EMBLEMS AND CUTS: PHILOSOPHY IN AND
AGAINST HISTORY
Alber to Toscano (Goldsmiths, Univer sity of London)
Alain Badiou’s theory of the subject has consistently opposed a vision
of History as meaning and totality, for the sake of an internal, subjec-
tive and discontinuous grasp of the periodisation of political “ se-
quences.” This article examines the theoretical trajectory that leads
Badiou to dislocate the historical dialectic, generating a comprehen-
sion of political time which is no longer bound to an ordered matrix of
expression and development; it also considers Badiou’s relation to
various strands of anti-humanist anti-historicism and tackles the theo-
retical tensions that inhere in his disjunction of nature and history.
The article concludes by discussing the effect of Badiou’s notion of pe-
riodisation on the very historicity and mutability of his own philosophi-
cal apparatus, and the immanent threat posed to his thinking of the
event by an ‘absolute historicism.’
In his 1997 novel, Calme bloc ici-bas, Alain Badiou tells the story of
Julien Oldenay, Professor of the Philosophy of History in the imagined
country of Prémontré—a country set apart from that of the reader not
simply by fictive space but by its time and calendars, born of founding,
constitutive events and, therefore, incommensurable with our own. The
tale is one of 44 that make up approximately half of the novel, all of
them beginning with classic incipits such as “C’est l’histoire de …,” “Je
conte de ...,” “Ce conte est …” and in this case a simple “Once upon a
time …,” “Il était une fois …” The irreverent portrayal of Oldenay is in-
dicative of Badiou’s philosophical instincts when it comes to history, as
both concept and discipline. Aside from his unkempt appearance, Olde-
nay is portrayed as combining a certain degree of self-satisfaction with a
“chronic intellectual hesitation,” as well as a rhetoric marked by nuance,
retraction and interminable self-criticism. Lecturing on the history of
Prémontré, Oldenay tentatively declares:
… [T]his History, if we provisionally accept that the word “His-
tory” is legitimate, which would require elaborate argumenta-
tion, I would say, with all the precautions that this concept de-
Emblems and Cuts 19
mands of us, that it is very clearly dialectical. Of course, “very
clearly” is a manner of speech, since the History of Prémontré is
anything but clear. And as I have already said, “dialectical” is
also a manner of speech, until we have distinguished between the
seven possible senses of the word … 1
Oldenay perseveres in these comical, scholastic convolutions. Among
Oldenay’s students, there is one, David Monvoisin, who intends to put a
twist in this infinitely qualified and typologically differentiated dialectic:
“It seemed to him,” writes Badiou, “that one could ‘cut’ through the con-
ceptual uncertainties of his professor by mentioning some symbolic
events, on the basis of which one could then reconstruct, without looking
for a continuous characterisation, the general sense of Prémontré. He
fixes his grey gaze, his thin athlete’s beauty, on Julien Oldenay, and all
of a sudden asks him if “dialectics” should not be understood in terms of
the contrast of violent cuts, or emblems.” 2 Monvoisin then draws such
punctual emblems from the history of Prémontré, in the form of a series
of events and dates, which are then followed by the consternation of the
other students and Oldenay’s own rigorously inconclusive reply, which
slowly lulls our young, radical dialectician to sleep.
In more than one respect this vignette dramatises one of the cen-
tral stakes in Alain Badiou’s decades-long confrontation with the concept
of history. Mediated by the heterodox allegiance to Marxism that still
marks much of his thought, this is, of course, the problem of dialectics—
to be understood, at least in a first moment, as a dialectic of the break
and the period of continuity and discontinuity. 3 But, of course, it can
never suffice to juxtapose the cautious professor’s dialectics of continu-
ity and hesitation to the impetuous student’s dialectics of emblematic
violence. Even if we opt for the latter, it behoves us to ask what new no-
tions of continuity and periodisation are generated by an emphasis on the
break, what are the internal criteria of these “cuts” that Badiou-
1
Alain Badiou, Calme bloc ici-bas (Paris: P.O.L., 1997), 302.
2
Ibid., 305.
3
Fredric Jameson, A Singular Modernity: Essay on the Ontology of the Present (London:
Verso, 2002), 23. The choice between the break and the period, discontinuity or continu-
ity marks, according to Jameson, “an absolute historiographic beginning, that cannot be
justified by the nature of the historical material or evidence, since it organizes all such
material or evidence in the first place.”
20 Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy
Monvoisin speaks of, and indeed what concept (if any) of history may be
reconstructed in their wake. To begin, we need to interrogate the manner
in which historicity and temporality have been affected by Badiou’s re-
castings of the dialectic—a question that cannot avoid some assessment
of the legacy of Hegelianism within Badiou’s philosophy. Secondly, the
issue of a dialectics of periodisation, which emerges out of Badiou’s con-
frontation with Hegel in his 1982 Theory of the Subject, should be con-
fronted both with Badiou’s stance vis-à-vis the existence or otherwise of
“objective” historical periods (ages, centuries, or even meta-historical
categories such as “modernity”) and his thinking regarding the periodisa-
tion that is immanent in the trajectory of a subject. Third, and following
from this issue of periodisation, the conflictual articulation and scission
of politics and history needs to be considered, together with the diverging
status of history as viewed from the vantage points of philosophy and of
politics (or other truth procedures). Fourth, we must address the question
of how Badiou’s struggle with the question of history is affected by his
demarcations (which are often also appropriations) from his intellectual
forebears and contemporaries, namely, Sartre, Althusser and Foucault.
I would like to tackle this last question first by exploring
Badiou’s stance vis-à-vis accounts of historical ruptures that do not iden-
tify the bearers of such ruptures (or of their systematic consequences) as
subjects, that is, positions that adopt the theme of transcendental trans-
formations but avoid the formalism of decision and militancy. This is a
matter taken up by Badiou in a recent paper on Foucault, tellingly subti-
tled “Continuity/Discontinuity.” In dealing with Foucault’s own archaeo-
logical treatment of epistemic discontinuities, Badiou qualifies such a
thinking of history as fundamentally non-philosophical. 4 Why? To begin
with, because of Foucault’s disdain for great names and great inven-
tions—his construction of refined archival periodisations in which Des-
cartes features as a footnote and Marx as a minor Ricardian economist.
Alluding to the figure of the eighteenth century emerging from Fou-
cault’s The Order of Things, Badiou starkly proposes that such a history
is unacceptable for a philosophy which, by his definition, is concerned
with the eternity and transmissibility of revolutionary truths. One of the
insistent themes of Badiou’s thinking—most prevalent perhaps in the
first lesson from his book The Century—is that historical time (in the
4
Alain Badiou, “Foucault: continuité / discontinuité” in Le célibataire: Revue de psy-
chanalyse 9, 2004. Quoted from the original manuscript.
Emblems and Cuts 21
guise of periods, epochs, ages, or indeed events) only exists for philoso-
phy to the extent that it presents singular but immortal (atemporal) truths,
moments of subjective exception that explode their spatio-temporal par-
ticularity and are available for universalisation. Indeed, philosophy itself
is defined as the exercise of sheltering the heterogeneous truths of a
given “time,” of rendering these plural and singular truths compossible.
Thus, it is in a sense up to philosophy to produce a time, to give rise to
the concept of a period in which certain truths are contemporaneous to
one another, in a kind of localised network of universalities (of the kind
that might conjoin Einstein, Cantor, Lenin, Picasso and Freud, for in-
stance …). Thus, an eighteenth century filled with minor but momentous
scientists, infamous men and imperceptible, clandestine transformations,
but deprived of Lavoisier or Lagrange, Rousseau or Goethe, is simply in
Badiou’s eyes a non-philosophical century. It is worth noting here the
preponderance in Badiou’s concept of history not just of the emblematic
dates so dear to his character Monvoisin, but of proper names. Much
could indeed be said, especially at the level of the thinking of eventality
delineated in Being and Event, of the periodising function of proper
names (and of their necessary duality: Freud/Lacan; Marx/Lenin; or even
Plato/Badiou…) as representatives of the unrepresentable, opaque mark-
ers of the transcendental transformations that so preoccupy Badiou. But
if, as Jacques Rancière noted, “the revolution in historical science [car-
ried out by the likes of Bloch, Fevbre and Braudel] wanted precisely to
revoke the primacy of events and proper names for the sake of long dura-
tions and the life of the anonymous,” 5 then Badiou’s operation, within
the field of philosophy, constitutes a kind of partial counter-revolution,
albeit one that retains a considerable dose of anonymity within the con-
stitution of the subject and also eschews talk of motives and intentions.
Having said that, it is worth keeping in mind the extent to which
Badiou’s attachment to names and events obliges him into certain narra-
tive gestures seemingly alien to his overall formalising drive. This might
indicate the degree to which his thinking too is determined by the poetics
of history, understood as, to quote Rancière once more, the “power of ar-
ticulation of names and events which is linked to the ontological inde-
terminacy of the story [récit].” 6
5
Jacques Rancière, Les mots de l’histoire (Paris: Seuil, 1992), 7.
6
Ibid., 18.
22 Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy
But, possibly because of the impact of the likes of Braudel,7 and
even more strongly, of his own past, but never repudiated, Marxist alle-
giances, it does not seem that for Badiou history as a discipline could be
conceived in terms of the singularity of the articulation between names
and events. This is why he thinks that Foucault, as a non-philosophical
thinker of singularities, in the end cannot be co-opted by what Badiou
sardonically refers to as the “terrible union of historians,” le terrible syn-
dicat des historiens. For history appears to Badiou first and foremost as a
search for regularities, which, incorporating a reflection on time (versus
Foucault’s immersion of temporal forms into the “spaces” of discourse)
has as its “central formal object … the State/society couple” (where Fou-
cault’s guiding couple is instead the transversal articulation of
power/knowledge). 8 Inasmuch as Badiou links the very concept of the
State to the fundamentally conservative logic of knowledge and repre-
sentation—such that the State is a domain for him devoid of truth or sub-
jectivity—this appears at first as a kind of indictment, a drastic (and we
might even say idealist) separation between history, on the one hand, and
philosophy and subjectivity, on the other.
In his assessment of Foucault’s Society Must Be Defended,
Badiou salutes Foucault’s attempt to move beyond the epistemic discon-
tinuities set out in The Order of Things, and to introduce, in the wake of
the events of ’68, an element of genealogical continuity predicated on the
notion of subjective struggles. According to Badiou, Foucault’s later
texts can be read in terms of the desire to think politics and history to-
gether, and of thinking their bond without subsuming it under the classi-
cal categories of sovereignty or the Marxist critique of political econ-
omy. Badiou’s negative judgment of this attempt, however, is based on
the idea that in the last instance Foucault cannot surpass the horizon that
subordinates both politics and history—or, more precisely, the historicity
of politics—to the paradigm of the State. Foucault’s turn to strategy as
the binding concept between politics and history—founded, in the narra-
tive of Society Must Be Defended, on the convergence of historical narra-
tives of struggle and the bio-political transformation of the State into an
agency for the government and management of life (a convergence
which is in turn anchored in the concept of “race”)—fails, according to
7
Alain Badiou, “Some Replies to a Demanding Friend”, tr. A. Toscano in Think Again:
Alain Badiou and the Future of Philosophy, ed. P. Hallward (London: Continuum, 2004).
8
“Foucault: continuité/discontinuité”.
Emblems and Cuts 23
Badiou, to fulfill Foucault’s own philosophical desideratum, which con-
sists in being able to think the very activity of politics from a subjective
point of view. In other words, Foucault’s two equations, according to
which politics= the State = power, and history = war, end up, in Badiou’s
estimation, subordinating the invention of political forms to the train of
historical becoming. Badiou’s indictment, which resonates with a very
significant bone of contention within the Marxist tradition9, is that Fou-
cault collapses into historicism. The consequence of such a historicism is
that, having stuck politics in the narrow space between “the theory of
powers and the tactics of struggles,” Foucault is incapable of producing
“an affirmative theory of politics”—of politics defined by Badiou as an
“irreducible thought/practice.” 10
This theme of anti-historicism, echoing in part Althusser’s fa-
mous critique of Gramsci in Reading Capital, is one that has marked
much of Badiou’s thinking of politics. In his very sympathetic treatment,
in Metapolitics, of Anthropology of the Name, a book by his friend and
political comrade Sylvain Lazarus, Badiou is most explicit in linking the
aim of thinking the affirmative and irreducible singularity of politics (or
more precisely, of a political sequence) to a critique of historicism and
indeed a separation from history itself, of the kind that might indeed war-
rant Hallward’s estimation that Badiou’s philosophy is grounded in “the
radical subtraction of politics from history altogether.” 11 According to
Lazarus then, “it is only possible to think the singularity of a thought by
evacuating time.” 12 The reason for this stark verdict is that predicating
the singularity of thought and politics on time introduces a dimension of
heteronomy, such that politics is constantly obliged to refer to something
(a context, a base, a motor…) beyond itself, leading to a capture or re-
duction of that very dimension of singularity that was sought in the first
place. This politics of singularity is not simply pitted against the recu-
perative dialectics of totality proper to a Hegelian lineage but also repu-
diates historical-materialist critique, which, according to Lazarus, un-
dermines Hegelian absolute-subjective time by making it circulate be-
9
See Fredric Jameson, “Marxism and Historicism” in The Ideologies of Theory, vol. 2:
The Syntax of History (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1988).
10
“Foucault: continuité/discontinuité”.
11
Peter Hallward, Badiou: A Subject to Truth (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 2003), 43.
12
Alain Badiou, Metapolitics, tr. J. Barker (London: Verso, 2003), 35.
24 Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy
tween two heterogeneous realms (objective-material and ideological-
subjective), and is therefore incapable of thinking singularity. The tem-
poral substance of historical change is thus replaced with a primacy of
names (such as “worker”) that determine the singularity of a politics. As
Badiou puts it, in Lazarus there is an “abolition of time by the name.”
And yet, as Rancière suggests, the names of politics cannot simply be
sundered from their articulation with events and, therefore, from their af-
finity with some notion of time. Hence, the prominence in the thinking of
both Lazarus and Badiou of the notion of a sequence, to be understood in
the first place as a temporality that is immanent to the singularity of a
politics. As Lazarus himself puts it, “the work of identification [of a sin-
gular political thought] is carried out through the delimitation of a se-
quence and its dating.” 13 Whence a certain calendrical obsession that al-
most replaces a traditional concern with political history, and returns us
to the “emblematic” thinking (or “monumental” history, to use a
Nietzschean term) dramatized in the tale from Calme bloc ici-bas.
This problem of the linkage between history and politics, and of
the capacity for the latter to achieve real autonomy as a truth procedure,
is also the guiding idea in Badiou’s reckoning with Althusser, whose
seminal attack on historicism does not suffice, in Badiou’s eyes, to pro-
vide him with the means to develop a real thinking of insurrectionary and
emancipatory subjectivity, which is to say, a thinking of politics. Whence
Badiou’s question: “How are we to distinguish politics from the science
of processes without a subject, that is to say, from the science of history,
in the form of historical materialism? How do we distinguish politics
from (the) science (of historical materialism) without, quite obviously,
reducing it to ideology?” 14 For Badiou, Althusser’s solution is dependent
on a certain understanding of philosophy, which, as an agent of demarca-
tion, is aimed at indicating the space of politics (the space of the subject,
of militancy, of contingency and antagonism) without allowing it to be
fully colonised by the theory of science or the logic of ideology. “Phi-
losophy is guarded from the danger of confusing history and politics
(therefore science and politics) on account of itself lacking history. Phi-
losophy authorises a non-historicist perception of political events.” 15
This last sentence provides us with an apposite characterisation of an im-
13
Quoted in Metapolitics, 38.
14
Metapolitics, 60.
15
Metapolitics, 62.
Emblems and Cuts 25
portant aspect of Badiou’s own research program. Significantly,
Badiou’s own attempt at generating an anti-humanist theory of the sub-
ject was first announced in his 1967 review of For Marx and Reading
Capital, which ended on the promissory note of complementing the Al-
thusserian grasp of the epistemological break constituted by Marx’s dis-
covery of the continent of history, with a militant and subjective focus on
a Sartrean “theory of historical sets.”16 However, though Badiou com-
mends Sartre for holding fast to the question of the subject in the middle
of structuralist “objectivism,” and for providing guidance in the thinking
of a radical upsurge of emancipatory novelty, he cannot ignore Sartre’s
own historicism, which is to say, his temporalised thinking of social to-
tality. Thus, in the pamphlet he wrote on the occasion of Sartre’s death in
1980, Badiou looks back on his old mentor, and more specifically on the
project outlined in the massive Critique of Dialectical Reason, in the fol-
lowing terms:
But in the end we can say the following: the Subject, which is
necessarily in question today is not the subject of History. The
idea of a historical totalisation is not admissible. It is the political
subject, an altogether particular subject, which is in question. So
Sartre’s question is not exactly the right one.… But Sartre re-
mains an awakener of Marxism. He precisely invites us to reflect
on politics and on History, because he has taken to its limit a
purely historical and revolutionary conception of Marxism. 17
In the work produced following the high period of his “militant”
philosophical production, Badiou appears to radicalise the Althusserian
attack on historicism and on theories of expressive totality and jettison
the very notion of historical totality altogether, severing him from much
of what would pass for Western Marxism. In Theory of the Subject, the
text that concerns me here, this detotalisation is extracted from a hetero-
dox or anti-synthetic reading of Hegel, as well as from Lacan’s theses on
the Real as the impasse of the symbolic. In more recent work, it will de-
pend more heavily on mathematical logic and the set-theoretical axio-
16
Alain Badiou, “Le (re)commencement du matérialisme dialectique” in Critique 240
1967, 466–7. See also Nina Power, “Towards an Anthropology of Infinitude: Badiou and
the Political Subject” in Cosmos and History, vol. 2, no. 1, 2006, 186–209.
17
Alain Badiou, Jean-Paul Sartre (Paris: Éditions Potemkine, 1980), 8, 16.
26 Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy
matic, though Hegelianism will remain both the target and touchstone of
Badiou’s thinking. 18 In a painstaking endeavour to disarticulate the circu-
larities and redundancies of the Hegelian dialectic, Badiou seeks to gen-
erate a materialist dialectic that is capable of including the unpredictable
irruptions and interventions of organised subjects, to affirm radical nov-
elty at the very point where the Hegelian dialectic maintained not just a
structure of expression but one of recollection, such that any novelty is
always-already a kind of unfolding, if not a mere return. It is this attempt
to force political novelty into the dialectic that obliges Badiou to face the
question of periodisation, of the time, and indeed the timing of politics.
The paradox that dominates this theoretical moment, and to some extent
his more recent work as well, can perhaps be formulated as follows: in
order to avert the absorption of politics by History, Badiou must think
through the historicity proper to politics.
Ontologically speaking, the requirement of a periodising dialec-
tic is founded on the statement that “history does not exist,” for it would
otherwise be a “figure of the whole,” 19 and the whole is seen by Badiou,
already a thinker of the radicality of transformation, as synonymous with
a ban on the new. Moreover, such a detotalisation is explicitly concerned
with the issue of communism, which as we saw, dominates, at least in a
first phase, Badiou’s thinking on history. The inexistence of history-qua-
totality is explicitly linked to a Maoist conception of communism, which
refuses to consider it as a domain of the pure and simple realisation of
equality, as an end of history—and which thus opens onto the inelucta-
bility of periodisation and the need to think the trajectories of the subject
(what Badiou refers to, following Lacan, as the subject’s “topology”).
The lesson that Badiou draws from this militant critique of totality is
summed up in the words: “Periodise, and move beyond.” 20 From success
to failure to new success to new failure, the political subject journeys
through linked but discontinuous conjunctures, every one of which is
relative to the sequence in question, such that the subject is not allowed
any horizon of final victory. Making show of a kind of “Beckettian”
communism, Badiou thus declares: “Every victory is the beginning of a
18
Alain Badiou, “Hegel and the Whole” in Theoretical Writings, ed. R. Brassier and A.
Toscano (London: Continuum, 2004), 227–38.
19
Alain Badiou, Théorie du sujet (Paris: Seuil, 1982), 110.
20
Ibid.
Emblems and Cuts 27
new type of failure.” 21 Struggles may be final, but final relative to the se-
quence, and this finality is the internal mode of historicisation or tempo-
ralisation proper to a given sequence, what Badiou calls its “satura-
tion.” 22 This is the sense in which the theory of the subject as a theory of
Marxist politics (as opposed to historical materialism) depends for
Badiou on overturning the traditional image according to which Marxism
is founded on a thinking of capitalist society as a totality. If history as to-
tality—as the history of the totality and the totality of history—does not
exist, what is the element in which the subject traces the arduous path of
its novelties (and its destructions)? For Badiou only historical epochs, or
better “historicisations” are given, not History.
The subject of these historicisations, wrested from the repetition
that governs any order, is identified by Badiou with novelty, with the
struggle between the old and the new. This forms what we could call the
heroic frame underlying much of his thought. As Badiou emblematically
declares, “every rightness (justesse) and every justice are in principle
novelties, and everything that repeats itself is unjust and inexact.”23 Such
a novelty can only be attested by its consequences, and these conse-
quences can only be gauged in terms of how a novelty traverses and
transforms (or destroys) the situation or world whence it arose. Looking
beyond the dates that punctuate a sequence, there is thus a need of think-
ing the historicity internal to a truth procedure or a process of subjectiva-
tion. In the earlier works, this can be found in the theme of purification,
such that “in every contradiction, force manifests its impurity by the
aleatory process of its purification.” 24 In the more recent writings, this
temporality or historicity is provided by the extraction of a generic set,
which is impervious to (or technically speaking, “indiscernible”) to the
knowledge of the situation, and which generates a truth of the situation in
what Badiou refers to as a “future perfect” (futur antérieur ).
Though the temporality or historicity immanent to a subjective
sequence has perhaps not received sufficient attention in Badiou’s
work—excepting perhaps his two recent treatments of the Paris Com-
21
Ibid.
22
See the interview with Alain Badiou in Carceraglio, available at:
http://scentedgardensfortheblind.blogspot.com/2006_10_15_scentedgardensfortheblind_a
rchive.html#116103479719156657).
23
Théorie du sujet, 57.
24
Ibid., 56.
28 Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy
mune and the Cultural Revolution, now collected in the book Polemics—
as I have noted already his thinking has struggled quite consistently with
the issue of periodisation. Indeed, in Théorie du sujet the very task of
history is defined as that of finding “the right period.” Badiou thus pre-
sents periodisation in the Théorie du sujet as a dialectical alternative to
the Hegelian absolute, understood as a thinking that closes the dialectical
process. According to Badiou, the Hegelian notion of the absolute de-
pends on the idea that a “dialectical sequence approaches its closure
when the practical process carries the theory of its own trajectory (sil-
lage).” 25 But, it is vis-à-vis this question of closure that dialectics splits
into two. The Hegelian option is that of “theological circularity, which,
presupposing the absolute in the germs of the beginning, leads us back to
this very beginning once all the stages of its effectuation, exit-from-itself,
or alienation have been deployed.” It is a theological circularity, which
finds its explicit model in the relationship between God and his Son,
such that the sundering of the former is ultimately evidence and guaran-
tee of his eternal unity and totality. The path of periodisation is instead
marked by the violence of discontinuity, by a “pure passage from one se-
quence to the other, in an irreconcilable and unsuturable lag, in which the
True of the first stage is only given as a condition of the fact of the sec-
ond, and leads to nothing but the deployment of this fact.… The second
sequence gets into gear when the condition for the theoretical balance-
sheet of the first are ready.” 26
Albeit enriched by his attempt to recast the Hegelian dialectic as
a dialectic of irreducible division, Badiou’s model of periodisation here
is explicitly political. It is a matter of grasping, from within the history of
Marxist politics, how revolutionary politics is itself periodised by the
non-expressive relation between sequences. This discontinuity marks the
fact that we are not dealing with a seamless and cumulative tradition,
where later sequences would simply learn from the lessons of the old, but
with the notion that it is in the impasses and impossibilities of a previous
sequence, a first moment, that a second sequence intervenes, generating
the kind of novelty which does not simply solve the problems of the first,
but generates an entirely new evaluation of the requirements of novelty
and emancipation. It is this creative retroaction, according to Badiou, that
permits us to periodise, and to understand the act of periodisation as im-
25
Ibid., 37.
26
Ibid., 38.
Emblems and Cuts 29
manent in the deployment of a subject (and thus incommensurable with
any objective chronology). The dialectic of cumulative completion and
resolution is thus replaced by a dialectic of failure and innovation, where
what stood as an impasse and remained unthinkable in a previous se-
quence is not the germ, but merely the site for the inventions of a later
one. It is thus that “Lenin’s Bolshevik party is the active bearer of the
failures of the Paris Commune. This is what Lenin marks by dancing on
the snow when power has been held in Moscow in 1917 for one more
day [73] than in Paris in 1871. It is the break of October which periodises
the Paris Commune, turning a page of the history of the world.”27 This
periodisation, made up of “deferred and differing retroactions,” whereby
nothing can be deduced in the passage from the first sequence to the sec-
ond, is at the heart of Badiou’s attempt to recast dialectics in the Théorie
du sujet. Against the single time of the Hegelian dialectic, Badiou, by
taking the evaluations of the Commune by Marx and Lenin respectively
as his material, points us to the splits internal to the very notion of perio-
disation, and a fortiori, to that of novelty:
Every periodisation must embrace its dialectical double time, to
contain, for instance, October ’17 as the second, and provision-
ally final, scansion of the balance-sheet [of the Paris Commune].
Whence the embarrassment of historians: according to the rela-
tion between force and place, the Commune is new (Marx). Ac-
cording to the relation between the objective and the subjective,
it is instead October that is new, and the Commune is that edge
of the old whose practical perception, by purifying force, par-
takes in the engendering of its novelty. 28
In other words the dialectical criteria of periodisation are themselves split
(at least) into two, thus demonstrating the complexities of subjective pe-
riodisation—which here depends on the retroactive intervention of the
Bolshevik sequence (a thinking of the party and of the subjective “art of
insurrection”)—and its irreducibility to any criteria of objective chronol-
ogy.
27
Ibid., 38. See also the more recent appraisal in “The Paris Commune: A Political Dec-
laration on Politics” in Polemics, tr. S. Corcoran (London: Verso, 2006), 257–90.
28
Théorie du sujet, 64–5.
30 Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy
Though, as I have noted, the problem of periodisation, and of the
articulation between politics and history, is one that has remained with
Badiou, the more recent work, with its attempt to bolster a Theory of the
Subject with a set-theoretical ontological infrastructure, has found itself
obliged to grapple with, and substantially reinvent, the demarcation be-
tween nature and history. Without delving overmuch into the technical
details, “nature” in Being and Event (1988), is understood as the form of
homogeneity of the (structured) multiple, or multiple-in-situation. His-
tory is instead recast by Badiou as a meta-ontological category; it enters
the fray with the issue of “what-is-not-being-qua-being,” with the inter-
ruption of the natural order, or the excess vis-à-vis the normalcy of na-
ture. In other words, where his earlier Theory of the Subject found it nec-
essary to declare the inexistence of history to make room for the discon-
tinuous historicity of periodisations, in Being and Event “history” stands
for the untotalisable and the singular. As Badiou writes:
The place of thought of that-which-is-not-being is the non-
natural; that which is presented other than natural or stable or
normal multiplicities. The place of the other-than-being is the
abnormal, the unstable, the anti-natural. I will term historical
what is thus determined as the opposite of nature. 29
Moreover, whereas even in texts like the recent talk on Foucault, history
is equated with a thinking of the State, in Being and Event, the category
of “history” is used to very different ends, to indicate those multiplicities
which are singular, in other words one of whose terms is presented in a
situation but not represented by the State (Badiou’s example is that of a
“singular” family, one of whose members—a clandestine lodger, for in-
stance—cannot be counted or recognized by the state, understood as the
agent of re-presentation). A situation is defined as historical, then, when
it includes not just singular multiples but what Badiou calls an “evental
site,” to wit a multiple none of whose parts is accounted for in represen-
tation.
We might wonder what is the strategy or reasoning behind this
equating of history with singularity, especially if we take into account the
detotalising character of the dialectic as presented in Theory of the Sub-
ject. To an extent, this strategy is dictated by the parameters of Being and
29
Alain Badiou, Being and Event, tr. O. Feltham (London: Continuum, 2006), 173–4.
Emblems and Cuts 31
Event as a historically specific philosophical intervention. Writing in
1988, and no longer preoccupied directly with salvaging a kernel of dia-
lectic novelty from Marxism and Hegelianism, Badiou is really trying to
usurp, with the aid of his formidable meta-ontological capture of set the-
ory, the ontological mantle from Heidegger. Hence the new formalisation
of the notion of “historicity”: “The multiple-form of historicity is what
lies entirely within the instability of the singular; it is that upon which the
state’s meta-structure has no hold. It is a point of subtraction from the
state’s re-securing of the count.” 30 Where historicity is linked to singular-
ity, “history,” as a non-totalisable domain, is related to the idea of the en-
tirely abnormal multiple, the eventual site—a concept that Badiou had
coined in order to maintain the idea of a rational grasp of the sources of
emancipatory politics, drawn from the Marxist notion of the proletariat,
whilst abdicating any notion of historical totality or direction.31
The void of the proletariat as a historical exception is now trans-
ferred onto a void in the situation, and history—inasmuch as it is linked
to multiples whose elements are unrepresented, excluded—is always in a
sense a history of, or from, the void (whilst if we remain within the situa-
tion as it is ordinarily represented all we have is knowledge and its repe-
tition). In Badiou’s definition, a “historical situation is therefore, in at
least one of its points, on the edge of the void. Historicity is thus presen-
tation at the punctual limits of its being.” 32 History and historicity are
thereby withdrawn from the domain of meaning and totality, and ren-
dered over to an interventionist notion of singularity, whereby subjectiv-
ity is what forces the unrepresented, that which is foreclosed from the
situation, into appearance, in other words, what gives body and voice to
what was, viewed from the standpoint of the state of the situation, a nul-
lity. This also means that the Hegelian notion of the absolute in history,
of an absolute history—already attacked by the earlier theory of periodi-
sation—is further distanced. As Badiou writes, in his most succinct defi-
nition of the nature/history dichotomy:
Nature is absolute, historicity relative. One of the profound char-
acteristics of singularities is that they can always be normalized:
30
Ibid.
31
See my “Marxism Expatriated: Alain Badiou’s Turn” in Critical Companion to Con-
temporary Marxism, ed. J. Bidet and S. Kouvelakis (Leiden: Brill, 2007).
32
Being and Event, 177.
32 Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy
as is shown, moreover, by socio-political History; any evental
site can, in the end, undergo a state normalization. However, it is
impossible to singularize natural normality. If one admits that for
there to be historicity evental sites are necessary, then the fol-
lowing observation can be made: history can be naturalized, but
nature cannot be historicized. There is a striking dissymmetry
here, which prohibits—outside the framework of the ontological
thought of the pure multiple—any unity between nature and his-
tory. 33
But this very notion of the relativity of history is what allows Badiou to
incorporate, into the speculative fabric of Being and Event, the declara-
tion of Theory of the Subject, according to which “history does not ex-
ist.” For in this new schema, there is no such thing as History conceived
as a trans-situational site for the emergence of the new, as a global con-
text of subjectivation. As argued above, historicity can only be defined
situationally, never intrinsically (unlike nature): “there are situated even-
tal sites, but there is no evental situation.”34 This is why the criterion for
defining a historical situation is always “local” according to Badiou.35 In
other words, the idea of an absolute or total domain of history is chimeri-
cal, since it would be the idea, in Badiou’s terms, of a domain, a region
of absolute abnormality. That is why he can declare: “We can think the
historicity of certain multiples, but we cannot think a History.”36 This
thesis is then at the heart of Badiou’s distancing from what he now re-
gards as the largely imaginary idea of revolution—as the “idea of an
overturning whose origin would be a state of the totality”—and the ob-
verse move to what he calls a “differential topology of action” in which
every “radical transformational action originates in a point, which, inside
a situation, is an evental site.” 37 Though this seems to radically limit the
purview of history, there is a sense in which Badiou seems to resuscitate
a notion of history as revelation, a notion which is far more immediate
than Hegel’s expressive dialectic of historical revelation. As Badiou
writes in Being and Event, inasmuch as history and historicity are linked
33
Ibid., 176.
34
Ibid.
35
Ibid., 511.
36
Ibid.,176.
37
Ibid.
Emblems and Cuts 33
to the pivotal notion of the evental site, it is “solely in the point of his-
tory, the representative precariousness of evental sites, that it will be re-
vealed, via the chance of a supplement, that being-multiple inconsists.” 38
In other words, it is only in “history” that the inconsistency which
Badiou argues is at the heart of being makes itself felt through the irrup-
tion of novelty and the construction of the generic by a subject. This
means, however, that history is once again—albeit outside of any figure
of totality, as a kind of flash and aftershock—the arena for the revelation
of being (inasmuch as what is not being qua being, the illegality of the
event, is the only thing that allows the thinking of being qua being, i.e.,
inconsistency).
Finally, and to complicate even further the history of Badiou’s
relation to history—which as we have seen is also full of anticipations,
retractions, and impasses, which is to say of periodisations—we must
note that ontology itself (which is to say mathematics) is itself open to
historicity, in a way which we could provocatively say turns Badiou into
something like an absolute historicist. As he writes in Being and Event:
“Our goal is to establish the meta-ontological thesis that mathematics is
the historicity of the discourse on being qua being.” 39 In other words, far
from being a static eternal formalisation of abstract being, ontology
(mathematics) is itself structured by radical events. Indeed, it was one of
these events, the invention of irrational numbers against the background
of Pythagorean mathematics, that in Badiou’s Being and Event served as
the paragon of subjectivation, understood as that which forces an impos-
sible into the field of the possible, and draws the consequences of this
new inclusion.
The real is the impossible, to wit the resistance of the in-
numerable, of what is not a natural number. The subject presents,
in the failure of the imaginary [the philosophical wish for the
simple order of natural numbers], the numerable to the innumer-
able: it effectuates itself as the mathematical desire to number
the innumerable, to legalise the impossible. 40
38
Ibid., 177.
39
Ibid., 13.
40
Théorie du sujet, 219.
34 Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy
Badiou’s own thinking of periodisation, not just of mathematics, but of
politics, is explicitly founded on this model, on this gesture of historicis-
ing mathematics and mathematising history, in order to retain both the
absoluteness of truth and the contingency of its emergence.
I want to allude to at least one of the problems opened up by
such a powerful gesture, when its own criteria are dialectically applied to
itself. In a superb commentary on some of the possible impasses and
paradoxes generated by such a historicisation of ontology via mathemat-
ics, Quentin Meillasoux, author of After Finitude, defines the fundamen-
tal tenets of Badiou’s philosophy in terms of two statements, to wit that
“mathematics is ontology” and that “every truth is post-evental.” The
consequence of the first statement, as noted, is rather momentous for the
relation between philosophy and history:
To assert that mathematics is ontology comes down to attributing
to ontology a history, and a history which is moreover independ-
ent of any philosophical postulation. This history is the history of
mathematics, which no one can anticipate, which makes onto-
logical novelties to come into essentially unpredictable emer-
gences. 41
According to the second statement, since all truths are post-evental, the
very structure of the historicity of mathematics will remain faithful to the
schema of evental truth—as laid out by Badiou’s philosophy. However,
Meillasoux argues, the tension between the two statements—born of the
fact, confronted by Badiou himself, that not all mathematical ontologies
are compatible with his thinking of truth—results in the subordination, in
Badiou’s work, of the first to the second. In other words, the philosophy
of the event filters mathematics, and legislates in a way over how the his-
tory of ontology may “turn out.” Meillasoux instead proposes to invert
the subordination and—by affirming the tendency in Badiou’s work to
absolutising the history of ontology—to problematise the very thinking
of history borne by his most recent intellectual production. The option
proposed by Meillasoux consists in saying that “since nothing can be an-
ticipated about the becoming of ontology—including its future compati-
bility with the philosophy of the event—the evental status of truths itself
41
Quentin Meillasoux, “Nouveauté et événement” in Alain Badiou. Penser le multiple,
ed. C. Ramond (Paris: L’Harmattan, 2002), 39.
Emblems and Cuts 35
must be able to succumb under the weight of a new ontology” (which is
to say that ontological novelties might no longer be truths). 42 This possi-
bility of a novelty that dislocates Badiou’s own concept of novelty (qua
post-evental subjectivation and construction of a generic truth) is a risk
which a philosophy that began by breaking open the Hegelian circle for
the sake of an unpredictable spiral of periodisations cannot avoid. It is
perhaps in this sense that Badiou’s philosophy, by holding fast to its anti-
historicist impetus in order to save the singularity of the event and the
emancipatory potentials of novelty, cannot help but confront the chal-
lenge and threat that an absolute historicism poses to the concept of
truth.43
[email protected]
42
Ibid., 42.
43
In Jameson’s terms, this designates the Marxian scandal of “the conjunction between
an absolute scientific truth and its enabling situation in contingent, empirical history.”
“Marxism and Historicism”, 164.