Religion and Science Freebook
Religion and Science Freebook
Religion and Science Freebook
VISIT WWW.ROUTLEDGE.COM
TO BROWSE FULL RANGE OF RELIGION TITLES
4
1
THE BASIC QUESTION
SCIENCE OR RELIGION, OR SCIENCE
AND RELIGION
Learn more
Chapter 1
6
Chapter 1
7
Chapter 1
8
Chapter 1
9
Chapter 1
10
Chapter 1
11
Chapter 1
12
Chapter 1
13
Chapter 1
14
Chapter 1
15
Chapter 1
16
Chapter 1
17
Chapter 1
18
Chapter 1
TAKING STOCK
What can we learn from this debate? First, it breaks at least one
widespread stereotype: the tendency to associate all naturalists
with science and all theists with an anti-scientific attitude. This is
the first assumption many make in any discussion of science and
religion; it is also one that is widely popularized in the media and
in large-market books. Many people tend to identify science with
an ultimate or ?metaphysical?naturalism; they then associate belief
in God with an anti-scientific attitude.
Yet our short debate has already shown that such easy
identifications are too simplistic. Our theist, at any rate, was
interested in the results of science. He accepted evolution and
incorporated it as part of his understanding of life on earth and of
human beings. He grounded his arguments for the existence of God
in data about the origin of the universe and its laws (cosmology).
19
Chapter 1
20
Chapter 1
21
Chapter 1
22
2
ISLAM AND SCIENCE
Learn more
Chapter 2
24
Chapter 2
25
Chapter 2
26
Chapter 2
27
Chapter 2
28
Chapter 2
29
Chapter 2
30
Chapter 2
31
Chapter 2
32
Chapter 2
view on matter and the material world. This theory relied on the
presence of four main elements, which constituted the entire
material universe in the sub-lunar sphere. Outside the sub-lunar
sphere, celestial bodies were formed of a different, more superior
element, and moved in perfect circles around the Earth. This
theory, as espoused and developed by many Islamic philosophers,
such as Avicenna and Averroes, implied the eternity of the universe
and that the entire cosmological formation has existed since
eternity and is infinite in nature (Averroes 2001).
Coming into contact with the religious notions of
instantaneous creation, philosophers and scientists were inspired
to develop the Aristotelian principles and the theological doctrines
in different directions. Averroes, who was a judge, a physician, and
a philosopher, argued that instantaneous creation contradicts the
main tenets of Islamic creed, as it implies a change in the will of
God, who is unchanging and permanent. Some Mutazilite
theologians argued that instantaneous creation is necessary to
ensure the uniqueness of the Deity and argued, still in line with
Aristotelian theory, that this theory does not imply the eternity of
the universe by necessity.
Al-Ghazali found the Epicurean atomist theory to provide a
more plausible understanding of the world. According to the
ancient and medieval atomist theory, all beings are made of
infinitely small indivisible particles called atoms, which coalesce to
form different beings. Muslim Epicurean physicists believed that
these atoms have an inherent continuous random movement,
which would not allow them to stay in form save for the will of
God, who can keep bodies intact. This view was adopted by schools
of occasionalist theology, which also claimed a continuous act of
creation by God in the form of preserving bodies from inevitable
disintegration. On the other hand, other Epicurean scientists, along
with many theologians and religious scholars, such as Imam Fakhr
33
Chapter 2
34
Chapter 2
35
Chapter 2
36
Chapter 2
37
Chapter 2
38
Chapter 2
underpinnings.
Early twentieth century and the popularization of science
During this period, the intellectual elite changed radically in its
identity, training, and aptitude. The new elite was formed of
graduates of European-style schools, missionary schools, as well as
universities in the main European intellectual centers. This allowed
for the appearance of many journals, magazines, and newspapers,
which engaged in the popularization of sciences. Many of these
publications addressed direct technical needs of their readerships,
such as methods to manufacture glue, or to treat acne. Other
magazines specialized in a particular kind of technical knowledge,
such as the famous?mamlakat al-Nahal/ The Kingdom of
Bees,?which presented the reader with scientific methods in
apiculture (Elshakry 2008).
At the same time, al-Azhar Magazine(1929), along with other
publications, featured the writings of a number of religious
scholars and scientists of religious background, who insisted on the
genealogical connection of modern science to the Islamic middle
ages. Writings on the scientific interpretation of sacred texts
gained popularity, where religious scholars argued that the Quran
should be viewed as a book of nature as well as of religion, and
that it contains, albeit in hidden and cryptic language, references to
modern scientific facts, which prove the divine nature of the text.
The religious intellectual elites of the period encountered
evolution, which constituted a scientific theory and a
socio-political discourse, as Darwin and Huxley?s writings were
translated to Arabic. Religious authors argued that Darwinism was
not based on scientific facts and that it was refuted by most
scientists in Europe, and evolution was portrayed as a political
ideology that was forced on science. In that sense, evolution was
rejected by many religious scholars through emphasizing a
39
Chapter 2
40
Chapter 2
41
Chapter 2
42
Chapter 2
43
3
THE COGNITIVE SCIENCES
A BRIEF INTRODUCTION FOR
SCIENCE AND RELIGION
#
Learn more
Chapter 3
45
Chapter 3
46
Chapter 3
47
Chapter 3
48
Chapter 3
49
Chapter 3
50
Chapter 3
the brain. This means that the BOLD signal can differ depending
only on differences in circuit organization, even for circuits in the
same general area of the brain and under circumstances that yield
identical numbers of action potentials.
Another aspect of brain-activity measurement by fMRI is that
measured BOLD signal changes due to cognitive processing are of
the order of 0.1 to 1 per cent of the total measured signal (Raichle
2003). Thus one must always keep in mind that the BOLD signal is
generally a contrast in signal between two or more measurements,
each conducted under some set of defined conditions. What this
means is that reported fMRI activations, or areas where the brain
looks to be?lit up?by bright spots, are not the result of the neural
circuitry in those areas going from an?off? state to an?on?state.
Rather, activations are typically the result of a brain area going
from giving a signal of, say, 10 to a signal of 10.05, in a statistically
significant manner. BOLD activations are almost always differential
activations between conditions. This means that the given region
may have been activated in all conditions, but more so in some
than in others.
When inferring the information processing that associates
with a given brain area?s activation, it is important to keep in mind
that whether or not a brain area is activated during a given
information-processing condition does not by itself establish that
the brain area is, or is not, required for the information processing
function under investigation (Cacioppo et al. 2003). Observed brain
activation could be (1) due to a failure to control for all key
contextual variables in contrasting task conditions; or (2) the result
of activity in another circuit in another area entirely, which actually
carries out the information-processing function. Conversely, failure
to observe brain activation could arise even in the presence of
differences in neural activity, if the differences are in different
neural circuits that differ substantially in synaptic organization
51
Chapter 3
52
Chapter 3
53
Chapter 3
54
Chapter 3
55
Chapter 3
56
Chapter 3
57
4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE
SCIENCE THAT DOESN'T
ALIENATE EVERYONE
# EXCEPT COGNITIVE
SCIENTISTS
Learn more
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
Abst ract
This introductory chapter discusses the phenomena that
preoccupies this book: religious belief taken for granted as
self-evident truisms. A challenge to studying these phenomena is
that researchers are ?speaking a different language? than the
participants in the studies. There seems to be an impasse, and this
chapter is about looking to William James as inspiration for how to
overcome it. James was against an abstract notion of belief where
something can be separated from a belief about the thing. Belief is
misunderstood when we separate it from a thing that we have a
belief about because belief necessarily involves knowledge about
something. He was also against a disembodied notion of belief.
Experience includes how our senses entwine with happenings in
life. The flow of human experience includes continual relation
among ideas and the body, which means that it does not make
sense to abstract belief from the concrete materiality of the world.
This chapter outlines how an impasse between researchers and
participants emerges because the former take an abstract and
disembodied approach to belief. The quarrel with research is not
with the dismissal of religious belief as an accident, but the
underlying presuppositions of what religious belief is. This chapter
thereby outlines how the impasse emerged and presents what we
can do to move forward.
Int roduct ion
Blake Wenner was a student for whom I supervised a research
project on the topic of religious doubt. He was interested in
examining how Christian believers developed and reconciled
doubts. His desire to do this research came from his own
experience where he saw belief held together by dubious
rationalizations and thinly veiled self-interest. He recruited and
interviewed participants who were Christian believers and what
59
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
Participants described belief, but they did not spend a lot of time
wondering why they believed. They illustrated how belief, like in
this quote above, is a simple thing that becomes a matter of trust
and not one worthy of preoccupation. It was just taken for granted
as a truism, and participants did not know why they believed per se
because they simply trusted. Blake did not get what he was looking
for, and the question is, ?Why??
Blake is typical of researchers in a way that helps us
understand why he did not get what he was looking for. It was like
he was speaking a different language than his participants. He was
talking about beliefs grounded in careful rationale, and they just
didn?t talk in these terms. They were talking about a life that imply
included belief. While Blake?s engagement was kindly agnostic,
60
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
61
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
62
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
63
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
belief functions in life to show how our religious beliefs are about
something. He highlighted how belief is about relationships in the
sense that one can have knowledge about another thought or
another thing, but it always involves a relation to another thing. All
things that fall under the banner of belief involve relationships so
that we do not have any element of belief that is isolated and on its
own. That is, every belief is related to something else, and it simply
does not make sense to talk about a belief that stands as a
subjective isomorphic proposition. Belief is a kind of knowledge in
relation to something else, and so we always have religious belief
in relation to another thing.
This approach to belief is what enables James to break us out
of the abstract approach we get from Kant and Descartes, which is
important because abstract conceptions of belief simply miss the
phenomenon. This position has a huge implication for how we
think of ideas like subjective mind and objective reality. James
wrote:
Just so, I maintain, does a given undivided portion of
experience, taken in one context of associates, play the part
of the knower, of a state of mind, of ?consciousness?; while in
a different context the same undivided bit of experience
plays the part of the thing known, of an ?objective?content . .
. since it can figure in both groups simultaneously we have
every right to speak of it as subjective and objective both at
once.
(James, 1996/ 1912, p. 10)
To many people, speaking in terms of belief being both objective
and subjective seems strange, but it provides a very helpful idea. A
belief in another belief can be subjective, but the web of relations
involved in belief never stops there in self-contained subjectivity.
All belief eventually comes into relation with something in the
64
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
65
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
66
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
how our senses entwine with happenings in life. When one looks
out at the environment in which one is reading, for example, light
rays stimulate cells on the retina, and the activity of cells happens
in relation to what is in life. This is a simplistic example of
experience and highlights how experience involves a flow of
sensory stimulation occurring in relation to the world. We move
through life with our bodies responding in relation to things, and
so one experience passes into another in a constant flow.
The constant flow of experience involves more complexity
than merely being stimulated by an environment. If one were to sit
and read in a café, one could look around and see the stimuli in
terms of coherent and meaningful unities like ?tables? and
?chairs.? Previous flows of experience such as learning the names
for such things in childhood bleeds into the current flow to give
sensory stimulation shape. Included in the previous experiences
that are brought into the present are emotions and personal
histories. A café may feel a certain way because of previous
experiences like, for example, spending time with a caregiver at
cafés that gives the tables and chairs emotional valence. James
(1996/ 1912) pointed out that experience includes a constant flow
of stimuli in relation to one another and in relation to
psychological phenomena like concepts and emotions. He pointed
out how experience involves an inseparable relation between
psychological phenomena and physiological ones. The flow of
human experience includes continual relations among a range of
elements, and so it does not make sense to abstract conscious
phenomena like belief from the concrete materiality of the world.
Hence, he argued against the idea that that the ?thought-of [an]
object is hid away inside the thinking subject? (1996/ 1909, p. 19)
because the past can impact us directly to shape what is
experienced as real. Belief is something that is experienced in the
flow of the life that we live and experience as real. It is part of the
67
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
68
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
69
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
70
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
71
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
72
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
73
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
74
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
75
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
notion of scientific truth. This section outlines a vision for CSR that
sets the groundwork for the future steps proposed herein. For our
purposes, I will outline three criteria for truth that enable this
expansion.
First criterion for truth: fit in life
James (2011/ 1909) expanded the definition of truth by arguing
that it is always inextricably bound to life because people do not
use truth in an abstract and disembodied sense. This means that
truth is not used in a vacuum because people use it in relation to
all of the other aspects of life. For example, consider the following
interview extract.
76
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
77
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
78
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
79
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
80
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
81
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
82
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
83
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
84
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
85
Chapter 4
TOWARD A COGNITIVE SCIENCE
THAT DOESN'T ALIENATE EVERYONE
EXCEPT COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS
Excerpted from Culutre and the Cognitive Science of Religion
86
5
RELIGIOUS POWER AND
KNOWLEDGE
QUESTIONS RAISED ON THE
# PRESUPPOSITIONS OF
"PERSPECTIVISM" AMONG INDIGENOUS
PEOPLES
Learn more
Chapter 5
Pref ace
In this article, I take a holistic approach to the various bodies of
powerful knowledge guarded by religious specialists in Baniwa
culture that can all be seen as interrelated. Based on my research, I
show that Baniwa jaguar shamans are central figures in a nexus of
religious knowledge and power in which healers, sorcerers, priestly
chanters, and ceremonial dance-leaders share complementary
functions, linking the living guardians of traditions with the deities
and great spirits of the cosmos, the primordial and eternal
?owners,? ?keepers? and generators of knowledge and power.
Throughout, I shall comment on the adequacy of the line of
ethnology called ?perspectivism? for the study of Baniwa
cosmology and religious history. Thus it is first appropriate to
outline briefl y the main presuppositions of perspectivism. An
important feature of many indigenous cosmologies is the existence
of multiple points of view about the nature of being held by
different kinds of beings (humans, animals, fish, etc.). This
perspectivism, a term that has been used by Eduardo Viveiros de
Castro to characterize ?Amerindian? modes of thought, is useful in
understanding many Amerindian religious traditions, although it
has not been shown to be a universal feature.The theory focuses
on certain kinds of relations among beings? human and
other-than-human? that are strongly influenced by the themes of
predation (studied typically in rituals of cannibalism, warfare,
sorcery and mortuary symbolism). It should be pointed out,
however, that other forms of reciprocity? as in giving thanks,
offerings to the Creator, expressions of the Creator?s love for
humans, and forms of divine sacrifice for the well-being of
humanity? were not considered in the first versions of the
perpectivist theory by Viveiros de Castro.
According to this theory, the way in which humans see
88
Chapter 5
89
Chapter 5
90
Chapter 5
91
Chapter 5
92
Chapter 5
Prophet Movement s
Prophets emerge from a configuration of historical circumstances
internal or external to society, such as outbreaks of witchcraft, or
the dangerous accumulation of secular power. A brief review of key
themes in prophetic movements in Northwest Amazonia reveals
that most have been focused on the same questions that lie at the
foundation of their traditions: how can the knowledge and a way of
life (a habitus,if you will) be reproduced in the face of constant
historical changes? How can humans secure what is most sacred to
them in the face of potentially massive destruction and/ or
obliteration of their ancestral traditions?
To begin the discussion, common to many of the prophetic
movements throughout Amazonian history is the search for a
utopia, which can take one of two forms. The first is spatial,which
can mean either a return? led by the prophet(s)? to a place of
sacred origin in order to re-unite with the primordial and eternal
people and divinities. This was a dominant theme in seven
prophetic movements that took place within a relatively short
period of time at the beginning of the twentieth century among the
Ticuna of the upper Amazon River. Humanity, it was believed, had
strayed too far from the morally correct ways of living, and the
prophets, or ?those who desire to be sacred? (young people in
several cases), showed the way back to places at the headwaters of
certain streams where Yoi,the Creator, and the primordial people
were to be found.
Often, the search for a perfect place is something ?foretold
from old.? That is, in the stories of creation and the first people,
mention is made of ancient migrations to the perfect place, which
only some attained, whereas the rest did not. The Apurina,
Arawak-speaking people of the southern Amazon, tell the story of
ancestral migrations to the perfect place in the north; half of
93
Chapter 5
94
Chapter 5
like those of the Andean region with whom the Guarani maintained
regular commercial relations. The tendency to centralization of
power met resistance, however, from karai who disputed the power
of the chiefs, gathering followers who believed in their
extraordinary powers to lead people to places where they could
gain access to an original state of perfection, where they would
become immortal without having to pass through the ordeal of
death.
There is evidence that cults developed around these
prophetic leaders who lived a wandering life, visiting villages to
announce their message that the time had come for people to
renew their spiritual connections with their ancestors in places that
had never before been inhabited (yvy maraey literally means ?land
on which nothing has been built or cultivated?; early missionaries
interpreted this phrase to refer to the Christian paradise, a ?land
without evil?).
The second form of prophetic movements emphasizes a
timeor moment of transformation, when the earth? considered to
be irredeemably flawed with impurities, rotten with the corpses of
so many dead, contaminated by sicknesses and toxicity, and
plagued by dangerous and harmful creatures? will be purified by
fire, then washed by water. After this, the survivors who managed
to escape by having dug out a huge hole in the earth where they
hid until the fire had passed, or had taken refuge by tying their
canoes to the tops of trees, will re-appear to a new life, free of
demons. The stories of creation of many peoples tell of a time
when these events occurred. The prophets thus conjugate the logic
of their sacred stories to the situational demands of contemporary
action. The prophets are the emissaries of the divinities and thus
are the only ones who should know when these things will take
place and what people are to do about them. The critical factor
here then is temporality, a time of salvation known only to the
95
Chapter 5
96
Chapter 5
97
Chapter 5
to give up their old ways because if they do, then they will be
overcome by the enemy (whomever that may be).
The narratives of phratric ancestors (that is, a group of clans
interconnected through primordial kinship ties) can be seen in a
similar light, as they focus on key decisions taken by the ancestors
that resulted in their autonomy from the whites,survival from near
total destruction at the hands of the enemies, and revitalization
movements. Narratives of the (non-prophet) ancestors
demonstrate how they sought to reproduce the prosperity of their
lives and guarantee their autonomy. The prophets?messages, for
their part, have consistently pointed to keeping the traditions alive,
to the dangers of selling out to the whites, to the need for living in
harmonious conviviality, to the need to eliminate sorcery, etc.
Even today, both shamans and ordinary people can
communicate with the souls of these great seers at certain sites,
such as at the Great Boulder of Dzuliferi (the great shaman deity),
located right above Hipana waterfalls, where, cosmogony affirms,
the ancestors of humanity emerged from the holes in the stones of
the First World.There, people leave offerings and request help and
protection from the shaman deity. This has been a region-wide
practice noticed by outside travelers since the fi rst contacts in the
eighteenth century. Tombs of the great wise people/ savants of the
past are likewise visited in Venezuela and Colombia, where
followers still go to request from them protection or a cure. In
numerous cases in the Americas and across the globe, those
religious virtuosos considered as prophets are understood to be
more like gods than humans.
What kinds of special knowledge do these prophets and
jaguar shamans have that mark them off from the rest of the
population? How does that knowledge find its basis in
cosmological forces or powers that exclusively religious specialists
can obtain? What is the essence of that power and knowledge?
98
Chapter 5
99
Chapter 5
100
Chapter 5
101
Chapter 5
102
Chapter 5
103
Chapter 5
104
Chapter 5
the first whipping rite, their songs and dances, and above all, the
great initiation chants, and the pepper chants where all
spirit-knowledge can be found.
The Knowl edge of t he Universe Owners
The transformative power of the life-force elements that fl ow
through the universe is intimately connected to the forms of
knowledge (ianheke) that brought the universe into being and that
has overcome all attempts by enemies to destroy it. It is critical to
understand how the knowledge and power of each of the deities is
distinct but complementary. The forms of knowledge each one
owns or guards were transmitted from the original owners to their
descendants, who then became guardians of that knowledge in
This World.
In the undifferentiated Before-World of the deities and great
spirits, one personage could assume the attributes and powers of
another. In the Baniwa pantheon, there are connections among all
major spirits/ deities that demonstrate the nexus of religious power
and knowledge and its replication among the principal religious
specialists. They share in each other?s powers and knowledge in
some critical way. As in the Before-World, so in This World, the
different keepers of knowledge can accumulate power, but only at
their own risk, for the sorcerers are ever-present to provoke
instability.
The vertical representation the Baniwa make of their cosmos
might suggest a hierarchy of knowledge and power. I find it more
productive to see that each of these deities represents a body of
knowledge and power corresponding in This World with living
specialists; thus the knowledge and power of the Other World is
directly transposed onto and into This World via the shamans,
dance-leaders, and priestly chanters. The relation between the
Other World and This World comes alive through them: during
105
Chapter 5
106
Chapter 5
107
Chapter 5
108
Chapter 5
109
6
KNOWLEDGE AND THE
OBJECTION TO RELIGIOUS
BELIEF FROM COGNITIVE
# SCIENCE
Learn more
Chapter 6
KNOWLEDGE AND THE OBJECTION
TO RELIGIOUS BELIEF FROM
COGNITIVE SCIENCE
Excerpted from The Roots of Religions
111
Chapter 6
KNOWLEDGE AND THE OBJECTION
TO RELIGIOUS BELIEF FROM
COGNITIVE SCIENCE
Excerpted from The Roots of Religions
religious belief.
Since no formal arguments are presented, it remains unclear
how the research in the Cognitive Science of Religion (CSR) is
alleged to undermine the positive epistemic status of the belief
that God exists (hereafter, we shall call such attempts?the CSR
objection?). Some (e.g., Murray, 2009; and Clark and Barrett, 2010;
2011) have taken up the challenge of proposing different ways in
which such arguments could be formulated to the conclusion that
religious beliefs are irrational. This chapter is a continuation of this
line of work, but differs in two respects. First, we consider how the
CSR objection might be understood in terms of Timothy
Williamson?s knowledge-first framework (Williamson, 2000).
Second, in light of the significant role that testimony plays in the
acquisition and transmission of religious belief, we consider the
role that the epistemology of testimony could play in the CSR
objection. Section 2 begins with a presentation of the relevant
aspects of the CSR research. Thereafter follows a brief explanation
of Williamson?s claim that safe belief is a necessary condition for
knowledge. A treatment of several epistemic terms of art
concludes section 2. In section 3 we present two different ways in
which the CSR objection can be formulated as an argument to the
effect that the belief that God exists is unsafe. We argue that
neither version works.
Part II
The Cognitive Science of Religion
Owing to differences in methodologies and research goals, there is
no definitive statement of the cognitive and evolutionary
psychology of religion. For our purposes it will suffice to draw
attention to the work of Justin Barrett (2004; 2009), a dominant
figure in the CSR literature. Here is a rough sketch of Barrett?s
theory.
112
Chapter 6
KNOWLEDGE AND THE OBJECTION
TO RELIGIOUS BELIEF FROM
COGNITIVE SCIENCE
Excerpted from The Roots of Religions
113
Chapter 6
KNOWLEDGE AND THE OBJECTION
TO RELIGIOUS BELIEF FROM
COGNITIVE SCIENCE
Excerpted from The Roots of Religions
114
Chapter 6
KNOWLEDGE AND THE OBJECTION
TO RELIGIOUS BELIEF FROM
COGNITIVE SCIENCE
Excerpted from The Roots of Religions
115
Chapter 6
KNOWLEDGE AND THE OBJECTION
TO RELIGIOUS BELIEF FROM
COGNITIVE SCIENCE
Excerpted from The Roots of Religions
Finally, there is good reason to think that the appropriate norm for
assertion and practical reasoning is knowledge and not justified or
rational belief (Williamson, 2000, pp. 238ff; Hawthorne and
Stanley, 2008). Since theistic belief is often the subject of assertion
and, more importantly, influences the way theists go about living
their lives, it makes sense to worry about whether theists can know
that God exists in light of the CSR research more than whether
theists can rationally believe that God exists.
Before commencing our treatment of the CSR objection, two
epistemic terms of art need to be addressed. First, there is a
distinction between individual epistemology and social
epistemology. The first makes normative assessments of a specific
agent?s beliefs, e.g., that an agent S?s belief that p is warranted or
rational or justified or known if and only if conditions C1,? , Cn are
satisfied. The second differs in that normative assessments are
made about an entire community?s belief(s). We understand the
methodology of social epistemology to begin with an assessment
of which method or cognitive process a group uses to produce a
certain belief and then to judge the epistemic status of that belief,
the judgment naturally applying to all agents in that community. An
adequate treatment of the CSR objection must take into account
this distinction for it is unclear whether CSR objectors have specific
theists in mind or intend their remarks to apply to all theists.
Second, knowledge is factive? only true propositions can be
known. Without thereby begging the question, it makes little sense
for the CSR objection to be framed on the assumption that theism
is false, for then it would be trivially true that theistic belief is
unsafe. The CSR literature would then be irrelevant to the claim
that theistic belief is unsafe. We therefore interpret the CSR
objector as making the claim that despite it being true that God
exists, one does not know that God exists. Given the conceptual
dependence of assertion, practical reasoning, and evidence on
116
Chapter 6
KNOWLEDGE AND THE OBJECTION
TO RELIGIOUS BELIEF FROM
COGNITIVE SCIENCE
Excerpted from The Roots of Religions
117
Chapter 6
KNOWLEDGE AND THE OBJECTION
TO RELIGIOUS BELIEF FROM
COGNITIVE SCIENCE
Excerpted from The Roots of Religions
118
Chapter 6
KNOWLEDGE AND THE OBJECTION
TO RELIGIOUS BELIEF FROM
COGNITIVE SCIENCE
Excerpted from The Roots of Religions
119
Chapter 6
KNOWLEDGE AND THE OBJECTION
TO RELIGIOUS BELIEF FROM
COGNITIVE SCIENCE
Excerpted from The Roots of Religions
120
Chapter 6
KNOWLEDGE AND THE OBJECTION
TO RELIGIOUS BELIEF FROM
COGNITIVE SCIENCE
Excerpted from The Roots of Religions
121
Chapter 6
KNOWLEDGE AND THE OBJECTION
TO RELIGIOUS BELIEF FROM
COGNITIVE SCIENCE
Excerpted from The Roots of Religions
122
Chapter 6
KNOWLEDGE AND THE OBJECTION
TO RELIGIOUS BELIEF FROM
COGNITIVE SCIENCE
Excerpted from The Roots of Religions
123
Chapter 6
KNOWLEDGE AND THE OBJECTION
TO RELIGIOUS BELIEF FROM
COGNITIVE SCIENCE
Excerpted from The Roots of Religions
124
Chapter 6
KNOWLEDGE AND THE OBJECTION
TO RELIGIOUS BELIEF FROM
COGNITIVE SCIENCE
Excerpted from The Roots of Religions
125
7
INTELLIGENT DESIGN AS
SCIENCE OR
PSEUDOSCIENCE
#
Learn more
Chapter 7
127
Chapter 7
explanations.
In this chapter, I will analyse the controversy over ID and the
definition of science. In the first section I will look at ID?s critique
of methodological naturalism and several ways in which
methodological naturalism has been defended against this critique.
I then move on to consider several possible defences and
formulations of methodological naturalism. I argue that
intellectually responsible defences of methodological naturalism
will not allow us to dismiss the consideration of the more
interesting questions in the debate, such as the evaluation of ID?s
arguments. In the third section of the chapter, I discuss other ways
of differentiating between science and non-science, and argue that
the definition of science is not the central philosophical question
of the debate, unless we accept some kind of scientism ? or unless
we care most about influencing public education than the core
philosophical questions of the debate.
Met hodol ogical nat ural ism and ID?s crit ique
The historical background of methodological naturalism
Methodological naturalism has historical roots extending far
beyond current political controversies. Methodologically
naturalistic science can be broadly construed as a project of
understanding the structure of the universe in terms of natural
causes. It always looks for natural explanations, laws and
mechanisms, rather than resorting to supernatural explanations of
any phenomena. As Ronald Numbers argues, this broad approach
has Christian and even medieval roots. Even in the middle ages,
natural philosophy was guided by a ?preference for natural
explanations over divine mysteries?when dealing with natural
phenomena. It was thought that God had created a rational world,
whose structure was pen to human investigation. Explaining things
by reference to God?s mysterious will was not the default position
128
Chapter 7
129
Chapter 7
Philip Quinn even argues that while there are good arguments
against creationism, these may be too complex, and so ?there may
well be circumstances in which only the bad effective argument
will work against them in the political or legal arenas. If there are,
then I think, though I come to this conclusion reluctantly, it is
morally permissible for us to use the bad effective argument?. As
Bradley Monton has commented, this strategy is unfortunate. We
should seek for the truth and reject bad arguments, even if they are
expedient.To that end, I will go on to consider some critiques and
defences of methodological naturalism.
ID?s designer and the critique of methodological naturalism
Methodological naturalism was used as a weapon against
creationism, and so it has also been used as an argument against
understanding ID as part of the natural sciences. To defend the
scientific nature of their argumentation, proponents of ID have
responded by criticizing methodological naturalism. As I pointed
out in Chapters 3 and 4, proponents of ID argue that cosmology
and biology provide data which point to purposeful design as the
explanation. The structure of the argument is often aimed to show
that the design argument utilizes the best methods used in
historical science, such as the inference to the best explanation.
Proponents of ID argue that their design argument is analogous to
forensic sciences, archaeology and the search for extraterrestrial
intelligence (SETI), and as such should also be accepted as
scientific.
It is somewhat curious why methodological naturalism
should be an issue in the debate, since as noted, proponents of ID
typically insist that their designer does not have to be
supernatural. While Johnson?s early argumentation in Darwin on
Trial critiqued the way methodological naturalism bars
supernatural design from science, later ID writings have
130
Chapter 7
131
Chapter 7
132
Chapter 7
133
Chapter 7
for the origin of life and much of its development, and that there
are real ?gaps?in the capabilities of natural processes nature. In this
case, reliance purely on the results of methodologically naturalistic
science would produce a false picture of the history of life, because
it could not even in principle recognize this being?s role and the
really existing limits of naturalistic processes. In such a case,
science would lead us away from the truth. Proponents of ID argue
that this can be avoided by giving up methodological naturalism.
Def ending met hodol ogical nat ural ism
The ID movement?s critique of methodological naturalism
generally assumes that methodological naturalism means an a
priori restriction barring the use of supernatural or teleological
explanations from the natural sciences. Proponents of ID generally
also operate on the premise that methodological naturalism is not
credible in any traditional theistic framework, because theism
allows that God could have acted in natural history. However, in
the literature responding to the ID movement, there are different
strategies for defending methodological naturalism, not all of
which are vulnerable to ID?s critique.
Strong methodological naturalism
In its critiques of methodological naturalism, ID mainly criticizes
methodological naturalism as an a priori restriction on what kinds
of explanations are allowed in science. This kind of strong form of
methodological naturalism does indeed exist, and it has indeed
been a central part of the legal strategy against creationism and ID.
For instance, Ruse, whose testimony was pivotal in the creationism
trial of 1987, defines methodological naturalism as the claim that
?any reliance on a supernatural force, a Creator intervening in a
natural world by supernatural process, is necessarily not science?.
This means that excluding design from the natural sciences is not
134
Chapter 7
135
Chapter 7
136
Chapter 7
137
Chapter 7
138
Chapter 7
139
Chapter 7
140
Chapter 7
141
Chapter 7
142
Chapter 7
143
Chapter 7
144
Chapter 7
145
Chapter 7
146
Chapter 7
147