Aquinas Aesthetics
Aquinas Aesthetics
Aquinas Aesthetics
Thomas Aquinas
Author(s): Charles Side Steinberg
Source: The Philosophical Review , Sep., 1941, Vol. 50, No. 5 (Sep., 1941), pp. 483-497
Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Duke University Press and are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to The Philosophical Review
483
II
While aesthetic theory does not constitute a distinct realm of
discourse in the writings of Thomas, there are nevertheless certain
root terms or key concepts in the metaphysics, psychology, and
the epistemology, which are applicable to a theory of the beautiful.
These include the Thomist connotation of the terms mind, being,
love, presence, habitus, concrete real, and joy. The mind seeks out
being, impelled by love and the activity of the will. It is confronted
by the presence of the concrete, and finds joy in the contemplation.
This, reduced to the barest essentials, is the mechanism of the
aesthetic experience, but the psychology may be considered more
profitably after certain general distinctions have been made clear,
among these the distinction between art and beauty, and between
art and fine art. There is a further distinction between art and
prudence, which is best considered in the discussion of art and
morality. Art, residing in the practical order, signifies work to be
done, a practical activity, a mode of doing. Beauty, conversely,
does not involve an activity but a contemplation, a satisfaction in
the mere knowing. Beauty is defined as "Id quod visum placet",
and resides primarily in the faculty of cognition.5 It is passive;
art is active. It is concerned with the joy of possession; art is
concerned with the practice of making. In general, the distinction
between art and the fine arts is not defined so clearly as that be-
tween art and beauty. Art (ars), for the ancients, indicated skill
in activity; and, while art tended to produce a work designated for
use, fine art aimed to produce a work which was essentially pleas-
ing to the sight, and therefore beautiful. But fine art and beauty
are not completely severed into practice and contemplation. For, if
art demands an action, it involves inherently the use of the fac-
ulties of the will and the appetite. And what is produced for the
appetite becomes an object of desire, and brings the subject into
closer proximity with being. The result of making, then, by bring-
ing being to the subject, brings beauty also; thus art and beauty
find common grounds for reconciliation.
The nature of beauty seems clearly defined: "Pulchra enim
dicuntur, quae visa placent", or, more succinctly, "Id quod visum
'I q. 5, a. 4, ad I.
ism at this point in the Thomistic system. But the abiding achieve-
ment of the philosophy of Thomas is the approach to a problem
by the empirical mode of analysis. Only at the conclusion is there
a rapprochement with mysticism in the interests of Scholastic
theology. Hence the act of knowing is an active and actual process.
What is known is a real thing, objectively verifiable, and known
as real by virtue of the formal element in the object. Only the
mind can seize upon being, however, and the experience is brought
to fruition primarily by the activity of the mind.14 The mind in-
herently strives for the very being of God, but has been consigned
to a mode of discursive and indirect knowledge. It is the faculty of
the will, operating through love, that forces the mind to seize
upon the presence of the concrete real.15 While the mode of analy-
sis and the general epistemology are of Aristotelian origin, there
is a curious overtone of the Platonic notion of knowledge as recol-
lection, derived from St. Augustine. Aesthetic experience brings
with it a sense of memory, a perception of that which the mind
recollects having known previously. Thus the empirical, Aris-
totelian approach to knowledge, with its emphasis upon the senses,
is juxtaposed with the notion of an innate knowledge in the in-
terests of Thomistic metaphysics. In this way Thomas is able to
retain the Aristotelian analysis, and at the same time introduce
the necessary appendage of the selfconsciousness of the soul and
the proximity of God.
Maritain has pointed to the intellectualist quality in Thomist
aesthetics, emphasizing the cognitive aspect of the experience. But,
if the cognitive side is fundamental, it is of equal significance to
note that the intellectual response is accompanied by a strong
emotional quickening. It is important to recall that beauty was
defined as Id quod visum placet; and, while this involves no mere
titillation of the senses, it indicates the presence of a pervading
sense of satisfaction, a feeling-tone of felt delight. The whole
process is a pleasurable one, but the aura of joy in the experience
of the beautiful is ultimately the satisfaction of the mind in con-
templation. What knows is mind, and mind alone has access to
the infinity of being. While beauty pleases the senses, it has not
flowered fully unless the senses are joined by the mind in the
III
pleases the appetite; but let that be termed beautiful which in the
mere apprehension gives pleasure."2' The beautiful, however, has a
relation to the appetite, and this is shown clearly in the Thomistic
psychology. But the analyses of the attributes would seem to indi-
cate quite clearly that beauty does have an ontological status. If
it is not on absolute parity with unity, truth, and goodness, it is
analogously an attribute of being, at least, because it partakes of
the other attributes. In a metaphysical sense, beauty and goodness
are identical, for the desire of the good is also the desire of the
beautiful.22 Beauty, then, is an attribute of being, an aspect of be-
ing, and in one sense being itself. It is a transcendental.
The status of beauty is revealed most clearly in the Thomistic
psychology. The impulsion of the mind to seek out being stems
from the agencies of love and the will, and this association offers
still another basis for comparison between the good and the beauti-
ful. Now the mind desires the concrete thing spontaneously, and is
impelled by the effect of love on the concrete.23 Love reveals two
aspects-desire itself, natural desire, and will. The mind has a
desire for fusion with being, and that which satisfies the natural
desire of the mind may be called beautiful. The will, allied with
the knowledge-process, works posterior to desire, and accepts what
is presented to the mind through knowledge. But ultimately love
transcends cognition, for things are present in knowledge in a
representative way, but the objective of love is absolute union of
lover and beloved, mind and thing.24 When this is achieved the
desire of the will is also placated and an aesthetic experience has
taken place. Both the appetite and the faculty of desire have been
satisfied by the presence of the beautiful. The aesthetic experience,
considered as a psychological phenomenon, is engendered by love.
Love seeks a union with the object presented to sense, and this
union brings joy and satisfaction. But the satisfaction of the emo-
tions is not the fundamental fact. The act of the intellect is pre-
dominant. The truest comprehension of the beautiful is cognitive,
and, ultimately, mystic and suprarational.
While the mind seeks out being as such and desires to unite with
the concrete, it has been relegated to a condition of rational elabora-
tion, rather than intuitive activity. The will functions to aid in
galvanizing the mind to the presence of the concrete. It may thus be
thought of as an efficient cause. The will in man forces the mind
to the concrete which God's will has created.25 When the mind
unites with the concrete, it enjoys a presence of the concrete, which
flows into the mind with pure intelligibility. But man is not capa-
ble, on his own level, of this experience, and again a divine activity
is adumbrated. For only divine essence can inform the mind with
pure intelligibility. At this point Thomistic ontology is superim-
posed on the psychology and the empirical analysis gives way to
the tenets of Scholastic theology. The influence of grace has been
all along a puissant factor in the experience of the concrete, and
the presence of God, the source of all being, is the cause of all
things beautiful to man. The aesthetic experience is intellectual
in character, but takes place without conceptual reasoning. It is
this immediate union with the intelligible real that is analogous to
the mystic grace. It is doubtful whether contemporary Thomist doc-
trine would admit the possibility of a "true" aesthetic experience,
i.e., an immediate intuition of the concrete, without the action of
grace. What may be admitted is the possibility of a union, but
perfect union, which is analogous to the beatific vision, can occur
only through the agency of grace. Thus mystical experience is
directly allied with aesthetic experience, and the Platonist theory
of reminiscence in Thomas has its own purpose; the mnemonic
element in knowledge and in experience is also a recognition of
the presence of God in the soul and a reminiscence of Him.26
When the mind fuses with the concrete in knowledge and in love,
the presence of God in the soul is illumined by grace. The aesthetic
experience, then, is a kind of mystic contemplation, and the paint-
ing of St. Theresa in Ecstasy would probably serve as a particu-
larly lucid example of a Thomistic aesthetic experience. A reason
beyond reason seems imminent in the aesthetic act. For God
Himself is beautiful, the most beautiful of all things, and the first
and final cause of all specific beauties. Man turns finally to God
as the source of all beauty. Not Euclid alone, but every man, can
look upon beauty bare through the intervention of grace. This
physical union of mind and object is analogous to God's identity
with Himself.27
IV
For a consideration of specific beauties Thomas turns again to
empirical analysis. The experience of beauty is not the experi-
ence of a Platonic archetype, but the completest union with a con-
crete thing. Certain conditions exist as prerequisites before an
object may be termed beautiful. Since beauty exists to satisfy the
desire of the mind, these conditions are: integrity, proportion, and
clarity. Beauty delights the mind by presenting the integrity, pro-
portion, and clarity, of concrete things to the mind. "For beauty
three things are necessary: Integrity . . . due Proportion . . . and
Clarity or brightness: thus bright colored things are termed beau-
tiful."28 The mind responds actively to the presence of integrity,
proportion, and clarity.
Integrity signifies a perfection in the object, but the notion of
integrity is relative to the aim and end of the artist's concept. Im-
plied in this notion is a Thomist acceptance of modern art, for
even a physically distorted figure may manifest integrity, if the
aim is realized. The mind and the senses find aesthetic gratification
also in "due proportion", the correct juxtaposition of part to part
and to the whole.29 But proportion, too, is not absolute, but acquires
meaning solely in the expressed aim and end of the work.
Neither proportion nor integrity, then, has significance apart
from the end of the work, which is to accommodate the brilliance
of form on matter. This is the third element, clarity, and the
notion of "claritas" involves the imposition of form on matter.
What is essential to the beauty of the work is a "splendor formae".
For matter is not accessible to the reason save by means of a form,
and the very possibility of interaction between perceiving subject
and object hinges upon the clarity of the object in perception. In
the perfection of a beautiful thing is reflected the mind's own perfec-
tion, and the predominant force present is that of "claritas", bright-
ness. And the greater the degree of clarity, the more luminous the