UNIT 3 Pritchard
UNIT 3 Pritchard
UNIT 3 Pritchard
scepticism
about other minds
• The problem of other minds
• The argument from analogy
• A problem for the argument from analogy
• Two versions of the problem of other minds
• Perceiving someone else’s mind
basis are nothing more than unminded automata or zombies who have no thoughts
and feelings at all. How would we tell the difference? (This is particularly troubling
in the case of zombies, where there is no obvious underlying physical difference.) This
difficulty concerning how we know that there are other people who have minds like
we do is called the problem of other minds.
The English philosopher and economist, John Stuart Mill, was one of the most
influential men of his day. Like his father, James Mill (1773–1836), Mill was a
prominent liberal reformer committed to utilitarianism – the view that actions
are morally right to the extent to which they promote the greatest happiness in
the greatest number of people. He was a member of the British parliament and
forcefully argued for the rights of women.
The starting point for this argument is our knowledge both of the existence and nature
of our own minds. After all, we cannot seriously doubt that we have a mind, since who
then would be doing the doubting? (This is the point of Descartes’ ‘cogito’: ‘I think,
therefore I am’.) Moreover, it is also held that there cannot be any troubling sceptical
argument concerning our access to what is going on in our own minds because this
access is privileged. That is, we have immediate non-inferential access to what is going
on in our own minds – what we are thinking and feeling – and this means that our
scepticism about other minds • 163
knowledge in this regard is entirely secure (at least if any knowledge is). It follows that
we can put our knowledge of our own minds together with our knowledge of how
we, as minded creatures, behave, to determine what sort of behaviour a minded
creature should have.
For example, we might notice that when we are in pain, as when we accidentally burn
ourselves on a match, we respond in certain ways (e.g. by calling out). Suppose we
notice a number of these correlations between external stimuli (e.g. the burning of a
match, the tickle of a feather), external response (e.g. calling out, giggling), and the
associated mental state (e.g. pain, pleasure). Suppose further that we observe other
apparently minded people behaving in the same ways in response to the same stimuli
(i.e.they call out when burnt by matches and giggle when tickled with feathers).
Wouldn’t we then be entitled to inductively infer that there are other minds just like
our own?
Here is the form of the inductive argument that is being used here:
A1 There are patterns in my behaviour in response to external stimuli which
reveal that I am having mental states of a certain sort (e.g. my crying out in
response to being burnt by a match indicates that I am in pain).
A2 This same behaviour in response to external stimuli is exhibited by others.
AC These others experience the same mental states that I do, and so are
minded, just like me.
On the face of it, this looks like a good way of responding to the problem of other
minds.
Indeed, we don’t need to consider science fiction movies in order to get an example
of this sort of ‘deviant’ mindedness. After all, some people are colour-blind, for
example, and so see colours very differently to ‘normal’ people. Others have unusual
senses of taste and hearing, perhaps being unable to taste/hear things that others can
taste/hear, or tasting/hearing them differently. Often we can tell that this is happening
because it has an impact on someone’s behaviour. For example, if a certain fruit that
tastes sweet to others tastes very sour to them, then they will respond with disgust
upon tasting it. We can easily imagine cases, however, in which another person
experiences the world very differently and yet this difference does not manifest itself
in experience. For instance, suppose that someone sees red as blue and vice versa.
Accordingly, they would grow up calling what they experience as blue ‘red’, and vice
versa. Would this ever come to light? It might in that it might affect how they respond
to other colours on the spectrum, for example. Equally, however, it might not in that
this person might just go through life systematically mistaking red for blue and blue
for red. If this is possible, however, then it raises the question of how certain we can
be that we are all experiencing the world in the same way. Perhaps we have just
learned to categorise the world in a standard way, even though the subjective natures
of our experiences are in fact very different from case to case?
166 • do we know anything at all?
STUDY QUESTIONS
1 Why might it be thought problematic to suppose that one can know that there are
other minds? What is it about our beliefs in the existence of other minds that makes
them suspect?
2 What is the argument from analogy, and how is it supposed to resolve the problem
of other minds? What difficulties does this argument face? Does this argument
succeed in showing that we can have knowledge of other minds?
3 Explain, in your own words, why there is a difference between doubt about the
existence of other minds, and doubt that others have minds like one’s own. What
special reasons might there be to doubt the latter?
4 Is it plausible to suppose that one can directly observe someone else’s pain, and
thereby come to know, without inference, that they are in pain? If one could, then
how would this help us resolve the problem of other minds?