Wanting and Liking
Wanting and Liking
Author Manuscript
Inquiry (Oslo). Author manuscript; available in PMC 2010 August 1.
Published in final edited form as:
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
KENT C. BERRIDGE
University of Michigan, USA
Abstract
Different brain mechanisms seem to mediate wanting and liking for the same reward. This may have
implications for the modular nature of mental processes, and for understanding addictions,
compulsions, free will and other aspects of desire. A few wanting and liking phenomena are presented
here, together with discussion of some of these implications.
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
for an outcome is distinguishable from both experienced utility (hedonic impact or “liking”
the outcome) and forecast or predicted utility (expecting in advance to like an eventual
outcome). This is part of what makes “wanting” a unique module and quite different from
wanting (no quotation marks) in the usual sense of the word as a conscious, cognitive desire.
That is why my colleagues and I put quotation marks around “wanting” when writing about
incentive salience. Ordinarily, incentive salience “wanting” is congruent with other forms of
desire such as cognitive wanting, and is also congruent with the hedonic pleasure or “liking”
of the outcome. But dissociations can occur among all of these utility forms, and when they
do incentive salience is revealed as a distinct module of desire.
How does ordinary wanting in the usual sense of desires differ from “wanting”? Ordinary
cognitive desires involve explicit thoughts of the target or reward. In cognitive desires, or
wanting in the ordinary sense without quotation marks, you know what you want, or at least
think you do, you expect to like the wanted target, and you may have some idea of how you
Correspondence Address: Kent C. Berridge, 4038 East Hall, Psychology Department, 525 E University St, Ann Arbor, MI 48109-1109,
USA. [email protected].
BERRIDGE Page 2
intend to get it. Such desires are guided by explicit memories of how nice the target was in the
past, or if never before experienced then at least on imagination of what it would be like to
experience.
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
By contrast, none of this cognition need be part of incentive salience “wants”. Incentive salience
is a percept-bound type of “wanting”, which typically occurs as relatively brief peaks upon
encountering a reward or a physical reminder of the reward (a cue). Incentive salience does
not require a clear cognition of what is wanted, and does not even need to be consciously
experienced as a feeling of wanting, at least in some cases (though when it is brought into
consciousness it can considerably intensify feelings of desire). Perhaps a reason for the
difference is that incentive salience is mediated chiefly by subcortical brain mechanisms,
whereas cognitive forms of desire are more dependent on higher cortex-based brain systems.
Incentive salience may have evolved using early brain systems as a distinct “wanting” module
to pursue particular innate incentives. Possibly it gave an elementary form of goal directedness,
which could guide behavior in the right direction in advance of experiencing the goals. Later
in evolution “wanting” may have become harnessed to serve “liking” and learned features of
reward, so that most incentive salience in our lives today is probably attributed to learned
reward cues.
Incentive salience as a module is only one type of wanting. It is not the one we are most aware
of in daily life nor the type of desire that has been the greatest focus of philosophers. But
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
incentive salience is important in daily life, as it is needed to color conscious desires with
motivational power, to make them compelling spurs to action. It may be a crucial component
of our most intense and visceral desires, and especially important in the pathological intensity
of some addictions and compulsive desires.
salience also triggers momentary peaks of intense motivation to obtain a cued reward. Such
features (reward cues becoming motivational magnets, cues as objects of desire, peaks of cue-
triggered “wanting” for the actual reward) allow us to recognize incentive salience in
behavioral neuroscience experiments with animals as well as in people.
In the neuroscience experiments, we manipulate the brains of rats or mice in painless ways that
alter the operation of underlying substrates for “wanting”, using techniques such as
microinjection of tiny drug droplets into a targeted brain structure. Such microinjections remain
painless because they are made through a permanently implanted cannula that was previously
fixed in place when the rat was under surgical anesthesia.
When activated by a brain microinjection, the chief features of incentive salience that become
enhanced are cue-triggered “wanting” for rewards, the potency of reward cues as motivational-
magnet, and their potency as conditioned reinforcers. These features are described below.
Pavlovian conditioned stimuli or CSs) with an ability to trigger powerful peaks of “wanting”
for their own associated reward. For example, the scent of food may suddenly make you
ravenous as lunchtime approaches even if you were not feeling particularly hungry moments
before that cue occurred. As suggested by Olav Gjelsvik in his Workshop commentary, the
arrival of a dessert trolley at your restaurant table may make you succumb at that moment to
the temptation to indulge. The tinkling sound of an email arriving in your computer inbox may
trigger a sudden urge to check the message. In all such cases, cue-triggered “wanting” occurs
as a temporary peak, bound to a particular encounter with a cue or to a vivid mental image of
the reward. Peaks of cue-triggered “wanting” are sudden, intense, temporary, reversible and
repeatable.
activation selectively increased the peaks of “wanting” for a sugary reward that were triggered
by encounters with its cue (Wyvell & Berridge, 2001). Each cue was the sound of a beeping
tone that on previous occasions had predicted a sugar pellet reward (the cue is sometimes called
a Pavlovian CS or conditioned stimulus in literature on such experiments).
The sound of the cue triggered the rat to engage in a burst of effort in pressing on a lever that
had previously earned it sugar pellets. Each CS cue lasted about 30 seconds, and the peak of
enhanced “wanting” lasted not much longer. More stable forms of desire that continued to
motivate working for the reward in the absence of the cue were not enhanced by amphetamine
microinjections (including cognitive expectancies of the reward or habitual goal-seeking
responses that continue stably whether the cue is present or not). So in a half-hour session, as
the cue came and went several times, bursts of cue-triggered “wanting” appeared as mountain
peaks resting on a plateau of stable motivation. The effect of mesolimbic dopamine activation
was to selectively make the mountain peaks of “wanting” taller without changing the elevation
of the plateau on which they sat, and the higher the amphetamine dose, the higher the peaks of
cue-triggered “wanting” became (Figure 1). Each peak of cue-triggered “wanting” lasted less
than a minute after the cue, regardless of height. Of course the exact temporal features in this
example are peculiar to rats, and human “wanting” peaks might well last longer if powered by
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
sustained imagery about the reward. But the example helps show how cue-bound incentive
salience depends closely on percepts even when the brain is activated more constantly.
“Wanting” occurs as a temporary burst linked to the cue presence, and mesolimbic brain
systems need a cue on which to act in order to motivate. In the experiment described, a rat’s
brain would have been constantly flooded with dopamine after an amphetamine microinjection,
yet its “wanting” came and went with the coming and going of the physical cue for sugar.
Incentive salience thus reflects a synergy between brain states of mesolimbic activation and
particular events happening in the world. Both must be present to trigger the “want”. These
constraints of operation help show the psychological boundaries of the “wanting” module and
reveal it as just one among several psychological mechanisms of desire—albeit a powerful one
when present.
make that stimulus “wanted”, even if the stimulus is just the cue. The Pavlovian CS stimulus
becomes an attractive “motivational magnet” itself, in addition to triggering “wanting” for its
hedonic reward, although the CS cue is only a learned predictor for the reward with no intrinsic
value of its own. In a sense, a cue can even become “good enough to eat”. Stephen Mahler in
our lab has shown that activating incentive salience makes a rat more intensely approach,
handle, and even try to “consume” a metal object whose presence predicts sugar, with nibbles
and sniffs of the metal cue that are similar to movements used in eating actual sugar (Mahler
& Berridge, 2009). Cues for other rewards become attractive in their own ways. Crack cocaine
addicts, for instance, have been reported to compulsively “chase ghosts” when they have no
cocaine, that is to scrabble around on the floor after tiny whitish specks under the table, even
if they know the specks are more likely to be sugar than cocaine (Rosse et al., 1993). They are
chasing a visual cue for cocaine: white specks. Such motivational magnet features of attractive
cues are made much more potent by activation of mesolimbic systems, such as the amygdala
or nucleus accumbens. Motivational magnet features of reward cues may account for a host of
phenomena in which individuals become pulled toward reward cues acting as beacons to guide
brain motivation systems.
A related mark of a motivational magnet is that individuals may “want” to possess that cue,
just as they “want” its hedonic reward. Animals in an activated brain state will work harder to
obtain a CS or cue that is attributed with incentive salience, just as they would work to obtain
the actual reward. This is sometimes called conditioned reinforcement. For example, rats will
learn to press a lever or poke their nose into a hole simply in order to obtain a sound or other
cue-event or object that has been previously associated with a sugar reward or a cocaine reward.
Activating their mesolimbic brain systems makes them work much harder at it. People too may
sometimes “want” cues for particular rewards, as when a miser wishes to handle and count the
physical money as coins or notes in the hand, motivated to feel these mere cues or symbols,
above and beyond possessing the monetary wealth. And perhaps to be motivated to obtain mere
symbols is not unknown even among academics.
to poppy-derived opiate drugs like opium, heroin or morphine), glutamate and GABA. We
have often used dopamine and opioid activations in mesolimbic structures to turn on incentive
salience in our laboratory. The dopamine neurons project from the midbrain (this origin gives
the “meso” portion of the name) where their neuronal cell bodies are, sending axon fibers
upwards to nucleus accumbens, other parts of striatum, amygdala and prefrontal neocortex
(these targets give the “limbic” portion). Opioid neurons live within these structures
themselves, as well as entering in from deep brain sites. Amygdala and cortex neurons project
down to nucleus accumbens, forming a common interchange there. Nucleus accumbens in turn
projects downwards to ventral pallidum and eventually up again into prefrontal cortex, and
also again back down to midbrain, where the process can start over, forming recursive loops
for reward-related signals.
Sensitization of mesolimbic systems arises as a permanent change that addictive drugs can
produce in the brains of susceptible individuals. Sensitization increases the neurochemical
responsiveness of these neurons and can even change their physical shapes. Individual
susceptibility is determined by genetic factors, hormonal factors, previous drug experiences,
and previous experiences with major stresses in life. Sensitization is also influenced by drug
dose and the speed with which it reaches the brain, and is facilitated most when the drugs are
taken in binges. Neural sensitization of mesolimbic dopamine systems means that the brain
system becomes hyperreactive to drugs. The system is not constantly hyperactive in a stable
fashion, but it can be put temporarily into a hyperactive state by reaction to the drug again or
to related cues: it is hyper-reactive to particular stimuli. Sensitization of mesolimbic systems
may create compulsive levels of “wanting” for drugs or other addictive incentives. A sensitized
brain responds with extra incentive salience to reward cues just as a brain that has been drugged
with amphetamine does—even if the sensitized brain has no drug on board at that moment. A
sensitized addict’s brain, on encountering the right drug cue, would irrationally “want” the
cued reward at that moment because of excessive incentive salience—even if the person
cognitively expected not to like it very much and eventually did not like it much in the end.
And crucially, sensitization may last years after an individual stops taking any drugs.
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
What are the neural bases of pleasure “liking” itself? A much more restricted brain circuit
appears to mediate hedonic “liking” rather than incentive “wanting” (Peciña, Smith, &
Berridge, 2006; Smith et al., 2009). The generation of pleasure “liking” is more restricted
neurochemically: opioid stimulation but not dopamine stimulation in some limbic strutures
can enhance “liking” (whereas “wanting” is enhanced by both). “Liking” is also more restricted
anatomically: enhanced by opioid “hotspots” but not by the rest of the same limbic structures
(even if the entire structure can enhance “wanting”). And “liking” generation is also more
restricted as a brain circuit, requiring unanimous activation of multiple hotspots simultaneously
(whereas “wanting” can be enhanced by a single hotspot). In short, enhancement of pleasure
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
“liking” is restricted and fragile, and brain pleasure systems are relatively recalcitrant to
activation compared to “wanting” systems. Consequently, our limbic mechanisms may consign
us more often to states of desire than of pleasure.
Hedonic hotspots are what my colleagues and I call the anatomically small pleasure-generating
islands of brain tissue contained within the larger sea of a limbic structure, such as nucleus
accumbens or ventral pallidum (Figures 2 and 3). The signature feature of these hedonic
hotspots is that they can generate increases in pleasure “liking” reactions when stimulated with
appropriate neurochemical microinjections. The size of each hotspot discovered so far is only
a cubic millimeter in volume of the brain of a rat. In the brain of a person a hotspot would be
expected to be about a cubic centimeter in volume, extrapolating on the basis of the difference
between rats and humans in whole brain size.
babies, for example, sweet tastes elicit positive facial “liking” expressions such as rhythmic
tongue protrusions and licking of the lips, whereas bitter tastes instead elicit negative
“disliking” expressions such as gapes (Steiner, Glaser, Hawilo, & Berridge, 2001). Essentially
the same facial reactions have evolved in apes, monkeys and rats as in humans. Whether human,
ape or rat, the brain seems to use the same mechanisms to generate sensory “liking”, and we
count on that similarity to find the brain bases of pleasure.
There are several hedonic hotspots scattered across the brain, as an archipelago of interacting
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
islands (Figure 2). The entire archipelago appears to become activated as a single integrated
circuit to amplify sensory pleasures. The various hotspots must cooperate together to do this.
For example, activation of one hotspot with an opioid microinjection automatically recruits
activation in other hotspots in different brain structures (Smith & Berridge, 2007). Pleasure
magnification requires unanimity among all opioid hotspots in nucleus accumbens and ventral
pallidum (Smith & Berridge, 2007). Pleasure will not be enhanced by a hotspot opioid
activation if unanimity is prevented by simultaneously suppressing another hotspot with an
opioid opposing drug. Although opioid stimulation of either hotspot would usually be sufficient
to enhance “liking”, it cannot do so if the larger circuit is prevented from joining in the
activation. However, “wanting” stimulation of “wanting” still persists after either hotspot is
activated, even if “liking” enhancement has been prevented. Thus partial activation of the
limbic circuit is enough to generate desire, whereas pleasure generation requires the whole.
Up to this point in the paper, my goal has been to describe some of the affective neuroscience
findings that gave rise to the notions of “wanting” and “liking”. In the remaining portion, I
would like to switch focus to potential implications of these ideas. In particular, I will turn to
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
a few philosophical issues regarding desire that were raised at the Oslo workshop, and try to
say something about what “liking” and “wanting” might mean for those issues.
However, it must be acknowledged that even cue-triggered “wanting” can detach to some
degree from the actual associated reward. Experiments have shown this detachment by using
manipulations to reduce the value of the actual reward from what was remembered before. In
such cases, the “wanting” may persist or widen inappropriately, as mentioned above, and at
least a partial widening of “wanting” is not uncommon.
A less reasonable form of intentionality seems involved when the cue itself becomes “wanted”
as a motivational magnet, rather than only the actual pleasant reward. When cues become the
focus of desire there is a slight distortion in the targeting of intentionality. No reason exists to
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
desire the cue, there is merely a psychological associative history and a neural mechanism that
makes it desired. In some addiction situations, an individual may become so obsessively
focused on the attractive cue that opportunities are lost to obtain the actual reward it is
associated with. In experiments when the mesocorticolimbic system for incentive salience is
activated, animals may persistently approach and gnaw on their cue even if doing so delays or
loses receipt of the actual reward.
“Wanting” of a cue as motivational magnet can detach further from intentional wanting of the
reward in some instances when the actual reward is devalued, such as by satiety or pairing with
aversive events. Similarly to the persistence of cue-triggered “wanting” after goal devaluation,
a cue may still sometimes be “wanted” and worked for even after its associated reward is no
longer valuable.
Least intentional of all may be the cases of truly indiscriminate attribution of incentive salience
we began with, in which nearly everything becomes simultaneously “wanted” at once. Certain
forms of brain mesolimbic activation may cause diffuse “wanting” attribution to all stimuli
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
that are present. A brain electrode activation or a drug microinjection in some limbic structure,
and perhaps brain sensitization in some cases of human addiction might activate the system to
a very high degree, and simultaneously disrupt associative mechanisms that usually focus
“wanting” on a particular target. As a result, incentive salience in such cases may be attributed
broadly to many different stimuli at the same time. At the extreme, essentially everything
perceived at that moment might become more attractive and “wanted”. For example, some
people who have been implanted with brain stimulation electrodes in their mesolimbic systems
have been reported to describe the entire room as “brightening” in a motivational sense, so that
they perceive everyone present as more interesting, more socially attractive and even more
romantically or sexually attractive, and at that moment they feel motivated to do quite a number
of things. Such indiscriminate “wanting” is powerfully motivational, but when “everything”
is “wanted”, then nothing in particular is. Does such an unfocused desire have intentionality
at all?
“wanting” have been demonstrated in people ranging from drug addicts to ordinary college
students.
For instance, my former colleague Piotr Winkielman, who is now at the University of California
at San Diego, asked college students to view a computer screen on which they were told faces
would be flashed for ½ second, in which the student’s task was to identify the gender of the
face as woman or man (Winkielman & Berridge, 2004). Unbeknownst to the participants,
subliminally fast faces with happy or angry emotional expressions were also sometimes flashed
on the screen extremely briefly (1/60th second each). These brief flashes could not be
consciously seen nor the faces recognized later. Finally, the students were also told they would
subsequently be asked to judge a new fruit-flavored beverage that was under development by
a beverage company, and they were given a pitcher of the drink to pour, taste and rate before
the end of the session.
All the students reported their own hedonic mood and emotional feelings before and after
viewing the computer screen. Their reports completely failed to show any sign of the happy
or angry faces they had subliminally “seen”. They did not feel any increase in positive or
negative mood after seeing an emotional facial expression once they had finished their gender
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
identification task. Yet when presented a few minutes subsequently with the novel beverage,
students found the drink 50% more attractive after seeing the subliminal happy face, pouring
and drinking more and rating it more highly. Further, they expressed willingness to pay 4 times
more for the drink if it were sold when asked after the happy faces than after the angry faces.
We think the subliminal happy faces activated incentive mesolimbic circuits of “wanting” in
the brains of students who viewed them, which persisted for some minutes undetected as
students evaluated their own mood. The “wanting” surfaced only when an appropriate target
was finally presented in the form of a hedonically laden sweet stimulus that they could taste
and choose to ingest or not. Similarly, drug addicts who have been given an intravenous cocaine
dose too low to produce detectable physiological effects after pressing a button for it, have
been reported to say that the injection feels empty and completely devoid of any cocaine at all,
yet the addicts still work substantially more to receive more of the same “empty” dose.
Such instances of unconscious “wanting” suggest that incentive salience can at least sometimes
operate underneath conscious awareness. Mesolimbic “wanting” may run in parallel with
ordinary (and more cortex-mediated) wanting. Usually they point in the same direction, but in
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
cases of unconscious “wanting”, only one of the mechanisms seems to be in operation. These
cases may lack recruitment of the additional brain and psychological mechanisms needed under
more usual conditions to translate the core “wanting” process into a cognitive and conscious
desire, so that both motivate toward the same target. From the philosophical perspective,
doesn’t an unconscious “want” seem difficult to reconcile with intentionality in the usual sense?
To the degree that an unconscious “want” can be assigned to a malleable target, it does not
have an explicit object of desire. It has only a stimulus target, which may to some degree depend
on chance in the form of what happens to turn up next.
Could either impatience and urgency be related to incentive salience in any way? It seems
reasonable to speculate that incentive salience might on occasion contribute to impatience, by
making an outcome more intensely “wanted”. It is less clear whether urgency to act relates to
incentive salience at all, at least at first sight. Incentive salience as my colleagues and I have
typically conceived it is a property attributed to physical stimuli and their neuropsychological
counterparts: stimulus perceptions, and mental memories and images of absent objects or
events. By contrast, actions are not physical objects or stimulus sensory events, except in so
far as they produce sensation feedback during the act.
Still, I’d like to suggest that there may be a role for a mechanism in action similar to incentive
salience, which might be considered to contribute to urgency. I call this notion action
salience. My colleagues and I have often wondered whether an action-attributed form of
incentive salience might attach to action representations in the brain (e.g., motor programs),
just as “wanting” attaches to stimulus representations. If so, the transformation of the action
representation might give incentive properties to an action. As a consequence one might
urgently “want” to act. The urge to act may be evolutionarily old, and shared by animals and
humans. Mink, seals and polar bears may “want” to swim, rodents “want” to run, gnaw, and
build nests, and so on, and even people may have their own set of urgent actions (Elster,
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
2008; Glickman & Schiff, 1967; Mason, Cooper, & Clarebrough, 2001).
This possibility gains some physiological plausibility from considering that there is substantial
neurobiological overlap between brain dopamine systems of action and of desire. The two brain
systems are surprisingly intermingled: so surprisingly that neuroscientists have been hard
pressed to separate their two functions in experimental evidence, and in many experiments the
functions refuse to separate at all. To the degree they can be separated, here is the textbook
difference between them. A “nigrostriatal” system of dopamine projections exists just above
the mesolimbic system, and is implicated in action. The nigrostriatal action system is famous
for its involvement in Parkinson’s disease, and involves similar loops of neural circuitry. For
example, dopamine neurons project from midbrain to striatum; striatum sends its output down
to a pallidus target. The pallidus projects to thalamus and from there to cortex, which sends
loops back to striatum, and so on. The two systems even merge in some respects (for example,
signals in the mesolimbic system migrate up through spiralling circuits into the nigrostriatal
system) so that there is no strict division between them as they function. Could particular
dopamine activations of nigrostriatal circuits make actions “wanted” in the same sense that
mesolimbic activations make objects “wanted”? If so, action salience would be simply the
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
action mirror image of incentive salience, and “wanting” might contribute as a partial cause to
create a compelling urge to act—now!
Recent neuroscience results suggest “wanting” could contribute most to temporal discounting
when two conditions are simultaneously met: 1) mesolimbic dopamine systems are activated,
and 2) a cue is present for the immediate reward.
The simultaneous requirement of immediate cues and mesolimbic activation for a “wanting”
contribution to discounting is suggested by evidence from the laboratory of my colleague at
the University of Michigan, J. Wayne Aldridge (Tindell, Berridge, Zhang, Peciña, & Aldridge,
2005; Berridge & Aldridge, 2008). His team recorded the firing of limbic neurons in an output
station of mesocorticolimbic circuits that coded the incentive salience of reward cues.
Examining the effect of activating mesolimbic dopamine systems with drugs or with prior
sensitization, the team found that neuronal “wanting” signals were intensely enhanced by
mesolimbic activation—but only for a cue that signaled immediate reward. Another earlier cue
that predicted reward at greater temporal distance was not nearly as enhanced in signal by
dopamine activations (even though the earlier cue was only a little bit more separated in time
from the same reward).
Those neural results suggest that brain dopamine activation may specifically enhance cue-
triggered “wanting” for an immediately available reward, much more than for an even
moderately more distant reward. Cues for immediate reward are especially powerful at eliciting
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
desire and addictive relapse. For a recovering alcoholic, for example, the clink of the ice cubes
in the glass and smell of the alcohol that are associated with the drug may become able to
trigger compulsively high “wanting”. Even if the person has successfully resisted more
temporally-distant cues such as the sight of the tavern door or the bottle on the shelf, the clink,
or especially, smell, may break through the resolution to abstain and precipitate drinking again.
Immediate cues become especially dangerous. And if a recovering addict tries to take “just one
hit”, the limbic data of Aldridge and colleagues suggest that the combined neuronal
enhancements of inebriation and sensitization may add together into a one-two punch of doubly
extreme “wanting”. Such results may possibly help to provide a brain-based explanation of
why hyperbolic discounting especially describes the choices of sensitized addicts, the
inebriated, or even ordinary people who are in a momentary “hot” state that recruits
mesocorticolimbic circuits (Ainslie, 2001, 2008; Frederick et al., 2002).
frightening threat. They are hedonically opposite outcomes: one positive in valence and the
other negative. But desire and dread may share something surprisingly in common at
mechanistic levels, in the form of a shared affective building block. One possibility for overlap
was highlighted by George Ainslie at the Oslo workshop (Ainslie, 2008), and is described in
his article in this issue. Another possibility is found in recent results from our laboratory at
Michigan, which promote the idea that desire and dread may involve a paradoxical sharing of
motivational mechanisms (Reynolds & Berridge, 2008).
The shared mechanism of desire and dread takes the form of a mesocortical generation of
motivational salience whose affective valence can be flipped back and forth between positive
and negative. Even in the same individual and in the same hour, both can be activated together
by a brain manipulation, and it is possible to convert one into the other. The shared
psychological feature of motivation salience is essentially incentive salience with the positive
valence drained out. What that leaves is an intrinsically nonvalenced salience that can be used
in the service of either motivation, and as equally applied to a negatively valenced threat as to
a positively valenced salience. Applied to a threat, this produces fearful salience: a frightening
stimulus is attention-grabbing and compels a motivated response of avoidance, almost as an
incentive stimulus grabs attention and compels approach, but the threat is perceived as sinister
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
Either incentive salience or fear can be activated as one chooses in rats by tapping an
appropriate emotional key in a limbic keyboard, done through a cortical signal-blocking
microinjection placed in the nucleus accumbens. Part of the nucleus accumbens is arranged as
an emotional keyboard, front to back, that organizes incoming signals about the outside world
(Reynolds & Berridge, 2008). Tapping keys in the front of this structure elicits strong desires,
for example stimulating intense eating and creating a desire to return to the place where the
keys were tapped. Tapping keys in the back conversely elicits strong fear (antipredator
reactions to the sight or touch of people, sometimes accompanied by fearful squealing and
escape attempts). Desire and dread are opposites, but we have found that taps in the middle of
the accumbens keyboard reliably elicit both together. This observation made us wonder
whether a shared motivational salience mechanism might contribute to generate both, so that
they could so closely overlap in mechanism. If so, we hoped it might be possible to flip an
intermediate neural key in accumbens back and forth between generating fear and generating
desire, as a flexible psychological building block, depending on the psychological context in
which it was activated (Reynolds & Berridge, 2008).
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
Sheila Reynolds examined the shared mechanism possibility by testing the effects of the
microinjections in situations where the ambience could be flipped: either a soothing
environment (the rat’s own home: dark, quiet and familiar) or a stressful environment (a room
with bright lights and where a loud discordant soundtrack played of the punk rock musician
Iggy Pop). The rats much preferred their home to Iggy Pop if given the choice. But if not given
a choice, and simply plopped in one or the other environment after a brain microinjection, the
environment determined what the brain building block became built into. Sheila Reynolds
found that many middle keys in accumbens could switch between desire and dread, depending
on which environment the rat was in as the microinjection acted. Some accumbens sites flipped
completely, changing from pure fear-generators to pure desire-generators, or vice versa. This
flip is consistent with the counter-intuitive possibility that a single shared psychological
operation exists as a truly flexible building block within desire and dread.
Do incentive salience mechanisms carry consequences for concepts of free will? On this topic
I defer to those better qualified philosophically to evaluate this issue who participated in the
Oslo workshop, such as Richard Holton and Jennifer Hornsby. Here I offer only a brief and
admittedly naïve opinion: no. Scientific knowledge of “wanting” mechanisms should not
necessarily change the philosophical status of free will concepts. Philosophers of free will have
always recognized the existence of temptations in the form of independent or involuntary
desires that act to subvert the intentions of a will to abstain from those temptations. A temptation
remains a temptation regardless of its brain mechanism. Identifying mesolimbic mechanisms
of incentive salience as a substrate pinpoints a brain basis and clarifies certain psychological
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
operating rules, but does not seem to me to substantially change the situation as far as a
philosopher need be concerned. If philosophy has ever successfully reconciled temptation to
free will, then it might well succeed again in a reconciliation with incentive salience (Holton,
2004; Holton, 2008; Hornsby, 2004, 2008).
Perhaps a step in this direction was illustrated by Holton’s discussion in the Oslo workshop of
the potential compartmentalization of free will into some domains versus other domains which
are less able to be controlled (Holton, 2008). Activation of incentive salience potentially might
tilt or nudge an individual between these domains. As Holton put it in his workshop essay, “an
agent is less free to F the harder it is to follow though on a decision to F” (Holton, 2008).
“Wanting” makes it harder to do F if F requires abstaining from acting upon a salient incentive.
Harder is just a matter of degree, as the mechanism of “wanting” is always graded in intensity.
In some individuals and in some conditions harder may indeed approach very high levels so
as to legitimately be called compulsive. Just how hard it is to resist a compulsive “want” at the
highest intensities is still an open question, but no doubt it might be hard indeed, so hard that
most of us might fail if put to the test again and again. Still, in principle, incentive salience
seems no different from ideas of temptation that philosophers have wrestled with for ages.
The techniques for exerting self control over temptations that Holton and others describe seem
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
usefully applicable also to incentive salience, and could be employed for example even by an
addict to help resist sensitized “wants”. The very modularity of incentive salience may open
opportunities for its control by other facets of mind, through the boundary conditions that limit
its realm of operation. Precommitment to an alternative course of action that excludes giving
in to the tempting incentive is one tactic considered by Holton. Perhaps equally important for
coping with sensitized cue-triggered “wanting” might be to arrange as much as possible to
avoid encountering the tempting reward and its cues (Elster, 2003; Holton, 2004; Holton,
2008; Metcalfe & Mischel, 1999). It is difficult to control brain mesolimbic states, but avoiding
particular physical and sensory triggers (rewards and their cues) may be crucial and a feasible
tactic to avoid overturning of precommitment strategies. Avoiding imagery of the reward
stimulus and cues is admittedly a trickier problem (Wegner, 2002).
Thus although psychological and neural mechanisms of incentive salience are inherently
deterministic, perhaps philosophers can reconcile them with modern concepts of free will and
agency. While that task is not easy, nothing seems changed in principle by the modern
identification of brain mechanisms for temptations that philosophers have known to exist all
along.
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
XVI. Conclusion
In sum, “wanting” a reward is distinct from “liking” the same reward. The two usually
converge, but can sometimes diverge. When dissociations occur, most notably, “wanting” can
become unjustifiably high, as in addiction. The identity of incentive salience as a distinct
module within desire creates conditions under which in some cases incentive salience creates
a compulsive “wanting” that exceeds the expected goodness of the outcome, persists in the
face of a sincere cognitive intention to do the opposite, and is not matched by actual pleasure
of the outcome in the end. Incentive salience can detach from intentionality in the form of
cognitive goals, and attach to percepts that are associated with incentives, sometimes pulling
“wanting” in odd directions. Incentive salience might also attach to particular actions, as well
as to stimuli, creating urges to act that are as motivationally compelling as any external
incentive. Finally, incentive salience provides a mechanism for temptation, but perhaps not a
new challenge to philosophers of free will. I am grateful for the opportunity to have participated
in the Oslo Workshop that combined the approaches of philosophy, neuroscience and
psychology. Building bridges between the disciplines, as the workshop helped to do, would
seem to have much to offer for carrying these issues further.1
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
References
Ainslie, G. Picoeconomics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1992.
Ainslie, G. Breakdown of Will. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press; 2001.
Ainslie, G. Pleasure and aversion: Challenging the dichotomy. Paper presented at the University of Oslo
Philosophy workshop on wanting and liking; 2008.
Berridge KC. Motivation concepts in behavioral neuroscience. Physiology and Behaviour 2004;81(2):
179–209.
Berridge KC. The debate over dopamine’s role in reward: The case for incentive salience.
Psychopharmacology (Berl) 2007;191(3):391–431. [PubMed: 17072591]
Berridge KC, Aldridge JW. Decision utility, the brain and pursuit of hedonic goals. Social Cognition
2008;26(5):621–46.
Camerer CF. Wanting, liking, and learning: Neuroscience and paternalism. The University of Chicago
Law Review 2006 Winter;73:87–110.
Carver CS. Impulse and constraint: Perspectives from personality psychology, convergence with theory
in other areas, and potential for integration. Personality and Social Psychology Review 2005;9(4):312–
33. [PubMed: 16223354]
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
Damasio, AR. The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness. 1.
New York: Harcourt Brace; 1999.
Davidson, RJ.; Scherer, KR.; Goldsmith, HH. Handbook of Affective Sciences. Oxford; New York:
Oxford University Press; 2003.
Elster J. Don’t burn your bridge before you come to it: Some ambiguities and complexities of
precommitment. Texas Law Review 2003;81(7):1751–87.
Elster, J. Impatience and urgency. Paper presented at the University of Oslo Philosophy workshop on
wanting and liking.; 2008.
Fodor, JA. Modularity of Mind: An Essay on Faculty Psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; 1983.
1I thank Olav Gjelsvik and other organizers of the Oslo Workshop on Liking and Wanting, and all the participants, for a stimulating and
enjoyable experience in colleagueship. I also thank Jay Schulkin and Barbara Smuts for helpful comments on an earlier version of this
manuscript. The laboratory experiments described in this paper were made possible by grants from the US National Institutes of Health.
Frederick S, Loewenstein G, O’Donoghue T. Time discounting and time preference: A critical review.
Journal of Economic Literature 2002;40(2):351–401.
Gjelsvik, O. Commentary on Ainslie’s ‘Pleasure and aversion: Challenging the conventional dichotomy’.
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
Paper presented at the University of Oslo Philosophy workshop on wanting and liking; 2008.
Glickman SE, Schiff BB. A biological theory of reinforcement. Psychological Review 1967;74:81–109.
[PubMed: 5342347]
Holton R. Rational resolve. Philosophical Review 2004;113(4):507–35.
Holton, R. Choice and effort. Paper presented at the University of Oslo Philosophy workshop on wanting
and liking.; 2008.
Hornsby, J. Agency and actions. In: Hyman, J.; Steward, H., editors. Agency and Action. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press; 2004. p. 1-23.
Hornsby, J. Commentary on Holton’s ‘Choice and effort’. Paper presented at the University of Oslo
Philosophy workshop on wanting and liking; 2008.
Kahneman D, Wakker PP, Sarin R. Back to Bentham? Explorations of experienced utility. The Quarterly
Journal of Economics 1997;112:375–405.
LeDoux, J. The Emotional Brain: The Mysterious Underpinnings of Emotional Life. New York: Simon
& Schuster; 1996.
Mahler S, Berridge K. Which cue to ‘want’? Central amygdala opioid activation enhances and focuses
incentive salience on a prepotent reward cue. Journal of Neuroscience 2009;29(20):6500–13.
[PubMed: 19458221]
Mason GJ, Cooper J, Clarebrough C. Frustrations of fur-farmed mink. Nature 2001;410(6824):35–36.
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
[PubMed: 11242031]
Metcalfe J, Mischel W. A hot/cool-system analysis of delay of gratification: Dynamics of willpower.
Psychological Review 1999;106(1):3–19. [PubMed: 10197361]
Peciña S, Smith KS, Berridge KC. Hedonic hot spots in the brain. Neuroscientist 2006;12(6):500–11.
[PubMed: 17079516]
Pinker, S. How the Mind Works. New York: Norton; 1997.
Reynolds SM, Berridge KC. Emotional environments retune the valence of appetitive versus fearful
functions in nucleus accumbens. Nature and Neuroscience 2008;11(4):423–25.
Robinson TE, Berridge KC. The neural basis of drug craving: An incentive-sensitization theory of
addiction. Brain Research Reviews 1993;18(3):247–91. [PubMed: 8401595]
Robinson TE, Berridge KC. Addiction. Annual Review of Psychology 2003;54(1):25–53.
Rosse RB, Fay-McCarthy M, Collins JP Jr, Risher-Flowers D, Alim TN, Deutsch SI. Transient
compulsive foraging behavior associated with crack cocaine use. American Journal of Psychiatry
1993;150(1):155–56. [PubMed: 8417561]
Smith KS, Berridge KC. Opioid limbic circuit for reward: interaction between hedonic hotspots of nucleus
accumbens and ventral pallidum. Journal of Neuroscience 2007;27(7):1594–605. [PubMed:
17301168]
Smith, KS.; Mahler, SV.; Pecina, S.; Berridge, KC. Hedonic hotspots: Generating sensory pleasure in
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
the brain. In: Kringelbach, M.; Berridge, KC., editors. Pleasures of the Brain. Oxford: Oxford
University Press; 2009. p. 27-49.
Sperber, D. Commentary on Elster’s ‘Impatience and urgency’. Paper presented at the University of Oslo
Philosophy workshop on wanting and liking; 2008.
Steiner JE, Glaser D, Hawilo ME, Berridge KC. Comparative expression of hedonic impact: Affective
reactions to taste by human infants and other primates. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews
2001;25(1):53–74. [PubMed: 11166078]
Tindell AJ, Berridge KC, Zhang J, Peciña S, Aldridge JW. Ventral pallidal neurons code incentive
motivation: Amplification by mesolimbic sensitization and amphetamine. European Journal of
Neuroscience 2005;22(10):2617–34. [PubMed: 16307604]
Wegner, DM. The Illusion of Conscious Will. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; 2002.
Winkielman P, Berridge KC. Unconscious emotion. Current Directions in Psychological Science 2004;13
(3):120–23.
Wyvell CL, Berridge KC. Incentive-sensitization by previous amphetamine exposure: Increased cue-
triggered ‘wanting’ for sucrose reward. Journal of Neuroscience 2001;21(19):7831–40. [PubMed:
11567074]
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
lever pressing in absence of cue and during irrelevant cue, (CS−) (right). Modified from Wyvell
and Berridge, 2000.
NIH-PA Author Manuscript
hedonic “coldspot” suppresses “liking” reactions to sucrose, whereas a larger zone suppresses
“disliking” reactions to quinine. Reprinted by permission from Smith et al., 2009.
NIH-PA Author Manuscript