The Impact of Transgressions of Rights: What Is Universal?
The Impact of Transgressions of Rights: What Is Universal?
The Impact of Transgressions of Rights: What Is Universal?
peoples, a transgression of rights in one place in the world is felt everywhere. – Immanuel Kant
Kant claims that since a narrower or wider universal community prevails among the people of the
world, the impacts of an action are not restricted to the local region, but have a global impact as
well. In this sense it is important to look at what can be said to be the concept of a universal
community, and whether such a state of affairs exists or not, as Kant claims it does. In this essay, I
will attempt to defend Kant’s viewpoint, and address objections to his argument, by first evaluating
the meaning of the terms in the quote, constructing a defense of his argument, and then
considering other viewpoints.
What is Universal?
The concept of universal is a very broad idea, seeing as it aims to encompass the extent of all that is
known to humans. To describe anything as universal would be to ensure that it describes all that
exists in the universe, and all that is known about. As such an idea leads to few things being called
truly universal, one can take an approximation to include the sum of all things relevant to the matter
at hand. So a universal community would ideally deal with mankind and the impacts of our actions
and ideas, such that all of mankind, and all that has been thought of, or felt by mankind, are
encompassed in this. Some might argue, and go on even further to include the other species of this
planet as well, seeing as how our actions, and our ideas impact them, and yet others would indeed
expand it to include the universe, seeing as how we have the power to shape it, or change it, or
understand it. So for instance, would colonies in space come under the umbrella of a universal
community? If not, is there a distance factor while calculating universal communities (since we
typically take universal to assume our tiny Earth only)? If there is a distance factor, then what is the
precise distance? Would the people in the UK and Australia be in the same universal community?
What about the astronauts and scientists on the International Space Station?
The reason behind the need to reason out the nature of the universal property is to understand the
degree and extent of the global impact of actions which Kant talks about. For the purpose of this
essay, I would indeed take a universal community to be the total sum of humans, whether they be
anywhere – in separate countries, in separate planets, or even in separate eras (for I believe that the
impacts of actions live on longer than the humans who caused them). The reason I am excluding
animals, or other species, is because Kant is talking with respect to the rights of people, and if the
development of such a universal community among the people of this world has led to people
feeling the transgression of rights everywhere.
It is here that I would like to draw attention to the fact of narrower and wider universal
communities, which Kant mentions. As we have examined above, universal communities vary in
their size and range as people perceive themselves, or others, to be part of a different universal
community. If someone was making statements about a universally accepted idea about democracy
being the best form of government, perhaps that person is not being inclusive enough about the
kings, the noblemen, etc. who lost power due to the rise of democracy, who may not necessarily
agree with what is being said. In my opinion, Kant is trying to highlight, or bring about the different
perspectives above “universal” as a description or as a descriptive property. The more inclusive
“universal” is, the wider the community, and more exclusive ideas of “universal” would refer to
“narrower” communities with respect to the inclusive, wider, communities.
A problem that one might raise with Kant’s chain of reasoning is an issue with his premise. Kant
presumes the existence of such a universal community to obtain his conclusion, but his very usage
of the terms narrower and wider refutes the concept of a truly universal community. A community
which is truly universal cannot be subject to interpretation or perception of individuals with respect
to whether they belong to the community, or not. For instance, it is perhaps up to my identity, or
my choice with regard to who I am, when I identify as a member of a religious community, or as an
atheist or agnostic. But when I am defining a universal community, whose objective is to include
everything, it cannot be so that I choose to be in that community, and nor should it be possible to
exist outside of it. Thus the very idea of a narrow universal community is subject to the feelings or to
the identity of people, and thus it is not universal, as people can be excluded from it, or exclude
themselves from it.
A response to this idea would be consider the idea of approximation with regard to relevance. When
we choose to grant the property of being “universal” to a certain attribute, it is unwise to consider
irrelevant examples, as they sit within the universal set, but as empty, hollow elements with trivial
cases if the problem in question is applied to them. So if I argue that democracy is universally
accepted as the best form of government, it makes no sense to ask the sheep what it thinks about
this statement, given that the sheep is not relevant to political systems, since it cannot feel their
impacts, at least not in the same context of rights and transgressions which humans feel it in. But on
the other hand, humans do have opinions with respect to political systems, and it makes much more
sense to “narrow” the set to the relevant people impacted by the “universal” idea. Similarly, in other
cases, it might make more sense to “widen” the set to include various other viewpoints.
Humans are different in innumerable ways, be it ideologically, physically or with respect to mental
abilities. To define a universal community, and in turn to define rights with respect to such a
universal community, one also needs to question whether we do have any similarities at all other
than our biological DNA and common biological functions (we walk, we grab, we bend in more or
less the same manner). Rights are one such example of a property that (people claim that) all
humans have. Rights can be defined as a moral authority to perform actions. If one claims one has
the right to education, one also has a moral authority to get educated, and one can claim moral
superiority, at least in this isolated context, over someone who is denying them their education. A
lot of different bases for rights are given in different contexts. Some claim that rights necessitate a
legal foundation, which grants people the moral authority to use them. Others claim that rights are
a product of sociocultural feelings, and revolve around the societies by which they are influenced.
And some would go ahead and contest my definition by claiming that authority can be ideally
claimed by any person. I might go ahead and claim authority to kill someone: would that
automatically give me the right to kill?
The keyword that I would like to note as central to the definition of a right is moral. Rights grant
individuals and communities moral authorities, thus they must be grounded in moral values, or in a
moral code of conduct. Rights are seen as a product of a moral ideology, as legal/political
institutions with different ideologies would grant different rights. The right to free speech, for
instance, may not be seen as having a moral basis in a monarchy, but is well-grounded in the moral
values underlining the spirit of a democracy. To see why my definition of rights holds, one must
attempt to see society in a vacuum, before the existence of legal or political “right giving”
institutions, such as courts and monarchs. My argument would be that if one has a moral code, one
has a concept of rights ingrained into it. So for example, today, we claim that discrimination present
in certain places goes against the rights of people in those places. The courts may allow this
discrimination to take place, and deny people legal guarantee of their rights. Society may condone
oppression, and deny people social support for their rights. But even then, we can see a violation of
these rights, rights that would not otherwise exist if one took definitions pertaining to society, or to
legal institutions.
Thus, once the concept of rights is established, we can examine the transgressions of rights.
Transgressions would be actions which either act against the concerned right (for instance, murder
acts against an individual’s right to life), or denies them the exercise of that right (denial of
education denies people the exercise of the right to education). Transgressions may happen in
different places, in different manners, and one cannot define them in absolute ethical terms, by
making blanket statements such as “transgressions are morally correct”, and “transgressions are
wrong”. This is because while it may feel intuitively easy to make moral decisions about
transgressions in an isolated system (for instance, denying the right to education of a person feels
wrong), rights are often used in conjunction with other rights, and sometimes clash with other rights
as well. For example, if the government seizes the land of an individual to build a school which is of
the utmost importance to provide education in the area, then the right to education is clashing with
the right to property, and whichever way an ethical viewpoint takes, a transgression will necessarily
be committed. So there cannot be an absolute metric to decide whether transgressions are always
right or wrong, because ethical viewpoints (save those which do not believe in rights and wrongs)
will need to make a decision with regard to whether this action was right and wrong.
Thus, we have notions of universal communities, of their rights, as well as their transgressions. In
the next section, I will try to examine the impacts of transgressions of rights and see whether their
impacts are as widely felt as Kant says.
The Impacts of Transgressions of Rights
Kant claims as his premise that we do, indeed, live in universal communities, however narrow or
wide they may be. But since we do live in such communities, transgressions of rights taking place in
a particular area will be felt everywhere. The idea of everywhere is vague in this sense that one
cannot calculate the extent to which everywhere extends. For example, a transgression of the right
to life does not seemingly have any impact on Jupiter, but can we claim that Jupiter comes under
Kant’s “everywhere”?
In the previous section, I demonstrated that transgressions of rights are not necessarily good or bad.
But impacts are felt of both good actions, and of bad actions. Suppose we assume a deontological
perspective, and think of ethical judgments along Kant’s maxim to act in a manner such that it is
universally possible to act so. Within that moral code, I can lead myself to believe that some actions
are condemnable as they take away or hinder some “good actions” which are universally applicable
(at least in my opinion), and thus we can observe transgressions of rights. If such transgressions of
rights take place, even if they might be good for some people, my perspective would not allow for
certain actions to be good with respect to circumstance. An example would help illustrate the point:
murder is not universally possible by Kant’s maxim. To commit murder to rid children of their
abusive parents, who deny them the right to education, cannot be called good, and is a
transgression on the parents’ right to life. Thus while one transgression of rights was prevented,
according to the moral code, another was committed.
But would you agree as to this action being right or wrong? Maybe you would, maybe you wouldn’t,
and perhaps certain legal systems (and ethical viewpoints) would be more sympathetic to the
perpetrator of this crime as compared to, say, an arbitrary murder by a serial killer. But the impact it
did have is that it called into doubt or supported the logic behind Kant’s maxim. Some of us would
defend the action passionately as being right, and others would cry foul, and demand that the
perpetrator be put behind bars. So it did impact us, even when different viewpoints would be
impacted differently.
Thus, I would argue that transgressions of rights do impact us, and this is because rights have
objectives in mind when being framed. I had defined rights as a moral authority to perform actions,
but there must be a performer to perform actions, an objective to grant someone (or something) a
moral authority. It is this performer who is impacted if the transgression of a right occurs, and other
performers like him, who are impacted by this transgression. Thus people feel this transgression,
whether the feeling is internal (mental or emotional) or physical.
Now one must examine Kant’s claim of universal communities. The argument says more regarding
where this impact is felt. If one were to support Kant’s viewpoint, one takeaway that one would
need from the entire argument of the existence of universal communities is regarding that of
communication. An important feature of being in a universal community is that humans do not exist
in vacuums. We exist in shared ecosystems, environments, countries, etc. and we have the ability to
communicate with each other. An example can be that of the Internet, where people from around
the world can connect with each other. But what happens when we see a transgression of the right
to life in war-torn areas, like Syria? As we share common features with Syrians (as well as people of
other nationalities), a threat to these features are detected. The argument was that the performer
of the action is impacted by the transgression, so Syrians dying in the war are impacted, and they
feel the transgression. But we, as humans who can live (and die) like they do, we, who can feel pain
and anguish at the loss of loved ones, like they do, we, too, are impacted to an extent by what we
see. The feeling of sadness, and pain, and everything we observe is universal in our universal
community, and we react to this mixture of emotions.
But how do we guarantee it being felt everywhere? There seems to be an obvious counter-
argument that not all the places in the world, even where members of our universal community
exist, have access to the Internet (or other means of communication), and do not necessarily have
knowledge of Syria. Here is a point that differs from the practical reality of sharing knowledge, since
not all knowledge reaches everywhere. Here I would like to divide the concept of the feeling of
transgressions of rights to two parts, which involve the capacity of feeling, and the eventual feelings.
The capacity for feeling can be performed as a theoretical experiment involving taking copies of the
news about Syria, taking them with you, to places without Internet, and explaining what is
happening there. The reaction you would provoke would vary from people to people, depending on
what their notion of rights involves. In another war-torn area, this might be seen as regrettable, but
regular, and people might empathize with the Syrians. But in places which have not experienced war
for a long period of time, this might be seen as shocking, and disturbing. So the only hindrance to
the impact being felt is a practical one involving the sharing of knowledge, as everyone does have
the capacity to feel the impacts of transgression. Note that the nature of this feeling varies from
place to place, and this is because people have different notions of what their rights are. But for
people who recognize the right being violated, and identifying with it, this capacity to feel exists, and
they would sympathize with the people whose rights are being violated.
The eventual feelings are feelings which make it to these places without communication, somehow,
in some manner, centuries after the occurrence of the actual events. This is a consequence of living
in a shared world, as ideas and ideologies spread and percolate among people in different manners.
The war in Syria, and the justifications for the war, may not be immediately relevant to people who
do not know about it simply because of the transgression of rights. Food shortages might be felt, the
value of the currency may go down, and other practical impacts might be observed, and these
would be consequences of the transgressions, and these would also count as feeling the
transgressions of rights.
But a more direct impact of the transgressions of rights would act in something similar to what
happened in the aftermath of World War II. As Hitler lost, and his crimes were discovered, many
people around the world vilify Nazism, and point out flaws in its ideology, and so on and so forth.
Had Hitler won, we might have ended up with entirely new kinds of philosophy who might have
taken Nazism as a model example, to be defended at all costs. These philosophies might have
provided the ideological groundwork for further transgressions of rights to be committed, and these
would affect other areas, including those who had no idea what Nazism was during the war, and
who were otherwise unaware of the Nazis. So one must also look at feelings on a timescale, because
while transgressions of rights may not impact us directly, they might provide ideological bases for
future violations, which would in turn impact us. Thus the seed for the impact of such feelings has
already been sown in the transgression of these rights.
In the following few sections, I will evaluate a few other viewpoints that would differ with Kant.
One possible way of arguing against Kant would claim that the concept of rights does not have a
solid foundation. When defining rights, I argued that rights are subject to moral codes of conduct,
and ethical ideologies. If we consider a nihilistic approach, holding, according to Nietzsche, that
nothing is true, everything is permitted. Then the groundwork for rights is annihilated, as moral
authorities do not make sense when looking at Kant from that perspective. Transgressions of rights
would merely be sequences of events, and people can choose to feel or not feel anything about
them. Different people might have different ideas with respect to right and wrong, and thus
different notions of rights, and each would be correct and wrong in their own manner. Thus Kant
would be unable to guarantee the necessity of the feeling of the impacts of transgressions.
What the nihilistic approach explained over here pre-supposes is that people are passing judgment
on actions as external observers. They may not agree with what is right and wrong, and since we
cannot come to conclusions about right and wrong, there may not even be any absolutely right and
wrong actions. But when Kant is examining the feelings of individuals, he is assuming a fundamental
notion regarding whether they believe they have rights or not. Certain individuals might be pre-
disposed towards choosing certain actions over others, as they believe that they might be morally
better, and thus believe in rights and transgressions. Others may act like nihilists and treat
transgressions indifferently, and not “feel” anything about it of their own accord. But the reasoning
behind the performance of actions can be used to justify the performance of other actions as well.
So suppose a nihilist treats a doctor’s act of reviving a nearly-dead patient and the murderer’s act of
killing people with the same indifference, eventually, if left to their own ends without any external
interference, the nihilist would observe a change in the manner in which society operates, since all is
now permitted. Thus murderers would be free to murder, and doctors free to operate, without any
ethical consequences. This, in turn, would be a change from the previous society, in which doctors
were allowed to operate, but murderers were not allowed to murder. This change is the impact that
the nihilist would feel. Thus, irrespective of the nihilist, due to the transgressions of rights, there is
an impact being felt all the same.
Another issue with this statement might regard the assumption that Kant has made supporting the
premise that a universal community does exist on this world. Granted that humans can define their
own notions of universal communities, and narrow and widen them, it is perhaps likely that humans
might not want to see themselves in the same light as other humans, and claim that the only
similarities existing between them are biological in nature. Thus, one can argue against Kant by
claiming that, for example, certain tribes in certain parts of the world choose to indulge in their own
practices and in their own ideologies with respect to how they live. They refuse to be influenced by
modern advances, and instead wish to maintain their traditional culture and way of life. Similarly,
one might have popular monarchs who deny people their rights. Kant’s argument for the impact of
transgression of rights seems to fail here, as such people would be unlikely to be impacted by the
transgression of rights in other parts of the world.
One way of responding to this objection would to look at it from the perspective of living in a shared
world itself, and looking at those tribes and kingdoms living in such a manner. Their very ability to
lead different lifestyles relies on the moral authority that has been exerted by them in accordance to
foreign powers, or other governments, namely the right they have to being left alone, as they are.
The de-recognition of this right would force open their gates to external influence, making them the
same as the rest of us. Thus, while they might believe that a particular transgression is ethically
correct or wrong, it does impact them irrespective of their choices because of the intrinsic nature of
the sharing of information that takes place. Even their non-recognition of matters relating to rights
and transgressions is a right in itself, in which they claim moral authority to their own way of living.
Thus, the concept of transgressions of rights impacting a universal community holds even if people
may not choose to belong to that universal community, for recognizing their choice is a right
accorded to them itself. Furthermore, if the cases of capacity of feeling, and eventual feelings, were
carried out, even such individuals might feel these transgressions. Thus, they belong to at least this
aspect of the universal community, even if they may not identify themselves with the rest.
Hidden Transgressions
Another objection to Kant can be considered with regard to the notion of hiding transgressions. If
possible to hide transgressions, very efficiently with regard to revealing to the public of the true
nature of such transgressions, such that none come to know of the happenings of that time period,
then wouldn’t Kant’s ideas regarding feelings become obsolete? Indeed, while Kant’s ideas seem
grounded in the practical belief that concealment of transgressions for eternity is an unlikely
happening, theoretically, too, one can examine the feelings Kant is talking about.
An interesting example to take here with regard to hiding the nature and occurrence of
transgressions involves the Nazis carefully hiding the existence of concentration camps and policies
of extermination which they followed. While eventually, the horrors of the Holocaust were
discovered later, in the event that they had not, our ideas with respect to Nazism might have turned
out to be very different. Today, consequentialists can look at the ruins of these camps, and of the
symbols of Nazi power, and ethically determine the impact of racism at such a scale, and condemn
Nazism. But had these transgressions been hidden from the public, Nazism would have been seen
merely as a political ideology of the twentieth century, and not as a social, economic and political
framework dedicated to the destruction of the lives of Jews. Thus, the commitment of these
transgressions has impacts felt as well, even if we do not know it. Thus, the absence of the evidence
of Nazi transgressions would have been “felt”, but in a different manner than their presence is felt
today.
Conclusion
In this essay, I have attempted to define concepts of a universal community, rights and
transgressions of rights, and tried to construct a defense of Kant’s ideas. I have further considered
opposing viewpoints which disagree with Kant, and tried to show that they are false. Thus,
transgressions of rights are felt everywhere, even when committed at one place in the world,
because of the narrower or wider community which prevails among the people of the Earth.