable (but not certain)
phenomena.
Any attempt to develop a mathematical dialectics is a search for a synthesis
of symbolic logic and dialectics. The nature of their relationship, however, is
356 H. C. SABELLI
Dealing with the concreteness of human thinking rather than with simplified
psychological or logical constructs, psychiatry necessarily speaks dialectics.
Psychiatrists often do so unknowingly, as Monsieur Jourdain spoke prose, but
the validity of their contribution to a multidisciplinary study of thinking
cannot be overlooked. Piaget has, in fact, revolutionized the study of thought
via his concept of experimental epistemology. His pediatric studies have
shown an ordered sequence of development in which different mathematical
structures successively serve the normative role of an organizing logic. Group
structures, for instance, characterize certain stages of development, while
the overall evolution of thinking is obviously more complex than Hegelian
dialectics. Within this framework, dialectic thinking is one among many
natural patterns of thinking (e.g., abstract-mathematical, mechanistic,
autistic, free-associations, etc.). It seems likely that biological evolution has
selected such multiplicity as being more advantageous than a single pattern of
thinking. Within his view, the rejection of anyone of these thinking modes
may be a misguidedly premature attempt to correct evolution. A naturalisitc
study of dialectic thinking may offer significant contributions to philosophi-
cal diale ctics.
Conversely, there is a wide range of applications of dialectics to psychiatry,
particularly because contradiction is an essential component of many differ-
ent types of thinking processes. For instance, the brilliant analysis made by
1. Lakatos of the logic of mathematical discoveries via the contradiction of
'Proofs and Refutations' illustrates the dialectic nature of creative thinking;
and of course, one of Freud's main contributions was his discovery of the
'illogical' but not random nature of the 'primary process' thinking observed in
dreams, psychoanalytic free-associations, errors and slips of the tongue, etc.
Because dialectics deals with contradictory thinking - which non-dialectic
logic excludes - it may have a clinical application in psychiatry in the inter-
pretation of the covert and often contradictory meaning of thinking and
behavior. For instance, the dialectic notion that opposites imply each other
provides a 'dictionary' for probable (but not certain) psychoanalytic inter-
pretations (e.g., irritable <+ irritating <+ irritated, dominant ,.,. submissive;
anger <+ fear). Freud discovered that in dreams things are often represented
COMMENT ON GAUTHIER AND KOSOK 359
University of Wisconsin
Madison
HEGEL AND THE SCIENCES
BIBLIOGRAPHICAL NOTE
COLLECTED WORKS
INDIVIDUAL WORKS
365
R. S. Cohen andM. W. Wartofsky (eds.), Hegel and the Sciences, 365-367.
366 HEGEL AND THE SCIENCES
L [W, 1892] The Logic of Hegel. Trans. W. Wallace. 2nd rev. and aug. ed. Oxford,
Clarendon Press, 1892. Translation of Logik, Part I of the Encyklo-
piJdie der philosophischen Wissenschaften, 1830.
L [W,1975] Logic. Trans. W. Wallace; with a foreword by J. N. Findlay. Oxford,
Clarendon Press, 1975. Translation of Logik, Part I of the Encyklo-
piJdie der philosophischen Wissenschaften, 1830.
Logik Logik (Part I of the Encyklopiidie der philosophischen Wissenschaf
ten). Edited by L. Henning. (Werke 6, 1840). For English translation
see L [,1892] and L [W, 1975].
PG Philosophie des Geistes (Part III of the EncyklopiJdie der philosoph is-
chen Wissenschaften). Edited by L. Boumann. (Werke 7, 1845).
Phan [G] Phanomenologie des Geistes. Edited by H. Glockner. (Jubilaumsaus-
gabe 2, 1927). For English translation see Phen [B] andPhen [M].
Phan [H, 1937] Phanomenologie des Geistes. Edited by J. Hoffmeister. 4th ed.
(Siimtliche Werke (Lasson ed., critical ed.) 2, 1937). For English
translations see Phen [B] andPhen [M].
Phan [H,1952] Phanomenologie des Geistes. Edited by J. Hoffmeister. 6th ed.
(Samtliche Werke (new critical ed.) S, 1952). For English translations
seePhen [B] andPhen [M].
Phen [B] The Phenomenology of Mind. Trans. J. B. Baillie. 2nd rev. and corr.
ed. London, Allen and Unwin; New York, Macmillan, 1931. (Reprint-
ed several times.) Translation of Phanomenologie des Geistes (Phan
[G,H]).
Phen [M] Phenomenology of Spirit. Trans. A. V. Miller, with analysis of the
text and foreword by J. N. Findlay. Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1977.
Translation of P/'lanomenologie des Geistes (Phan [G, H]).
PM Philosophy of Mind. Trans. W. Wallace, together with the Zusatze in
Boumann's text (1845), trans. A. V. Miller; with foreword by J. N.
Findlay. Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1971. Translation of Philosophie
des Geistes (PG) , Part III of the Encyklopadie der philosophischen
Wissenschaften, 1830.
PN Philosophy of Nature. Trans. from Nicolin and Poggeler's edition
(1959) and from the Zusatze in Michelet's text (1847) by A. V.
Miller; with foreword by J. N. Findlay Oxford, Clarendon Press,
1970. Translation of Naturphilosophie, Part II of the Encyklopadie
der phl10sophischen Wissenschaften, 1830.
PR Philosophy of Right. Trans. T. M. Knox. Oxford, Clarendon Press,
1942. Translation of Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts (GPR).
SL [J/S] Science of Logic [1929]. Trans. W. H. Johnston and L. G. Struthers.
2 vols. London, Allen and Unwin, 1951. Translation of Wissenschaft
der Logik (WL [L]).
SL [M] Science of Logic. Trans. A. V. Miller, foreword by J. N. Findlay.
London, Allen and Unwin; New York, Humanities Press, 1969.
Translation of Wissenschaft der Logik (WL [L]).
WL [1812] Wissenschaft der Logik. 2 vols. Nuremberg, Schrag, 1812-1816. For
Eng1ish translations see SL (JIS, M].
WL [L] Wissenschaft der Logik. Edited by G. Lasson. 2 vols. (Siimtliche
BIBLIOGRAPHICAL NOTE 367
Werke 3,4, 1923; 1934, reprinted 1948). For English translations see
SL [J/S, M].
369
370 INDEX OF NAMES