The Logic of "Actually": Reports On Mathematical Logic January 1977
The Logic of "Actually": Reports On Mathematical Logic January 1977
net/publication/268536956
CITATIONS READS
113 1,107
2 authors:
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
All content following this page was uploaded by Lloyd Humberstone on 08 May 2016.
1. Introduction
S. J. Surma and A. Wronski. He also acknowledges with pleasure the hospitality afforded him
by the following institutions and their members during the writing of this paper: University
of Warsaw, Technical University of Wroclaw, Jagiellonian University of Cracow, P olish Aca
demy of Sciences and Ateneo de Manila University, Philippines. The second author would like
to thank M. K. Davies for stimulating conversations on the topics of this paper.
12
that the logical use of 'actually' is to clarify matters of relative scope when
a modal operator is involved. According to this idea it would be quite wrong
to introduce an 'actually' opera.tor into a semantically lucid formal language:
the logical function of 'actually' is to effect scope-disambiguations, indicating
which of two alternative translations into such a language is appropriate, and
not to figure, itself, as an element in either.
The trouble with this account is that there turn out to be occurrences of l
logical 'actually' which cannot be treated as mere scopeclues in this way, but
have instead to be regarded as occurrences of a genuine scope-bearing operator,
so that there is a point in considering modal languages into which an actuality
operator has been introduced alongside necessity and possibility opera.tors.
Presently, we shall have a look at a purely propositional such language and its
associated logic, but, to :motivate that discussion, we should give at least one
example of why the interpretation of 'actually' criticised above will not do -
and the example to be given is itself quantificational. For this example, we make
the enormously simplifying assumption that the semantics for our modal lan
guage, in terms of possible worlds, is such that t,he domain of individuals does
not vary from world to world (as in Hughes & Cresswell's semantics for SS
(see [2] chapter 10)). With such a language in mind consider how we might
render the ambiguity of the sentence:
(3) It is possible for every red thing to be shiny.
or equivalently,
(3') It is possible that every red thing sl10uld be shiny.
The ambiguity in question is brought out by asking whether (3) asserts the
existence of a possible world in which every red object (i. e., every object red
in that world) is shiny, or instead the existence of a possible world in which all
the objects which are red in the actual world are shiny. These are quite clearly
distinct senses, the latter of which could be isolated by reformulating (3) as:
(4) It is possible that everything which is actually red, should be shiny.
Yet equally clearly, the ambiguity in question cannot be rendered by transla
tion into our conventional modal language. For the materials at our disposal
in such a language allow us to assemble at most the following three putative
translations:
(5) O('v'x) (Red(x) ::::> Shiny(x))
(6) ('v'x)O ( Red(x) ::::> Shiny(x))
(7) ('v'x) (Red(x) '.) O Shiny(x))
Now, while (5) adequately captures the first sense of (3), neither (6) nor (7) gets
anywhere near capturing the second sense, since these allow us to pick, for each
object, a different world in which it is, if red, shiny, in the case of (6), and, in
the case of (7), for every red object, a different world in which it is shiny. Thus
they capture at best the senses of such sentences as 'It is possible for any red
object to be shiny'. Wbat we want for the 'missing' sense of (3), however, is
13
a single world in which every object red in our world is shiny: an 'every' reading,
rather than an 'any' reading. So the universal quantifier must appear within,
and not outside, the scope of the possibility operator. But the semantics for
conventional modal languages dictates that the truth-value of a 'possibly'
formula is determined for a given world exclusively by the truth-value of the
immediate subformula involved at some world possible relative to the given
world, and this itse:f is determined by how things are in the new world and in
yet further worlds possible relative to it. VVhat we require to capture the missing
sense is some device for referring back to how things are in the original world:
in the possible world envisaged in (4) the objects which are to be shiny are those
objects which, in our world, are red. The semantics to be given in the next
section for tbe propositional fragment of a modal language containing an
actuality operator are such as to give this back-referring function to the new
operator. Writing 'A' for 'it is actually the case that', the idea is that in the
enriched language, the missing sense of (3) is to be captured by a more-or-less
direct translation of (4):
Having established the case for an actuality operator, what are we going
to do about it? On the walk-before-you-run principle, we can make some fairly
obvious - at least, obvious in the light of the discussion so far - suggestions
about modal propositional logic with 'actually', and again in the interests of
simplicity, let us think of our underlying modal logic as SS. It will be recalled
that a semantics for S5 can be given in terms of what is sometimes called a model
W = ( W, V), where W is a non-empty set (of possible worlds) and V is a function
which assigns to each propositional variable and world a truth-value. V is then
extended to all formulae in the following way, where we write W l=wa for
'V(a, w ) = T':
(i) W l=w,...., a if and only if not W l=wa,
(ii) W l=wa :> /3 if and only if either not W l=wa or W l=w/3,
(iii) W l=wOa if and only if for all w' € w, W l=w,a.
(We may take possibility, and the remaining truth-functional connectives
as defined in terms of negation, implication, and necessity in any of the usual
14
of a model so as to take into account the idea of one world being singled out as
the actual world. In other words, let us say that a model, W, is to be a triple
(W, w*, V), where w* E W (we call w* the 'actual world' of the model). vVe@
extended V to all formulae by adding to (i)-(iii) above
(iv) W l=wAa if and only if W l=w* a.
.As usual, a formula is valid just in case it is assigned the truth-value Tin every
world in every model of SSA.
By obvious analogy with Kripke's use of the phrase 'rigid designator',
we could say that SSA, as here defined, gives 'actually' the logic of a 'rigid
operator'. Indeed, if one chooses to regard sentences as designating their truth
-values, (iv) tells us that '.A.a' rigidly designates that truth-value that 'a' de
signates in the actual world; so the parallel with proper names and rigidly used
descriptions is quite close. .Another general point worth making is that SSA pre
serves for 'A' a property which its other non-truth-functional operators have,
namely, that formulae introduced by these operators do not change their truth
-values - as purely truth-functional formulae may - from world to world. This
is in striking contrast, of course, to the situation which obtains in modal logics
weaker than SS, and constitutes a large part of our motive for consideiing the
'actually' extension of 85.
SSA can be axiomatised by subjoining to some axiomatisation of S5 with
necessitation as a rule of proof the following five axioms:
(.Al) A(Ap'.Jp)
(.A2) A (p '.J q) '.J (Ap '.J Aq)
(.A3) Ap = �A �p
(.A4) Op '.J Ap
(.A5) Ap '.J OAp
This axiom set brings out rather well the contrast between our own approach
and that of some others (e.g., Kaplan's treatment of 'actually' in [4], and
Kamp's treatment of 'now' in [3]), on which the analogue of 'Ap = p' is a theo
rem. Evidently, in such approaches, the substitutivity of provable equivalents
fails to hold, so providing a contrast with the usual modal logics. In our system1
however, no such deviations are required: necessitation holds unrestrictedly
as a rule of proof, and one can show that provably equivalent formulae are
intersubstitutable salva provabilitate. The closest we get to 'Ap = p' as a theorem
is in 'A(Ap = p)' which is easily seen to be valid on the semantics given. No
doubt the idea that the former equivalence should be a theorem stems from the
observation that the outright assertion of '.Actually p' (or 'Now p') is tantamount
to the assertion of the simple 'p', but it is far from clear that any such relation
15
a.s this deserves promotion to the ra.nk of 'va.lid equiva.lence'. Such promotion
a.rgua.bly involves a. confusion between the idea. of logica.l truth or logica.l neces
sity, the pre-formal correla.te of va.lidity, on the one ha.nd, a.nd wha.t, in a. na.tura.l
extension of the terminology introduced by Ca.sta.iieda. in [1], ma.y be ca.lled
'la.lie necessity', on the other. No doubt such sentences a.s 'I a.m here' a.re la.lica.lly
necessa.ry in the sense tha.t they ca.nnot be falsely a.sserted, but to sa.y this is
certa.inly not to sa.y tha.t they cannot be false, a.nd some arguing would need to
be done by a.nyone proposing to a.ccord va.lidity to such contingencies. At a.ny
ra.te, wha.tever the worth of these considera.tions, it is of interest to explore
a.lterna.tives to these other a.pproa.ches, to see wha.t they look like when de
veloped.
For a.11 this, one could of course introduce a distinction between, let us ca.11 it
general validity, the property tha.t a. formula has if it can be falsified at no world
in any SSA- model, and real- world validity, that property a formula has if it
can be falsified at no world designated the actual world in any SSA- model.
General validity is what our set of axioms is designed to capture, but we can
make a few points concerning real-world validity while we are on the subject.
In the first place, it is obvious that if a contains no occurrences of 'A', then a is
generally valid if, and only if, a is real-world valid. In the second place, a for
mula f3 is real-world valid if, and only if, A/3 is generally valid.
The completeness of our axioms relative to this notion of general validity
can be shown by an adaptation of the completeness proof for propositional SS
given by Hughes & Cresswell (op. cit., 116-121) 2• Their proof adapts to the
case of SSA without any difficulties because our axioms suffice for the reduction
of any formula to a (:modified modal conjunctive) normal form, in the sense
that any formula is provably equivalent in SSA to a conjunction of formulae
of the form:
/3 V Dr1v...v Drn v Oov As ,
where the only occurrences of O, O, and A are those exhibited 3 Such a con •
a.nd from it to the corollary that SSA's axioms are complete, is that given
by Hughes& Cresswell for the case of S5, with a few obvious and minor changes.
(For instance, for the 'only if' part, we argue that if no such disjunction is valid
then we can construct for the conjunct in question a falsifying SSA model
(W, w*, V), where W= {w*, w0 , w11 , Wn} in which V (ovs , w*) =1!',
•••
V(ov{3, w0)=1!', and V(oVyi, wi)=J!' for l�i�n. Evidently, V (a, w0)=1!',
where a is the conjunct in question.)
3. Questions of Redundancy
(the proof being supplied in Section 5) 4 that the actuality operator of propo
sitional SSA turns out to be, in the sense just given for the phrases, indirectly
real-world redundant. (It is not, by the way, directly real-world redundant:
we could not, for instance, prove ' OAp' real-world equivalent to 'Op'; i.e., we
do not have 'A( OAp = Op)' as a theorem in SSA.) The upshot of this discussion
of redundancy, then, is that an 'actually' operator of the sort we have been
looking at is more important, from the point of view of expressive power, as an
addition to a quantified, than to a purely propositional, alethic modal language.
4. Global Operators
The last topic to be covered in our informal discussion of SSA concerns not
so much the system itself, as the possibility of extending it in such a way as to
meet a likely objection. The anticipated objection is to our fifth axiom
'Ap ::> OAp' , which may indeed, if read literally, strike one as counter-intuitive.
It seems unlikely that objections would be raised to any of the other axioms,
but this one may be so unpalatable to some readers that they rather doubt the
value of SSA as even a candidate for a plausible modal actuality logic. Its validity
arises from the fact that it is one and the same world that counts as the actual
world, for every world in the model. So if something is true in that world it. is
certainly going to be true in every other world that it is true in that world. It
would appear, then, that there is no simple tinkering with our semantical
framework that would leave us with .Al-.A4 valid, while invalidating .A5, keeping,
of course, the whole of SS itself intact. It is, perhaps, somewhat startling that
such straightforward assumptions about necessity as are embodied in SS, when
combined with some equally simple-minded ideas about 'actually', lead us to
accept the offending axiom as valid. (In fact, we do not wish to commit ourselves
to saying that ther� is anything unacceptable about .A5, - only to provide
food for thought for those who have made up their minds against it.)
Faced with this situation, in which independently quite nice ideas about
'necessarily' conflict with independently quite nice ideas about 'actually' when
the two concepts are brougl1t into relation, many would no doubt say that the
'
less nice ideas are those about this young upstart, 'actually', and it is therefore
these tlmt should be scrapped if we want to get an acceptable modal actuality
logic. Since this would amount to infanticide, or at any rate to a culpable
reluctance to persevere, we make precisely the contrary proposal, wanting
a novel account of necessity which will mesh well with the account already
provided of 'actually'.
4 In fact this is proved there (as Theorem 18) for a proper subsystem of SSA which we call
SSAR, from which it fol lows a fortiori that the result holds for SSA.
To give this new account, we introduce the idea of what may be called global
operators. .A rough idea is given by saying that global operators stand to modal
operators in much the same relation as modal operators stand to truth-functional
operators. More precisely, we observe, in notations like that used in (i)-(iv)
above, that both the model superscript, and the world subscript, on the truth-at
turnstile lie dormant in the statement of the truth-conditions for truth-functional
compounds. The semantics for modal operators, on the other hand, requires
that the world variable come to life - in general that it be either quantified
or have some function applied to it (as, e.g., a successor function on the 'moment
of time' variable in giving the semantics of'next' in a tense logic). .Analogously,
we may define a global operator as one whose semantics bring the model place
itself to life 5• In particular, consider the relation 'is a variant of' on SSA models
holding between any two such models differing at most in what world is actual,
and in any consequences this may have (regarding the .A- containing formulae)
for V. In terms of this relation, which we symbolise '� ', we define what it is
for a formula a to be fixedly true (represented '.:F') at a world in a model:
(v) W Fw .:Fa if and only if for all W ' � W , W ' t=wa .
It is not hard to see how such an operator might come to have a role in the
representation of necessity, since to say that something is necessarily true comes
pretty close to saying that it would be true no matter which (possible) world
was the actual world. Variance between models being an equivalence relation,
we shall obviously have, as valid for '.:F', everything valid for' D' in SS. Whether
or not we have anything else will depend on a choice we must now make as to
the interpretation of propositional variables (a choice, it might be mentioned,
of a sort that regularly arises when one pursues the logic of global operators).
On the one hand, we could choose to read them in such a way that
(9) p:J.:Fp
comes out valid. This is not an unnatural reading, since we might be thinking
along the following lines: any propositional variable assigned truth at a world
in a model will clearly be assigned truth at that world in every variant model,
since it is only the truth-value of .A- containing formulae that is affected by
passage over to new variants. But the trouble with this reading is that uniform
substitution fails to preserve validity in the resultant logic, since
(10) .Ap :J .:F .Ap
is a substitution instance of (9), and (10) is invalid. Indeed, the whole point of
introducing the 'fixedly' operator is to invalidate (10), the analogue of our
originally controversial formula (.Axiom 5) relating necessity and actuality.
.Anyway, another way of reading propositional variables is to think of them as
bound by invisible outermost universal propositional quantifiers, ranging over
all propositions, or, to think of the matter substitutionally over all formulae of
the language. Trivially, such a reading enables uniform substitution to preserve
validity, and (9) turns out invalid, since not every formula implies its own
'fixation' (witness (10)). It does not much matter what we choose to do, since
the problem of the validity of something like (9) will come up in the end, say,
if we think of introducing our 'fixedly' operator into an applied first-order
language, whereupon we shall find such formulae as
best described as an alternative actuality logic based on SS. The reason for this
is that the completeness problem for this alternative system is not so easily
settled as for SSA, in the absence of a correspondingly tidy normal form theorem.
(It will be seen from Theorem 21 below that the normal forms we eventually
get out cannot be guaranteed to be 'first-degree' formulae, whereas for SSA,
they are.) Hopefully, then, our discussion of this new system should provide
a good basis for any subsequent treatment of the 'actually' extensions of modal
logics weaker than SS, as well as yielding the results for SSA itself promised in
notes 3 and 4.
To see that there is room for two alternative S5-based actuality logics, recall
that the semantics for SS can be given in either of two ways. In Section 2,
above, we invoked that version of the semantics in which models are taken as
pairs (W , V), and by adding to the attendant clauses (i), (ii), and (iii), the
obvious clause for 'actually' (iv), we arrived at our semantics for SSA. The
other version of the semantics of SS, however, takes as its models triples of the
form (W, R, V) where Wand V are as before and R is some equivalence relation
on W, which enters into the clause for D (clauses (i) and (ii) remaining un"
changed);
(iii)' W l=w Oa if and only if for all w' such that wRw', W l=w,a •
.Although, as is well known, the two semantical accounts yield the same set
of valid formulae within the familiar modal language, they cease to do so when
we add a 'w*' to our models along with clause (iv), to deal with formulae con
taining 'A'. That is, if we take wbat we may call a.n S5AR-model to be a structure
(W , w*, R, V) where w* e W, R is an equivalence relation on W, and V is a func�
tion from pairs of propositional variables and elements of W to truth-values,
extended to all formul�e in accordance with (i), (ii), (iii)', and (iv), and we define
SSAR-validity as unfalsifiability at any world in any SSAR-model, then we
find that the set of SSAR-valid formulae does not coincide with the set of
SSA-valid formulae. Our axfom .A4 of Section 2 above, for instance, is SSA-but
not SSAR-valid. However, if we delete that axiom from our basis for SSA.
and add a rule of 'actualization' ('.Act.', for short), analogous to necessitation,
we obtain a sound and complete axiomatisation of the SSAR-valid formulae.
In this section, then, we shall show, amongst other things, that the addition of
the following to any basis for SS with necessitation as a rule of proof gives an
axiomatisation of the SSAR-valid formulae:
(.Al) A(Ap '.) p)
(.A2) A(p :::i q) '.) (Ap '.) Aq)
(.A3) Ap = ,..,_A -p
(.A4) Ap :::i OAp
(.Act.) If a is a thesis, then .A.a is a thesis.
From this point on, we use '.A4' for the fourth axiom here, and not as in Section 2.
21
Our strategy will be to give a completeness proof for S5AR in the style of
Makinson [5], and then a decision procedure based on a normal form theorem
in the style of Hughes& Cresswell [2]. The normal form theorem also yields an
alternative completeness proof.
Proof. If a is valid then V(a, w)= T for all w and in particular for w = w*.
7. Ap
8. "'(p'.)q)'.)"'q Tautology
9. A"' (p:) q)'.) A"'q cf. 3, 4, 5
10. "'Aq cf. 6, 7
11. Ap'.)("'Aq'.)"'(.Ap'.)Aq)) Tautology
12. "'(Ap'.)Aq) modus ponens 7, 10, 11.
Hence the result by taking contrapositives.
We shall see below that A does not commute with D (or O). As usual we
define a Lindenbaum set to be a maximal consistent set of formulae (of SSAR).
Proof. Suppose a¢ A* then A.a¢ A. Hence "'Aa EA. Now "' commutes
with .A, so by Lemma 7(i) and (ii) A"' a EA. Hence "'a EA*. So either a or
"'a EA*.
Now suppose A* is not consistent. Then for some au ... , an EA*, SSAR l
a1 '.) ( a2'.)...'.) ,..., (p '.) p) .. .) .By (Act.) and (A.2) we obtain SSAR l-Aa1'.)(A.a�'.) . . . '.)
'.) "' (.Ap '.) Ap) ... ) . But Aau ... , Aan EA so A is inconsistent, which is a contra
diction. Thus A* is a Lindenbaum set.
Lemma 9. Let A be a Lindenbaum set. Let a be any formula such that Da€A. ,...,
Proof. Suppose not; then there are formulae Aau ... ,Aam€A, {J1,... ,f3n
such that D/311 ... , Df3n €A and S5AR f- Aa1'.) (... '.) (Aam'.)({J1 '.) ... '.) (f3n '.)
'.)a) ... ) ) . .. ) . By necessitation and the S5 thesis D(y '.)a)'.) ( Dy'.) Do) we
obtain by repeated use of modus ponens
SSAR f- OAa1 '.J (... '.J (OAam '.J ( Df31 '.J . '.J (Df3n '.J Oa) ... )) . .. ) .
..
By .Axiom (.A4) and modus ponens using Lemma 7, if Aai €A,OAai €A. Further
0{31,... , DfJn €A. Hence by Lemma 7, Oa€A. This contradicts the con
sistency of A.
Lemma 12. For each formula a, V(a, A)= T if and only if a€A.
W l=wA Op but W /oFw Op. (Notice that, in contrast with our first two examples,
this formula, A Op) Op, is a thesis of SSA.)
Lemma 15. (i) SSAR I- OAp = Ap; (ii) S5AR I- <)Ap = Ap.
This lemma and the examples above will ultimately show that the normal
form we now set out to establish is irreducible in an obvious sense.
First we shall establish the indirect redundancy of A in S5AR (see section 3
above).
Lemma 16. (i) SSAR 1- A( DAa = a); (ii) S5AR I- A( <)Aa = a).
Proof. We first put a into a form containing only the connectives ,...,, &, v,
O, <> and A. Next we move the negation signs as far into the formula as possible
using S5I- p= ,..., p, de Morgan's laws, the modal laws S5 I-
,...,
DP = <>,..., p
,...,
and SSI- <>P = D ,..., p and Lemma 5. In the formula so obtained, negation
,...,
signs can occur only immediately preceding propositional letters. Now we use
the modal reduction laws SS 1- <>P= D OP, SS 1- DP = O DP, S5 1- OP = OOP
and SS I- DP= D DP to reduce all iterated modalities to single modal operators.
Now we proceed by induction on the construction of the formula (which for
convenience we shall again call a) so obtained.
Case 1. If a is a propositional letter preceded by zero or more negation
signs, let a' = a.
Case 2. If a is of the form AP let a' = p then by Lemma 6, SSAR I- A (a = a').
Case 3.1. If a is of the forni op.
Subcase 3.11. If p is of the form ,..., y then y is a propositional variable so a
does not contain A, so let a' = a.
Subcase 3.12. If p is of the form Ay then by Lem:ma 16, S5ARI- A(D Ay = y)
so let a'= y'. By Lemma 5, S5ARI- A(a = y').
Subcase 3.13. p is of the form y& b. Then SSAR I- DP = Dy& Ob. By the
induction hypothesis there exist formulae y', b', not containing A such that
26
Corollary 19.
There is an effective proceditre which assigns to each formula a
a formiila a' not containing A such that S5AR I- Aa = Aa'.
'Ne now proceed to our normal form theorem.
Given a formula a we perform the following reductions on it. By virtue of
Corollary 19 above and theorems of 85 it will follow at each stage that the
formula a* obtained is such that S5AR f- a = a*.
Step 1. \Vrite a so that its only connectives are , &, v, D, <) and A.
,...,
Step 2. Use the laws of negation and modalities and Lemma 5 to move
negation signs inwards as far as possible, so that they only precede propositional
letters and at the same time cancel double negations.
Step 3. For any well-formed part of a which is of the form A,8 and is not
properly contained in any other well formed part of a beginning with A use
Corollary 19 to obtain a formula ,B' such that S5AR I- A,8 = A,8' where ,B' does
not contain A. Replace A,8 by A,B'. The formula now obtained contains no
nested occurrences of A .
Step 4. Reduce all iterated modalities to single modal operators by the
reduction laws of the modal logic SS.
Step 5. If the combination DA or <)A occurs in a replace the combination
by A. The resulting formula is still equivalent to the original one by Lemma 15.
Step 6. If the resulting formula still contains a modal operator with an occur
rence of a modal operator or A in its scope, apply step 6.1 or 6. 2 according as
a nested part is of the form D,8 or <),8.
Step 6.11. D,8 is of the form D(y& o). Then replace this by Dy& Do.
Then the resulting formula is still provably equivalent to a in S5AR.
Step 6.12. D,8 is of the form D(yVOo) where O is D or <); replace this
by OyvOo. Similarly for D(Oyvo). The resulting formula is still provably
equivalent to a in S5AR.
27
Step 6.13. 0(3 is of the form (.AyVo). Then replace this part by .Ayv Do.
Similarly for (yv.Ao). Since SSAR f- D(.Ayvo) = D.Ayv Do = .AyvD o the
resulting formula is still provably equivalent to a in SSAR.
Step 6.14. DP is of the form yva where neither y nor a begins with .A, D
or <). Since yvo contains a modal operator either y or a must be a conjunction.
Suppose y= s&C then S5AR I- DP= D{(s&C)vb) = D{(svo)&(Cvo)).
So replace DP by D(svo)& D(Cvo). Similarly if o is a conjunction.
Step 6.2 . .As for 6.1 with <) replacing D and & replacing v and vice versa.
Step 7. Use Lemma 5 to move the operators .A as far in as possible p:;i.st all
propositional connectives except �.
W2 = {w*, w�, .. . , w;,.} and W= W1 u W2• V\Te set wRw' for w, w' E W if and
only if w, w' E W1 or w , w' E W2• \-Ye define V as follows. By hypothesis there
are assignments V0 , ••• , Vm and V�, ... , V� making the formulae in (**) and (***)
false. Let V (p , wi )=V i (p), V ( p, w*) = V� ( p) and V ( p , w� ) = V� (p) for
0 <i <m, 1 <j<n .
Now we consider V( (*) , w0). By construction V ( avy , w0)=If so V ( a , w0)=F
and V (y , w0)=JJ'. Similarly V (y , wi)=F for 1 <i<m, but w0 , , Wm are all
• • •
the worlds R-related to w0 so V ( ()y , w0) =F. Since V ({h, wi) =F, V (DPi , wi)=F
for O<i<m. Hence V ( aVDP1V ... YDPmV()y , Wo)=F.
Similarly V (a'VDP�V... VDP�V()y', w*) =F. But
References
[l] Cast ane d a, H. N.: Some Nonformal "Logical" Relations, Phi los. Studies, Vol. 8 (1957),
89-92.
[2] H u gh es G. E. and Cress w e l l M. J.: An Introduction to Modal Logic, London, Methuen,
1968.
[3] Ka m p J. .A. W.: Formal Properties of 'Now', Theoria, Vol. 37 (1971), 227-273.
[4] Ka p l a n D.: The Logic of Demonstratives (Unpublished, Circa 1970).
[5] M a k i nson D. C.: On some completeness theorems in modal logic, Zeits. f. Math. Logik
u. Grundlagen d. Math. Vol. 12 (1966), 379-384.
[6] M e n d e lson E.: Introduction to Mathematical Logic, Princeton, van Nost rand, 1968.
[7] M o n t a g u e R.: Logical Necessity, Physical Necessity, Ethics, and Quantifiers, Inquiry,
Vol. 4 (1960), 259-269.