Sweet 1999
Sweet 1999
Sweet 1999
http://cps.sagepub.com/
Published by:
http://www.sagepublications.com
Additional services and information for Comparative Political Studies can be found at:
Subscriptions: http://cps.sagepub.com/subscriptions
Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav
Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav
Citations: http://cps.sagepub.com/content/32/2/147.refs.html
What is This?
I present a theory of the emergence and evolution of governance, conceived as the process
through which the rules systems in place in any social setting are adapted to the needs of those
who live under them. The theory is composed of three elements: normative structure, dyadic
contracting, and triadic dispute resolution. I demonstrate that a move to triadic dispute resolution
leads the triadic dispute resolver to construct, and then to manage over time, specific causal rela-
tionships between exchange, conflict, and rules. In this way, political life is judicialized. Under
certain conditions, the triad will constitute a crucial mechanism of political change. I then ex-
plain judicialization and the dynamics of change in two very different polities: the international
trade regime and the French Fifth Republic. The conclusion draws out some of the implications
of the theory and data for our understanding of the complex relationship between strategic be-
havior and social structure.
JUDICIALIZATION AND
THE CONSTRUCTION
OF GOVERNANCE
AUTHOR’S NOTE: For enormously helpful comments and criticisms, I am indebted to Christo-
pher Ansell, James Caporaso, Harry Eckstein, Henry Farrell, Neil Fligstein, Ron Jepperson, Pe-
ter Katzenstein, Robert Keohane, Nicholas Onuf, Paul Pierson, David Rowe, Wayne Sandholtz,
Martin Shapiro, Anne-Marie Slaughter, Rogers Smith, and Susan Sterrett. Earlier versions of
the article were presented at the Seminar on International Law and International Relations at
Harvard Law School (organized by Anne-Marie Slaughter and Andrew Moravcsik, November
1995); the Legal Theory Workshop at the Yale Law School (organized by Bruce Ackerman and
Owen Fiss, February 1996); two Workshops on International Law and International Relations
Theory at Yale University (organized by Harold Koh and Alexander Wendt, February 1996, and
COMPARATIVE POLITICAL STUDIES, Vol. 32 No. 2, April 1999 147-184
© 1999 Sage Publications, Inc.
147
The model comprises three core elements: the dyad, the triad, and norma-
tive structure.
The dyad, “the simplest sociological formation” (Simmel, 1950, p. 122),
is any “pattern of [direct] exchange” between two individuals or groups (see
Foster, 1977). The dyad alone defines, more or less comprehensively, a wide
range of basic human relationships. Examples exist wherever we look for
them. In marriage (the union of two people), in feudal polities (the tie between
serf and vassal), in parliamentary democracies (the dichotomy of party of
government and party of opposition), in industrial production (the interde-
pendence of capital and labor), and in international relations (the network of
allies and enemies), dyadic structures constitute core social identities of indi-
vidual entities. Because dyads bind single units together, they are primordial
by Harold Koh, October 1997); and the Research Seminar Series of the Center for Culture,
Organization, and Politics at the University of California–Berkeley (organized by Neil Flig-
stein, April 1998). The article began as an attempt to elaborate a theory of judicial politics capable
of synthesizing key insights of two rival approaches to the study of public law in political science: the
political jurisprudence of Martin Shapiro and other legal pluralists and behavioralists, and the nor-
mative jurisprudence of Rogers Smith and others who work at the intersection of case law and new
institutional approaches to politics. The article was transformed as a result of these discussions.
social institutions. They are building blocks to society, that is, they can be
linked in chains and clusters to form larger social formations, and they
1
develop quite naturally within such constructs.
The normative basis of the dyadic form is reciprocity. Reciprocity is the
glue holding the dyad (society) together, which accounts for why it exists in
every human community about which we know anything (Gouldner, 1977).
Stripped to essentials, the norm holds that “people should help those who
help them” (Gouldner, 1977, p. 37). Promises made are to be kept; debts
incurred are to be repaid; kindnesses received are to be recognized and
returned. Reciprocity, according to Simmel (1950), gives to the dyad “a spe-
cial consecration,” by linking each party to “a common fate” (pp. 123, 135).
The notion that reciprocity is crucial to the maintenance of social systems
has been a staple of social science (e.g., Hobhouse, 1906, Malinowski, 1932,
Parsons & Shils, 1951). With the rise of neorationalism in contemporary
political science, analytical priorities have shifted from the normative and
social contexts of politics to strategic choice contexts within which individu-
als seek to maximize their utility. Although neorationalists also privilege the
dyad, they problematize reciprocity in particular and norms in general (e.g.,
Axelrod, 1986). Indeed, the paradigmatic metaphors of game theory—
prisoner’s dilemma, chicken, the assurance games—focus our attentions on
the fierce difficulties of establishing and maintaining dyadic cooperation.
Dyadic forms are inherently unstable, neorationalists tell us, because each
party faces powerful incentives to ignore normative obligations thereby
cheating on the other.
I will return to a discussion of neorationalism later. For now, it is enough to
recognize that dyadic forms can accommodate cooperation, which can be
socially enabling, and conflict, which can be socially debilitating.
The triad, two disputants and a dispute resolver, is a universal, if under-
theorized, phenomenon (but see Black, 1998, chap. 6). I understand the triad
to be a primal technique of organizing social authority and, therefore, of gov-
erning. The underlying reason for this is simple: The triadic entity is the guar-
antor of reciprocity. Quite literally rooted in the dyadic form, the triad brings
an external presence to the dyad, a presence whose interest is in the fate of “a
common fate,” that is, in the durability of social relationships across time.
Viewed functionally, triadic dispute resolution (TDR) serves to perpetuate
the dyad, given changes in the preferences or identities of the two parties, or
changes in the environment. As Simmel (1950) puts it: “The triad indicates
1. In noticing the ubiquity of relationships organized in twos, I do not mean to imply that
dyadic forms are all that matter. I focus on them, as a representation of “the social,” for theory-
building purposes, namely, to obtain advantages that come with reduction.
transition” (p. 145). The triadic entity responds to, and is a crucial agent of,
social change.
Two ideal types of TDR are relevant to the analysis. The first is consensual
TDR, triads constituted by the voluntary consent of both disputants, that is,
by an ad hoc act of delegation. The act recognizes but also confers social
authority, or legitimacy, on the third party. Siblings appeal to parents, class-
mates to one another or to a teacher, villagers to a shaman, a chief, or a sage.
The second type is compulsory TDR, triads that are permanently consti-
tuted by jurisdiction: dispute resolution processes are triggered by one
party to a dispute against the will of the other. In this type, office replaces
delegation (Shapiro, 1980, chap. 1), that is, an initial—constitutional—act
of delegation is frozen in place, for the life of the polity. Courts are the para-
digmatic form of compulsory TDR (but legislative bodies perform similar
social functions).
To move from the dyad to the triad is to construct a particular form of
governance—the triadic. In dyads, conflict can be debilitating, but conflict is
constitutive of the triad. Once activated, TDR performs governmental func-
tions: to generate normative guidance about how one ought to behave, to
stabilize one’s expectations about the behavior of others, and to impinge on
ex ante distributions of values and resources. Stated simply, the social func-
tion of TDR (governance) is to regulate behavior and to maintain social cohe-
sion as circumstances change.
The final element of the model is normative structure: the system of
rules—or socially constituted constraints on behavior—in place in any com-
munity. A great deal of controversy surrounds the subject of norms and rules,
their status and explanatory value. Although this article is partly a response to
this controversy, I do not attempt to resolve it here.
What I call normative structure is equivalent to what North (1990) calls
“institutions,” variously: “the rules of the game,” “customs and traditions,”
“conventions, codes of conduct, norms of behavior, statute law, common law,
and contracts” (pp. 3-6). It is congruent with how Eckstein (1988; see also
Wildavsky, 1987) conceptualizes culture: “mediating orientations,” those
“general dispositions of actors to act in certain ways in sets of situations”
(p. 790). It conforms to March and Olsen’s (1989) notion of rules: the
“beliefs, paradigms, codes, cultures, and knowledge” that permit us to “iden-
tif[y] the normatively appropriate behavior” (p. 22). It equates norms, as Tay-
lor (1989, p. 135) does, with ideologies and culture, and it conceives of institu-
tionalized rules, in Jepperson’s (1991, p. 145) terms, as “performance scripts.”2
Despite clear differences in how structure is understood, culturalists and
(at least a few) neorationalists agree on far more than we might expect. For
Eckstein (1988), culture allows people to “decode experience . . . to give it
meaning,” which “saves virtually all decision costs” (pp. 791-792). For North
(1990), institutions (a subset of which is “culture”—“a language-based con-
ceptual framework for encoding and interpreting . . . information”) “exist to
reduce the uncertainties involved in human interaction,” thus saving “trans-
action costs” (pp. 6, 17, 25; see also Johnson, 1997; Kreps, 1990). Normative
structures enable human interaction by simplifying the range of choices
available to individuals and by investing those choices with meaning.
Across the social sciences, change in normative structure has proved diffi-
cult to theorize (e.g., Eckstein, 1988; Powell & Dimaggio, 1991, chap. 1;
Taylor, 1989; Tsebelis, 1990, chap. 4). We better understand the logic of
institutional inertia. Rules facilitate exchange between individuals, creating
opportunities for collective action. Behavior that responds to these opportu-
nities, once locked in (e.g., in dyadic forms), reinforces normative structure.
In culturalist or constructivist terms, because normative structures constitute
individual and collective identities, and therefore give meaning to action,
they are difficult to change by way of action, without a concomitant change in
identities. In either case, it is clear that the reproduction of particular ways of
doing things inheres in the organization of human community.
In the next section, I model the transformation of the normative structure,
focusing on the dynamics of change that are endogenous to the logic of
dyads, triads, and rules.
CONSTRUCTING GOVERNANCE
• strategic behavior, how individual actors conceive and pursue their interests
within any given community;
• policy making, how values and resources are distributed within any given com-
munity; and
2. I am aware that I have just assembled, in a very small tent, a disparate group of scholars
who traditionally do not agree on many first principles, least of all how we ought to think about
social structure. I have referenced them together for two reasons. First, I am seeking to build a
theory that strips governance down to its constituent elements, structure being one such element.
Although the scholars cited disagree for some good reasons, we can easily identify what each of
them means by structure; we can also see that, despite distinctly different approaches to research,
structure fulfills more or less equivalent functions. Second, if (as I am claiming) my theory is
relevant to the study of governance generally, my audience must be broad not narrow.
• systemic change, how the normative structure in place in any given community
is constituted, maintained, and revised.
The model breaks down this process into four stages, each a chronological
shift along a circular path, moving clockwise. Movement is generated by the
relative intensity of two relationships: of the dyad and triad and of normative
structure and strategic behavior. Although each shift is conditioned by what
has happened in prior stages, the discussion highlights distinct aspects of
these relationships.
codifies promises that are meant to be legally binding (Foster, 1977, p.16).
Both forms establish reciprocal rights and duties among two contractants.
In contracting, two individuals coordinate their self-interest in terms of
some shared view of the future. Such coordination is difficult, if not impossi-
ble, without at least a primitive cultural framework: in the form of language
(communication), and in the form of the norm of reciprocity, which is embed-
ded in notions of individual commitment, reputation, and responsibility.
Reciprocity, a crucial building block of society, enables the construction of
the dyadic form; as Gouldner (1977) has it, the norm constitutes a “starting
mechanism” that “helps to initiate social interaction” (p. 39).
Normative structure also serves to maintain dyadic contracts by facilitat-
ing dispute resolution. It does so in three ways, two of which are relevant at
this stage. First, at the level of the single actor, reciprocity—or a relevant rule
or established manner of doing things—can prevent disputes to the extent
that the norm provides individuals with behavioral guidance and an under-
standing of the consequences of reneging on a promise and that individuals
constrain their behavior accordingly. Second, once a dispute has erupted,
reciprocity and other relevant rules may provide the contracting parties with
the materials for settling the dispute on their own, dyadically. Such norms
furnish the bases for evaluating both the disputed behavior and potential solu-
tions to the conflict. The authority, or legitimacy, of these standards depends
heavily on their inherent neutrality with respect to the dispute, in the strict
sense that the relevant norms predate the dispute.
3. In excluding coercion from consideration, the model does some violence to reality. Surely
all dyadic relationships reflect or organize ongoing power relationships that contain elements of
(at least implied) coercion. I nevertheless theorize a consensual rather than a coercive model of
governance to focus attention on outcomes that result exclusively from the internal logic of rules,
dyads, and triads. Put differently, mine is a theory of ideational and normative—not physical or
material—power (influence).
4. My position is largely congruent with Robert Sugden’s. Sugden (1989, pp. 93-96) sug-
gests that norms (he focuses on “conventions”) develop in path-dependent, self-reinforcing
ways, one mechanism of which is the ubiquity, and naturalness, of normative reasoning itself.
Normative structures are inherently expansionary to the extent that they enable people to reason
from one situation to another, by way of analogy. The move to precedent (and, therefore, to
something akin to case law) is one result of analogous reasoning. If this is so, TDR is embedded
within, and further reinforces, the path-dependent nature of the greater process through which
rule systems evolve.
narrower paths, that is, individuals will continuously adapt their behavior to
increasingly differentiated sets of rules. It is also institutionalization: A
process through which specific social contexts will be increasingly defined
by specific rules of behavior—those curated by the triadic entity. Individuals
will absorb and act on these rules, thus (re)making themselves and their
community.
not function, on their own, to restore reciprocity given dyadic conflict and
change in exogenous circumstances.
The function of sanctions is to buttress dyadic and triadic dispute resolu-
tion. By sanctions, I mean social provisions that penalize noncompliance
with rules and triadic rule making. To the extent that they operate effectively,
sanctions counteract behavior that blocks the restoration of reciprocity
among disputants.
In consensual triadic governance, sanctions are informal but potentially
fully effective. Individuals will be led to abandon existing contracts, or avoid
entering into future contracts, with a chronic rule violator, an individual who
willfully disregards obligations imposed by a dyadic contract or by a triadic
dispute resolver. To the extent that this occurs, the violator forgoes the benefits
associated with social exchange and suffers stigmatization (the loss of reputa-
tion). If the violator’s behavior has led all other actors to refuse contractual
relations with the violator, social exclusion is the sanction. Banishment, virtual
death, is the ultimate penalty associated with consensual governance.
In compulsory triadic governance, explicit rules govern this sequence:
dyadic contract triadic dispute resolution decision compliance. Such rules
commonly enable the move from dyad to triad in the absence of the consent
of one of the parties, require the triadic dispute resolver to consider the com-
plaint,5 oblige the parties to comply with the terms of an eventual decision,
and organize enforcement measures in cases of noncompliance.
Like the move from dyadic to triadic governance, the transition from con-
sensual to compulsory TDR is inherently the stuff of political development.
The move is not automatic because the condition necessary for transition is
not sufficient. The condition is that, for any community or pool of potential
contractants, existing normative structure fails to provide an adequate frame-
work for social exchange, although the social demand for coordinative rules
and dispute resolution has increased. This may occur for a variety of reasons.
The potential contractants may be strangers, that is, they do not share a com-
mon normative structure. Or, changes in normative structure may not have
kept pace with changes in the nature of social exchange within a given com-
munity. A community of neighbors can become a group of strangers as a
result of migration, increased social differentiation, or the division of labor.
In any case, when existing rules cannot sustain social exchange at an optimal
level, people have an interest in developing new ones. The condition is not
sufficient because the construction of such rules is a potentially irresolvable
collective action problem. Thus, the model does not predict that TDR always
produces systemic change. On the contrary, when people (a) share a relatively
8. For example, the constant struggle to establish or to revise constitutions, electoral systems,
and the legislative and judicial processes.
9. I am not suggesting that the development of a stable mechanism of TDR is the only way to
achieve the virtuous circle depicted by the model. Cases in point are Avner Greif’s accounts
(1989, 1993, 1994) of how other (quasitriadic) mechanisms have performed similar functions. In
his analysis of trade relations in the Mediterranean region during the late medieval period, Greif
shows that the expansion of overseas commerce depended heavily on the activities of middlemen
(organized as the Maghribi Trader’s Coalition) operating within a relatively fixed rule system
(the Merchant’s Law). In Greif’s account, and in the theoretical and empirical materials I present
here, outcomes depend on the extent to which three factors—(a) social exchange, (b) organiza-
tional capacity to manage potential conflict associated with exchange, and (c) rule struc-
tures—develop together, thereby constituting a dynamic system of reciprocal influence. A
related theoretical framework has been developed to explain the dynamics of European integra-
tion (Stone Sweet & Caporaso, 1998a; Stone Sweet & Sandholtz, 1997).
10. After decades of neglect, the field of comparative judicial politics now thrives (e.g.,
Shapiro, 1980; Shapiro & Stone, 1994; Tate & Vallinder, 1995; Volcansek, 1992).
11. I rely heavily on detailed studies of the judicialization of the GATT system (Hudec, 1992,
1993; Stone Sweet, 1997) and of the French Fifth Republic (Stone, 1992, 1996).
pp. 70-71). Diplomats excluded lawyers from GATT organs and opposed liti-
gating violations of the treaty. In the 1950s, TDR emerged in the form of the
Panel System. Panels, composed of 3-5 members, usually GATT diplomats,
acquired authority through the consent of two disputing states. In the 1970s and
1980s, the system underwent a process of judicialization. States began
aggressively litigating disputes; panels began treating the treaty as enforce-
able law, and their own interpretations of that law as authoritative; and jurists
and trade specialists replaced diplomats on panels. The process generated the
conditions necessary for the emergence of the compulsory system of adjudi-
cation now in place in the World Trade Organization (WTO).
Table 1
Dispute Settlement Activity in GATT: 1948-1989
Complaints
Complaints filed 53 7 32 115 207
Settled: Conceded by defendant 22 2 12 28 64
Settled: Withdrawn by plaintiff 10 0 5 40 55
Settled: Panel rulings 21 5 15 47 88
Panel activity
Panels convened 25 5 22 59 111
Rulings rendered 21 5 15 47 88
Published opinions 9 4 14 19 46
Rulings
No violation by defendant 6 0 7 7 20
Violation by defendant 15 5 8 40 68
Source: Adapted from data presented in Hudec, 1993, chap. 11.
When mediation failed, panels could, with the consent of the disputants,
resolve conflicts according to relevant treaty provisions.
Before 1970, states did not exploit the connection between TDR and rule
making. But, being both imprecise and rigid, the regime’s normative struc-
ture proved insufficient to sustain optimal levels of trade over time. The treaty
mixes a few hard obligations (the MFN norm and tariff schedules) with a
great many statements of principle and aspiration. Despite its flexibility,
important GATT provisions could be revised only by unanimous consent.
Although the success of GATT was partly due to normative imprecision—the
more vague a rule, the easier it was for states to sign on to it—textual impreci-
sion was often locked in by the unanimity requirement. The tension is obvi-
ous. Achieving optimal levels of exchange partly depends on the continuous
adaptation of abstract rules to concrete situations, but the GATT legislator
was ill-suited to perform this adaptation for the trade regime.
Dyad to Triad
Beginning in 1970, the largest trading states turned to the Panel System
not just to resolve their trade conflicts but also to make trade policy. Statistics
tell part of the story (Tables 1-3). After falling into desuetude in the 1960s
(only seven complaints filed), TDR exploded into prominence afterward. Of
the 207 complaints filed through 1989, 72% were filed after 1969 and 56% after
1979. The four largest trading states—Canada, the European Community,
Table 2
Dispute Settlement, 1980-88: Compliance Among Selected States
Complaints Adverse
Against Ruling Compliance* Noncompliance**
United States 36 9 6 4
European Community 30 9 5 3
Canada 9 6 4 2
Japan 14 4 4 0
All other states 14 7 7 0
Total 103 35 26 9
Source: Adapted from data presented in Hudec, 1992, pp. 34-35.
*Includes promises to comply made by defendant state.
**Includes 3 instances of noncompliance on the part of the EC; the disputes were settled to the
plaintiff state’s satisfaction after subsequent trade negotiations.
12. Disputants tend to litigate what diplomats failed to legislate. Conflicts over agriculture and
subsidies paralyzed trade negotiations, and they also dominated TDR processes after 1970. Of 115
complaints filed in the 1980s, 51 (44%) concerned trade in agricultural goods. Of the 44 disputes
filed citing one of the GATT codes, 21 (or 48%) relied on rules found in the subsidies code.
Table 3
The Review Activities of the French Constitutional Council: 1958-1993
Referrals 9 66 136 98
President 0 0 0 0
Prime minister 6 2 0 4
President of the Assembly 0 2 0 1
President of the Senate 3 0 2 3
60 deputies, or 60 senators — 62 134 90
Decisions* 9 46 92 70
Censuring text 7 14 49 38
Favorable to text 2 32 43 32
Source: Stone, 1996.
*Due to multiple referrals, the number of referrals since 1974 is larger than the number of decisions.
Three general motivations animated the move to TDR. In the vast majority
of instances, states initiated complaints in order to induce other states to mod-
ify their domestic trading rules. As we will see, the GATT panels proved to be
a relatively effective means of doing so. Second, states appealed to panels to
alter, clarify, or make more effective existing GATT rules. This motivation
overlaps the first, because virtually all trade disputes are translatable into a
general argument about the meaning and application of specific treaty provi-
sions. Disputants worked to convince panels to adopt their versions of GATT
rules to encourage the spread of practices they considered lawful and to dis-
courage practices they considered unlawful. Third, although difficult to ver-
ify, governments sometimes participated in TDR to delegitimize—and thus
facilitate the revision of—their own trade practices.13
To maximize their success, governments had a powerful interest in replac-
ing diplomats and generalists with lawyers and trade specialists. The Ameri-
cans understood this immediately; the Nixon administration turned GATT
litigation over to trade lawyers in 1970. By that year, the enormous complex-
ity of trade disputes—the resolution of which requires determining (a) the
13. In 1988, the United States instituted proceedings against the EC’s payment regime for
oilseed processing. A panel ruled that the program both discriminated against foreign processors
and functioned as an indirect subsidy for EC producers. France, invoking the consensus norm,
sought to suppress the decision but the EC adopted the ruling over France’s objection. The EC
then replaced the payment system with a new one. In effect, the EC had used TDR to delegitimize
an outmoded, costly program of which France had blocked revision within internal EC lawmak-
ing processes. Complaint No. 179, U.S. v. EC (22 April 1988). Complaints have been assembled
and numbered chronologically in Hudec (1993, Appendix). I use Hudec’s reference system to
refer to cases in this and subsequent notes.
Triadic Governance
In activating TDR, GATT members delegated to the Panel System an
authority that is inherently governmental. As panels exercised this authority,
they generated three sets of political outcomes; these outcomes can only be
explained by attending to the dynamics of TDR.
First, panels altered the terms of global exchange by provoking, with their
decisions, the modification of national trading rules. If complied with, every
decision declaring a national rule or practice inconsistent with GATT rules
concretely affects the lives of importers, exporters, consumers, and produc-
ers. Statistics (Tables 1-3) show that activating TDR worked in favor of plain-
tiff states: Plaintiffs enjoyed a success rate of 77% in the 1948-1989 period,
rising to 85% in the 1980s. The rate of compliance with adverse decisions
was 74% in the 1980-1989 period.
To resolve many of the most complex disputes, panels had no choice but to
reach far into national jurisdictions. Thus, a panel ruled that a U.S. law pro-
viding a special administrative remedy for patent infringement claims involv-
ing imported goods violated GATT because defendants stood a better chance
14
of winning in district courts. To arrive at this decision, panelists investigated
U.S. litigation rates and judicial outcomes, concluding that biases in the admin-
istrative procedure constituted a discriminatory bias affecting trade. In separate
cases, panels required Canada to force provincial governments to remove taxes
on foreign gold coins and to force provincial liquor boards to change regulatory
practices favoring domestic alcoholic beverages.15
rules that, among other things, served to expand the grounds for future
complaints.
Panels also generated rules governing their own jurisdiction (Hudec,
1993, pp. 258-265). By the end of the 1980s, a stable case law asserted that,
among other things, panels could
• not only review the consistency of national acts with the treaty but also detail
what kinds of similar, if hypothetical, acts might violate GATT rules;
• announce answers to questions not raised by plaintiffs, but which were never-
theless relevant to other trade disputes; and
• report a ruling even if the dispute on which it was based had become moot (e.g.,
as a result of prior dyadic settlement), in order to clarify GATT rules and thus
facilitate future dyadic and triadic dispute resolution.
GATT decisions, and the move provoked the EU to adopt similar measures.
Facing a trading world in which GATT rules might be enforced unilaterally
by the most powerful states, the rest of the world joined the United States and
Europe in working to strengthen multilateralism.
But, if converging state interests were crucial to the enhancement of TDR
in GATT, judicialization generated the context necessary for that conver-
gence. Judicialization is socialization. As states gained experience with dis-
pute settlement, as panels performed their dispute resolution functions, as a
stable case law enhanced legal certainty, GATT members could afford to
view triadic rule making as a useful, cost-effective guarantor of regime reci-
procity. In the 1980s, states did not consider abolishing the Panel System but
debated how best to enhance it. By the end of the decade, a collective future
without effective TDR was no longer a serious option.
The 1958 Constitution was France’s 15th since the Great Revolution. Like
its predecessors, the constitution enshrined an official state ideology, the
“general will,” the twin corollaries of which are statutory sovereignty and the
prohibition of judicial review. In the 1970s, a process of judicialization
began. Legislators turned to the Constitutional Council to resolve their dis-
putes about the constitutionality of pending legislation; the Council
responded by developing the constitution as a system of substantive rules
governing policy making. As these interactions intensified, the Council
became an active participant in the legislative process; legislators became
active participants in the construction of constitutional law; and a new ideol-
ogy, that of constitutionalism, replaced the ideology of the general will.
19. The Council is composed of nine members; the president of the Republic, the president of
the Assembly, and the president of the Senate each appoints three members who serve 9-year
terms.
any partisan dispute about legislation, once translated into a dispute about
constitutional rights, could be used to activate TDR.
Dyad to Triad
In the 1958-1970 period, the Council rendered only six decisions, siding
each time with the prime minister in disputes between the government and
Parliament over their respective legislative powers.20 Since 1974, the Coun-
cil’s caseload has been constituted, almost exclusively, by opposition refer-
rals alleging the unconstitutionality of legislation proposed by the govern-
ment and the parliamentary majority.21 When in power, parties of the Left and
Right have decried the Council’s growing authority over the lawmaking
processes, and both have threatened to abolish the organ to restore “the sover-
eignty of the general will.” In opposition, Left and Right have exploited,
without apology, the capacity of TDR to obstruct majority rule.
Oppositions are attracted to TDR for a simple reason: The Council is the
only state institution capable of altering legislative outcomes that is not con-
trolled by the government and the parliamentary majority. Referrals extend
the legislative process to include another stage: triadic rule making. The
move to TDR alters the strategic context of French policy making, redistrib-
uting political initiative in the opposition’s favor and reducing the influence
of the government and the majority over legislative outcomes. When the
opposition activates TDR, the government and the majority are placed on the
defensive, forced to participate in processes they do not control.
After 1974, referrals quickly became quasisystematic (Tables 1-3). Since
that year, opposition parties have referred every annual budget and, since
1981, virtually every major piece of legislation. In the 1974-1980 period, the
Giscard presidency, 46 laws were referred to the Council, or 6.6 per year; in
the 1981-1987 period, the first Mitterrand presidency, 92 laws, 13.1 per year,
were referred. The average number of references has remained above 10 per
year ever since. Expressed in different terms, since 1981 about 30% of all leg-
islation adopted has been referred,22 a huge ratio because most legislation is
politically noncontroversial and does not lead to a formal roll call vote at the
time of adoption. Substantively, the vast majority of referrals allege that the
referred law violates one or more constitutional rights capable of being
20. In 1962, the body also refused to rule on a complaint made by the president of the Senate.
21. By parliamentary majority, I mean those parties that support the government in parlia-
mentary votes.
22. Excluding the statutory ratification of international agreements.
Triadic Governance
The move to triadic governance generated three sets of outcomes that
deserve our attention.
First, the Council evolved into a powerful policy maker, a kind of adjunct
legislative body with the capacity to veto, amend, and even propose legislative
provisions. Annulments have blocked or radically altered a score of major leg-
islative initiatives. In 1982, the Council vetoed the Left’s nationalization bill,
ruling that the legislation would not have provided sufficient compensation to
25. Council decisions consist of numbered paragraphs. In the 1974-1979 period, the average
length of decisions (calculated annually) was 7 paragraphs, with a high of 8 in 1975. In the 1980-
1986 period, the average length of decisions (calculated annually) was 23, never falling below
13, with a high of 42 paragraphs in 1983 (Stone, 1992, p. 101).
Third, triadic rule making reconstructed the very nature of the French pol-
ity. Since the revolution, the constitution has been understood to be a law that
enabled state officials to govern but was unenforceable. Republican constitu-
tions proclaimed statutory supremacy and prohibited judicial review of statute
(perhaps a moot point because constitutions did not contain rights provisions,
and public liberties that were recognized in statute could be rescinded by
majority vote). In the absence of TDR, French constitutional law was static; it
developed no dynamic life of its own. Today, the constitution is a living law
that binds all public authorities in their interactions with each other and with
private individuals.
For the first time in history, French constitutional law is case law: The law
is what the Council interprets it to be (despite the formal absence of a doctrine
of stare decisis in the civil law tradition). In consequence, French legislative
politics, which operated on the basis of majority rule, have been reconstituted
as a constitutional politics, which operates as a continuously evolving, rule-
based discourse governing the exercise of legislative authority. In this poli-
tics, legislators continuously incorporate, into the language and practice of
policy making, a vocabulary and grammar of constitutional law. Lawmakers
do so to maximize their own political effectiveness. In their interactions with
each other, they debate and take authoritative decisions about the constitu-
tionality of statutes before them. This inherently judicial behavior, institu-
tionalized in the 1980s, is now a ubiquitous feature of the legislative
process.26 Referrals transfer these constitutional debates to the Council. In
this way, legislators participate in the construction of the constitution, pro-
viding the legal materials for constitutional adjudication, and legitimizing
the Council’s political authority.
Last but not least, judicialization also transformed the nature and function
of the French judiciary (Cour de Cassation, 1995). As constitutional review
steadily undermined legislative sovereignty, judges asserted their own
authority to interpret statutes and enforce the constitution. In the early 1980s,
the Supreme Court (Cassation) developed a rule that requires civil judges to
CONCLUSION
One virtue of the model is its inherent capacity to translate between micro-
level effects (or outcomes) and macro-level effects (or outcomes), simultane-
ously. The theory generates testable propositions about behavior and out-
comes at both levels. These propositions can be evaluated by focusing
empirical attention—at one point in time, at one level of analysis—on the
strategic interaction of individuals, the micro level, or the development of
normative structure, the macro level, while holding the other level constant.
The theory implies, however, that we will not be able to explain systemic
change adequately if we privilege, systematically and a priori, the causal
importance of one level vis-à-vis the other. The point deserves elaboration.
I have argued that how systems of governance emerge and evolve has every-
thing to do with the interdependence of rules and strategic behavior. If I am
right, Shift 2 is partly the province of neorationalism and game theory.
Rational individuals maximize utility by adjusting behavior—including how
they reason through, and talk about, norms—to changes in rules of the game.
In clarifying the scope and content of existing constraints, triadic rule making
shapes how players calculate the payoffs of available strategies. Stage 3—the
triadic dispute resolver’s response to the dilemma posed by the delegation of
political authority—can also be understood in neorationalist terms. Her inter-
est in her own survival leads the triadic figure to behave in predictable ways.
The analysis also suggests that neorationalism alone is inadequate to the
task of explaining systemic change. Game theorists rely heavily on struc-
ture—conceived as fixed rules—to provide the conditions necessary for pre-
dicting outcomes from strategic interaction. Although the macro level is an
integral part of any game theoretic analysis, all the action that matters actually
occurs at the micro level. Game theorists openly admit that they have barely
begun to theorize the dynamics of institutional change (see Tsebelis, 1990, chap. 4).
This article suggests that to the extent that neorationalism does not account for
28. Stone Sweet and Brunell (1998) and Stone Sweet and Caporaso (1998a, 1998b) test a
series of specific hypotheses derived from the theory in their explanation of European legal inte-
gration, the process through which a transnational legal system for the EC has been constructed.
29. See Note 7 and corresponding text. Furthermore, I have left undertheorized, or ignored
altogether, certain patterns of behavior that are of obvious importance. First, I had little to say
about why and how actors negotiate the terms of their exchange in the first place, although the
more commitment-based are the rule structures they build, the more push for judicialization we
can expect (I thank Nicholas Onuf for reminding me of this point). Second, the kind of perpetual
motion machine theorized, one that produces ever higher levels of legal discourse and triadic
authority, has not functioned in most polities in the world, past or present. Two families of nega-
tive cases were nonetheless identified. Actors may be willing to tolerate, or even cultivate,
dyadic conflict without moving to TDR. In some cases, as when their respective identities are
constituted in opposition, disputants may have a higher interest in maintaining the conflict. In
other cases, for example, zero-sum situations, no joint gains issuing from dispute resolution are
possible, and in still others, neither party may be willing to budge from original, fixed, and radi-
cally opposed positions (there is no negotiating space for the triadic entity to exploit). A second
class of negative cases concerns instances in which the move to TDR does not lead to rule mak-
ing but to rule reinforcement and social control. Finally, I provide no theory of judicial rule mak-
ing, that is, how the dispute resolver interprets and makes rules. Nonetheless, core elements of
such a theory are implied in the Constructing Governance section (Shift 3, Note 4, and corre-
sponding text), and in my treatment of the two case studies.
REFERENCES
Arthur, W. B. (1994). Increasing returns and path dependence in the economy. Ann Arbor: Uni-
versity of Michigan Press.
Axelrod, R. (1986). An evolutionary approach to norms. American Political Science Review, 80,
1095-1111.
Black, D. (1998). The social structure of right and wrong. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Calvert, R. L. (1995). Rational actors, equilibrium, and social institutions. In J. Knight & I. Sened
(Eds.), Explaining social institutions. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Collier, J. F. (1973). Law and social change in Zinacantan. Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press.
Cour de Cassation. (1995). La Cour de Cassation et la Constitution de la République (The
Supreme Court and the Constitution of the Republic). Aix-en-Provence, France: Presses
Universitaires d’Aix-en-Provence.
Eckstein, H. (1988). A culturalist theory of political change. American Political Science Review,
82, 789-804.
Ellickson, R. C. (1991). Order without law: How neighbors settle disputes. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Foster, G. M. (1977). The dyadic contract: A model for the social structure of a Mexican peasant
village. In S. W. Schmidt, J. C. Scott, & L. G. Landé (Eds.), Friends, followers, and factions.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Fudenberg, D., & Maskin. (1986). The folk theorem in repeated games with discounting or with
incomplete information. Econometrica, 50, 533-554.
Giddens, A. (1984). The constitution of society: Outline of the theory of structuration. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
Gouldner, A. W. (1977). The norm of reciprocity. In S. W. Schmidt, J. C. Scott, & L. G. Landé
(Eds.), Friends, followers, and factions. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Greif, A. (1989). Reputation and coalitions in medieval trade: Evidence on the Maghribi traders.
Journal of Economic History, 49, 857-882.
Greif, A. (1993). Contract enforceability and economic institutions in early trade: The Maghribi
trader’s coalition. American Economic Review, 83, 425-448.
Greif, A. (1994). Cultural beliefs and the organization of society: A historical and theoretical
reflection on collectivist and individualist societies. Journal of Political Economy, 102, 912-
950.
Hobhouse, L. T. (1906). Morals in evolution: A study in comparative ethics. New York: Holt.
(Reprint: 1968, New York: Johnson)
Hoffmann, S. (1991). Ethics and the rules of the game between the superpowers. In L. Henkin
(Contributors), Right v. might: International law and the use of force. New York: Council on
Foreign Relations.
Hudec, R. E. (1992). The judicialization of GATT dispute settlement. In M. H. Hart & D. B. Steger
(Eds.), In whose interest?: Due process and transparency in international trade. Ottawa,
Canada: Center for Trade Policy and Law.
Hudec, R. E. (1993). Enforcing international trade law: The evolution of the modern GATT legal
system. Salem, NH: Butterworth.
Jepperson, R. L. (1991). Institutions, institutional effects, and institutionalism. In W. M. Powell &
P. J. Dimaggio (Eds.), The new institutionalism in organizational analysis. Chicago: Univer-
sity of Chicago Press.
Johnson, J. (1997, Summer). Symbol and strategy in comparative political analysis. APSA-CP:
Newsletter of the APSA Organized Section in Comparative Politics.
Kandori, M. (1992). Social norms and community enforcement. Review of Economic Studies,
59, 63-80.
Kreps, D. M. (1990). Corporate culture and economic theory. In J. E. Alt & K. A. Shepsle (Eds.),
Perspectives on positive political economy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Landé, C. H. (1977). The dyadic basis of clientelism. In S. W. Schmidt, J. C. Scott, & L. G. Landé
(Eds.), Friends, followers, and factions. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Long, O. (1985). Law and its limitations in the GATT multilateral trade system. Boston:
Martinus Nijhoff.
Malinowski, B. (1932). Crime and custom in savage society. London: Paul, Trench, and Trubner.
March, J. G., & Olsen, J. P. (1989). Rediscovering institutions. New York: Free Press.
Moe, T. (1987). An assessment of the positive theory of congressional dominance. Legislative
Studies Quarterly, 12, 475-520.
North, D. R. (1990). Institutions, institutional change, and economic performance. Cambridge,
UK: Cambridge University Press.
Onuf, N. (1989). World of our making: Rules and rule in social theory and international rela-
tions. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press.
Onuf, N. (1994). The constitution of international society. European Journal of International
Law, 5, 1-19.
Parsons, T., & Shils, E. A. (Eds.). (1951). A general theory of action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Pierson, P. (1996). The path to European integration: A historical-institutionalist analysis. Com-
parative Political Studies, 29, 123-163.
Pierson, P. (1997). Path dependence, increasing returns and the study of politics. Study of Ger-
many and Europe Working Paper No. 7.7. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Center for
European Studies.
Powell, W. W., & Dimaggio, P. J. (1992). Introduction. In W. W. Powell & P. J. Dimaggio (Eds.),
The new institutionalism in organizational analysis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Rosenberg, S. W. (1995). Against neoclassical political economy: A political psychological cri-
tique. Political Psychology, 16, 95-136.
Shapiro, M. (1980). Courts: A comparative and political analysis. Chicago: University of Chi-
cago Press.
Shapiro, M., & Stone, A. (Eds.). (1994). Special Issue: The new constitutional politics in Europe.
Comparative Political Studies, 15.
Simmel, G. (1950). The sociology of Georg Simmel. New York: Free Press.
Smith, R. (1988). Political jurisprudence, the “new institutionalism,” and the future of public
law. American Political Science Review, 82, 89-109.
Stone, A. (1992). The birth of judicial politics in France: The Constitutional Council in com-
parative perspective. New York: Oxford University Press.
Stone, A. (1994). What is a supranational constitution?: An essay in international relations the-
ory. Review of Politics, 56, 441-474.
Stone, A. (1996). The Constitutional Council, constitutional politics, and malaise. In J.T.S. Keeler &
M. Schain (Eds.), New patterns of public policy in France: State responses to social change
and European integration. New York: St. Martin’s.
Stone Sweet, A. (1997). The new GATT: Dispute resolution and the judicialization of the trade
regime. In M. Volcansek (Ed.), Law above nations: Supranational courts and the legaliza-
tion of politics. Gainesville: University of Florida Press.
Stone Sweet, A. (1998). Rules, dispute resolution, and strategic behavior. Reply to Vanberg.
Journal of Theoretical Politics, 10, 327-338.
Stone Sweet, A., & Brunell, T. L. (1998). Constructing a supranational constitution: Dispute
resolution and governance in the European Community. American Political Science Review,
92, 63-81.
Stone Sweet, A., & Caporaso, James A. (1998a). From free trade to supranational polity: The
European Court and integration. In W. Sandholtz & A. Stone Sweet (Eds.), European inte-
gration and supranational governance. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Stone Sweet, A., & Caporaso, James A. (1998b). La Cour Européenne et l’intégration (The
European Court and integration). Revue Française de Science Politique, 48, 195-244.
Stone Sweet, A., & Sandholtz, W. (1997). European integration and supranational governance.
Journal of European Public Policy, 4, 297-317.
Stumph, H. P., Shapiro, M., Danelski, D. J., Sarat, A., & O’Brien, D. M. (1983). Whither politi-
cal jurisprudence: A symposium. Western Political Quarterly, 36, 533-570.
Sugden, R. (1989). Spontaneous order. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 3, 85-97.
Tate, C. N., & Vallinder, T. (Eds.). (1995). The global expansion of judicial power. New York:
New York University Press.
Taylor, M. (1989). Structure, culture, and action in the explanation of social change. Politics and
Society, 17, 115-188.
Tsebelis, G. (1990). Nested games: Rational choice in comparative politics. Berkeley: Univer-
sity of California Press.
Vanberg, G. (1998a). Abstract judicial review, legislative bargaining, and policy compromise.
Journal of Theoretical Politics, 3, 299-326.
Vanberg, G. (1998b). Reply to Stone Sweet. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 3, 339-346.
Volcansek, Mary L. (Ed.). (1992). Special issue on judicial politics in Western Europe. West
European Politics, 15.
Wendt, A. (1992). Anarchy is what states make of it: The social construction of power politics.
International Organization, 46, 391-426.
Wildavsky, A. (1987). Choosing preferences by constructing institutions: A cultural theory of
preference formation. American Political Science Review, 81, 3-21.
Alec Stone Sweet is official fellow, chair of comparative government, Nuffield College,
Oxford. His research interests include comparative politics, international relations, and
international law. Recent books include European Integration and Supranational Gov-
ernance (Oxford, 1998), coedited with Wayne Sandholtz; The European Court and the
National Courts—Doctrine and Jurisprudence: Legal Change in its Social Context
(Hart, 1998), coedited with Anne-Marie Slaughter and Joseph H.H. Weiler; and Govern-
ing with Judges: Constitutional Politics in Western Europe (Oxford, forthcoming).