Untitled
Untitled
Loyola eCommons
1948
Recommended Citation
Langenderfer, Norman H., "The Theory of Supposition: An Answer to Some of the Difficulties of Modern
Logicians" (1948). Master's Theses. 257.
https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/257
This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It
has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more
information, please contact [email protected].
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License.
Copyright © 1948 Norman H. Langenderfer
THE THEORY OF SUPPOSITION
AN ANSWER
TO SOME OF THE DIFFICULTIES OF MODERN LOGICIANS
BY
NORMAN H. LANGENDERFER, S. J.
OCTOBER
1948
VITA AUCTORIS
Page
Preface ------------------------------------~------------ i.
Chapter I --- An Introduction to the Problem. ----------- 1.
The purpose of the thesis. ··-· Chief exponents and
the philosophical trend of thought on which the dis-
cipline has been built. •••• Description of modern
logic. •••• Formal definition. •••• The objects of
modern and traditional logic. •••• The supposition
of terms -- the problem.
Chapter II --- Purpose and Use of Supposition in Tradi-
tional Logic. ---------------------------~ 26.
Limitations of a system of language-signs in expres-
sing the thought of the mind. •••• Diverse properties
of a term in a proposition. •••• The diverse of a
term in a proposition a point of study in logic.
•••• The need of these properties. •••• Modern lo-
gicians are conscious of the same difficulty. ••••
Number of properties. •••• Definition of supposition.
•••• Must meet the needs of the copula. •••• Natural
and accidental supposition. •••• Supposition and sig-
nification. •••• Supposition must be consistent. ••••
Amplification and restriction of a supposition. ••••
The object of logic for traditional and modern lo-
gicians. •••• Objections of modern logicians.
Chapter III --- An Application of the Boole-Schroeder
Algebra to the Syllogism and the Result-
ing Difficulties. ---------------------- 41.
A few symbols of modern logic. •••• Standard propo-
sitions of logic symbolized ••••• Existence and non-
existence implied in the symbolized proposition •••
•• Application of the algebra to the AAA syllogism.
•••• Mechanical elimination of the middle term •••
•• Importance of the universality of the middle
term. •••• Application o£ the algebra to an AII syl-
logism. •••• Application of the algebra to a fal-
lacious syllogism ••••• Application of the alge-
bra to an EAO syllogism. •••• The existence and
non-existence implied in universal and particular
propositions. •••• An argument from the notion of
the null-class. •••• Types of existence implied
in propositions. •••• Resulting conclusions of
modern logicians.
Chapter IV --- Supposition -- An Answer to Some of the
Modern Logicians' Difficulties. ----------- 59.
Natural and accidental supposition. •••• Proposi-
tions in necessary matter imply no actual exis-
tence. •••• ·Propositions in necessary matter may
be universal or particular. •••• Propositions in
contingent matter imply actual existence •••••
Propositions in contingent matter may be universal
or particular ••••• Use of amplification andre-
striction to vary supposition. •••• In subalterna-
tion, partial conversion, and certain syllogistic
moods of inference the conclusion is legitimate.
•••• Mathematical procedure a difficulty to mo-
dern logic.
Chapter V --- The Use of the Supposition of Terms in
Modern Logic. ~-~--------------------------- 69.
The technique of modern logic follows that of
mathematics. •••• System-form of symbols needed.
•••• Things for which the symbols stand. ••••
Meaning of the symbols. •••• Problem of the null-
class ••••• Meaning of the null-class and the
empty class. •••• The significance of the symbol
11 11
0 for the mathematicians ••••• Its significance
in modern logic. •••• A point about the principle
of contradiction ••••• Null-class in traditional logic •
•••• Symbols have a substitutive value. •••• Logic
has a reference to reality ••••• Purpose of modern
logic ••••• The negligence of the modern logicians.
Bibliography
PREFACE
has its own particular approach, and some of them express diffe~
Leibniz 1 s idea was, indeed, novel and gave rise to the la-
ter developments of symbolic or mathematical logic. The success
of Leibniz•s work would have been greater, say most modern w.ri-
ters, if he had not been impeded by certain traditional laws in
regard to the intension and extension or the subject and pre-
dicate.l7
18 Enriques, 115.
19 1!2.!,g. 1 110.
20 ~., 111.
8.
development of thought obeys certain inner con-
trolling forces, and in the different currents
there can still be seen a reflection of tradi-
tional problems. The various specialized ten-
dencies are in this way reunited in firm knots
which give birth to higher doctrines. In short,
that order which mind is not able to derive
from external nature it finds in itself, in the
full freedom of its activities. It is not, how-
ever, an order that is giv~n; it is one that is
progressively constructed. 1
One fact stands out clear at this point in the discussion,
namely, that hand in hand with the new developments in mathe-
matics the dichoto~ of the processes of the mind trom external
reality was becoming wider. Modern mathematics possessed a dif-
ferent aspect from classical mathematics, which "held to the ex-
igencies of guantitas interminata.n22 Cassirer in speaking
about mathematics expresses this very point. He says:
Here a field of free and universal activity
is disclosed in Which thought transcends all
limits of the 'given'. The objects which we
consider and into whose objective nature we
seek to penetrate, have only an ideal being;
all the properties which we can predicate of
them, flow exclusively from the law of their
original construction.23
In the abstract science, then, of mathematics the whole con
struction flows from first principles which form the foundation
of the mathematical science. Whether these first principles are
in anyway connected with the physical sciences is arbitrary; the
27 Enriques, 158.
28 Lewis and Langford, 1 - 8.
11.
11
he developed many new forms of propositions with the rules for
transformation and the statement of equivalents.n29 We will
pass over the validity of these propositions at present, and
merely state that his versatile mind made great strides in the
development of modern logic. By investigating the modes of in-
ference according to his principles he found new classifications
and presented principles to g~vern them.30
29 Ibid., a.
30 Ibid.
31 !D!a., 9. •
32 Enriques, 159 - 160.
12.
it is Boola who is remembered for his algebra of classes.33
37 Ibid., 16.
38 Ibid., 22 - 23.
39 Enriques, 169.
14.
different fashion, The calculus of classes for him is derived
from the calculus of propositions. Peano, also, developed his
work along this line. For him, however, the precedence of the
calculus was merely a contingent matter, Whereas for Russell it
expresses a fundamental logical relation.4o
4o Ibid., 169.
41 Ibid., 170.
geometry and calculus started the search for a new universal
science which could be used in all knowledge. Boola's algebra
achieved this to some extent, and showed that some mathematical
operations could be applied to logic. Russell and Whitehead de-
veloped the discipline further and defined all arithmetical idea
in terms of logical notions.42
42 Kocourek, 98.
16.
and sensibly real objects.n43
4.3Wel1muth, 5.
W+ Ibid., 8.
45 Ibid., 8.
46 Leonard J. Eslick, "Grammatical and Logical Form,"
lasticism, XIII (1939), 233 - 244. --
New Scho-
pure sense experience, there is a possibility that this might be
true. But the mind has the power of thinking on its sense ex-
periences, and as such, may make mistakes despite the perfection
of the language. Language is of great importance in the accur-
ate presentation of thought. However, a study of language is
not logic. Logic, as Maritain remarks, nbears upon the act of
reason itself,n47 and therefore is concerned about the thought
content.48
56 Wellmuth, 156.
57 Ibid.
58 Ibid., 162.
21.
in experimental science, but it must not be confused with tra-
ditional logic.59 Traditional logic also is a formal science.60
But 1 formal 1 has a slightly different meaning according to the
traditional logicians. Traditional logic is formal in so far
as it "studies what reasoning is, and how it must proceed what-
ever ll.! content or the use which mind makes of it.n61 To stop
there in our description of traditional logic would leave plenty
of room for ambiguity. Although traditional logic has a formal
aspect it is not by any means purely a study of form. Maritain
writes: "Since logic is the art which enables us to proceed
with ease, order and correctness in the act of reason itself, it
must treat both the ,!:2!:!!! and the matter of our reasoning. n6 2
59 Kocourek, 98.
60 Mari tain, 9.
61 Ibid~, 10.
62 Ibid., 9
63 "Tlie'"use of the word 'formal' in modern logic has many and
varied meanings. Father Wellmuth in his manuscript makes a
rather detailed analysis of the term. 146-155. Such an an-
alysis is outside the scope of this paper.
22.
would require a consideration of the content of propositions,
that is, in so far as demonstration concludes to the ~ or
false. Demonstration is had in a certain sense in formal logic,
that is, in so far as formal logic sets forth the rules which
must be observed if demonstration is to be correct in relation
to the disposition of materials. But demonstration cannot be
had in formal logic in so far as demonstration concludes to the
true or false since reasoning attains to the true or false in
virtue of the matter. For demonstration, as Aristotle says, ~
67 Eslick, 233.
68 ~., 235 - 236.
69 Maritain, 222.
~------------------------------------------~
24.
might be answered by recalling that modern logic is said to have
its foundation in mathematics,70 and is defined as, "a deductive
science of deduction in general." This i'ormal study is con-
structed, as Father Wellmuth mentions, according to the methods
of pure mathematics. Now, pure mathematics is a system of
theorems deduced from a set of undefined elements, properties,
functions, and relations, and a set of unproved propositions by
the methods of formal logic Which abstracts completely from all
reality.71 Thus, just as pure mathematics is concerned with the
realtions between the mathematical symbols which represent the
postulates and definitions, so modern logic is concerned with
the relations between "ideographic signs" which represent the
expressions of our thought.72 Here, then, can be faintly seen
the close relationship between modern logic and pure mathematics.
CHAPTER II
THE PURPOSE AND USE OF
SUPPOSITION IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC
74 Maritain, 58.
~·------------------------------~
27.
twofold effort is had there remains "but a radically insufficien
system of lifeless symbols.n75 In consequence of this Maritain
continues:
Hence a twofold necessity accrues to philosophy:
it must acquire a mastery over language by
means of a whole technical apparatus of forms
and verbal distinctions (terminology), and it
must unceasingly exact from the mind an act of
internal vitality such that[si~words and for-
mulae can never replace, for they are there
but to spur the mind to this act. ••• Lan-
guage, then, expresses or signifies as much of
our thought as is necessary in order that an-
other intellect, hearing the pronounced ~ords,
may present the same thought to itself. 7
75 Ibid.
76 Ibid., 59
-
77 Ibid.
28.
stated. Its full significance is only going to be understood
by a study of the diverse properties that affect the term in the
proposition.
80 Maritain, 59.
81 Joannes A s. Thoma, 28-42, 166-179. Ct. Javelli sub su~~ositio
82 Javelli, Logicae Compendium Peripateticae, VenetiiS, 1541, 168
)0.
analysis and the shaping accordingly a new
language arter the fashion or algebra. 8 3
It is, indeed, a commendable ambition to attempt to remove the
inadequacies o£ language, but it is a gross error to say, as
some writers do, that the ancient logicians were in ignorance
about this difficulty, and, therefore, made rather grievous
errors in inference.84
89 Ibid.
90 .Ibid., 61. Cf. Joannes As. Thoma, 29, 168.
33.
thing, and is said to have a natural supposition, because it is
11
always connected with the predicate. In such a case the copula
denotes possible existence only, and is thus outside or time."9l
11
For example, if' I say, The three angles of' a triangle are equal
to 180 degrees," I am stating a proposition in which the predi-
cate is essential to the subject, and as such is always true
even though a triangle does not actually exist here and now.
When the predicate, however, is accidental to the subject, e.g.
11
My dog is white," it is necessary to know if' the subject has a
substitutive value berore it can be said to be true, because the
copula expresses actual existence, or "existence in time.n92
in this paper. Whatever the substitutive value may be, the im-
portant thing is that it conform with the principles we have al-
ready discussed, namely, (1) the supposition of a term must meet
the exigencies of the copula, (2) the supposition and the signi-
fication of a term, and, (3) the supposition must re~ain con-
sistent in a valid inference.
97~.
37.
of this seems evident when we remember that language or words
are merely a material instrument used to express the thought of
a spiritual faculty -- the intellect --, which rises above
material elements in its operations. Furthermore, the fact that
a single word can have the same meaning and yet have different
substitutive values in speech will always demand the operation
11
of distinguishing" in human discourse. As long as the hUman
intellect is able to function, never will a system of signs be
so perfect as to eliminate thought, and always will there remain
a margin of thought in any discourse which will demand more than
pure passivity on the part of the receiving mind.
-
98 Ibid., 232.
38.
Professor Reichenbach. He writes: "Symbolic logic is the analy-
sis of language."99 If we accept this statement at its face
value it seems to follow that symbolic logic is nothing more
than an analysis of a set of words. In symbolic logic the lo-
gician is interested, as Reichenbach puts it, in the "mechanical
11
manipulations with symbols." These symbols, as he adds, are
distinguished only by geometrical shape," and "take the place of
thought operations based on realizing the meaning of the sym-
bols.ulOO
99 Reichenbach, 2.
100 Ibid., 165.
101 iir!tain, 226.
39.
Since the objects of modern and traditional logic are so
different, the two should, it seems, remain entirely diverse dis-
ciplines. Modern logicians, however, view the situation under
a different light, and as a result, maintain that they are
making additions in traditional logic,l02 and even, in fact,
finding certain principles of traditional logic erroneous.l03
The syllogism in general, subslternation, partial conversion, and
the square of opposition receive the brunt of their criticisms.
A rather lengthy and summary quotation from Lewis and Langford,
I believe, will bring the heart of the objection more clearly to
light. They write:
Traditional logic is primarily a logic of
terms. The laws of identity, contradiction,
and the excluded middle, the dictum de omn1
~ nullo, and the rules of the syllogisiiia'Il
tell us what must be or what cannot be true
of the relations of terms. But terms have
both intension and extension; they connote
concepts or essential attributes, and they
denote things or classes. The laws of inten-
sion and those of extension are analogous,
••• the relation of a given set of terms in
intension may not be parallel to their rela-
tions in extension. For example, "No tres-
passers are arrested" might be true in ex-
tension, meaning that the class of actually
arrested trespassers has no members; but
false in intension, meaning that the concepts
'trespassing' and 'being arrested' are mutual-
ly incompatible ••••
And a logic which is adequate to all pro-
positions must, therefore, cover both inten-
sion and extension. The traditional logic
110 Ibid.,55.
111 ESlick, 235.
r
.!.2 + !; -.£ =0
but, since,the middle term is not positive in one premise and
negative in the other, no conclusion can be drawn. The modern
logicians attempt to explain this by calling attention to the
form of the syllogism. The two premises of the syllogism affirm
that something is equal to 0, and the conclusion that something
is not equal to 0 1 or in other words, the premises assert a
non-existence, and the conclusion an existence. Thus the syllo-
gism is invalid because it implies an existence which is said
not to be implied in the premises. Lewis and Langford write in
this regard that "universals affirm that something is = o, and
particulars that something is I o. -
That is, a universal pro-
position in extension asserts a non-existence •••• and a parti-
cular proposition in extension asserts an existence.n119 As a
result, modern writers of logic immediately conclude that
-
122 Ibid., 62.
r
53.
universal propositions do not imply existence, and particular
propositions always imply it. About this last point a question
at present will perhaps give the general trend of the solution
which will follow. Does a particular proposition imply existenc
because it is a particular proposition, or, is it because it ex-
presses a contingent truth?
~ Quaestiones Duo-
123 Thomas Aquinas, Quaestiones Disputatae
decim uodlibetales, ~ Verit., I, 1, ad 3 in contr., Marl-
ett!, Taurini, 19 1, III.
124 Maritain, 53.
r 54.
that has no existence at all. The universal contradictory pro-
position of "Some centaurs are not Greeks 11 could be had only i.f
some type of ~ were present, since contradictory propositions
- --
require esse and non-esse. But i.f centaurs have no existence,
there would be no~ o.f any kind in either the universal affir-
mative or particular negative proposition. Furthermore, neither
truth or falsity can be had once existence has been denied,
since truth .follows existence.l25 Thus, once centaurs are de-
nied all form o.f existence there can be no question of contra-
dictory propositions, or of truth and .falsity.
--
or ideal, and a proper understanding of esse and non-esse for
-
contradictory propositions must be had. The whole purpose of
the argument is to prove that universal propositions do not
CHAPTER IV
SUPPOSITION -- AN ANSWER
TO SOME OF ~~E MODERN LOGICIANS• DIFFICULTIES
l48 Ibid.
149 :fOannes A s. Thoma, 37.
r
65
expresses existence, but a possible existence, that is, it is
able to exist in the physical order. On the other hand the
statement "The centaur is a fabulous creature" expresses exis-
tence, but ideal existence, that is, an existence that is only
in the mind. It was not uncommon to vary the supposition from
ideal to actual, or actual to ideal existence. The whole pro-
cess did not require any special reference in the proposition
itself, but the logician who had made a study of the diverse
properties of the term was conscious of what took place, and was
careful to keep the kind of existence, whether ideal or real,
the same throughout his reasoning proeess. If he understood the
premises to imply actual existence, he was consistent and main-
tained an actual existence in the conclusion. For example, the
syllogism,
All men are mortal,
But Stalin is a man,
Therefore, Stalin is mortal.
The major premise asserts an eternal truth, and in itself does
not imply actual existence, but the traditional logician would
be careful to understand actual existence, and, therefore, keep
the supposition consistent throughout the reasoning. Again, the
syllogism that the modern logicians keep presenting to show the
ambiguities of traditional logic causes no trouble once the
supposition of terms is undarstood. The syllogism,
66.
No absentees are failed,
But all absentees receive a grade of zero,
Therefore, some who receive a grade of zero do not fai
The syllogism arrives at a perfectly valid conclusion as long as
it is remembered that the existence implied in the two premises
is restricted to actual existence. This use of the supposition
is frequent in traditional logic, and was clearly understood by
traditional logicians before they began a study of syllogistic
inference. It is in the light of this that Javelli remarked,
~ autem adverte novitie, guod.praedictas defensiones servare
~ poteris, donee intellexeris tractatum suppositionum et ~
67.
writers say imply actual existenee, 1 51 may express eternal
truths, and, in so far as they express eternal truths, they do
not imply actual existence because a proposition that has an
essential supposition or expresses an eternal truth 11 abstracts
from time in its verification."l5 2 Furthermore, a particular
proposition in which the subject has only an accidental supposi-
tion and implies real existence, may be understood as having
only an ideal or possible existence.
CHAPTER V
THE USE OF THE SUPPOSITION OF TERMS
IN MODERN LOGIC
16,3 Ibid.
164 George Boole, The Mathematical Analysis £! Logic, 3, as
quoted by Enriques, 127
74.
a sense, the indefinite is always definitely determined. This
still does not mean, however, that the interpretation given is
without its ambiguities. A symbol is a symbol only in so far as
it directs someone's attention to a thinkable something-or-othen
But when an interpretation is given the symbol, two questions,
as Father Wellmuth also notes, might be asked: (1) What object
of thought does the user intend? And when the object of thought
is recognized, (2) does the symbol represent the results of a
correct logical analysis? Thus despite the exacting efforts of
modern logicians in the representation of the objects of thought
through symbols, they still have their difficulties, for the
most accurate symbol in the most carefully written treatise can-
not tell us the precise intended meaning as used by a particular
user on a particular occasion.l65 The difficulties that might
arise from this are beyond the scope of this paper. It might
be remarked, however, that all the difficulties that follow from
an improper use of supposition will be present. The point that
we wish to make at present is that although the symbols may re-
ceive many forms of interpretation, they still have a substitu-
tive value, even though it is a purely ideal one. That is,
whenever an interpretation is given, the symbols stand for a de-
11
finite thinkable something-or-othertt in the mind.
Summing up, then, this perhaps can be said, that all the
symbols do have some real substitutive value, and that those
that do not have any value have no meaning, either in mathematics
or in modern logic. A response to our first question now seems
11
to appear, Is there a place for the use of supposition in mo-
dern logic"? We can answer in the affirmative, that .there is,
and without it modern logicians become merely nthoughtless
thinkers."