Untitled
Untitled
OX F O R D S T U D I E S I N W E S T E R N E S O T E R IC I SM
Series Editor
Henrik Bogdan, University of Gothenburg
Editorial Board
Jean-Pierre Brach, École Pratique des Hautes Études
Carole Cusack, University of Sydney
Christine Ferguson, University of Stirling
Olav Hammer, University of Southern Denmark
Wouter Hanegraaff, University of Amsterdam
Ronald Hutton, University of Bristol
Jeffrey Kripal, Rice University
James R. Lewis, University of Tromsø
Michael Stausberg, University of Bergen
Egil Asprem, University of Stockholm
Dylan Burns, Freie Universität Berlin
Gordan Djurdjevic, Siimon Fraser University
Peter Forshaw, University of Amsterdam
Jesper Aa. Petersen, Norwegian University of Science and Technology
SPIRITUAL ALCHEMY
From the Age of Jacob Boehme to
Mary Anne Atwood, 1600–1910
Mike A. Zuber
MYSTIFYING KABBALAH
Academic Scholarship, National Theology, and
New Age Spirituality
Boaz Huss
OCCULT IMPERIUM
Arturo Reghini, Roman Traditionalism, and the
Anti-Modern Reaction in Fascist Italy
Christian Giudice
VESTIGES OF A PHILOSOPHY
Matter, the Meta-Spiritual, and
the Forgotten Bergson
John Ó Maoilearca
Vestiges of a Philosophy
Matter, the Meta-Spiritual, and the Forgotten
Bergson
J O H N Ó M AO I L E A R C A
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers
the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education
by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University
Press in the UK and certain other countries.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.001.0001
1 3 5 7 9 8 6 4 2
Printed by Integrated Books International, United States of America
Contents
Notes 179
Bibliography 217
Index 229
Illustrations
Figures
Table
Among the many challenging ideas found in the works of Henri Bergson, one
of the strangest, and most difficult, concerns what he called “complete rela-
tivity.” This concept appears in his penultimate monograph, Duration and
Simultaneity. This text gathered ideas concerning Bergson’s infamous clash
with Albert Einstein at the Société française de philosophie in 1922.1 At the
center of their disagreement lies a difference in attitude toward “Langevin’s
paradox,” or the “twin’s paradox,” first put forward in 1911 by the physicist
Paul Langevin in his own exploration of Einstein’s special theory of relativity
(STR). This paradox concerns a thought experiment where one “voyager,”
Paul, sends his twin brother, Peter, off in a rocket at a speed just less than
that of light.2 After a year, the rocket turns around and heads back to earth
at the exact same velocity. Peter gets out after what has now been a two-year
journey in the rocket only to discover that Paul has “aged” two hundred years
“and has long been in his grave.”3
This is a predicted result from STR due to Peter traveling close to the
speed of light, which retards the aging process (following Einstein’s theory).4
Understood as two (biological) clocks, Peter’s velocity relative to Paul allows
him to age more slowly than Paul. Peter cannot reverse time, but he does
retard it, at least relative to Paul. Yet it might still be asked: why is it Paul’s
aging alone that quickens relative to Peter? After all, in a consistent rela-
tivism of time, surely Paul could be seen as traveling at near to the speed
of light relative to Peter—their speeds are reciprocal and covary—in which
case, there would be no age difference between the two at all.5 So here is the
paradox: the answer to whose aging slows down and whose speeds up all
depends on which frame of reference you decide to treat as immobile (and
take your measurements from), and which is taken as being in motion rela-
tive to this frame. And, as this decision is entirely contingent, it leaves STR
looking somewhat perverse as a theory.
Moreover, for Bergson, separated twin siblings are more than interchange-
able clocks; they are living beings that cannot be substituted for each other
without losing something in the process. From this vantage point, a clock is
an impersonal abstraction of our lived experience of time (durée). Indeed, it
xii Prologue
is one that privileges only one frame of reference at a time in what Bergson
dubs a “single” or “half-relativity” (la demi-relativité)—the frame of reference
of the immobile measuring the mobile. In contrast to this seemingly flawed
approach, Bergson proposed a “double” or “complete relativity” (la relativité
complete) where there are no privileged reference frames and where no per-
spective can be completely represented by another in an act of substitution.6
Every frame or perspective is equalized as completely individual. It is impos-
sible for Paul to represent the personal experience of Peter fully, because ex-
perience is more than the representation of experience. For one to represent
fully another’s lived time, one must experience it in every detail, in person.
But this is impossible without actually being that other person: “if I want to
actually measure Peter’s time, I must enter Peter’s frame of reference; I must
become Peter. If I want to actually measure Paul’s time, I must take Paul’s
place.”7 Otherwise, all I am left with is my virtual image of Paul, not his ac-
tuality. Ultimately, STR is predicated fallaciously on “a time or a space [that
is] always virtual and merely imagined, never real and experienced.” Its “es-
sence” is to “rank the real vision with the virtual visions” or to hide “the dif-
ference between the real and the virtual.”8
Let’s pause for a moment to think this through, because, in one way or
another, it is crucial for everything that follows in this book. Fulfilling the
counterfactual, “if I had been you . . .” entails me being all that you are, and
hence not I-being-you (which would only bring along non-you baggage with
it), but you-being-you (which even includes all of your kinds of self-alterity,
auto-differentiation, etc.). We need a complete history (material, psycholog-
ical, and social) to “transform” one person genuinely into a real other person
(rather than merely an abstraction of that other): this would be an exhaustive
factual analysis of that person-there-and-then that only that person-there-
and-then can embody.9
This emphasis on haecceity, on the thisness of this temporal perspective
(a real time that is always lived by an actual someone, somewhere) is not to
reinstate a totalizing logic of self-identity, hermetically sealed off from all al-
terity, however. Indeed, to circumvent the dichotomies associated with STR,
it is precisely the logic of separation (Peter or Paul) that must be overcome.
The scene is thereby set for alternative logics, logics based on objects that are
not only solid, hard bodies impervious to substitution with each other, but
also fluid ones, watery and gaseous ones, or even sonic ones. This will involve
performative, imagistic, and diagrammatic thinking, where some things
can indeed be this and that, here and there, but not through a transcendent
Prologue xiii
I believe precisely that, at the base of all our mystical states, there are
techniques of the body which have not been studied. . . . I think that
there are necessarily biological means to enter into “communication
with God”.
—Marcel Mauss, “Body Techniques”1
Zelator
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0001
2 Vestiges of a Philosophy
on me for a while as it is one of the few things I can easily recollect from that
period of my life.
This thesis of memory as ontological, as a real persistence of the past in
our psychic lives, obviously did not come to life with Bergson alone: in var-
ious forms it harks back to the Renaissance (the spheres of the universe as
memory system) and then ever further to Plato’s anamnesis (recollection
not merely as knowledge of the past but knowledge from a past life abiding
within us as the soul travels from one life to another—metempsychosis). The
idea that memory is a form of (mental) time travel can be understood cogni-
tively rather than ontologically, of course, wherein it is only a representation
of the past, albeit one that has real effects in the present.3 This is the way it is
understood in numerous psychological studies, the most well-known pos-
sibly being Ellen Langer’s “Counter Clockwise Study” in 1979. This experi-
ment involved eight elderly men living for a week in a residential retreat that
re-created the social and physical environment of 1959. After the week was
over, all eight appeared to have grown younger as a result, be that under-
stood in terms of cognitive or physical health. Their attitude—conditioned
within a kind of “Proustian space”—reversed the effects of the aging pro-
cess to render them younger, as measured on a number of levels (physical
strength, perception, cognition, taste, hearing, and visual thresholds). The
house they entered was a figurative time slip of sorts: Perry Como played on
a vintage radio; The Ed Sullivan Show shone from a black-and-white TV; all
the books and magazines in the house were period correct. Nor were there
any mirrors in the house that might break this spell. Moreover, the eight men
in the experimental group were instructed to behave, to act, just as if it re-
ally were 1959 now, rather than to reminisce about 1959 from the current
year of 1979. Meanwhile, a control group in another house “remained” in
1979 and only had to recollect the life they had in 1959. In them, no signif-
icant changes were detected at the end of the exercise.4 The eight in the ex-
perimental group, however, exited the house as different people, analogically
de-aged.5 Yet, of course, beyond the confines of this house, everything was
still in “1979”: though the effects of some of the men’s advancing years might
have been tempered, nobody conducting this experiment was claiming that
time itself was really put in reverse, inside or outside of the house.
The idea of a real (psychological) time machine—one where you, or some
aspect of you, are the machine—was not being entertained in this experi-
ment. Some films, on the other hand, have flirted with this idea. One of them
is Jeannot Szwarc’s Somewhere in Time (1980), which was filmed at about
Strange Memory 3
One year later, in a lecture given in Paris on “The Soul and the Body,” Bergson
attempts to “push the argument to its limit” by imagining a single sentence
4 Vestiges of a Philosophy
“lasting for years”: “well, I believe that our whole psychical existence is some-
thing just like this single sentence, continued since the first awakening of
consciousness, interspersed with commas, but never broken by full stops.
And consequently I believe that our whole past still exists.”8 Attention is the
time machine for Bergson. Indeed, one might even say that each of us suffers
from some degree of attention-deficit disorder, only it is one which is species-
specific, with (perhaps) only a few artists, mystics, and so-called madmen, as
we will see, being less “disordered” than the rest of us.
In extending this attention (by whatever means) what we call our “past” is
embraced within what we call our “present.” The former distends the latter.
So far, so “merely” psychological, perhaps. After all, it is only a matter, for
now, of what we call “past” and “present.” Yet Bergson seems to hedge his bets
between psychology and ontology by remaining unclear as to what is being
maintained here—my past as I remember it, or the past itself. Ordinarily, we
would say that there is a major difference between the two, yet Bergson invar-
iably fails to make the distinction, speaking interchangeably about “my past,”
“memory,” and “the past.”9 On one page of his 1907 book Creative Evolution,
for instance, he writes that “the piling up of the past upon the past goes on
without relaxation.” Only then does he say on the next page that “it is with
our entire past, including the original bent of our soul, that we desire, will
and act,” and later again that “from this survival of the past it follows that con-
sciousness cannot go through the same state twice.”10 So, once more, though
it is I who actively remembers from the present moment, what returns is not
a recollection, but the past in which I reside (my past is the past).
Ultimately, most commentators agree on this one point as regards
Bergson’s theory of memory—for him the past is a real agent, alive and
kicking, in one form or another: “it is we who are in time, rather than time
that is in us” (Grosz); “we are not ‘in’ time, in the manner that objects oc-
cupy parts of space. We are time, unfolding at different speeds” (Khandker);
“rather than conceiving of memory as a way of relating to the past from the
perspective of the present, Bergson regularly equates memory with the to-
tality of one’s past as it is preserved in itself ” (Perri); “the past is not in the
past but in a present which exists virtually and which lies below and beyond
the time of adaptation” (Mourélos).11 I could go on (don’t worry, I won’t).
Nicolas de Warren calls all this “Bergson’s Copernican Revolution” whereby
consciousness as a whole does not move from the present to the past, but
“from the past to the present, from memory to perception.”12 When I re-
member, I do not reach from the present into the past, but a part of the past
Strange Memory 5
Ipsissimus
Strange ideas to be sure, then, and yet, despite some appearances to the con-
trary, this is not a Bergsonian idealism that would render the world as being
“for me,” the real as my idea, or as an artifact of language, a product of desire,
power, difference, or whatever else. Bergsonism has always proposed some-
thing between realism and idealism—ideas related to the world realistically.
To answer the question, “What returns in memory?” therefore, with only
ever one kind of part—an idea, a representation, or even more concretely,
an affect, an attitude, or a bodily relation, would still confuse one part for the
whole. What returns is the real past itself, in part. And ideas, too, are real, for
of course they are parts of the real as well. The real past sometimes returns
in part as idea, but oftentimes in many other forms. As Matter and Memory
puts it:
Between this perception of matter and matter itself there is but a difference
of degree and not of kind . . . the relation of the part to the whole. . . .
My consciousness of matter is no longer either subjective . . . or rela-
tive. . . . It is not subjective, for it is in things rather than in me. It is not rel-
ative, because the relation between “phenomenon” and the “thing” is not
that of appearance to reality, but merely that of the part to the whole.13
the present and therefore already memory—is not a series of distinct terms
outside of one another, nor a coexistence of the past with the present. But
rather, it manifests the indivisibility of a change, a change that, as Bergson
notes in chapter four of Matter and Memory, undoubtedly endures.”14
Change changes—so there is not one monolithic or homogeneous conti-
nuity for Bergson (as Gaston Bachelard liked to portray it in his never-ending
critique of duration), but a range of continuities with different durations
strewn throughout the cosmos.15 Indeed, they are the cosmos: continuities
of bodies, large and small, of spatial arrangements, of ideas, of affects, of
species, of phyla, and so on—each enduring at different, changing, and foli-
ated levels of tension (or “tone” as Trevor Perri puts it).16 What unites these
temporal parts, if only partially, is not containment within any one single,
transcendent timeline, but this tone or level of tension. It is something imma-
nently temporal that we will call “covariance.” What makes one temporal part
that part of this whole (which is itself another part of another whole) is the
durée it shares with others, its covariance.
Admittedly, the phenomenology of grief, for instance, will offer a coun-
terexample to all this talk of continuity, especially when it is phrased in wa-
tery metaphors of “flow,” “streams,” “fluids,” or “waves.” Grief, by contrast,
blocks—it stops. Grief and mourning (or even more severely, trauma) are
experienced by many as a halt in time, a stoppage of time in its supposed
“flow.” All the clocks are stopped, and time freezes within either a past trau-
matic event or a perpetual present of loss. These clocks are mechanical, of
course, but to resort to that fact here would be a crude response. Nor do we
need to invoke the truism that “time heals all wounds,” or even retort that
our biological clocks are immune, or at least indifferent, to the psychological
phenomena of suffering (they are not, by the way). It is not a coincidence that
the Indo-European root for memory is (s)mer—which means “to mourn,”
and that the Germanic root is smerd—which means “pain.” As the psychol-
ogist Patrick McNamara notes in this regard, “memory’s deep roots extend
back into mourning.”17 In fact, such a wholly different experience of time,
the seemingly complete restriction of its flow, is precisely evidence for ex-
actly the multiplicity of times being put forward here. Time flows differently
on different planes, sometimes in such felt experiences of endured deceler-
ation that it indeed feels as if at a complete standstill. In truth, the intimate
connections between grief, mourning, and memory are precisely some of
the different ways in which the past survives within the present, or rather re-
mains indivisible within a present.
Strange Memory 7
Theoricus
But I am getting far ahead of myself. To lay my cards on the table, the strange-
ness of Bergson that I mentioned at the outset is not restricted to a number of
conceptual peculiarities or inconsistences found in odd corners of his work.
It concerns the entire thrust of his thought as a philosopher, one following
the best scientific data of the day from psychology, biology, and physics, and
yet also enframing them within a context where the physical world is un-
derstood as movement, energy, and force, alongside of which lie many other
forces that might be dubbed physical and “spiritual” as well. It concerns a
Strange Memory 9
(eventually taking over as its sole head a little after Samuel’s death in 1918).23
She did this while living in Paris and performing public rites as one part of
the Order’s activities, the other involving private rituals of initiation and ad-
vancement in occult learning. Such was her fame in the last decade of the
nineteenth century that historian Dennis Denisoff has described her and
Samuel as the “neo-pagan power couple” of the Belle Époque.24
What did they do, then—what was the purpose of such Orders as the
Golden Dawn? This simple description from Christopher Armstrong ini-
tially sums it up well: “the acquisition of a certain ‘gnosis’ or private experi-
ential contact with ultimate realities through the deliberate deployment of
incantations and rituals, drawn from various sources, some genuinely an-
cient and associated with the historic Rosicrucian movement, some osten-
sibly archaic but in fact of very recent concoction.”25 Pace Armstrong’s jibe
about “concoction” by the Golden Dawn, their public performances were
never intended to be historically accurate. They were creative and artistic
invocations—a “performance art,” according to Denisoff, with ceremonies
that were, as Frederic Lees described them at the time, “artistic in the ex-
treme.”26 Performed at the Théâtre La Bodinière and other secret locations in
Paris, Mina Bergson, dressed as high priestess Anari, would invoke the god-
dess Isis materially, immanently, and in person.27 (Parenthetically, whereas
an evocation in Enochian magic brings a spirit into the world as a separate en-
tity, in an invocation the spirit is channeled by the medium into another body,
her own being a common choice for such embodiment: she is not a means of
communication so much as an incarnation of spirit, a moving conduit that,
as we will see, works through mimetic performance as well as symbolism.)28
Isis, who is first recorded c. 2350–2100 bce, is the Egyptian goddess of life,
the all-encompassing mother, a moon goddess, as well as the goddess of
nourishment, healing, and magic (in the Osiris Myth, she brings her brother,
Osiris, partially back from the dead).29 So important for the Golden Dawn
were these Isis rites, moreover, that after 1900 Samuel and Mina would refer
to all their work as part of the “Isis movement.”30 That a goddess was central
to the Golden Dawn is not surprising given the feminist orientation of many
of its principles: the Golden Dawn preached the equality of the sexes on all
fronts, as well as other radical causes in that era, such as animal rights and
vegetarianism.31 In our efforts here to recover Mina Bergson’s ideas, it will
also be necessary to examine a number of specific facets contained within
this image of a feminine, divine “movement,” and thereby a means to see it
equally as an assembly of continuities, of covariants.
Strange Memory 11
Philosophus
matter. Indeed, such approaches more or less continued well into the twen-
tieth century in positivist philosophies, with only very recent developments,
such as “New Mechanical Philosophy” (or “New Mechanism”), tempering
the views held by many in this tradition.36
By contrast, new materialism loosely follows Gestalt principles and deems
matter to form complex, nonlinear, dynamic wholes that are not the sum
of their parts. This focus on the micro by both old and new materialisms—
in physics to be sure but also in biology (stem cells) and cognitive science
(neural plasticity, embryonic epigenesis)— is what Sam Coleman calls
“smallism”: the idea that truth resides in the smallest particulars of reality
(which may clump together to form larger wholes); that “the ontological
truth is to be found with the small, or with all the “smalls” in all their in-
numerable multiplicity.”37 In the new materialism, however, wholes are also
real, even though emergent—their properties constitute a genuinely different
level of reality, albeit that they are generated by the complex interactions of
their smaller, constitutive elements. This emergence of the larger from the
smaller, one that is neither reductive (the large does not reduce entirely to the
small) nor mechanistic (such small matter is not passive), is a crucial aspect
for much of this thinking. The question of level and scale, therefore, both
spatial and temporal, will be critical in what follows here, too.
Whether it be Quentin Meillassoux’s “mathemic” valorization of contin-
gency, the idea of “plasticity” in Catherine Malabou’s neurophilosophy, en-
tanglement in Karen Barad’s philosophy of physics, or “vibrant matter” in
Jane Bennett’s neo-vitalism, we can also see a second, less explicit premise
of new materialism in much of its work: namely, that whatever number of
emergent, nonreducible properties are allowed to matter, the idea of spirit
cannot be added to the list. Nonreduced materiality alone prevails, while a
transcendent, Platonist notion of spirit—the only one deemed possible by
some—remains the conceptual outsider to be either eliminated or simply
ignored. As John Zammito writes: “one of the essentially contested issues
surrounding the new materialism is how to conceive the relation of ‘spirit’ to
the natural.”38 This is why the possibility of a nontranscendent (or immanent)
spirit is rarely, if ever, entertained. This is where some historical research may
be of use, in particular around the school of “French Spiritualism.” This was
a loose tradition of thought that lasted from the late eighteenth century up
to Henri Bergson himself as its final representative. Despite its name, it was
not a school of the occult, but what we might nowadays call a nondualist,
nonreductive approach to mind and body. These earlier French philosophers,
14 Vestiges of a Philosophy
What we see, then, is a clear reciprocal acceleration between the flight of new
materialism away from old materialism—a flight that was inflected by prop-
erties also associated with spirit (creativity and contingency)—and the flight
of the new spiritualism away from the old, whose own trajectory was mod-
ified by elements from material science. So, instead of talking of matter or
spirit, we might talk in terms of continua, of contingency, creativity, and vi-
tality. But again, these continua are not homogeneous, but themselves replete
with qualitative change, with mutation.
And here is where we can also make a further point about covariance.
In his essay, “Scale Variance and the Concept of Matter,” Derek Woods
speaks about the difference between “scale variance” (things that change
with scale) and “scale invariance” (things that do not).49 This notion
builds on the work of philosopher of science Mariam Thalos and her con-
cept of “scale freedom,” which Woods interprets in his own work to mean
“freedom from the notion that any single scale is the master scale.” What
Woods takes from this is the principle that “there is irreducible activity at
every scale,” and finally that “matter may not be the best concept for what
the new materialism works to address.”50 The covariance, and covariants,
we will talk about here concern a continuity formed through movements
changing in concert: not as the same activity simpliciter but as different
activities (plural) in some form of temporal reciprocity. And neither a
spiritualism devoid of matter nor a materialism devoid of spirit can ac-
commodate such continua.
Strange Memory 17
Practicus
Bergson, for the first time, gives us a sense that philosophy is an act that each
of us undertakes on his own account, as if he were alone in the world, as if
he were the first to do it, as if no one had ever done it before him. Naturally,
that is not true, but one must act as if. In this respect, the philosophical act
resembles love. The one who does it redoes what millions of human beings
have done before him. And yet he experiences what he does as something
entirely new, unheard of, original, spring-like. For him, redoing is doing;
for him, to start again is really to start; the one who loves for the first time is
in his own way a brilliant inventor and improviser.52
In Henri Bergson’s own words, “one knows, one understands only what one
can in some measure reinvent.”53 This Bergsonian movement does not begin
or end with Henri Bergson either (nor even with Mina Bergson as an equal
protagonist). Each reinvention begins as if anew, like an act of love (what
Alain Badiou would call an “event”). New materialism is one example of a
presently widespread movement that is both itself and a reinvention. Yet
some may still ask, what is the subject of such movements? What is being
reinvented, what is being remade in these hetero-continuities? And the an-
swer, it seems, is all kinds of different, heterogeneous beings: spatial (covari-
ance all the way up, and down), temporal, affective, bodily, and conceptual (to
name a few). There is an indefinite number of continuities in this continuist
stance. We, however, will look at it through five domains in the following
order: history, psychology, biology, philosophy, and physics.
18 Vestiges of a Philosophy
In her book Vibrant Matter, Jane Bennett discusses Michel Serres’s own
discovery of structural invariance in the historical birth of physics: as far
back Lucretius’s De Rerum Natura, we see a powerful isomorphism at work:
The Book V, on the world and nascent humanity, is traversed by the same
laws as the Book IV, on perception; and these are the laws of matter found
in Book II. Always the same whole, a multiplicity of elements, and al-
ways the same operations at work on these wholes. The method by struc-
tural invariants, generalised to the global stability of flowing movements,
establishes materialism.54
1
Kether
(Crown)
3
Binah 2
(Under- Chokmah
standing) (Wisdom)
5 4
Geburah Chesed
(Severity) (mercy)
6
Tiphareth
(Beauty)
8 7
Hod Netzach
(Splendor) (Victory)
9
Yesod
(Founda-
tion)
10
Malkuth
(Kingdom)
the system, how many grades have been completed (first number) and how
many remain outstanding, in principle at least (second number).56
In this book, however, the diagram and its elements are used syncretically,
bringing philosophical issues together with historical and spiritualist
ones: for Zelator, the issue of discrete opposites versus continuities in the past
20 Vestiges of a Philosophy
not the model; that is, they are adopted without any “religionist” commit-
ment to their ontology, to what Wouter J. Hanegraaff describes as an “impos-
sible dream of a ‘history of truth.’ ”59
And this is why their grades are employed here in a disorderly fashion, or
rather they are flattened: there is no hierarchy, teleology, or evolution of stages
at work here. In one sense, however, the covariants themselves do “evolve” as
they appear and reappear through the book: and that evolution is through
their duration. Beginning quite small and almost as an aside from the struc-
ture of the main argument, they grow in scale until, by the end, the parts
have virtually overwhelmed the whole. As such, the structure of the book
performs a thesis that is sustained throughout (almost ad nauseum)—that
any continuity harbors a discontinuity within itself, that is, a heterogeneity,
an interference. Only, at this higher level, a new heterogeneous continuity
of sameness and difference is thereby invented. I will leave the reader to dis-
cover any other elements that might covary (and so continue) between ei-
ther the parts of the work or within each part. This is especially with regard
to one historical covariance that hardly needs to be pointed out (though of
course I will): that the three women and one nonbinary person who occupy
most of these reflections comprise one spiritualist from the past and three
materialists from the present.
1° =10° Zelator Covariant
For Bergson, matter and mind are not substances. They are “tendencies” or
“forces.” These tendencies conflict and collaborate in many areas of human
experience and, beyond, of reality. [ . . . ] For him, the mind/body problem
(or more broadly the mind/matter problem) had to be examined in areas
where these distinctions were obscure: phenomena of a high degree of ma-
terial complexity, which can also be interpreted as “lower manifestations of
the mind.” The spiritualist/materialist debate is uninteresting and sterile if
it focuses on the superior psychological faculties, understanding, reason,
creative imagination.2
So let us leave names aside for now. In fact, even Anglo-French spiritualism/
spiritisme in the nineteenth century was not averse to the incorporation of
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0002
1° = 10° Zelator Covariant 23
the physical into its explanations of the paranormal, especially in the light
of new scientific discoveries about the nature of matter. As Richard Noakes
points out, new conceptions of “electricity, energy and ether offered possible
physical explanations of telepathy, telekinesis and disembodied souls.” In
fact, a good amount of historical research has shown that in the nineteenth
and twentieth centuries, “theories and ideas in psychology, biology, and
physics flowed to and, occasionally, from psychical research”3
And that means can cut both ways, either to re-enchant matter (in-
flate science) or reduce mind (deflate psychism). Richard Jones’s work on
the “philosophy of mysticism,” for instance, concedes that an individual’s
mystical experience achieved through meditation (opening the “doors
of perception,” etc.), might also be realized through both more mun-
dane methods (enjoying the beauty of nature, art, or music), as well as
more pathological ones: emotional stress, grief, despair, illness, starva-
tion, disability (e.g., epilepsy), brain injury, or sense deprivation.8 And
any of these ordinary methods can also serve to deflate one’s spirits, in
every sense.
Jones also points out that there are generally two types of reduction that
can work to discredit mystical claims: scientific ones that see mystical states
as “nothing but electrochemical activity in the brain or some other physical
or biological phenomenon,” and sociocultural reductions that interpret them
as “social, psychological, or cultural phenomena.”9 Pamela Thurschwell’s
approach would be a sophisticated version of the latter. Following the ex-
ample of Friedrich Kittler’s work in media archaeology, spiritualism is read
by her as a kind of “magical thinking” informed by the new kinds of repro-
duction and communication technologies that were emerging in the nine-
teenth century. Apparatuses like the telegraph and telephone “suggested
that science could help annihilate distances that separate bodies and minds
from each other.” Suddenly, the claims of spiritualist mediums might be
supported: “talking to the dead and talking on the phone both hold out
the promise of previously unimaginable contact between people.”10 Yet the
technology can also rebound on those employing it as a model. If medium-
ship is made analogous to a technology, perhaps the former’s emergence as
a cultural phenomenon at the same time as the introduction of the latter is
more than just a coincidence. Thurschwell quotes Kittler to great effect on
this matter:
the tapping specters of the spiritualistic séances with their messages from
the realm of the dead, appeared quite promptly at the moment of the in-
vention of the Morse alphabet in 1837. Promptly, photographic plates—
even and especially with the camera shutter closed—provided images of
ghosts or specters which in their black and white fuzziness, only empha-
sized the moments of resemblance. Finally one of the ten uses Edison
predicted . . . for the recently invented phonograph was to preserve the “last
words of the dying.”11
1° = 10° Zelator Covariant 25
Katz puts it more pithily as follows: “what the Buddhist experiences as nir-
vana is different from what the Jew experiences as devekuth.” This is simply
because “mystical experience is ‘over-determined’ by its socio-religious mi-
lieu.”13 Nothing is purely given—and all seeming givens are the product of
selection and shaping. Yet where Jones refers to Katz and his followers as
“constructivists,” Katz himself prefers to describe his approach as “contex-
tualist,” and the crucial context for all experience, according to Katz, is lan-
guage: “language,” he contends, is “integral to mystical practice. This is not to
exaggerate this fact or, yet, to attack the central issue of ineffability, but it is
to begin to widen our parameters, to broaden our understanding, as to how
language relates to mystical experience.”14
However, these approaches can be double-edged, too. “Nonconstructivists”
or “decontextualists”—arguing for the irreducibility of mystical experience—
will reason that various cultural conceptualizations may indeed influence
our interpretations of the spiritual, but that this “does not mean that they
must be present during the depth-mystical experience itself.”15 There re-
mains something that transcends every mediation. Against all such Kantian
(constructive) approaches, “any postexperience intentional object is the
26 Vestiges of a Philosophy
The basic idea is that there are many different kinds of matter- like
substances. Among them are psychic forces, granite rocks, imagined
objects, spiritual essences and so forth. All of these substances interact with
each other, but granite-like objects and spirit-like objects are governed by
different natural laws. The point is that things which are normally thought
not to exist (like a mental image of a polar bear, outside the imaging subject’s
mind) do exist, but in a different way, and under different laws, than do ta-
bles and chairs. Golden-hearted dragons are real, but not like brown-eyed
anthropologists.23
Even though different versions of this general idea might be favored by dif-
ferent magicians, nevertheless, according to Luhrmann, “most of them view
things imagined as a sort of stuff, which has an impact upon a tables-and-
chairs reality.”
This “magical realism,” so to speak, raises another question from the
Bergsonian vantage point, however: what if this alternative “stuff,” these
“different kinds of matter-like substance” that might not even fit our usual
“phenomenal categories” like space—what if this stuff was not any kind of
substance at all, within or without ordinary experience? In other words, what
if it was rather a kind of temporal continuity that always operates imma-
nently, only at different scales (be they super-or sub-), some of which, being
so different from our own “norm,” that they are taken as para-normal when
all they are is super-normal—a continuation rather than an alternative? What
we might call the “supernormal”—to give a new use to an old word—is the
ordinary at a different temporal level, yet always in some kind of continuity
with others.24 Not one ulterior reality parallel to ours, but unattended aspects
of a multilayered reality shared with indefinitely many others.
The Zelator grade, as its name would suggest, indicates all the energy of
the initiate, the student, an absolute faith in the earth (“Malkuth” in the Tree
of Life diagram), which, all the same, must not be taken as unspiritual.25
Confidence in the power of the first name learned at the outset will soon give
way to a continuism that sees names like “material” segue into the “spiritual”
and “spirit,” just as “psychical” research bleeds into “physics” research, spirit-
ualism into “spiritisme,” and so on. And such continuities represent what we
will later call the “meta-spiritual.”
1
Ordinary Mysticism, the Hyperbolic, and
the Supernormal
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0003
30 Vestiges of a Philosophy
the “unknown to the already known,” and so went from “normal to abnormal
to supernormal psychological phenomena.”5 As he himself wrote in 1885,
“when we speak of an abnormal phenomenon we do not mean one which
contravenes natural laws, but one which exhibits them in an unusual or inex-
plicable form.” The supernormal is the abnormal normal, so to speak—and
both exist on a “continuum” or “spectrum.”
In this way, we can think of supernormalization as pure imma-
nentism: there is an immanent continuity such that the supernormal is al-
ways already the so-called normal: time travel is always already recollection
(and not merely as “mental” time travel); the ghost is always already a pure
memory. In other words, it was Kansas all along, Dorothy. Where we differ
with Myers is as follows: he would think of telepathy or clairvoyance, say, as
liminal versions of mental representation, that is, as mental states lying along
the same spectrum as our normal psychical life, only far from where we ordi-
narily operate. We, however, simply take the corollary to heart: there is some-
thing always already “telepathic,” say, in our ordinary, normal ability to “read
minds” (such that, to those who supposedly suffer “mind-blindness,” having
a neurotypical “theory of mind” is a mystery).6 Similarly, self-representation
could be seen as a kind of out-of-body, or astral, experience, with so-called
astral projection simply being the hyperbolic form of representation (“hyper-
bole” originally meaning “a throwing beyond”—from the Greek, hyperballein,
“to throw above or beyond”). These states all exist on a continuum, as Myers
puts it, but for us it is a heterogeneous continuity. Whereas Myers focuses on
the unseen part of the “spectrum” in order to anchor its liminal status in the
normal (going from mundane to extra-mundane), we, instead, enfold the
extra-mundane into the ordinary without qualitatively altering the latter—
everyday mental events are always already varied enough or sufficiently het-
erogeneous (if we could pay closer attention to them): Kansas metaphysics.7
This is why we will ask whether Mina Bergson’s mystical practice, as found
in performances such as the rites of Isis, scrying, or astral travel, might not be
rendered both “ordinary” and epistemological through a supernormalization
without reduction. Such an “ordinary mysticism” would change the way we
see the extraordinary by enfolding it within the ordinary while also showing
how esoteric knowledge might be equal (continuous) with supposedly more
“accessible” forms of knowledge. Indeed, in her own occult practices, as we
will see, we can sidestep both Mina Bergson’s religionist commitments (and
their assumed hierarchies) as well as any merely decorative and aesthetic in-
terpretation of her work, so as to then see her use of costume, props, posture,
32 Vestiges of a Philosophy
dance, and other “movement arts” all playing a role as equalized forms of
knowledge (what she herself will call an “occult science”).8 In other words,
her methods of mysticism will be used, without religious or supernatural
commitments, as a model of knowing.9
Some might suspect that any method of teaching and learning that eman-
ates from a hermetic society cannot avoid some form of authority, some
crypto-philosophical hierarchization of knowledge. Secret rituals, initiation
rites, privileged access, and scaled grades of membership, do not bode well
as regards any presupposition of an equality of knowledge (as we are enter-
taining here). And turning to the aesthetic dimensions of mystical ritual
would not necessarily provide a “get out of jail” card with respect to author-
itarian epistemology either. As Bruce Lincoln has shown, authority can op-
erate through both language and, more subtly, a whole “theatrical array of
gestures, demeanors, costumes, props, and stage devices.”10 So perhaps the
suggestion that a hierarchy of knowledge is still at work here remains perti-
nent. This all remains to be seen. We will endeavor, nevertheless, to subtract
the “religionist” element of even this aspect of the Golden Dawn, their arcane
infrastructures and obfuscating bureaucracy notwithstanding, to leave only
the raw material of their spiritualist approach in view, seeing their “emic”
worldview, as it were, via an “etic” stance. And, ultimately, we will thereby try
to show how mystical experience can be immanent within ordinary experi-
ence just as mystical thought is immanent within philosophy.
2
Meet the Bergsons
Henri and Mina were the son and daughter of Michal Bergson (1820–1898)
and Katherine Levinson (1838–1928). They were born six years apart, in
1859 and 1865, respectively, and were the couple’s second and fourth born, in
a family with seven offspring. Their five other children were Juliette, Joseph,
Philip, John, and Renée. Their father, a pianist of some repute, was born in
Warsaw; their mother, in Doncaster, England. She was of Anglo-Irish ex-
traction, though both she and Michal were also Jewish. The family was per-
ipatetic, following Michal’s musical career across Europe—Henri was born
while they were based in Paris; Mina, while they were in Geneva. In 1869,
four years after Mina’s birth, the family left Paris for London, where they
stayed thereafter. However, they left Henri behind in Paris (then aged about
ten) to complete his education in the French system, visiting home in Britain
only in the summer holidays. Indeed, while his family became British, Henri
eventually adopted French nationality in 1878. Curiously enough, then, there
is not a drop of French blood in Henri Bergson, supposedly the quintessen-
tially French philosopher of his time, nor in any of his siblings, including
Mina. As Henri Bergson’s biographers conclude, the current Bergson family
is British.1 After their father Michal’s death in 1898, their mother Katherine
retired to Folkestone with her daughter, Renée. She died thirty years later in
1928. Within that period from the 1890s to the 1920s, as we well know, two of
their children brought more than a little celebrity to the family name.
Henri’s story is familiar to many: graduation from the École Normale
Supérieure in 1881; a professor of philosophy at lycees in Angers, Clermont-
Ferrand, and finally Paris all through the 1880s; the publication in 1889 of
his doctoral thesis, Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience (trans-
lated into English as Time and Free Will), followed seven years later by Matter
and Memory in 1896. He held a chair at the Collège de France from 1900
onward and, in 1907, published his most famous work, Creative Evolution,
which has defined Bergsonism ever since as a vitalist philosophy. World
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0004
34 Vestiges of a Philosophy
renown followed—though one that faded rapidly after the Great War—with
the Noble Prize for Literature coming in 1927. Following the German occu-
pation of Paris in 1940, Henri refused any special treatment from the new re-
gime as a celebrated Frenchman rather than as a Jew: despite moving close to
the Catholic faith in the late 1930s, at the end he wished to show his solidarity
with the Jewish people. And, as Jewish, he was required to register at his local
police station, which he did, contracting bronchitis while standing in line.
He died on January 3, 1941, aged eighty-one and was buried at the Cimetière
de Garches just outside Paris—“the most influential of all twentieth-century
French philosophers,” as Jean Gayon describes him.2
Mina’s story is far less known. A talented artist from an early age, she
studied at the Slade School of Art in London, where she became friends
with fellow student, Annie Horniman (who would also later join the Golden
Dawn). In 1887, she met the English occultist Samuel Liddell MacGregor
house, less than a ten-minute walk. They surely saw each other frequently
enough, Mary Greer going so far as to speculate that they most likely met
to discuss “their mutual interest in aspects of the spirit and in psychology.”8
As to the lack of any record of these encounters, we can easily imagine many
reasons why Henri, for one, would have wanted to keep such associations
private, if not completely secret, for the good of his budding philosophical
and academic reputation. Perhaps Mina did, too, for both personal and ideo-
logical reasons. Yet, even if by some miracle they had never met alone and in
person in this period, in what follows we shall show how they met, and con-
tinued to meet, in spirit.
* * *
Meet the Bergsons 37
1. The study of Qabalah, Alchemy, Astrology, the Tarot and the system of
Magic called “Enochian”;
2. Exercises in visualization, meditation, concentration, and other
procedures such as divination;
3. The practice of rituals, either as a group in a properly furnished and
consecrated Temple, or alone, in the privacy of one’s own Temple or
Oratory (which could be almost wholly imaginary, i.e. visualized, with
the irreducible minimum of magical paraphernalia, such as a wand and
a sword).9
Of course, this para-academic training, with its own entry requirements and
graduating degrees, operated with a secret knowledge, a kind of gnosticism
rather than publicly accessible research databases and outputs. This secrecy
can doubtlessly be interpreted in terms of power, then, and through that, in-
equality. With access to higher, privileged grades of knowledge (gnosis) only
coming through bizarre forms of ritual initiation (the rules of which were
kept confidential) and a strict hierarchy of command maintained within the
Order, from Zelator through to the various grades of Adept, it is easy to inter-
pret its clandestine processes as a cover for various forms of obfuscation and
control. Such tactics are familiar to anyone acquainted with modern-day cult
movements, or at least their representation in mainstream media.11
However, even if one were to ignore the clear disanalogies between occult
groups like the Golden Dawn and present-day prejudices about modern cult
movements and their leaders, we are left with two other ponderable issues.12
First, that knowledge, and access to knowledge, has always been connected to
power (who would be so naïve to think otherwise?), and, though one might
grant this fact while still maintaining that the difference of degree involved
made these Hermetic societies that much more pernicious, it was nonethe-
less the Golden Dawn that actually practiced real equality in its admissions
policy and paths to “promotion.” Furthermore, a second thought concerns
the question of secrecy directly. It is perfectly consistent that a group dedi-
cated to self-improvement through education of the self, self-illumination in
other words (“know thyself ”), should employ methods involving first-person
experience, privileged access to subjective states (and therewith states of the
subject), and a knowledge that was less ineffable or incommunicable than
bodily and performative (it had to be physically practiced to be achieved).
That a prioritization of interiority, the private, and the personal informed its
mission and structure should come as little surprise. Indeed, Pasi connects
the primacy of embodiment in the rituals of the Golden Dawn positively to
the question of power and equality:
It could be argued that in occult groups such as the Golden Dawn, an at-
tention for the body was already intrinsic to the kind of ritual work that
was being practiced. Unlike mainstream freemasonry, in this case both
men and women participated in the rituals. It is certainly no coincidence
that several members of the Order were theater actors by profession,
including one of the most prominent women among its membership,
Florence Farr.13
Meet the Bergsons 39
the public concept of a “New Woman” began to emerge. She could hold a
job or have a vocation. She loved whom and where she chose. Although
she continued to hold chastity as an ideal, she now considered the standard
equally applicable to men.14
For the status quo, this was often regarded as a dangerous development:
The Golden Dawn’s heyday was in the 1890s. The first decade of the new
century would belong more to Mina’s brother, of course, especially fol-
lowing the publication of Creative Evolution in 1907. Yet Mina Bergson
still had an imposing presence, and not only on account of her celebrated
performances. The ideas embedded in these performances are not just “ar-
tistic in the extreme” (as we heard) but extremely thought-provoking as well.
Notwithstanding ideas of, at best, “proximal authority” or, at worst, a sup-
posed female “mind passivity” within occult Victorian circles, her spiritualist
ideas and practices developed within the Golden Dawn remain fascinating
on their own merits and worthy of comparison with other philosophies of
the time.16 That is not our only motive for examining them here, however.
Though any influence she might have had on Henri’s work (or he on hers)
40 Vestiges of a Philosophy
Here, she has articulated almost verbatim a key tenet of the “new spiritu-
alism” that had come to the fore in French philosophical circles near the start
of the belle époque. Meanwhile, we know that Henri Bergson was always in-
terested in philosophical spiritualism, psychical research (though somewhat
furtively for the most part) and, latterly, religious mysticism.18 Yet the sources
for some of his own esoteric ideas remain largely uncharted, especially those
appearing in the first and third chapters of Matter and Memory. Given that
a nonstandard philosophy can be found in Mina Bergson’s writings and
mystical practices, this should give us pause. In her theorization of these
performances, we go beyond aesthetics to find her use of costume, color,
voice, movement, and forms of dance all playing a role as kinds of occult
science, equal to any science of matter. Moreover, we will unearth ideas con-
cerning time, process, and an “astral plane” that bear more than just a passing
resemblance to one of Henri Bergson’s most challenging concepts—that of
the Virtual—which is his own, processual version of a “universal substance”
that generates matter and spirit.
This brings me to another point of convergence, that around the Golden
Dawn’s feminist principles, Mina Bergson’s “feminist ritual performance,”
and their analogue in what might be called “Bergsonian feminism.” In the
chapter of her book The Philosophical Imaginary entitled “Long Hair, Short
Ideas,” Michele Le Doeuff comments on a facet of the cult of (Henri) Bergson
in the 1900s that struck many—its large female membership:
We still smile at the court of women who flocked round Bergson, but we
systematically forget to wonder whether this court was not in fact satisfying
(or inspired by) Bergson’s own desire. The fact that this court was composed
of women who were following the Collège de France lectures in an amateur
Meet the Bergsons 41
The symmetry of women gaining entry to the academy, either through the
public system of the Collège de France or the para-academy of the Golden
Dawn (or, in some cases perhaps, both), reveals a parallel inventiveness
needed by women in pursuit of knowledge at that time. Yet it also exposes
a larger social issue. As Emily Herring asks in an essay on Henri Bergson’s
celebrity, “why, when Bergson was popular, was he so popular, and espe-
cially with women?”20 Despite being given “derogatory nicknames such
as caillettes” (a small bird signifying a “frivolous babbling woman”), or
“snobinettes,” as well as a simple prejudice that his female audience were “ig-
norant socialites more interested in being seen at a fashionable event than in
learning about philosophy,” Herring argues that there may have been some-
thing significant happening in this adulation.21 On the one hand, it might
have been that Henri Bergsonʼs philosophy, being seen as “grounded in an
unreliable and obscure mysticism that was “feminine” in nature,” attracted
many followers despite, or even on account of, this putative aspect.22 This as-
cription was undoubtedly offered at the time as a slur, of course, hitting two
targets at once (mysticism and presumptuous women). On the other hand,
however, there may have been an intrinsic value to this association between
Henri Bergson’s philosophy and feminism—as Herring explains:
In 1913, the American author and feminist Marian Cox (born Mabel
Marian Metcalfe) published the article “Bergsonʼs Message to Feminism.”
She argued that humanityʼs quest for a better understanding of the
Universe, both scientific and theological, had so far been entirely based
on male, materialistically driven methods. Instinct and intuition, on the
other hand, were in tune with the creativity of life and with the female
mind. By placing instinct and intuition at the centre of his philosophical
method, Bergsonʼs outlook was therefore “an exposition and a plea for
this female-method in the future quest of knowledge.” Ultimately, said
Cox, Bergsonʼs philosophy would aid the liberation of women. Therefore,
at a time when the idea that Bergsonism was inherently feminine was
being used to diminish his authority as a philosopher, Cox argued that it
was because Bergsonʼs philosophy was feminine in nature that it should
be taken seriously.
42 Vestiges of a Philosophy
Certainly, this connection between Henri Bergson and the feminine can be
unpacked further in a number of ways. On the question of mysticism, Marie
Cariou was writing about Henri Bergson and mysticism in the 1970s in this
very context: in the section titled “La Féminité” of her book Bergson and le
fait mystique, she states how “the woman’s gaze, we are told, is the prototype
of the mystical gaze” (“Le regard de la femme, nous dit-on, est la prototype
du regard mystique”).23 Though, of course, we must be alert to the presump-
tion of a particular feminine essence supposedly found in mysticism (as if
mysticism, alongside the feminine, were both givens that did not need to be
historically reclaimed from patriarchal meanings and structures—as, for in-
stance, Grace Jantzen attempted in her work),24 Cariou’s intervention reveals
another curiosity in the history of Henri Bergson’s philosophical legacy: its
postwar domination by Francophone women. This will be hard to hear for
some within the Anglophone reception of Bergson who, for various reasons
(I’ll say it—mostly ignorance), place the survival of Bergson’s philosophy
entirely at the feet of Gilles Deleuze and his 1966 book, Le Bergsonisme.25
Yet the fact remains that the major commentators on Henri Bergson all
through the 1950s, 1960s, and 1970s in France were mostly women: it was
the works of Rose-Marie Mossé-Bastide, Madeleine Barthelemy-Madaule,
Angèle Kremer-Marietti, Jeanne Delhomme, and Marie Cariou that kept the
Bergson flame burning within the French academy for nearly forty years.26
In the face of a Deleuzian consensus that has served as a gatekeeper to inter-
pretations of Henri Bergson for many years now, their names and, in some
cases, superior readings have all but been erased from the philosophical re-
cord, even in France. Small gesture though it is, we acknowledge their in-
valuable work here, for that record. In addition, the connections formed in
this book between contemporary female philosophers of matter and Mina
Bergson’s spiritual practices and theories will also, we hope, be regarded as
part of a historical revisioning of Bergsonism that works in a similarly un-
fashionable “fashion.”
10° =1° Ipsissimus Covariant (Neophyte)
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0005
44 Vestiges of a Philosophy
to suggest that there is a large but still limited number of forms of memory
is to think of memory incorrectly in terms of “individual recollections” that
are “fixed, static, and something ready-made (tout fait).”5 Instead, for Henri
Bergson “memory is a single dynamic process in and through which the past
that is preserved in itself can be manifested in an infinite number of different
ways.”6 As Henri Bergson writes in his 1904 course on the history of theories
of memory, memory “is not a thing; it is progress; it is a movement.”7 The
puzzle for him, therefore, was why this movement gets interrupted—why do
we forget? Given the survival of the past through continuous movement, as
in a speech act that might last a lifetime, the question becomes, why do we
suffer any amnesia at all, why are we not all “hypermnesic”? The answer for
Henri Bergson will also turn to the brain, but not as a mysterious organ of
storage but one of selection, of exclusion. Turned toward life, the living must
focus their attention on the practicalities of survival, on the future, leaving
their past “elsewhere,” so to speak, on the periphery of vision.8 This is why
the “mysterious apparition,” the “ghost” of memory, only appears as such to
those who do not experience the relevant continuity (as, of course, most of
us are physiologically and cerebrally conditioned to do). Only some individ-
uals have such a “weakness” in their futural, “forward” vision that it allows
them to look backward as much as forward, to reverse the usual orientation
of human experience. In this respect, it is significant that what struck Jean-
Paul Sartre about Henri Bergson’s theory of memory images was its supposed
magical quality: they possessed “tendencies and powers as magical as the
powers of attraction that Hume conferred on images.” Yet, as we will explain
later (in the “Theoricus Covariant”), this “magical” quality exists in the eye
of each beholder, in a selective in/attention. Hence, what Sartre sees as the
magical “force” belonging to memory that allows memory to “insert itself ”
mysteriously within present perception can also be seen, on another level,
as a kind of continuity or covariance that has not been heeded.9 The magic
is natural, perhaps even material, but operating at a level such that some can
only see it hyperbolically as preternatural (and even call “spiritual”).
Let us stay with the issue of storage, though, and leave selection aside
for now. Henri Bergson’s key criticism of the theories of memory current
in his era was that they thought that memory was a set of images stored
in the brain. Today, we talk instead of “engrams” (from the Ancient Greek
γράμμα, grámma, a “written character, letter, that which is drawn”), which
are traces or pathways left from repeated cerebral activity—furrows for long-
term memories. The brain as internal notepad. One of the earliest examples
10° = 1° Ipsissimus Covariant (Neophyte) 45
This “special structure” now carries the burden of the enigma of memory.
Yet the problems for storage theories are only beginning. What traces
also cannot do is convey how memory feels, or as ter Schure puts it, the
46 Vestiges of a Philosophy
“historicity of a memory, its historical feel that causes it to stand out dis-
tinct from the present.”15 Moreover, not only are impressions and traces
unfaithful to the phenomenology of memory (which, in any case, could
be discredited by self-styled eliminativists who regard qualia or “feels”
like these as just so much deluded folk psychology), storage theories
equally call into question the veridicality of memory. As Aristotle also
asked: why should the perception of a trace be taken as a memory of some-
thing else rather than what it is—a perception? However, as ter Schure
himself concludes, to escape this conundrum, we need to turn to Henri
Bergson: his “radical answer” is found in his ultra-realism, the fact that
“we know a memory from a perception because memory remains attached
to the past by its deepest roots.”16
Whereas for some philosophers, “realism” toward the past simply entails
the belief that the past did once exist (that it was indeed once present), Henri
Bergson’s ultra-realism is the view that the past still exists. Opposed to both
these positions is that of the “anti-realist,” who would say that the past need
not have existed, even as a previous present. It is perfectly logical to think
of the past as an unreal fiction that is constantly constructed retrospectively
within the present (which continually regenerates itself). This version of
“now” really is special, and multiple. Bertrand Russell is probably the most
renowned representative of such an extreme presentism toward the past, at
least from the logical point of view:
In the face of such powerful logic, all is not lost for pastists, however. The
Bergsonian response to the idea of an ever-renewed now turns on its already
narrow, and question-begging, conception of the present. Henri Bergson’s
ultra-realism toward the past is based on his temporal holism: it is the con-
tinuity or indivisibility of the past in the present that makes memory “real.”
Indivisibility means that the present is always already partly “in” (what we
call) “the past.”18 Hence, what Henri Bergson eventually calls “pure memory”
is not a mental duplicate referring to the historical past (which can never
genuinely prove its credentials as past), but rather the past itself as it persists
in the present. Pure memory should not be confused with recollection, which
always mixes memory images with present perceptions, which thereby also
form corruptions and other inaccuracies in our faculty of recall. Whereas a
recollection actualizes the past in an image, pure memory is this past. Indeed,
any form of recollected memory, as habit, disposition, a picture, or whatever
else, is simply one or other distortion of this purity of memory, which is, in
truth, merely the reality of the past itself. The only way to prove the past is to
show that it never left; or as Matter and Memory says, “the truth is that we
shall never reach the past unless we frankly place ourselves within it.”19
Admittedly, this stance is no less question-begging than that of an eternal
Now, given that it assumes a uniform immanence of the past within the pre-
sent, or rather, a shared extension of a present that continues into a so-called
past. And yet we might recall the points made earlier about qualia, as well as
the immanent experience of durée, “within the phenomenon”: the fact is that
different experiences of time qua durée are possible. This is not a relativism
but an immanentism: different temporal experiences, or levels of attention,
are equally real. It may well be that no one level of the distended present-
past is shared by all; that Bertrand Russell, for instance, truly experiences
(at times) an extremely narrow breadth of duration, though it may border
on what is deemed “pathological” among humans (the parallels between
philosophers and the insane need no rehearsal here). Naturally, as a Platonist
of sorts, Russell would regard the logic of his argument as sui generis (having
nothing to do with experiences of time), whereas, as empiricists, we would
relate it to worldly matters—indeed, his logic simply is one kind or level of
temporal experience. In the end, we should heed the advice of Ian Hacking,
who cautions us against thinking that any opposition between a presentist,
physicalist approach to memory (what he calls “memory as anatomy”) and
a more Proustian, phenomenological approach (“memory as narrative”) is
48 Vestiges of a Philosophy
between the plane of action—the plane in which our body has condensed
its past into motor habits—and the plane of pure memory, where our mind
retains in all its details the picture of our past life [“le tableau de notre vie
écoulée”], we believe that we can discover thousands of different planes of
consciousness, a thousand integral and yet diverse repetitions of the whole
of the experience through which we have lived.27
Not one, two, or ten types, but thousands: thousands of levels or planes of
memory. Memories from planes closer to the pole of action straddle all the
different ways that a past can be enacted or embodied rather than simply
“represented.” As Stephen Kern puts it, “for Bergson every movement leaves
50 Vestiges of a Philosophy
traces that continue to affect all subsequent physical or mental processes. The
past collects in the fibers of the body as it does in the mind and determines
the way we walk and dance as well as the way we think.”28 Pure memories
are not individuated pictures (Bergson’s reference to “le tableau de notre vie
écoulée” notwithstanding): they are more like embryos that “contain” the past
as a “biological process” in waiting.29 And even recollections that represent
(or “think”) that past do not picture it either: “to picture is not to remember,”
according to Bergson.30 Recollection is not a static imaging, for every trace,
be it localized or widely distributed, is a movement, the dynamic record of
previous selections.31
Accordingly, this is not a quantitative multiplicity where memories differ
only in an arithmetical scale of “rhythm,” “complication,” or “contraction,”
say, or of being more of less visually clear, or whatever else. It is a continuity
of qualified variations that, of course, includes ideas of rhythm and contrac-
tion, but that are also as different from each other as a picture, a pain, a dance,
a taste, a hallucination, or the passage of grief can be from each other. Henri
Bergson is adamant that each plane is completely different in nature from the
next: to put all memories on one plane would be to differentiate them only by
“degree of complication” or “composition.” The cone is a “solid” volume, as
Bergson puts it in his lecture course on memory from 1904, and not simply
a flat “surface.”32 And yet these qualitative differences are still in continuity
because each plane is also the manifestation (in different modes) of the same
entire past. Each plane is a different way in which the same surviving past—
”tout de la mémoire”—reappears.33
A B
A' B'
A'' B''
And yet, recalling Ian Hacking’s warning not to see too great a divide between
the anatomical and narrative approaches to memory, it is also noteworthy
how “trace” can play a role in much more personal accounts of the past. In
Family Secrets: Acts of Memory and Imagination, Annette Kuhn writes that
“the past is gone forever. We cannot return to it, nor can we reclaim it now as
52 Vestiges of a Philosophy
it was. But that does not mean it is lost to us.” In fact, for Kuhn the survival of
the past comes only through its markers, its traces:
The past is like the scene of a crime: if the deed itself is irrecoverable, its
traces may still remain. From these traces, markers that point towards a
past presence, to something that has happened in this place, a (re)construc-
tion, if not a simulacrum, of the event can be pieced together. Memory work
has a great deal in common with forms of inquiry which—like detective
work and archaeology, say—involve working backwards—searching for
clues, deciphering signs and traces, making deductions, patching together
reconstructions out of fragments of evidence.36
* * *
The radical anti-realist—like Russell—places much more store on imag-
ination as the creative agent in the process of remembering, present per-
ception continually imaging a fictional wake trailing behind it. Even for
less outlandish accounts, though, scientific evidence seems to support the
view that “memory and imagination are profoundly intertwined.”38 As
Kourken Michaelian, asks: “. . . the question for the theory of remembering
becomes: What distinguishes episodic remembering from episodic imag-
ining?”39 Children, for example, are highly prone to embellishing their mem-
ories of an event with more detail and better organization than was ever
10° = 1° Ipsissimus Covariant (Neophyte) 53
contained within the original experience. As McNamara puts it, “the child’s
memory is creative. Each act of remembering is, for better or worse, a cre-
ative achievement.”40 Not only children participate in this fancy, however,
and there is a huge literature dealing with “memory distortion” and “crea-
tive remembering” for all ages, young and old, and all states of mind, healthy
and unhealthy. Medical cases of memory loss provide many examples of
false memory, certain kinds of patient often filling in the gaps with fantastic
or impossible accounts (of prior lives, how they arrived into hospital, what
their current condition is, what the world beyond the hospital is like, and so
on). These accounts are known as “confabulations.” Yet these patients are not
intentionally lying. McNamara describes the real tragedy of their situation
thus: they believe they are reporting “true memories and one gets the feeling
when witnessing an episode of confabulation that one is present at the birth
of new memories.”41
It is notable that such creative remembering poses a challenge for
causal accounts of memory involving storage and localization (traces,
markers, engrams, etc.) in as much as a major virtue of the causal ac-
count is that the true memory is supposed to be real precisely because it
was caused by real events. If memories are now seen as fundamentally
“intertwined” with imagination, even in nonpathological cases, what price
now their basis in real causation by real events? “Simulationist” accounts,
such as Kourken Michaelian’s, renege on the need for a causal trace but
also risk disconnection with any “representational content” (real events)
as a result.42
Furthermore, what would follow were we to raise the stakes, and scale,
of such (con)fabulations even higher, by returning to both the spiritualist
and ultra-realist approach to memory and the past? Indeed, from the her-
metic perspective, the opposition between memory and imagination is a
false one. For practitioners within the Golden Dawn, for instance, imagi-
nation is not a faculty of the unreal, of the nonexistent—it has its own re-
ality. As Tanya Luhrmann writes, the doctrine of the Golden Dawn explicitly
stated that “imagination was a reality and that it could affect the material
world. The different ‘plane’ that these magical writers present is not de-
fined by different rules—that conception emerges somewhat later—but is
rather composed of different materials, one apparently unsubstantial, the
other substantive, but both ultimately interdependent.”43 Indeed, one of the
Golden Dawn’s teaching texts, or “Flying Rolls” (No. V, “Some Thoughts on
the Imagination”), resolutely states:
54 Vestiges of a Philosophy
is called into being by the soul in its state of higher consciousness, the
things perceived in this state of consciousness are spiritual facts, and spir-
itual beings, to which the senses have no access, and—since this condition
of the soul is caused by meditating upon symbols, or “imaginations”—the
sphere to which this condition of higher consciousness belongs may be
termed the imaginative world, and the knowledge relating to it, imaginative
knowledge.50
about identity” (and so instead turns to William James for this part of his
enquiry).54 Yet he does Henri Bergson a disservice on this front. Actually, at
the very outset of Matter and Memory’s selectionist approach, it is not only
the brain that is an instrument of selection (rather than localization), but my
own identity, too, is intertwined with the selection among images. Among
“this aggregate of images which I call the universe,” there is one of them, Henri
Bergson says, “which is distinct from all the others, in that I do not know
it only from without by perceptions, but from within by affections: it is my
body.”55 One image stands out, is selected, through affect—the feeling of
being embodied in the first person, as “my body.”
It is worth lingering over this misreading, or omission, because it offers
us a clear example of what Henri Bergson means by “continuous heter-
ogeneity.” His selectionist approach does not say that the self in irredeem-
ably fragmented or fractured, but rather that it is multiple and unitary at
the same time (this is also a major tenet of his 1903 essay, “Introduction to
Metaphysics”). There is a continuity, but it is heterogeneous, even in oneself.
Now, at one point in his study, McNamara puzzles over a “whole series” of
autobiographical memory images: as someone who grew up in a family, went
to school, met friends and developed these friendships, married, had chil-
dren, parented those children, and so on. He then answers the subsequent
question “Who am I?” as follows: “you are many.”56 In this dialectic of the one
and many, McNamara also revisits a debate whose modern form was shaped
by Joseph Butler’s criticism of John Locke’s theory of the self. When Locke
based personal identity on memory (“the same thinking thing, in different
times and places”), Butler pointed out that memory is an inherently personal
selection. As such, memory presupposes personal identity and so cannot rest
upon it.57 In McNamara’s updated version: “memory, therefore, presents to us
a paradox”: it can “constitute the basis for personal identity, since it preserves
a record of the story of our lives,” yet it also “imaginatively constructs mul-
tiple identities.”58 Continuity and discontinuity. One self and many selves.
However, Bergsonian duration also allows for the same conjunction, the self
as one and many, or a heterogeneous continuity of many selves, and indeed of
many pasts. In fact, Henri Bergson devoted a good amount of his 1910/1911
course at the Collège de France to Morton Prince’s pioneering psycholog-
ical study of what we nowadays call “Dissociative Identity Disorder” (or pre-
viously, “multiple personality syndrome”). Prince’s celebrated case of Sally
Beauchamp particularly interested Henri Bergson, and he even likened the
phenomenon of multiple personality to a series of “possessions.”59 Despite
10° = 1° Ipsissimus Covariant (Neophyte) 57
McNamara’s claim to the contrary, Henri Bergson does have a lot to say about
identity, or at least its many varieties.
Integrated into Henri Bergson’s own metaphysics of different levels of du-
ration, one can only say that the self is one and many “at the same time,” if
this “sameness” is understood as covariance or invariance rather than simul-
taneity (which would be an abstract spatial rendering). As Leonard Lawlor
writes,
Even when compared to her brother’s fickle celebrity, the ascent and de-
scent of Mina’s star was rapid. Other than a few cursory entries in biog-
raphies of Henri Bergson, Mina Bergson’s name mostly survives through
histories of the Golden Dawn and other occult societies. And apart from
those histories, there are few references to her in contemporary culture.1
Moreover, if we are to gain an impression of what Mina Bergson believed
about spiritualism and the occult, she did not leave us much to go on.
The available texts laying out her methods and ideas amount to four core
documents (currently, at least): her 1926 preface to the second edition
of Samuel Mathers’s Kabbalah Unveiled (originally published 1898) and
three teaching texts (or “Flying Rolls”): “No.21, Know Thyself ”; “No.23,
Tattwa Visions”; and “No.36, Of Skrying and Travelling in the Spirit-
Vision.”2 Alongside these writings, and any historical documentation of
her and Samuel’s activities in Paris, we do, however, also have all of the rit-
ualistic practices and paraphernalia from the Golden Dawn and Alpha et
Omega grimoires (handbooks on magical practices): the copious phrases,
symbols, languages, props, costumes, sets, mathematic equations, colors,
choreographies, and stagings that were part of any member’s initiation
and ongoing training as they moved from neophyte through the higher
grades within the Order.
Naturally, such a profusion of rituality brings with it a hierarchy of apti-
tude (Neophyte, Practicus, Adeptus Major, etc.) as well as hermeticity—but
as we said, this does not necessarily imply inequalities within institutional
power so much as advancements in aptitude. Henrik Bogdan describes its
structures as follows:
The initiatory system of the Golden Dawn is based on the kabbalistic Tree
of Life. Each degree is attributed to a particular sefira, starting with the de-
gree of Zelator which is attributed to Malkuth, and ending with Ipsissimus
which in its turn is attributed to Kether. The degree of Neophyte is a prelim-
inary degree and is considered to take place below Malkuth. The candidate
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0006
Hyper-Ritual 59
thus symbolically ascends the Tree of Life through the rituals of initiation.
At the initiations, he or she is instructed in the particular symbolism of the
sefira that the degree is attributed to, as well as in the symbolism of the paths
leading to the said sefira.3
Perhaps this book has been written because a number of young men and
women, you and I among the number, met nearly forty years ago in London
and in Paris to discuss mystical philosophy. You with your beauty and
your learning and your mysterious gifts were held by all in affection, and
though, when the first draft of this dedication was written, I had not seen
you for more than thirty years, nor knew where you were nor what you
were doing, and though much had happened since we copied the Jewish
Schemahamphorasch [“the explicit name”] with its seventy-two Names
of God in Hebrew characters, it was plain that I must dedicate my book
to you.8
60 Vestiges of a Philosophy
In 1899 Mina and the order caused something of a sensation in Paris when
they staged a theatrical performance at La Bodinière Theatre, called the
Rite of Isis. Jules Bois was on stage to explain the ancient cult to the fashion-
able audience. The Paris correspondent of the Sunday Chronicle reported
that Mina achieved a great success. Rivalling her brother in popularity at
least for the moment, she “completely won their sympathy by her graceful
attitude and dignified manner. More than that, she is very handsome, she
has a beautiful oval face with large black, mysterious eyes and beauty always
tells in Paris.” In gratitude for the performance the ladies offered bouquets
of flowers and the gentlemen threw wheat on the altar.11
Such an engaged spiritualist might well remind us of the “heroes” and active
models that Henri Bergson commended in his 1932 book, The Two Sources
of Morality and Religion, as the great mystics within the Christian tradi-
tion.12 Mina Bergson herself wrote that the mystic “should not retire from
the world,” that it is better to live among others and “influence them by our
example.”13 In her preface to Kabbalah Unveiled, she adds that mysticism “is
a system eminently suited to Western occultism, which a man can follow
Hyper-Ritual 61
while living the ordinary life of the world, given that this is understood in its
highest sense.” So much for the “hermetic,” the “enclosed.” Here, the active
mystic meets the ordinary human.
The need to restrain oneself from the usual stereotypes of mysticism, espe-
cially egocentricity and monomania, are also uppermost in Mina Bergson’s
descriptions. In Flying Roll No.21, “Know Thyself,” she writes
There is too much tendency to wish all to follow the Ideal of one—we are
apt to forget that the Ideal of each will lead to the same Truth. We can help
each other better, then, by helping each to rise according to his own ideas,
rather than, as we often unwisely do, in advising him to rise to what is best
in ourselves only. That error of wishing to make another as ourselves is an-
other and a very hurtful form of most subtle egotism.14
We will assume for the moment that we know nothing of theories of matter
and theories of spirit, nothing of the discussions as to the reality or ideality
of the external world. Here I am in the presence of images, in the vaguest
sense of the word, images perceived when my senses are opened to them,
unperceived when they are closed.16
propose that the two “are derived from a wider and higher form of existence”
and that it must have been the one process that “cut out matter and the in-
tellect, at the same time, from a stuff [étoffe] that contained both.”17 Mina
Bergson’s “universal substance” again, or perhaps what we will see her later
call the “eternal attraction between ideas and matter”: matter and ideas (or
spirit) as “poles” within one spectra(l), continuous entity, which she then
names “the secret of life.”18 Both of Henri’s texts were written while Mina
was in Paris, obviously, but it is especially Matter and Memory that stands
out in this secret correlation—a book that has been variously described as his
most “learned,” “rich,” “brilliant,” and “difficult” works.19 This is the book he
published in that glorious decade of the 1890s, when Mina and Samuel, the
“neo-pagan power couple,” held court to great acclaim.
4
“O My Bergson, You Are a Magician”
The era’s fascination with what Alex Owen in The Place of Enchantment
calls, “a new esoteric spirituality” meant that, for some, the more mystical
aspects of Bergson’s thought were adopted and integrated into the outlooks
of movements like Theosophy and the Order of the Golden Dawn. This
connection, though unconfirmed by the philosopher, was for its disci-
ples given credence by his acceptance of the presidency for the Society for
Psychical Research (1913) and, furthermore, by public knowledge that he
was the brother of leading occultist Moina Mathers (née Mina Bergson).1
Green then proposes that Mina Bergson herself must have felt sufficiently
certain that her brother’s ideas were in harmony with her own mystical beliefs
to mention, again, how “material science would appear to be spiritualising it-
self ” in her preface to The Kabbalah Unveiled. This is doubtless a crucial state-
ment by Mina Bergson, of course. In point of fact, however, she did not name
her brother in this connection at all, but rather the distinguished English
physicist, and part-time psychical researcher, Sir Oliver Lodge (a figure Henri
Bergson also admired, incidentally, and who had read the philosopher’s
work).2 Indeed, Alex Owen’s 2004 book, subtitled British Occultism and the
Culture of the Modern, tempers this enthusiasm for the syncretic, especially
on Henri Bergson’s own part, by noting that when Yeats visited Mina Bergson
in Paris in 1894, he was “aware that MacGregor Mathers was irritated by his
inability to impress his brother-in-law with his magic.” Owen goes on to add
that “there is no indication that Bergson showed any interest in magic, but he
was nonetheless involved with psychical research and deeply concerned with
matters relating to spirit and consciousness.”
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0007
64 Vestiges of a Philosophy
Owen’s caution here raises an allied question: what was Henri Bergson’s
view of traditional religion? Though it has been argued elsewhere that Henri
Bergson was a spiritualist even “from the start” of his philosophical career,
and that the problem of God was central to all of his work, such interpret-
ations of his ideas are outliers, to say the least.3 As Vladimir Jankélévitch
states in an essay on “Bergson and Judaism,” the “pluralist immanentism of
Matter and Memory and Creative Evolution doesn’t lend itself well to the idea
of a monotheistic transcendence.” Indeed, it is difficult to see how a doctrine
that is, as Jankélévitch says, “temporalist, continuationist, immanentist, and
on top of all that pluralist [could] have anything in common with Hebrew
monotheism.”4 All the same, Jankélévitch will also say that,
put it, provides a similar covariant.7 For Kabbalists, then, it is clear that
one must retrace the emanations in order to progress through the sefira. As
Grogin notes,
the Bergsonian and Kabbalistic views of man, so popular in the late nine-
teenth century, proceed from the same assumptions: that man lives a highly
routinized, mechanical life, mundanely bound by the rhythms of his body
and by habits of reaction and perception. He is a man who blindly seeks
pleasure and avoids pain, and it is only the rare man who, through the
proper instruction, can overcome this, break the outer crust of habit and
enter into a higher spiritual awareness.8
. . . the ceremonies of the order were not acts of worship; their focus was the
celebrant. It was far from obvious, in the performance of the Qabbalistic
Cross, whether the kingdom, the power, and the glory belonged to God or
66 Vestiges of a Philosophy
were being promised to the human carrying out the ritual; this ambiguity
no doubt made it acceptable to people with a wide range of beliefs.10
Such avowed heterodoxy can be seen in the approach of Mina’s brother, too.
Recalling Henri Bergson’s adage that one can only understand “what one can
in some measure reinvent,” we must also note that both brother and sister
were lapsed or secularized Jews, with each eventually inventing his or her own
means to engage with the most abstract questions of existence. Significantly,
Henri Bergson’s definition of the “amateur” as opposed to the professional in
philosophy completely upends our usual understanding: it is the former who
approaches problems entirely using the ready-made techniques and termi-
nology set by others, by the “tradition”; the professional approach is instead
to invent one’s own route through the problem.13 In place of doctrinal belief,
we have an immanent, almost artistic practice.
Contrary to Yeats’s account, moreover, we know that Henri Bergson was
actually interested in magic, at least as a field for academic study, and this
concern culminated in the publication of The Two Sources in 1932. Hence, it
should not be so surprising to Owen, as it seems to be, that “in a striking par-
allel with occult thought, he argued that matter and spirit are not opposites
but part of a whole.”14 Our book’s primary concern is precisely with this
striking parallel. Owen even notes how the great historian of mystic thought,
Evelyn Underhill, attended Henri Bergson’s London lectures of 1913 in the
wake of her own recent success with the book Mysticism and reported back
“O My Bergson, You Are a Magician” 67
that she was “drunk with Bergson.”15 Significantly, much of the historical re-
search underpinning Henri Bergson’s own theories in The Two Sources did
in fact come from her work. In a note in The Two Sources, he acknowledges a
mutual influence with Underhill: “similar ideas will be found in the remark-
able works of Evelyn Underhill. . . . The latter author connects certain of her
views with those we expressed in L’Evolution Creatrice, and which we have
taken up again, to carry them further, in the present chapter.”16
I said “significantly” earlier because, for a number of years in the mid-
1900s, Evelyn Underhill was also a member of the Golden Dawn. Indeed,
Underhill even wrote “a defence of magic” in 1907.17 Now, I opened this sec-
tion with an irreverent use of William James’s famous note to Henri Bergson,
dispatched after he had first read Creative Evolution, “O my Bergson, you are a
magician and your book is a marvel.”18 Taken literally (other than as fawning
praise or a lazy slur), Henri Bergson was no magician to be sure, but he was
philosophically interested in the topic. He was clearly aware of mediumship
where “the magician sometimes works through the medium of spirits” and
the notion of occult forces.19 That a magician might even believe she is able
to influence events and material objects at a distance is described in The Two
Sources as “a logic of the body, an extension of desire, which comes into play
long before intelligence has found a conceptual form for it.”20 Rage against an
absent enemy, for instance, can so magically transform the world as to make
our gestures of attack (pouncing, throttling) bring the image of our opponent
within our grasp.21 Expressed bodily, it is a “logic”; taken conceptually, it is a
force, though one with many names:
Words such as mana, wakonda, etc., express this force, and at the same time
the prestige surrounding it. You will not find the same precise meaning for
all of them, if you are looking for precise meanings, but they all correspond
to the same vague idea. They express that which causes things to lend them-
selves to the operations of magic. As to these operations themselves, we
have just determined their nature. They begin the act which man cannot
finish. They go through the motions which alone could not produce the
desired effect, but which will achieve it, if the man concerned knows how to
prevail upon the goodwill of things.22
declares that magical thinking is not the preserve of the so-called primitive
mind or the magician, but that “magic is then innate in man.” Indeed, it is in
all men and women. He continues:
Ahead of his time, Henri Bergson has no truck here with the idea of a teleo-
logical progress from “primitive” mentality toward the modern rational (usu-
ally Western) mind. He offers an evolutionary view, without a doubt, but he
does not confer moral or intellectual value on its later “stages” such that the
modern psyche leaves the earlier ones behind in its inevitable advance. Each
phase lives on in all minds.
Henri Bergson’s own discussion of “fabulation” in The Two Sources is it-
self an examination of one such natural tendency toward magical thinking,
namely our inclination to anthropomorphize certain physical processes as
“Events.” Some processes are deemed to possess intent, especially ones with
deadly effects (natural and man-made disasters). An earthquake, say, seems
to be deliberately trying to kill me. It is as if there was some malign purpose
from the outset: hence, the disparate processes (which is “all” an earthquake
actually is—a set of natural processes) are combined into one Event, the
“Earthquake,” with its own intentionality. The reason we fabulate the event
like this is in order to give ourselves the possibility, overwhelmed as we are, to
thwart the will of this larger being: though we may appear physically doomed,
if it has an intent, then we may be able to outwit it.24 This is the peculiar kind
of innate magical thinking, that is, for Henri Bergson, latent within each of
us. As a tendency, it “bides its time” and emerges only in extremis, with pro-
cesses involving death or serious injury in accidents or disasters. So basic is it
that it would be wrong to think of fabulation as “only” a form of imagination,
according to Henri Bergson, still less a form of play, artistry, simulation, or
pretense: it is far more elementary than each of these and lies not only at their
source but also at the source of much religious belief—animatism, animism,
polytheism, and so on. If imagination is only imaginary for Henri Bergson,
then it seems that fabulation is, at least at some level, more than imaginary.
Moreover—and this point will become ever more crucial in what follows—
given that in Creative Evolution Henri Bergson attributes consciousness and
“O My Bergson, You Are a Magician” 69
memory to life at all levels of the real, and even to matter (understood as a
relatively distended duration), it is not a little ironic that the magical fabu-
lation of life and mind within physical processes is not actually philosophi-
cally baseless for him.25 Such fabulations are simply operating at the wrong
scale, one where human intervention deludes itself as to its own power over
matter. Our “magical” beliefs are never thrown away by the so-called modern
mind, nor should they be. Matter itself is “magical,” so to speak (a panpsy-
chism runs through Bergson, as we will soon see), but it would be wrong to
think that it must respond to our interventions. Such an illusion is simply
thought, logic, or desire, projecting itself at what is an inappropriate level for
it. Counterfactually, then, we might say that magical thinking might be right
to behave as if ritual, incantation, or performance could conquer space, time,
and the standard laws of physics and biology, were it not for the case that:
Myers, by the way). In fact, beyond this discussion of magic, his ongoing en-
gagement in psychical research has already been noted, even though it was
not always made public.28 Long before this Presidential Address, his interest
in the paranormal was clear, as Howard Caygill has discussed in his essay
“Hyperaesthesia and the Virtual.” This essay deals with an early report by
Henri Bergson, published in the Revue philosophique in 1886. In “De la sim-
ulation inconsciente dans l’état d’hypnotisme,” he records his participation
(with his assistant, “Robinet”) in the case of a boy who had been credited
with powers of telepathy while hypnotized. This boy was supposedly able to
read the mind of a man who was reading a book unseen to him (the boy
would report back the words the man was silently reading). In this case,
though, Henri Bergson demonstrated his skepticism. He was able to disprove
telepathy by discerning instead an extraordinary degree of sensitivity of vi-
sion (hyperaesthesia) under hypnotic suggestion (the man reading was also
the hypnotist). The boy could read the book’s text, reflected (back to front) in
the cornea of the reader’s eyes. Here is Caygill citing Henri Bergson’s account:
For Bergson and Robinet it was as if the hypnotised subject “read every-
thing correctly, but as if read in a mirror where they had perceived symmet-
rical images of real objects.” From this the investigators drew the startling
conclusion that the reading took place “on the cornea of the hypnotist,
playing the role of a convex mirror. Without doubt the reflected image must
have been extremely small, given that the numbers or letters must have
been hardly 3 millimetres in height. Taking into account the radius of the
cornea at 7 to 8 mm, a simple calculation shows that this cornea, working
as a convex mirror, would reflect an image of the numbers and letters a little
less than 0.1 mm.” This extraordinary deduction pointed to the existence of
hyperaesthesia, or the ability to perceive way beyond the limits of normal
perception.29
The solution to the case was both more ordinary than telepathy and yet
extraordinary, too. Seeing in miniature, in a biological crystal ball so to
speak, only hugely reduced in scale. Smallism. Here is a good example of
supernormalization—extracting the supernatural by natural means: the
boy is not telepathic—he is only seeing things, albeit seeing things extraor-
dinarily well—hyperacuity. This is less a deflation (of the psychical, the
paranormal, spiritualism, or magic) and more a case of the ordinary being
elevated from within—hyperaesthetic conditions going unnoticed (because
“O My Bergson, You Are a Magician” 71
they are natural, innate) in Frederic Myers’s sense of the supernormal. Where
we would extend Myers’s version of supernormalization, via Bergsonism, in
this context would be by showing that even normal levels of any visual acuity
are only normalized after the fact. The “magic” of all vision is the “always al-
ready” of an immanent bond with reality: the visual image that is part of the
real-whole, which is itself, according to Matter and Memory, a set of images.
Our vision of the world is not a constructed representation (in a Kantian-
style duality between mind and reality), but what remains, a selection, from
a reality made of images. Hyperacuity is simply a different selection. As a
comparison, even normal, rather than telepathic, intersubjective communi-
cation can often appear to employ a “power of divination” between individ-
uals, according to Henri Bergson.30 Hence, the need to insert a mysterious
“theory of mind” (or, in miniature, “mirror neurons”) to explain intersub-
jectivity. This insertion comes retrospectively in a rationalist reconstruction
or reverse engineering. In point of fact, it is simply that individuals (minds,
images, thoughts) are not fully individuated, being the product of a partial
dissociation (a set of images refracting themselves) rather than an association
(one image representing another). Or if you prefer, our mental separation
was never a given, solid factum, but follows a much waterier logic.
Incidentally, while we know that Henri Bergson read Myers’s work (they
even corresponded in 1886), and that he had this early interest in psychical
research, we also know that his 1886 report on telepathy would be the last
time for many years that he would engage with such research, or anything
else close to the paranormal and spiritual, at least publicly.31 It is no coinci-
dence, then, to learn that Henri Bergson was admonished for showing this
interest by one of his own supporters, Alphonse Darlu (1849–1921). Darlu
was a professor of philosophy and would eventually become the Inspector
General of Higher Education from 1901 until his retirement in 1919. Even
earlier than that, however, he was a mentor to many young philosophers
within the French education system (he even founded the journal Revue de
métaphysique et de morale in 1893 with some of his students).32 Darlu would
have known, therefore, that dabbling with such fringe experiments in telep-
athy could easily harm the early career of any academic perceived as devi-
ating from the orthodoxies of the day, which were still highly positivist and
materialist.
Nearly thirty years later by 1913, however, Bergson’s career, and reputa-
tion, was unimpeachable. The title of his address to the Society for Psychical
Research was “Phantasms of the Living and Psychical Research,” and here,
72 Vestiges of a Philosophy
And, in fact, Matter and Memory offers a model of such perception which is
only different from sensation by degree, as part is to whole. Moreover, it is not
that perception is built upon the priority of the senses but that the senses are
a posterior narrowing of, or selection from, this “pure” perception.
“O My Bergson, You Are a Magician” 73
Bergson intimates that the life of action and utility preserved by the “atten-
tion to life” of consciousness can be succeeded by a new attention to life ap-
propriate to hyperaesthesis and the virtual, an “attention to life” to which he
gives the name “joy.” Such an attention to life, one of hyperaesthesia, would
free us from the limits of action and survival and would bring the “refrac-
tory earth” back in line “with the essential function of the universe, which is
a machine for making gods.”37
We will speculate later on what the idea of “making gods” might entail (Henri
Bergson does not expand), especially as regards the Egyptian mysteries
performed by Mina Bergson. In the meantime, the “striking parallels” Alex
Owen spoke of between the investigations of brother and sister will only con-
tinue to mount, be they in terms of magic or the psychical. For it may well
have already struck those readers with an interest in psychic phenomena that
Henri Bergson’s analysis of the case of the dying officer above is neither one
of standard telepathic nor clairvoyant power: when Henri Bergson says that
“she perceived that scene,” it advances the prospect of something far more
occult—that this was a case of spontaneous astral projection, what we will
hear Mina Bergson describe as “travelling in spirit vision.”38
Before we turn in more detail to Mina Bergson’s own oeuvre, however,
a word about terminology. Owen recounts how “Bergson’s ideas resonated
with Kabbalistic and other occult notions of the crucial conjunction of words
and images in creating a timeless moment of spiritual illumination.”39 In
similarly imagistic vein, we just heard Howard Caygill make reference to
“hyperaesthesis and the virtual.” In the context of discussing perception and
images, however, I have long argued that Henri Bergson’s notion of the vir-
tual must be taken in all of its optical specificity. Alas, the Deleuzian effect on
many readers of Henri Bergson has resulted in my protests often falling on
deaf ears, with some exceptions. Perhaps we will have a better hearing from
74 Vestiges of a Philosophy
Mina Bergson. The following comes from her introduction to the Kabbalah
Unveiled:
Take the astral plane in its varied divisions, where some of the adventures
described by the seer take place. This plane may be described as a hall
panelled with mirrors, where one is confronted with bewildering reflexes.
Manifesting therein are numerous and varying entities.40
the word,” the vagueness of the word belies the individuality of its sense. For
Henri Bergson, the individuality of movement and image simply is its meta-
physical status—that is how what he calls a “true empiricism” merges with a
“real metaphysics,” for there is no such thing as movement “in general” (or
anything else “general” for that matter).45 Any “principle of individuation”
exists immanently within real, actual movement rather than a “metaphys-
ical”—meaning immaterial—substrate of “prime matter,” as Aristotle might
have it. For Bergson, matter is already individuated by its own movement,
rather than being merely an instrument of individuation.
5
On Watery Logic, or Magical Thinking
In their 1900 joint interview with Frederic Lees, Mina and Samuel, per-
forming as High Priestess Anari and Hierophant Rameses, discussed their
personae and what was occurring on stage in their performances. Samuel/
Rameses first:
we are not monotheists, and for that reason we have sometimes been called
idolators. But is not the universe, God manifest in matter, a great eidolon?
We are pantheists; we believe that each force of the universe is regulated
by a god. Gods are, therefore, innumerable and infinite. . . . Nothing that
you can see here is without its meaning, nothing is without its purpose. For
instance, here is a sistrum [an ancient Egyptian musical instrument like
a rattle] which is shaken during our ceremonies. One side of the wooden
body of this instrument represents the Beginning, the Alpha; the other side
the End, the Omega; the metal part symbolises the Arch of Heaven; the four
metal bars are the four elements. You will notice that on each of these bars
are five rings, which, being shaken, represent the shaking of the forces of
nature by or through the influence of the divine spirit of life. It is the same
with our dress. . . .1
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0008
On Watery Logic, or Magical Thinking 77
the female principle. Why, she asks, do we so often neglect the feminine as
that part of the divine
which represents at one and the same time the faculty of receiving and that
of giving—that is to say, love itself in its highest form—love the symbol of
universal sympathy? That is where the magical power of woman is found.
She finds her force in her alliance with the sympathetic energies of Nature.
And what is Nature if it is not an assemblage of thoughts clothed with
matter and ideas which seek to materialize themselves? What is this eternal
attraction between ideas and matter? It is the secret of life. Have you ever
realized that there does not exist a single flame without a special intelli-
gence which animates it, or a single grain of sand to which an idea is not
attached, the idea that formed it? It is these intelligent ideas which are the
elementals, or spirits of Nature.2
Life and its secret(s). Love, attraction, and “sympathy,” too—the last, a key
term in Bergson’s theory of intuition but also a word with strong mystical
significance—form a set of images shared between Mina and Henri.
In respect to “secrets” in particular, the language of cloaks, films, and
veils (removed, as in Kabbalah Unveiled, or not), is also concurrent between
78 Vestiges of a Philosophy
the two. In his 1911 lecture “Philosophical Intuition,” Henri Bergson talks
about “films,” “screens,” and other veil-like structures in a thought-provoking
manner in so far as he does so while directly addressing the use of concep-
tual imagery itself. Discussing how a philosopher might use images to think
through philosophical concepts such as, for example, Berkeley’s subjective
idealism, he writes that
according to this, matter is a language which God speaks to us. That being
so, the metaphysics of matter thickening each one of the syllables, marking
it off, setting it up as an independent entity, turns our attention away from
the meaning to the sound and hinders us from following the divine word.6
Crucially, however, for Henri Bergson all such images are actually superior
to philosophical concepts because, when aggregated in number, they sug-
gest a movement that straddles time. The very same philosophy could operate
“in other times,” only not through concepts. If Berkeley’s thought survives it
will be as a meaningful image that “is less a thing thought than a movement
of thought, less a movement than a direction.”7 This is what survives from
Berkeley or continues through a Berkeleyan movement in thought: what we
have called covariance.8
One exceptionally prominent image throughout Henri Bergson’s own
writings is that of water. Given his metaphysics of transformation, that images
On Watery Logic, or Magical Thinking 79
of fluidity, liquidity, flow, and water itself are so prevalent is not surprising.
As Camille Riquier points out, Henri Bergson uses the material image of
water (and, to a lesser extent, air and fire) “in order to suggest, through the
image, the moving reality in which his new metaphysics is installed.” Hence,
we get a thoroughly liquid metaphysics propounded through such images
as “the ‘jet of vapor,’ the ‘fluid,’ the ‘ocean of life,’ the ‘sheaf,’ the ‘immense
wave’ [onde], the ‘wave’ [vague], the ‘flow’ . . . and the ‘fluent.’ ” Riquier
argues that this “mediating image of his [Bergson’s] own thought” operates
by suggestion. These images “suggest what escapes” the concept, what the
concept “cannot absorb and which continues to be felt as the properly ac-
tive moment of being: its mobility, its moving [mouvance], its duration.”9
Indeed, Riquier goes so far as to say that, “if water is a privileged image it is
because Henri Bergson himself cannot do without it. It runs through all his
writing as the new element into which he wants to install philosophy. It is the
mediating image of his own thought and from which no intuition, even his
own, can be deprived.”10 That is why we can say, without exaggeration, that
Bergsonism is not simply a philosophy of flow and the fluid, but that it is
a fluid philosophy built upon, as Henri Bergson himself demands, “almost
fluid representations.”11 Of course, less tangibly material images can also be
found in his work, such as those taken from music, but nonetheless, Riquier
still asks, whether we “have to wonder if it is not the fluidity of water, air
or fire and the continuity of their passage into each other (fluidification of
boiling, condensation, freezing, fusion) that then provides Bergsonian im-
agery with its evocative power.”12 (Parenthetically, we could contrast Riquier’s
use of evocation, wherein a continuity of passage is suggested through a
flowing medium, with Mina Bergson’s use of invocation, wherein the con-
tinuity is embodied through the medium herself. And the apparent pun on
“medium” here is intended, though not in jest.)
This primacy of water imagery even extends to Henri Bergson’s discus-
sion of the origins of religion in The Two Sources. The evolution of religious
thought, he argues, follows a path whereby matter was originally “fabulated”
as a living being through a process he likens to a “partial anthropomor-
phism.” In fact, there are at least three forms of fabulation (animatism, an-
imism, and theism) in his account of religion that can also be seen as three
forms of mediating imagery. The intentionalization and vitalization of matter
begin with diffused, impersonal forces (animatism) before concentrating
those forces into spirits localized in particular places (animism), followed
by the attribution of increasingly more human personality to those spirits
80 Vestiges of a Philosophy
that at the same time detaches them from the world, until we have a full-
blown theism with a divinity that transcends its creation, including a ma-
terial world now deemed spiritless and inert.13 Despite the clear teleology
here, each “stage” is an end in itself and retained as a fundamental perceptual
faculty. Two features of fabulation stand out, however: first, that it more or
less mirrors Bergson’s own philosophical progress, only in reverse—his first
book Time and Free Will (1889) confining durée, and with that life, memory,
and consciousness, to the human mind, before Matter and Memory (1896)
and then Creative Evolution (1907) extend this durational being to all life and
even matter. In that sense, Bergsonian metaphysics reascends the slope that
the “modern” mind has come down (or in Kabbalist terms, it retraces the
path of emanation). Second, the image of water—itself full of metaphysical
purpose in Henri Bergson’s iconography—is central to his discussion of an-
imism. He argues that “water spirits,” for example, began as “vague entities
dwelling, for instance, in springs, rivers and fountains.” Once given a name,
they acquire their “own particular shape,” a “clearly defined personality,” and
even later become a “minor deity.” Yet, before these religious reifications
occur (substantializing and immobilizing in one), there was the fabulation of
the water spirit directly:
the spirit of the spring must have been the spring itself, as possessing a
beneficent virtue for man. To put it more clearly, that beneficent action,
in its ever-present aspect, was the spirit. It would be an error in such a
case to regard as an abstract idea, I mean an idea extracted from things
by an intellectual effort, the representation of the act and of its continu-
ation. It is a datum provided directly by the senses. Our philosophy and
our language first posit the substance and surround it with attributes,
and then make such and such acts arise therefrom like emanations. But
we cannot too often repeat that the action may be forthcoming first and
be self-sufficient, especially in cases where man is particularly con-
cerned. Such is the act of pouring us a drink [nous verser à boire]: it can
be localized in a thing, and then in a person; but it has its own inde-
pendent existence.14
“It has its own independent existence.” The spirit of the spring is its “drink-
pouring”, so to speak, is its gift-offering. Despite further and further an-
thropomorphism (further down the slope of “emanations”), the original
fabulation of life is basic: such early spirits, “in the elemental form which they
On Watery Logic, or Magical Thinking 81
first possess . . . fulfil so natural a need that we must not be surprised to find
the belief in spirits underlying all ancient religions.”15
Water is also central to Mina Bergson’s self-understanding of her prac-
tice, as can be seen in the “Tattwa Visions” Flying Roll. The Flying Rolls, re-
member, were types of lecture—teaching texts—that were also instruction
manuals for members of the Golden Dawn. The date of “Tattwa Visions”
is uncertain but it must predate The Two Sources (which appeared in 1932,
four years after Mina’s death). In it, she describes a vision of one of the
“elementals,” the “spirit of water” or “Akas of Apas.” It begins thus:
A wide expanse of water with many reflections of bright light, and occa-
sionally glimpses of rainbow colours appearing (perhaps symbolising the
beginning of formation in Water). When divine and other names were pro-
nounced, elementals of the mermaid and merman type appear, but few of
other elemental forms. These water forms are extremely changeable, one
moment appearing as solid mermaids and mermen, the next melting into
foam.16
with the Kether of Assiah, are initiating the force of that which we as human
beings call Moisture.”18 Prolix though this appears, it is clearly a technique of
image and sound manipulation employed to attune our perception within a
watery logic.19 Seen through the assortment of New Age formulae that have
accumulated around similar practices since (opening the “doors of percep-
tion,” drawing back the “veil,” “altering” or “raising” our state of conscious-
ness, etc.), this will doubtless seem both far too outré and equally old-hat
to be refracted into anything useful for us. Alternatively, we could regard
them as epistemic models or technologies: structural placeholders within
nonstandard techniques for thinking that involve images and sounds, body
practices, and ritualized movements (a “magical thinking” rehabilitated for
thought). In Henri Bergson’s language, if the embodied brain is a filter, then
varying that body-brain by whatever means—art, philosophy, mysticism,
diet, self-harm, injury, disease—must also alter the filter, our attention, for
good or ill (no drugs required).20 Performed knowledge—or what others
might call the need to “think in duration” (not about it).21
In the (relatively) respectable direction of this very same thought, we see
Henri Bergson writing, for example, about Socrates as a philosophical exem-
plar who operates more as a posture or contagious emotion than a set of ideas.
His thought is described as “alive” (vivant), a “living thing” that conveys an
“attitude” (from attitudine, “fitness,” “posture”). When later philosophers
adopt that attitude, one of dialogical critique with others, with society, then
“Socrates is there, Socrates alive.” These successors do not follow an archetype
so much as a Socratic movement, which is a form of living. The Socratic is also
called a “creative emotion.”22 Others might be tempted to call it an affective
“meme,” or “block of affect.”23 Yet the continuities at issue here are remakes or
translations rather than “replicators”—they mutate in each act of copying or
emulation (a hetero-continuity).24 So, when we wrote earlier that, for Henri
Bergson, the individuality of movement was both its lived, empirical truth
and its metaphysical reality, we might now take this further: movement is
personalized (being general and individual at once).25 We can therefore ask,
which is more insane: invoking “spirits” through ritualized bodily behavior,
or continuing a life as movement, as attitude? Continuing the Socratic move-
ment or, indeed, George Berkeley’s philosophical thought (the Berkeleyan
movement) through the manipulation of images; or expanding one’s spirit-
vision through objects, practices, and sound?
Don’t answer that question just yet. In a peculiar concurrence, George
Santayana produced a scathing critique of Henri Bergson in 1913 that would
On Watery Logic, or Magical Thinking 83
certainly imply that committal papers were needed for both brother and
sister. It is sufficiently entertaining and illuminating, however, that it is worth
quoting at some length:
We will see, however, that Bennett would actually contest any connection
between her vibrant matter and “spirit.” In her materialism, it is matter alone
that has both real agency and life. So far, so old vitalism perhaps, but this
rough similarity to older vitalisms conceals a real advance on them in her
view. For example, she rejects Aristotle’s hylomorphic dualism of a “pas-
sive,” “raw, brute, or inert” matter that, like some sleeping beauty, awaits a
suitor to wake it into apparent life. This dualist view sees “vibrant life” as
what arrives from an outside to insert itself into a “dull” material (hyle), give it
form (morphé), and make it flower into a semblance of its own life.2 Though
she admits that the hylomorphic model is “a kind of vitalism, positing some
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0009
86 Vestiges of a Philosophy
Did the typical American diet play any role in engendering the widespread
susceptibility to the propaganda leading up to the invasion of Iraq? Do
sand storms make a difference to the spread of so-called sectarian violence?
Does mercury help enact autism? In what ways does the effect on sensibility
of a video game exceed the intentions of its designers and users?14
The ancients had imagined a World Soul supposed to assure the conti-
nuity of existence of the material universe. Stripping this conception of its
mythical element, I should say that the inorganic world is a series of infi-
nitely rapid repetitions or quasi-repetitions which, when totalled, consti-
tute visible and previsible changes. I should compare them to the swinging
of the pendulum of a clock: the swingings of the pendulum are coupled
to the continuous unwinding of a spring linking them together and whose
unwinding they mark; the repetitions of the inorganic world constitute
rhythm in the life of conscious beings and measure their duration. Thus the
living being essentially has duration; it has duration precisely because it is
continuously elaborating what is new and because there is no elaboration
without searching, no searching without groping. Time is this very hesita-
tion, or it is nothing. Suppress the conscious and the living (and you can do
this only through an artificial effort of abstraction, for the material world
once again implies perhaps the necessary presence of consciousness and
of life), you obtain in fact a universe whose successive states are in theory
calculable in advance, like the images placed side by side along the cinemat-
ographic film, prior to its unrolling. Why, then, the unrolling? Why does
reality unfurl? Why is it not spread out? What good is time?19
and so rhythmic and temporal, indicates for Bergsonism the presence of life
in the material realm. As Camille Riquier comments, taking color vibrations
as his example, and all the while interpolating Henri Bergson’s own words:
Red is, at one level, a light that “accomplishes 400 trillion successive
vibrations,” at another level, a sensation of color for a perception that has
contracted it “in a duration too narrow to capture the moments.” Body and
soul, matter and perception, “flow posed on a flow,” the “difference in ten-
sion” between their rhythms “explains their duality and their coexistence.”
At the same time as consciousness intensifies in perception, its own rhythm
is thwarted and delayed by the rhythm of matter.20
one might ask . . . if it is not precisely to pour matter into this deter-
minism . . . that our perception stops at a certain particular degree of con-
densation of elementary events. In a more general sense, the activity of the
living being leans upon and is measured by the necessity supporting things,
by a condensation of their duration.21
down to the word “spirit,” a term still associated with Bergsonism, despite
Deleuze’s “monstrous” reading that downplayed its role to that of a bit part.23
To participate in Bennett’s version of a new materialism, all notions of spirit
must be exorcized. As she puts it, there can be no “spiritual supplement”
added to matter.24 “The vibrancy I posit in matter,” she writes, can never be
“attributed to a nonmaterial source, to an animating spirit or ‘soul.’ ”25 The
“temptation” of pervious vitalisms, including Henri Bergson’s but also Hans
Driesch’s, is always to “spiritualize the vital agent”—and this must be avoided
in any new vital materialism that she could support.26
Admittedly, Bennett is honest about some of the extra-philosophical
motives in her animosity toward spiritualism, taking a considerable time-
out to familiarize the reader with specifically American trends in political
culture. In particular, there is what she calls the “soul vitalism” of Christian
evangelists (promoted by ex-President George W. Bush while in office be-
tween 2000 and 2008). Caught up with the politics of embryo rights and
women’s rights, these Christians interpret “vital force” as “a divine spirit
that animates the matter of the embryo.”27 And, though Bennett is careful
to distinguish the vitalism of Henri Bergson and Hans Driesch from this
soul vitalism, one still suspects that there remains some guilt by associ-
ation nonetheless, a good deal of the problem resting on the term “soul”
and its connections with “spirit.” Yet, as we know, not all spiritualisms are
alike, and we should be careful to distinguish “spiritism” from philosophical
spiritualism.
Indeed, the term “spiritualist” belongs with a whole constellation
of other titles that can be ascribed to Henri Bergson equally. As Mark
Sinclair proposes: “Bergson is an animist, a spiritualist, and a panpsychist”
(ironically, only “vitalist” is missing from his list here).28 Marie Cariou
would add “pantheism” to that list, though it would be unlike any form
that went before: “if Bergson rejects traditional pantheism and monism
it is on the ground of a new pantheism and a new monism: an open pan-
theism and monism where the union of God with nature is not confusion,
where the unicity of the élan vital is not reductive but where one cannot
deny, without contrivance, that the all is in the same and the same in all.”29
“Dynamic monism,” “dualist and unitary,” “dualism of tendency”—these
descriptions, and others, can be taken as synonymous, or at any rate as
alternative images for the “heterogeneous continuity” we have been
defending throughout these pages.30 They certainly do not denote reduc-
tive, mechanical conceptions of matter.
2° = 9° Theoricus Covariant 91
The quotation from Henri Bergson that we used earlier to introduce his own
vital materialism (and panpsychism) referred to the ancient conception of
a “World Soul,” an idea he then stripped of its “mythical element” in order
to offer us his metaphysical variation on the same theme. Oddly enough,
for all Bennett’s aversion to “soul vitalism” in favor of something more non-
human, we know that she is not against all forms of anthropomorphism in
principle. A “touch of anthropomorphism” she says, can “catalyze” our sen-
sibilities: “revealing similarities across categorical divides and lighting up
structural parallels between material forms in “nature” and those in “culture,”
anthropomorphism can reveal isomorphisms.”33 Furthermore, Bennett goes
so far as to liken vibrant matter to that sense of the word “nature” that histori-
cally “signaled generativity, fecundity,” and was anthropomorphically named
“Isis or Aphrodite.”34 (We will return to Isis, or rather she to us, later.)
Such anthropomorphizing may even be “worth running the risks associ-
ated” with it, Bennett concedes, namely “superstition, the divinization of na-
ture, romanticism”—in other words, the mythic language of souls.35 Again,
her charity of interpretation does seem rather one-way. For the fact is, it only
92 Vestiges of a Philosophy
Modern theories concerning the relationship between images and magic run
from examples like André Bazin through Stanley Cavell to Vilém Flusser,
each emphasizing in their own fashion how images operate very differently
when set within the context of magic. As Flusser writes, “in the historical
world, sunrise is the cause of the cock’s crowing; in the magical one, sunrise
signifies crowing and crowing signifies sunrise.”1 He extends this reciprocity
of meaning further when discussing color images:
If one compares the colour of our own world with that of the Middle Ages
or of non-European cultures, one is faced with the difference that the
colours of the Middle Ages and those of “exotic” cultures are magic symbols
signifying mythical elements, whereas for us they are mythical symbols at
work on a theoretical level, elements of programs. For example, “red” in the
Middle Ages signified the danger of being swallowed up by Hell. Similarly,
for us “red” at traffic lights still signifies “danger,” but programmed in such
a way that we automatically put our foot on the brake without at the same
time engaging our consciousness.2
Within the Hermetic context, the power of the image, and the making of
images through special use of the imagination, gains even more power, taking
the image well beyond any unreal representational interpretation. Recall the
guidance from the Flying Roll on “Some Thoughts on the Imagination” stip-
ulating that the creation of images is a very real act: the imagination is not
“imaginary”—it forms a reality.3 Imagination, “the faculty of building an
image” as Mina Bergson puts it, is a creative tool that the occult practitioner
uses with trained skill.4 When she discusses Tattwa cards revealing the “spirit
of water,” or “Akas of Apas,” the images of each are no mere pictures alone—
they are implements as well. The image for “Akas” is a black or indigo egg,
and for “Apas” a silver crescent (see Figure 5).
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0010
96 Vestiges of a Philosophy
some scene in the universe reflected in the symbol which you hold, this
latter being to you as a mirror which shall reflect to you some scenes not
within your range of sight. And secondly, you can continue the operation
by using the same symbol, and by passing through it project yourself to the
scene in question, which before you had only perceived as a reflection.7
In other words, the Tattwa vision is a form of virtual image. She con-
tinues: “you must be prepared to receive impressions of scenes, forms, and
Of the Survival of Images 97
sounds as vivid thought forms.” Such “thought forms” are not only visual,
though, but involve complete “experiences,” that is, “things heard, things felt,
as well as things seen, which would prove that the qualities that we are here
using are really the sublimated senses.” This material “crystallizes the astral
plane and completes it.”8
The image is not “imaginary,” remember, and there is almost a quasi-
synesthesia of images being employed here, one that defragments our sep-
arate sensory modalities in order to remount the slope of emanation from
the infinite Ein Sof. When neuroscience argues that synesthesia could be an
example of “human vestigiality” (reflecting a phase of brain development
prior to its evolution into specialized sensory functions), then synesthetes
themselves become vestiges of our neurological past—living embodiments
of the “spiritual in art” (as Wassily Kandinsky put it) or the art in spiritu-
alism (seen in members of the Golden Dawn and their practices).9 A “spir-
itual synesthesia” might even be something nonsynesthetes could acquire
through the Golden Dawn’s training methods: operating on the plasticity of
mind and brain to reintegrate separate images into a more holistic, contin-
uous perception.
Indeed, in what could almost be Mina Bergson’s own invocation of
Leibniz’s notion that each monad’s perception is a more or less confused
image of the entire universe (a reference Henri Bergson was fond of making),
she adds that these “insignia and implements” embody “a perfect represen-
tation of the universe.”10 The ritual implement is a monad, no less than each
image of the universe in Matter and Memory’s first chapter is also a monad.
And when writing about travelling on the astral plane, Mina Bergson goes
further still:
We earlier heard Egil Asprem talking about this testing phase of occult travel
in the imagination as a method of verification and error elimination with
98 Vestiges of a Philosophy
quasi-scientific rigor. Mina Bergson herself finally notes that the return to
this world from the Astral Plane can also be challenging:
We need no reminder that Matter and Memory begins with images “in the
vaguest sense of the word”—a vagueness that is not by chance and is not a
lack. Again, Henri Bergson’s position was that his seemingly vague (and or-
nate) language was the clearest way to depict durée.13 In an interview with
Lydie Adophe, he responded curtly to the suggestion that his ideas were
sometimes metaphorical: “I rarely make metaphors, interrupted Bergson
sharply. These are images.”14 Indeed, when it comes to the “spiritual world,”
for Henri Bergson it is the suggestive power of the image that may allow
us a “direct vision.”15 Here is my point: vagueness also operates in Henri
Bergson’s travels, not on the Astral Plane, but on his own virtual one of pure
memory, where the past/my past exists. In one passage from Matter and
Memory, he offers us instructions on how to “actualize” a recollection from
this virtual plane of pure memory (so beloved of Deleuzian readers):
B'
C'
D'
The diagrams found in the handbook of the Golden Dawn are clearly
embedded within a very different network of mystical references and
practices. Nonetheless, though they do not offer us a stand-alone philosophy
(unless we take their practices as philosophy), they do evoke many continui-
ties with Henri Bergson’s diagrams in Matter and Memory.19
The image on the next page (Figure 8) is the “Connection Between the
Worlds” of Malkuth and Kether. Malkuth () מלכות, drawn top, is the most “ma�-
terial” emanation from Ein Sof ()אין סוף. Kether ()כתֶ ר,ֶ ּ shown bottom, is the
closest or most direct to Ein Sof of any order of manifestation. Note that its ori-
entation is inverse to the Tree of Life, where Malkuth is at the base, Kether at
the summit. The Tree of Life itself (see Figure 1 on page 19), leaves even less to
the comparative imagination. It is composed of ten spheres (“Sephiroth”), with
each sphere (Sephirah) denoting a divine or universal quality, an emanation of
God, but also possessing specific attributes of angels, angelic orders, or astro-
logical correlates. They are arrayed according to these orders, ranked in terms
of immediacy to the highest divine quality, with Kether utmost at the top. Every
aspect of an adept’s training is to allow him or her to progress from the base to
the summit. The final image (Figure 9) is titled “Directions of Force in Enochian
Pyramids.”20 What echoes here are the lines of force of each of the elements,
which are similarly centripetal and placed along two perpendicular axes in the
diagram, similar to Henri Bergson’s “psychical life” drawing (Figure 7).
Particularly redolent, however, are the conic images and the movements
they outline, there even being a clear though indirect influence between Henri
Bergson’s usage and the Golden Dawn’s via W. B. Yeats. The famed images of
“widening” gyres, cones, and vortices strewn throughout Yeats’s poetry, but es-
pecially in his book A Vision (that he dedicated to Mina Bergson), stem from
Figure 8 Connection between the Worlds (Reproduced from Israel Regardie,
The Golden Dawn, 1937)
Strongest Weakest
place of place of
Air Fire
Strongest Strongest
place of place of
Earth Water
Weakest Weakest
place of place of
Water Earth
Strongest Weakest
place of place of
Fire Air
the “experiments and thinking” he took away from his time with the Golden
Dawn. Furthermore, according to Meghan McGuire, Yeats was also influenced
by Henri Bergson directly after his Golden Dawn period, and those very
same gyres correlate heavily with “the diagrams of cones and gyres scattered
throughout Yeats’s copy of Matter and Memory.”21 Naturally, however, such fig-
ures do not establish any sure lineage—they are just lines after all—and so they
do not prove influence (be that proof through logical argument or empirical
evidence). But this display is not about influence. What it does demonstrate
(show) are visual echoes, covarying images, that, circumstantial though they
are, help to complete a picture in our imagination.
The diagrammatic and rich, colorful use of Tattwa symbols is also part of
this image-building practice. I already introduced some of the Tattwa visions
for Akas and Apas earlier. The most significant others are reproduced here in
full (Figure 10).
Earth
(Prithivi)
Air
(Vayu)
Water
(Apas)
Fire
(Tejas)
Spirit
(Akasa)
Even more complex are the myriad diagrammatic drawings found within
the grimoires of Golden Dawn members, each one devoutly copied out by
hand. Several pages, from the copy held at the Free Masons’ United Grand
Lodge in London, are reproduced here (Figures 11a–c).22
Of course, though seldom mentioned thus far, the contribution of the
Tarot—or divination cards—to the graphical toolkit of the Order is extremely
important, too. In fact, Mina Bergson designed her own set specifically for
the Golden Dawn—as did each member, irrespective of his or her artistic
talent.23 We should consider, though, that Mina Bergson was also the most
accomplished visual artist in the Golden Dawn (see Figure 12),24 and this
left her responsible for illustrating various manuscripts as well as much of
the visual design and decoration of the Ahathoor Temple in Paris, including
its contents—the props, implements, and other paraphernalia of ceremony.
Indeed, Mina Bergson’s artistic skill and training were eventually dedi-
cated to spiritual practices alone, such that when she writes to Yeats about
conducting “various experiments with colour,” this should be understood
as more than simply an aesthetic development—it must have been an oc-
cult experiment, too.25 As Charlotte de Mille notes, Mina Bergson “may have
mostly stopped painting oil on canvas, but she did not stop creating. And
in accordance with the beliefs of the GD, she regarded her work in ritual as
a means of manifesting a truer, more insightful consciousness in the indi-
vidual, and by that individual, in society at large—the noblest endeavor pos-
sible in a lifetime.”26
The stage design for the Ahathoor Temple must be included in this spir-
itualized art practice. A computer graphic of a temple Vault and its layout
for one ceremony (“Adeptus Minor Temple, Third Point”) is reproduced
here (see Figure 13). The stage design and “directions,” so to speak, are
conspicuous.
The ceremonial vault is clearly both a sealed room and one species of
Proustian space, a prepared chamber with choreographed movements inter-
woven with a configured area that is both highly decorated and populated
with various apparatuses. Like all such ceremonial vaults, it was based on
descriptions of the tomb of Christian Rosenkreuz, the mythical fifteenth-
century founder of the Rosicrucians, from which the Golden Dawn claimed
ancestry in their system of beliefs and practices. A continuity of movements,
but with a semifictional origin—confabulation again.
A helpful idea in the context of interior design comes from Jane Bennett
and her own re-enchantment of space. She employs the traditional Chinese
concept of shi, which involves “the style, energy, propensity, trajectory, or
(a) (b)
(c)
Figure 11 Three Images from the Golden Dawn Grimoire (Courtesy of the
Library at the Grand Lodge, Holborn, London)
Of the Survival of Images 105
The shi of a milieu can be obvious or subtle. It can operate at the very
threshold of human perception or more violently. A coffee house or a
106 Vestiges of a Philosophy
East
Chief Adept
North
South
Second Adept
Third Adept
West
Figure 13 Vault Layout for Ceremony (Reproduced from Israel Regardie, The
Golden Dawn, 1937)
Not that the shi itself is static (a container)—it is a continuity that includes
change: “it is the mood or style of an open whole in which both the member-
ship changes over time and the members themselves undergo internal alter-
ation.” Intertwined with the agency of human celebrants, the prepared space
of the Golden Dawn’s temple can consequently be seen to have its own agency
in how it both remembers/continues its past arrangements while innovating
novel forms out of them through emerging practices. Such a space is never
Of the Survival of Images 107
static. Its own movements are a memory, too, that is, a type of continuity
keeping the “present” specious and the “past” immanent.28
Alongside this “montage-collision” of visual images that we have staged
here, we must not forget sound: “thought forms,” remember, are “things
heard, things felt, as well as things seen,” according to Mina Bergson. For
every clairvoyant, there is also a clairaudient. Mina Bergson was both. The
vibratory method—sounds produced by the practitioner—is key to this.29
After all, “chanting,” the rhythmic repetition of voice, shares its etymology
with “enchantment” (from cantare, to sing) wherein the world is brought
under the influence of magic. Instructions for the “correct pronunciation and
vibration” of divine names (often from the Enochian “angelic” language)—
for water, say—appear repeatedly in Mina Bergson’s texts.30 Pronunciation is
a careful material sounding that must be performed correctly if it is to be ef-
fective. And the vibratory mode is even more corporeal: according to Samuel
Mathers’s script, it starts with inhalation and a vivid picturing of the letters
to be vibrated, followed by exhalation and slowly pronouncing “the Letters
so that the sound vibrates within you. . . . Imagine that the breath, while quit-
ting the body, swells you so as to fill up space. Pronounce the Name as if you
were vibrating it through the whole Universe, and as if it did not stop until it
reached the further limits.”31
Setting aside this last cosmic aspect for now (the parallels with techniques
in certain forms of transcendental meditation are clear), we can also find a
counterpart to this “vibratory mode” of thought in Henri Bergson. This is
another aspect of his own philosophical strangeness emerging from those
passages in his writing that emphasize the form and rhythm of sound as a
tool for communicating meaning. Here he is in the 1912 lecture “The Soul
and the Body”:
Consider thinking itself; you will find directions rather than states, and you
will see that thinking is essentially a continual and continuous change of
inward direction, incessantly tending to translate itself by changes of out-
ward direction, I mean by actions and gestures capable of outlining in space
and of expressing metaphorically, as it were, the comings and goings of the
mind. Of these movements, sketched out or even simply prepared, we are
most often unaware, because we have no interest in knowing them; but we
have to notice them when we try to seize hold of our thought in order to
grasp it all living and make it pass, still living, into the soul of another. The
words may then have been well chosen, but they will not convey the whole
of what we wish to make them say if we do not succeed by the rhythm,
108 Vestiges of a Philosophy
by the punctuation, by the relative lengths of the sentences and part of the
sentences, by a particular dancing of the sentence, in making the reader’s
mind, continually guided by a series of nascent movements, describe a
curve of thought and feeling analogous to that we ourselves described. [ . . . ]
The rhythm of speech has here, then, no other object than that of choosing
the rhythm of the thought: and what can the rhythm of the thought be but
the rhythm of the scarcely conscious nascent movements which accom-
pany it?32
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0011
110 Vestiges of a Philosophy
substance” nor Henri Bergson’s “wider and higher form of existence” name
fixed things or states, only tendencies: spirit as becoming, force, creativity,
and certainly process-in-motion (vibrating, entangled, plastic, even).
Spirit, consequently, can act as a structural placeholder— or “meta-
spirit”: whatever falls outside of, and resists, a reduction to nothing. Such
a meta-spirit can have a multitude of names, one of which might even be
“matter,” or, understood as a tendency, the “meta-material.”7 The objective is
to naturalize spirit, and even matter (as supernormal) in the ordinary Real—
not with only one name (“plasticity” or “vibrancy” or even “duration”) but
with multiple names, equally pronounced—all the names of all the practices
of the Real. Hence, while Mina Bergson’s “thought-forms” can be regarded as
materializing spirit in the manner that she depicted, Bennett’s “thing power”
or “vibrant matter” can, as we saw, equally be seen as “spiritualizing” matter,
despite her disavowals. As Henri Bergson says on a related issue, “if telepathy
be real, it is natural”: all we need to know is which “nature,” and whose natu-
ralism, is in question.8
Supernormalization is not, therefore, the decision that all and any
“spooky,” “meta-psychical,” or paranormal phenomena are real, but rather
the hypothesis, the thought experiment, that asks, if such phenomena were
real, how would we naturalize them, how would we integrate or reverse-
engineer them into (one knowledge of) nature? If X be real, X is natural—
but what would this integration into our view of nature look like? What we
need, to use a Wittgensteinian strategy, are redescriptions that leave “every-
thing as it is”: we see things, attend to them, and theorize them, differently,
within the Real rather than outside of it in some impossible view from no-
where. The Theoricus covariant does not re-enchant phenomena; it restores
them within the Real—one might say that it merely de-impoverishes them.
Hence, for example, if ghosts were real, we can ask what they might be
like, naturally. What part of the ordinary might they continue, in some de-
gree? Would they look like . . . memories, for example? We already heard
Henri Bergson describe how the reappearance of a memory in conscious-
ness “produces on us the effect of a ghost.” It is most likely a coincidence,
then, but still interesting to learn that Maurice Maeterlinck, who thought
of Henri Bergson as “the greatest thinker in the world” (and who was also
one of Henri Bergson’s favorite writers), should employ memory in his
1908 play The Blue Bird as a faculty of resurrection: as the awakened spirit
of Granny Tyl tells her grandchild, “every time you think of us, we wake up
and see you again.”9
112 Vestiges of a Philosophy
Naturalization need not entail reduction, however. For example, one su-
pernormal interpretation of time travel (or at least one of its more feasible
versions) leaves it hidden within the status quo: if time travel is possible, then
it will have already happened. And if such be the case, then we in our world
might already be a “future” being visited by its relative past or vice versa: if
the anomalous phenomenon is real, it is natural.10 In other words, to the pro-
posal that all memories are ghosts, we might add that some ghosts might be
time travelers, too.
On this issue of seemingly anomalous phenomena, Ian Hacking offers a
helpful insight on the related topic of “marvels”:
phenomena. Until its effect had been completely integrated within extant
discourses of science, it was a “marvel” that could feed into various eso-
teric systems of thought or “visions of the world.”13 Even the mystical “astral
plane,” though it had its roots in medieval thought, could be mundanized as a
fourth spatial dimension in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries.
Zelator covariance again.
The repetition of a supposedly supernatural phenomenon, which is not
the same as its repeatability (it may still recur spontaneously and unpredict-
ably), is one route to such naturalizations. Images stemming from popular
entertainments are a prime site for such everyday miracles. For example, the
banalization of even the dead returning to life is a favorite trope of science-
fiction television (Les Revenants, 2012–15; Dr Who’s “Army of Ghosts,” 2006),
film drama (Jonathan Glazer’s Birth, 2004), every ghost film ever seen, and
the entire zombie horror genre. Fictional biological processes, mind ma-
nipulation, or time slips may be some of the mechanisms deployed to sup-
port such bizarre events. Resurrection or reincarnation would be religious
variants of such para-explanations, too, of course.
Alternatively, were one to clarify properly the immaterialist version of
spiritual return or survival after death, so as to ask, “What would it be
for a spirit, qua purely immaterial entity, to return in all its unembodied
phenomenality?,” the subsequent answer might be surprising. What would
pure spirit look like, divested of all matter? This would be a thought exper-
iment akin to Henri Bergson’s purifying method in Matter and Memory,
which attempts to separate out completely what we understand as the sub-
stantial difference(s) between matter and spirit, perception and memory,
in the most rigorous sense of their opposition. The results are what he calls
pure perception and pure memory, two virtual forms of normal perception
and memory, only completely dissociated in terms of any spatial proper-
ties. He pursues this purification so that we might be better able to discern
the immaterial in both its difference and its continuity with matter, that
is, in its difference of tendency, of orientation, within a continuity. Here is
a kind of “dualization”—not to be confused with a dualism of substance,
for this concerns a process—a dualization of different kinds of movement
in order to found a new monism of movement.14 This dualizing would
be in contrast to the fudge between bodilessness and nonbodilessness
found in literalist approaches, be they in the Christian tradition (with
the conundrums that follow from the resurrection of all bodies: are they
clothed or unclothed, old or young, cremated, amputated, etc.?), the
114 Vestiges of a Philosophy
to Morin here because he then adds that this cinema is where we see “past,
present and future oscillate as in a state of osmosis just as in the human brain,
memories, the imaginary future and the experienced moment merge. This
Bergsonean [sic] duration, the perceivable indefinite, it is the cinema that
defines it.”19 Cinema is composed of images that fuse time and haunt us—
memories that are ghosts and ghosts that are time travelers. Yet, as images,
these specters are equally material and spiritual in the Bergsonian rendering
of these terms as temporal (rather than in Hollywood’s confused dualities of
substance).
In fact, it is the very same sub-Cartesian dualism that still dominates con-
temporary philosophy of mind and transhumanist culture (where mind is
seen as an intelligence separable from any one physical “platform”), that
equally reigns on the silver screen through ghost films, body-swap com-
edies, reincarnation stories, and other genres where spirit is simply a form
of faux substance, a transferable energy, or quasi-thing (basically, fanciful
equivalents to the telegraphy, X-rays, and higher-dimensional planes that so
impressed certain nineteenth-century spiritualists). For Henri Bergson, these
are confused dualities that require proper separation in order to be reunited
temporally (not in space). As he puts it in Matter and Memory: “questions
relating to subject and object, to their distinction and their union, should be
put in terms of time rather than of space.”20
All the same, if we also strip away everything substantial from spirit (ex-
tended space, inert body, mechanism, efficient cause and effect), with what
are we left? Movement. According to Henri Bergson, movement is altera-
tion or qualitative becoming (not spatial transition). Something truly ordi-
nary is “hiding” in plain sight (nothing is hidden, or “virtual,” to everyone): a
something that might also survive at some level, then, that might straddle
those things we call “past” and “present.” Only that “thing” is not a thing but
a partial continuity, a movement, a specific becoming in person (there is
no “becoming in general”).21 Spirit, purified in this way as a kind of move-
ment, is, oddly enough, visible everywhere, restored to space, bodies, and
even causation. But this is not a hylomorphic reinsertion of “spookiness.”
I think I can see why Jane Bennett only sees such restorations as dualistic: be-
cause they are viewed in terms of a substantialized space—res extensa and
“res inextensa” (extended and unextended things)—rather than in terms of
time. A logic of separated, solid bodies, rather than a watery, temporalized
logic. The Bergsonian restoration or reintegration is only the temporalizing
redescription or revisioning that leaves everything as it is, while also uniting
116 Vestiges of a Philosophy
difference “in terms of time rather than of space.” Nonetheless, what results is
at best a marvel to some, or an unseen variation to others. What is unseen, or
unknown, though, can itself be a force, an élan in thought.
The standard Hollywood version of the supernatural is simply what it
projects as the inconsistent hyperbolic of the natural, an outsider or “qualita-
tive” emergent, rather than what it is—the “merely” quantitative, the differ-
ence of degree. It is the difference within the one and many durées understood
as heterogeneous continuity. For we have said it often enough: there are only
differences of degree. But a “degree of what?” one might ask. In fact, how can
there be degrees or even levels and planes in duration, in creative change?
Isn’t that simply another form of spatialization? This question requires the
mereological response—the “part” or degree being of a whole that is open,
incomplete, enduring, or not-whole. As a part, it is “smaller” and contained
or foliated (if one must speak now in terms of size and scale), and yet it is not
strictly quantifiable, measurable, or reducible to being a mere component: its
participation concerns temporality or movement, a covariance that is shared,
continued, and not owned by any part, large or small.
At an even more metatheoretical level (without this “meta-” implying a
logic of higher-order representation, by the way), we can say that matter is
simply this, and spirit that—too gestural demonstratives, literally and figura-
tively. These gestures, or “poles,” in Mina Bergson’s language, are the minimal
dyad (be it of substance, property, or even direction of process), and all that
“matters” is that they be mutually irreducible. This irreducibility explains why
the Real does not appear as just one thing, even if only in virtue of the illusion
or hallucination of at least two things (because then we have the illusion and
nonillusion—two things): “spirit” and “matter,” “manifest” and “scientific,”
“living” and “dead,” or just “illusion” and “reality.” There is always the dual
aspect, the double life. The names are unimportant, but the demonstrability
is (showing “this” and “that” by giving each a name). Naturalisms are rarely
naturalistic enough, then, and need to be hyper-correlational, hyper-parallel,
with psycho-physical parallels going all the way “up” and “down,” “in” and
“out.” So, to say that everything is X (an old or modern arché), that everything
is matter, or everything is spirit, or difference, or durée, is ultimately vacuous,
for there is always the real illusion of at least two. (You could say that this illu-
sion is itself an illusion, but I wouldn’t if I were you.)22
Conversely, for a pluralism that says, “Everything is many,” its own for-
mula, too, must be sufficiently recursive if it is to avoid a substantial monism,
a static nomination: it must continually and indefinitely reperform itself
On the Meta-Spiritual 117
anew with novel formulations and names. To speak like a gnostic, it must per-
petually resurrect itself. As we will see next, this performance of new names
(and new ways of naming, many of them nonlinguistic) simply is the ramifi-
cation or bifurcation of types (kinds, levels, planes, or degrees), at once both
logical and cosmological, that emanate from the paradoxes of reflexivity. In
what follows, a Philosophus covariant will be visible at work in the plasticity
and epigenetics of Catherine Malabou’s thought—one that tackles this same
aporia of reflexivity and asks: must a philosophy of change, change, too?
4° =7° Philosophus Covariant
It is time to speak more about scales and scalarity, a topic that has dogged our
discussion from the moment we first referred to levels, parts, or degrees in
space, time, and memory. In “Philosophical Intuition” (1911), Henri Bergson
says this: “the matter and life which fill the world are equally within us, the
forces which work in all things we feel within ourselves; whatever may be
the inner essence of what is and what is done, we are of that essence.”1 Mina
Bergson, in “Know Thyself,” states as follows: “the God of the Macrocosm only
reflects Himself to Man through the God of Man’s Microcosm. [ . . . ] hence
the great assistance given to us in the teachings of our Order which insist
on a careful study of the Kingdoms of the Macrocosm and the Microcosm
side by side with our Spiritual Development, one study helping the other;
in fact the two are almost inseparable.”2 Microcosm and macrocosm. One
of the key principles of Hermeticism is that of “as above, so below.” This is
the idea that earthly events reflect those occurring on an astral plane by
means of correspondences and attunements. In “Of Skrying,” Mina Bergson
describes how
Once again, we see the importance for the Golden Dawn of a nonimaginary
use of imagination—here as the ability to “build” an image attuned to the
macrocosm. (We should also remind ourselves that the Kabbalistic “Tree
of Life” was also called the Minutum Mundum—the “little world or uni-
verse.”) As regards levels, in Wouter Hanegraaff ’s analysis of the systematic
“correlations between the macrocosm and the microcosm,” he describes how
the occultist was able to explore “the various dimensions of the astral plane
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0012
4° = 7° Philosophus Covariant 119
so as to change his or her own inner structure and to enable him or her to me-
diate divine influences to the world.”4 The divine is immanent to the human.
Obviously, this can be turned on its head, as Ludwig Feuerbach does by re-
ducing God to a human projection of our species’ perfection (“as below, so
above,” as it were). Beyond the religionist or anti-religionist commitments of
theism or atheism, however, in secular terms we can say that the occultist’s
spatial model removes the need to transcend oneself in unity with the “above”
because each human can already ally or attune him or herself with the Real in
the “below.” The self is remolded, not annihilated.
Sometimes the esoteric homologies between macroscopic and micro-
scopic employed obvious anthropomorphism (the sun and moon as eyes, the
moon as breast, the sun as face, and so on).5 Yet, as Joscelyn Godwin notes,
these doctrines of correspondences, complements, or analogies were not just
between polarities of large and small, human and divine—they also existed
between elemental colors and sound, colors and elements, or colors, letters,
and shapes.6 And indeed, Mina Bergson’s own “allying and attuning” would
seem to denote quasi-physical images of connection: an “alliance” is a binding
(from alligare, “to bind”), while an attunement is a tension or stretching
(from teinein, “to stretch”).7 In each image, a material connection, binding
and tensile, is formed between micro-and macro-levels, a physico-spiritual
amalgam that is both unifying and multilayered. Writing about the Corpus
Hermeticum, Joshua Ramey explains its teaching that “materiality and spir-
ituality are profoundly united,” with life itself being a process in which “the
nature of the divine is both discovered and produced in an unfolding of per-
sonal and cosmic, evolutionary and historical time. This is the meaning of ‘as
above, so below’: the process of natural life as a ‘manifestation of encosmic
divinity.’ ”8
We might say that the center is “decentered” through a proliferation of
centers: in Bergsonian terms, a kind of “complete relativism” is installed, a
flattened ontology with no unsurpassable hierarchy of macro over micro (at
least in principle)—there is movement between levels. We have noted, how-
ever, that with the fabulation of minds beyond our own, such proliferations
should be treated cautiously: attributing powers at the wrong scale, irrespec-
tive of the equalities of macrocosm and microcosm, can lead to delusions
of voluntarism and control (what cognitivists call “hyperactive agency de-
tection”). Moreover, this type of Renaissance “episteme,” one governed by a
relation of analogy between every level of nature, above and below, need not
be seen simplistically as only spatial, despite the language used to describe
120 Vestiges of a Philosophy
it. Scale is not always a set of nesting Russian dolls, of quantities containing
quantities. Many authors agree on this. For Bruno Latour, the notion of con-
tinuous, transitive scales needs to be dismantled entirely, such that switching
dimensions is never a smooth “zoom” in or out, but a disorientation that
is “as much temporal as spatial.”9 Likewise for Karen Barad, scale is “much
more complex than simply a “nesting relationship,” being instead “a property
of spatial phenomena intra-actively produced, contested, and reproduced.”10
Even Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari’s idea of the “molar” and “molecular”
must be seen, they say, as systems of reference or relation rather than as spa-
tial scales.11
Indeed, even quantitative scales themselves can be qualified, too, as being
more than quantity, more than the ability for one magnitude to contain an-
other.12 Size, too, can resist quantification. Writing about “bigness” within
the theoretical humanities, David Wittenberg points out that
doing “X,” even though we each thought at the time that we were operating
individually doing “Y.”16 Hence, as Bennett suggested earlier, American food
may have facilitated the invasion of Iraq, and sandstorms may be involved
in the spread of violence. As we see, the part-whole relations in play in these
examples are not at all scalar in any quantitative sense of containment. The
principle of “as above, so below,” of the “micro” reflecting the “macro,” can
also be translated into a number of other, more contemporary vocabularies,
such as general systems theory, complex systems, Deleuzian assemblage
theory (giant molecules and “microbrains”), or David Bohm’s radical holism
(which we will address later), to name just a few more ordinary renderings.
Each of these translations brings its own difficulties with it, no doubt.
Much of the puzzling nature of scale and composition can be tempered,
however, when we think of it in terms of time. The relations between parts
and wholes, mereology in other words, must be thoroughly temporalized.17
For example, we can also qualify a scale by temporalizing it in terms of
rhythm, say, or in the language of memory. We can follow the second route by
comparing Henri Bergson’s ideas with those of Carl Jung (no stranger to eso-
teric ideas either in his own psychology). Pete Gunter does exactly this when
he writes about Jung’s “collective unconscious” alongside Creative Evolution’s
theory of a “biological memory” contained within each animal, “dormant
potentialities, ‘memories’ of a common past which it shares with all other
living creatures.”18 Examples given by Henri Bergson himself include the
Ammophila wasp, which seems to have a magical knowledge of the physi-
ognomy of its traditional prey, a caterpillar, allowing it to apply just enough
venom to paralyze but not kill it (mummifying it alive for later consump-
tion).19 In what could be seen as an animal prefiguring of Arthur C. Clarke’s
“third law”—that “any sufficiently advanced technology is indistinguishable
from magic”—for Henri Bergson, any sufficiently evolved “instinct” will ap-
pear to reason as magical knowledge. Yet this miracle is only apparent: what
is real is the continuity formed by the coevolutionary movement of two ap-
parently separate entities—wasp and caterpillar—in one relation. These bio-
logical forms are really two sides of a continuous process—a process that is
itself composed from other, interpenetrating processes. Instinct appears mi-
raculous only when we do not think of it in terms of continuous evolutionary
movements at the correct scale, movements that are “reciprocally deter-
mining” (in Deleuzian language), “entangled” (Barad), or, in Henri Bergson’s
idiom, “interpenetrating” each other. Though this biological account from
Creative Evolution would need updating, its essentials remain the same, as
122 Vestiges of a Philosophy
would not the whole of history be contained in a very short time for a con-
sciousness at a higher degree of tension than our own, which should watch
the development of humanity while contracting it, so to speak, into the
great phases of its evolution? In short, then, to perceive consists in con-
densing enormous periods of an infinitely diluted existence into a few more
differentiated moments of an intenser life, and in thus summing up a very
long history. To perceive means to immobilize.28
These “higher degrees” are also rendered as “planes” in Henri Bergson’s work,
of course. We have already examined the resemblances evoked between the
plane of pure memory (or virtual) and the Golden Dawn’s astral plane as
extensions of our optico-perceptual apparatus (the latter once described by
Mina Bergson as a “hall panelled with mirrors”). But they share a distribu-
tion or scalarity in how they work as well. Matter and Memory tells of a “scale
of being” along which diverse rhythms of duration are arrayed. For Henri
Bergson, “there is no one rhythm of duration; it is possible to imagine many
different rhythms which, slower or faster, measure the degree of tension or
124 Vestiges of a Philosophy
* * *
A final discussion of levels, of above and below, must now involve philosophy
itself, the Philosophus covariant. In her essay “Before and Above: Spinoza and
Symbolic Necessity,” the philosopher Catherine Malabou ordinarizes the “sa-
cred” in her own particular manner through what she calls “an experience of
overreading.” For Spinoza, she writes, the mind
has a natural tendency to overinterpret—and such is the origin, the very pos-
sibility of the sacred. [ . . . ] For Spinoza, to overread or overinterpret means
to confer semantic content on a word or phrase by inflating its (absence
of) referent. This overinflating is fundamentally both spatial and temporal.
Spatial: God is understood as a central power, coming from above, a high-
ness (hence all the superpowers attributed to a God conceived as a legis-
lator: jealousy, arbitrariness, love, and others). Above, in Spinoza, is the
most acute example of the spatial overreading of the sacred. It implies an
overarching and overlooking position proceeding from a hidden and un-
reachable power. Temporal: in its temporal sense, above means “before.” All
prophets have seen, have heard somebody or something that was there be-
fore, already, waiting to be seen or heard. Above and before are the two main
structures or patterns of sacralization. . . . In these two structures, we recog-
nize the very economy of superstition.31
The “over” can be understood as excess but also, in its excess, as a fabula-
tion of the spatial in terms of superstition—the God or gods operating above
us. However, just as Henri Bergson’s theory of animist fabulation found that
its error rested only in its animating the natural world at an improper level,
so Malabou argues that superstition can be redeemed within a theory of in-
terpretation. And this also operates on superstition of the past, the Before,
alongside the Above. Citing Emile Benveniste’s work in linguistics, she
reports: “superstitio is the gift of second sight which enables a person to know
4° = 7° Philosophus Covariant 125
the past as if he or she had been present, superstes. This is how superstitiosus
denotes the gift of second sight, which is attributed to ‘seers,’ that of being a
‘witness’ of events at which he has not been present.”32 For Benveniste and
Malabou, then, as a tendency to overread, superstition is not “bad per se”:
On the contrary, it marks the origin of the symbolic, and in that sense it
cannot be totally separated from ideality. [ . . . ] what he showed is that
the origin of interpretation resides in overinterpretation. . . . No need, for
Spinoza, to refer to any transcendence in the message. Overinterpretation
is, in a certain sense, immanent to the message.33
There is much to discuss in this passage: superstition as both belief and ac-
tion (or presence) at a distance; or sacralization as equally temporal and
spatial (“before and above”). But we will focus first on Malabou’s theory of
interpretation in this regard, and especially on how it impacts on the ques-
tion of language and the evolution of theory—how philosophy mutates into
different forms from itself. For the fact is that the excess or overinterpreta-
tion that Malabou sees within the “sacred” message can also be applied to
her own work as a new materialist. Her text Morphing Intelligence can be
(overly?) read as immanent to the evolution of her project’s ambition to keep
Continental philosophy informed by the latest research emerging from the
brain sciences. In maintaining this acquaintance with the empirical, she has
found that her own renowned thesis concerning the “plasticity” of our brain
requires reformation.34 In her book What Should We Do with Our Brain?, she
originally argued that the concept of neurological plasticity, the idea that our
brains change throughout the course of our lives as they adapt to evolving
circumstances, brings with it the promise of a new kind of human freedom.
It opens up the possibility that we can intervene in our brain’s evolution by
changing those circumstances: we are not biologically determined bottom
up, but can change our fates, top down, working in tandem with this biolog-
ical flexibility.
And yet, in the preface to Morphing Intelligence she offers a new account
that mitigates, among other things, the voluntarism of her earlier view. She
admits that “for a long time I believed that neuronal plasticity proscribed any
comparison between the “natural” brain and machines, especially computers.
However, the latest advances in artificial intelligence, especially the develop-
ment of ‘synaptic’ chips, have mounted a serious challenge to this position.”35
The need to develop her concepts and languages—in particular, replacing
126 Vestiges of a Philosophy
With a certain zeal of the new convert, the philosopher pushes further than
the science, proclaiming a real identity over a correlated function. More than
that, however, Malabou’s own thesis has “morphed:” as a bio-philosophical
hybrid of deconstructive thought and brain science, it has deconstructed it-
self, rendered plasticity plastic by tempering its own freedom with epigenetic
predictability, programmability. As such, she asks, “how could we not con-
clude that plasticity is programmable, since it is becoming the fundamental
program of cybernetics? But is a programmable and programmed plasticity
4° = 7° Philosophus Covariant 127
still plasticity? Not that plasticity is the opposite of the concept of program on
principle. Epigenetic mechanisms are programmed genetically.”37
Such a renewal in language-thought no doubt reflects in part a desire to
seek out the new and extraordinary within science in order to maintain a
philosophical distance from the ordinary (empirical evidence quickly dating
itself and the philosopher’s reliance on it). However, there is the counter-
vailing need to renew language simply in order to think in duration. This is
part of the price paid by any “scientific philosophy,” in the truest sense of the
term. In Time Reborn, physicist Lee Smolin writes with great relevance to this
point: “Scientists think in time when we conceive of our task as the invention
of novel ideas to describe newly discovered phenomena, and of novel mathe-
matical structures to express them. If we think outside time, we believe these
ideas somehow existed before we invented them. If we think in time, we see
no reason to presume that.”38 And this is exactly what Henri Bergson meant
by the requirement of philosophy to “think in duration”—the need for it to
use “flexible, mobile, almost fluid representations” in order to stay true to the
“mobility of the real.”39
Like Malabou, Henri Bergson formed much of his philosophical research
around the empirical sciences, Matter and Memory focusing on studies of
the brain in particular. Yet, as Paul Atkinson explains, Henri Bergson was
looking to place “the brain within an ontology of perception rather than
deriving a theory of perception from the operation of the brain.”40 And
that ontology was processual and immanentist. In terms of methodology,
therefore, he insisted on the inevitability for any serious philosophical
terminology—and he includes his own language of “durée,” “multiplicity,”
and “differentiation” here—to lose its purchase on real process unless it, too,
continually mutated.41 Every new idea is eventually stripped of its suggestive
power as it slowly absorbs the more mundane thoughts linked to it by associ-
ation. Philosophy must renew its language and imagery if it is to remain vital.
A theory of change must itself change. Or, as Malabou would say, intelligence
morphs.
Even our attempt here to reintegrate the paranormal within the normal (as
“supernormal”) is also, for now, a renewal of language that must eventually
lose its way, not by coming to the end of its line, but by being replaced with
other lines of continuity. Following Henri Bergson’s lead and Malabou’s re-
cent example, philosophy must overinterpret itself. This need not be achieved
only through scientific fluency (though that could be part of it, too): what is
needed is the ability to create new philosophical concepts and images using
128 Vestiges of a Philosophy
whatever materials come to hand. Changing names once or twice is not suf-
ficient either: the real is not comprehended simply “by giving it a name.” On
the contrary, because reality and logic, too, are essentially processual (or in-
essential) for Henri Bergson, philosophy must keep creating the right expres-
sion to fit new realities. Names need to keep multiplying, like images.
Such mutation or morphing could even act reflexively as the recursive
metamorphosis of “meta-physics” itself, so it would be understood now as an
ever-expanding perception rather than an intellectual grasp of some eternal
truth—an empirical metaphysics sub specie durationis, as Henri Bergson put
it, over Spinoza’s sub specie aeternitatis. Yet such ramifications would not pro-
ceed within a disembodied logical regress of types or orders of representation,
so much as a real progress within cosmological tiers, levels, or planes.42 And
this is why overinterpretation—a multiplication of names—is not the repre-
sentation of this one level, but the invented effects of many levels construc-
tively interfering with each other.43 Out of the paradoxes of “reflexivity” (does
a theory of change, change?) stem not only different, ramifying logical types,
but different cosmological levels, generated through a material-spiritual auto-
poetic agency, or what we will hear Thomas Nail call “bifurcation.” As above,
so below, micro and macro, super and sub: heterogeneous kinds of conti-
nuity operating “vertically” and “horizontally” on different scales, temporal
and spatial.
And so also, before and after. An expanded perception (or “second sight”)
for Bergson means that a “past” is brought back to presence by distending, or
stretching, this present if only momentarily. Superstitio. For Mina Bergson’s
“superstition,” one becomes a “seer” of the “before,” a witness of events at
which one was never present, but which continue in lines of movement that
can be recreated. And that recreation also involves renaming conventions—
all the names of the divine, and more.
8
Vestigia Nulla Retrorsum
“Leave No Trace”
When the rite began the priest and priestess knelt at the foot of the statue
[of Osiris] to light a diffuser of perfume, and the sanctuary was filled with
the scent of benzoin and incense. Then they sprinkled grains of wheat and
flowers on the floor and on the worshippers. [ . . . ]
The white veils and garlands along the walls fell with an ominous shiver
and the walls were revealed to be covered in black. At the same time the
torches were extinguished, as if by an invisible wind. The drapes at the rear
of the hall then tore apart with a sinister rustling. In the distance a shapeless,
chaotic mass was slowly emerging from the blackness. The worshippers sat
up, rigid, motionless, then cried out, three times: “Osiris! Osiris! Osiris!”
[...]
All around were sighs and convulsive cries. Bodies rolling on the ground,
in the darkness, prey to terrible nervous spasms. Others stood up, straight
and rigid, their faces drained of blood, their eyes haggard. A reddish glow lit
the depths of the sanctuary with an infernal light, from behind the gigantic
statue which seemed to be locked in a terrible grin. At the foot of the statue
appeared a fantastic circle of superhuman beings: the hawk’s head of the
god Horus, the jackal’s muzzle of Anubis, the bull’s head of the god Thor.1
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0013
130 Vestiges of a Philosophy
effects in his Theater of Cruelty thirty years later. In his essay, Denisoff is
most interested in the ephemerality of such a performance, its transience as
an event, which he connects with Peggy Phelan’s idea of the “unmarked”: “the
transience of performance—its amorphous function across the private and
the public—was recognized as a source of power and is what drew Golden
Dawn initiates to it.”2 For Phelan herself the “power of impermanence” is
real: “there is real power,” she contends, “in remaining unmarked; and there
are serious limitations to visual representation as a political goal.”3 Hence,
Denisoff for his part continues thus: “the evanescence of the supernatural
is one with that of performance; while the latter can be recorded, it is never-
theless itself impermanent. This agency of the unaccountable, I argue, occult
practitioners recognized as a magical power.”4 The unmarked, the evanes-
cent, the traceless—these terms can indicate lack, absence, or what stands
hyperbolically beyond the fullness of nature as supernature; but they can also
signify something quite ordinary—the plenitude of movement.
Of Mina Bergson’s numerous names, possibly the most telling is her
chosen Golden Dawn magical name, Vestigia Nulla Retrorsum (often abbre-
viated in manuscripts to VNR). A condensation of a phrase from Horace’s
Epistles, I, i, 75, meaning “the past leaves no traces,” it can also be variously
translated as: “I Leave No Traces Behind,” “No Stepping Back,” or, most sug-
gestively, “Leave No Trace.”5 Given that these chosen names were often aspi-
rational, we might ask what it might have signified in Mina’s case. The past as
ephemeral? Or a traceless existence in which “there is real power”? Or a de-
sire to be untraceable, to be unmarked in some way? Mina Bergson certainly
did her best to have it so. Mary Greer notes that, at the end of her life, having
rejected all friendly offers of support, she essentially starved herself to death.
All of the original temple furniture from Alpha et Omega and all of her re-
maining papers were subsequently burned (following instructions from the
highest order of the “Secret Chiefs”).6
In terms of Phelan’s thesis of performance as unmarked, and Mina’s in-
vocation of spirits as an occult performance, we might say that what is not
left behind is also what can be brought to “presence” in such performance: a
movement, a bodily gesture, projected colors, vibrated sounds—but no solid
residues, no “permanent” things. Not representing (picturing) the past but
performing it, even with images. And no spooky substances either, no con-
fusion of matter and spirit as opposed things—only traceless ghosts. Indeed,
the very idea of séance or ectoplasm was anathema to both the Golden Dawn
and the Alpha et Omega which followed it—they did not practice that kind
Vestigia Nulla Retrorsum: “Leave No Trace” 131
a different shape and different symbols that actually connect with ideas of
ephemera (the untraced), performance, and the spiritualization of matter
(see Figure 14).10
The topmost plane of the cone, marked by RR”, is the “plane of dream”
(“plan du rêve”). Note, however, the way that the lines of the cone now pass
upward beyond RR”. Indeed, they do so indefinitely because the human
dream state never defined pure memory for Henri Bergson—it merely in-
dicated (“figuratively,” as he says) the direction of those planes approaching
pure memory “above” more closely than those “below” nearer to living per-
ception.11 As he explained in these lectures, there are memories that, the
closer to RR” they approach, the more personal, virtual, and really past they
are (“in” a past that is real). Memories that come closer to a perception at
the point of the cone M gather together through various “dynamic sche-
mata” (marked SS”) rather than simply falling chaotically into our present
perceptions (at least while we are awake and not dreaming).12
M symbolizes a “plane of movement” (sometimes also called a “plane of ac-
tion”) at this point of the cone.13 But it is how Henri Bergson newly describes
the way in which memories move down from RR” to M that is truly revealing.
Matter and Memory described how a memory produces on us the effect of a
“ghost,” but eight years later, his language has amplified: now, he says, “there
are ghosts,” of a sort. Though the memories located at RR” are still “obscure,”
he claims that they nonetheless exert “a kind of thrust” that might help them
“return . . . to full light.” “In a way,” he continues, they are “ghosts who would
like to materialize themselves.” The analogy proceeds as follows:
R R'
S S'
At the top of the cone, at point M, there is movement, there is, one might
say, life; there is the flesh and blood that make life; but on the plane RR”,
there are ghosts. These ghosts would like to borrow from point M the blood
and flesh found there to become living beings. [ . . . ] Which . . . amongst
all these ghosts, will be the ones who succeed in materializing themselves?
Those who have the strongest relationship with the present perception,
those best able to insert themselves, those also who exist better than others
in the movement that we are sketching. . . . 14
Thus, we see the significance of calling the point of the cone M, the “plane of
movement.” To return, a ghost must fit into a movement that (we might add)
calls it, invokes it, and so allows it to materialize (materializing “spirits” by
spiritualizing matter with a particular movement, so to speak).
Henri Bergson is writing playfully here, of course, and so are we, in part.
Yet the analogy with phantoms and spirits is a recurrent trope within his
writing, even in “serious” work in the philosophy of psychology or the his-
tory of philosophy. When citing Plotinus’s Enneades, for example, he also
likens memories to “souls” that are “lying in wait in the depth of the uncon-
scious,” a “phantom memory, materializing itself in sensation which brings
it flesh and blood, becomes a being which lives a life of its own, a dream.”15
The mention of dreaming is striking here, for the reference to the Enneades
comes in Henri Bergson’s 1901 lecture on “Dreams” (Le Rêve) where the
question of movement, of how pure memory-images gain a foothold in the
living, moving world, is given an even more suggestive rendering—as phan-
toms entering a dance:
But the memories which are preserved in these obscure depths are for us
in the state of invisible phantoms. They aspire, perhaps, to the light: they
do not even try to rise to it; they know it is impossible, and that I, a living
and acting being, have something else to do than occupy myself with them.
But suppose that, at a given moment, I become disinterested in the present
situation, in the pressing action, in both of the forces which concentrate
on one single point all the activities of memory; suppose, in other words,
I fall asleep: then these repressed memories, feeling that I have set aside
the obstacle, raised the trap-door which held them back below the floor
of consciousness, begin to stir. They rise and spread abroad and perform
in the night of the unconscious a wild phantasmagoric dance. They rush
together to the door which has been left ajar. They all want to get through.
134 Vestiges of a Philosophy
But they cannot; there are too many of them. Of the many called, which
will be chosen? It is easy to guess. Just now, when awake, the memories
admitted were those which could claim relationship with my present sit-
uation, with my actual perceptions. [ . . . ] So, then, among the phantom
memories which aspire to weight themselves with colour, with sound, in
short with materiality, those only succeed which can assimilate the colour-
dust I perceive, the noises without and within that I hear, etc., and which,
besides, are in harmony with the general affective state which my organic
impressions compose. When this union between memory and sensation is
effected, I dream.16
It is the “phantom memories” that perform this wild dance here. I am asleep
and only dreaming. Yet dreaming is only one state of my consciousness. Other
planes of consciousness, of trance, fugue, hypnotic states, dissociative states
(all of which Henri Bergson was well acquainted with in his research) would
each offer different means for materialization, diverse forms of movement at
M. The movements that we “sketch” (or perhaps “trace”) can be multiple—
and doubtless ones produced in artistic and mystical performances could be
counted in their number. Phantom memories need to find a purchase, a rela-
tion in, or kinship with, the present in order to return to life. What the jour-
nalist Gaucher described as “a shapeless, chaotic mass . . . slowly emerging
from the blackness” in Mina Bergson’s Rites—such phantoms need to live as
“blood and flesh.” So the question naturally arises: what type of movement
might reanimate those who, in Henri’s words, “rise and spread abroad and
perform in the night of the unconscious a wild phantasmagoric dance”?17 Or,
in other words, what else might M stand for?
* * *
To return ourselves to the question of leaving no trace in the context of Mina
Bergson’s biography, it is noteworthy how Henri Bergson’s own preoccupa-
tion with “discretion” and the “virtues of the private and the secret” struck
many of his contemporary commentators.18 In a final item of correspond-
ence from 1939, and sounding like an astronaut about to return to his space-
ship, he wrote: “I continue to work as best I can, but it is wrong to have said
that I was preparing a new book. The truth is that I would like, before leaving
our planet, to come to an opinion on certain points, and to do it for me.”19
One year later in December 1940, Henri Bergson would, against all advice,
line up with his co-religionists to register as a Jew. He died within a month
Vestigia Nulla Retrorsum: “Leave No Trace” 135
after contracting bronchitis. In his will, he forbade the publication of any un-
published writing. No final book appeared after he had left “our planet.” Like
his sister, all his personal notes and correspondence were destroyed on his
instruction.20
That we have only just now cited ideas from works that were unpublished
in Henri’s own lifetime is, therefore, a partial betrayal of his request. Yet no
less is true of this very enquiry into the vestiges of Mina’s ideas, a woman who
wished to remain without a trace. Should we disturb their spirits too much,
we might hope for some exoneration in the view that it is the unmarked
performance which has real creative power, that the indefinite, ephemeral
movements of enduring life (Henri) and spiritual ritual (Mina) contain an
immanent truth that survives unseen. And these truths will remain at least
partially untraced, despite what we are documenting here. Alternatively, be-
yond any virtue signaling in my retelling of Mina’s “her-story” (though hers
is a story that should be told, irrespective of motive), and beyond endorsing
Henri’s possibly bourgeois values of “discretion” or “privacy” (though staying
faithful to “the inner,” to “knowing thyself,” was truly paramount for both
him and Mina), there remains the necessity of invention when trying to un-
derstand the alterity of another. This is no less true of my documentations
of the two Bergsons. When I cannot be the other, I must fabulate, remake,
or invoke him or her. In our fabulation, therefore, our infidelity to both
Bergsons could be redeemed through Vladimir Jankélévitch’s recommenda-
tion that we remake Bergson rather than simply reproduce him—that it is
“the Bergsonian direction, the Bergsonian movement” alone that continues,
that survives.21 Only, in this performance, it is the two Bergsons together,
as alter egos, that need to be brought to life—not in “flesh and blood” but as
covarying movements of thought. If this book is about memory and a for-
gotten Bergson, it is also a book that performs its recollection as an invoca-
tion through heterogeneity, discontinuity, and covariance.
3° =8° Practicus Covariant
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0014
3° = 8° Practicus Covariant 137
Matter is neither fixed and given nor the mere end result of different pro-
cesses. Matter is produced and productive, generated and generative.
Matter is agentive, not a fixed essence or property of things. Mattering is
differentiating, and which differences come to matter, matter in the itera-
tive production of different differences.6
138 Vestiges of a Philosophy
We will look more closely at these claims anon, but we should first hear Barad
out when they claim that their “diffractive approach” to physics is no mere
compare-and-contrast exercise. Their research has no patience, they write,
for tricks with mirrors, where, for example, the macroscopic is said to
mirror the microscopic, or the social world is treated as a reflection of the
metaphysics of individualism perfected in atomic theory, and so on. The
drawing of analogies, like that between special relativity and the cubist
school of painting, for instance . . . can be very interesting. But these
common modes of analysis are only of limited value, and insufficient for
understanding the deeper philosophical issues at stake. . . . This diffractive
methodology enables me to examine in detail important philosophical is-
sues such as the conditions for the possibility of objectivity, the nature of
measurement, the nature of nature and meaning making, the conditions
for intelligibility, the nature of causality and identity, and the relationship
between discursive practices and the material world.7
No model of “as above, so below” here, then. Nor will readers, they add,
looking to be “dazzled, entertained, and mystified by a quixotic sideshow of
isolated facts and cutesy quirks of quantum theory,” find any satisfaction in
their work.8 Their approach is serious and explores “deeper philosophical is-
sues,” as we heard, without any showmanship.
Iris van der Tuin is one philosopher who has taken Barad’s work very
seriously and, indeed, seen parallels between it and Henri Bergson’s ideas.
When Barad states that “reality is not composed of things-in-themselves
[thingification] or things- behind-phenomena [representationalism] but
‘things’-in-phenomena,” or when they write of an “ongoing flow of agency,”
and a “processual historicity,” van der Tuin sees ideas here that are “very
much in line with Bergson.”9 Indeed, the dynamism at the heart of Barad’s
view of the world is thoroughly Bergsonian in spirit if we look to Barad’s
writing directly:
are a part, which matters to the ongoing materialization of the world in its
intra-active becoming, which makes a difference in subsequent patterns of
mattering, and so on; that is, matter is enfolded into itself in its ongoing
materialization.10
Barad’s conspicuous use of the verbal form “mattering” (which we will later
see David Bohm call a “rheomode,” or deeply verbal grammar) and their
emphasis on matter as process—materialization—is obviously evocative of
Henri Bergson, too. This materialization is best understood as a process of
emergence for Barad: “matter refers to the materiality/materialization of phe-
nomena, not to an inherent fixed property of abstract independently existing
objects of Newtonian physics.”11 Similar comparisons between Barad and
Henri Bergson can be made with regard to the dimensions of time as well.
On the question of the persistence of the past, their interpretation of the new
physics contains many echoes of Matter and Memory: “the existence of the
quantum discontinuity,” for instance, means that “the past is never left be-
hind, never finished once and for all [ . . . ] rather the past and the future are
enfolded participants in matter’s iterative becoming.”12
Though there is much more emphasis on matter or the language of “mate-
rialization” here than might be found in Henri Bergson himself, the fact that
it is framed within a processual context of “becoming,” or “the inexhaust-
ible dynamism of the enfolding of mattering,” makes for familiar reading,
with further talk of “the world and its possibilities for becoming [that] are
re-made with each moment,” and the need to be “alive to the possibilities of
becoming,” which is itself an “ethical call . . . written into the very matter of
all being and becoming.”13 And so on. Barad’s critique of “thingification” is
likewise very Bergsonian: even though they retain the idea of substance, like
him, they rerender it as process, as becoming: “matter is substance in its intra-
active becoming—not a thing but a doing.”14
Whereas Bennett puts far greater store on “thing-power” at the larger scale
she is mostly writing about, Barad’s subatomic level of discourse sees things
differently. Things for them are emergent from processes, or as they put it,
“relata do not preexist relations; rather, relata-within-phenomena emerge
through specific intra-actions.”15 When Henri Bergson writes about ani-
mism in The Two Sources in terms of things being substantialized by having
their activity extracted from them, we clearly see an antecedent position to
Barad’s: “our philosophy and our language first posit the substance and sur-
round it with attributes, and then make such and such acts arise therefrom
140 Vestiges of a Philosophy
like emanations. But we cannot too often repeat that the action may be
forthcoming first and be self-sufficient.” An action, for Henri Bergson, “can
be localized in a thing . . . but it has its own independent existence.” When
such actions are hypostatized, extracted as immobile ideas, the “subject”
of the process thereafter can only “relapse the more completely into the state
of a thing pure and simple.”16 Things emerge from actions, from processes
deemed intentional and predicated of a substance, a subject.
Barad’s neologism “intra-action,” cited earlier, signifies “the mutual con-
stitution of entangled agencies,” and it is the cornerstone of their approach.17
It is more than simply a concept of relation or dialectic that has been given
a physicist’s spin, however. Relata do not exist and then interact: their ex-
istence emerges reciprocally, intra-actively. Hence, as Barad proclaims, their
notion of intra-action “constitutes a reworking of the traditional notion of
causality.”18 And there is something performative at work here at a basic,
metaphysical level, too. Agency, they write, “is a matter of intra-acting; it is
an enactment, not something that someone or something has.”19 This agency,
this performativity, is also posthuman for Barad; indeed, they call it a
“posthumanist notion of performativity” as it involves “all bodies, not merely
‘human’ bodies.” What interests them is how these bodies “come to matter
through the world’s iterative intra-activity—its performativity.”20 Finally,
we should also note that this phrase “come to matter” is a play on words by
Barad: things “matter” for them in as much as they emerge as both material
and of value in one and the same process of materialization. That is why we
earlier heard them mention an “ethical call” in their project: this is more than
a contribution to knowledge; it is also a portrayal of how what matters is si-
multaneously known, valued, and meaningful.
All these concepts are tied together—meaning, mattering, valuing—so
that the word play is not only played by words but is part of a larger perfor-
mance: “meaning is not a property of individual words or groups of words but
an ongoing performance of the world in its differential intelligibility.”21 The
ultimate name or “ism” for all of this, then, is proposed by Barad as follows:
grating one at a time (that is, even if there is, if you will, nothing else around
for each particle to interfere with, whatever that might mean).24
With the reference to “space and time” here, perhaps we should not be sur-
prised that Battista’s descriptions of Turrell’s work then take a turn that, like
van der Tuin earlier, connects Barad’s work to Henri Bergson’s ideas:
. . . despite the fact that light’s frequencies, particles and waves, refractions
and reflections are absorbed by and entangled with/in our organism, this is
a theatre that does not need us human beings for starting its performances.
Light and its particles are actors that vibrate and travel, project and move,
regardless of whether we are present or not [ . . . ] Our participation in these
processes invite[s]reflection on the ephemerality, mutability of life; a cer-
tain humility, recognition of scale (of a life, a thought, and everything in
between); but also offers the possibility of liberation from functional/in-
strumental time in our culture, and related conceptions of the self.29
also echoes Mina Bergson’s language of the “eternal attraction between ideas
and matter,” which is for her “the secret of life.”32 And as for the “move-
ment of dematerialization of matter,” it takes very little to see here also ideas
belonging to both the Bergsons, yet voiced specifically by Mina Bergson as
the “spiritualizing” of “material science.”
The direct connection between Mina Bergson and not only art but per-
formance art (and, therewith, Barad’s posthuman performativity) has been
discerned by Dennis Denisoff and Charlotte de Mille. She writes of Mina
Bergson’s art work for the Golden Dawn as “an elaborate form of perfor-
mance art.” It is an art practice, however, “with a very particular intention.”
As de Mille reports: in a letter to Yeats, Mina Bergson was adamant that the
creation of rituals was “ ‘a long and difficult business . . . Anything of the
kind got up without the solid foundation of Truth we will not have anything
to do with, and neither will you of course.’ ”33 What Truth were the rituals
invoking? Obviously, nothing too “solid,” given their spiritualist leaning. The
mystery rites invoke the past, past spirits, only as movement, in performance.
So we might now ask this kind of question: can a dance, or even a gesture
in a dance, be a memory? According to the many kinds of bodily memory
we listed earlier, the answer is yes. But can such a memory be transpersonal,
acting beyond the individual’s biographical space and time to a distribution
not only within a collective space but also across a supra-personal time? This
would not be a past life remembered, but a prior movement in a person that
is continued into another life, another “body.” To do something, this thing,
“in memory of me,” for example, need not entail reproducing biographical
events faithfully and “to the letter”: it would be to continue a movement, even
as it has been interrupted, and perhaps even corrupted, in its multiple inter-
pretations (“materializations”), partly accurate and partly inaccurate.
This is not “spooky performance,” however. Let me give another example.
Simone Forti’s performances as a “movement artist” rely on the body as a pri-
mary source of memory that is both personal and supra-personal, human and
nonhuman: “I am interested in what we know of things through our bodies,”
she states.34 This knowledge can even be nonhuman knowledge, such as “of ”
animal movements, for instance, even as they are continued within her own
human body. Indeed, especially as they are continued within her body. As
Filipa Ramos says, this is not an imitation or reproduction of the movement
of a flamingo, say, or a bear, but its heterogeneous continuation—a mimesis
of processes. Or as Forti herself claims, “it seems that vertebrate animals
transitioned from ocean to dry land; their first and second adaptations were
3° = 8° Practicus Covariant 145
The starting point for all of Seers’s work is a personal family connection,
and for “Nowhere Less Now” it’s an old photograph of Seers’s great-great-
uncle George, himself a sailor, as was Seers’s father. The photograph was
taken in 1890, when George was 24, on a ship called The Kingfisher. “As
soon as I began looking into George’s story, I uncovered lots of uncanny
facts,” Seers explains. . . . “The first being that George and I share the same
birthday, September 27, and that we were born exactly 100 years apart—
he in 1866 and myself in 1966.” [ . . . ] Another photograph Seers drew
on for this project was of an early female freemason, possibly George’s
wife, Georgina. “George was a mason, like many naval men,” she says.
“I’m very influenced by the ideas of French philosopher and mystic Henri
Bergson (1859–1941), whose sister, Moina Mathers, was married to one
of the founders of esoteric organisation Golden Dawn, based on free-
mason practices,” Seers explains, “This was also one of the first of such
groups to admit female members.” Mathers studied at the Slade School
of Art, as did Seers. When she tried to find out what records they had
of Mathers, all that came up was a card saying that during that time she
was living in Kilburn. “Moina was born in 1865, George in 1866 and the
Kilburn church was built between 1863 and 1866, so everything meets at
this one point in time.”40
than Bergson the occult-artist: “the starting point is from a notion of the phi-
losopher Henri Bergson’s intuition as practice, to make art ontological.” To
make art ontological—to give it “being.” This is highly apt. Given that Henri
Bergson was portrayed by Paul Valéry and others as having “questioned as
a professor and replied as . . . a poet,” it is not all that surprising that Henri
Bergson himself should have described philosophy unapologetically as an
art for the masses, offering altered perceptions “more continual and more
accessible to the majority of men.”41 Philosophy, he continued, enables a de-
mocracy of vision irrespective of artistic aptitude: “all things acquire depth—
more than depth, something like a fourth dimension which permits anterior
perceptions to remain bound up with present perceptions.”42 The fourth di-
mension again, only here not in any immaterial sense, but as an enhanced
aesthesis, a purer perception.43 In its own fashion, Nowhere Less Now
performs these “anterior perceptions” and gives them “being” through eyes,
cameras, costumes, avatars, ships, churches, and cults.44 As such, it professes
an absolute equality of images (“everything is images, and all images are
equal”) no less than that found in Matter and Memory which begins and ends
“in the presence of images.”
The installation takes the form of two thirty-three-minute films that are
projected simultaneously within the Kilburn church, along with a multilay-
ered soundtrack relating George’s story as a sailor, his family life, journeys to
Zanzibar, and so on. Storytelling, or narrative memory, again:
From the seed of one name, George Edwards, Nowhere Less Now has
constructed a strange reality set simultaneously in the past and future.
[ . . . ] But the question of “who is George?” still remains unanswered even
after exploring this space. Upon researching once at home, a motto taken
up by Mathers/Bergson for The Hermetic Order of The Golden Dawn ee-
rily appears to speak for the unidentified character, reading “Vestigia Nulla
Retrorsum,”—”I leave no traces behind.”50
Figure 15 Lindsay Seers in Nowhere Less Now (Courtesy of Lindsay Seers)
150 Vestiges of a Philosophy
(see Figure 15), in a costume embroidered with Masonic and Golden Dawn
insignia, the following is written: “ ‘This is me dressed as my great great
aunt Georgina. She is my manifestation of Moina. Do what you need to do.
Further the image? Repeat yourself? I trust you. Let me know what I can do.’
It was signed ‘Lindsay Seers.’ ”52
Seers’s work is obviously not an attempt to be true to the past (whatever
that might mean, given the multiple pasts, human and nonhuman, micro
and macro, that she invokes). It is, rather, an overt exercise in fabulation
and confabulation, a “faultiness of memory” that is simultaneously accurate
and inaccurate. It is this mixture of images that may, nonetheless, capture
something real on account of the suspension of any one identity possessing
them: what they continue and recollect is not the same, homogeneous thing,
but a heterogeneous group of movements. Ironically, the mystic artworks of,
and performances led, by Mina Bergson herself were seldom offered the same
charitable interpretation. The garments used in her Golden Dawn ceremonies
were indeed (as critics now argue) an unfaithful mix of Hermetic and Egyptian
influences, the rituals themselves being anachronistic as well as a hodgepodge
of Rosicrucianism, Freemasonry, and amateur Egyptology. What Mina and
Samuel’s reconstruction of the Egyptian mysteries offered was a “kind of
not-quite-right approach to ancient Egyptian religion.”53 In fact, according
to C. J. Tully, the main problem with Mina and Samuel’s attempt at creating
their initiatory system was that “there were no Egyptian Mysteries to begin
with.” It was a mistake to believe both that these public Egyptian festivals for
Osiris were actually “mystery initiations,” as well as “the idea that participants
in the Graeco-Roman Isis processions were all mystae, rather than simply
members of the collegia.”54 In sum, the Parisian Isis movement was hopelessly
compromised with “historically inaccurate syncretic constructions.” Like the
Golden Dawn initiation ceremonies themselves, far from being “authentic an-
cient Egyptian rituals,” they “were constructed from a combination of clas-
sical and pharaonic sources filtered through a Hermetic lens.”55
Yet did Mina and Samuel care? Of course not. Their works were, as we
heard, “artistic in the extreme” (and in more than one sense), and they were
clearly content to work with their ahistorical reconstruction of Isis as an
“eternal, mysterious, magical figure representative of universal harmony,
unity and nature.”56 Faced with the ridicule of professional Egyptologists,
their response (in interview) was to commend “beautiful truths . . . dead to
the Egyptologist, but so living and so full of vital force to them.”57 Indeed,
it may have struck the reader earlier that Mina Bergson’s text, “Of Skrying,”
3° = 8° Practicus Covariant 151
Returning to Seers’s work, we can see that it, too, similarly confabulates
false memories together with real historical detail, biological facts, and bi-
ographical musings—with photographic imagery and optical apparatuses
supporting both tropes within the artwork, real and unreal. The micro-
doubling found in Karen Barad’s engagement with subatomic physics is
rendered, independently and through art, on a human and macro-scale, cre-
ating alter egos straddling space and time as two aspects of one “being.” And
why not? According to Barad, “quantum mechanics is thought to be appli-
cable at all scales.”60 In fact, the central idea of entanglement is not, they say,
“simply to be intertwined with another, as in the joining of separate entities,
but to lack an independent, self-contained existence [ . . . ] Individuals do not
preexist their interactions; rather, individuals emerge through and as part
of their entangled intra-relating.”61 This is the elimination of “absolute sep-
aration,” where those “distances that separate bodies and minds from each
other” are rendered derivative, emergent.62 If you had not already noticed,
I have just been citing Barad’s research alongside Pamela Thurschwell’s de-
scription of psychical research. Doubtless, separation and distance have
not been eliminated by Barad in the figurative manner seen when para-
normal researchers linked telepathy with the new telecommunications of
the nineteenth century, but distance is still seen as secondary by Barad in
a corresponding fashion: “phenomena are the ontological inseparability of
agentially intra-acting components.”63 What we wish to do now, in conclu-
sion, is temporalize this intra-action at an even larger scale through the work
of the two Bergsons.
Barad points to this temporal possibility, though most often only in
passing:
time and space, like matter and meaning, come into existence, are itera-
tively reconfigured through each intra-action, thereby making it impos-
sible to differentiate in any absolute sense between creation and renewal,
beginning and returning, continuity and discontinuity, here and there, past
and future.64
configurings that are more akin to how electrons experience the world” (we
might call this “what is it like to be an electron?”). And yet, it is an experi-
ment that simultaneously avoids “flat-footed analogies between ‘macro’ and
‘micro’ worlds” while also providing “a way of thinking with and through dis/
continuity.” They write of a . . .
to use new names, new practices, new philosophies. To continue using the same
language of “matter” (or indeed of “spirit,” or of “movement”) for all levels of
space and time becomes untenable, or rather, it simply is rendered mutant by
its own eventual recursion. Hence, scale invariance, qua “movement,” can be
seen at the same time as a conceptual variance (or mutation) that opposes the
transcendentalism of philosophy.69 As we learned with Catherine Malabou in
the Philosophus covariant, thought must mutate, change will change.
So now we place physics center stage again, only this time with a new
protagonist—one who will emphasize a kind of quantum continuity over
the lacks and privations attendant upon Barad’s use of Neils Bohr and post-
structuralist thought. We will also see a temporalization of the quantum
that is not based upon ontological ambiguity (an impossibility to “differen-
tiate in any absolute sense between . . . past and future”), but a fundamental
and positive holism within time. For all its well-argued championing of the
dominant Bohrian interpretation of quantum phenomena, tucked away in
a few corners of Barad’s Meeting the Universe Halfway is this alternative vi-
sion of the quantum realm: the radically holist model developed by physi-
cist David Bohm. The differences between the two perspectives boil down
to this dyad: localization and holism. Where Bohr maintains that (what we
nowadays call) “entanglement” demonstrates that differently located enti-
ties are nonetheless nonseparable (their quantum properties are intrinsically
coengendered), Bohm pushes this half-holism even further. His “radical ho-
lism” completely denies any such localization and argues instead for “radical
nonlocality” within quantum theory (what a Bergsonian might call “com-
plete holism”). It is not that different things intra-act—different things do
not exist: “for Bohr . . . holism is about (specific) differences (and specific
connectivities) that matter—differences within oneness, rather than [as for
Bohm] oneness as a seamless, all-encompassing whole.”70 The latter, “one-
ness as a seamless, all-encompassing whole,” is the radically holist view.
This position, initially dubbed the “hidden-variable theory” but later the
“ontological theory” (as nothing is actually hidden for it), was initiated by
Bohm in the 1950s, and especially with his book Causality and Chance in
Modern Physics in 1957. It was further developed in subsequent works with
physicist Basil Hiley in the 1970s and 1980s.71 Bohm’s stance is situated
somewhat “halfway” between Einstein and Bohr on two issues. On the one
hand, he partly sides with Einstein against Bohr on the reification of proba-
bility: God does not play dice. On the other, whereas both Einstein and Bohr
were unwilling “to give up on locality” (though they “passionately disagreed
3° = 8° Practicus Covariant 155
be and often is ignored on the subatomic scale. Bohm and Hiley [Bohm’s
co-researcher from the 1970s and later] insist that their “ontological inter-
pretation helps bring out a fundamental inconsistency between relativity
and quantum theory, centred on the question of nonlocality.”76
For Einstein, his theory of relativity simply states that, in his own words, “the
general laws of nature are to be expressed by equations which hold good for
all systems of coordinates, that is, are covariant with respect to any substitu-
tions whatever (generally co-variant).”77 According to Murphy, this means
that “physical laws remain the same for all frames of reference and so all
frames of reference may be transformed into one another.”78 This is how
we arrived at the twin’s paradox discussed at the outset—a geometric (“ge-
neral”) covariance that actually retains an absolute point of view, reducing
all other changes to mere relations relative to its immobile stance—a tran-
scendent view from nowhere. For Henri Bergson, a real (“intégrale”) covar-
iance, as in two trains moving in concord with the same vector, is shared (or
continuous) simply because it is not interchangeable, because it is between
two heterogeneities. To adopt the position of the other completely, I must
become the other. In quantum nonlocality, there is a violation of the theory
of relativity in as much as it “posits apparently instantaneous (or at least ex-
tremely rapid) communication, real simultaneous determination, between
widely separated objects.”79 In Henri Bergson’s terms, this is a lived simul-
taneity that is not a spatialized now, but real covarying processes: the “com-
munication” is based on real experience, on higher and wider experiences
that have not fully dissociated (Bergsonian panpsychism). What looks like
telepathy or spooky “action-at-a-distance” is simply what has not been fully
individuated. Of this, Henri Bergson writes
It is not that one mind accesses another mind from without (separation), but
rather that the two were never fully differentiated from each other to begin
with (partial dissociation over total unity or disunity). Durée is shared as
3° = 8° Practicus Covariant 157
one and many, one between many: its internal structure, its heterogeneity,
simply is the alterity we comprise in our degree of differentiation, our level
of durée. (Parenthetically, such a dissociative, nonsolid logic also allows for a
supernormalization of an apparent “power of divination” between minds.)
For Bohm, the nonlocal movement of particles takes place within “a unique
frame in which the nonlocal connections operate instantaneously.” As
Murphy sees it, Bohmian nonlocality “undoes the reduction of time to space
performed by relativity theory and establishes an irreducibly privileged frame
of temporal reference for physical experiments.”81 Real time is restored—not
as a view from nowhere extracted from real experience by eliminating its in-
dividuality, but as a “temporal reference” to precisely what is unique in any
one real perspective. This is where Bohm clearly shows that he is Bergsonian,
as we seen in this final quotation from Murphy:
would be involved are indeed relative and only apparent to one perspective,
but the perspectives that comprise them are real. They are neither illusory
nor merely optical (virtual): what embodies, what incarnates those “gaps,”
are physical processes. They are not hidden but simply unseen because they
are spread everywhere in different spaces and across different times; hidden
in plain or ordinary sight, across the whole (which is itself becoming). As
Seers would put it, they are nowhere because they are everywhere. They are
real physical movements, levels of durée, foliated or “implicated” (in Bohm’s
words) within the other levels of durée that comprise an incomplete whole.
One and many.
For Henri Bergson, the whole is indefinite or open, itself continually
evolving as well. Barad comes close to this idea, or rather its implications,
when writing that, for intra-actions, “interior and exterior, past, present,
and future, are iteratively enfolded and reworked, but never eliminated (and
never fixed).”85 Later, she adds, “the past is never finished once and for all and
out of sight may be out of touch but not necessarily out of reach.”86 Barad,
using Bohr, entangles things across space for sure (such that things are not
fully “across” from each other at all); and here she gestures toward a temporal
version of the same: entangled time. The “spiritual hyperplane” that Paul
Halpern described nineteenth-century psycho-physicists searching for is not
Mina Bergson’s astral plane or Henri Bergson’s virtual plane. Nor is it Bohm’s
“hyperplane of constant time.” What connects these planes is neither family
resemblance nor overweening analogy, but a continuity that is uneven, inter-
rupted, and heterogeneous.
The spiritually inclined physicists that we started out with, Stewart, Tait,
and Zöllner, might themselves be spooked to find that spirit was never dis-
embodied in a higher dimension of space, but perfectly incarnated among
a covarying set of processes stretched throughout the “life of the cosmos”
(to use Lee Smolin’s phrase). In Duration and Simultaneity, Henri Bergson
criticized the idea of a geometric covariance as illusory, where Peter is but
a fictional image for Paul, and vice versa. For Henri Bergson, we recall, to
represent fully another’s lived time, one must experience it in every de-
tail, in person. But this is impossible without becoming that other person: “If
I want to actually measure Peter’s time . . . I must become Peter.”87 This is
real covariance—not possible through a fanciful picturing of the other, but
possible through a real continuation of their movements in oneself. When it
comes to time, to a real covariance between a past and a present, we have the
continuity that Henri Bergson called “experienced and lived” (an expanded
3° = 8° Practicus Covariant 159
present that retains a past). Such expansion is not wholly due to individual
agency in recollection (you), but the agency of time itself, the past, remem-
bering you. Invocation, if it works at any level, would be the voluntary attempt
to “call upon” (invocare) the involuntary, to make time intervene through
ritual, performance, or even, in Henri Bergson’s philosophical version, what
he also called “intellectual effort.”88 Real covariance as nonlocalized memory
(continuing heterogeneous movements across time). And invocation as
intra-action. This is how the two Bergsons, Henri and Mina, respectively
entangle time “across” past and present. They themselves may be entangled,
too, as covarying siblings, albeit operating at different levels of duration in
their lives’ researches, each one invoking the other.
Patrick McNamara adds a further dimension to this radical holism of time,
splicing it here with the operations of memory and the selection of multiple
identities:
the game of Tarot? With origins going back to fifteenth-century Italy where
it began as a simple game of chance, its occult repurposing came three hun-
dred years later near the end of the eighteenth century. With that, the cards
gave seemingly chance events new meaning for the purposes of divination,
or as Catherine Christof puts it, “a symbolic cipher for universal truths,
representing . . . the transformational and evolutionary journey of a soul.”91
Chance is tamed, a little, with nonstandard causality (foretelling Bohm’s first
crucial work, Causality and Chance in Modern Physics). Divination through
cartomancy offers us a little fabulated order coming out of chaos, signs of a
probable fate from a random selection of cards. Again, memory, even Yeats’s
“Great Memory,” is not stored anywhere: it is selected. If one asks, “From
where?” the answer comes: the past that lives on through new (heteroge-
neous) lines of continuity. And who selects? Again, the past, though at an-
other of its levels, which are indefinite in number simply because “the past”
does not exist—there are only the numerous lines of presents-pasts inter-
fering with each other “all the time.”
So does the Tarot divine the future through its selection? I would say that
it is highly improbable that it should, but not impossible. The Tarot, or any
other form of supernatural divination, is rightly deemed absurd by most, for
in (nearly) all probability it is ridiculous to think that one level of durée could
control a constructive interference with another at such a higher degree of
tension. And yet, within the enduring universe or open whole, no amount of
improbability, or implausibility, can exhaust an indefinite period in the long
run—and, as David Hume realized, “the long run” is a very long time, indeed.
That said, a very long time could pass in the blink of a fabulated God’s eye.
Perhaps that is why hope—or what Jean-Paul Sartre called humanity’s “use-
less passion”—springs eternal.
9
Spirit in the Materialist World
To truly be here in this space and time, one must truly be of this space and
time, at least eventually. The arrival from elsewhere, then, may be gradual.
Yet the change in identity will not be of essential substance (which, by its own
definition, cannot change) but of movements.
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0015
162 Vestiges of a Philosophy
Let us return, therefore, to this idea of the ordinary and push it a little fur-
ther. Possibly the best sign or revelation of any time travel being possible is
precisely when our mind makes it happen—when one’s ordinary memory
expands “the” so-called present. Perhaps all of us (unbeknownst to ourselves)
are time travelers who are “here” already, having always already arrived, or
are perpetually arriving anew. “Mental time travel,” thus, would be neither
figurative nor second-best: it would be as good as it gets.3 This is one way to
supernormalize time travel: through the idea that we already “travel” in our
own mind through our own lifespan, our past (and perhaps also that we see
others, our alter egos, traveling the other possibilities of life alongside us).
Alternatively, out of that glimpse of a different durée, we can invent, or rather
fabulate, the idea of a hyperbolic time travel that is free-ranging across an im-
personal time, the past, and which is contained along a spatializing timeline,
measured by a clock and propelled by a machine.
Yet this switch from the subjective to the objective, from the view from
somewhere to a view from nowhere, is not the only option possible. Rather
than eliminating the role of one’s mind in mental time travel to leave us with
an abstracted or generalized time travel (no ghost, only the machine), mind
could be extended otherwise as spirit, as psychic, metaphysical movement.
This is not a Platonic metaphysics of abstraction, but the Bergsonian one of
an enlarged attention to life. “Introduction to Metaphysics” concludes with
a contrast between a general abstraction and such an attentive holism: “in
this sense, metaphysics has nothing in common with a generalization of ex-
perience, and yet it could be defined as the whole of experience (l’expérience
intégrale).”4 This would be a different kind of amplified time travel, not
through objectivized spatial lines and general mechanisms, but via an ex-
tended mental attention, collective, intersubjective memory, and embodied
performance—each of them components of “l’expérience intégrale.” It would
still be real and immanent, despite its transcendence of any one individual
life. Our own mental time travels in memory could then be compared to
this real time travel, as one might compare a part to the whole, a glimpse
that is immanent to what it sees. What Henri Bergson refers to as a real past
surviving in the elasticated present (“our whole past [that] still exists”), and
Mina Bergson practices as the invocation of a distant past through her own
body, would then be the real expansions of this glimpse: one, academic and
respectable, the other, occult and outlandish, but both realized through
movement.
Spirit in the Materialist World 163
The ordinary can also help us rethink other temporal continuities, such
as survival after death. Normally, any supposed persistence of our personal
identity would be denied by traditional materialism on account of a finite
continuity of the body (in particular, that of the mortal brain), but affirmed
by traditional spiritualism and its trust in an infinite continuity of mind (or a
putatively “immortal” aspect of mind such as memory or intellect).5 In each
case, however, one kind of substantial continuity is assumed, be it a nega-
tive, terminable one (based on matter), or a positive, interminable one (based
on spirit). The specific language of continuity might change (from what “re-
mains,” or “survives,” to what “persists,” “subsists,” or even “transcends”),
but its tacit homogeneity stays constant. The idea that we are forwarding
instead—of hetero-continuities taking myriad forms, ones that are not de-
pendent on any particular vehicle (material or immaterial substance) nor any
one (homogeneous) form of continuity—is given brief attention. Standardly, a
substance is denied or affirmed in its continuity, be it mysterious or not: but a
multiplicity of different continuities—covarying, interfering, ephemeral, and
existing at different levels (yet always mundane, wherever they may be)—is
left unnoticed or unseen.
In the work before you, we have attempted to think survival through con-
tinuity and indivisibility, through ritualized, habitual, movements or beha-
vior: a “supernormal” that, only when projected at an improper level, will
fabulate the implausible, the “spooky.” This would be a destructive inter-
ference that cancels out the continuity in a single, fleeting thought rather
than amplifying it through a sustainable, collective bodily response. The act
of offering water by the Spring, for example, is fabulated as a spirit, a per-
fectly individuated metaphysico-real movement. Isis, goddess of healing
and nourishment, simply is the giving of sustenance, is that movement,
too—continued, surviving, or “invoked,” across another body, that of Mina
Bergson. The Practicus covariant—a machine for making a goddess (man-
ifest).6 This watery logic is one of the new, heterogeneous logics needed to
rethink the relationship between “knowings,” between “sophia” (philosophy)
and “gnosis” (mysticism).7 The philosophy of mysticism (Henri’s) becomes
indiscernible from the mysticism of philosophy (Mina’s): not on account of
a fuzziness that would only be an exotic variant of classic, hard-bodied logic,
but as a real, practiced, water logic (or air logic, or sonic logic).8 As Marcel
Mauss put it in our opening epigraph: “mystical states” are simply “body
techniques that we have not yet studied.”9 But then, following his deflation,
164 Vestiges of a Philosophy
comes the inflation: “I think that there are necessarily biological means of
entering into ‘communication with God.’ ”10 What God is, however, is super-
normal, too.
So there really is nothing unreal to see here, only aspects of the Real left
mostly unseen—its becomings, its arrivals, its movements. One might even
ask oneself this: if a human subject does not pre-exist as substance but only
comes to be (say, through “fidelity” to an “Event,” as Alain Badiou argues);
and, correspondingly, if a divine subject (the philosophers’ God) can only
come into existence through radical contingency (Quentin Meillassoux’s
extension of Badiou’s idea)—then, what of the existence of a nonstandard
Goddess? What if the Goddess-spirit never pre-existed as substance or sub-
ject at all, but comes into existence—is invoked each time anew—through
heterogeneous continuity, through wholly random and contingent acts of per-
formance, a set of hyper-ritualistic practices involving other communicants,
their use of voice, script, and dialogue, as well as animals, the environment,
sets, costumes, and ceremonial regalia? Some of these acts might not even be
voluntary or intentional and include both small and large nonhuman actors
(or “actants” if you prefer), such as brain events, metabolic events, viral and
bacterial agents, climate and atmospheric occurrences, and so on. What if
all that, already, simply was the invoked goddess insofar as she might par-
tially manifest at all: immanent-divine movements covarying across bodily-
temporal scales, “above” and “below”? This is as good as it gets. Infinitesimally
improbable, perhaps, but not impossible. The fabulations of such improbable
“faith,” taken as a mystical state, rest on a fluid, hopeful logic in as much as
covariance is not about the same continuity (Isis returned in all her flesh and
blood existence for doubters to probe), but different, hetero-continuities. Or
rather, qua supernormalization, personal and collective “memory,” with all
its worldly facilitators, would be the invocation of the goddess, because the
goddess does not transcend the act. Invocation as immanence: all memories
are ghosts; some ghosts are time travelers; and perhaps some time travelers
are gods.
* * *
Henri Bergson’s strangest ideas in Matter and Memory point to the possi-
bility of transcending the present, the “now,” with a distended perception, an
expanded attention that reanimates my past. Mina Bergson’s work attempted
to transcend her personal identity in performative invocations of the past—
“the Isis movement,” as she and Samuel so often called it, being literally that
Spirit in the Materialist World 165
In this research into the conceptual relations of Mina and Henri Bergson,
we might seem to be traveling among “veridical hallucinations,” which was
how Henri Bergson described paranormal perception. Our own fabulations
may amount to no more than a set of reciprocating projections, or dream-
like coincidences, between the two. Dreams, in Henri Bergson’s view at least,
are “only” relaxed forms of perception in any case: they are perceptions that
have been overwhelmed with wildly associating images from pure memory,
the phantasmagoria of the past.1
According to François Laruelle, however, every philosopher (not only the
crazy ones) hallucinates a world that is “withdrawn” from the Real, only then
to hold itself as the authoritative account of all reality. This is not simply a
Kantian admonition against the misplaced ambitions of traditional met-
aphysics: all philosophy, for Laruelle, simply is the gesture in thought that
gives itself the authority to pronounce on the essence of reality, to master it
from a hallucinated outside—a view from nowhere.2 It is the withdrawn or
de-parted part of the Real. The hyperbolic part that stands “over and beyond”
the Real, transcending it. Irrespective of whether any particular historical
philosophy is materialist, idealist, realist, nihilist, or whatever else, qua phi-
losophy, we could say that its real conditions are supernatural for Laruelle,
“spooky.” This ghostly philosophy is neither spectral nor “hauntological” on
account of an aporetic presence-as-absence, that is, as a Derridean ontology
of difference. It is simply the de-parted. Mixing Laruelle and Henri Bergson
together like this, we arrive at a position that sees standard, conceptual phi-
losophy become the thought, from whatever source, that abstracts itself from
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0016
Veridical Hallucinations 167
few from that era of my life, returns to me unbidden, channeled along tracks
in my brain that are laid “deeper” with each reminiscence. The original expe-
rience grated on me, of course, no doubt from Freudian motives, but now it
returns for both personal and impersonal reasons.
While I did not discover a reciprocity between the Bergson siblings as a
ready-made fact, as I say, it was not entirely invented either. According to
Meghan McGuire, “although Moina and her brother did not agree on all phil-
osophical issues, there are frequent echoes of his theories in her words and
her actions within The Golden Dawn.” McGuire adds that the connections
between brother and sister are often quite subtle, such as in Mina Bergson’s
magic name, Vestigia Nulla Retrorsum, which, she claims, is “reminiscent of
her brother Henri’s philosophy of change, where the past is always present,
and the present is only a process of becoming.”6 Or, perhaps the resemblance
moves in the other direction or in both directions at once. Henri Bergson
frequently argued that, when an increasingly large number of probabilities,
no matter how improbable, begin to converge and interfere, there is cause
for certainty. So let me draw up a table (see Table 1) of the most obvious
concordances between the two protagonists of our story and look for this
convergence. Though these are not the “infinite number of coincidences” that
Henri Bergson spoke of as transforming the improbable into a certainty, they
are indicative of some parallelism, and even covariance.7
“Realism toward the Past” is listed on both sides of the table. Perhaps it
should be “my past” on Henri Bergson’s side. The “return to the past,” the
“reality of the past,” a sense of the “nearness” of the past within “the pre-
sent”: such ideas can be understood personally (as memory in Henri
Bergson), impersonally (the brain traces of objective science), or, dare we
say, transpersonally (suggested in Bergsonian pure memory and pure per-
ception, but fully implemented in Mina Bergson’s invocations).
Returning to Ellen Langer’s “Counter Clockwise Study,” it is easy enough
to think of this “memory house” as a Proustian space retrieving “lost time”
for us, a “time travel” within one’s own experience, one’s own memory alone.
And we can simply leave it at that—memory is subjective, it’s all in the head
after all. Supernormalization, by contrast, sees personal memory as a glimpse
of transpersonal “time travel,” a past (because there is no one thing behind
the expression, “the past”) restored through an expanded or “defragmented”
attention, be it formed voluntarily, involuntarily, or some mixture of the two.
Is it merely all “in your head”? Yes. Deflation. But the head is the brain—
the expansion can be objective, or at least differently “personal”: it involves
170 Vestiges of a Philosophy
selections performed through your brain part, your engram (this one, not that
one). Reinflation. External objects, props, visuals, sounds, and (“Proustian”)
spaces correlate with internal organs of “representation” centripetally, so to
speak (top-down); but also “spontaneously” (congenitally, bottom-up), me-
chanically, or chemically induced. Above and below. The (brain) part can
also mutate to excess and centrifugally affect the whole in a kind of dementia.
What J. W. Dunne, for one, thought of as real time travel within nth higher
dimensions of the brain becomes a real restoration of the past through phys-
ical mutation of brain cells, often life-threatening to the organism as a whole,
of course. Thought through the prism of scale, of macro-and micro-(and
a little anthropomorphism), one can say that these parts are attempting to
overtake the whole (which is also Henri Bergson’s definition of pain in Matter
and Memory).8 Destructive interference from the radicalized part, the mu-
tant, the cancer.
Veridical Hallucinations 171
a part, too: so it is partly real, yet not like everything else (everything else is
not like everything else either). In other words, all things are real but not in
any one way that makes all things the same. Not all things flow with the same
liquidity or speed, for instance (sometimes it pays to be bleedingly obvious).
That said, solid beliefs (and the beliefs of solids) are not entirely immovable
and impenetrable either, at least not in principle and at the appropriate level
or scale. Yet they are supremely enduring: once again, difference and same-
ness are matters of time rather than space.
One might conclude, therefore, that “heterogeneous continuity” (or co-
variance) is not so much a solution to any problem but simply a new name for
a perennial problem—of how past and present interact, and with that inside
and outside, spirit and matter. And this may well be true, though such con-
tinual renaming of a problematic, especially if the new name “sticks,” is also
the best we can hope for—it is as good as it gets. If the new name, and con-
comitant new conceptualizations of everything else around the name, do in-
deed stick, it should be because they form a varying, partial whole with a set
of other current problematics: ones concerning, say, the place of traditional
practices within the contemporary, the nature-culture divide, religion and
science, decolonizing knowledge, or posthuman and animal thought. It is a
name that is also a becoming-unproblematic, a dissolution rather than solu-
tion. And, like any arrival, that becoming is gradual.
* * *
It is in Creative Evolution that Henri Bergson offers an orientational reading
of life and matter, a duality of direction—“le physique soit simplement du
psychique inverti.” The physical is simply the psychical, inverted.15 Indeed,
Georges Canguilhem once redubbed Creative Evolution as equally a theory
of the “élan matérielle” were one simply to invert (but not in any way dismiss)
its arguments.16 Obvious wordplay aside, these inversions do capture some-
thing of the Mina-Henri bifurcation, one of methods and materials (mysti-
cism/philosophy, spiritualism/science) dovetailing from different “poles” of
the one “substance” (which is not a substance but a movement). This would
offer a shared vision of life and world united through temporality, the one op-
erating performatively to invoke and embody parts of the past directly in the
person of the priestess; the other, operating conceptually to explain my past
as immanent within a set of “larger,” stratified presents, accessed through an
expansion of attention. The difference is one of orientation (as when a rocket
Veridical Hallucinations 175
rotates to head back to its point of departure), one going from the past to my
past, the other from my past to the past.
The question that remains, therefore, is who of the two, Mina or Henri,
was really in the rocket while the other remained on earth.
Epilogue
The Whole of the Moon
According to Bergson (Henri), “the truth is that we shall never reach the past
unless we frankly place ourselves within it.”1 One aim of this work has been to
ask how literally we should take this statement. A little over twenty years ago,
I published an introduction to Henri Bergson’s philosophy that had, as one of
its declared aims, to retrieve his ideas from what I described then as the “phil-
osophical ghettos of ‘vitalism,’ ‘spiritualism’ and ‘psychologism.’ ”2 Perhaps,
in attempting to model a nonstandard philosophy using spiritualism as its
source material, all I have achieved here is a certain gentrification of those
ghettos, replacing their original residents with new, respectable types: Didn’t
you know that Plato was a mystic, too, as were these physicists? And what
these modern materialists say over there is very similar to this nonsense over
here (heck, even a Wykeham Professor of Logic at Oxford University, the late
Michael Dummet, wrote about the Tarot).
Understandably, I hope that such interpretations of this experiment will
be rare (though I do not delude myself into thinking that they will be non-
existent). The purpose of supernormalization is to show hetero-continuities
between the ordinary and the extraordinary, to show that something sup-
posedly unearthly is found in plain sight by looking at the earth (and even
its most disreputable denizens) with far more attention than it is usually
given. In the pairing of Henri and Mina, we see two allied attempts to natu-
ralize spirit and spiritualize matter at work, two inverse, yet covarying ways
of rethinking naturalism and spiritualism beyond deflation or inflation (they
are, in their different ways, both supernormal). The work of one of them was
well-acknowledged at the time and subsequently (Henri’s); the other, Mina’s,
has been lost to contemporary view for a good while, even as its performa-
tive, mystical, and artistic approach to spirit and matter has become all the
more timely.
Mina Bergson came from a respectable family and had a very famous, and
very respectable, brother. She did not lead a respectable life, however. Yet her
Vestiges of a Philosophy. John Ó Maoilearca, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197613917.003.0017
Epilogue 177
ideas and practices matched those of her closest relative both in breadth and
depth. Possibly even more so—there is still so much more to research and for
future scholars to unearth about both the Bergsons and their strange ideas
about spirit, matter, and, of course, time—especially the past and memory.
One might even say that Henri gave us the “special theory of the past and
memory” while Mina left us the “general theory.” Perhaps Henri knew this,
too. There is an odd passage near the middle of his 1911 essay on William
James’s pragmatism that, in retrospect, can be read in the light of much more
than its ostensible subject:
* * *
There is a song by The Waterboys that now seems appropriate to mention
by way of a final remark. “The Whole of the Moon” may, or may not, have
been playing at that house party in March 1990 when I tried to explain the
Bergsonian philosophy of time and memory—or at least Henri’s version of
it—to my interlocutor. Yet when Mike Scott sings “I was grounded /While
you filled the skies /I was dumbfounded by truth /You cut through lies,” it
seems like he must have been in the room, too. The lyrics continue to resonate
178 Epilogue
with the story of Mina and Henri, especially when the protagonist describes
how “I spoke about wings /You just flew /I wondered, I guessed, and I tried /
You just knew,” before ending with the perfectly astral conceit: “I saw the
crescent /You saw the whole of the moon.” The philosopher-mystic and the
mystic-philosopher, the part and the whole.
Notes
10. Paul Atkinson follows F. C. T. Moore in the view that we need to nuance our usual
understanding of “duration” in this regard: “F. C. T. Moore argues that the trans-
lation of durée as duration omits one of the other senses of the word as ‘the fact or
property of going through time’ or continuance and, consequently, he argues that
the English expression ‘durance’ is more suitable. Here the emphasis shifts from
the description of a temporal expanse to the movement inherent in time and what
it means to endure, for the continuity of time is actually felt as a continuance that is
irreducible to an external and measurable representation” (Atkinson 2020, p. 20).
1. My translation from Mauss 1968, p. 386: “Je crois que précisément il y a, même au
fond de tous nos états mystiques, des techniques du corps qui n’ont pas été étudiées. . . .
Je pense qu’il y a nécessairement des moyens biologiques d’entrer en ‘communication
avec le Dieu’.”
2. This is how Henri Bergson himself puts it: “The truth is that memory does not con-
sist in a regression from the present to the past, but, on the contrary, in a progression
from the past to the present. It is in the past that we place ourselves at a stroke. We
start from a ‘virtual state’ which we lead onwards, step-by-step, through a series of
different planes of consciousness, up to the goal where it is materialized in an actual
perception” (Bergson 1990, p. 239).
3. It is also claimed that such episodic (“autonoetic”) memory is specific to humans
(acquired about the age of four years): see Tulving 2005, pp. 4, 21. My thanks go to
Markus Rajala for this reference.
4. Langer 1989, p. 155, “The control group was told once again that they were to con-
centrate on the past. [ . . . ] In contrast, the orientation remarks for the experimental
group stressed that the best way to learn about the past may not be through simple
reminiscence. Rather, we should try to return as completely as possible in our minds
to that earlier time.”
5. “The experimental group as a whole improved while the control group’s performance
worsened somewhat over time” (Langer 1989, p. 163).
6. I do not pretend that this account of Proust’s position is the only tenable one, and I am
sure that much nuance could be added by Proustian scholars.
7. Bergson 1992, pp. 151–2.
8. Bergson 1975, pp. 69–70.
9. See Bergson 1911a, pp. 5, 6; in French, see Bergson 1959, pp. 498–9: “l’amoncellement
du passé sur le passé se poursuit sans trêve,” and then “c’est avec notre passé tout entier,
y compris notre courbure d’âme originelle, que nous désirons, voulons, agissons,”
followed by “de cette survivance du passé résulte l’impossibilité, pour une conscience,
de traverser deux fois le même état.” See also his Cours on memory (Bergson 2018,
pp. 32–33): “si nous pouvions la retrouver, nous serions transportés dans le passé;
nous revivrions notre passé” etc.
Notes 181
10. Bergson 1911a, p. 5. All emphases mine. Both Bertrand Russell and Jacques Maritain
specifically upbraided Henri Bergson for this conflation of memory with the past; see
Russell 1914, pp. 21–24; Maritain 1968, pp. 219–23, 231–36.
11. Grosz 2005, p. 3; Khandker 2020, p. 85; Perri 2017, p. 510 (citing François 2008, p. 30);
Mourélos 1964, p. 136.
12. de Warren 2015, p. 247. See also p. 248: “The pure or virtual past is not in me; on the
contrary, I live in the pure past.”
13. Bergson 1990, p. 230.
14. Hyppolite 2002, p. 112.
15. See Bachelard 1963. Conversely, one might say, with Leibniz, natura non facit saltus
(“nature does not make jumps”), of course: but this Leibnizian axiom of the spa-
tial plenum, where there are no breaks or cuts, can also be temporalized through
Bergsonism as the plenitude of creativity, the fullness of novelty, or the continuity of
change. Spatial cuts, be they affirmed (Bachelard) or denied (Leibniz), are no longer
opposed to continuity, once they are temporalized as heterogeneous continuity.
16. Perri 2017, p. 516.
17. McNamara 1999, p. 117.
18. Bergson 1990, p. 197; Bergson 1910, p. 101.
19. Naturally, then, if there is no universal time but only instead partial durations, any
feasible time travel would only concern local moments rather than encapsulate a uni-
versal slice of time—a certain “bubble” of activity within, say, “1912,” a part of 1912,
rather than “all” that happened within that calendar year—whatever “all” might be
imagined to mean here.
20. Bergson 1992 (“The Perception of Change”), pp. 143–4. The irony of this image of
moving trains is palpable given the importance of trains in Albert Einstein’s thought
experiments explaining his special theory of relativity, which Henri Bergson argues
confuses real time with space.
21. See Bergson 2018, p. 308.
22. In addition, after one foray into psychical research (a case of telepathy) early in his ca-
reer, Bergson immediately stopped all such enquiries for almost thirty years, probably
on the sound advice that this would hamper his academic career. We return to this
event later.
23. As will become clear, names and naming conventions are extremely important for
the practices of the Golden Dawn, and Mina herself had many names, both outside
the Golden Dawn and within it. This leads to some challenges for writing about her
life and work alongside that of her brother and husband. If I were to use her taken
surname, “Mathers,” in any discussion of an idea or practice, I would have to differ-
entiate between which Mathers (Samuel or “Moina”—her adopted forename in mar-
riage) was in question. Even more so, however, when discussing ideas belonging to
“Bergson,” it would be unclear if it is Henri or Mina who is in question. So I have de-
cided to use forename and surname for both her and her brother, “Mina Bergson” and
“Henri Bergson” whenever the context might not make it clear. Not only can this act
to reinforce their sibling relationship, it should also help to equalise their status within
this study as thinker-practitioners of equal value. Moreover, if I use the adjective
182 Notes
to his old inclinations, whereas I am not nearly so sure that I shall always stick to
mine. He has been through both experiments; I have only tried one. His repulsion
grows stronger as he fixes his attention on it, whereas my satisfaction is largely a
matter of inattention and tends to pale in a strong light. I do believe it would fade away
altogether, if decisive experiments came to prove, as it is not impossible they will, that
I am directly and slowly poisoning myself by eating meat.” It may well turn out that he
was correct. Bon appétit.
32. See Pattison and Kirkpatrick 2018 for a very respectable collection of essays on the
mystical sources of existentialism. For the Gnostic, or rather “Hermetic,” Hegel, see
Magee 2001. See also Ramey 2012, p. 234n on such readings: “certain post-Kantian
thinkers such as Hegel, Schelling, Novalis, and Josef Hoëné-Wronski were all strongly
influenced by esoteric traditions. As [Christian] Kerslake has now definitively
shown, this post-Kantian esoteric line had a profound influence upon Deleuze.” Such
enterprises can also be pursued for less edifying reasons, such as Peter Hallward’s Out
of This World (2006), the primary purpose of which was to damn Deleuze by associa-
tion with spiritualist ideas, and thereby (even more importantly) bury his philosophy
in advance of the emergence of Alain Badiou’s thought, which could thereby assert its
dominance within the Anglophone reception of contemporary French philosophy all
the more easily.
33. Ramey 2012, p. 10.
34. Gamble, Hanan, and Nail 2019, p. 111.
35. Gamble, Hanan, and Nail 2019, p. 116.
36. See the essays collected in The Routledge Handbook of Mechanisms and Mechanical
Philosophy (Glennan and Illari 2017). In particular, see the essay by Mark Povich
and Carl F. Craver, “Mechanistic Levels, Reduction, and Emergence” (Povich and
Craver 2017): p. 188: “In aggregates, the property of the whole is literally a sum
of the properties of its parts. The concentration of a fluid is an aggregation of
particles; allelic frequency is a sum of individual alleles. Aggregate properties
change linearly with the addition and removal of parts, they don’t change when
their parts are rearranged, and they can be taken apart and reassembled without
any special difficulty. This is because in true aggregates, spatial, temporal, and
causal organization are irrelevant. . . . Mechanisms, in contrast, are literally more
than the sums of their parts: they change non-linearly with the addition and re-
moval of parts, their behavior is disrupted if parts are switched out, and this is
because their spatial, temporal, and causal organization make a difference to how
the whole behaves.”
37. Coleman 2006, pp. 40–44; cited in Pinch 2014–15, p. 15.
38. Zammito 2017, pp. 309–10.
39. It was Ravaisson who showed how habit must be seen as spiritual rather than
mechanical.
40. See Edelman 1992, pp. 212–18. Oddly enough, Edelman cites W. B. Yeats’s “A Vision”
to show how even intelligent people can be attracted to the “spooky and mystical”
(p. 213). Yeats’s “A Vision” was dedicated to Mina Bergson.
184 Notes
41. See Delitz 2021, pp. 109–14 for an engagement with a new materialism that takes a
positive line on Bergson’s influence.
42. Adela Pinch, “The Appeal of Panpsychism in Victorian Britain,” p. 1.
43. Sommer McGrath 2020, p. 10.
44. Sommer McGrath 2020, p. 10.
45. Sommer McGrath 2020, pp. 15–16, 13.
46. Sommer McGrath 2020, p. 135.
47. Dunham 2020, pp. 1005, 988; Sinclair and Antoine-Mahut 2020, pp. 862, 863. Sinclair
and Antoine-Mahut also describe “two halves” (p. 857) of French spiritualism, one
dominated by Victor Cousin, with its “eclectic” mix of German idealism and Scottish
common-sense philosophy, and a more “positivist” spiritualism following Ravaisson
and the idea that biology has more in common with psychology than physics (p. 860).
48. Gayon 2005, p. 47.
49. Woods 2017, pp. 200–24.
50. Woods 2017, pp. 201–2.
51. Jankélévitch 2015, p. 257.
52. Jankélévitch 2015, p. 257.
53. Bergson 1992, p. 87. See also Bergson 2018, p. 198: “suivre un calcul, c’est le refaire pour
son propre compte.”
54. Bennett 2010, p. 154n26.
55. See Morrison 2007, p. 17.
56. Different occult societies had different hermetic grading systems, and the
Golden Dawn had ten grades using ten positions or divine emanations (“se-
phira”) on the Tree of Life (Malkuth, Kether, etc.). However, it is noticeable
that the numbers of the grade always add up to eleven rather than ten (3° = 8°
Practicus; 4° = 7° Philosophus, etc). This is because the Golden Dawn also
counted an extra step, “Daath” in the middle as a special position synthesizing
all of the sephira. Both this and the final three positions of the “third order”
(10° = 1° Ipsissimus, 9° = 2° Magus, and 8° = 3° Magister Templi) were only
achievable “in principle” as many argued that they were the unique prove-
nance of “astral beings,” or “Superieurs Inconnus”—t he “secret chiefs” guiding
the Order and instructing its leaders. Non-astral beings could progress no
further than 7° = 4° Adeptus Exemptus (which Mina Bergson did attain). The
equals sign, as mentioned, is not an equation but functions graphically. It can
be likened to the dividing line of the letter Aleph —אi ndicating a connection
upward and a connection downward, as well as a division. As such, it shows
how each side is linked to the ascent the student is working on and a de-
scent to where she began. A spiritual diagrammatology of sorts. My thanks to
Dr. Mark Price for these insights.
57. Malabou, Barad, and Bennett probably represent the most important and original fig-
ures among the first generation of new materialist thinkers, with second-generation
work being done by Felicity Colman, Iris van der Tuin, and others. Some of the newer
work is collected in the journal Matter: Journal of New Materialist Research.
58. See Laruelle 2013.
59. Hanegraaff 2008, p. 296.
Notes 185
1. Grogin 1988, p. 59n10. Grogin also notes that “spiritism” has an added
“reincarnationist component” over the English “spiritualism.”
2. Gayon 2005, p. 46.
3. Noakes 2014, p. 2.
4. Noakes 2014, pp. 1–2.
5. Noakes 2008, p. 11.
6. Morrison 2007, p. 63.
7. See Jones 2016, pp. 176–7.
8. See Jones 2016, pp. 135–6.
9. Jones 2016, p. 134.
10. Thurschwell 2001, p. 3.
11. Thurschwell 2001, p. 23.
12. Katz 1978, p. 22.
13. Katz 1978, pp. 38, 46.
14. Katz 1992, pp. 34n9, 15.
15. Jones 2016, p. 60.
16. Jones 2016, pp. 60, 59.
17. Forman 1990, p. 25.
18. Forman 1990, pp. 37–38.
19. Forman 1998, p. 29.
20. See Mullarkey 2004b.
21. Forman 1998, p. 32; Bergson 1992, p. 161.
22. Jones 2016, p. 173.
23. Luhrmann 1991, pp. 274–5.
24. This use of the term “supernormal” also contrasts starkly with the other contempo-
rary usage in biology and psychology that builds on Nikolaas Tinbergen’s pioneering
work in ethology: there, a supernormal stimulus is an exaggeration of a normal
condition, one sometimes eliciting maladaptive behavior—so the “super” is indeed
a real excess (see Barrett 2010). In our usage here, the emphasis is on ordinarizing
the “super” through a reinterpretation of the normal, bringing it back to earth, so to
speak, by enlarging our view of how the normal functions.
25. As Mina Bergson puts it in the Golden Dawn’s language, “Malkuth is in
Kether . . . Kether is in Malkuth” (Bergson/Mathers 2016c), p. viii.
simply allows its protagonist (“Richard Collier”) the supernatural ability to will him-
self to return to a distant past (partly also through self-hypnosis—mental time travel
in extremis as it were), in the book we are told that the hero has a brain tumor, leaving
it open that his entire experience was in fact only “in his head,” literally. Skeptical
work, such as seen in Shermer 2011, grasps this nettle by talking simply of “the
believing brain” or “believing neuron” when it comes to explaining belief in super-
natural or preternatural phenomena: belief in such patent falsehoods is itself a brain
phenomenon. Yet the existence of these clear cerebral correlations can be reoriented in
order to inflate the cerebral rather than deflate the phenomenal.
4. See Mullarkey 2004a; Ó Maoilearca 2015, chapter four.
5. Kelly et al. 2007, p. 72. See also p. 78: “To illustrate this view of our ordinary self as
a ‘segment’ of a larger Self, Myers used an analogy with the electromagnetic spec-
trum. Specifically, he suggested that the Individuality or larger Self can be thought
of as analogous to a ray of light which, when filtered through a prism, appears as a
continuum, or spectrum, of colors. Our ordinary waking consciousness corres-
ponds only to that small segment of the electromagnetic spectrum that is visible to
the naked eye (and varies from species to species); but just as the electromagnetic
spectrum extends in either direction far beyond the small portion normally visible
to us, so human consciousness extends in either direction beyond the small portion
of which we are ordinarily aware. In the ‘infrared’ region of consciousness are older,
more primitive processes—processes that are unconscious, automatic, and primarily
physiological. [ . . . ] Sleep, for example, and its associated psychophysiological pro-
cesses are an important manifestation of an older, more primitive state. . . . In contrast,
in the ‘ultraviolet’ region of the spectrum are all those mental capacities that remain
latent because they have not yet emerged at a supraliminal level through adaptive ev-
olutionary processes. In the ‘ultraviolet’ region, therefore, are those new modes of
functioning that appear rarely, fitfully, and briefly. They are the “super-conscious op-
erations. . . . ”
6. A passage of dialogue from the biopic of the animal scientist Temple Grandin, who is
not neurotypical, runs as follows:
Temple: “[People] keep on giving each other looks and I don’t know what
they mean.”
Eustacia (Temple’s mother): “People tell each other things with their eyes.”
Temple: “I will never learn how to do that”
(Temple Grandin, dir. Mick Jackson, 2010).
What appears mysterious, or even magical, clearly lies in the neural connections
of the beholder.
7. Delivering a phenomenon from the category of the supernatural, understood as a
projected hyperbolic discontinuity, into the supernormal, understood as many dif-
ferent or heterogeneous continuities, is also bound up with a conversion from only
seeing a phenomenon associatively (going from the parts to the whole) to seeing it
dissociatively (running from wholes to parts). At heart, then, these are two different
orientations in mereology when it is understood as a process.
8. Bergson/Mathers 2016c, p. viii, my italics.
Notes 187
8. Greer 1995, p. 42: “Although Mina saw little of the brother she idealized while growing
up, she was later to live near him in Paris for twenty-five years. It seems obvious that
with their mutual interest in aspects of the spirit and in psychology (Henri became
the president of the British Society for Psychical Research), they no doubt met often
for discussion and probably argued over their differing perspectives.”
9. Tereshchenko 1986, pp. 82–83.
10. Pasi 2009, p. 64.
11. For an articulation of something like this view, see Franklin 2018, p. 42: “Perhaps the
real point is to keep the ultimate source mysterious by ever pointing backward and
insisting that it only can be known to the fully initiated adept. This, after all, is the
strategy used to effect by the adepts of Theosophy, the Golden Dawn, and, for that
matter, the Church of Scientology, a more recent occult-scientific religion that rivals
the hybridity of its late nineteenth-century antecedents.”
12. The Golden Dawn invited individual adults as members, not minors nor indeed whole
families; its members came and went with relative ease; and the founding members
did not profit from the group’s activities—indeed, something closer to penury was
more often the norm. Whether or not contemporary new religious movements (aka
“cults”) actually conform to the antithesis of each of these characteristics (and the
prejudices of many toward them) is another matter altogether.
13. Pasi 2009, p. 65.
14. Greer 1995, pp. 13–14.
15. Greer 1995, p. 15. The theme of invisibility and power returns later.
16. See Hedenborg White 2021; Owen 1989.
17. Bergson/Mathers 2016c, p. viii. Of course, “materialization” is rich in meaning for
occultists, and its significance for both Bergson’s shall gradually manifest in what
follows.
18. This is how R. C. Grogin reports on Henri Bergson’s attitude: “What Bergson was
trying to do in large part in the generation following 1889 (and this only becomes
clear with the appearance of Creative Evolution in 1907) was validate esoteric ideas
through empirical and rational means. This was why he rejected the more ex-
treme forms of the occult in favour of the empirical methods of psychical research.
According to his brother-in-law, MacGregor Mathers, Bergson was not the least bit
interested in magic” (Grogin 1988, p. 43). Grogin’s last point oversteps the mark, how-
ever, especially since Henri Bergson’s The Two Sources spends so much effort elabo-
rating a sociobiological account of the origins of magical thinking.
19. Le Doeuff 2002, pp. 107–8.
20. Herring 2019, p. 10.
21. Herring 2019, p. 3.
22. Herring 2019, pp. 5–6.
23. Cariou 1976, p. 226.
24. See Jantzen 1998.
25. See Deleuze 1988. To a lesser extent Deleuze’s two Cinema books in the mid-1980s
helped to maintain this impression, especially in Film Studies.
Notes 189
26. Significant works by these authors include Mossé-Bastide 1959; Mossé-Bastide 1955;
Barthelemy-Madaule 1966; Kremer-Marietti 1953; Delhomme 1954; and Cariou
1990. This is not to reduce the important role of male commentators in this period,
such as Leon Husson, Jean-Claude Pariente, Henri Gouhier, Georges Mourélos, or
Alex Philonenko—the Henri Bergson bibliography is so huge (with over three thou-
sand items up to 1986 and probably in excess of a thousand more since then) that a
numerical majority of works by male philosophers in almost inevitable given the sys-
temic biases against women in academia both before and after World War II: but this
makes the relatively large representation of women among the best secondary litera-
ture all the more striking.
1. See McNamara 1999, p. 11. See also Michaelian 2016, p. 5: “In psychology, Tulving has
influentially dubbed this form of memory episodic (Tulving 1972, 1983). . . . Episodic
memory refers, roughly, to the form of memory responsible for allowing us to revisit
specific episodes or events from the personal past. It is typically contrasted with se-
mantic memory, which allows us to recall facts without necessarily giving us access to
the episodes in which they were learned.” Procedural memory is “the kind of memory
at work when one learns a new behavior or skill” (p. 26).
2. Bergson 1990, p. 145.
3. McNamara 1999, p. 122.
4. Hacking 1998, p. 201.
5. Perri 2017, p. 516.
6. Perri 2017, p. 516.
7. Bergson 2018, p. 309.
8. See Bergson 1975, pp. 70–71, on how the brain keeps our attention pointing forward
and on life.
9. Sartre 2012, p. 51.
10. Plato 1997, p. 212.
11. Ricoeur 2006, p. 426. Cited in ter Schure 2020, p. 128.
12. ter Schure 2020, p. 128.
13. As first revealed through animal experiment: see Bickle 2017, pp. 34–47.
14. Barbour 2000, p. 105.
15. ter Schure 2020, p. 128.
16. ter Schure 2020, p. 128. For Bergson’s own discussion of Aristotle on memory, see his
lectures on the history of theories of memory given at the Collège de France in 1904
(Bergson 2018, pp. 255ff).
17. Russell 1921, pp. 159–60.
18. For a contemporary version of Russell’s presentism, we need only turn to Julien
Barbour’s cosmology (Barbour 2000): see Marchesini 2018 for a Bergsonian critique
of Barbour’s “Platonian” notion of “special Nows” or “time capsules.”
190 Notes
Three: Hyper-Ritual
1. Apart from appearing in David Fenton’s novel The Ghost Club (2014), an earlier
novel by F. Gwynplaine MacIntyre, The Woman Between the Worlds (2000), and artist
Lindsay Seers’s installation Nowhere Less Now (2012), her only other modern appear-
ance that I have found is a very odd one in an online fan page (“wiki”) for the video
game, Assassin’s Creed: https://assassinscreed.fandom.com/wiki/Moina_Mathers. We
examine Seers’s engagement in the Practicus covariant.
2. There is also a fourth, technical Flying Roll by Mina Bergson, “No.31, Correspondence
between Enochian and Ethiopian Alphabets,” which is of less interest. More signifi-
cant is a joint interview from 1900, “Isis Workshop in Paris,” between Frederic Lees
and Samuel and Mina, a.k.a., Hierophant Rameses and the High Priestess Anari,
which holds some interesting information. There is also some surviving personal cor-
respondence; though, from what I have seen of it thus far, these hold less interest for
general readers.
3. Bogdan 2008, p. 251.
4. See Luhrmann 1991, p. 268: the “ ‘Middle Pillar’ is a term used by Golden Dawn
students (and their descendants) to describe the balanced use of the kabbalah, along
the central core of the Tree of Life—Malkuth, Yesod, Tiphareth, Kether. The term is
often shorthand for a balanced, integrated approach to life and its problems.”
Notes 193
5. The link between modern performance theory and ritual, religious or secular, is un-
controversial, going back to Richard Schechner’s “broad spectrum” approach in the
1970s whereby “any action that is framed, presented, highlighted, or displayed is a
performance” (see Schechner 2002, pp. 1–2). The hyper-rituals of the Golden Dawn
could then be seen as hyper-performative, a further extension of the spectrum into
different space-times (allegedly).
6. See Schechner 2002; Turner 1986.
7. As might time travel be understood: the suspension of disbelief or acting as if it
were 1912.
8. Yeats 1978, p. ix.
9. In Kabbalah the most intricate of the divine names comprises seventy-two letters, but
the letters in varying combinations can become seventy-two names as well.
10. See Greer 1995, p. 357.
11. Grogin 1988, p. 40. Coincidently, Henri Bergson’s lecture rooms were also covered in
offerings of flowers from his adoring audiences, at least at the height of his fame; see
Antliff 1993, p. 99.
12. Oddly enough, despite a certain gender bias toward male mysticism in The
Two Sources, Bergson’s actual examples are more often than not female—St.
Teresa, St. Catherine of Sienna, Joan of Arc, etc. Published four years after
his sister’s death, one might also wonder about the effect her death had on its
composition.
13. Bergson/Mathers 1987, p. 155. One clear example of this activity lies in the fact that
both Henri and Mina were very active during the First World War, Henri partici-
pating early on in a number of diplomatic missions to the United States in order to
convince Woodrow Wilson to join the Allies in the war, while Mina and Samuel
transformed their home in Paris into an army recruitment center, which, according
to W. B. Yeats, succeeded in recruiting six hundred Americans and Britons living in
France (see Greer 1995, p. 349).
14. Bergson/Mathers 1987, p. 158.
15. Bergson/Mathers 2016c, pp. vii–viii.
16. Bergson 1990, p. 17—my emphases. It is notable that Macgregor Mathers, in his
1900 interview with Lees, claimed that “the universe . . . [is] a great eidolon [image or
ideal].” Mina Bergson will later use this term when discussing imagination.
17. Bergson 1911a, pp. 197, 210.
18. From Greer’s citation of Lees, Greer 1995, pp. 208–9.
19. Kolakowski 1985, pp. 37–38; Pilkington 1976, p. 7. Mourélos writes (1964, p. 103): “we
absolutely agree with M. Jankélévitch declaration that, of all of Bergson’s works,
Matter and Memory is the most brilliant.”
3. See Hude 1989–1990: the “hypothesis” of Hude’s eccentric study is that there is a
“spiritualist Bergson from the start” (vol. I, p. 19) and even that “the problem of god”
is Bergson’s continual problem (vol. II, p. 185).
4. Jankélévitch 2015, p. 228.
5. Jankélévitch 2015, p. 227.
6. Bergson 1990, pp. 184, 185.
7. Bergson 1992, p. 190; see Moore 1996.
8. Grogin 1988, p. 61n31. He continues, “Bergson once acknowledged that he had taken
instruction in Hebrew, but was quite clear in maintaining that he had ignored the
Kabbala. Nevertheless, critics have insisted that the connection exists.”
9. Murdoch 1999, p. 225.
10. Hutton 1999, p. 82. For the Golden Dawn as a syncretic” or “hybrid” religion, see
Franklin 2018, p. 185.
11. See Hanegraaff 2020, p. 78: “A large-scale empirical study directed by Heinz Streib
and Ralph W. Hood has demonstrated that the term “spirituality” is broadly under-
stood today as referring to the practice of what they call “privatized, experience-
oriented religion. . . . Hence it refers to types of religion that (1) are focused on the
individual rather than the collective, (2) are concerned with the cultivation of per-
sonal experience(s) more than with legal or doctrinal matters, and (3) emphasize
praxis over belief.”
12. Franklin 2018, p. 154. It is Michael Bevir who coined the term “Victorian and
Edwardian immanentism” (Bevir 2011, p. 22).
13. See Bergson 1972, p. 1528.
14. Owen 2004, pp. 135, 136, my emphases.
15. Owen 2004, p. 136.
16. Bergson 1977, p. 194n.
17. For more on Underhill’s time in the Golden Dawn, see Armstrong 1975, pp. 36ff. Her
1907 “A Defence of Magic,” was reprinted in its majority in her key work, Mysticism in
1911, though by that time some of her initial belief in mystical magic had waned.
18. James 2015, p. 181.
19. Bergson 1977, p. 148.
20. Bergson 1977, p. 140.
21. In 1939, Sartre would generalize this idea in Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions
to make the function of all emotion a magical transformation of the world. See
Sartre 2001.
22. Bergson 1977, p. 141.
23. Bergson 1977, pp. 141, 146.
24. See Mullarkey 2007.
25. See Bergson 1975, p. 11 “consciousness is coextensive with life.” That matter also
endures is a major thesis of Matter and Memory and Creative Evolution.
26. We will return to the question of probability and chance when discussing the Tarot at
the conclusion of the Practicus covariant later.
27. Caygill (2013, pp. 256–7) links hyperaesthesia and panoramic vision thus: the one
operates in space, the other in time: “His most telling example is the panoramic view
Notes 195
of the past that is evoked in a moment of mortal danger. This is not the spatialization
of time, but the phenomenon of hyperaesthesia assuming its temporal dimension in
memory. [. . . ] A new attention to life thus emerges, one not restricted to voluntary
action and oriented ahead, but which assumes the complex nexus of past, present and
future that constitutes the monad.” See also Bergson 2018, pp. 132–3.
28. In 1901 (twelve years before his address to the Society for Psychical Research),
Henri Bergson records his participation in the “Groupe d’études des phénomènes
psychiques,” whose task was to look at “psychic phenomena”; see Bergson 1972,
pp. 511–12. His 1903 report talks of radiation and psychic phenomena (Bergson
1972, pp. 606–9). Grogin (1988, pp. 51–52) discusses the case of “Eusapia Palladino”
who was “tested in forty-three seances which were conducted between 1905 and
1908. She was examined at various times by a distinguished company of physicists,
psychologists and physiologists who included Professors Richet, Ballet, Courtier and
Madame Curie of the Sorbonne, and D’Arsonval, Perrin and Bergson of the Collège
de France. On several occasions Bergson and Madame Curie were the controllers—
they held Eusapia’s hands to insure against cheating.” Henri Bergson was skeptical of
her performance as genuine. He records these sessions in Bergson 1972, pp. 673–4.
Grogin also notes (1988, p. 65n85) that Henri Bergson was a member of the “Thirteen
Club,” which met on the thirteenth of each month to discuss psychic matters. Its
other members included Charles Richet, Eugène Osty (director of the Institut
métapsychique internationale), Emile Boirac, and Flammarion. See also de Mille
2022, p. 2. In fact, Henri Bergson’s interest in psychic phenomena goes back as far
as 1886, as we will see later, but he held it at a distance from his public research work
until 1913.
29. Caygill 2013, p. 250.
30. Bergson 1992, p. 32.
31. See Evrard 2021 for an overview of Bergson’s undulating public enthusiasm (or “une
certaine ambiguïté,” p. 249) toward psychical research throughout his career, espe-
cially in the light of his more positive private investigations in the area, which some
have even described as an “open secret” in certain French academic circles.
32. See van Gemert and Eland 2021.
33. Bergson 1975, p. 82. Henri Bergson, quoting an interlocutor who told him the story
of this vision, only says that the officer died “in an engagement”; but from the details
of his own discussion of the case thereafter, it is clear that it was an engagement on a
battlefield.
34. Bergson 1975, p. 85, my emphasis. Not that telepathy is discounted as a myth by Henri
Bergson, but, as always, its putative reality will need to be naturalized: see Bergson
1975, pp. 79–80. See also Barnard 2012a, pp. 239ff: Barnard ruminates on the possi-
bility that a “radio reception” or “filter theory” of consciousness fits Henri Bergson’s
approach best, and would allow him to think of telepathy as real (p. 239): for “Bergson,
it is quite likely that telepathic communication between minds still does take place
‘under the radar’ almost continuously, not just for especially gifted psychics, but for
everyone (in much the same way that radio or television waves are ubiquitous).”
35. Bergson 1975, p. 86.
196 Notes
1. Lees 1900.
2. From Greer’s citation of Lees, see Greer 1995, pp. 208–9.
3. Bergson 1911a, p. 142.
4. Bergson 1992, p. 119.
5. Bergson 1992, p. 109.
6. Bergson 1992, p. 119.
7. Bergson 1992, p. 121.
8. And this survival is no less true of Henri Bergson himself, as Jankélévitch said
(Jankélévitch 2015, p. 257)—“it is Bergsonian to look in the direction he shows,” not
to reproduce his ideas as he wrote them.
9. Riquier 2009, pp. 43–44, 35–37. All translations mine.
Notes 197
10. Riquier 2009, pp. 43–44. Italics mine. For more on the centrality of images in general
for Henri Bergson’s method and philosophy, see Podoroga 2014, pp. 129ff.
11. Bergson 1992, p. 168.
12. Riquier 2009, pp. 43–44. Italics mine. See Szerszynski 2021, p. 16 for an interesting
take on Bergsonian individuation in terms of “colloidal social theory” (colloids are
substances such as foams, powders, or gels that exhibit macroscale physical proper-
ties that go beyond the binary of solid or liquid): “a colloidal social theory can help us
to be more sensitive to the animacy and sociality of matter and materials. Thinking in
and across the whole family of colloidal species and their subspecies provides a frame-
work for understanding and relating a wide range of material powers and behaviours.
In the substance of the colloid, what Bergson called the élan vital derives its creativity
by dividing itself not into individual entities and lineages, or into life’s explosive force
and the resistance of matter, but into solid and fluid, continuous and dispersed, and
across causal domains at different spatial scales.”
13. Bergson 1977, pp. 152, 176.
14. Bergson 1977, pp. 152–3, translation altered. Italics mine.
15. Bergson 1977, p. 153.
16. Bergson/Mathers 2016b.
17. Wallace 2001, p. 181.
18. My italics. Yetzirah is the third of four worlds in the Kabbalistic Tree of Life. Assiah is
the fourth, an active realm incorporating the world of sensation and the unseen ener-
gies of matter.
19. See Neimanis 2017 for a contemporary use of “bodies of water” as the mediating
image for a feminist and posthumanist phenomenology.
20. See Barnard 2012b, p. 295: “Seen from a Bergsonian perspective, we are (subcon-
sciously) connected with the entire universe and the apparent clear-cut separa-
tion between objects is not ontologically real but instead is created by the filtering
mechanisms of the brain as well as by unconscious, deeply engrained patterns of
memory and belief. Given this alternate set of metaphysical assumptions, then, it
makes sense to posit that different spiritual disciplines (e.g., chanting, fasting, medi-
tation, dancing, ritualized ingestion of sacred plants, and so on) simply serve to open
up the inner floodgates in a ritually controlled and culturally sanctioned fashion,
allowing practitioners to more easily and effectively absorb and integrate the pow-
erful information that is pouring into them from different currents of the ocean of the
ever-changing images that make up the universe as we know it.”
21. Bergson 1992, p. 34. See Mullarkey 1999a, chapter eight.
22. Bergson 1977, pp. 61–62.
23. I am obviously referring here to the ideas of Richard Dawkins and Richard Semon
(meme/mneme theory) and Deleuze and Guattari (affect theory), respectively.
24. For the remake as a reinvention of form or movement rather than content, see Ó
Maoilearca 2015.
25. Though as we will see, movement is general (as quantity) and individual (as quality) at
different levels (“above” or “below”).
26. Santayana 1913, p. 87.
198 Notes
2° = 9° Theoricus Covariant
1. Flusser 2000, p. 9.
2. Flusser 2000, p. 66.
3. Resurgam 1987, p. 47.
4. Bergson/Mathers 2016a.
5. Godwin 2017, p. 467.
6. Bergson/ Mathers 2016a. Anyone in any way familiar with Henri Bergson’s
“Introduction to Metaphysics” of 1903 (Bergson 1992, pp. 159–200) will recognize a
similar dialectic of intuition and intellect here.
7. Bergson/Mathers 2016a.
8. Bergson/Mathers 2016a.
9. See Brang et al. 2010. Both an artist and occultist (like Mina Bergson), Pamela
Colman Smith was also the most famous actual synesthete member of the Golden
Dawn, using this faculty in her artistic and spiritual practices (see Denisoff 2019a).
Paul Atkinson discusses Kandinsky from a Bergsonian point of view at Atkinson
2020, pp. 215–16, and especially, p. 52: a “debt to Bergson” may have also “inspired
some of the ideas in Wassily Kandinsky’s Concerning the Spiritual in Art, in particular
when he talks about the importance of the ‘vital impetus,’ in which the artist as part of
a spiritual avant-garde is guided by ‘feeling’ as they strive toward the ‘immaterial.’ ”
10. Bergson/Mathers 2016a.
11. Bergson/Mathers 2016a.
12. Bergson/Mathers 2016a.
13. See Bergson 1992, p. 42; see also Bergson 2018, pp. 225–6 on the essential obscurity of
“movement” and how any clarity and distinction brought to its analysis must involve
its spatialization.
14. “Entretiens avec Lydie Adophe,” p. ix; cited in Riquier, p. 35.
15. See Mullarkey 1999a, pp. 241–2. See Bergson 1992, p. 43: “Let us not be duped by
appearances: there are cases in which it is imagery in language which knowingly
expresses the literal meaning, and abstract language which unconsciously expresses
itself figuratively. The moment we reach the spiritual world, the image, if it merely
seeks to suggest, may give us the direct vision, while the abstract term, which is spa-
tial in origin and which claims to express, most frequently leaves us in metaphor.” In
Notes 201
Bergson 1972, p. 980, Henri Bergson says that metaphors should be taken seriously,
that is, nonmetaphorically.
16. Bergson 1990, pp. 133–4. Remember that “attitude” means something closer to “pos-
ture” for Henri Bergson.
17. In later works, like “The Perception of Change,” this “survival” is rerendered as an
indivisibility—the indivisible continuity within different levels of duration (and their
related levels of “condensation” of, or “attention” to, temporal change or passage). This
is why our earlier analysis of Henri Bergson’s interpretation of a case of telepathy in
“Phantasms of the Living and Psychical Research” equated pure perception with astral
projection, whereas here we compare the plane of pure memory with the astral plane.
In truth, these two equations can themselves be merged because memory and percep-
tion become indivisible in Henri Bergson’s later work—just as the past and the pre-
sent become nominal: they are things we call “past” and “present” depending on our
degree of attention to life. That said, there is already an earlier version of this striated
version of duration in the fourth chapter of Matter and Memory, which puts much
more emphasis on what unites the different planes (condensation or tension) and not
what divides them (as in the first and third chapters on perception and memory, re-
spectively, as separated temporal modalities). Vladimir Jankélévitch goes so far as to
say that the fourth chapter of Matter and Memory contradicts the rest of the book.
I would not go that far: it simply takes the first steps toward cosmologizing the more
first-person perspective of the earlier chapters (that later work would elaborate, as
psyche leaves the human ego to enter the nonhuman world as movement).
18. Bergson 1990, p. 132.
19. Mullarkey 2006, chapter five.
20. “Flashing Tablets” should also be mentioned here. These were talismans, magical
objects, often decorated in complementary colors and with divine names, or symbols,
that had special powers that would aid in invocations or evocations.
21. See McGuire 2017, p. 24, who argues that “due to Yeats’s relationship with Mina
Bergson and the Order of the GD, he was exposed to Bergsonian ideas long before he
read and studied the philosopher’s work for himself.” Moreover, “in addition to the
diagrams of cones and gyres scattered throughout Yeats’s copy of Matter and Memory,
his annotations suggest that the poet found an interesting correlation between
Bergson’s complex understanding of memory and his own representation of the Four
Principles” (p. 59). The four principles are “Spirit, Celestial Body, Husk, and Passionate
Body.” See also Yeats 1978, p. xi: “The symbolic forms of psychic geometry projected in
VA [A Vision, 1925 edition] were not in fact based primarily on Plato or Swedenborg
or others of the classical writers Yeats liked to cite but rather on the experiments and
thinking of his many friends and fellow students, first in the Hermetic Order of the
Golden Dawn and more significantly in the Society for Psychical Research.” This is
especially true of the vortices, gyres, or cones (p. 31n129).
22. Similar documents from Golden Dawn members can be found at the Museum of
Witchcraft and Magic, at Boscastle, Cornwall. Other archival materials are reputed
to exist in San Francisco, New York, and Geneva, though I have yet to gain access to
them. There are also at least three private collections concerning the Golden Dawn
202 Notes
which are held by individuals wishing to remain anonymous and are difficult for
scholars to access. See Gilbert 1987, pp. 163–68.
23. Pamela Colman Smith, artist, synesthete, and Golden Dawn member, was also re-
sponsible for the artwork in the classic Waite-Smith Tarot deck; see Denisoff 2019a,
pp. 146–64.
24. It is notable that Mina Bergson retains her maiden name in this illustration from
1898. She translated some of Fiona Macleod’s (William Sharp’s) poetry, including
“The Melancholy of Ulad.” Sharp was also a member of the Golden Dawn. The aqua-
relle work here, a painting with thin, transparent (rather than opaque) watercolors,
appears to be an advertisement for a staging of a fragment of the poem. Mina planned
several such stagings, including ones of Yeats’s works (having translated Yeats’s early
play The Land of Heart’s Desire, she apparently planned a production of it in Paris in
1898). See Yeats 1977, pp. 42–43.
25. Yeats 1977, p. 43.
26. De Mille 2022, p. 16. Citing Greer (1995, p. 225), De Mille notes how Mina Bergson
wrote to Yeats stating that she “had to abandon any idea of an independent career in
that direction, to be kept busy not only with the techniques of magic itself but with the
techniques of art in magic’s service.”
27. Bennett 2010, p. 35.
28. In addition, the group that Samuel and Mina founded after the Golden Dawn, the
“Rosicrucian Order of the Alpha et Omega,” placed great emphasis in its name on
what Mina calls the “living images” of all religions, the Rose, Cross, Lily, and Lotus.
The image of the Rose is crucial for Mina Bergson—“its mysterious centre, its nu-
cleus, the central Sun, is a symbol of the infinite and harmonious separations of
nature”—and it appears throughout the visual occulture of Alpha et Omega. See
Bergson/Mathers 2016c, pp. ix–x.
29. The vibratory is essential to invocation, as Nicolas Tereshchenko points out
(Tereshchenko 1986, pp. 85–86): “The most important rituals of invocation are also
the quite essential training towards the supreme moment of eventual Union with the
One Creator. For this to become possible, and before daring to attempt it, everything
must change in the aspirant. More precisely and specifically, the vibratory rate of all
his bodies must become considerably higher than man’s usual rate, approaching the
high frequency of vibrations of the Absolute Being. Through the prescribed rituals,
exercises and prayers . . . little by little the vibratory rate of the practicing magician
rises through the frequent and intimate contact with the invoked ‘god–forms’ of
Egyptian and other Divinities.”
30. See Bergson/Mathers, “Flying Roll No.31.” See also the W. B. Yeats online archive at
https://my.matterport.com/show–mds?mls=1&m=CfD9eU6iPhf (accessed July 24,
2021): “Adepts of the Golden Dawn practised the ‘Enochian Magic’ developed by the
Elizabethan magician Dr. John Dee and his medium Edward Kelly, revealed to them
by angels and using an angelic language supposedly first given to the patriarch Enoch
by the angel Ave. Words from this language of the angels were used in Golden Dawn
ceremonies, referred to as Enochian calls. The structure of the Enochian system was
based upon a cipher of numerological and set permutations of elements arranged on
Notes 203
a grid of letters called the Enochian Tablets. From these elemental tablets were de-
rived the names of various elemental powers, angels, beings, and spiritual dominions
known as Aethyrs.”
31. MacGregor Mathers, “Flying Roll No.12, Telesmatic Images and Adonai.”
32. Bergson 1975, pp. 56–59.
33. Bergson 1992, pp. 86–87. It is undoubtedly disappointing that its title La pensée et le
mouvant was translated in English as The Creative Mind.
1. See the section, Vestigia Nulla Retrorsum: “Leave no Trace” for an explanation of this.
2. Bergson 1992, p. 145.
3. Valiaho 2010, pp. 17, 60.
4. Moore 1993, p. 166. Paul Atkinson points out (Atkinson 2020, p. 17) that Bergson
“formulated the theory of durée, his response to the philosophy of the Eleatics,
while taking a walk during his tenure at Clermont-Ferrand” and that “according to
Chevalier, in 1926 Bergson complained that he was beginning to have problems with
his movement and claimed that this also affected his thought. Bergson was someone
who liked to move around while thinking and while teaching, and he did not like the
way that the École normale and the Collège de France limited his movement” (p. 13).
5. Gamble, Hanan, and Nail 2019, p. 125.
6. Bergson 1911a, p. 232.
7. As Khandker (2020, p. 161n6) points out with regard to Charles Hartshorne’s
“psychicalism”: “Hartshorne defends this position as a ‘true physicalism.’ It is not
simply that he is a ‘spiritualist’ or idealist, but that what we understand physicality
and spatial position to be require reformulation: ‘If physical means spatial then
mentalism or psychicalism is physicalism, for space is how sentient beings have
neighbors (Peirce) with whom they react, and their basic operations (Whitehead) are
prehensions, feelings of (others) feelings.’ ”
8. Bergson 1977, pp. 79–80: “If telepathy be a real fact, it is a fact capable of being re-
peated indefinitely. I go further: if telepathy be real, it is possible that it is operating
at every moment and everywhere, but with too little intensity to be noticed, or else in
such a way that a cerebral mechanism stops the effect, for our benefit, at the very mo-
ment at which it is about to clear the threshold of consciousness. . . . if telepathy be real,
it is natural” [“si la télépathie est réelle, elle est naturelle”].
9. See Grogin 1988, pp. 42–43, 61n36.
10. See Ó Maoilearca 2019a.
11. Hacking 1998, p. 143. Earlier we heard William James not only call Henri Bergson a
“magician” but his book Creative Evolution “a marvel.” That the Bergsonian approach
to evolution, being neither mechanist nor finalist, has never found a natural home
within standard evolutionary theory or its standard antitheses, makes calling it a
“marvel” all the more prescient, given Hackings description here.
204 Notes
4° = 7° Philosophus Covariant
4. Denisoff 2014, p. 9. We saw Greer 1995 (p. 15) also connect power with invisibility.
5. Horace, Epistles, I, i, 75.
6. Greer 1995, p. 358.
7. Schneider 2011, p. 102.
8. See Bergson’s lecture on memory from January 29, 1904 (Bergson 2018, pp. 116–17,
119) on the importance of distinguishing between “impersonal memories” and mem-
ories that belong to my own personal experience. This seemingly fatuous distinction
(don’t all memories belong to some person by definition?) covers an important point
about “actualization”: nearer the plane of pure memory and unrecollected, memories
belong to my past, which is really present, in embryo so to speak. Once recollected or
actualized, memories come closer to an impersonal, or public, sharable perception—a
memory-image that is not so much mine, that is, belonging to my past reality, my
past-time (or “event” as Bergson puts it at one point—p. 125), as one that, though
dated and signed as mine, is nonetheless now a common currency, an impersonal
memory (of mine). He also describes it as a process of “interference” (p. 129) between
different personal memories as they actualize, erasing or “neutralizing” (p. 134) some
of their individual personality as they move from subjectivity to objectivity (p. 129). It
is the difference between what has not yet manifested and what has manifested.
9. We have already referred to the Cours on memory (Bergson 2018) a number of times
in these notes. The lecture scripts are not Henri Bergson’s originals (he forbade any
posthumous publication of his private notes and correspondence) but have been
reconstructed from professionally typed notes taken during his courses at the behest
of the poet and essayist Charles Péguy, a devotee of Bergson.
10. See Bergson 2018, p. 123. More generally, the editor of the 1903–4 Cours, Arnaud
François, refers to how the lectures build on Bergson’s positions in Matter and
Memory, noting in particular a third form of recognition being added to the auto-
matic (or inattentive) and attentive forms discussed in the 1896 book—“recognition
through movements of imitation” (echoing Bergson’s frequent statement that to un-
derstand something is to remake or reinvent it for ourselves). This theory of three
kinds of recognition then becomes a “general concept of mental life” through “planes
of consciousness” (just as in Matter and Memory). See François 2018, p. 12.
11. Bergson 2018, pp. 127, 138.
12. These schemata—first introduced in Bergson’s 1902 article “Intellectual Effort”—are
dynamic, imageless ideas that organize our memories as they descend from RR,”
ferrying them from virtual life back to actual life (see Bergson 1975, pp. 186–230).
Each schema is a guiding model for constructing mental images as they are actual-
ized in perception, neither particular nor universal, but capable of mediating between
memory-images and perception. Though Bergson says that such dynamic schema
are “not easy to define” (Bergson 1975, p. 196), he nonetheless explains how a set of
images must be “reconstructed” through these schema in order to “meet” a percep-
tion (Bergson 1975, p. 208). Sounding at times like a Kantian idea, at other times a
Husserlian one, the schema is a “meaning” that “guides us in the reconstruction of
forms and sounds,” and thereby informs recognition. Though the schema is an aid to
the subdivision and coordination of images as they come closer to a perception, it is
208 Notes
itself not an image. Bergson gives the example of the peculiar ability of chess masters
to remember the state of play of several chessboards at once: “the players all agreed
that a mental vision of the pieces themselves would be more disturbing to them than
useful” (Bergson 1975, pp. 207, 197–8). Rather, it is the chess piece’s function or
meaning that is paramount.
13. Bergson 2018, pp. 127, 138.
14. Bergson 2018, p. 128.
15. The full quotation goes as follows (Bergson 1975, p. 118): “. . . souls dwell in the
world of the Ideas. Incapable of acting, and moreover not even thinking of acting,
they lie at rest above time outside space. But, among bodies, there are some which
by their form respond more than others to the aspirations of certain souls. And,
among souls, there are some which find their own likeness, so to say, in certain
bodies. The body, unfinished, as it has been left by nature, rises towards the soul
which can give it complete life. And the soul, looking down on the body and per-
ceiving it as the reflexion of itself in a mirror, is fascinated, leans forward and falls.
This fall is the beginning of life. I may liken these detached souls to the memo-
ries lying in wait in the depth of the unconscious, and the bodies to our sensations
during sleep. Sensation is warm, coloured, vibrant and almost living, but vague;
memory is clear and distinct, but without substance and lifeless. Sensation longs for
a form into which to solidify its fluidity; memory longs for matter to fill it, to bal-
last it, in short, to realize it. They are drawn towards each other; and the phantom
memory, materializing itself in sensation which brings it flesh and blood, becomes a
being which lives a life of its own, a dream.”
16. Bergson 1975, pp. 116–17.
17. In the French (Bergson 1959, p. 886), the line goes, “dans la nuit de l’inconscient, une
immense danse macabre.” The translator of the lecture, H. Wildon Carr, notes, how-
ever, that not only was this translation authorized by Henri Bergson, it was also a
collaborative effort. Bergson was bilingual, so the deliberate choice to translate the
French “une immense danse macabre” as something quite different (“a wild phantas-
magoric dance”) is revealing.
18. Lacroix 1943, p. 197n1.
19. Bergson 1972, pp. 1588–89.
20. See Soulez and Worms 1997, p. 36.
21. Jankélévitch 2015, p. 257.
3° = 8° Practicus Covariant
1. Halpern 2018.
2. Halpern 2018.
3. Halpern 2018.
4. Barad’s chosen pronoun is “they.”
5. Gamble, Hanan, and Nail 2019, p. 123.
Notes 209
37. For more on backbone memories (or “continuities”), see Wills 2008 and
Moynihan 2019.
38. Valery 1976, p. 65; Badiou 2005; Laruelle 2013, pp. 148–9. Alongside Valery et al.,
Einav Katan (Katan 2016), provides an updated example of what Laruelle means by
such philosophical appropriation, a “salvation” of dance that sublimates it into “this
superior choreography that is philosophy.” Katan writes: “expression generates a sur-
plus and its ideas go beyond the intentionality of a dancer and/or a choreographer.
Along with its actual rhythm of development, an expression conveys an illusion; it
becomes a gesture with a semblance that transgresses its actuality” (p. 194). See also
Cvejić (2015), who uses Bergson to interesting effect.
39. Lindsay Seers’s Nowhere Less Now was an Artangel commission that ran from
September 8 to October 21, 2012, at The Tin Tabernacle in London. The interview
with Aesthetica Magazine can be found at http://www.aestheticamagazine.com/blog/
lindsay-seers-nowhere-less-now-london/—accessed July 24, 2021.
40. https://www.lindsayseers.info/content/lindsay-seers-nowhere-less-now—accessed
July 24, 2021. For the record, I was born in 1965. That Henri Bergson is described
here as a “philosopher and mystic” is rather premature in my view, making the present
work seemingly redundant.
41. Cited in Pilkington 1976, p. 104; Bergson 1992, p. 157. Atkinson 2020 notes (p. 16)
that “rather than creating a new system of thought, Bergson developed new ways of
thinking through philosophical problems as a way of revitalizing philosophy. Valéry
argues that one of Bergson’s greatest contributions to philosophy was the develop-
ment of an alternative language to the sciences and systematic philosophy, which
brought together poetry with the rigour of the exact sciences in order to reveal the
orientation of a philosopher’s thought.”
42. Bergson 1992, p. 157. See also Atkinson 2020, p. 24: “Bergson confirms his view that
the arts are founded on intuition like philosophy and that ‘philosophy is a genre and
the different arts are its species’ (la philosophie est un genre dont les différents arts sont
les espèces).”
43. Significantly in this regard, Atkinson (2020, p. 39) also reports that “while sitting
for his portrait with the painter Jacques Émile Blanche, Bergson asked Blanche
about Cubism because the Cubists were at the time seeking some type of theoret-
ical foundation for their ideas on the fourth dimension, but the interest was only
passing.”
44. Hagen 2012, p. 8; Bergson 1990, p. 17.
45. https://www.lindsayseers.info/content/lindsay-seers-nowhere-less-now.
46. Hagen 2012, p. 181.
47. Hagen 2012, p. 23.
48. Hagen 2012, p. 8.
49. Hazelton 2012.
50. Hazelton 2012.
51. Hagen 2012, pp. 116, 122, 9.
52. Hagen 2012, p. 161, 165.
53. Tully 2009, p. 68.
Notes 211
54. Tully 2009, pp. 69, 71. According to Tully (p. 69): while there certainly were Greco-
Roman mysteries of the Hellenized Isis, the false idea that there were ancient Egyptian
“mysteries” originated with Greeks such as Herodotus, who misunderstood the
Egyptian cult of Osiris at Abydos, interpreting it as “mysteric” because it was carried
out by a specially consecrated priesthood, unlike the part-time priests of Greece.
While access to the inner recesses of the Egyptian temple was limited to the priest-
hood, festivals were open to the public, not restricted to groups of initiates.
55. Tully 2020, pp. 145, 151.
56. Tully 2020, p. 160.
57. Tully 2009, p. 72.
58. Cited in King and Skinner 1976, p. 15.
59. Hanegraaff 2003, p. 368; see also Josephson Storm 2017.
60. Barad 2007, p. 350. See also p. 279: “Clearly there are major obstacles to observing
quantum behavior for large-scale systems. But however difficult it is to realize in prac-
tice, in principle we ought to be able to observe quantum behavior in macroscopic
systems.”
61. Barad 2007, p. ix.
62. Barad 2007, p. 89; Thurschwell 2001, p. 3.
63. Barad 2007, p. 33.
64. Barad 2007, p. ix.
65. Barad 2010, pp. 240, 244.
66. This “reintegration” could also be seen as the “disintegration” or dissolution of what is
for Bergson a “false” dichotomy (or binary).
67. Nail 2019, p. 69.
68. These are the bifurcations we referred to earlier when addressing the ramifications
of logical types (Russell) and cosmological levels (Bergson) that emerge from the
paradoxes of reflexivity. Oddly enough, though, Nail makes little mention of the work
of Ilya Prigogine and Isabelle Stengers on thermodynamic bifurcation, despite its
huge influence and the fact that Prigogine and Stengers also acknowledge their debts
to Henri Bergson. See Prigogine and Stengers 1984.
69. This is what François Laruelle calls the “structural invariance” of one thought
standing outside and dominating all other scales, all other thoughts—a thought he
dubs “philosophy.”
70. Barad 2007, p. 459n61.
71. Murphy notes that hidden-variable theory actually goes back to Louis de Broglie
(1892–1987), who was a student of Langevin, and himself acknowledged the influ-
ence of Henri Bergson on his own ideas: “Louis de Broglie, who developed the first
‘hidden variable’ interpretation of quantum mechanics in the 1920s and later in-
spired Bohm in his fuller version of it, notes the many similarities between quantum
theory and Bergson’s work as a whole in his Physics and Microphysics” (Murphy 1999,
p. 79n18).
72. Barad 2007, p. 319. As Barad also says (2007, p. 174): “Bohr did not find Einstein’s
concerns troubling because Bohr did not share the same metaphysical beliefs.” Hence,
no dice for Einstein.
212 Notes
73. Though Bergson rarely uses the verbal form, to “temporalize” as we have here, he
can talk about adding a “temporal colour” to the description of a phenomenon: see
Bergson 2018, p. 116.
74. Bohm 1980, pp. 34–60.
75. Van der Tuin 2011, pp. 28–29n6. Murphy (and Van der Tuin) are not alone, however,
with Paul Atkinson (2020, pp. 224–5) also writing about Bergson and Bohm both
believing in “undivided wholeness.” Milič Čapek (Čapek 1971, p. 309), too, records
Bergson’s likeness to Bohm’s concept of a qualitative infinity within the cosmos: “ ‘the
qualitative infinity’ . . . of nature shows clearly his [Bohm’s] affinity with process phi-
losophy of the type [Bergson’s] discussed in this book.”
76. Murphy 1999, p. 74.
77. Cited at Murphy 1999, p. 74.
78. Murphy 1999, p. 74.
79. Murphy 1999, p. 74.
80. Bergson 1992, p. 32.
81. Murphy 1999, p. 75.
82. Murphy 1999, pp. 75–76. We would take issue with the use of this last line taken
from Duration and Simultaneity (Bergson 1965, p. 47), given Henri Bergson’s dia-
logical approach: he seems to be assenting to a theory of impersonal time here, and so
giving away some ground to the STR; but this is only so that he can later retake that
ground by showing where such impersonal time still falls short of real time (durée).
Nonetheless, there are indeed more extended rhythms of duration that contract our
own in Henri Bergson’s theory (especially outside Duration and Simultaneity), and
these would appear impersonal relative to us (at least before we fabulate a personality
out of them).
83. Barad 2007, p. 273.
84. Barad 2007, pp. 318, 319.
85. Barad 2007, p. 182.
86. Barad 2007, p. 394.
87. Bergson 1969, p. 174.
88. See Bergson 1975, pp. 186–230.
89. McNamara 1999, p. 136.
90. Another relatively ordinary example of metempsychosis, or what he calls the “translife
of the soul,” comes in Laurent Debreuil’s concept of an “intellective space” (Debreuil
2015, pp. 111ff): “I may still speak of my soul as an effect of this mind toward another
I than the one I think I am using. My soul is a singular persistence of my thinking into
yours, yours, and yours. [ . . . ] Our souls are ‘immortal,’ for they do not live. They
have a translife, they are differentially performed by organisms. They disappear, when
painted stones are erased, languages go extinct, memories vanish. But, as long as their
tracé is to be found, they will appear, and sink. [ . . . ] This strange place, I call it the in-
tellective space, that is, a putative space where thought and knowledge are performed
and shared, and not only computed according to universal laws that would ‘speak’ to
us directly and by themselves” (pp. 119, 120, 3).
91. Christof 2017, p. 160.
Notes 213
1. As McNamara relates (1999, p. 129), Henri Bergson “suggested that the dream in-
volved a lifting of the normal inhibitory stance of the brain, a relaxation of the
usual ‘interested’ and outward-oriented stance of the individual.” For J. W. Dunne,
such dreams could be tokens of real time travel—but that’s another story: see Ó
Maoilearca 2019b.
2. See Laruelle 2013.
3. Laruelle 2017, p. 160. Laruelle writes of an “ordinary mysticism,” wherein he claims
that “the mystical is pre-philosophical, or, as we will say, ‘ordinary’ ” (Laruelle 2017,
p. 59).
4. Bergson/Mathers 2016c, p. x. Indeed, the charge that mystical systems of thought de-
sire unity with one absolute principle may well be undeserved in many cases, at least
in terms of their underlying metaphysics. See Jones 2016, pp. 193–4: “most mystical
systems do not involve an all-encompassing nonduality in which all of the apparent
diversity in the world is in the final analysis unreal. [ . . . ] There may be a sense of
union or a sense of individuality melting away, but there is no ontic change in na-
ture from what was already our true situation all along—only the false conceptual
boundaries that we ourselves had created soften or disappear. Through experiencing
the commonality of being, one gains a knowledge by participation, but there still is no
new ontic union of substances.” Jones continues, using Brahmanism as his example
(p. 197): “For Advaita, only Brahman is real, and thus there is nothing else to unite
with it. There is no ‘absorption’ of an independent self into ‘the Absolute.’ Nor is the
universe the pantheistic body of Brahman. The Upanishads have an emanationist
position, but Advaita and Samkhya interpret the situation differently. The popular
image of a drop of water merging in the ocean does not fit the metaphysics of these
traditions.”
5. Burton 2015, pp. 109–10.
6. McGuire 2017, pp. 23, 24.
7. See Bergson 1975, pp. 84–85. It should be noted that Bergson is more likely to speak
of tendencies, rather than probabilities, when it comes to anything else, material or
spiritual, other than epistemology. But the notion of real probability that emerges in
physics with Bohr’s work can be plausibly translated into the language of tendency
when seen through the lens of heterogeneous continuity.
8. See Bergson 1990, p. 56, 233–4. See also Bergson’s course on memory at the Collège
de France for February 5, 1904, where he reiterates this mereological theory of phys-
ical pain but also adds the same part/whole analysis for emotional suffering, taking
grief for a deceased parent as his example (Bergson 2018, pp. 145–7). Recall also that
in Richard Matheson’s novel Bid Time Return we are told that the hero has a brain
tumor, leaving it open that his entire experience of time travel was literally “in his
head.” But such a deflation can be pivoted to inflate the cerebral rather than deflate the
phenomenal.
9. See Lawlor 2002, p. 82. See also Deleuze 2004: pp. 25–26: “But for Bergson, alterity is
still not enough to make it so that being rejoins things and really is the being of things.
Notes 215
Antliff, Mark. Bergson: Cultural Politics and the Parisian Avant- garde. Princeton
University Press, 1993.
Armstrong, Christopher. Evelyn Underhill. Mowbray, 1975.
Asprem, Egil. “Beyond the West: Towards a New Comparativism in the Study of
Esotericism.” Correspondences 2 (2014): 3–33.
Asprem, Egil. “Explaining the Esoteric Imagination: Towards a Theory of Kataphatic
Practice.” Aries 17 (2017): 17–50.
Asprem, Egil. “Magic Naturalized? Negotiating Science and Occult Experience in Aleister
Crowley’s Scientific Illuminism.” Aries: Journal for the Study of Western Esotericism 8
(2008): 139–65.
Asprem, Egil, and Markus Altena Davidsen. “Editors’ Introduction: What Cognitive
Science Offers the Study of Esotericism.” Aries: Journal for the Study of Western
Esotericism 17 (2017): 1–15.
Atkinson, Paul. Henri Bergson and Visual Culture: A Philosophy for a New Aesthetic.
Bloomsbury, 2020.
Bachelard, Gaston. Dialectique de la Durée. Presses Universitaires de France, 1963.
Badiou, Alain. “Dance as a Metaphor for Thought.” In Alain Badiou, Handbook of
lnaesthetics, translated by Alberto Toscano. Stanford University Press, 2005, pp. 57–71.
Barad, Karen. Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of
Matter and Meaning. Duke University Press, 2007.
Barad, Karen. “Posthuman Performativity: Toward an Understanding of How
Matter Comes to Matter.” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 28, no. 3
(2003): 801–31.
Barad, Karen. “Quantum Entanglements and Hauntological Relations of
Inheritance: Dis/continuities, SpaceTime Enfoldings, and Justice-to-Come.” Derrida
Today 3 (2010): 240–68.
Barbour, Julian. “Time, Instants, Duration and Philosophy.” In Robin Durie, ed., Time
and the Instant: Essays in the Physics and Philosophy of Time. Clinamen Press, 2000,
pp. 96–111.
Barnard, G. William. Living Consciousness: The Metaphysical Vision of Henri Bergson.
State University of New York Press, 2012a.
Barnard, G. William. “Tuning into Other Worlds: Henri Bergson and the Radio Reception
Theory of Consciousness.” In Lefebvre and White, 2012b, pp. 281–98.
Barrett, Deirdre. Supernormal Stimuli: How Primal Urges Overran Their Evolutionary
Purpose. W. W. Norton & Company, 2010.
Barthelemy-Madaule, Madeleine. Bergson, adversaire de Kant: Etude Critique de la
Conception Bergsonienne du Kantisme. Presses Universitaires de France, 1966.
Battista, Silvia. Posthuman Spiritualities in Contemporary Performance. Palgrave
Macmillan, 2018.
Bennett, Jane. Vibrant Matter: A Political Ecology of Things. Duke University Press, 2010.
218 Bibliography
and Jan A. M. Snoek, eds., Women’s Agency and Rituals in Mixed and Female Masonic
Orders. Brill, 2008, pp. 245–63.
Bohm, David. Wholeness and the Implicate Order. Routledge, 1980.
Brang, D., E. M. Hubbard, S. Coulson, M. Huang, and V. S. Ramachandran.
“Magnetoencephalography Reveals Early Activation of V4 in Grapheme- Color
Synesthesia.” NeuroImage 53, no.1 (October 2010): 268–74.
Breitwieser, Sabine, ed. Simone Forti: Thinking with the Body. Hirmer Verlag, 2014.
Brouwer, L. E. J. “Consciousness, Philosophy, and Mathematics” (1948). In A. Heyting,
ed., Collected Works: Volume One: Philosophy and Foundations of Mathematics. North-
Holland, 1975, pp. 480–94.
Burton, James. The Philosophy of Science Fiction: Henri Bergson and the Fabulations of
Philip K. Dick. Bloomsbury, 2015.
Butler, Alison. Victorian Occultism and the Making of Modern Magic: Invoking Tradition.
Palgrave, 2011.
Butler, Joseph. Analogy of Religion, Natural and Revealed (1736).
Canales, Jimena. The Physicist and the Philosopher: Einstein, Bergson, and the Debate That
Changed Our Understanding of Time. Princeton University Press, 2015.
Canguilhem, Georges. “Commentaire au troisième chapitre de L’Evolution créatrice.”
Bulletin de la faculté des lettres de Strasbourg XXI, no. 5–6 (1943): 126–43 and XXI,
no. 8 (1943): 199–214.
Čapek, Milič. Bergson and Modern Physics: A Reinterpretation and Re-evaluation. D.
Reidel, 1971.
Čapek, Milič. “Bergson’s Theory of the Mind-Brain Relation.” In Papanicolaou and Gunter,
1987, pp. 129–48.
Capra, Fritjof. The Tao of Physics: An Exploration of the Parallels Between Modern Physics
and Eastern Mysticism. Shambhala Publications, 1975.
Cariou, Marie. Bergson and le fait mystique. Aubier Montaigne, 1976.
Cariou, Marie. Lectures Bergsoniennes. Presses Univérsitaires de France, 1990.
Caygill, Howard. “Hyperaesthesia and the Virtual.” In Ó Maoilearca and de Mille, 2013,
pp. 247–59.
Christof, Catharine. “Feminist Action in and through Tarot and Modern Occult Society.”
La Rosa di Paracelso 1 (2017): 153–69.
Clarke, Julie. The Paradox of the Posthuman: Science Fiction/Techno-Horror Films and
Visual Media. VDM Verlag, 2009.
Coleman, Sam. “Being Realistic.” In Galen Strawson et al., eds., Consciousness and Its Place
in Nature: Does Physicalism Entail Panpsychism? Imprint-Academic, 2006, pp. 40–52.
Colquhoun, Ithell. Sword of Wisdom: MacGregor Mathers and the Golden Dawn. Neville
Spearman, 1975.
Cooper, David E. Senses of Mystery: Engaging with Nature and the Meaning of Life.
Routledge, 2017.
Cvejić, Bojana. Choreographing Problems: Expressive Concepts in European Contemporary
Dance and Performance. Palgrave Macmillan, 2015.
De Brigard, Felipe. “Memory and Imagination.” In Bernecker and Michaelian, 2017, pp.
127–40.
De Mille, Charlotte. Bergson in Britain: Philosophy and Modernist Painting c. 1890–1914.
Edinburgh University Press, 2022.
Debreuil, Laurent. The Intellective Space: Thinking beyond Cognition. University of
Minnesota Press, 2015.
220 Bibliography
Deleuze, Gilles. “Bergson, 1859–1941.” In Gilles Deleuze, Desert Islands: And Other Texts,
1953–1974. Semiotexte, 2004, pp. 22–31.
Deleuze, Gilles. Bergsonism. Translated by Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam.
Zone Books, 1988.
Deleuze, Gilles, and Felix Guattari. A Thousand Plateaus. Translated by Brian Massumi.
Athlone Press, 1987.
Delhomme, Jeanne. Vie et conscience de la Vie: Essais sur Bergson. Presses Univérsitaires
de France, 1954.
Delitz, Heike. “Life as the Subject of Society: Critical Vitalism as Critical Social Theory.” In
Hartmut Rosa, Christoph Henning, and Arthur Bueno, eds., Critical Theory and New
Materialisms. Routledge, 2021, pp. 107–22.
Denisoff, Dennis. “Pamela Colman Smith, Symbolism and Spiritual Synaesthesia.” In
Andrew Radford and Christine Ferguson, eds., The Occult Imagination in Britain,
1875–1947. Routledge, 2019a, pp. 146–64.
Denisoff, Dennis. “Performing the Spirit: Theatre, the Occult, and the Ceremony of Isis.”
Cahiers victoriens et édouardiens 80 (2014): 2–12.
Denisoff, Dennis. “Queer Occulture and Feminist Ritual Performance.” Presented at
Queen Mary University, London. May 23, 2019b.
Dubilet, Alex. “’Neither God, nor World’: On the One Foreclosed to Transcendence.”
Palgrave Communications 1 (2015): 1–8.
Dunham, Jeremy. “Overcoming the Divide between Freedom and Nature: Clarisse
Coignet on the Metaphysics of Independent Morality.” British Journal for the History of
Philosophy 28 (2020): 987–1008.
Edelman, Gerald. Bright Light, Brilliant Fire: On the Matter of the Mind. Basic Books, 1992.
Eslick, Leonard. “Bergson, Whitehead, and Psychical Research.” In Papanicolaou and
Gunter, 1987, pp. 353–68.
Evrard, Renaud. “Bergson et la télépathie: à propos d’une correspondance inédite.”
Bergsoniana 1, no. 1 (2021): 237–55.
Fenton, David. The Ghost Club. Smashwords, 2014.
Flusser, Vilém. Towards a Philosophy of Photography. Translated by Martin Chalmers.
Reaktion Books, 2000.
Forman, Robert K. C. “Introduction: Mystical Consciousness, the Innate Capacity, and
the Perennial Psychology.” In Robert K. C. Forman, ed., The Innate Capacity: Mysticism,
Psychology, and Philosophy. Oxford University Press, 1998, pp. 3–41.
Forman, Robert K. C. “Introduction: Mysticism, Constructivism, and Forgetting.” In
Robert K. C. Forman, ed., The Problem of Pure Consciousness: Mysticism and Philosophy.
Oxford University Press, 1990, pp. 3–49.
Forti, Simone. Planet, Edizioni Pari & Dispari, Cavriago, Reggio Emilia, 1976.
François, Arnaud. Bergson. Ellipses, 2008.
François, Arnaud. “Présentation: De la mémoire à la liberté.” In Bergson, 2018, pp. 9–17.
Franklin, J. Jeffrey. Spirit Matters: Occult Beliefs, Alternative Religions, and the Crisis of
Faith in Victorian Britain. Cornell University Press, 2018.
Galloway, Alexander R. “Laruelle and Art.” continent 2, no. 4 (2013): 230–36.
Gamble, Christopher N., Joshua S. Hanan, and Thomas Nail. “What Is New Materialism?”
Angelaki 24 (2019): 111–34.
Gaucher, André. “Isis à Montmartre.” L’Echo du Merveilleux (1900): 446–49.
Gayon, Jean. “Bergson’s Spiritualist Metaphysics and the Sciences.” In Gary Gutting, ed.,
Continental Philosophy of Science. Wiley-Blackwell, 2005, pp. 43–58.
Bibliography 221
Jankélévitch, Vladimir. Bergson. Translated by Nils F. Schott. Duke University Press, 2015.
Jankélévitch, Vladimir. “Bergson and Judaism.” In Lefebvre and White, 2012, pp. 217–45.
Jantzen, Grace M. Becoming Divine: Towards a Feminist Philosophy of Religion. Manchester
University Press, 1998.
Jones, Richard H. Philosophy of Mysticism: Raids on the Ineffable. State University of
New York Press, 2016.
Josephson Storm, Jason A. The Myth of Disenchantment: Magic, Modernity, and the Birth
of the Human Sciences. University of Chicago Press, 2017.
Katan, Einav. Embodied Philosophy in Dance: Gaga and Ohad Naharin’s Movement
Research. Palgrave Macmillan, 2016.
Katz, Steven T. “Language, Epistemology, and Mysticism.” In Steven T. Katz, ed., Mysticism
and Philosophical Analysis. Oxford University Press, 1978, pp. 22–74.
Katz, Steven T. “Mystical Speech and Mystical Meaning.” In Steven T. Katz, ed., Mysticism
and Language. Oxford University Press, 1992, pp. 3–41.
Kelly, Edward F., et al. Irreducible Mind: Towards a Psychology for the 21st Century.
Rowman and Littlefield, 2007.
Kern, Stephen. The Culture of Time and Space: 1880–1918. Harvard University Press, 1983.
Khandker, Wahida. Process Metaphysics and Mutative Life: Sketches of Lived Time. Palgrave
Macmillan, 2020.
King, Francis X., and Stephen Skinner. Techniques of High Magic. Destiny Books, 1976.
Kolakowski, Leszek. Bergson. Oxford University Press, 1985.
Kremer-Marietti, Angèle. Les formes du mouvement chez Bergson. Les Cahiers du nouvel
humanisme, 1953.
Kuhn, Annette. Family Secrets: Acts of Memory and Imagination. Verso, 2002.
Lacroix, Jean. “L’Intuition, Méthode de Purification.” In Albert Beguin and Pierre
Thevanez, eds., Henri Bergson: Essais et Témoignages. Editions de la Baconniere, 1943,
pp. 196–204.
Lambert, Gregg. “What the Earth Thinks.” In Ian Buchanan and Gregg Lambert, eds.,
Deleuze and Space. Edinburgh University Press, 2005, pp. 220–39.
Langer, Ellen, J. Mindfulness. Perseus Books, 1989.
Lara, Ali. “Wine’s Time: Duration, Attunement, and Diffraction.” Subjectivity 10
(2017): 104–22.
Laruelle, François. A Biography of Ordinary Man: On Authorities and Minorities.
Translated by Jessie Hock and Alex Dubilet. Polity Press, 2017.
Laruelle, François. “First Choreography or the Essence-of-Dance.” Qui Parle 21, no. 2
(Spring/Summer 2013): 143–55.
Laruelle, François. “A Light Odyssey: La découverte de la lumière comme problème
théorique et esthétique.” Le Confort Moderne, 1991.
Laruelle, François. Mystique non- philosophique à l’usage des contemporains.
Harmattan, 2007.
Laruelle, François. Principles of Non-Philosophy. Translated by Nicola Rubczak and
Anthony Paul Smith. Bloomsbury Academic, 2013.
Latour, Bruno. “Anti-Zoom.” In Michael Tavel Clarke and David Wittenberg, eds., Scale in
Literature and Culture. Palgrave, 2017, pp. 93–101.
Latour, Bruno. Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network-Theory. Oxford
University Press, 2005.
Lawlor, Leonard. The Challenge of Bergsonism. Continuum Press, 2002.
Bibliography 223
McGuire, Meghan. Gyres and Waves: Bergsonian Movement and Multiplicity in the Works
of W.B. Yeats and Virginia Woolf. University of North Carolina, Greensboro PhD
thesis, 2017.
McNamara, Patrick. Mind and Variability: Mental Darwinism, Memory and Self.
Praeger, 1999.
McRoy, Jay. “Case Study: Cinematic Hybridity in Shimizu Takashi’s Ju-On: The Grudge.”
In Jay McRoy, ed., Japanese Horror Cinema. Edinburgh University Press, 2005,
pp. 175–84.
Michaelian, Kourken. Mental Time Travel: Episodic Memory and Our Knowledge of the
Personal Past. MIT Press, 2016.
Montebello, Pierre. “Matter and Light in Bergson’s Creative Evolution.” Translated by
Roxanne Lapidus. SubStance 36, no. 3 (2007): 91–99.
Moore, F. C. T. Bergson: Thinking Backwards. Cambridge University Press, 1996.
Moore, G. E. “Proof of an External World.” In Thomas Baldwin, ed., G.E. Moore: Selected
Writings. Routledge, 1993, pp. 147–70.
Morin, Edgar. Le Cinema ou l’Homme Imaginaire. Essay d’Anthropologie. Les Editions de
Minuit, 1956.
Morrison, Mark. Modern Alchemy: Occultism and the Emergence of Atomic Theory.
Oxford University Press, 2007.
Mossé-Bastide, Rose-Marie. Bergson éducateur. Presses Universitaires de France, 1955.
Mossé-Bastide, Rose-Marie. Bergson et Plotin. Presses Universitaires de France, 1959.
Mourélos, Georges. Bergson et les niveaux de réalité. Presses Universitaires de
France, 1964.
Moynihan, Thomas. Spinal Catastrophism: A Secret History. Urbanomic Press, 2019.
Mullarkey, John. Bergson and Philosophy. Edinburgh University Press, 1999a.
Mullarkey, John. “Bergson’s Method of Multiplicity.” Metaphilosophy 26 (July
1995): 230–59.
Mullarkey, John. “Creative Metaphysics and the Metaphysics of Creativity.” Bergson
Now, special issue of the Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 35
(2004b): 68–81.
Mullarkey, John. “Forget the Virtual: Bergson, Actualism, and the Refraction of Reality.”
Continental Philosophy Review 37 (2004a): 469–93.
Mullarkey, John. “Introduction: La Philosophie Nouvelle or Change in Philosophy.” In
Mullarkey, 1999b, pp. 1–16.
Mullarkey, John. “Life, Movement, and the Fabulation of the Event.” Theory, Culture &
Society 24, no. 6 (2007): 53–70.
Mullarkey, John, ed. The New Bergson. Manchester University Press, 1999b.
Mullarkey, John. Post-Continental Philosophy. Continuum Press, 2006.
Mullarkey, John. “The Tragedy of the Object: Democracy of Vision and the Terrorism
of Things in Bazin’s Cinematic Realism.” Angelaki: The Promise of Cinema: Revisiting
themes from Bazin 17, no. 4 (2013): 39–59.
Murdoch, Iris. Existentialists and Mystics: Writings on Philosophy and Literature. Edited
by Peter Conradi. Penguin, 1999.
Murphy, Timothy S. “Beneath Relativity: Bergson and Bohm on Absolute Time.” In John
Mullarkey, ed., The New Bergson. Manchester University Press, 1999, pp. 66–81.
Nail, Thomas. Being and Motion. Oxford University Press, 2019.
Neimanis, Astrida. Bodies of Water: Posthuman Feminist Phenomenology. London:
Bloomsbury Academic, 2017.
Bibliography 225
Povich, Mark, and Carl F. Craver. “Mechanistic Levels, Reduction, and Emergence.” In
Stuart Glennan and Phyllis Illari eds., The Routledge Handbook of Mechanisms and
Mechanical Philosophy. Routledge, 2018, pp. 185–97.
Prigogine, Ilya, and Isabelle Stengers. Order Out of Chaos: Man’s New Dialogue with
Nature. Bantam, 1984.
Ramey, Joshua. The Hermetic Deleuze: Philosophy and Spiritual Ordeal. Duke University
Press, 2012.
Ramos, Filipa. “The Zoological Apparatus: Chris Marker, Simone Forti and Joan Jonas’
Artistic Engagement with Animals.” PhD diss., Kingston University, 2021.
Regardie, Israel. The Golden Dawn: The Original Account of the Teachings, Rites,
and Ceremonies of the Hermetic Order (1937). Edited by John Michael Greer.
Llewellyn, 2016.
Resurgam, V. H. Fra. Flying Roll No. V “Some Thoughts on the Imagination.” In Mathers,
King, and Gilbert, 1987, pp. 47–51.
Ricoeur, Paul. Memory, History, Forgetting. Translated by Kathleen Blamey and David
Pellauer. University of Chicago Press, 2006.
Riquier, Camille. Archéologie de Bergson; Temps et métaphysique. Presses Universitaires
de France, 2009.
Robbins, Stephen E. “Analogical Reminding and the Storage of Experience: The
Paradox of Hofstadter-Sander.” Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 16, no. 3
(2017): 355–85.
Robbins, Stephen E. “On the Possibility of Direct Memory.” In V. W. Fallio, ed., New
Developments in Consciousness Research. Nova Science, 2006, pp. 1–64.
Robins, Sarah K. “Memory Traces.” In Bernecker and Michaelian, 2017, pp. 76–87.
Russell, Bertrand. The Analysis of Mind. George Allen and Unwin, 1921.
Russell, Bertrand. The Philosophy of Bergson. Macmillan, 1914.
Santayana, George. Winds of Doctrine: Studies in Contemporary Opinion. Charles
Scribner’s Sons, 1913.
Sartre, J. P. The Imagination. Translated by Kenneth Williford and David Rudrauf.
Routledge, 2012.
Sartre, J. P. Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions. Translated by Philip Mairet. Routledge, 2001.
Schechner, Richard. Performance Studies: An Introduction. Routledge, 2002.
Schneider, Rebecca. Performing Remains: Art and War in Times of Theatrical Reenactment.
Routledge, 2011.
Seers, Lindsay. “Nowhere Less Now.” https://www.lindsayseers.info/content/lindsay-
seers-nowhere-less-now. Accessed June 17, 2020.
Shermer, Michael. The Believing Brain: From Ghosts and Gods to Politics and Conspiracies—
How We Construct Beliefs and Reinforce Them as Truths. Henry Holt and Co., 2011.
Sinclair, Mark. Bergson. Routledge, 2020.
Sinclair, Mark, and Delphine Antoine-Mahut. “Introduction to French Spiritualism
in the Nineteenth Century.” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 28, no. 5
(2020): 857–65.
Sinnett, A. P. Collected Fruits of Occult Teaching. J.B. Lippincott, 1919.
Sinnett, A. P. The Occult World. Trubner and Company, 1881.
Smith, Anthony Paul, and Nicola Rubczak. “Cloning the Untranslatable: Translators’
Introduction.” In François Laruelle, Principles of Non-Philosophy, translated by Nicola
Rubczak and Anthony Paul Smith. Bloomsbury Academic, 2013, pp. xi–xix.
Smolin, Lee. The Life of the Cosmos. Weidenfeld and Nicholas, 1997.
Bibliography 227
Smolin, Lee. Time Reborn: From the Crisis in Physics to the Future of the Universe.
Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 2013.
Sommer McGrath, Larry. Making Spirit Matter: Neurology, Psychology, and Selfhood in
Modern France. University of Chicago Press, 2020.
Soulez, Philippe, and Fréderic Worms. Bergson. Flammarion, 1997.
ter Schure, Leon. Bergson and History: Transforming the Modern Regime of Historicity.
State University of New York Press, 2020.
Steiner, Rudolf. An Outline of Occult Science. The Theosophical Publishing Society, 1914.
Szerszynski, Bronislaw. “Colloidal Social Theory: Thinking about Material Animacy and
Sociality beyond Solids and Fluids.” Theory, Culture, and Society (September 2021): 1–
21. https://doi.org/10.1177/02632764211030989. Accessed October 5, 2021.
Tereshchenko, Nicolas. “Israel Regardie (1907–1985) and the Golden Dawn.” Aries (old
series), no. 4 (1986): 71–87.
Thurschwell, Pamela. Literature, Technology and Magical Thinking, 1880– 1920.
Cambridge University Press, 2001.
Tully, C. J. “Celtic Egyptians: Isis Priests of the Lineage of Scota.” In Eleanor Dobson and
Nichola Tonks, eds., Ancient Egypt in the Modern Imagination: Art, Literature and
Culture. Bloomsbury Academic, 2020, pp. 145–60.
Tully, C. J. “Samuel Liddell Macgregor Mathers and Isis.” In Dave Evans and Dave Green,
eds., Ten Years of Triumph? Academic Approaches to Studying Magic and the Occult.
Hidden Publications, 2009, pp. 62–74.
Tulving, Endel. “Episodic Memory and Autonoesis: Uniquely Human?” In Herbert S.
Terrace and Janet Metcalfe, eds., The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective
Consciousness. Oxford University Press, 2005, pp. 3–56.
Turner, Victor. The Anthropology of Performance. PAJ, 1986.
Underhill, Evelyn. “A Defence of Magic.” The Fortnightly Review (November
1907): 754–65.
Valery, Paul. “Philosophy of the Dance.” Salmagundi, No. 33/ 34 (Spring-
Summer
1976): 65–75.
Valiaho, Pasi. Mapping the Moving Image: Gesture, Thought and Cinema Circa 1900.
Amsterdam University Press, 2010.
Van den Broek, Roelof, and Wouter J. Hanegraaff, eds., Gnosis and Hermeticism from
Antiquity to Modern Times. State University of New York Press, 1997.
Van der Tuin, Iris, ““A Different Starting Point, A Different Metaphysics”: Reading
Bergson and Barad Diffractively.” Hypatia: A Journal of Feminist Philosophy 26, no. 1
(2011): 22–42.
Van Egmond, Daniël. “Western Esoteric Schools in the Late Nineteenth and Early
Twentieth Centuries.” In Van Den Broek and Hanegraaff, 1997, pp. 311–46.
Van Elferen, Isabella. Timbre: Paradox, Materialism, Vibrational Aesthetics.
Bloomsbury, 2020.
Van Gemert, Ties, and Johan Eland. “Bergson and the Fringes of the Psyche: Psychical
Research, Spiritualism, and Vitalism.” Paper presented at “Bergson and Vitalism(s): An
Online Workshop,” at Ghent University—University Toulouse Jean Jaurès, April 29–
30, 2021.
Wallace, Vesna A. The Inner Kālacakratantra: A Buddhist Tantric View of the Individual.
Oxford University Press, 2001.
de Warren, Nicolas. “Memory in Continental Philosophy: Metaphor, Concept, Thinking.”
In Dmitri Nikulin, ed., Memory: A History. Oxford University Press, 2015, pp. 228–7.
228 Bibliography
Werning, Markus. “Predicting the Past from Minimal Traces: Episodic Memory and its
Distinction from Imagination and Preservation.” Review of Philosophy and Psychology
11 (2020): 301–33.
Wills, David. Dorsality: Thinking Back through Technology and Politics. University of
Minnesota Press, 2008.
Wittenberg, David. “Bigness as the Unconscious of Theory.” ELH 86, no. 2 (Summer
2019): 333–54.
Woods, Derek. “Scale Variance and the Concept of Matter.” In Sarah Ellenzweig and
John H. Zammito, eds., The New Politics of Materialism: History, Philosophy, Science.
Routledge, 2017, pp. 200–24.
Yeats, W. B. A Critical Edition of Yeats’s a Vision (1925). Edited by George Mills Harper and
Walter Kelly Hood. Macmillan, 1978.
Yeats, W. B. Letters to W. B. Yeats: Volume 1. Edited by Richard J. Finneran, George Mills
Harper, and William Murphy. Macmillan, 1977.
Yeats, W. B. W.B. Yeats Online Archive. https://my.matterport.com/show-mds?mls=1&m=
CfD9eU6iPhf. Accessed November 24, 2021.
Zammito, John H. “Concluding (Irenic) Postscript: Naturalism as a Response to the New
Materialism.” In Sarah Ellenzweig and John H. Zammito, eds., The New Politics of
Materialism: History, Philosophy, Science. Routledge, 2017, pp. 300–21.
Zukav, Gary. The Dancing Wu Li Masters: An Overview of the New Physics. William
Morrow, 1979.
Index
For the benefit of digital users, indexed terms that span two pages (e.g., 52–53) may, on
occasion, appear on only one of those pages.
Tables and figures are indicated by t and f following the page number
Bergson, Henri, 33–34, 34f, 35–36 causation, 48–49, 52, 53, 69, 95, 115–16,
Bergson’s Circles of Expanded 138, 145–46, 194n.26
Memory, 99f Cavell, Stanley, 95
Bergson’s Cone of Memory (first Caygill, Howard, 69–70, 73–74, 194–
variation), 50f 95n.27, 213n.6
Bergson’s Cone of Memory (second ceremony, 10, 65–66, 76, 106f–3, 131
variation), 132f chance, 69, 154–55, 159–60. See also
Bergson’s Line of Pure Memory to probability
Perception, 100f change, 5–6, 7, 8, 94, 106–7, 110, 116–17,
Bergson’s selectionist memory 120–21, 127, 128, 143, 153–54, 161
theory, 48 continuous, 91–92, 107–8
Bergson, Michal, 33 creative, 116
Bergson, Mina, 33, 34–36, 36f in duration, 143
Bergsonism, 1–2, 5, 17, 29, 33–34, 41–42, indivisible, 5–6, 201n.17
70–71, 78–79, 84, 88–90, 122–23 qualitative, xiii, 16, 94, 153
Berkeley, George, 77–78, 82 Charmers, David, 11–12
Besant, Annie, 196n.41 Christof, Catherine, 159–60
Bevir, Michael, 194n.12 cinema, 2, 11, 113, 114–15
bifurcation, xii–xiii, 116–17, 128, 153–54, clairvoyance. See scrying
173–74, 211n.68 Clarke, Arthur C., 121–22
biology, 8, 11–12, 13, 17, 18–19, 22–23, Cleopatra, 83
68–69, 92, 173–74 clocks, xi–xii, 6, 88, 162
Blanche, Jacques Emile, 210n.43 Coleman, Sam, 13, 205n.11
bodies, xii–xiii, 49–50, 85–86, 87–88, 89– Colman, Felicity, 184n.57
90, 120, 130–31, 140, 143, 144–45, Colman Smith, Pamela, 39, 200n.9,
156, 162–64 202n.23
inert, 109–10, 115–16 color, 40, 58, 81, 89, 95, 96, 98, 119, 133–
Bogdan, Henrik, 58 34, 143, 172–73
Bohm, David, 94, 120–21, 154–58, 159– Como, Perry, 2
60, 190n.23, 211n.71, 212n.75 concentration. See attention
Bohr, Niels, 94, 137, 141, 154–55, 158, concepts, 14, 16, 22–23, 53, 54, 78–79, 90,
211n.72, 214n.7 125–27, 140, 142, 143
Bois, Jules, 60 conceptualization, 25–26, 65, 92, 93–94
Boutroux, Emile, 13–14, 16, 22, 110–11 concordances, 39–40, 169, 170t
brain, 23, 24, 25, 30, 43–45, 48, 96, 97, 127, Connection between the Worlds, 101f
131, 168–69, 171, 189n.18 consciousness, 3–5, 26, 29–30, 81–82, 83,
Brodie-Innes, John William, 150–51 84, 87–88, 89, 123–24, 133, 134, 156
Brouwer, L.E.J., 120 higher, 55
Burton, James, 114, 168 human, 22, 43–44, 64, 156
Bush, George W., 90 constructivists, 25
Butler, Alison, 54, 182n.28, 191n.47 contingency, 13–14, 16
Butler, Joseph, 56–57 continuity, 5–7, 8, 16, 28, 31, 43–44, 50,
56–57, 78–79, 87–88, 106–7, 113–14,
Canales, Jimena, 179n.2 120–22, 127–28, 152–54, 158–59,
Canguilhem, Georges, 174–75, 215n.16 163–64, 201n.17
Čapek, Milič, 212n.75 continuity and discontinuity, 56–
Capra, Fritjof, 137 57, 152–53
Cariou, Marie, 42, 90 temporal, 28, 163
Index 231
goddesses, 10, 43, 81, 150–51, 163–64 heterogeneity, 21, 31, 56–57, 150, 151, 153,
feminine divinity, 10, 41–42, 76–77 156–57, 158, 159–60
Godwin, Joscelyn, 96, 119 heterogeneous continuity, xiii, 17, 21,
Golden Dawn, The, 9–1 0, 18–1 9, 56–57, 82, 90, 116, 128, 142, 151,
20–2 1, 37, 38–4 0, 53, 54, 58, 153–54, 163–64, 172, 173, 174,
59, 60, 65, 66, 100–2 , 103, 122, 186n.7, 199n.33. See also continuity;
129–3 1, 149–5 0, 181–8 2n.23, discontinuity
184n.56, 188nn.11–1 2, 193n.5, hierarchy, 21, 31–32, 58
194n.10, 200n.9 Hirai, Yasushi, 91
Gonne, Maud, 39 holism, 120–21, 154, 159, 162, 190n.23
grades, hermetic orders of, 18–20, 21, 28, Horace, 130
31–32, 37, 38, 60, 93–94, 123–24, Horniman, Annie, 34–35, 39
184n.56 Horos group, 34–35
Grandin, Temple, 186n.6 Horus, 129–30
Green, Helen, 63 Hude, Henri, 91, 194n.3
Green, Richard, 92 Hume, David, 43–44, 160
Greer, Mary, 35–36, 39, 130, 187n.7 Hutton, Ronald, 65
grief, 6, 24, 50 hyper-ritual, 59, 60, 193n.5. See also ritual
Grogin, R.C., 22, 60, 64–65, 185n.1, hyperaesthesia, 69–71, 73–74, 109–10
188n.18, 195n.28 hyperbolic, 23, 162, 166–67, 172, 215n.13
Guattari, Félix, 86–87, 119–21, 205n.11, hyperplane (of constant time), 157–58
205n.19 Hyppolite, Jean, 5–6
Gunter, Pete, 121–22
gyres, 100–2 idealism, 5, 20–21, 22, 84, 140, 171
identity, 19–20, 48–49, 55–57, 147, 148,
habit, 13–14, 47, 65 149–50, 159, 161, 163–64
Hacking, Ian, 43, 47–48, 51–52, 112, multiple, 56–57, 159
192n.59 See also individuality; self
hallucination, 30, 50, 116, 168, 172 images, 55–56, 61–62, 70–71, 74–75,
Hallward, Peter, 183n.32 77–80, 81–82, 83–84, 92–93, 95, 97,
Halpern, Paul, 136–37, 158 98–102f, 127–28, 130–32, 143–44,
Hanan, Joshua, 12–13, 110–11, 137, 146–48, 197n.10
199n.27 of fluidity, 78–79, 147–48
Hanegraaff, Wouter J., 20–21, 55, 66, 118– mediating, 78–79
19, 151, 194n.11 and memory, 43–44, 48, 55–57, 100f
Hartshorne, Charles, 203n.7 photographic, 147–48, 149–50
hauntology, 152–53, 166–67 virtual, xi–xii, 96–97
Hazelton, Claire, 148 imaginary, the, 37, 54, 68, 87, 92–93, 95,
Hedenborg White, Manon, 188n.16 97, 114–15
Hegel, G.W.F, 11, 183n.32 imagination, 52–53, 54–56, 68, 95, 97–98,
Heidegger, Martin, 94 100–2, 118, 122, 147–48, 150–
Heraclitus, 61 51, 173–74
Hermes Trismegistus, 18 and memory, 51–53
Hermes, 18 See also eidolon
hermetic principle, 131, 177 immanence, 13–14, 20–21, 29–30,
Herring, Emily, 41 31–32, 66, 93–94, 106–7, 125,
hetero-continuities. See heterogeneous 162, 173–75
continuity immaterialism, 22, 113–15, 200n.9
heterochromia, 147–48 immobility, xi–xii, 7–8, 139–40
234 Index
macrocosm, 118, 119, 171. See also Meillassoux, Quentin, 13–14, 110–11
microcosm; scales Melancholy of Ulad, 105f
Maeterlinck, Maurice, 111 memoro-politics, 43–44, 47–48
magic, 10–12, 37, 39, 43–44, 54, 63, 66–71, memory
95, 121–22, 150–51 biological, 49, 121–22, 145–46, 205n.18
magical thinking, 24, 67–69, 81–82 collective, 121–22, 131
magicians, 28, 54, 67–68 cone of, 8–9, 50–51, 99, 100–2, 131–
magnitude. See scale 32, 133
Malabou, Catherine, 13–14, 19–20, 124– diversity of, 49, 144
28, 131, 153–54, 167–68, 184n.57, false, 52–53, 147, 150, 152
205n.34 great, 122, 159–60
manifestation, 50, 86–87, 100, 119, 149–50 and imagination, 51–53
Marchesini, Paula, 206n.38 localization, 44–45, 158–59
Maritain, Jacques, 181n.10 long-term, 44–45
marvels, 67, 112–13, 115–16, 203n.11 narrative, 47–48, 147
materialism, 11–13, 14–15, 16, 18, 19–21, personal, 29, 49, 169–70
22, 84, 85–86, 110–11, 125–26, 176, phantom, 133–34
203n.7, 213n.5 plane of pure, 49, 98–99, 100f, 123–24
new, 11–15, 16, 17, 85, 89–90, 109– pure, 31, 47, 49–50, 74–75, 98, 99, 100f,
10, 137 113–14, 132, 166, 169, 201n.17 (see
vital, 85, 86, 87–88, 89–90, 91, 94, also perception, pure)
199n.27 traces, 51, 52
materiality, 53, 61–62, 67, 79–80, 86–87, mental time travel, 31, 162
88–89, 114–15, 119, 133–34, 138 mereology, 5–6, 116, 121–22, 171, 186n.7,
materialization, 40, 54, 59, 61, 132, 133, 214n.8. See also relation
134, 138–39, 140, 188n.17 meta-spiritual, the, 28, 111. See also
mathematics, 7, 11–12, 120, 173–74 spiritual, the
Mathers, Moina. See Bergson, Mina metaphor, 51, 98, 145–46, 172–73,
Matheson, Richard, 161, 185– 200–1n.15
86n.3, 214n.8 metaphysics, 11, 27, 57, 74–75, 78–80, 110,
matter 128, 162, 166–67
spiritualizing, 14–15, 84, 111, 133, 176 metempsychosis, 2, 171, 212n.90
vital, 85, 86, 87–88, 89–90, 91, 94, Michaelian, Kourken, 52–53, 189n.1,
199n.27 191n.42
Matter and Memory, 8–9, 61–62, 64, microcosm, 13, 70–71, 83, 91, 118, 119,
72–73, 74–75, 84, 98, 99–102, 123, 120–21, 128, 170t, 171, 173–74. See
193n.19, 194n.25, 201n.17, 201n.21 also macrocosm; scales
Mauss, Marcel, 1, 163–64, 213n.10 Minutum Mundum, 18–19, 118–19. See
McEwan, Ian, 190n.20 also Tree of Life, the
McGinn, Colin, 200n.42 mirrors, 2, 70, 73, 74, 96, 138
McGuire, Meghan, 100–2, 169, 201n.21 mnemonics, 43, 145
McNamara, Patrick, 43, 48, 49, 52–53, 55– monism, 22, 90, 116–17, 170t, 198n.31
57, 121–22, 159, 192n.59, 214n.1 Montebello, Pierre, 143
McRoy, Jay, 204n.17 Moore, G.E., 110
meaning as mattering (Barad), 137, 138– Moore, F.C.T., 180n.10
39, 140, 141, 142, 152 Morin, Edgar, 114–15
mechanism, 55, 113, 115–16, 131, 183n.36 Morrison, Mark, 23, 112–13
mediums, 10, 67, 78–79 Mossé-Bastide, Rose-Marie, 42
236 Index
science, 12–13, 14–15, 18, 20–21, 23, 24, spiritualists, 9, 10, 14, 17, 19–20, 21, 23, 90,
39–40, 68, 112–13, 126–27, 136–37 112–13, 115, 136–37
antiscientific ideology, 47–48 spirituality, 63, 66, 110–11, 119, 137
scientism, 14 spiritualization (of matter, science), 23, 40,
Scott, Mike, 177–78 61, 63, 76, 109, 130–32, 143–44
scrying, 31–32, 55, 58, 74, 96, 118, 150–51, Steiner, George, 84
170t, 196n.38 Steiner, Rudolf, 54, 198n.28
secrecy, 31–32, 38, 64–65, 77–78, 93–94, Stengers, Isabelle, 211n.68
134–35, 143–44, 161 Stewart, Balfour, 136, 158–59
Seers, Lindsay, 40, 145–46, 149f, 210n.39 storage (of memory), 43–45, 48–49, 51, 53.
selection (theory of memory), 43–45, 48– See also localization
50, 55–57, 70–72, 159, 170t Storm, Josephson, 211n.59
self, xii–xiii, 31, 38, 55–57, 118–19, 143, 147, strangeness (of Henri Bergson), 8–9, 11
159. See also identity; individuality Strawson, Galen, 11–12
Semon, Richard, 197n.23 subject, 17, 38, 115, 139–40, 163–64, 171,
sensation, 26, 71–72, 89, 133–34 172. See also substance
Serres, Michel, 18 substance, 28, 48, 57, 79–80, 109–11,
Shermer, Michael, 185–86n.3 113–15, 116, 130–31, 139–40, 161,
shi, 103–7 163–64, 174–75, 208n.14
Sinclair, Mark, 15–16, 90–91, 184n.47 immaterial, 93–94, 163
Sinnett, Alfred, 54 universal, 40, 61–62, 110–11
smallism, 13, 70–71, 131, 205n.11 See also subject
Smolin, Lee, 127, 158–59, 206n.38 substitution, xi–xiii, 156
Socrates, 59, 61, 82 super-nothing, 64
Soddy, Frederick, 112–13 supernatural, 31–32, 113, 114, 122, 129–
solidity, xiii, 81, 115–16, 173–74 30, 151, 166–67, 186n.7
Sommer McGrath, Larry, 14–16, 213n.9 supernormal, 28, 29–31, 54, 70–71, 111,
soul vitalism (Bennett), 90, 91 114, 163–64, 169–70, 171, 172, 176,
souls, 2, 4, 22–23, 44–45, 47–48, 55, 89–90, 185n.24, 186n.7
91–92, 107–8, 176–77 survival, 73, 113–14, 163. See also death;
space, 4–5, 27, 48, 103–5, 106–8, 115–16, resurrection
136, 142–43, 144, 145, 156–59, symbols, 25, 55, 58–59, 77, 96, 97, 131–32
161, 171–72 Szerszynski, Bronislaw, 197n.12
spatiality, 13, 17, 84, 119–20, 123–25, 128, Szwarc, Jeannot, 2–3
157–58, 161, 162, 200n.13
Spinoza, Baruch, 85–86, 87, 89–90, 124, Tait, Peter Guthrie, 136, 158–59
125, 128, 167–68, 205n.30 tarot, the, 37, 39, 59, 103, 159–60, 176,
spirit vision, 58, 73, 74, 82, 172 194n.26, 202n.23
spiritual, xii–xiii, 8, 28, 43–44, 55, 59, 65, tattwa, visions and symbols, xiii, 58, 74, 81,
73–74, 136–37 95, 96–97, 102, 102f, 196n.45, See also
practices, 42, 58, 66, 103, 163–64 thatness
world, 65, 98, 200–1n.15 telepathy, 22–23, 31, 69–72, 83, 111, 156,
See also meta-spiritual, the 181n.22, 195n.34
spiritualism, 14–16, 22, 23, 24, 28, 39–40, tendency, 22, 43–44, 61, 68, 86, 87, 91,
89–90, 97, 171, 174–75, 176, 194n.3, 110–11, 113–14, 203n.8, 214n.7, See
197n.20, 213n.5 also direction; probability
new, 14–16, 40 tension (degrees or levels of), 6, 89, 119,
See also French Spiritualism 120–21, 123–24, 160
Index 239