Choice Under Risk and Uncertainty
Choice Under Risk and Uncertainty
Definition
This entry outlines what is meant by decision making under risk and uncertainty. It illustrates
the model of Expected Utility, its properties and the Allais paradox as the main violation of the
model. It describes the Subjective Expected Utility model of decision under uncertainty, and the
Ellsberg paradox as an example of the Knight’s approach to uncertainty.
Introduction
In real economic life, many decisions are taken under risk and uncertainty, for example
investment decisions, decisions about consumption through time, buying and selling insurance,
investment in new industries and countries, choosing new technologies, stock market purchases
and sales.
The literature on decision making under risk and uncertainty can be divided in: (1) the
literature concerning decision making under risk, which includes: (a) the Expected Utility model
(EU) and its axiomatizations (Bernoulli 1954; von Neumann and Morgenstern 1947); (b) the
criticisms to the EU model (Allais 1953) and its alternatives (Kahneman and Tversky 1979;
Quiggin 1982, 1993; Loomes and Sugden 1982); (2) the literature concerning decision making
under uncertainty, which can be divided in two different approaches: (a) the Bayesian approach
(De Finetti 1937; Ramsey 1931; Savage 1954), according to which people assign subjective
probabilities to uncertain events and these probabilities follow the rules of mathematical
probability theory and (b) the approach by Knight (1921) and Keynes (1921) according to which
people cannot assign subjective probabilities to uncertain events that follow the mathematical
rules of probability theory (Ellsberg 1961; Schmeidler 1989; Tversky and Kahneman 1992).
In a situation of risk one does not know with certainty the outcomes of one’s choice, and the
uncertainty related to a decision can be represented by an objective probability distribution over
the events or states of the world which relate actions to outcomes, as for example with a gamble
based on the roll of a die or a roulette wheel.
In a situation of uncertainty, the uncertainty relating a decision cannot be represented by an
objective probability distribution. In this case the individual is either considered able to attach a
subjective esteem of the probability to each event (Savage 1954) - in which case decision under
uncertainty reduces into decision under risk – or probabilities are not known and cannot be
assigned (Knight 1921).
History
The first important argument on the subject was that of the mathematician Daniel Bernoulli
(1738), who (independently from Gabriel Cramer) developed a new hypothesis based on the
solution of a problem posed by his cousin Nicholas Bernoulli, the ‘St Petersburg Paradox’.
Suppose you have to toss a coin till ‘Head’ comes out; the first time this happens, you stop
tossing the coin and prizes are determined in the following way: if ‘Head’ comes out at the first
toss, you earn $2; if ‘Head’ comes out at the second toss, you earn $2 2; if ‘Head’ comes out at
the third toss, you earn $23 and so on. The probability that at every toss ‘Head’ comes out is
equal to ½, and tosses are independent from each other: then, the probability that ‘Head’ comes
out at the first toss is ½, the probability that ‘Head’ comes out at the second toss is (½) 2 (that is,
the probability that ‘Tail’ comes out at the first toss times the probability that ‘Head’ comes out
at the second toss, that is, ½ * ½), the probability that ‘Head’ comes out at the third toss is (½) 3,
and so on. Thus, the expected value of this lottery is infinite: 2 (½) + 4 (½)2 + 8 (1/8) +…..+2n
(½)n + …= 1 +1 +1 +1 +1+… = ∞, as the coin is thrown if necessary an infinite number of times
and the expected prize from each toss is equal to 1. An individual who looks at the highest
expected value would be willing to pay an infinite amount of money to play this lottery. But this
is very unrealistic: nobody would be willing to pay more than a modest amount for it. In fact,
this is a very risky lottery: it gives the opportunity to gain an increasing big prize with a
decreasing small probability - people would not be willing to undertake this risk.
Bernoulli argued that this and similar choices could be explained by assuming that
individuals do not choose the lottery with the highest expected value, but that with the highest
expected utility, where the utility is represented by a function like the square root of wealth,
where utility increases with wealth, but at a decreasing rate. Bernoulli introduced both the
concepts of expected utility maximization and of decreasing marginal utility of wealth.
However, Bernoulli’s idea of expected utility maximization had little effect on the theory of
decision making under risk till the work ‘Theory of Games and Economic Behaviour’ by von
Neumann and Morgenstern was published in 1947. After that, it had soon to become the
normative and positive theory of decision making under risk.
3
gives an expected prize equal to the sure one – he or she prefers the expected value of the lottery
to the lottery itself. The individual is averse to the risk connected to the lottery.
We should note that this risk aversion is implicit in the shape of the utility function, which is
concave. As an illustration of this, consider lotteries ($60, ½;$0, ½) and ($40, ½;$20, ½) above.
In calculating their expected utilities, we have assumed a form for the utility function equal to
U(x) = √x, which has a shape like in Figure 2. This is a utility function implying risk aversion,
as shown by the fact that when calculating the expected utilities of the above lotteries, we find
that the riskier lottery has a lower expected utility than the ‘safer’ lottery.
The case of the utility function of an individual with a proneness to risk is given in Figure 3.
It can be seen here that for such an individual the expected utility of a lottery is higher than the
utility of a sure outcome, that is equal to the expected value of the lottery. The individual who is
risk loving will choose the lottery which gives an expected prize equal to the sure outcome
instead of the sure alternative – he or she prefers the lottery to the expected value of the lottery
itself. This individual loves the risk connected to the lottery.
The individual preferences towards risk can also be expressed using the concepts of (1)
certainty equivalent (CE) and (2) risk premium .
(1) As an example, consider the lottery L = ($100, ½;$0, ½). The expected value of this
lottery is 50. Consider asking this individual what is the amount of money which makes her
indifferent to the lottery. This is defined as the certainty equivalent of the lottery. Therefore, the
utility of the CE of the lottery is defined as equal to its expected utility - U(CE) = EU(L).
Suppose the individual is indifferent between the lottery and $40 for certain, that is, his CE
for the lottery is equal to 40, less than the expected value of the lottery. It follows that the
subject would accept any sum > 40 instead of the lottery and the lottery to each sum < 40. In
this case we say that the subject is averse to risk - U(CE) < EV(L). This is represented in Figure
4. The reverse inequality defines risk proneness, and the equality defines risk neutrality.
(2) The risk premium is defined as the maximum part of the expected value that the subject
is willing to give up to avoid the risk associated to the lottery, = EV(L) – CE (see Figure 4).
Consider the example of a CE for the above lottery equal to 40; this means that the individual
is willing to give up at most $10 of the expected monetary value of the lottery, that is, the risk
premium is 10. The sign of the risk premium gives the attitude to risk for that lottery. In general,
when for any lottery is positive, the individual is averse to risk; when is negative, he is risk
lover; when = 0 the individual is risk neutral.
The most common analytical measures of risk aversion have been introduced by Arrow
(1964) and Pratt (1964) and extensively used in finance, insurance markets, health, game theory.
4
• A 100% chance of 100 millions)
or
• B 10% chance of $500 millions
89% chance of $1 million
1% chance of 0
• and
• C 11% chance of $1 million
89% chance of 0
• or
D 10% chance of 500 millions
90% chance of 0
If the individual has expected utility preferences, a choice of A over B in the first pair
implies a choice of C over D in the second pair. However empirical findings show that the
modal choice is for A over B in the first couple of lotteries, but D over C in the second couple.
This pattern of choice violates expected utility. In fact, A preferred to B implies U(100 millions)
> .10U(500 millions) + .89 U(1 million) + .01U(0), that is, .11U(100 millions) + .89U(0)
> .10U(500 millions) + .90U(0), while D preferred to C implies .10U(500 millions) + .90U(0)
> .11U(1 million) + .89U(0), which is a contradiction.
The widespread and systematic empirical violations of the linearity property has put under
discussion the descriptive validity of the theory, giving rise to a growing body of literature of
new theoretical models of choice under risk as, for instance, Prospect Theory (Kahneman and
Tversky 1979; Tversky and Kahneman 1992), Rank Dependent Utility Theory (Quiggin 1982,
1993), Regret Theory (Loomes and Sugden 1982).
5
The proportion of the red and black balls in the second urn is not known and so we do not
know which probability to assign to red and black. Avoiding to choose to draw a ball from Urn
II is called by Ellsberg uncertainty aversion.
According to the theory of Savage we should be indifferent between the two urns since the
probability of getting red can be represented by a second order probability distribution (a
probability distribution over probability), whose expected probability is 50/100 as in the case of
Urn I. However, people prefer to bet on the first urn showing that they prefer to draw a ball
from an urn in which the probabilities of the two colours balls are precisely defined.
Aversion to uncertainty creates a problem to Savage theory also for another reason. Let’s
consider again the two urns. If you always choose to draw a ball from Urn I, whatever colour
you prefer, this implies that you consider the probability of getting red plus the probability of
getting black in Urn I different from the probability of getting red plus the probability of getting
black in Urn II. If this is the case, then, the sum of your probability estimates of the two colour
balls for the two urns is going to be different from 1. In particular, ambiguity aversion implies
that your estimate of the probability of red plus your estimate of the probability of black in Urn
II is less than 1. Your probability estimates thus are not following the mathematical rules of
Savage theory. Intuitively, the difference of the sum of the two probabilities from one is the
room that we leave to the existence of uncertainty, that is to say, the possibility of occurrence of
some unexpected situation. As a consequence it is very difficult to deduce our probability
estimate from our choice as pointed out by Ellsberg. Ellsberg’s work has been confirmed by a
substantial number of empirical and theoretical research contributions (Camerer and Weber
1992; Trautman et al. 2008; Machina and Siniscalchi 2014; Gilboa and Marinacci 2016).
Cross-References
Certainty Equivalent
Radical Uncertainty
Risk Management, Optimal
References
Allais, Maurice (1953), “Fondements d’une théorie positive des choix comportant un risqué
et critique des postulates et axioms de l’école Américaine”, Econometrica, 21(4), pp.503-546.
Allais, Maurice and Hagen, Ole (eds) (1979), Expected Utility Hypothesis and the Allais
Paradox, Dordrecht, D. Reidel.
Arrow, Kenneth (1964), “The Role of Securities in the Optimal Allocation of Risk-Bearing”,
Review of Economic Studies, 31, pp. 91–96.
Bernoulli, Daniel (1954), “Specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis”. Commentarii
Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae, 1738. Trans. as “Exposition of a new theory
on the measurement of risk”, Econometrica, 22, pp. 23-26.
Camerer, Colin E. and Weber, Martin (1992), “Recent Developments in Modeling
Preferences: Uncertainty and Ambiguity”, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5 (4). pp. 325-370.
de Finetti, Bruno (1937), “La prévision: ses lois logiques, ses sources subjectives”, Annales
de l'Institut Henri Poincaré, 7(1), pp.1-68.
Ellsberg Daniel (1961), “Risk Ambiguity and the Savage Axioms”, Quarterly Journal of
Economics, 75, pp.643-69.
Gilboa, Itzhak and Marinacci, Massimo (2016), “Ambiguity and the Bayesian Paradigm”, in
Arló-Costa, Horacio, Hendricks, Vincent F. and van Benthem, Johan (eds), Readings in Formal
Epistemology, new York, Springer.
Kahneman, Daniel and Tversky, Amos (1979), “Prospect Theory: an Analysis of Decision
under Risk”, Econometrica, 47, pp.273-291.
Keynes John, M.(1921), A Treatise on Probability. London, McMillan.
Knight, Frank (1921), Risk, Uncertainty and Profit, Boston, Houghton-Mifflin.
6
Loomes, Graham and Sugden, Robert (1982), “Regret Theory: An Alternative Theory of
Rational Choice under Uncertainty”, Economic Journal, 92, pp. 805-824.
MacCrimmon, Kenneth R. and Larsson, Stig (1979), “Utility Theory: Axioms versus
‘Paradoxes’, in Allais, Maurice and Hagen, Ole (eds), Expected Utility Hypothesis and the
Allais Paradox, Dordrecht, D. Reidel.
Machina, Mark (1987), “Choice under Uncertainty: Problems Solved and Unsolved”,
Journal of Economic Perspectives, 1(1), pp. 121-154.
Machina, Mark and Siniscalchi, Marciano (2014), “Ambiguity and Ambiguity Aversion”, in
Machina, Mark and Viscusi, Kip (eds), The Handbook of the Economics of Risk and
Uncertainty, Oxford, North-Holland.
Marschak, Jakob (1950), “Rational Behavior, Uncertain Prospects, and Measurable Utility”,
Econometrica, 18, pp. 111-141.
von Neumann, John and Morgenstern, Oskar, Theory of Games and Economic Behaviour. 2nd
edition, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1947.
Pratt, J.W. (1964), “Risk Aversion in the Small and in the Large”, Econometrica, 32, pp.
122-136.
Quiggin, John (1982), “A Theory of Anticipated Utility, Journal of Economic Behaviour and
Organization, 3, pp. 323-343.
Quiggin, John (1993), Generalized Expected Utility Theory, Dordrecht, Kluwer.
Raiffa, Howard (1968), Decision Analysis: Introductory Lectures on Choices under
Uncertainty, Reading MA, Addison-Wesley.
Ramsey, Frank P. (1931), “Truth and Probability” in The Foundations of Mathematics and
other Logical Essays, New York, Harcourt, Brace.
Savage, Leonard (1954), The Foundations of Statistics, New York, Wiley.
Schmeidler, David (1989), “Subjective Probability and Expected Utility without Additivity,
Econometrica, 57(3), pp.571-587.
Starmer, Chris and Sugden, Robert (1989), “Violations of the Independence Axiom in
Common Ratio Problems: An Experimental Test of Some Competing Hypotheses”, Annals of
Operations Research, 19(1), pp. 79-102.
Starmer, Chris (2000), “Developments in Non-expected Utility Theory”, Journal of
Economic Literature, 38, pp. 332-382.
Trautmann, Stefan T., Vieider, Ferdinand M. and Wakker, Peter P. (2008), “Causes of
Ambiguity Aversion: Known versus Unknown Preferences”, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty,
36(3), pp. 225-243.
Tversky, Amos and Kahneman, Daniel (1992), “Advances in Prospect Theory: Cumulative
Representation of Uncertainty”, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, pp. 297-323.
7
U
b
U(x2)
c
U(x)=EU(L2)=(½Ux1+½Ux2)
=U(EV)
a
U(x1)
x1 x=(½x1+½x2)=EV x2 Wealth
b
U(x2)
d
U(x)= U(½x1+½x2)=U(EV)
EU(L2)=(½Ux1+½Ux2)
c
a
U(x1)
x1 x=(½x1+½x2)=EV x2 Wealth
8
U
b
U(x2)
c
EU(L2)=(½Ux1+½Ux2)
U(x)=U(½x1+½x2)=U(EV)
a d
U(x1)
x1 x=(½x1+½x2)=EV x2 Wealth
b
U(x2)
d
U(x)=U(½x1+½x2)=U(EV)
EU(L2)=(½Ux1+½Ux2)=
U(CE) c
a
U(x1)
x1 CE(L2) x=(½x1+½x2)=EV x2
Wealth
Figure 4. Utility function of a risk averse individual with certainty equivalent and risk
premium measures