Philosophy Decoded
Philosophy Decoded
Philosophy Decoded
Philosophy is useless.
Philosophy has never solved a problem, never answered a question, and never made progress.
Philosophy can tell you a million reasons why you’re wrong, but it can’t give you a single true fact.
Yet it’s not for lack of trying! People have been philosophizing since Ancient Greece. And yet, after
2500 years of hard work, they haven’t found one single answer. Not one. In what other field could
thousands of people get paid year after year, and retire after a long career knowing full well that they
accomplished nothing? Imagine if every mathematician only answered “Maybe.” Imagine if engineers
could only ever say “Probably not.” That’s what philosophers do. Obviously, nobody in her right mind
would take it up.
Because, like I said, philosophy is useless. It is utterly and completely useless.
But you know, so is much else. Many beautiful things are completely worthless. Music is useless; art
is useless. We could all (and may yet have to) survive on a vitamin-enriched, calorie-dense, lukewarm
gruel—so fine cuisine is useless. French is utterly useless; the French could all (and may yet have to)
learn American. French plaza-side cafés with art on the walls and two charming, old, mustachioed
musicians playing accordion and guitar and flirting with pretty women ladies, then? The most useless
things of all, I figure.
And the most wonderful. Can you see that?
The old, great philosophers—Plato, Aristotle, and Socrates—said that doing philosophy was the very
purpose of life. They thought that philosophizing was the very best thing in the world—and I’m sure
they sounded then every bit as self-serving as that sounds now. But, as usual, the Greats were onto
something. Philosophy is an ‘end’. It isn’t good for anything else; it is just good. Full stop. It is plain,
old-fashioned, no-frills, no-nonsense good. It just is.
Things that are good for other things are called ‘means’. Money is the quintessential means: it’s
useless except when you use it to get other stuff. Fame, power, and good luck are also means. They
aren’t good except for what they bring: other things. They aren’t good ‘in-themselves’. Philosophy, on
the other hand, is good in itself.
Philosophy is an ‘end’, and it is only an end. It serves no purpose whatsoever.
Good music, fine food, flirtatious old men and beautiful women—they are ends too. Just plain, no-
point-in-arguing-about-it good things. They’re (some of) the reasons we live.
The dead Greeks knew this, but they made a mistake. They said that philosophy is the end, or the
chief end, or the best end. It’s not. It’s merely one end among many. Good food, good sex, good wine,
good music, and good friends are some of the others. Philosophy is unusual, though, in that most people
consider it entirely superfluous. You are probably willing to go out of your way for food, sex, wine,
music, food and friendship, but you likely have never tried philosophy. And that is a little sad. It’s a
little tragic to live a life without philosophy. Philosophy is just one of those things. I’m not saying, as the
Greats said, that you should devote your life to it, any more than I would say you should devote your life
to wine or sex; I’m saying that you need to try it enough to appreciate it. Because it’s just plain good.
I’m going to try to make you like it. At least a little.
Look, let me be honest with you: this is not a good philosophy book. We’re going to blast through
2500 years of philosophy, careening around, doing terrible injustice to very great thinkers who devoted
their whole lives to philosophy. These people sweated every word and laboured over their books. We’re
going to read people who wrote with quills on animal skin to get their ideas through thousands of years,
across deserts, through war, the sacking of cities, and the burnings of libraries, down to you.
And, meh, we’re just going to keep on going.
Like I said, this is a terrible philosophy book. If you want a good one, there are thousands—but this
one has an advantage over all of them.
It’s easy.
I don’t feel bad about this.
The way I see it, my job here is simple: I’m going to give you a crash course of the best bits of the
great thinkers, so that you can go on with your life knowing just a little about this enormous, wonderful,
moving, and beautiful field of human knowledge. When you want to learn more, pick up one of those
excellent books and go forward, doing great things. Here, we’re going to have some fun.
Some people say that philosophy is the love of wisdom. Others say that it is the father of
the sciences, or the world’s greatest waste of tuition. I say that philosophy is giving bad
answers to good questions.
Sometime in your life, you have almost certainly had a dream so realistic that you didn’t
recognize it as a dream. You didn’t know that you had been asleep until you woke up. Perhaps
you were sad to awaken; maybe you had been flying. Perhaps you were happy to wake; you
may have been having a nightmare. For some period, though, appearance and reality differed.
You appeared (to yourself) to be doing something other than drooling face down.
Of course, there are many times when appearance and reality diverge. Drugs, fever,
mental illness, or any number of other things (some of which are quite banal, like optical
illusions), may cause the split. Usually, we can somehow tell that things are not quite right.
We know that something has gone wrong in our heads. Other times, though, it is impossible
to tell. Occasionally, as in the case of some kinds of mental illness, the ‘break from reality’
can last a very, very long time—so long that we lose touch entirely.
Let me, then, ask you a good question: how do you know that you are not dreaming,
hallucinating, or are otherwise out of touch right this very minute? Maybe you are only
imagining this book in your hand. Maybe you are, in fact, going kooky. Maybe it has been
happening for such a long time that you have forgotten.
How do you know that what you see is a faithful representation of reality?
This good question is a philosophical question. You can tell so because it is:
• Simple
• Irritating
• Meant to be answered (and perhaps can only be answered) with argumentation.
Science is of no use.
• Finally, and importantly, you will never, ever, answer this question correctly.
No offense: nobody ever answers philosophical questions correctly, not even
the greatest philosophers. In the 2500 years that people have been doing
philosophy, not one question has been answered correctly. Not a single one.
There have been many bad answers to the simple question I asked above. Some easy ones
are pinching yourself, calling Jessica Alba (or Ryan Gosling), trying to fly, and just waiting to
wake up. All of these have problems, though. It’s not hard to imagine a dream (or a
hallucination) so real that you felt pain, or one in which you couldn’t get Ms. Alba (or Mr.
Gosling) to come over, or in which you couldn’t fly. You can at least conceive of a
hallucination so real that this kind of thing happens. That means, if you are really being strict,
that you do not know for sure that you are not asleep or hallucinating right now. You can’t be
absolutely certain.
Several years ago, the movie The Matrix considered just this problem. In it, Neo discovers
that his body is in a post-apocalyptic, machine-ruled, lightless world, while his mind is in a
computer program simulating twentieth-century America. In other words, Neo figures out that
he has been, in essence, hallucinating. He had a break from reality. While everyone else in the
matrix is ignorant of the real ‘reality’, Neo somehow knows.
So, here is a new question, more suitable for our times: how do you know that you are not
living in the matrix? The matrix is a totally immersive hallucination. How can anyone tell
when she is being completely fooled?
There are actually two questions implicit in the above problem of the matrix.
1. What is reality?
2. How do you know it?
The first is the fundamental question of metaphysics: what is real? The second is the
fundamental question of epistemology: how do you know what you know? These may seem
like strange questions. They are clearly philosophical questions: they are simple, irritating,
and hard to answer.
Metaphysics
Metaphysics tries to answer a simple question: what is reality? I know that seems stupid.
Reality seems quite real; it is all-too pressing for many of us. It seems pretty stupid to ask
what it is—it’s this stuff right here.
Indulge me. Scientists now think that the universe is composed of matter and space. Yet in
the past they thought otherwise. They thought that the universe contained matter, void, angels,
demons, energy, minds, Forms, essences, monads, or a myriad of other daft things.
But here is the freaky part. They knew about our current ideas (the atomic theory has been
around for thousands of years) so they preferred their explanation to ours. You should really
wonder why you’re so sure you got it right when really smart people for thousands of years
thought you were wrong.
I’ll concede, though, that scientists have now cornered most of the metaphysical market.
Even so, there are still unresolved questions. Take, for instance, numbers. What are they?
What do two days and two ducks have in common? Not a lot, apart from something we might
call ‘two-ness’. But that doesn’t really answer the question. What is two-ness?
This is an amazingly great question, even if it seems strange at first. Mathematics is deep.
Math rules the universe. Everything that happens can be described through equations. The
smallest particles and the largest planets, the blood in your heart and the plasma of the sun;
they are governed by one math that even kids can learn. If you stop and think about it, this
should blow your mind. The language of numbers is in charge.
In some serious way, though, we have no idea what this language means.
Very few people have ever stopped to wonder just what numbers are. Are they real? What
does it even mean to say that they are real? Since they seem to govern the material world, are
they somehow more real than it? Perhaps they are merely a language that we use to describe
the material world. All of these are serious, plausible, ideas.
Numbers, though, are not atoms, matter, or space. They’re not part of that normal,
scientific view of the universe that we take for granted. What are they? That’s a metaphysical
question.
There are other metaphysical questions. Among them:
• What is a law of nature?
• What is existence?
• What is causality?
• What is time?
• What are kinds or categories?
Nobody has come up with a final answer for any of these. Trying to answer these
questions, though, is both fun and revealing. If you feel so inclined, ask yourself this: what
makes the matrix less real than the machine-ruled, lightless world that Neo found himself in?
We feel it is less real—but why? Answer that, and you’re doing metaphysics.
Epistemology
Epistemology is another area of philosophy. It asks how we know what we know.
My students tend to be deferential. They say that teachers taught them what they know.
That’s goofy. Teachers taught me only some of what I know. Many things I learned by
myself.
Look at this thing, for instance:
It’s a circle, right? But how do you know that? There is, as you’ve probably heard, no
such thing as a perfect circle. This one is no exception. That circular thing only resembles a
circle.
If you’ve only ever seen things that resemble circles, how do you know what a circle is?
Do you somehow mentally remove the imperfections in any particular circle? If so, you
would have needed to know what the perfect circle looks like so that you could remove the
imperfect parts. But I was asking how you came up with the idea of the perfect circle in the
first place, so that would be a quite roundabout answer: you remove imperfect parts from
circles you see using the perfect circle in your mind to come up with the perfect circle (that
was already in your mind).
Maybe you abstracted from several circles on paper to a kind of circle-ness. I think that
this is often what my students mean when they say they have been taught. Someone showed
them some circles, and said, “Look! These are circles! Get it? Take what they have in
common, and that’s a circularity!” But to see what any circles have in common, we need to
have some idea of what to look for. Why take the roundness and not the line-ness or the
bumpiness or the blackness? And where did we get the idea of roundness from anyway? It’s
the same problem as before: we need to know what we’re looking for to see what we are
looking at.
Perhaps you were born with the idea of a circle. As far as I know, every culture knows
what a circle is. Maybe there are some ideas we are all born with, ideas like up, down,
triangularity, circularity, and time. Maybe. But that also sounds a bit fishy: why do we also
teach these ideas in school if we were born with them?
Maybe you define it with words first? Maybe circles are part of our built-in mental
frameworks? Maybe, maybe, but you get the idea: every answer has problems. That’s why
this is a philosophical question.
The problem of the perfect circle is only one epistemological question. There are others,
which may be more interesting,
• What is truth? What is falsity?
• What is justification?
• What is evidence?
• What is a belief?
• How should (or do) we make generalizations?
Our first reading, from René Descartes’ Meditations takes up this classical problem of
epistemology. Descartes asks how we know what we know and if there is anything that we
can know for certain. He comes up with an amazing answer. It will blow your mind.
This time, imagine that you are in a lifeboat, with a juicy fat boy, an old skinny man, and
a pregnant woman. You have no food, and if you do not eat today, all four of you will die.
• Who do you eat?
• More importantly, how do you decide who to eat?
Clearly, these are philosophical questions. (They are simple, irritating, and meant to be
answered with argumentation.) They have another characteristic of the genre too: they are
ridiculous and a little disgusting.
Of course, the answers to the first question are unimportant (unless you’re the one being
eaten). The second question is much more difficult. Perhaps we should eat according to who
would feed us for the longest time. The pregnant woman, then, would be a good choice. But
maybe we should respect her because she is bringing more life into the world. She might get
an exemption that a merely fat woman would not. By the calorie criterion, the juicy fat boy is
the second best solution. Still, he is young. We should maybe consider who would contribute
most to the world and eat those who are past their prime. If that’s the case, while he is skinny
and tough, the old man is clearly lunch. Or, and this is a choice my students very rarely
consider, perhaps one ought to sacrifice oneself for the goodness of the group. Finally, maybe
nobody should eat; it might be better to die than to be so debased.
All of the criteria are plausible:
• Maximize calories per life taken
• Maximize happiness and minimize unhappiness
• Value youth and promise
• Sacrifice for the greater good
• Die rather than do evil
These are ethical rules (though they’re not all good ones), and they lead us to the third
area of philosophy: ethics.
Ethics studies right and wrong, but simple lists of good and bad things are boring. It is
much more interesting to try to find rules we can use to decide what is right or wrong. These
rules are fun to debate, and philosophers spend a lot of time considering them. Eating the fat
boy—that’s boring. Deciding how to decide who to eat is much more exciting.
In short, ethics asks another simple question: How do we know what’s right and wrong?
By now, you won’t be surprised to hear that this is a surprisingly difficult question to
answer. Many answers seem good at first blush but lead to outrageous consequences. Other,
more nuanced systems lead to contradictions.
Logic
There is one last area of philosophy. I was hoping you wouldn’t notice. It’s logic.
I love logic, but it’s ridiculously hard. It is a mongrel of math and computer programming,
just as difficult, and half as well-paying. It is technical, demanding, and amazing. It’s also
way too hard for me. But, for the sake of parallelism, I’ll tell you the question it answers, kind
of:
• How do we systematize rational thought?
The thing is, logic is much more besides this. Math governs the very unfolding of the
universe, and logic governs math. Logic might very well answer “What was in god’s mind?”
Why you shouldn’t read this book
This book is a little odd. First I take the great works of philosophy and remove all the boring parts. It
would be a stretch to say what remains is the good stuff, but it is less boring. I add a few of my own
ideas off to the side, to explain context, draw connections, or spread some nasty rumours. Then, finally,
I take the philosophers’ very thoughtful, considered, plodding and careful prose, and I mangle it into
modern 21st-century English.
Let me be clear: This was all probably a bad idea. You should read these wonderful thinkers in their
own words. I’ll go further: you should read them in their original languages; lots of brilliant people have
thought that Aristotle was worth learning Ancient Greek for. And you should sit with them, and read
them carefully, savouring every word they wrote, rolling the ideas around in your mind like you roll a
good drink around in your mouth.
But you won’t.
I don’t blame you. To be honest, philosophers can be a bit long-winded. And philosophers’ books,
unlike booze, don’t age well. Descartes’ 350-year-old French is quite hard to follow now; Kant was hard
to follow even at the time.
So what we’re doing here is fast philosophy. You should probably not use this book in a real
philosophy course, or with—gods forbid—a real philosopher. This book is a bit Beyoncé to their Bach if
you know what I mean, so it wouldn’t be suitable for research essays. Honestly, I wonder if it’s even
really suitable for print.
René Descartes
René Descartes is called “The Father of Modern Philosophy”, but he slept around; he also fathered
the modern world.
Descartes straddles a great divide. Before Descartes, if you had a question, you asked your priest.
Knowledge was in the Bible, and the church was the final word on everything. After Descartes,
everything was different—his side runs to the modern age. He showed Europe something we now take
for granted: knowledge is discovered, not revealed. He trusted his own intellect; he investigated the
natural world and proved facts with his mind. Doing so, Descartes (and a few other people you will have
heard of), forced religion’s retreat from the ground now owned by science. This took gutsiousness
does.mindnly scosophy has accomplishedher.se 'es when you bought my book. I chopped it down to the
bare essentials. d t, not least because heretics were still occasionally being burned at the stake.
Descartes was more than just gutsy, though. He was a genius, world-traveller, friend of royalty,
soldier, and dreamer. He loved to sleep and swordfight, indulged in mysticism, and knocked up his
maid. He was so popular that he often had to hide from his friends to get work done—and boy, did he
ever get work done. He was the world’s greatest philosopher and the world’s greatest mathematician.
Cartesian geometry (the geometry of the game Battleship) is named for him.
Math is odd: everything in it is perfect and demonstrable. A rectangle can be divided with a single
line into two triangles—that is not often or usually true: it’s always true. When Descartes turned his
mind to philosophy, he kept a mathematical attitude: he figured all knowledge should be just as perfect
and absolute. So, in the following selections from Meditations on First Philosophy, Descartes is trying to
end the problem of skepticism, which is this: once we get a grain of uncertainty, it is hard to stop
doubting.
I’ll give you stupid example: I used to study in bed. Philosophy is boring, so I fell asleep a lot with a
book on my chest. Oddly, I often found myself dreaming about reading philosophy. I would transition
very smoothly from awake to asleep, and I wouldn’t even notice. I would appear to myself to still be
doing homework.
Right now, I am quite certain that I am awake, sitting in front of the computer. But that smooth
transition I used to have while dreaming makes me worry a lot: there were times I didn’t notice falling
asleep. So how do I know that I’m not snoozing, dreaming that I’m worried about dreaming?
In fact, how do I know I’ve ever even been awake? Wakeful life and vivid dreaming are very
similar. Maybe everything is a dream! Maybe nothing is real! Maybe I am not real!
This is the problem of skepticism: doubt snowballs. A small moment of skepticism leads to big
problems. Descartes wants to stop the snowballing. This might seem like a very minor thing, but it isn’t.
Descartes wants to get rid of doubt altogether. He wants to remove any doubt, in any field, and make all
knowledge perfect.
Think about that for a second. It should sound insane. Descartes wants to build knowledge on a
completely doubt-free foundation, so that, forevermore, it will be certain. He wants to do away with
error. He wants to make everything we know as certain as math.
Oh, and he wants to do it in a couple of days.
This may seem bonkers, but if anyone could do it, it’s Descartes. After all, he had already single-
handedly reinvented one field, and he did it when he was only 23. You might remember from your
grade-10 math class that shapes can be described with equations and equations with shapes. Descartes
was the one who showed that, and he thus united geometry and algebra, two fields that had for all of
history been separate. Fixing that took him a few weeks.
His philosophical strategy remains known as the Cartesian method. He says, roughly, he will try to
doubt everything systematically, and see what remains. Instead of fighting the problem of skepticism,
then, he flips it around; he won’t try to prove that his former ideas are certain. Rather, he will shake
them to see if they tumble.
Descartes starts by doubting ‘a posteriori’ ideas, then he moves on to ‘a priori’ ones. It is impossible
to overstate the importance of this distinction. It’s the fundamental discovery of epistemology—as
important to philosophy as DNA is to biology. It is also one of those rare ideas that can change your life.
Take a step back from all the facts you know and consider them from a distance. Philosophers think
that every one of them falls into one of two categories: facts you test through experience, and facts you
can test using only your mind. (It is very important to see that the question is not how you learned these
facts, but how you test them.)
The facts you test with experience are obvious. Is it dark outside right now? I check by looking. Is
my father alive? I will call him. These are a posteriori facts. (For some reason, it’s always printed in
italics.)
The facts you test with your mind are less obvious, but generally they have to do with math. How
many degrees are in a triangle? The absolutely wrong way to find this out is to measure a few triangles.
If you were to do that, you might find that your first triangle is 178º, say, and your second is 181º. Your
third might be 177º. “They are all close to 180º, so close enough”, you might say, and you would be
dead wrong.
You decided that you should average and round the measurements. Why average them? How did
you know that 177º isn’t the right answer? Maybe all the other answers are wrong. Why round to 180º?
What makes you think that nature works in round numbers, or even base 10 numbers? Why not round to
a prime number? Why round at all?
If you are really honest, you’ll admit that you were making up the rules as you went.
The correct way to find the degrees inside a triangle follows. Do it with me. Really! Grab a pencil.
It’s worth it.
Start by drawing a tipi. Then draw another line parallel to the base that intersects the crossed tipi
sticks at the top. Draw a half circle on top of that line. Clearly, that arc is 180º, because it covers the
straight line. (If it were less or more than 180º, the line would be curved or bent.)
The angles at A, B, and C are the same as at angles D, E, and F, respectively, because the lines are
parallel. So, if D, E, and F are 180º, A, B, C must add up to 180º too.
And that’s it. That’s how you prove that the interior angles of a triangle add up to 180º. Notice
something though. We didn’t prove it for any particular triangle. We proved for all triangles. That, if
you think about it, is amazing. We proved something that will always be true about every triangle
everywhere, and it’s not trivial at all: a triangle’s interior angles are 180º, the same as the angles on one
side of a line or half of a square. Neat!
Even deeper, though, is that we proved this using only our minds. This is really amazing: we can
prove an eternal truth about the universe with our eyes closed. Meditate on that. It should be astonishing.
What are the chances that we, one little species on one little rock in one little solar system, should have
access to eternal mathematical truths? This is one of the deepest, most mystical, most amazing things I
can imagine.
Finally, you should have felt something when you proved this. Did you? Did you feel a fleeting
sense of clarity, of surprise, of finality? This one thing is finished, once and for all: you have
demonstrated a complete, perfect fact. It is delightful.
That was an a priori proof. There are other a priori truths, some trivial (bachelors are unmarried
men) and some profound (some infinities are bigger than other infinities). All of them, though, are
proved using only the mind. Your senses cannot not help at all; in fact, your senses get in the way.
For much of history, a priori truths were truth. People genuinely thought that we could best prove
things about the world using our minds alone. Actually, some people still do think this, if only a little
bit, now and then, and mostly for God and physics. Ancient Greek philosophers thought they could
prove that the world is made up of atoms and void using only their minds. Now, I hear, physicists think
the universe is round in all dimensions, as if that makes sense.
Despite the nutty uses to which a priori arguments have sometimes been put, they are very deep. I
think—and I’m not alone—that a priori truths are more certain than a posteriori ones, and that they are
more permanent, more discoverable, and even, maybe, in some way, more true. Whether the atmosphere
is 72% or 68% nitrogen (a very important a posteriori fact) seems somehow fleeting compared to the
proof that there is an infinite number of infinite numbers.1
Descartes agrees about the relative profundity of a priori truths. In Meditations he first questions a
posteriori facts. Then he questions a priori knowledge. He rejects both as being untrustworthy, though
1 Yes. Remember when you fought with your brother and you said “I hate you” and he said “I hate
you +1” and you said “I hate you infinity” and he said “I hate you infinity + infinity!”? He was actually
right.
Some infinities are bigger than other infinities. How much bigger? Infinitely bigger, of course. There
are actually an infinite number of infinite numbers infinitely larger than infinity, and someone (not me!)
can prove this perfectly. Just trust me, though. The first person to prove it went insane. No, seriously.
the difficulty he has in ridding himself of a priori facts shows how certain mathematics really is.
Doing this, he knocks down the foundation of his knowledge. Without his mind or his senses, it
seems like nothing certain remains. He cannot trust his eyes. He cannot trust his mind. What is left? You
can almost feel the despair and the sense that he has gone too far, to the edge of sanity—because as well
as being a brilliant philosopher, mathematician and swordsman, Descartes was also a great writer.
It turns out that the solution is the problem itself. He doubts everything, and doubt, paradoxically, is
the answer. You’ll see. Trust me, though; it’s amazing. He does judo and uses the force of uncertainty
against itself. It’s astonishing. It’s beautiful. It’s brilliant. The one small fact left over is called ‘the
cogito’, the most important sentence in all of philosophy, the one bit of philosophy that everyone knows.
From that one perfectly certain—and ridiculously small—point, Descartes wants to rebuild all of
science. I think it is safe to say that he failed in his efforts, and that it doesn’t matter he couldn’t succeed.
He showed that the one certain and true thing—“I think”—is only found within, in personal
reflection. It is not revealed by God and still less by the church. When he laid out his system of doubt,
established the most rigorous criterion for truth, and found the answer within, Descartes drew the line;
he was on one side of the watershed, and everyone before him was on the other.
Descartes died of sleep deprivation, unless the Pope poisoned him. He was so beloved, though that
the French tore his corpse apart for souven-ears. Really.
René Descartes: Medita'ons on First Philosophy, MeditaFons I–II, edited1
1 Descartes wrote two books on the same topic. This is the second; the first book was pretty bad, as
books by geniuses go. The book rewrites and improves on the first book, which was called Discourse on
Method.
2 This is nuts. Descartes wants to reinvent all of science—and he’s going to do it today.
3 This is called “The Cartesian Method”. He doesn’t want to doubt willy-nilly. He is going to doubt
systematically. First, he is going to doubt his ‘a posteriori’ ideas, then he is going to doubt his ‘a priori’
ideas. Finally, he will doubt (half-heartedly) God’s existence. He rebuilds science in the opposite order,
in the part of the book we don’t have here. First he proves (half-heartedly) God’s existence. Then he
reintroduces a priori and a posteriori ideas.
hands this piece of paper, with other intimations of the same nature. But how could I deny that I possess
these hands and this body, and withal escape being classed with persons in a state of insanity, whose
brains are so disordered and clouded by dark bilious vapors as to cause them pertinaciously to assert that
they are monarchs when they are in the greatest poverty; or clothed in gold and purple when destitute of
any covering; or that their head is made of clay, their body of glass, or that they are gourds? I should
certainly be not less insane than they, were I to regulate my procedure according to examples so
extravagant.
Though this be true, I must nevertheless here consider that I am a man, and that, consequently, I am
in the habit of sleeping, and representing to myself in dreams those same things, or even sometimes
others less probable, which the insane think are presented to them in their waking moments. How often
have I dreamt that I was in these familiar circumstances, that I was dressed, and occupied this place by
the fire, when I was lying undressed in bed? But I cannot forget that, at other times I have been deceived
in sleep by similar illusions; and, attentively considering those cases, I perceive so clearly that there
exist no certain marks by which the state of waking can ever be distinguished from sleep, that I feel
greatly astonished; and in amazement I almost persuade myself that I am now dreaming.
Let us suppose, then, that we are dreaming, and that all these particulars are merely illusions; and
even that we really possess neither an entire body nor hands such as we see. Nevertheless, it must be
admitted at least that the objects which appear to us in sleep are, as it were, painted representations
which could not have been formed unless in the likeness of realities; and, therefore, that those general
objects, at all events, namely, eyes, a head, hands, and an entire body, are not simply imaginary, but
really existent. For, in truth, painters themselves, even when they study to represent sirens and satyrs by
forms the most fantastic and extraordinary, cannot bestow upon them natures absolutely new, but can
only make a certain medley of the members of different animals; it is at least certain that the colors of
which this is composed are real. And on the same principle, we are nevertheless absolutely necessitated
to admit the reality at least of some other objects still more simple and universal than these.
To this class of objects seem to belong corporeal nature in general and its extension; the figure of
extended things, their quantity or magnitude, and their number, as also the place in, and the time during,
which they exist, and other things of the same sort.1
We will not, therefore, perhaps reason illegitimately if we conclude from this that Physics,
Astronomy, Medicine, and all the other sciences that have for their end the consideration of composite
objects, are indeed of a doubtful character; but that Arithmetic, Geometry, and the other sciences of the
same class, which regard merely the simplest and most general objects, and scarcely inquire whether or
not these are really existent, contain somewhat that is certain and indubitable: for whether I am awake or
dreaming, it remains true that two and three make five, and that a square has but four sides; nor does it
seem possible that truths so apparent can ever fall under a suspicion of falsity or incertitude.
Nevertheless, the belief that there is a God who is all-powerful, and who created me, such as I am,
has, for a long time, obtained steady possession of my mind. How, then, do I know that he has not
arranged that there should be neither earth, nor sky, nor any extended thing, nor figure, nor magnitude,
1This is fantastic. Descartes doubts these numbered pages and this chair by the fire. But can he
doubt that there are numbers, or places, or space and colour? It turns out he can.
nor place, providing at the same time, however, for the rise in me of the perceptions of all these objects,
and the persuasion that these do not exist otherwise than as I perceive them? And further, as I sometimes
think that others are in error respecting matters of which they believe themselves to possess a perfect
knowledge, how do I know that I am not also deceived each time I add together two and three, or
number the sides of a square, or form some judgment still more simple, if more simple indeed can be
imagined? But perhaps Deity has not been willing that I should be thus deceived, for he is said to be
supremely good.1 If, however, it were repugnant to the goodness of Deity to have created me subject to
constant deception, it would seem likewise to be contrary to his goodness to allow me to be occasionally
deceived; and yet it is clear that this is permitted.
I will suppose, then, not that Deity, who is sovereignly good and the fountain of truth, but that some
malignant demon, who is at once exceedingly potent and deceitful, has employed all his artifice to
deceive me; I will continue resolutely fixed in this belief, and if indeed by this means it be not in my
power to arrive at the knowledge of truth, I shall at least do what is in my power, viz, suspend my
judgment, and guard with settled purpose against giving my assent to what is false, and being imposed
upon by this deceiver, whatever be his power and artifice. But this undertaking is arduous, and a certain
indolence insensibly leads me back to my ordinary course of life; so I, of my own accord, fall back into
the train of my former beliefs, and fear to arouse myself from my slumber, lest the time of laborious
wakefulness that would succeed this quiet rest, in place of bringing any light of day, should prove
inadequate to dispel the darkness that will arise from the difficulties that have now been raised.2
MEDITATION II: OF THE NATURE OF THE HUMAN MIND; AND THAT IT IS MORE EASILY KNOWN THAN
THE BODY.
The Meditation of yesterday has filled my mind with so many doubts, that it is no longer in my
power to forget them. Nor do I see, meanwhile, any principle on which they can be resolved; and, just as
if I had fallen all of a sudden into very deep water, I am so greatly disconcerted as to be unable either to
plant my feet firmly on the bottom or sustain myself by swimming on the surface. I will, nevertheless,
make an effort, and try anew the same path on which I had entered yesterday, that is, proceed by casting
aside all that admits of the slightest doubt, not less than if I had discovered it to be absolutely false; and I
will continue always in this track until I shall find something that is certain, or at least, if I can do
nothing more, until I shall know with certainty that there is nothing certain. Archimedes, that he might
transport the entire globe from the place it occupied to another, demanded only a point that was firm and
immovable; so, also, I shall be entitled to entertain the highest expectations, if I am fortunate enough to
discover only one thing that is certain and indubitable.
I suppose, accordingly, that all the things which I see are false (fictitious); I believe that none of
those objects which my fallacious memory represents ever existed; I suppose that I possess no senses; I
believe that body, figure, extension, motion, and place are merely fictions of my mind. What is there,
1 Descartes is playing a dangerous game here. His contemporary, Galileo, was imprisoned and
perhaps tortured for less serious heresy than this. People were still being burned at the stake in Europe.
2 Descartes loved to sleep in, and, I hear, invented Cartesian geometry one late morning watching a
fly crawl around on the ceiling. Sleep is a theme that runs through the Meditations, too; in fact, it would
make a fine essay topic, if you happen to be looking for one.
then, that can be esteemed true? Perhaps this only, that there is absolutely nothing certain.
But how do I know that there is not something different altogether from the objects I have now
enumerated, of which it is impossible to entertain the slightest doubt? Is there not a God, or some being,
by whatever name I may designate him, who causes these thoughts to arise in my mind? But why
suppose such a being, for it may be I myself am capable of producing them? Am I, then, at least not
something? But I before denied that I possessed senses or a body; I hesitate, however, for what follows
from that? Am I so dependent on the body and the senses that without these I cannot exist? But I had the
persuasion that there was absolutely nothing in the world, that there was no sky and no earth, neither
minds nor bodies; was I not, therefore, at the same time, persuaded that I did not exist? Far from it; I
assuredly existed, since I was persuaded. But there is I know not what being, who is possessed at once of
the highest power and the deepest cunning, who is constantly employing all his ingenuity in deceiving
me. Doubtless, then, I exist, since I am deceived; and, let him deceive me as he may, he can never bring
it about that I am nothing, so long as I shall be conscious that I am something. So that it must, in fine, be
maintained, all things being maturely and carefully considered, that this proposition: I am, I exist, is
necessarily true each time it is expressed by me, or conceived in my mind.1
But I do not yet know with sufficient clearness what I am, though assured that I am; and hence, in
the next place, I must take care, lest perchance I inconsiderately substitute some other object in room of
what is properly myself, and thus wander from truth, even in that knowledge which I hold to be of all
others the most certain and evident. For this reason, I will now consider anew what I formerly believed
myself to be, before I entered on the present train of thought; and of my previous opinion I will retrench
all that can in the least be invalidated by the grounds of doubt I have adduced, in order that there may at
length remain nothing but what is certain and indubitable.
But as to myself, what can I now say that I am, since I suppose there exists an extremely powerful,
and, if I may so speak, malignant being, whose whole endeavors are directed toward deceiving me? Can
I affirm that I possess any one of all those attributes of which I have lately spoken as belonging to the
nature of body? After attentively considering them in my own mind, I find none of them that can
properly be said to belong to myself. To recount them were idle and tedious. Let us pass, then, to the
attributes of the soul. The first mentioned were the powers of nutrition and walking; but, if it be true that
I have no body, it is true likewise that I am capable neither of walking nor of being nourished.
Perception is another attribute of the soul; but perception too is impossible without the body; besides, I
have frequently, during sleep, believed that I perceived objects which I afterward observed I did not in
reality perceive. Thinking is another attribute of the soul; and here I discover what properly belongs to
myself. This alone is inseparable from me. I am—I exist: this is certain; but how often? As often as I
think; for perhaps it would even happen, if I should wholly cease to think, that I should at the same time
altogether cease to be. I now admit nothing that is not necessarily true. I am therefore, precisely
speaking, only a thinking thing, that is, a mind, understanding, or reason, terms whose signification was
before unknown to me. I am, however, a real thing, and really existent; but what thing? The answer was,
a thinking thing.
1 This is ‘the cogito’, the most famous sentence in all of philosophy. In the other book he wrote, it
took the form you know: “I think, therefore I am”. Notice what he’s done: he turned doubt on itself: “I
doubt, therefore I can be certain that there is an ‘I’ that doubts.” Juuuuudo!
The question now arises, am I aught besides? I will stimulate my imagination with a view to
discover whether I am not still something more than a thinking being. Now it is plain I am not the
assemblage of members called the human body. I already know that I exist, and that it is possible at the
same time that all those images, and in general all that relates to the nature of body, are merely dreams
or chimeras.
But what, then, am I? A thinking thing, it has been said. But what is a thinking thing? It is a thing
that doubts, understands, conceives, affirms, denies, wills, refuses; that imagines also, and perceives.
Assuredly it is not little, if all these properties belong to my nature. In fine, I am the same being who
perceives, that is, who apprehends certain objects as by the organs of sense, since, in truth, I see light,
hear a noise, and feel heat. But it will be said that these presentations are false, and that I am dreaming.
Let it be so. At all events it is certain that I seem to see light, hear a noise, and feel heat; this cannot be
false, and this is what in me is properly called perceiving, which is nothing else than thinking.
From this I begin to know what I am with somewhat greater clearness and distinctness than
heretofore. But, nevertheless, it still seems to me, and I cannot help believing, that corporeal things,
whose images are formed by thought which fall under the senses, and are examined by the same, are
known with much greater distinctness than that I know not what part of myself which is not imaginable.
Let us now accordingly consider the objects that are commonly thought to be the most easily, and
likewise the most distinctly known, viz, the bodies we touch and see; not, indeed, bodies in general, for
these general notions are usually somewhat more confused, but one body in particular. Take, for
example, this piece of wax; it is quite fresh, having been but recently taken from the beehive; it has not
yet lost the sweetness of the honey it contained; it still retains somewhat of the odor of the flowers from
which it was gathered; its color, figure, size, are apparent (to the sight); it is hard, cold, easily handled;
and sounds when struck upon with the finger. In fine, all that contributes to make a body as distinctly
known as possible, is found in the one before us. But, while I am speaking, let it be placed near the
fire—what remained of the taste exhales, the smell evaporates, the color changes, its figure is destroyed,
its size increases, it becomes liquid, it grows hot, it can hardly be handled, and, although struck upon, it
emits no sound. Does the same wax still remain after this change? It must be admitted that it does
remain; no one doubts it, or judges otherwise. What, then, was it I knew with so much distinctness in the
piece of wax? Assuredly, it could be nothing of all that I observed by means of the senses, since all the
things that fell under taste, smell, sight, touch, and hearing are changed, and yet the same wax remains.1
Let it be attentively considered, and, retrenching all that does not belong to the wax, let us see what
remains. There certainly remains nothing, except something extended, flexible, and movable. But what
is meant by flexible and movable? Is it not that I imagine that the piece of wax, being round, is capable
of becoming square, or of passing from a square into a triangular figure? Assuredly such is not the case,
because I conceive that it admits of an infinity of similar changes; and I am, moreover, unable to
compass this infinity by imagination, and consequently this conception which I have of the wax is not
1This is a super famous example. He’s trying to get at the relationship between a priori and a
posteriori ideas. If everything about the wax changes when it melts, what does he know about wax? Not
much, you might say—but as a geometer, he thinks differently. He knows that wax changes, but
geometry is universal and (nearly) certain. So the shape of the ball might change, but ‘shapiness’
remains.
the product of the faculty of imagination. But what now is this extension? Is it not also unknown? I
must, therefore, admit that I cannot even comprehend by imagination what the piece of wax is, and that
it is the mind alone which perceives it.
I consider all this in my own mind, words yet occasionally impede my progress, and I am almost led
into error by the terms of ordinary language. We say, for example, that we see the same wax when it is
before us, and not that we judge it to be the same from its retaining the same color and figure: whence I
should forthwith be disposed to conclude that the wax is known by the act of sight, and not by the
intuition of the mind alone, were it not for the analogous instance of human beings passing on in the
street below, as observed from a window. In this case I do not fail to say that I see the men themselves,
just as I say that I see the wax; and yet what do I see from the window beyond hats and cloaks that might
cover artificial machines, whose motions might be determined by springs? But I judge that there are
human beings from these appearances, and thus I comprehend, by the faculty of judgment alone which is
in the mind, what I believed I saw with my eyes.
But finally, what shall I say of the mind itself, that is, of myself? For as yet I do not admit that I am
anything but mind.
I find I have insensibly reverted to the point I desired; for, since it is now manifest to me that bodies
themselves are not properly perceived by the senses nor by the faculty of imagination, but by the
intellect alone; and since they are not perceived because they are seen and touched, but only because
they are understood or rightly comprehended by thought, I readily discover that there is nothing more
easily or clearly apprehended than my own mind. But because it is difficult to rid one’s self so promptly
of an opinion to which one has been long accustomed, it will be desirable to tarry for some time at this
stage, that, by long continued meditation, I may more deeply impress upon my memory this new
knowledge.
René Descartes: MeditaFons on First Philosophy, MeditaFons I–II, decoded
MEDITATION 1
I’m retired. Now that I have the time, I think I should get rid of all my false beliefs and start building
my knowledge up from a certain foundation. What else do I have to do today? Why not reinvent all of
science?
I won’t agree to anything that is probably true or almost certain any more than I would agree to
something obviously false. If I can doubt a fact at all, I’ll reject it. I will not deal with every belief
individually, however. Instead, I will remove the foundations of my beliefs and knock all my shaky
ideas down at once. This is the easiest way. For instance, I used to think that I could find truth from the
senses. But senses often mislead us. We should not trust them to give us truth.
Some people say, though, that there are experiences we cannot doubt. Like, say, that I am here, by
the fire, and holding a piece of paper. I’d have to be crazy to doubt that! That does seem plausible. The
trouble is this: I sleep. I have even dreamed that I have been sitting, by the fire, holding a piece of paper,
when I was actually in bed, asleep. Dreams can seem real.
Well, let me try that on for a second. What if I am dreaming? When I dream, I don’t dream anything
new. I may dream that I have two heads, but I knew what heads were before I fell asleep. Painters
imagine in the same way; they combine old parts to make new monsters. Even if you don’t believe that,
colours are certain, and nobody can invent a new colour. There are many fundamental things like these:
simple, universal things, and all the things in our consciousness are formed of those things. Maybe I can
be certain about these things.
Extension, shape, number, place, time: these are all things that I know for sure exist, because
everything else I see conforms to these things. Everything I know takes up space, has a shape, and is
separated from other things. These qualities may be certain. If so physics, astronomy and medicine are
all doubtful because they deal with physical things. Math and geometry deal with the pure things that
everything has: extension and number.
Math and geometry would be more certain, unless even the most basic things, like numbers and
space, cannot be trusted. God could have made them seem real all this time. He could have been fooling
me. It would take a superhuman power to fool me about numbers, but God has superhuman powers.
Oh no. Everything can be doubted. I can doubt everything. I will not be fooled again.
Okay, it’s not God who would fool me, since you could excommunicate me like you did Galileo a
couple of years ago. It’s an evil demon. An evil demon could be fooling me, making me think that
2+2=4, when in fact 2+2=5. Now all I know is that I can’t be sure of anything. Since I can’t be sure of
anything, I will suspend judgment on everything.
This is making me tired. I’m going to bed.
MEDITATION 2
I’m bummed out about yesterday. I’m going to stick to it though, and get rid of every belief that I
can doubt at all. If any belief could be wrong, then it is as good as totally wrong to me. I’ll get rid of
every belief until I find one I know to be true.
Everything I see seems to be doubtable. Everything I remember seems to be doubtable too.
Everything I sense and the world outside my mind seems doubtable. Maybe nothing is certain.
Maybe there is a god or something that makes me think these things. Or maybe there is not, since I
could think them without help. Either way, though, am I at least not something? Before, I thought that
there was no world outside of my mind. But did I think that I didn’t exist? No. Even if someone is
always fooling me, I know that there is an I that is being fooled.
That’s it! This sentence, “I am, I exist”, is necessarily true each time it is expressed by me, or
conceived in my mind! I think, therefore, I am. I am thinking, therefore I am amming! Ego cogito, ergo
sum! Je pense, donc je suis!
Hold on: I don’t know what I am. I exist, but what am I? I need to be careful not to jump to
conclusions.
There’s a lot I know I’m not. I may not have a body. I may not be a man. I may not have a soul.
I do know that I am a thinking thing. That much is certain.
Thinking is an attribute I certainly have. As long as I am thinking, I know that I exist. I am—I exist:
that is certain. But if I stop thinking, who knows? I could stop existing. I am, then, precisely speaking,
only a thinking thing. Still, that’s something: a thinking thing is a real thing.
Can I be sure of anything else? Not yet. What, then, am I? What is a thinking thing? It is a thing that
doubts, understands, conceives, affirms, denies, wills, refuses, imagines and perceives.
I doubt, I understand and I desire. I also imagine, even though what I imagine may not be real. Even
if what I perceive, see, hear, and feel is not real, I am real. All this perceiving is a part of thinking. I now
know that I exist as long as I perceive.
It seems crazy to say that I can’t trust the external world, but that is the truth. I find it really hard to
get my head around the idea that physical things can’t be trusted. Look at this piece of wax, though. It
smells nice; it is cold and solid. It is as real as anything I can imagine. Yet if I put it near the fire,
everything changes. It does not smell, look, or feel the same. It still seems to be the same wax—but
every quality it had has changed. The external world is much more complicated than it appears. What is
wax? Wax is like every physical thing. It is extended, flexible, and movable. Its other qualities are much
less certain, but these qualities seem fairly clear. If we ignore the senses when we consider physical
things, we can really get to the truth of what they are. We can do this with intuition and inspection of the
mind.
Instead of abstracting from things we sense, we should build up from our innate ideas. Some ideas
can be very clear and distinct. I have to be really careful. I’m very used to saying that I perceive things
with my eyes. I don’t really. I judge with my mind and I see with my eyes. Often, I confuse these two
things. It really seems like the clearest perceptions come from the mind, not the senses.
In conclusion, then, I do not know that I am anything other than mind. Whether I perceive with my
senses or through introspection, I know, however, that I am. It is more accurate to perceive physical
things with the mind than with the senses. My mind is the clearest thing my mind can perceive. I’m
pretty dumb, so I’d better stick with this much for today.
Back to bed.
Socrates
Socrates’ life was a complete disaster. He was ugly and poor and died ignobly. Yet Socrates is,
without a doubt, the most important philosopher to have ever lived. He’s right up there with the most
important people to have ever lived. He is adored by every student of philosophy and every philosopher.
Socrates lived in ancient Greece, in Athens, about 2500 years ago. Athens was a wonderful place to
live. It was democratic, wealthy, and full of parties, politics, drinking, and theatre. It was fabulous... as
long as you were an Athenian man. Women were not so lucky, and everyone else was a slave.
Socrates was famous for repudiating the Athenian ideals, ideals very much like ours today: freedom,
democracy, beauty, wealth, and gratification (for the non-enslaved). Socrates was also extremely ugly.
He was a terrible father and husband. He lived in poverty rather than get a real job, and he irritated
almost everyone he met. He never even wrote down his own ideas. Finally, in old age, Socrates got
himself executed.
Reading him, though, shows that our standards (and Athens’) are stupid and pitiless. Socrates was a
wonderful man. He was kind, and pure-of-heart, and brilliant. He was also a great joker and a terrible
tease. That he was an ugly deadbeat reveals the brutality and stupidity of our standards.
I used to think that philosophers took Socrates to heart. I thought that Socrates’ ethos was our ethos,
that we are irreverent, questioning, and concerned with the higher things. Of course, I’ve come to realize
that I was wrong, and that academic philosophers are usually only prattish sophists fighting over
granting agency scraps, always trying to one-up each other, and less even fun to hang with than actors.
Still, Socrates shows how far philosophers have strayed. If Socrates does not show what philosophers
are, he does show what they could be.
In The Apology, we see Socrates at his very best. The reading will seem very strange, as it is not
written in any recognizable format—it’s not an essay or a story. The Apology is a ‘dialogue’, which is
much like a play. There are two characters: Socrates and Meletus. Socrates does almost all the talking,
because most of the time he is talking to the audience. The audience is a jury.
But this play is not fictional. When Socrates addresses the jury, he is fighting for his life. He is being
tried on trumped-up charges, and the jury of 501 men will decide his fate before the sun goes down.
Socrates knows that he may very well be sentenced to death.
Socrates (via Plato): The Apology, edited
Socrates’ defense1
How you have felt, O men of Athens, at hearing the speeches of my accusers, I cannot tell; but I
know that their persuasive words almost made me forget who I was, such was the effect of them; and yet
they have hardly spoken a word of truth. But many as their falsehoods were, there was one of them
which quite amazed me; I mean when they told you to be upon your guard, and not to let yourselves be
deceived by the force of my eloquence. They ought to have been ashamed of saying this, because they
were sure to be detected as soon as I opened my lips and displayed my deficiency. I shall use the words
and arguments which occur to me at the moment. And I must beg of you to grant me one favor, which is
this: If you hear me using the same words in my defense which I have been in the habit of using, and
which most of you may have heard in the market, and at the tables of the money-changers, or anywhere
else, I would ask you not to be surprised at this, and not to interrupt me. For I am more than seventy
years of age, and this is the first time that I have ever appeared in a court of law, and I am quite a
stranger to the ways of the place; and therefore I would have you regard me as if I were really a stranger,
whom you would excuse if he spoke in his native tongue.
And first, I have to reply to the older charges and to my first accusers, and then I will go to the later
ones. For I have had many accusers, who accused me of old, and their false charges have continued
during many years; and I am more afraid of them than of Anytus and his associates, who are dangerous,
too, in their own way. But far more dangerous are these, who began when you were children, and took
possession of your minds with their falsehoods, telling of one Socrates, a wise man, who speculated
about the heaven above, and searched into the earth beneath, and made the worse appear the better
cause. These are the accusers whom I dread; for they are the circulators of this rumor, and their hearers
are too apt to fancy that speculators of this sort do not believe in the gods. And they are many, and their
charges against me are of ancient date, and they made them in days when you were impressible in
childhood, or perhaps in youth, and the cause when heard went by default, for there was none to answer.
And, hardest of all, their names I do not know and cannot tell; unless in the chance of a comic poet.2 But
the main body of these slanderers who from envy and malice have wrought upon you, and there are
some of them who are convinced themselves, and impart their convictions to others all these, I say, are
most difficult to deal with; for I cannot have them up here, and examine them, and therefore I must
simply fight with shadows in my own defense, and examine when there is no one who answers. I will
ask you then to assume with me, as I was saying, that my opponents are of two kinds, one recent, the
other ancient; and I hope that you will see the propriety of my answering the latter first, for these
accusations you heard long before the others, and much oftener.
I will begin at the beginning, and ask what the accusation is which has given rise to this slander of
1 Socrates is on trial. He will be judged by sundown by 501 of his peers. We don’t get to hear the
prosecution’s side; we only hear from Socrates. In fact, we don’t even really hear from him. This was
written by Plato, his student, some time after the actual events.
2 Athens was a small city, and Socrates was quite famous. He’s referring here to Aristophanes, who
wrote a play about Socrates.
me, and which has encouraged Meletus to proceed against me. What do the slanderers say? “Socrates is
an evil-doer, and a curious person, who searches into things under the earth and in heaven, and he makes
the worse appear the better cause; and he teaches the aforesaid doctrines to others.” But the simple truth
is, O Athenians, that I have nothing to do with these studies. Very many of those here present are
witnesses to the truth of this, and to them I appeal. Speak then, you who have heard me, and tell your
neighbors whether any of you have ever known me hold forth in few words or in many upon matters of
this sort…. You hear their answer. And from what they say of this you will be able to judge of the truth
of the rest.
As little foundation is there for the report that I am a teacher, and take money; that is no more true
than the other. Although, if a man is able to teach, I honour him for being paid. There is Gorgias of
Leontium, and Prodicus of Ceos, and Hippias of Elis, who go the round of the cities, and are able to
persuade the young men to leave their own citizens, by whom they might be taught for nothing, and
come to them, whom they not only pay, but are thankful if they may be allowed to pay them.1 Had I
[such knowledge], I should have been very proud and conceited; but the truth is that I have no
knowledge of the kind.
I dare say, Athenians, that someone among you will reply, “Why is this, Socrates, and what is the
origin of these accusations of you: for there must have been something strange which you have been
doing? Now I regard this as a fair challenge, and I will endeavor to explain to you the origin of this
name of “wise,” and of this evil fame. And although some of you may think I am joking, I declare that I
will tell you the entire truth. Men of Athens, this reputation of mine has come of a certain sort of
wisdom which I possess. If you ask me what kind of wisdom, I reply, such wisdom as is attainable by
man, for to that extent I am inclined to believe that I am wise; whereas the persons of whom I was
speaking have a superhuman wisdom, which I may fail to describe, because I have it not myself; and he
who says that I have, speaks falsely, and is taking away my character. And here, O men of Athens, I
must beg you not to interrupt me, even if I seem to say something extravagant. For the word which I will
speak is not mine. I will refer you to a witness who is worthy of credit, and will tell you about my
wisdom— whether I have any, and of what sort—and that witness shall be the god of Delphi. You must
have known Chaerephon; he was early a friend of mine, and also a friend of yours, for he shared in the
exile of the people, and returned with you. Well, Chaerephon, as you know, was very impetuous in all
his doings, and he went to Delphi and boldly asked the oracle to tell him whether—as I was saying, I
must beg you not to interrupt—he asked the oracle to tell him whether there was anyone wiser than I
was, and the Pythian prophetess answered that there was no man wiser. Chaerephon is dead himself, but
his brother, who is in court, will confirm the truth of this story.
Why do I mention this? Because I am going to explain to you why I have such an evil name. When I
heard the answer, I said to myself, What can the god mean? and what is the interpretation of this riddle?
for I know that I have no wisdom, small or great. What can he mean when he says that I am the wisest of
men? And yet he is a god and cannot lie; that would be against his nature. After a long consideration, I
at last thought of a method of trying the question. I reflected that if I could only find a man wiser than
1These men are ‘Sophists’, who Socrates hates (and you can get a sense of his famous irony here).
Sophists taught the young men to be politicians, and how to win in arguments. They were like
management consultants today: overpaid blowhards.
myself, then I might go to the god with a refutation in my hand. I should say to him, “Here is a man who
is wiser than I am; but you said that I was the wisest.” Accordingly I went to one who had the reputation
of wisdom, and observed to him his name I need not mention; he was a politician whom I selected for
examination—and the result was as follows: When I began to talk with him, I could not help thinking
that he was not really wise, although he was thought wise by many, and wiser still by himself; and I
went and tried to explain to him that he thought himself wise, but was not really wise; and the
consequence was that he hated me, and his enmity was shared by several who were present and heard
me. So I left him, saying to myself, as I went away: “Well, although I do not suppose that either of us
knows anything really beautiful and good, I am better off than he is—for he knows nothing, and thinks
that he knows. I neither know nor think that I know. In this latter particular, then, I seem to have slightly
the advantage of him.” Then I went to another, who had still higher philosophical pretensions, and my
conclusion was exactly the same. I made another enemy of him, and of many others besides him.1
After this I went to one man after another, being not unconscious of the enmity which I provoked,
and I lamented and feared this: but necessity was laid upon me—the word of God, I thought, ought to be
considered first. And I said to myself, “Go! I must to all who appear to know, and find out the meaning
of the oracle.” And I swear to you, Athenians, by the dog I swear! for I must tell you the truth the result
of my mission was just this: I found that the men most in repute were all but the most foolish; and that
some inferior men were really wiser and better. I will tell you the tale of my wanderings and of the
“Herculean” labors, as I may call them, which I endured only to find at last the oracle irrefutable. When
I left the politicians, I went to the poets; tragic, dithyrambic, and all sorts. And there, I said to myself,
you will be detected; now you will find out that you are more ignorant than they are. Accordingly, I took
them some of the most elaborate passages in their own writings, and asked what was the meaning of
them thinking that they would teach me something. Will you believe me? I am almost ashamed to speak
of this, but still I must say that there is hardly a person present who would not have talked better about
their poetry than they did themselves. That showed me in an instant that not by wisdom do poets write
poetry, but by a sort of genius and inspiration; they are like diviners or soothsayers who also say many
fine things, but do not understand the meaning of them. And the poets appeared to me to be much in the
same case; and I further observed that upon the strength of their poetry they believed themselves to be
the wisest of men in other things in which they were not wise. So I departed, conceiving myself to be
superior to them for the same reason that I was superior to the politicians.
At last I went to the artisans, for I was conscious that I knew nothing at all, as I may say, and I was
sure that they knew many fine things; and in this I was not mistaken, for they did know many things of
which I was ignorant, and in this they certainly were wiser than I was. But I observed that even the good
artisans fell into the same error as the poets; because they were good workmen they thought that they
also knew all sorts of high matters, and this defect in them overshadowed their wisdom. Therefore, I
asked myself on behalf of the oracle, whether I would like to be as I was, neither having their knowledge
nor their ignorance, or like them in both; and I made answer to myself and the oracle that I was better off
as I was.
This investigation has led to my having many enemies of the worst and most dangerous kind, and
1Socrates was famous for these interrogations (called ‘dialogues), and Plato, his student, wrote them
down. How accurate they are is a matter of debate.
has given occasion also to many calumnies, and I am called wise, for my hearers always imagine that I
myself possess the wisdom which I find wanting in others: but the truth is, O men of Athens, that God
only is wise; and in this oracle he means to say that the wisdom of men is little or nothing; he is not
speaking of Socrates, he is only using my name as an illustration, as if he said, He, O men, is the wisest,
who, like Socrates, knows that his wisdom is in truth worth nothing. And so I go my way, obedient to
the god, and make inquisition into the wisdom of anyone, whether citizen or stranger, who appears to be
wise; and if he is not wise, then in vindication of the oracle I show him that he is not wise; and this
occupation quite absorbs me, and I have no time to give either to any public matter of interest or to any
concern of my own, but I am in utter poverty by reason of my devotion to the god.
There is another thing: young men of the richer classes, who have not much to do, come about me of
their own accord; they like to hear the pretenders examined, and they often imitate me, and examine
others themselves; there are plenty of persons, as they soon enough discover, who think that they know
something, but really know little or nothing: and then those who are examined by them instead of being
angry with themselves are angry with me: “This confounded Socrates,” they say; “this villainous
misleader of youth!” And this is the reason why my three accusers, Meletus and Anytus and Lycon,
have set upon me; Meletus, who has a quarrel with me on behalf of the poets; Anytus, on behalf of the
craftsmen; Lycon, on behalf of the rhetoricians: and as I said at the beginning, I cannot expect to get rid
of this mass of calumny all in a moment. And this, O men of Athens, is the truth and the whole truth; I
have concealed nothing.
I have said enough in my defense against the first class of my accusers; I turn to the second class,
who are headed by Meletus, that good and patriotic man, as he calls himself. What do they say? “That
Socrates is a doer of evil, and corrupter of the youth, and he does not believe in the gods of the state, and
has other new divinities of his own.” That is the sort of charge; and now let us examine the particular
counts. He says that I am a doer of evil, who corrupts the youth; but I say, O men of Athens, that
Meletus is a doer of evil, and the evil is that he makes a joke of a serious matter, and is too ready at
bringing other men to trial from a pretended zeal and interest about matters in which he really never had
the smallest interest. And the truth of this I will endeavor to prove.
Come hither, Meletus, and let me ask a question of you. You think a great deal about the
improvement of youth?
Yes, I do.1
Tell the judges, then, who is their improver; for you must know, as you have taken the pains to
discover their corrupter, and are citing and accusing me before them. Speak, then, and tell the judges
who their improver is. Observe, Meletus, that you are silent, and have nothing to say. But is not this
rather disgraceful, and a very considerable proof of what I was saying, that you have no interest in the
matter? Speak up, friend, and tell us who their improver is.
The laws.
But that, my good sir, is not my meaning. I want to know who the person is, who, in the first place,
knows the laws.
1 Each dialectic ends the same way: with the interlocutor being baffled. The Greeks had a name for
it: aporia. Notice the beautiful symmetry: Socrates shows (but does not teach!) his companions that they
know nothing. He makes them wise, like him!
intentionally or unintentionally?
Intentionally, I say.
But you have just admitted that the good do their neighbors good, and the evil do them evil. Now is
that a truth which your superior wisdom has recognized thus early in life, and am I, at my age, in such
darkness and ignorance as not to know that if a man with whom I have to live is corrupted by me, I am
very likely to be harmed by him, and yet I corrupt him, and intentionally, too. That is what you are
saying, and of that you will never persuade me or any other human being. But either I do not corrupt
them, or I corrupt them unintentionally, so that on either view of the case you lie. If my offense is
unintentional, the law has no cognizance of unintentional offenses: you ought to have taken me
privately, and warned and admonished me; for if I had been better advised, I should have left off doing
what I only did unintentionally—no doubt I should; whereas you hated to converse with me or teach me,
but you indicted me in this court, which is a place not of instruction, but of punishment.
I have shown, Athenians, as I was saying, that Meletus has no care at all, great or small, about the
matter. But still I should like to know, Meletus, in what I am affirmed to corrupt the young. I suppose
you mean, as I infer from your indictment, that I teach them not to acknowledge the gods which the state
acknowledges, but some other new divinities or spiritual agencies in their stead. These are the lessons
which corrupt the youth, as you say.
Yes, that I say emphatically.
Then, by the gods, Meletus, of whom we are speaking, tell me and the court, in somewhat plainer
terms, what you mean! For I do not as yet understand whether you affirm that I teach others to
acknowledge some gods, and therefore do believe in gods, and am not an entire atheist. This you do not
lay to my charge; but only that they are not the same gods which the city recognizes. The charge is that
they are different gods. Or, do you mean to say that I am an atheist simply, and a teacher of atheism?
I mean the latter, that you are a complete atheist.
That is an extraordinary statement, Meletus. Why do you say that? Do you mean that I do not
believe in the godhead of the sun or moon, which is the common creed of all men?
I assure you, judges, that he does not believe in them; for he says that the sun is stone, and the moon
earth.
Friend Meletus, you think that you are accusing Anaxagoras; and you have but a bad opinion of the
judges, if you fancy them ignorant to such a degree as not to know that those doctrines are found in the
books of Anaxagoras the Clazomenian, who is full of them. And these are the doctrines which the youth
are said to learn of Socrates, when there are not unfrequently exhibitions of them at the theatre (price of
admission one drachma at the most); and they might cheaply purchase them, and laugh at Socrates if he
pretends to father such eccentricities. And so, Meletus, you really think that I do not believe in any god?
I swear by Zeus that you believe absolutely in none at all.
You are a liar, Meletus, not believed even by yourself. For I cannot help thinking, O men of Athens,
that Meletus is reckless and impudent, and that he has written this indictment in a spirit of mere
wantonness and youthful bravado. Has he not compounded a riddle, thinking to try me? He said to
himself: I shall see whether this wise Socrates will discover my ingenious contradiction, or whether I
shall be able to deceive him and the rest of them. For he certainly does appear to me to contradict
himself in the indictment as much as if he said that Socrates is guilty of not believing in the gods, and
yet of believing in them. But this surely is a piece of fun.
I should like you, O men of Athens, to join me in examining what I conceive to be his inconsistency;
and do you, Meletus, answer. And I must remind you that you are not to interrupt me if I speak in my
accustomed manner.
Did ever man, Meletus, believe in the existence of human things, and not of human beings? ... I
wish, men of Athens, that he would answer, and not be always trying to get up an interruption. Did ever
any man believe in horsemanship, and not in horses? Or in flute-playing, and not in flute-players? No,
my friend; I will answer to you and to the court, as you refuse to answer for yourself. There is no man
who ever did. But now please to answer the next question: Can a man believe in spiritual and divine
agencies, and not in spirits or demigods?
He cannot.
I am glad that I have extracted that answer, by the assistance of the court; nevertheless you swear in
the indictment that I teach and believe in divine or spiritual agencies (new or old, no matter for that); at
any rate, I believe in spiritual agencies, as you say and swear in the affidavit; but if I believe in divine
beings, I must believe in spirits or demigods; is not that true? Yes, that is true, for I may assume that
your silence gives assent to that. Now what are spirits or demigods? Are they not either gods or the sons
of gods? Is that true?
Yes, that is true.
But this is just the ingenious riddle of which I was speaking: the demigods or spirits are gods, and
you say first that I don’t believe in gods, and then again that I do believe in gods. You might as well
affirm the existence of mules, and deny that of horses and asses. Such nonsense, Meletus, could only
have been intended by you as a trial of me.
I have said enough in answer to the charge of Meletus: any elaborate defense is unnecessary; but as I
was saying before, I certainly have many enemies, and this is what will be my destruction if I am
destroyed; of that I am certain; not Meletus, nor yet Anytus, but the envy and detraction of the world,
which has been the death of many good men, and will probably be the death of many more; there is no
danger of my being the last of them.
Someone will say: And are you not ashamed, Socrates, of a course of life which is likely to bring
you to an untimely end? To him I may fairly answer: There you are mistaken. A man who is good for
anything ought not to calculate the chance of living or dying; he ought only to consider whether in doing
anything he is doing right or wrong acting the part of a good man or of a bad. Whereas, according to
your view, the heroes who fell at Troy were not good for much, and the son of Thetis above all, who
altogether despised danger in comparison with disgrace; and when his goddess mother said, “Fate waits
upon you next after Hector”; he, hearing this, utterly despised danger and death, and instead of fearing
them, feared rather to live in dishonor, and not to avenge his friend. “Let me die next,” he replies, “and
be avenged of my enemy, rather than abide here by the beaked ships, a scorn and a burden of the earth.”
Strange, indeed, would be my conduct, O men of Athens, if I who, when I was ordered by the
generals whom you chose to command me remained where they placed me, like any other man, facing
death. If I disobeyed the oracle because I was afraid of death, then I should be fancying that I was wise
when I was not wise. For this fear of death is indeed the pretense of wisdom, and not real wisdom, being
the appearance of knowing the unknown; since no one knows whether death, which they in their fear
apprehend to be the greatest evil, may not be the greatest good. I will never fear or avoid a possible good
rather than a certain evil.
If you say to me, Socrates, this time we will not mind Anytus, and will let you off, but upon one
condition, that you are not to inquire and speculate in this way any more, I should reply: Men of Athens,
I honor and love you; but I shall obey God rather than you, and while I have life and strength I shall
never cease from the practice and teaching of philosophy, exhorting anyone whom I meet after my
manner, and convincing him, saying: O my friend, why do you who are a citizen of the great and mighty
and wise city of Athens, care so much about laying up the greatest amount of money and honor and
reputation, and so little about wisdom and truth and the greatest improvement of the soul, which you
never regard or heed at all?
For I do nothing but go about persuading you all, old and young alike, not to take thought for your
persons and your properties, but first and chiefly to care about the greatest improvement of the soul. I
tell you that excellence is not given by money, but that from excellence come money and every other
good of man, public as well as private. This is my teaching, and if this is the doctrine which corrupts the
youth, my influence is ruinous indeed.
Men of Athens, do not interrupt, but hear me; there was an agreement between us that you should
hear me out. I would have you know that, if you kill such a one as I am, you will injure yourselves more
than you will injure me. Meletus and Anytus will not injure me: they cannot; for it is not in the nature of
things that a bad man should injure a better than himself. I do not deny that he may, perhaps, kill him, or
drive him into exile, or deprive him of civil rights. For if you kill me you will not easily find another like
me, who, if I may use such a ludicrous figure of speech, am a sort of gadfly, given to the state by the
God; and the state is like a great and noble steed who is tardy in his motions owing to his very size, and
requires to be stirred into life. I am that gadfly which God has given the state and all day long and in all
places am always fastening upon you, arousing and persuading and reproaching you. And as you will
not easily find another like me, I would advise you to spare me. I dare say that you may feel irritated at
being suddenly awakened when you are caught napping; and you may think that if you were to strike me
dead, as Anytus advises, which you easily might, then you would sleep on for the remainder of your
lives.
I will tell you a story—tasteless, perhaps, and commonplace, but nevertheless true. The only office
of state which I ever held, O men of Athens, was that of senator; the tribe Antiochus, which is my tribe,
had the presidency at the trial of the generals who had not taken up the bodies of the slain after the battle
of Arginusae; and you proposed to try them all together, which was illegal, as you all thought
afterwards; but at the time I was the only one of the Prytanes who was opposed to the illegality, and I
gave my vote against you; and when the orators threatened to impeach and arrest me, and have me taken
away, and you called and shouted, I made up my mind that I would run the risk, having law and justice
with me, rather than take part in your injustice because I feared imprisonment and death. This happened
in the days of the democracy.
But when the oligarchy of the Thirty was in power, they sent for me and four others into the rotunda,
and bade us bring Leon the Salaminian, as they wanted to execute him. This was a specimen of the sort
of commands which they were always giving with the view of implicating as many as possible in their
crimes; and then I showed, not in words only, but in deed, that, if I may be allowed to use such an
expression, I cared not a straw for death, and that my only fear was the fear of doing an unrighteous or
unholy thing. For the strong arm of that oppressive power did not frighten me into doing wrong; and
when we came out of the rotunda the other four went to Salamis and fetched Leon, but I went quietly
home. For which I might have lost my life, had not the power of the Thirty shortly afterwards come to
an end. And to this many will witness.
Now do you really imagine that I could have survived all these years, if I had led a public life,
supposing that like a good man I had always supported the right and had made justice, as I ought, the
first thing? No, indeed, men of Athens, neither I nor any other. But I have been always the same in all
my actions, public as well as private, and never have I yielded any base compliance to those who are
slanderously termed my disciples or to any other. For the truth is that I have no regular disciples: but if
anyone likes to come and hear me while I am pursuing my mission, whether he be young or old, he may
freely come. And if anyone says that he has ever learned or heard anything from me in private which all
the world has not heard, I should like you to know that he is speaking an untruth.
But I shall be asked, Why do people delight in continually conversing with you? I have told you
already, Athenians, the whole truth about this: they like to hear the cross-examination of the pretenders
to wisdom; there is amusement in this. And this is a duty which the God has imposed upon me, as I am
assured by oracles, visions, and in every sort of way in which the will of divine power was ever signified
to anyone. This is true, O Athenians; or, if not true, would be soon refuted. For if I am really corrupting
the youth, and have corrupted some of them already, those of them who have grown up and have
become sensible that I gave them bad advice in the days of their youth should come forward as accusers
and take their revenge; and if they do not like to come themselves, some of their relatives, fathers,
brothers, or other kinsmen, should say what evil their families suffered at my hands. Now is their time.
Many of them I see in the court. There is Crito, who is of the same age and of the same deme with
myself; and there is Critobulus his son, whom I also see. Then again there is Lysanias of Sphettus, who
is the father of Aeschines, he is present; and also there is Antiphon of Cephisus. I might mention a great
many others, any of whom Meletus should have produced as witnesses in the course of his speech; and
let him still produce them, if he has forgotten, I will make way for him.
Well, Athenians, this and the like of this is the defense which I have to offer. Yet a word more.
Perhaps there may be someone who is offended at me, when he calls to mind how he himself, on a
similar or even a less serious occasion, had recourse to prayers and supplications with many tears, and
how he produced his children in court, which was a moving spectacle; whereas I, who am probably in
danger of my life, will do none of these things. Perhaps this may come into his mind, and he may be set
against me, and vote in anger because he is displeased at this. Now if there be such a person among you,
which I am far from affirming, I may fairly reply to him: My friend, I am a man, and like other men, a
creature of flesh and blood, and not of wood or stone, as Homer says; and I have a family, yes, and sons.
O Athenians, three in number, one of whom is growing up, and the two others are still young; and yet I
will not bring any of them hither in order to petition you for an acquittal. And why not? Not from any
self-will or disregard of you. Whether I am or am not afraid of death is another question, of which I will
not now speak. But my reason simply is that I feel such conduct to be discreditable to myself, and you,
and the whole state. One who has reached my years, and who has a name for wisdom, whether deserved
or not, ought not to debase himself. At any rate, the world has decided that Socrates is in some way
superior to other men. And if those among you who are said to be superior in wisdom and courage, and
any other excellence, demean themselves in this way, how shameful is their conduct!
But, setting aside the question of dishonor, there seems to be something wrong in petitioning a
judge, and thus procuring an acquittal instead of informing and convincing him. For his duty is, not to
make a present of justice, but to give judgment; and he has sworn that he will judge according to the
laws. For if, O men of Athens, by force of persuasion and entreaty, I could overpower your oaths, then I
should be teaching you to believe that there are no gods, and convict myself, in my own defense, of not
believing in them. But that is not the case; for I do believe that there are gods, and in a far higher sense
than that in which any of my accusers believe in them. And to you and to God I commit my cause, to be
determined by you as is best for you and me.
1 Socrates and his accusers will now each propose a sentence. The jury must decide between the two
sentences.
2 He proposes a nice retirement package as his ‘punishment’.
a capital cause should not be decided in one day, then I believe that I should have convinced you; but
now the time is too short. I cannot in a moment refute great slanders; and, as I am convinced that I never
wronged another, I will assuredly not wrong myself. I will not say of myself that I deserve any evil, or
propose any penalty. Why should I? Because I am afraid of the penalty of death which Meletus
proposes? When I do not know whether death is a good or an evil, why should I propose a penalty which
would certainly be an evil? Shall I say imprisonment? And why should I live in prison, and be the slave
of the magistrates of the year—of the Eleven? Or shall the penalty be a fine, and imprisonment until the
fine is paid? There is the same objection. I should have to lie in prison, for money I have none, and I
cannot pay. And if I say exile (and this may possibly be the penalty which you will affix), I must indeed
be blinded by the love of life if I were to consider that when you, who are my own citizens, cannot
endure my discourses and words, and have found them so grievous and odious that you would fain have
done with them, others are likely to endure me.
Had I money I might have proposed to give you what I had, and have been none the worse. But you
see that I have none, and can only ask you to proportion the fine to my means. However, I think that I
could afford a minae, and therefore I propose that penalty; Plato, Crito, Critobulus, and Apollodorus, my
friends here, bid me say thirty minae, and they will be the sureties. Well then, say thirty minae, let that
be the penalty; for that they will be ample security to you.
1I love this part. Either death is a dreamless sleep, or he’ll go to heaven. If he goes to heaven, how
awesome would that be? Socrates can bug everyone all the time! And what are they going to do—he’s
already dead, so they can’t kill him again!
The End
Socrates (via Plato): The Apology, decoded
Socrates’ Defense
Well, here I am, on trial. My accusers have just told you how eloquent I am, but they should be
ashamed of themselves. You’ll soon see that they were lying. They are much more eloquent than me;
they’re so eloquent they almost made me believe them! In comparison, I am quite blunt. I can’t dress my
words up—but I shouldn’t have to. The truth is plain, and I will speak to you plainly. I know this is a
fancy courthouse, and I know people dress their words up like they dress themselves up when they come
here. But I’m old, and I’ve never been here before. Please, be kind; treat me like you would a stranger
from a different country, for in some ways, I am.
Before I deal with the charges that brought me here, I will have to deal with some old accusations.
These are accusations I have faced for years, and, to be honest, I’m more afraid of them than I am the
charges of Anytus. I know that you all have heard of me before. Some of you have heard of me since
you were children. You will have heard that I’m a wise man, and that I speculate about odd things and
love nothing more than to win an argument. You have heard these slanders for so long and from so
many people that it is hard for me to argue against them. I need to fight with shadows in my own
defense and cross-examine someone who does not answer. Only once I have done this will I be able to
deal with the other charges, the ones that have got me here in court.
You’ve all heard that I love to win arguments, correct? Have any of you actually ever seen me argue,
and argue to win? No? Then that’s that. What you heard is a false rumour, just a rumour. I admit, I love
to talk with people and to argue, but I always seek truth, not victory.
You may also have heard that I love to teach. I am not a teacher. I wish I knew something to teach! I
would love to teach! Gorgias of Leontium gets paid for teaching, and so do Prodicus of Ceos, and
Hippias of Elis. Their students not only pay but are glad to pay! How wonderful. If I were as talented as
they are, I would be very proud and conceited; but the truth is simple. I have nothing to teach.
I know you are all wondering how I ended up here in court, if none of these rumours is true. Men of
Athens, I’m here because I have a certain kind of wisdom. If you ask me what kind of wisdom, I’d have
to say a small and natural wisdom. Those others, the ones who teach, they have a great and supernatural
wisdom. Not me.
Hey, hey! Quiet down, you in the back! What I say is true! Ask the god of Delphi. Chaerephon, my
friend and yours, he went to Delphi and asked the oracle to tell him whether—hey, be quiet!—He asked
the oracle to tell him whether there was anyone wiser than me. The oracle said there was no man wiser.
Chaerephon is dead now, but his brother is here. Ask him if you want.
When I heard what the oracle said, I said to myself: What can the god be thinking? On the one hand,
I know that I’m not wise at all, but on the other hand, the oracle cannot lie. After thinking about it, I
figured out what to do. I decided that I would try to prove the oracle wrong. I made this my mission.
I went to a person who was supposed to be wise to have a little talk. In this case, since he was a
politician, I asked him about politics. Now, don’t worry. I won’t name names.
But you know, I realized after talking with him for a while that he wasn’t really wise. And I told him
so. Well you can imagine how he took that. He hated me. So did his friends. I knew, though, that neither
of us knows anything good, but I know that I don’t know, while he still thinks he does know. I’m better
off than him—for he knows nothing and thinks he knows something. I neither know nor think that I
know.
I did this again and again. I went to politicians, poets, artisans, the works. Let me tell you: I pissed a
lot of people off. I had to keep going, though. The god had said I was wise. And you know what: I found
that the men with the best reputations were really the most foolish, and I found some supposedly inferior
men were really wiser and better.
But boy, oh boy, did I make a lot of enemies. A lot. The kids, they liked me, but nobody else did.
The kids liked to hear me talk to the wise men. Eventually, they started doing it themselves, in fact. I
didn’t teach them how. I told you—I don’t teach. They just did it.
And this, men of Athens, this is the truth and the whole truth.
Now let me turn to my accusers, the ones who brought me here today: Meletus, Anytus, and Lycon.
They say this: Socrates is a doer of evil, and a corrupter of the youth, and he does not believe in the gods
of the state, and has other new divinities of his own. Let me go through these accusations step by step.
They say that I do evil and corrupt the youth; but I say, men of Athens, that Meletus is a doer of evil.
He is making a joke of this court. That’s a real evil.
Come here, Meletus, and let me ask you some questions. You say you know how to improve young
people?
Yes, I do.
Okay. When we want to improve young people, whom should we call? What, no answer? What
should we do? What improves young people?
The laws.
Oh, c’mon Meletus. You know that’s not what I mean. Who makes the laws?
The judges, Socrates, who are here in court.
Oh! Okay then! So the judges here are able to instruct and improve youth?
Yes, they must.
What, all of them?
All of them, yes. All of these great men improve our youth.
Get out of town! That is good news! There are plenty of improvers, then. And what about the
audience. Them too? They improve the youth?
Yes, they do.
And the senators?
Yes, the senators improve the youth.
But perhaps the members of the citizen assembly corrupt them? Or do they improve them?
They improve them. All the citizens of Athens improve our youth. I say that emphatically.
Then every Athenian improves the youth. All with the exception of me, poor Socrates. Am I their
only corrupter? Is that what you’re saying?
That is what I am saying.
Wow. If that were true, I’m would really be in trouble. But Meletus, you and I both know that it’s
not true. Let’s talk about horses. When it comes to training horses, is everyone good, or do some people
train them better than others? Can everybody be a trainer? Or do some people just make things worse?
Oh. No answer? Well, it seems to me that horses are a little like the youth. Both need specialized
teachers. And you have to admit that it’s a little unlikely that I’m the only person who corrupts them.
Let me ask you another question. You surely think it’s better to live with good people.
Certainly.
And do you think that I corrupt the youth intentionally or accidentally?
Intentionally! You, Socrates, corrupt the youth intentionally!
Now hold on. Why would I want to live around bad people? You just said that it is better to live with
good people. Why would I want to make things worse in my own town? Either I don’t corrupt them, or I
do corrupt them, but I do so accidentally. In either case, you’re lying. In either case, I’m not guilty. You
know that our law does not punish people who commit accidents.
Furthermore, if you really thought I did this by accident, you should have taken me aside and warned
me. Instead, you indicted me in this court. You don’t really care about helping the youth of Athens. You
are just out for revenge.
I still want to know, Meletus, what you think I’m doing wrong. I guess you must think that I teach
the youth about false gods. That’s what you charged me with.
Yes, that’s it. You believe in false gods!
Do you mean that I teach about false gods, or that I’m an atheist? You didn’t make that clear in your
charge, but do tell me what’s going on.
I mean that you are a complete atheist.
Don’t you think that I believe the sun and the moon are gods, just like everyone else here?
No, you do not. Judges, he says that the sun is stone, and the moon earth.
Meletus, you’ve confused me with Anaxagoras; don’t think that the jury is that dumb. They know
that the books of Anaxagoras the Clazomenian are full of these theories. And you do know that
Anaxagoras’ plays are at the theatre, right? The youth go there often. Even had I wanted to, I wouldn’t
be able to fool them into thinking these theories are mine. They are far too smart for that. You are a liar,
Meletus. You don’t even believe yourself. Go sit down.
Well that’s that. I have a lot of enemies, though. Meletus is only one. If I die here, it will be them,
not him, that kill me. Let me address some.
Someone is going to say that I should straighten up and be ashamed of my embarrassing life.
Someone is going to say that this life will get me killed. But you know what? A man who is good for
anything ought not to calculate the chance of living or dying; he ought only to consider whether in doing
anything he is doing right or wrong, acting the part of a good man or of a bad.
I have never feared death. Why would I start now, when I am old? When I was young and a soldier I
wasn’t afraid. When the tyrants were in charge, they tried to kill me. I wasn’t afraid then either. It would
be absurd for me to desert the philosopher’s post now. Being afraid of death is nothing but a pretense of
wisdom. No one knows whether death is good or bad. I know that I do not know, just like I said. This is
what makes me wiser than other men.
Someone will say that I should stop asking questions and be a good, quiet citizen, and you may
agree, and acquit me on that condition. If you let me go, and if you ask me to stop bugging you, asking
you questions, trying to discover the truth, and trying to keep you virtuous, I will disobey you. I will
persevere. Let me say this loud and clear: men of Athens, I honour and love you; but I shall obey god
rather than you. While I have life and strength, I will never stop doing philosophy. I will always tell
people I meet: Friend, you live in the great city Athens. Why do you care so much about getting rich and
being famous? Don’t you worry about your soul and truth?
No, I won’t stop, not with them or with you.
In fact, let me do it now. You, out there, old and young alike, stop worrying about yourself and your
stuff. Worry about your soul. Excellence does not come from money. No, money comes from
excellence, and so does every other good thing. This is my teaching, and if this is the doctrine that
corrupts the youth, my influence is terrible indeed.
I love you, but whatever you do, know that I shall never alter my ways, not even if I have to die
many times.
Hey! You promised that I’d be able to talk! And I think that what I am going to say will do you
good. It’s just one more thing, but you won’t like it.
If you kill me, you will injure yourselves more than you will injure me. Meletus and Anytus will not
injure me: they cannot; bad men can’t harm good men. They will only hurt themselves.
If you kill me, you won’t find another like me. I am a sort of gadfly, given to Athens by the gods.
Athens is a big, majestic horse. I’m the fly that bugs the horse and keeps it awake. Yes, I bug you. Yes,
you could kill me easily. But know this: if you do, you’ll slumber for the rest of your lives.
Alright, alright. There’s just one more thing. A lot of people come here and beg for mercy. They cry
and wail and bring out their wives and children. I’m too good for that. Don’t hold it against me.
Plato was Socrates’ best student. He was everything Socrates wasn’t: Socrates was poor, ugly, and
wonderful. Plato was rich, handsome, and a total jerk. Plato, though, is one of only a few stars that shine
as brightly as Socrates. In fact, it is safe to say that had it not been for Plato, Socrates, and philosophy as
we know it, would have been forgotten.
This is because Socrates never wrote anything down; Plato wrote things down for him. In fact,
almost everything we know about Socrates comes from Plato’s writings. Plato made things complicated,
though. While he started off by writing down Socrates’ ideas faithfully, Plato gradually started
integrating his own philosophy—yet had Socrates still say the words. While this is bad enough, and
makes it very difficult to distinguish Socrates’ ideas from Plato’s, Plato himself seems to have changed
from a tolerable sort of fellow into quite a nasty bully. In Plato’s later work, then, Socrates ends up
saying things that completely contradict what he said in places like The Apology.
In The Republic, for instance, Plato makes Socrates say that he quite likes a good dictatorship and
that there is nothing like a rousing bunch of executions to get the citizens all pulling together. These are
strange things for a man who was nearly killed for standing up to a dictatorship to be saying.
Still, The Republic is the 7th most important book in Western civilization. That’s a fact. It is Plato’s
masterpiece. It is also quite long, so I haven’t included it here. What follows is a crude shortening of
Plato’s fine book.
The Republic is a masterpiece because it presents a totally unified philosophy. Plato has a theory of
knowledge that explains (and is explained by) his theory of metaphysics. Plato’s metaphysics explains
his politics and his theory of ethics.
The central theme of The Republic is excellence, arete in Greek. Plato sees everything as having a
purpose; when it fulfills that purpose, it is excellent. So, a horse’s purpose is running. An excellent horse
runs well. A knife’s purpose is cutting, a fire’s purpose is warming, and so on. Plato wants to find out
what a person’s purpose is, and in doing so, he finds out what a country’s purpose is.
I won’t spoil the suspense by telling you what he thinks, but I do want to point out the two most
important parts of the book, at least from my perspective—and I have to say that, because The Republic
can be anything. To teachers, it is a treatise on education, to politicians, a book on governance. It even
has discussions of good cooking.
The Forms
There are four levels of reality. Everyone is familiar with the first two: images and physical things.
The second two are different aspects of what Plato calls “The Forms”.
The Forms are complicated. They are the perfect essences of things; they are immutable, permanent,
and the true reality, of which our reality is only a pale imitation. The Forms are a bit like heaven and a
bit like math. They’re not of this world, but they resemble it.
Forgive me for using geometry so much, and take a triangle. Any drawn triangle is imperfect. Its
sides are not perfectly straight, and its angles do not add up to 180º. A drawn triangle is an imperfect
imitation of the Form of Triangle—or, as I like to say, triangle-ness. Everything that has a -ness has a
Form: horsiness, humanness, squareness. Some -nesses are more basic than others, though—the perfect
triangle has both triangle-ness and perfect-ness. The most basic Forms are the top level of reality, and
they are things like, and including, Beauty, Truth, and Goodness.
BOOK II
Socrates: Justice1 is sometimes spoken of as the excellence of an individual, and sometimes as the
excellence of a state. In the larger, the quantity of justice is likely to be larger and more easily
discernible.
A state arises out of the needs of mankind; no one is self-sufficing, but all of us have many wants.
Then, as we have many wants, many persons are needed to supply them.
True, he said.2
And they exchange with one another, and one gives, and another receives, under the idea that the
exchange will be for their good.
Let us then consider, first of all, what will be their way of life [in the first small countries]. Will they
not produce corn, and wine, and clothes, and shoes, and build houses for themselves? And when they are
housed, they will work, in summer, commonly, stripped and barefoot, but in winter substantially clothed
and shod. They will feed on barley-meal and flour of wheat, baking and kneading them, making noble
cakes and loaves; these they will serve up on a mat of reeds or on clean leaves, themselves reclining the
while upon beds strewn with yew or myrtle. And they and their children will feast, drinking of the wine
which they have made, wearing garlands on their heads, and hymning the praises of the gods, in happy
converse with one another. And they will take care that their families do not exceed their means; having
an eye to poverty or war.
But, said Glaucon, interposing, you have not given them a relish to their meal.
True, I replied, I had forgotten; of course they must have a relish—salt, and olives, and cheese; for a
dessert we shall give them figs, and peas, and beans. And with such a diet they may be expected to live
in peace and health to a good old age.
Yes, Socrates, he said, and if you were providing for a city of pigs, how else would you feed the
beasts? You should give them the ordinary conveniences of life. People who are to be comfortable are
accustomed to lie on sofas, and dine off tables, and they should have sauces and sweets.
Yes, I said, now I understand: the question which you would have me consider is, not only how a
state, but how a luxurious state is created; and possibly there is no harm in this, for in such a state we
shall be more likely to see how justice and injustice originate. In my opinion the true and healthy
1 Justice is a terrible word to use here. He is talking about arete, or excellence. The Greeks think,
roughly, that things have a purpose, and when things do their purpose well, they are excellent. Plato is
trying to find out what excellent countries and people are. He calls them ‘just’.
2 Socrates is engaging in the ‘dialectic’ again—a kind of discussion with an interlocutor.
Interestingly, the essay hadn’t yet been invented. Almost all of Plato’s works are like this, and they are
called, for obvious reason, “The Dialogues”.
constitution of the state is the one which I have described.1 But if you wish also to see a state at fever-
heat, I have no objection. For I suspect that many will not be satisfied with the simpler way of life. Then
we must enlarge our borders; for the original healthy state is no longer sufficient. And the country which
was enough to support the original inhabitants will be too small now, and not enough? Then a slice of
our neighbours’ land will be wanted
And so we shall go to war, Glaucon. Shall we not? And our state must once more enlarge; and this
time the enlargement will be nothing short of a whole army. Then it will be our duty to select, if we can,
natures which are fitted for the task of guarding the city. And the selection will be no easy matter, I said;
but we must be brave and do our best.2
We must.
Is not the noble youth very like a well-bred dog in respect of guarding and watching? I mean that
both of them ought to be quick to see, and swift to overtake the enemy when they see him; and strong
too if, when they have caught him, they have to fight with him. Then now we have a clear notion of the
bodily qualities which are required in the guardian.
True.
And also of the mental ones; a dog, whenever he sees a stranger, is angry; when an acquaintance, he
welcomes him, although the one has never done him any harm, nor the other any good. Did this never
strike you as curious?
The matter never struck me before; but I quite recognise the truth of your remark.
And surely this instinct of the dog is very charming; your dog is a true philosopher.
Why?
Why, because he distinguishes the face of a friend and of an enemy only by the criterion of knowing
and not knowing. And must not an animal be a lover of learning who determines what he likes and
dislikes by the test of knowledge and ignorance? And is not the love of learning the love of wisdom,
which is philosophy?
Undoubtedly.
Come then, and let us pass a leisure hour in story-telling, and our story shall be the education of our
heroes. Can we find a better than the traditional sort?—and this has two divisions, gymnastic for the
body, and music for the soul.
Shall we just carelessly allow children to hear any casual tales which may be devised by casual
persons?
We cannot.
Then the first thing will be to establish a censorship of the writers of fiction. Neither, if we mean our
1 Socrates was Plato’s teacher, but Plato became an excellent philosopher in his own right. This, if
you ask me, is where Socrates ends, and Plato begins.
2 Athens constantly flipped between dictatorship and democracy. It’s understandable that he’d want
BOOK III
Glaucon, musical training is a more potent instrument than any other, because rhythm and harmony
find their way into the inward places of the soul, on which they mightily fasten, imparting grace. After
music comes gymnastic, in which our youth are next to be trained. Gymnastic as well as music should
begin in early years; the training in it should be careful and should continue through life. Then, to the
mind when adequately trained, we shall be right in handing over the more particular care of the body;
and in order to avoid prolixity we will now only give the general outlines of the subject.
Very good.
Of all persons a guardian should be the last to get drunk and not know where in the world he is.1 A
finer sort of training will be required for our warrior athletes, who are to be like wakeful dogs, and to see
and hear with the utmost keenness; amid the many changes of water and also of food, of summer heat
and winter cold, which they will have to endure when on a campaign, they must not be liable to break
down in health. And I can hardly be mistaken in saying that sweet sauces are nowhere mentioned in
Homer. In proscribing them, however, he is not singular; all professional athletes are well aware that a
man who is to be in good condition should take nothing of the kind.
Yes, he said; and knowing this, they are quite right in not taking them.
Then you would not approve of Syracusan dinners, and the refinements of Sicilian cookery? Nor, if
a man is to be in condition, would you allow him to have a Corinthian girl2 as his fair friend? Neither
would you approve of the delicacies, as they are thought, of Athenian confectionary?
Certainly not.
Did you never observe, I said, the effect on the mind itself of exclusive devotion to gymnastic, or the
opposite effect of an exclusive devotion to music?
Yes, he said, I am quite aware that the mere athlete becomes too much of a savage, and that the mere
musician is melted and softened beyond what is good for him.
Therefore, as I was just now saying, we must enquire who are the best guardians of their own
conviction that what they think the interest of the state is to be the rule of their lives. We must watch
them from their youth upwards, and make them perform actions in which they are most likely to forget
or to be deceived, and he who remembers and is not deceived is to be selected, and he who fails in the
trial is to be rejected. And there should also be toils and pains and conflicts prescribed for them, in
which they will be made to give further proof of the same qualities. And then, I said, we must try them
1 I’m out.
2 I have no idea what makes a Corinthian woman so dangerous, but boy, do I ever want to find out!
with enchantments—that is the third sort of test—and see what will be their behaviour: like those who
take colts amid noise and tumult to see if they are of a timid nature, so must we take our youth amid
terrors of some kind, and again pass them into pleasures, and prove them more thoroughly than gold is
proved in the furnace. And he who at every age, as boy and youth and in mature life, has come out of the
trial victorious and pure, shall be appointed a ruler and guardian of the state.1
And perhaps the word ‘guardian’ in the fullest sense ought to be applied to this higher class only
who preserve us against foreign enemies and maintain peace among our citizens at home, that the one
may not have the will, or the others the power, to harm us. The young men whom we before called
guardians may be more properly designated auxiliaries and supporters of the principles of the rulers.2
I agree with you, he said.
How then may we devise one of those needful falsehoods of which we lately spoke—just one royal
lie which may deceive the rulers, if that be possible, and at any rate the rest of the city?
How your words seem to hesitate on your lips!
You will not wonder, I replied, at my hesitation when you have heard.
Speak, he said, and fear not.
Citizens, we shall say to them in our tale, you are brothers, yet God has framed you differently.
Some of you have the power of command, and in the composition of these he has mingled gold,
wherefore also they have the greatest honour; others he has made of silver, to be auxiliaries; others again
who are to be husbandmen and craftsmen he has composed of brass and iron; and the species will
generally be preserved in the children. But as all are of the same original stock, a golden parent will
sometimes have a silver son, or a silver parent a golden son. They should observe what elements mingle
in their offspring; for if the son of a golden or silver parent has an admixture of brass and iron, then
nature orders a transposition of ranks, and the eye of the ruler must not be pitiful towards the child
because he has to descend in the scale and become a husbandman or artisan, just as there may be sons of
artisans who having an admixture of gold or silver in them are raised to honour, and become guardians
or auxiliaries. For an oracle says that when a man of brass or iron guards the state, it will be destroyed.
Such is the tale; is there any possibility of making our citizens believe in it?
Not in the present generation, he replied; there is no way of accomplishing this; but their sons may
be made to believe in the tale, and their sons’ sons, and posterity after them.
Then now let us consider what will be their way of life, if they are to realize our idea of them. In the
first place, none of them should have any property of his own beyond what is absolutely necessary;
neither should they have a private house or store closed against anyone who has a mind to enter; their
provisions should be only such as are required by trained warriors, who are men of temperance and
1 Athens was at war with Sparta when Plato was a young man. Spartans were as tough and as dumb
as pit bulls. Athenians were smart and soft. I think he’s trying to combine the best of both into his ideal
warrior.
2 We now have three classes: the guardians, the auxiliaries, and the peasants or commoner class,
about which Plato says very little. The guardians are sometimes called the philosopher kings. Notably,
the working class is actually the freest. They can own property and travel, for instance.
courage; they should agree to receive from the citizens a fixed rate of pay, enough to meet the expenses
of the year and no more; and they will go to mess and live together like soldiers in a camp. Gold and
silver we will tell them that they have from God; the diviner metal is within them, and they have
therefore no need of the dross which is current among men, and ought not to pollute the divine by any
such earthly admixture; for that commoner metal has been the source of many unholy deeds, but their
own is undefiled. And they alone of all the citizens may not touch or handle silver or gold, or be under
the same roof with them, or wear them, or drink from them. And this will be their salvation, and they
will be the saviours of the state. But should they ever acquire homes or lands or moneys of their own,
they will become housekeepers and husbandmen instead of guardians, enemies and tyrants instead of
allies of the other citizens; hating and being hated, plotting and being plotted against, they will pass their
whole life in much greater terror of internal than of external enemies, and the hour of ruin, both to
themselves and to the rest of the state, will be at hand. For all which reasons may we not say that thus
shall our state be ordered, and that these shall be the regulations appointed by us for guardians
concerning their houses and all other matters?
Yes, said Glaucon.
BOOK IV
Here Adeimantus interposed a question: How would you answer, Socrates, said he, if a person were
to say that you are making these people miserable, and that they are the cause of their own unhappiness;
the city in fact belongs to them, but they are none the better for it; whereas other men acquire lands, and
build large and handsome houses, and have everything handsome about them, offering sacrifices to the
gods on their own account?
Yes, I said; and you may add that they are only fed, and not paid in addition to their food, like other
men; and therefore they cannot, if they would, take a journey of pleasure; they have no money to spend
on a mistress or any other luxurious fancy, which, as the world goes, is thought to be happiness; and
many other accusations of the same nature might be added.
But, said he, let us suppose all this to be included in the charge.
You mean to ask, I said, what will be our answer?
Yes.
And our answer will be that, even as they are, our guardians may very likely be the happiest of men;
but that our aim in founding the state was not the disproportionate happiness of any one class, but the
greatest happiness of the whole. Suppose that we were painting a statue, and someone came up to us and
said, Why do you not put the most beautiful colours on the most beautiful parts of the body—the eyes
ought to be purple, but you have made them black—to him we might fairly answer, Sir, you would not
surely have us beautify the eyes to such a degree that they are no longer eyes; consider rather whether,
by giving this and the other features their due proportion, we make the whole beautiful. And so I say to
you, do not compel us to assign to the guardians a sort of happiness which will make them anything but
guardians. But if the latter be the truth, then the guardians and auxiliaries, and all others equally with
them, must be compelled or induced to do their own work in the best way. And thus the whole state will
grow up in a noble order, and the several classes will receive the proportion of happiness which nature
assigns to them.
I think that you are quite right.
Truly, I said, we are stupid fellows.1
Why so?
Why, my good sir, at the beginning of our enquiry, ages ago, there was justice tumbling out at our
feet, and we never saw her; nothing could be more ridiculous. Like people who go about looking for
what they have in their hands—that was the way with us—we looked not at what we were seeking, but
at what was far off in the distance; and therefore, I suppose, we missed her.
What do you mean?
I mean to say that in reality for a long time past we have been talking of justice, and have failed to
recognise her.
I grow impatient at the length of your exordium.
Well then, tell me, I said, whether I am right or not: You remember the original principle which we
were always laying down at the foundation of the state, that one man should practice one thing only, the
thing to which his nature was best adapted; now justice is this principle or a part of it.
Yes, we often said that one man should do one thing only.
Further, we affirmed that justice was doing one’s own business, and not being a busybody; we said
so again and again, and many others have said the same to us.
Yes, we said so.
Then to do one’s own business in a certain way may be assumed to be justice. Seeing then, I said,
that there are three distinct classes, any meddling of one with another, or the change of one into another,
is the greatest harm to the state, and may be most justly termed evil-doing?
Precisely.
And the greatest degree of evil-doing to one’s own city would be termed by you injustice?
Certainly.
This then is injustice; and on the other hand when the trader, the auxiliary, and the guardian each do
their own business, that is justice, and will make the city just.
Must we not acknowledge, I said, that in each of us there are the same principles and habits which
there are in the state; and that from the individual they pass into the state?—how else can they come
there? Take the quality of passion or spirit; it would be ridiculous to imagine that this quality, when
found in states, is not derived from the individuals who are supposed to possess it, e.g. the Thracians,
Scythians, and in general the northern nations; and the same may be said of the love of knowledge,
which is the special characteristic of our part of the world, or of the love of money, which may, with
equal truth, be attributed to the Phoenicians and Egyptians.
Admitting this to be true of desire generally, let us suppose a particular class of desires, and out of
1Here we return to the conceit of The Republic, that the excellence of the state and the individual are
somehow similar.
these we will select hunger and thirst, as they are termed, which are the most obvious of them?
Certainly.
Then the soul of the thirsty one, in so far as he is thirsty, desires only drink; for this he yearns and
tries to obtain it?
That is plain.
And if you suppose something which pulls a thirsty soul away from drink, that must be different
from the thirsty principle which draws him like a beast to drink; for, as we were saying, the same thing
cannot at the same time with the same part of itself act in contrary ways about the same.
Impossible.
No more than you can say that the hands of the archer push and pull the bow at the same time, but
what you say is that one hand pushes and the other pulls. And in such a case what is one to say? Would
you not say that there was something in the soul bidding a man to drink, and something else forbidding
him, which is other and stronger than the principle which bids him?
I should say so.
And the forbidding principle is derived from reason, and that which bids and attracts proceeds from
passion and disease?
Clearly.
Then we may fairly assume that they are two, and that they differ from one another; the one with
which a man reasons, we may call the rational principle of the soul, the other, with which he loves and
hungers and thirsts and feels the flutterings of any other desire, may be termed the irrational or
appetitive, the ally of sundry pleasures and satisfactions?
Yes, he said, we may fairly assume them to be different.
Then let us finally determine that there are two principles existing in the soul. And what of passion,
or spirit? Is it a third, or akin to one of the preceding?
I should be inclined to say—akin to desire.
Well, I said, there is a story which I remember to have heard, and in which I put faith. The story is,
that Leontius, the son of Aglaion, coming up one day from the Piraeus, under the north wall on the
outside, observed some dead bodies lying on the ground at the place of execution. He felt a desire to see
them, and also a dread and abhorrence of them; for a time he struggled and covered his eyes, but at
length the desire got the better of him; and forcing them open, he ran up to the dead bodies, saying,
‘Look, ye wretches, take your fill of the fair sight.’
I have heard the story myself, he said.
The moral of the tale is, that anger at times goes to war with desire, as though they were two distinct
things.
Yes; that is the meaning, he said.
Suppose that a man thinks he has done a wrong to another, the nobler he is the less able is he to feel
indignant at any suffering, such as hunger, or cold, or any other pain which the injured person may
inflict upon him—these he deems to be just, and, as I say, his anger refuses to be excited by them. But
when he thinks that he is the sufferer of the wrong, then he boils and chafes, and is on the side of what
he believes to be justice; and because he suffers hunger or cold or other pain he is only the more
determined to persevere and conquer. His noble spirit will not be quelled until he either slays or is slain;
or until he hears the voice of the shepherd, that is, reason, bidding his dog bark no more.
The illustration is perfect, he replied; and in our state, as we were saying, the auxiliaries were to be
dogs, and to hear the voice of the rulers, who are their shepherds.
I perceive, I said, that you quite understand me; there is, however, a further point which I wish you
to consider.
What point?
You remember that passion or spirit appeared at first sight to be a kind of desire, but now we should
say quite the contrary; for in the conflict of the soul spirit is arrayed on the side of the rational principle.
Most assuredly.
But a further question arises: Is passion different from reason also, or only a kind of reason; in which
latter case, instead of three principles in the soul, there will only be two, the rational and the
concupiscent; or rather, as the state was composed of three classes, traders, auxiliaries, counsellors, so
may there not be in the individual soul a third element which is passion or spirit, and when not corrupted
by bad education is the natural auxiliary of reason?
Yes, he said, there must be a third.
Yes, I replied, if passion, which has already been shown to be different from desire, turns out also to
be different from reason.
But that is easily proved: we may observe even in young children that they are full of spirit almost as
soon as they are born, whereas some of them never seem to attain to the use of reason, and most of them
late enough.
Excellent, I said, and you may see passion equally in brute animals, which is a further proof of the
truth of what you are saying. And we may once more appeal to the words of Homer, which have been
already quoted by us,
‘He smote his breast, and thus rebuked his soul,’
For in this verse Homer has clearly supposed the power which reasons about the better and worse to
be different from the unreasoning anger which is rebuked by it.
Very true, he said.
And so, after much tossing, we have reached land, and are fairly agreed that the same principles
which exist in the state exist also in the individual, and that they are three in number. Must we not then
infer that the individual is wise in the same way, and in virtue of the same quality that makes the state
wise?
Certainly.
Also that the same quality which constitutes courage in the state constitutes courage in the
individual, and that both the state and the individual bear the same relation to all the other excellences?
And the individual will be acknowledged by us to be just in the same way in which the state is just?
That follows, of course.
We cannot but remember that the justice of the state consisted in each of the three classes doing the
work of its own class? We must recollect that the individual in whom the several qualities of his nature
do their own work will be just, and will do his own work.
Yes, he said, we must remember that too.
And ought not the rational principle, which is wise, and has the care of the whole soul, to rule, and
the passionate or spirited principle to be the subject and ally?
Certainly.
And, as we were saying, the united influence of music and gymnastic will bring them into accord,
nerving and sustaining the reason with noble words and lessons, and moderating and soothing and
civilizing the wildness of passion by harmony and rhythm?
Quite true, he said.
And these two, thus nurtured and educated, and having learned truly to know their own functions,
will rule over the concupiscent, which in each of us is the largest part of the soul and by nature most
insatiable of gain; over this they will keep guard, lest, waxing great and strong with the fullness of
bodily pleasures, as they are termed, the concupiscent soul, no longer confined to her own sphere,
should attempt to enslave and rule those who are not her natural-born subjects, and overturn the whole
life of man?
Very true, he said.
Both together will they not be the best defenders of the whole soul and the whole body against
attacks from without; the one counselling, and the other fighting under his leader, and courageously
executing his commands and counsels?
True.
And he is to be deemed courageous whose spirit retains in pleasure and in pain the commands of
reason about what he ought or ought not to fear?
Right, he replied.
And him we call wise who has in him that little part which rules, and which proclaims these
commands; that part too being supposed to have a knowledge of what is for the interest of each of the
three parts and of the whole? 1
Assuredly.
1 In another book, Plato describes this as a charioteer with two horses. Reason, the charioteer,
commands the horses, but the best horses work together and are spirited. This makes sense: it’s not just
that the rulers, soldiers, and peasants all do their parts: they must all do their parts well, and work
together.
But in reality justice was such as we were describing, being concerned however, not with the
outward man, but with the inward, which is the true self and concernment of man: for the just man does
not permit the several elements within him to interfere with one another, or any of them to do the work
of others,—he sets in order his own inner life, and is his own master and his own law, and at peace with
himself; and when he has bound together the three principles within him, which may be compared to the
higher, lower, and middle notes of the scale, and the intermediate intervals—when he has bound all
these together, and is no longer many, but has become one entirely temperate and perfectly adjusted
nature, then he proceeds to act, if he has to act, whether in a matter of property, or in the treatment of the
body, or in some affair of politics or private business; always thinking and calling that which preserves
and co-operates with this harmonious condition, just and good action, and the knowledge which presides
over it, wisdom, and that which at any time impairs this condition, he will call unjust action, and the
opinion which presides over it ignorance.
BOOK V
I was proceeding to tell the order in which the four evil forms appeared to me to succeed one
another, when Polemarchus, who was sitting a little way off, just beyond Adeimantus, began to whisper
to him: stretching forth his hand, he took hold of the upper part of his coat by the shoulder, and drew
him towards him, leaning forward himself so as to be quite close and saying something in his ear, of
which I only caught the words, ‘shall we let him off, or what shall we do?’
Certainly not, said Adeimantus, raising his voice.
Why, he said, we think that you are lazy, and mean to cheat us out of a whole chapter which is a
very important part of the story; and you fancy that we shall not notice your airy way of proceeding; as
if it were self-evident to everybody, that in the matter of women and children ‘friends have all things in
common.’
Well, I replied, I suppose that I must retrace my steps and say what I perhaps ought to have said
before in the proper place. The part of the men has been played out, and now properly enough comes the
turn of the women. Of them I will proceed to speak, and the more readily since I am invited by you.
What I mean may be put into the form of a question, I said: Are dogs divided into hes and shes, or
do they both share equally in hunting and in keeping watch and in the other duties of dogs? or do we
entrust to the males the entire and exclusive care of the flocks, while we leave the females at home,
under the idea that the bearing and suckling their puppies is labour enough for them?
No, he said, they share alike; the only difference between them is that the males are stronger and the
females weaker.
And can you mention any pursuit of mankind in which the male sex has not all these gifts and
qualities in a higher degree than the female? Need I waste time in speaking of the art of weaving, and
the management of pancakes and preserves, in which womankind does really appear to be great, and in
which for her to be beaten by a man is of all things the most absurd?
You are quite right, he replied, in maintaining the general inferiority of the female sex: although
many women are in many things superior to many men, yet on the whole what you say is true.1
And if so, my friend, I said, there is no special faculty of administration in a state which a woman
has because she is a woman, or which a man has by virtue of his sex, but the gifts of nature are alike
diffused in both; all the pursuits of men are the pursuits of women also.
Very true.
You will not think much of this when you see the next.
Go on; let me see.
The law, I said, which is the sequel of this and of all that has preceded, is to the following effect,
‘that the wives of our guardians are to be common, and their children are to be common, and no parent is
to know his own child, nor any child his parent.’
You will please to give a defense.
Let me feast my mind with a dream. You, I said, who are their legislator, having selected the men,
will now select the women and give them to them; they must be as far as possible of like natures with
them; and they must live in common houses and meet at common meals. None of them will have
anything specially his or her own; they will be together, and will be brought up together, and will
associate at gymnastic exercises. And so they will be drawn by a necessity of their natures to have
intercourse with each other—necessity is not too strong a word, I think?
And how can marriages be made most beneficial? That is a question which I put to you, because I
see in your house dogs for hunting, and of the nobler sort of birds not a few. Now, I beseech you, do tell
me, have you ever attended to their pairing and breeding? And do you breed from them all indifferently,
or do you take care to breed from the best only?2
From the best.
Our rulers will find a considerable dose of falsehood and deceit necessary for the good of their
subjects: we were saying that the use of all these things regarded as medicines might be of advantage.
How so?
Why, I said, the best of either sex should be united with the best as often, and the inferior with the
inferior, as seldom as possible. Now these goings on must be a secret which the rulers only know, or
there will be a further danger of our herd, as the guardians may be termed, breaking out into rebellion.
Very true.
Had we not better appoint certain festivals at which we will bring together the brides and
bridegrooms, and sacrifices will be offered and suitable hymeneal songs composed by our poets: We
shall have to invent some ingenious kind of lots which the less worthy may draw on each occasion of
1 This, amazingly, is enough to make Plato the first feminist. “Sure women are generally inferior, but
the best women are better than the worst men”.
2 Plato is talking about eugenics here: breeding people for the ‘best’ qualities.
our bringing them together, and then they will accuse their own ill-luck and not the rulers.
To be sure, he said.
And I think that our braver and better youth, besides their other honours and rewards, might have
greater facilities of intercourse with women given them; their bravery will be a reason, and such fathers
ought to have as many sons as possible.1
Yes.
The proper officers will take the offspring of the good parents to the pen or fold, and there they will
deposit them with certain nurses who dwell in a separate quarter; but the offspring of the inferior, or of
the better when they chance to be deformed, will be put away in some mysterious, unknown place, as
they should be.2
Yes, he said, that must be done if the breed of the guardians is to be kept pure. But how will they
know who are fathers and daughters, and so on?
They will never know. The way will be this: dating from the day of the hymeneal, the bridegroom
who was then married will call all the male children who are born between the seventh and tenth month
afterwards his sons, and the female children his daughters, and they will call him father, and he will call
their children his grandchildren, and they will call the elder generation grandfathers and grandmothers.
All who were begotten at the time when their fathers and mothers came together will be called their
brothers and sisters, and these, as I was saying, will be forbidden to intermarry.
Both the community of property and the community of families, as I am saying, tend to make them
more truly guardians; they will not tear the city in pieces by differing about ‘mine’ and ‘not mine;’ each
man dragging any acquisition which he has made into a separate house of his own, where he has a
separate wife and children and private pleasures and pains; but all will be affected as far as may be by
the same pleasures and pains because they are all of one opinion about what is near and dear to them,
and therefore they all tend towards a common end.
Now then, I said, I go to meet that which I liken to the greatest of the waves; yet shall the word be
spoken, even though the wave break and drown me in laughter and dishonour; and do you mark my
words.
Proceed.
I said: ‘Until philosophers are kings, or the kings and princes of this world have the spirit and power
of philosophy, and political greatness and wisdom meet in one, and those commoner natures who pursue
either to the exclusion of the other are compelled to stand aside, cities will never have rest from their
evils.’
He said: Who then are the true philosophers?
Those, I said, who are lovers of the vision of truth.
1 Plato thinks of everything. Anyone else would have said “let’s have key parties so that the
guardians won’t know whose kids is whose”. Plato says “and let’s rig the keys!”.
2 He thinks we should kill weak children.
That is also good, he said; but I should like to know what you mean.
Then those who see the many beautiful, and who yet neither see absolute beauty, nor can follow any
guide who points the way thither; who see the many just, and not absolute justice, and the like—such
persons may be said to have opinion but not knowledge. But those who see the absolute and eternal and
immutable may be said to know, and not to have opinion only? But those who love the truth in each
thing are to be called lovers of wisdom and not lovers of opinion.
Assuredly.
BOOK VI
Whichever of the two classes are best able to guard the laws and institutions of our state—let them
be our guardians. In the first place, as we began by observing, the nature of the philosopher has to be
ascertained. We must come to an understanding about him, and, when we have done so, then, if I am not
mistaken, we shall also acknowledge that such a union of qualities is possible, and that those in whom
they are united, and those only, should be rulers in the state.
What do you mean?
Let us suppose that philosophical minds always love knowledge of a sort which shows them the
eternal nature not varying from generation and corruption.
And if they are to be what we were describing, is there not another quality which they should also
possess?
What quality?
Truthfulness: they will never intentionally receive into their mind falsehood, which is their
detestation, and they will love the truth. Such a one is sure to be temperate and the reverse of covetous;
for the motives which make another man desirous of having and spending, have no place in his
character.
Just so.
Now, that which imparts truth to the known and the power of knowing to the knower is what I would
have you term the idea of good, and this you will deem to be the cause of science, and of truth in so far
as the latter becomes the subject of knowledge; beautiful too, as are both truth and knowledge, you will
be right in esteeming this other nature as more beautiful than either; and, as in the previous instance,
light and sight may be truly said to be like the sun, and yet not to be the sun, so in this other sphere,
science and truth may be deemed to be like the good, but not the good; the good has a place of honour
yet higher.
What a wonder of beauty that must be, he said, which is the author of science and truth, and yet
surpasses them in beauty; for you surely cannot mean to say that pleasure is the good?
God forbid, I replied; but may I ask you to consider the image in another point of view?
In what point of view?
You have to imagine, then, that there are two ruling powers, and that one of them is set over the
intellectual world, the other over the visible. Now take a line which has been cut into two unequal parts,
and divide each of them again in the same proportion, and suppose the two main divisions to answer,
one to the visible and the other to the intelligible, and then compare the subdivisions in respect of their
clearness and want of clearness, and you will find that the first section in the sphere of the visible
consists of images. And by images I mean, in the first place, shadows, and in the second place,
reflections in water and in solid, smooth and polished bodies and the like: Do you understand?1
Yes, I understand.
Imagine, now, the other section, of which this is only the resemblance, to include the animals which
we see, and everything that grows or is made.
Very good.
Would you not admit that both the sections of this division have different degrees of truth, and that
the copy is to the original as the sphere of opinion is to the sphere of knowledge?
Most undoubtedly.
Next proceed to consider the manner in which the sphere of the intellectual is to be divided.
In what manner?
Thus: There are two subdivisions, in the lower of which the soul uses the figures given by the former
division as images; the enquiry can only be hypothetical, and instead of going upwards to a principle
descends to the other end; in the higher of the two, the soul passes out of hypotheses, and goes up to a
principle which is above hypotheses, making no use of images as in the former case, but proceeding
only in and through the ideas themselves.
I do not quite understand your meaning, he said.
Then I will try again; you will understand me better when I have made some preliminary remarks.
You are aware that students of geometry, arithmetic, and the kindred sciences assume the odd and the
even and the figures and three kinds of angles and the like in their several branches of science; these are
their hypotheses, which they and everybody are supposed to know, and therefore they do not deign to
give any account of them either to themselves or others; but they begin with them, and go on until they
arrive at last, and in a consistent manner, at their conclusion?
Yes, he said, I know.
And do you not know also that although they make use of the visible forms and reason about them,
they are thinking not of these, but of the ideals which they resemble; not of the figures which they draw,
but of the absolute square and the absolute diameter, and so on—the forms which they draw or make,
and which have shadows and reflections in water of their own, are converted by them into images, but
they are really seeking to behold the things themselves, which can only be seen with the eye of the
1 This is complicated, but, roughly, here’s how it goes: What do you really know for sure? If you
look at a picture of a unicorn, say, not much. What if you study a horse? More, certainly. Better, though,
would be to study horsiness, or horses in general. Then you’d know a lot of things for certain. Best of all
would be to study math. Math is totally permanent, certain and true. These top two levels are ‘The
Forms’—the objects of true knowledge. The bottom two levels are the physical world.
mind?1
That is true.
And of this kind I spoke as the intelligible, although in the search after it the soul is compelled to use
hypotheses; not ascending to a first principle, because she is unable to rise above the region of
hypothesis, but employing the objects of which the shadows below are resemblances in their turn as
images, they having in relation to the shadows and reflections of them a greater distinctness, and
therefore a higher value.
I understand, he said, that you are speaking of the province of geometry and the sister arts.
And when I speak of the other division of the intelligible, you will understand me to speak of that
other sort of knowledge which reason herself attains by the power of dialectic, using the hypotheses not
as first principles, but only as hypotheses—that is to say, as steps and points of departure into a world
which is above hypotheses, in order that she may soar beyond them to the first principle of the whole;
and clinging to this and then to that which depends on this, by successive steps she descends again
without the aid of any sensible object, from ideas, through ideas, and in ideas she ends.
I understand you, he replied; not perfectly, for you seem to me to be describing a task which is really
tremendous; but, at any rate, I understand you to say that knowledge and being, which the science of
dialectic contemplates, are clearer than the notions of the arts, as they are termed, which proceed from
hypotheses only: these are also contemplated by the understanding, and not by the senses: yet, because
they start from hypotheses and do not ascend to a principle, those who contemplate them appear to you
not to exercise the higher reason upon them, although when a first principle is added to them they are
cognizable by the higher reason. And the habit which is concerned with geometry and the cognate
sciences I suppose that you would term understanding and not reason, as being intermediate between
opinion and reason.
You have quite conceived my meaning, I said; and now, corresponding to these four divisions, let
there be four faculties in the soul—reason answering to the highest, understanding to the second, faith
(or conviction) to the third, and perception of shadows to the last—and let there be a scale of them, and
let us suppose that the several faculties have clearness in the same degree that their objects have truth.
I understand, he replied, and give my assent, and accept your arrangement.
BOOK VII
And now, I said, let me show in a figure how far our nature is enlightened or unenlightened: Behold!
human beings living in an underground den, which has a mouth open towards the light and reaching all
along the den; here they have been from their childhood, and have their legs and necks chained so that
they cannot move, and can only see before them, being prevented by the chains from turning round their
heads. Above and behind them a fire is blazing at a distance, and between the fire and the prisoners there
is a raised way; and you will see, if you look, a low wall built along the way, like the screen which
1 You can see here that Plato is trying to get at the idea of the a priori—2000 years before it was
tackled by Kant and Descartes.
marionette players have in front of them, over which they show the puppets.1
I see.
And do you see, I said, men passing along the wall carrying all sorts of vessels, and statues and
figures of animals made of wood and stone and various materials, which appear over the wall? Some of
them are talking, others silent.
You have shown me a strange image, and they are strange prisoners.
Like ourselves, I replied; and they see only their own shadows, or the shadows of one another, which
the fire throws on the opposite wall of the cave?
True, he said; how could they see anything but the shadows if they were never allowed to move their
heads?
And of the objects which are being carried in like manner they would only see the shadows?
Yes, he said.
And if they were able to converse with one another, would they not suppose that they were naming
what was actually before them?
Very true.
And suppose further that the prison had an echo which came from the other side, would they not be
sure to fancy when one of the passers-by spoke that the voice which they heard came from the passing
shadow?
No question, he replied.
To them, I said, the truth would be literally nothing but the shadows of the images.
That is certain.
And now look again, and see what will naturally follow if the prisoners are released and disabused
of their error. At first, when any of them is liberated and compelled suddenly to stand up and turn his
neck round and walk and look towards the light, he will suffer sharp pains; the glare will distress him,
and he will be unable to see the realities of which in his former state he had seen the shadows; and then
conceive someone saying to him, that what he saw before was an illusion, but that now, when he is
approaching nearer to being and his eye is turned towards more real existence, he has a clearer vision,—
what will be his reply? And you may further imagine that his instructor is pointing to the objects as they
pass and requiring him to name them—will he not be perplexed? Will he not fancy that the shadows
which he formerly saw are truer than the objects which are now shown to him?
Far truer.
And if he is compelled to look straight at the light, will he not have a pain in his eyes which will
make him turn away to take refuge in the objects of vision which he can see, and which he will conceive
to be in reality clearer than the things which are now being shown to him?
‘Better to be the poor servant of a poor master,’ and to endure anything, rather
than think as they do and live after their manner?
Yes, he said, I think that he would rather suffer anything than entertain these false notions and live in
this miserable manner.
Imagine once more, I said, such a one coming suddenly out of the sun to be replaced in his old
situation; would he not be certain to have his eyes full of darkness?
To be sure, he said.
And if there were a contest, and he had to compete in measuring the shadows with the prisoners who
had never moved out of the den, while his sight was still weak, and before his eyes had become steady
(and the time which would be needed to acquire this new habit of sight might be very considerable),
would he not be ridiculous? Men would say of him that up he went and down he came without his eyes;
and that it was better not even to think of ascending; and if any one tried to loose another and lead him
up to the light, let them only catch the offender, and they would put him to death.
No question, he said.
This entire allegory, I said, you may now append, dear Glaucon, to the previous argument; the
prison-house is the world of sight, the light of the fire is the sun, and you will not misapprehend me if
you interpret the journey upwards to be the ascent of the soul into the intellectual world according to my
poor belief, which, at your desire, I have expressed—whether rightly or wrongly God knows. But,
whether true or false, my opinion is that in the world of knowledge the idea of good appears last of all,
and is seen only with an effort; and, when seen, is also inferred to be the universal author of all things
beautiful and right, parent of light and of the lord of light in this visible world, and the immediate source
of reason and truth in the intellectual; and that this is the power upon which he who would act rationally
either in public or private life must have his eye fixed.
I agree, he said, as far as I am able to understand you.
Moreover, I said, you must not wonder that those who attain to this beatific vision are unwilling to
descend to human affairs; for their souls are ever hastening into the upper world where they desire to
dwell; which desire of theirs is very natural, if our allegory may be trusted.
Yes, very natural.
And is there anything surprising in one who passes from divine contemplations to the evil state of
man, misbehaving himself in a ridiculous manner; if, while his eyes are blinking and before he has
become accustomed to the surrounding darkness, he is compelled to fight in courts of law, or in other
places, about the images or the shadows of images of justice, and is endeavouring to meet the
conceptions of those who have never yet seen absolute justice?
Anything but surprising, he replied.
Anyone who has common sense will remember that the bewilderments of the eyes are of two kinds,
and arise from two causes, either from coming out of the light or from going into the light, which is true
of the mind’s eye, quite as much as of the bodily eye; and he who remembers this when he sees any one
whose vision is perplexed and weak, will not be too ready to laugh; he will first ask whether that soul of
man has come out of the brighter life, and is unable to see because unaccustomed to the dark, or having
turned from darkness to the day is dazzled by excess of light. And he will count the one happy in his
condition and state of being, and he will pity the other; or, if he have a mind to laugh at the soul which
comes from below into the light, there will be more reason in this than in the laugh which greets him
who returns from above out of the light into the den.
That, he said, is a very just distinction.
But then, if I am right, certain professors of education must be wrong when they say that they can
put a knowledge into the soul which was not there before, like sight into blind eyes.1
1 This is part of an ongoing argument in Plato’s work. Where does knowledge come from? He says
real knowledge is innate: you are born with. This isn’t as crazy as it sounds, if you remember that he
They undoubtedly say this, he replied.
Whereas, our argument shows that the power and capacity of learning exists in the soul already; and
that just as the eye was unable to turn from darkness to light without the whole body, so too the
instrument of knowledge can only by the movement of the whole soul be turned from the world of
becoming into that of being, and learn by degrees to endure the sight of being, and of the brightest and
best of being, or in other words, of the good.
Very true.
Then, I said, the business of us who are the founders of the state will be to compel the best minds to
attain that knowledge which we have already shown to be the greatest of all—they must continue to
ascend until they arrive at the good; but when they have ascended and seen enough we must not allow
them to do as they do now.
What do you mean?
I mean that they remain in the upper world: but this must not be allowed; they must be made to
descend again among the prisoners in the den, and partake of their labours and honours, whether they
are worth having or not.
But is not this unjust? he said; ought we to give them a worse life, when they might have a better?
You have again forgotten, my friend, I said, the intention of the legislator, who did not aim at
making any one class in the state happy above the rest; the happiness was to be in the whole state, and
he held the citizens together by persuasion and necessity, making them benefactors of the state, and
therefore benefactors of one another; to this end he created them, not to please themselves, but to be his
instruments in binding up the state.
True, he said, I had forgotten.
Observe, Glaucon, that there will be no injustice in compelling our philosophers to have a care and
providence of others; we shall explain to them that in other states, men of their class are not obliged to
share in the toils of politics: and this is reasonable, for they grow up at their own sweet will, and the
government would rather not have them. Being self-taught, they cannot be expected to show any
gratitude for a culture which they have never received. But we have brought you into the world to be
rulers of the hive, kings of yourselves and of the other citizens, and have educated you far better and
more perfectly than they have been educated, and you are better able to share in the double duty.
Wherefore each of you, when his turn comes, must go down to the general underground abode, and get
the habit of seeing in the dark. When you have acquired the habit, you will see ten thousand times better
than the inhabitants of the den, and you will know what the several images are, and what they represent,
because you have seen the beautiful and just and good in their truth. And thus our state, which is also
yours, will be a reality, and not a dream only, and will be administered in a spirit unlike that of other
says real knowledge is of things like geometry. I think it’s easy to make a case that your knowledge of
math is innate. You’ve never seen a perfect circle or line, but you can use those ideas just fine. Where
did you get them from? Not through observation.
states, in which men fight with one another about shadows only and are distracted in the struggle for
power, which in their eyes is a great good. Whereas the truth is that the state in which the rulers are most
reluctant to govern is always the best and most quietly governed, and the state in which they are most
eager, the worst.1
Quite true, he replied.
And will our pupils, when they hear this, refuse to take their turn at the toils of state, when they are
allowed to spend the greater part of their time with one another in the heavenly light?
Impossible, he answered; for they are just men, and the commands which we impose upon them are
just; there can be no doubt that every one of them will take office as a stern necessity, and not after the
fashion of our present rulers of state.
Yes, my friend, I said; and there lies the point. You must contrive for your future rulers another and
a better life than that of a ruler, and then you may have a well-ordered state; for only in the state which
offers this, will they rule who are truly rich, not in silver and gold, but in virtue and wisdom, which are
the true blessings of life. Whereas if they go to the administration of public affairs, poor and hungering
after their own private advantage, thinking that hence they are to snatch the chief good, order there can
never be; for they will be fighting about office, and the civil and domestic broils which thus arise will be
the ruin of the rulers themselves and of the whole state.
Most true, he replied.
And the only life which looks down upon the life of political ambition is that of true philosophy. Do
you know of any other?
Indeed, I do not, he said.
And those who govern ought not to be lovers of the task? For, if they are, there will be rival lovers,
and they will fight.
No question.
Who then are those whom we shall compel to be guardians? Surely they will be the men who are
wisest about affairs of state, and by whom the state is best administered, and who at the same time have
other honours and another and a better life than that of politics?
They are the men, and I will choose them, he replied.
Objects of sense are of two kinds; some of them do not invite thought because the sense is an
adequate judge of them; while in the case of other objects sense is so untrustworthy that further enquiry
is imperatively demanded.
I understand, he said, and agree with you.
And all arithmetic and calculation have to do with number?
Yes.
1 Isn’t this wise? People who want to be politicians are terrible politicians. Good politicians don’t
want the job.
And they appear to lead the mind towards truth?
Yes, in a very remarkable manner.
Then this is knowledge of the kind for which we are seeking, having a double use, military and
philosophical; for the man of war must learn the art of number or he will not know how to array his
troops, and the philosopher also, because he has to rise out of the sea of change and lay hold of true
being, and therefore he must be an arithmetician.
That is true.
And our guardian is both warrior and philosopher?
Certainly.
Then this is a kind of knowledge which legislation may fitly prescribe; and we must endeavour to
persuade those who are to be the principal men of our state to go and learn arithmetic, not as amateurs,
but they must carry on the study until they see the nature of numbers with the mind only; nor again, like
merchants or retail-traders, with a view to buying or selling, but for the sake of their military use, and of
the soul herself; and because this will be the easiest way for her to pass from becoming to truth and
being.
That is excellent, he said.
And so, Glaucon, I said, we have at last arrived at the hymn of dialectic. This is that strain which is
of the intellect only, but which the faculty of sight will nevertheless be found to imitate; for sight, as you
may remember, was imagined by us after a while to behold the real animals and stars, and last of all the
sun himself. And so with dialectic; when a person starts on the discovery of the absolute by the light of
reason only, and without any assistance of sense, and perseveres until by pure intelligence he arrives at
the perception of the absolute good, he at last finds himself at the end of the intellectual world, as in the
case of sight at the end of the visible.
Exactly, he said.
Then this is the progress which you call dialectic?
True.
But the release of the prisoners from chains, and their translation from the shadows to the images
and to the light, and the ascent from the underground den to the sun, while in his presence they are
vainly trying to look on animals and plants and the light of the sun, but are able to perceive even with
their weak eyes the images in the water (which are divine), and are the shadows of true existence (not
shadows of images cast by a light of fire, which compared with the sun is only an image)—this power of
elevating the highest principle in the soul to the contemplation of that which is best in existence, with
which we may compare the raising of that faculty which is the very light of the body to the sight of that
which is brightest in the material and visible world—this power is given, as I was saying, by all that
study and pursuit of the arts which has been described. But I must also remind you, that the power of
dialectic alone can reveal this, and only to one who is a disciple of the previous sciences.
Of that assertion you may be as confident as of the last.
And assuredly no one will argue that there is any other method of comprehending by any regular
process all true existence or of ascertaining what each thing is in its own nature; for the arts in general
are concerned with the desires or opinions of men, or are cultivated with a view to production and
construction, or for the preservation of such productions and constructions; and as to the mathematical
sciences which, as we were saying, have some apprehension of true being—geometry and the like—they
only dream about being, but never can they behold the waking reality so long as they leave the
hypotheses which they use unexamined, and are unable to give an account of them. For when a man
knows not his own first principle, and when the conclusion and intermediate steps are also constructed
out of he knows not what, how can he imagine that such a fabric of convention can ever become
science?
Impossible, he said.
Then dialectic, and dialectic alone, goes directly to the first principle and is the only science which
does away with hypotheses in order to make her ground secure; the eye of the soul, which is literally
buried in an outlandish slough, is by her gentle aid lifted upwards; and she uses as handmaids and
helpers in the work of conversion, the sciences which we have been discussing. Custom terms them
sciences, but they ought to have some other name, implying greater clearness than opinion and less
clearness than science: and this, in our previous sketch, was called understanding. But why should we
dispute about names when we have realities of such importance to consider?
Why indeed, he said, when any name will do which expresses the thought of the mind with
clearness?
At any rate, we are satisfied, as before, to have four divisions; two for intellect and two for opinion,
and to call the first division science, the second understanding, the third belief, and the fourth perception
of shadows, opinion being concerned with becoming, and intellect with being; and so to make a
proportion: As being is to becoming, so is pure intellect to opinion. And as intellect is to opinion, so is
science to belief, and understanding to the perception of shadows.
But let us defer the further correlation and subdivision of the subjects of opinion and of intellect, for
it will be a long enquiry, many times longer than this has been.
As far as I understand, he said, I agree.
The same practice may be followed, I said, in all these things—labours, lessons, dangers—and he
who is most at home in all of them ought to be enrolled in a select number.
At what age?
At the age when the necessary gymnastics are over: the period whether of two or three years which
passes in this sort of training is useless for any other purpose; for sleep and exercise are unpropitious to
learning; and the trial of who is first in gymnastic exercises is one of the most important tests to which
our youth are subjected.
Certainly, he replied.
After that time those who are selected from the class of twenty years old will be promoted to higher
honour, and the sciences which they learned without any order in their early education will now be
brought together, and they will be able to see the natural relationship of them to one another and to true
being.
These, I said, are the points which you must consider; and those who have most of this
comprehension, and who are most steadfast in their learning, and in their military and other appointed
duties, when they have arrived at the age of thirty have to be chosen by you out of the select class, and
elevated to higher honour; and you will have to prove them by the help of dialectic, in order to learn
which of them is able to give up the use of sight and the other senses, and in company with truth to
attain absolute being: And here, my friend, great caution is required.
Suppose, I said, the study of philosophy to take the place of gymnastics and to be continued
diligently and earnestly and exclusively for twice the number of years which were passed in bodily
exercise—will that be enough?
Would you say six or four years? he asked.
Say five years, I replied; at the end of the time they must be sent down again into the den and
compelled to hold any military or other office which young men are qualified to hold: in this way they
will get their experience of life, and there will be an opportunity of trying whether, when they are drawn
all manner of ways by temptation, they will stand firm or flinch.
And how long is this stage of their lives to last?
Fifteen years, I answered; and when they have reached fifty years of age, then let those who still
survive and have distinguished themselves in every action of their lives and in every branch of
knowledge come at last to their consummation: the time has now arrived at which they must raise the
eye of the soul to the universal light which lightens all things, and behold the absolute good; for that is
the pattern according to which they are to order the state and the lives of individuals, and the remainder
of their own lives also; making philosophy their chief pursuit, but, when their turn comes, toiling also at
politics and ruling for the public good, not as though they were performing some heroic action, but
simply as a matter of duty; and when they have brought up in each generation others like themselves and
left them in their place to be governors of the state, then they will depart to the Islands of the Blest and
dwell there; and the city will give them public memorials and sacrifices and honour them, if the Pythian
oracle consent, as demigods, but if not, as in any case blessed and divine.
You are a sculptor, Socrates, and have made statues of our governors faultless in beauty.
Yes, I said, Glaucon, and of our governesses too.
Plato: The Republic, decoded
BOOK 2
Glaucon: There is a fable I know. It is about Gyges. He was a good man, at least until he found a
ring when he was out taking care of his sheep. The ring made him invisible whenever he put it on. You
can guess what happened: he took advantage of his new power and became evil, marrying the queen,
killing the king, and all of that stuff. I think that this proves that vice is pleasant and that virtue is
unpleasant. Prove to us that virtue is better than vice. Prove to us that it is in our own interest to be just,
in other words.
Socrates: Since we’re not doing very well, let’s take the approach a short-sighted person takes. Let’s
make the letters we’re trying to read much larger. We should start with something big, examine its
details, then come back to this small thing. People are just and states are just. We should start looking at
justice in the state and come back to justice for the person.
Adeimantus: Sounds good.
But it would be hard to find a perfect state—I mean, look around! We should imagine a perfect state
instead. That might be hard, but don’t you think it would be worth it?
I certainly do!
It seems to me that people live in communities because they need to specialize. People are good at
different things, and when we trade, we all benefit.
That sounds right.
So in our imaginary state, we’ll need farmers and peasants, and artisans and businesspeople. We’ll
need people to weave clothing and raise cattle. We’ll need labourers and other people too. But on the
whole, things will be pretty simple.
I agree.
We will produce corn, and wine, and clothes, and shoes, and build houses. In the summer, our
people will be stripped and barefoot, but in the winter they will have good clothes and shoes. They will
eat plain food, and homemade bread and cakes. These they will serve up on a mat of reeds or on clean
leaves, themselves reclining upon simple beds. They will feast now and then, with their children, on the
food and wine they made, wearing garlands on their heads, and praising the gods. They will be happy,
and careful, keeping an eye on poverty and war.
Glaucon: But they live so plainly! That’s not exciting! People want wine, and furniture and
prostitutes.
Socrates: Well, I like my state. It seems like the natural one. But I guess we can consider yours, too,
Glaucon. In your state, if we’re going to be entertained, we’ll need actors, and tutors. We’ll have to have
poets and dancers and the like. That means that we will be envied by other countries, and that we will
need the resources of other countries, too. So, we will go to war.
Yes, that is true.
We will need specialized soldiers, then. I have to tell you, this makes me worried. Soldiers are
dangerous. We will want soldiers who are gentle with their friends and dangerous to their enemies. That
combination is hard to find.
It is.
Our soldiers will be like dogs: loyal and dangerous at the same time. A really good and noble
guardian of the State requires wisdom and spirit and swiftness and strength.
How will we raise these soldiers?
It so happens that I have a few thoughts on the matter. We cannot let them be taught in the usual
way—look what that leads to: nothing but strife. I think that we will need to educate our youth
differently. We will need to ensure that they never hear stories about gods quarreling. Stories of
quarreling among gods only set a bad example for our children.
BOOK 3
Socrates: We will need to make sure that the storytellers never mention that Hades is a terrible place.
Our soldiers must not fear death. We also need to forbid:
• Violent laughter
• Gifts of money
• Sentimental poetry
• Making funny noises
• Flutes
• Complicated rhythms and harmonies
• Sweet sauces
• Corinthian women
BOOK 4
Adeimantus: But Socrates, why should the guardians be poor? Everyone else in town is happy. They
are allowed to build large houses, party, and have private wealth. Aren’t the guardians suffering so that
the rest of the state can be happy?
Socrates: Yes, you’re right. Also, they can’t have mistresses or take vacations. There are other
things, too. Don’t forget the rest of the restrictions.
Adeimantus: Well?
Socrates: Well, we’ve made this state to make the whole state happy, not to favour one part. Suppose
that we were painting a statue, and some one came up to us and said, “Why do you not put the most
beautiful colours on the most beautiful parts of the body—the eyes ought to be purple, but you have
made them black.” We would probably say, “Sir, you don’t paint everything beautifully, part by part.
The whole thing has to be beautiful, and that requires balance.” It is the same thing with the republic.
Each person must do his job well and industriously, not meddling in the work of others. This will make
a noble, harmonious, and just state. If we let the potters drink and relax, they won’t make pots. If we let
the shepherds play flute all day, they won’t raise sheep. It is especially true of the guardians. They need
to work at their job; the security of the whole state is in their hands.
I think that you are quite right.
I wonder whether you will agree with another remark which occurs to me.
Tell me, what is it?
Truly, I said, we are stupid fellows.
Why so?
Well, we started off looking for justice. It fell right at our feet, and we just ignored it. We missed the
forest for the trees.
What do you mean?
I mean we have been talking of justice for a long time, but we have failed to recognize it.
Oh, come on, Socrates! Out with it.
Remember when we said that each person should do one thing well?
Yes, we said that one man should do one thing only.
We also said that justice was doing your own business, and not being a busybody.
Yes, we said so.
Then let’s finish what we started. Remember we said that if we looked for justice on the large scale,
that we might be able to see it on the small scale. We said that we would look for justice in the state to
see what it is in the individual. Let’s apply what we learned to the individual now.
Go on.
Well, the state is just when the three classes in it do their own business: when the rulers rule, the
soldiers soldier, and the peasants, er, peasant. And moreover, a state is best when the guardians have
good intelligence, the auxiliaries are brave, and the peasants are hard working.
True.
Well, it’s true of the individual, too! The soul has three parts, just like the state: Scythians are
passionate people. Athenians love knowledge. Egyptians love money. We all have some kind of desire:
let’s call this part of ourselves, ‘appetitive’.
Certainly.
But everyone also knows that the appetites can be excessive. We know from our intellects that
drinking too much or loving money too much is a bad thing. Reason dictates rules that we must try to
follow.
Clearly.
It seems, then, that we have two parts: the rational and the appetitive.
Yes, and they are clearly different.
Are there any other parts of the soul?
I don’t know. I don’t think so.
Well, there is a story I remember. Leontius saw some dead bodies lying on the ground where they
had been executed. He felt a desire to see them, yet also an abhorrence of them. He struggled and
covered his eyes for a while, but eventually, he ran up to the dead bodies and said “Look, you wretches,
take your fill of the fair sight.”
I have heard the story myself.
The moral of the tale is this: sometimes we hate our desires. We are angry with what we want.
Yes. That’s the meaning.
Also, sometimes, when someone suffers an injustice, he boils and chafes. He wants revenge. Either
he will get it, or his reason will quiet his anger.
Yes.
So, willpower is sometimes on the side of the intellect, and sometimes it is on the side of the
appetites. Some get their willpower under the control of their intellects, while some have their willpower
under control of their appetites. Some people’s willpower goes back and forth; that’s why they get angry
with themselves. The anger comes from their will.
Exactly.
So, the state and the person have the same three parts: intellect or reason, will or spirit, and appetite.
Excellence in one is the same as excellence in the other.
That follows, of course.
This is exactly as justice in the state was when each class did its own work.
Absolutely.
In summary, then, the rational principle, which is wise, should rule. The passionate or spirited
principle should be its ally. And these two, brought together by a good education in gymnastics and
music, should rule over the appetites. The appetites are the largest part of the soul and the most
insatiable.
That sounds perfect.
The best kind of person will have these three elements in friendly harmony. Reason leads. Spirit
executes instructions, and the desires follow. Justice is the same in the person and the state: the rulers
rule, the spirited parts are strong and effective, and the appetites follow orders. Each does its own role
well and all work in harmony.
Clearly.
BOOK 5
Adeimantus: What about women? You’ve spoken about men.
Socrates: They should do exactly the same thing as the men do. If they did, and if we didn’t keep
them separate from us, they wouldn’t be so attractive and mysterious. Here’s why. Men can do
everything a woman can do, right? We’re not as good at cooking and making jam, but we can do it.
You are quite right, women are generally inferior, but there are many women who are superior to
many men at many things.
Nature has given us all the same skills. Men tend to be better at almost everything, but the skills are
still there in women.
Very true.
Since men and women both have what it takes to be a guardian, we should let women try. If they are
better at it than some men, there is no reason to prefer the worse man to the better woman.
Very true.
Remember how I said that all the property of the guardians is to be shared?
Of course.
Well, I didn’t want to mention it, but here’s one more thing I wanted to say. The wives of our
guardians should be common, and their children should be common too. I don’t think parents should
know whose child is whose. No children should know who their parents are, either.
That’s a pretty bold thing to say.
I know, but we’re just daydreaming. Let me explain why I think this is a good idea. Men and women
are drawn together. We can’t stop that. We should try, though, to ensure that if men and women are
going to mate that they do so for the greatest good of the state. The best should be mated with the best as
much as possible, and the worst with the worst as little as possible.
Very true.
Nobody will like this, however, and I think we will again be forced to lie. We can have festivals to
bring people together. We will have a lottery, and set men and women up with each other. It will seem
random—but in secret, we will plan it all out so the best joins with the best.
Good idea.
When there are babies, we’ll take them away. The good ones we will keep. The bad ones will go to
some secret, unknown place, if you know what I mean. The good babies will be raised by everyone
together—that way every child will think every elder could be her father or mother, and every elder will
see each youngster as his child.
Yes, that must be done.
I’ve saved my biggest idea for last. Until philosophers are kings, or the kings and princes of this
world have the spirit and power of philosophy, and political greatness and wisdom meet in one, cities
will never be free from evil.
That’s a big one.
Philosophers are lovers of truth. Only philosophers know the absolute and eternal and immutable.
Everyone else sees only a portion of the absolute, eternal and immutable. They have mere opinion.
BOOK 6
Socrates: So it is clear, isn’t it Glaucon, that the state needs to be ruled by philosopher kings? Only
they are able to grasp the eternal and unchangeable.
Glaucon: There can be no question of that.
Philosophers love truth. They hate illiberality. They detest meanness. And they are magnificent of
mind and spectators to all existence.
Most true.
Philosophers will not be afraid of death nor will they love life. They will not be cowardly, boastful,
or covetous. They have harmonious souls and rule harmoniously. We should even be able to see these
characteristics in youth.
True.
The philosopher will have a well-proportioned and gracious mind that will love learning and seek
the truth of everything.
Yes, he will.
And isn’t it true that the brightest and best youngsters are likely to be flattered early in life? And
aren’t they likely to become lazy and vain, especially if their bodies are as beautiful as their minds?
Yes, certainly that is true.
True philosophers, then, are going to be very hard to find. The best and brightest will become lazy.
The space they leave behind will be taken over by Sophists. No state is free from this kind of problem
right now: the best are always ruined before they can reach their potential.
True enough.
That is why no state will be perfect until philosophers are compelled to rule, or until kings become
philosophers.
Quite right.
Let’s review, then. The philosopher kings have to be patriotic. They have to be tested. The
successful ones will come forth like gold is washed from rock. The golden will receive rewards in life
and after death. And now we say it clearly: the perfect guardian must be a philosopher.
Yes. Yes!
What does a philosopher study though?
Permanent things, I think we said. Isn’t that right, Socrates?
Yes, Glaucon. I’m going to try to explain something tricky. Try to keep up. Take a line and cut it
into two unequal parts. Take each of those parts, and cut them again, unequally. On the bottom, in the
smallest section, we have images, shadows, reflections, and stuff like that.
I understand.
Above that, we have animals and everything that is grown or made. Physical things.
Very good.
On the top two parts we have intellectual stuff.
Like what?
Well, the lower part is made up of the things we make hypotheses about. Above that, we have pure
ideas.
I do not quite understand your meaning, he said.
You know how when people do geometry, how they draw triangles and circles? They experiment
with ‘this circle’ or ‘that triangle’, but they are trying to draw conclusions about every circle and every
triangle.
I know about that.
Well, that’s what I’m referring to. We have images, physical things, sciency and geometric things
(like circles and triangles) and one level above that. This top level can only be reached by doing
philosophy. It is the realm of truth. It is above hypothesis. It is permanent and perfect. It is a kind of
intellectual heaven above the ideas of science and math.
Ok, I sort of get it. You are asking the big ideas, I think, when you get to this top level: what
knowledge and being are. You are contemplating questions like what truth and goodness are. I sort of
see it.
That’s right, Glaucon.
BOOK 7
Socrates: Imagine that there are prisoners in a cave. No, better: imagine that there is a prisoner in a
movie theatre. She has never been outside, and all she can see is the movie screen. She can’t move
around. It’s like virtual reality.
Glaucon: Sure. It’s strange, but I will try.
Imagine, too, that the movie projector is always on. It shows different movies all the time. It doesn’t
show credits, though.
Go on.
Well, our prisoner would think that the people on the screen were real. The movies would be reality
to her. And she would come to see the same person a few times. She might see Fight Club, Ocean’s
Thirteen and Mr. and Mrs. Smith. What do these movies have in common?
They are all bad?
Yes, especially Fight Club. But they all also have Brad Pitt in them. So our prisoner would see Brad
a bunch of times and probably even come to recognize him. She might call him “Rat Face”.
She might, I guess.
She would. She would even think that she knows Rat Face. She would think that she knows a lot
about him, after watching all those movies.
Right. What is your point?
She would know other people, too. She would know Julia Roberts and George Clooney. She would
think she knew what real people were like from watching the screen. In her mind, people would be huge,
and handsome, preternaturally witty, and well armed.
She certainly would think that.
So, our prisoner in the movie theatre would see two levels of ‘reality’, and think she knew them. She
would see Brad Pitt, and the characters that Brad Pitt plays. She would think herself quite clever, too,
knowing that the ‘real’ Brad Pitt is different from the characters. Those of us who are outside the theatre,
though, know that she is in error. The real Brad Pitt is flesh and blood, not on the screen. The real Pitt is
6 feet tall, not 30. Our prisoner thinks she knows reality, but doesn’t.
Quite right, Socrates.
Well, imagine, then, that we took her from the cinema and pulled her outside. After a lifetime inside,
the daylight would be blinding. She would want to go back. If we kept her there, after a while, her eyes
would adjust, and she would see that the real world is much different and much, much more real than the
world of the cinema.
Certainly.
And if we wanted to send her back down into the cinema, she wouldn’t want to go. She would hate
to go back down into the artificial world once she had seen the real world.
Sure.
Well, stay with me now, but I think that we are all like prisoners in the theatre.
What do you mean?
Well, we think we know what reality is, when in fact, we have been living in an artificial world.
Go on.
I’ve been trying to make an allegory. The cinema is the world of sight. We see things, and we think
that they are the real world. Crawling out of the cinema into the bright light of day is the soul’s
ascension into the intellectual world. This is the world of true knowledge.
Yes, I follow you.
Furthermore, the world of real knowledge, of certainty, and the world in the bright light is clear and
unmistakable. Once we have seen it, we cannot be fooled. It hurts to see it at first, but we adjust, and our
minds cannot be deceived a second time.
Yes. I see where you’re coming from.
Well, the way I see it, reality has one major division and two minor divisions. The major division is
between the physical world and the intellectual world. The minor divisions divide those two categories
up into four subcategories.
Tell me more.
It goes like this: there are the images of things, like a picture of a jug or a unicorn. These things are
not very real. Then there are the objects that seem permanent but are not. Those are objects, like this jug
or that horse. This is the stuff that most people believe to be real. Most people are mistaken, however.
Go on.
Then, in the intellectual universe, there are the real objects. I call these “The Forms”. These are the
really real things—things like horsiness or juginess. These are the essences. Once we have perceived
them, we know that they are the truth, and we can’t be mistaken about them. They are, more or less, the
objects of scientific knowledge.
Sure. Is that it? Are there three levels to reality? I thought you said there were four.
There is one more. This is the top level of The Forms. There are some capital-I Ideas we need to
understand the objects of science. We need to know some things like equality, unity, goodness, truth and
beauty. These must be a higher level of reality, because we can compare Forms like horsiness and
cowiness and see that they have something else in common. We can also compare Ideas like circularity
and triangularity and see that they have some things in common. These things must be the most real of
all.
If you say so, Socrates. But what does this have to do with our republic?
Well, Glaucon. The philosopher kings will have to keep their eyes on the top level of The Forms: the
Good, the Beautiful, and the Truth. This is what they should study if they are to lead the country.
However, just like the woman in the cinema, once they have seen real reality, we can expect that they
won’t be interested in stupid illusion. They won’t be interested in what the common people are worried
about. We will have to compel them to care.
Yes, I see. How will we do this?
Through a good education, of course. The philosopher kings will have to be educated in music and
gymnastics, as well as mathematics and geometry. Math and geometry make people wonder about the
big things. They also require the use of pure intelligence. Math and geometry study the eternal and the
perfect.
You are absolutely right.
But there is one more thing. Our philosopher kings will need to study dialectic and the art of
philosophy. Only philosophy goes straight to the top level of The Forms of things. Only philosophy is
concerned with the essence of a thing and the truth.
Wow, Socrates. This is good. Go over it one more time for me.
Sure. Reality is divided into four parts:
1. Ideas required for science
2. Ideas of science
3. Physical things
4. Images and representations
1 and 2 are the realm of The Forms. 3 and 4 are the realm of the physical world. The Forms are real,
even though most people think the physical world is. The physical world is impermanent, while The
Forms are permanent.
Great! That is so clear. But we have not really laid out a plan for our future philosopher kings.
Explain that to me one more time.
Well, here is how I see it. We take the first generation of children and send their parents away ‘into
the country’. Ahem. Then we educate the kids. For 20 years or so, we educate them in battle,
horsemanship, and gymnastics. The best ones go onto the second stage. For 10 years, we educate them
about the sciences. Again, we take only the best ones. For 5 years, we educate them about philosophy.
Then, when they are 35 years old, we send them out to work for a while. They can work in the military
or in politics. They do this until they are 50 or so. Finally, we take the best of the best, and teach them
about the highest level of The Forms. We tell them how to govern. By this time, they should be
concerned only with justice and fairness, and being the best rulers. They will not care about personal
success; they will only care about being good.
Wow. You are a sculptor, Socrates. You have made our governors and governesses faultless.
Plato: Phaedo, edited
Were you yourself, Phaedo, in the prison with Socrates on the day when he drank the poison?
Yes, Echecrates, I was.
I should so like to hear about his death. What did he say in his last hours?
I will begin at the beginning, and endeavour to repeat the entire conversation. On the previous days
we had been in the habit of assembling early in the morning at the court in which the trial took place,
and which is not far from the prison. There we used to wait talking with one another until the opening of
the doors (for they were not opened very early); then we went in and generally passed the day with
Socrates. On the last morning we assembled sooner than usual, having heard on the day before when we
quitted the prison in the evening that the sacred ship had come from Delos, and so we arranged to meet
very early at the accustomed place. On our arrival the jailer who answered the door, instead of admitting
us, came out and told us to stay until he called us. ‘For the Eleven,’ he said, ‘are now with Socrates; they
are taking off his chains, and giving orders that he is to die to-day.’ He soon returned and said that we
might come in. On entering we found Socrates just released from chains, and Xanthippe, whom you
know, sitting by him, and holding his child in her arms. When she saw us she uttered a cry and said, as
women will: ‘O Socrates, this is the last time that either you will converse with your friends, or they
with you.’ Socrates turned to Crito and said: ‘Crito, let some one take her home.’ Some of Crito’s people
accordingly led her away, crying out and beating herself. And when she was gone, Socrates, sitting up
on the couch, bent and rubbed his leg, saying, as he was rubbing: How singular is the thing called
pleasure, and how curiously related to pain, which might be thought to be the opposite of it; for they are
never present to a man at the same instant, and yet he who pursues either is generally compelled to take
the other; their bodies are two, but they are joined by a single head.
Upon this Cebes said: A question has been asked by many, and was asked of me only the day before
yesterday by Evenus the poet—he wanted to know why you, who never before wrote a line of poetry,
now that you are in prison are turning Aesop’s fables into verse, and also composing that hymn in
honour of Apollo.
Tell him, Cebes, he replied, what is the truth—that I had no idea of rivalling him or his poems; to do
so, as I knew, would be no easy task. But I wanted to see whether I could purge away a scruple which I
felt about the meaning of certain dreams. In the course of my life I have often had intimations in dreams
‘that I should compose music.’ I took some fables of Aesop, which I had ready at hand and which I
knew—they were the first I came upon—and turned them into verse. Tell this to Evenus, Cebes, and bid
him be of good cheer; say that I would have him come after me if he be a wise man, and not tarry; and
that to-day I am likely to be going, for the Athenians say that I must.
Simmias said: What a message for such a man! Having been a frequent companion of his I should
say that, as far as I know him, he will never take your advice unless he is obliged.
Why, said Socrates, is not Evenus a philosopher?
I think that he is, said Simmias.
Then he, or any man who has the spirit of philosophy, will be willing to die, but he will not take his
own life, for that is held to be unlawful.
Here he changed his position, and put his legs off the couch on to the ground, and during the rest of
the conversation he remained sitting.
Why do you say, enquired Cebes, that a man ought not to take his own life, but that the philosopher
will be ready to follow the dying?
I suppose that you wonder why, when other things which are evil may be good at certain times and
to certain persons, death is to be the only exception, and why, when a man is better dead, he is not
permitted to be his own benefactor, but must wait for the hand of another.
Very true, said Cebes, laughing gently and speaking in his native Boeotian.
I admit the appearance of inconsistency in what I am saying; but there may not be any real
inconsistency after all. There is a doctrine whispered in secret that man is a prisoner who has no right to
open the door and run away; this is a great mystery which I do not quite understand. Yet I too believe
that the gods are our guardians, and that we are a possession of theirs. Do you not agree?
Yes, I quite agree, said Cebes.
And if one of your own possessions, an ox or an ass, for example, took the liberty of putting himself
out of the way when you had given no intimation of your wish that he should die, would you not be
angry with him, and would you not punish him if you could?
Certainly, replied Cebes.
Then, if we look at the matter thus, there may be reason in saying that a man should wait, and not
take his own life until God summons him, as he is now summoning me.
Yes, Socrates, said Cebes, there seems to be truth in what you say. And yet how can you reconcile
this seemingly true belief that God is our guardian and we his possessions, with the willingness to die
which we were just now attributing to the philosopher?
The earnestness of Cebes seemed to please Socrates. Here, said he, turning to us, is a man who is
always inquiring, and is not so easily convinced by the first thing which he hears.
Yes, replied Socrates; there is reason in what you say. And so you think that I ought to answer your
indictment as if I were in a court?
We should like you to do so, said Simmias.
Then I must try to make a more successful defence before you than I did when before the judges. For
I am quite ready to admit, Simmias and Cebes, that I ought to be grieved at death, if I were not
persuaded in the first place that I am going to other gods who are wise and good (of which I am as
certain as I can be of any such matters), and secondly (though I am not so sure of this last) to men
departed, better than those whom I leave behind; and therefore I do not grieve as I might have done.
But do you mean to take away your thoughts with you, Socrates? said Simmias. Will you not impart
them to us?
I will do my best, replied Socrates. But you must first let me hear what Crito wants; he has long been
wishing to say something to me.
Only this, Socrates, replied Crito: the attendant who is to give you the poison has been telling me,
and he wants me to tell you, that you are not to talk much, talking, he says, increases heat, and this is apt
to interfere with the action of the poison; persons who excite themselves are sometimes obliged to take a
second or even a third dose.
Then, said Socrates, let him mind his business and be prepared to give the poison twice or even
thrice if necessary; that is all.
I knew quite well what you would say, replied Crito; but I was obliged to satisfy him.
And now, O my judges, I desire to prove to you that the real philosopher has reason to be of good
cheer when he is about to die, and that after death he may hope to obtain the greatest good in the other
world. And how this may be, Simmias and Cebes, I will endeavour to explain. For I deem that the true
votary of philosophy is likely to be misunderstood by other men; they do not perceive that he is always
pursuing death and dying.
Simmias said laughingly: Though not in a laughing humour, you have made me laugh, Socrates; for
I cannot help thinking that the many when they hear your words will say how truly you have described
philosophers.
And they are right, Simmias, in thinking so. But enough of them. Let us discuss the matter among
ourselves: Do we believe that there is such a thing as death?
To be sure, replied Simmias.
Is it not the separation of soul and body? And to be dead is the completion of this; when the soul
exists in herself, and is released from the body and the body is released from the soul, what is this but
death?
Just so, he replied.
There is another question, which will probably throw light on our present inquiry if you and I can
agree about it. Ought the philosopher to care about the pleasures—if they are to be called pleasures—of
eating and drinking?
Certainly not, answered Simmias.
And what about the pleasures of love—should he care for them?
By no means.
And will he think much of the other ways of indulging the body, for example, the acquisition of
costly raiment, or sandals, or other adornments of the body? Instead of caring about them, does he not
rather despise anything more than nature needs? What do you say?
I should say that the true philosopher would despise them.
Would you not say that he is entirely concerned with the soul and not with the body? He would like,
as far as he can, to get away from the body and to turn to the soul.
Quite true.
Whereas, Simmias, the rest of the world are of opinion that to him who has no sense of pleasure and
no part in bodily pleasure, life is not worth having; and that he who is indifferent about them is as good
as dead.
That is also true.
What again shall we say of the actual acquirement of knowledge? Is the body, if invited to share in
the enquiry, a hinderer or a helper? I mean to say, have sight and hearing any truth in them? Are they
not, as the poets are always telling us, inaccurate witnesses?
Certainly, he replied.
Then must not true existence be revealed to the soul in thought, if at all?
Yes.
And thought is best when the mind is gathered into herself and none of these things trouble her—
neither sounds nor sights nor pain nor any pleasure—when she takes leave of the body, and has as little
as possible to do with it, when she has no bodily sense or desire, but is aspiring after true being?
Certainly.
And in this the philosopher dishonours the body; his soul runs away from his body and desires to be
alone and by herself?
That is true.
Well, but there is another thing, Simmias: Is there or is there not an absolute justice?
Assuredly there is.
And an absolute beauty and absolute good?
Of course.
But did you ever behold any of them with your eyes?
Certainly not.
Or did you ever reach them with any other bodily sense? And I speak not of these alone, but of
absolute greatness, and health, and strength, and of the essence or true nature of everything. Has the
reality of them ever been perceived by you through the bodily organs? or rather, is not the nearest
approach to the knowledge of their several natures made by him who so orders his intellectual vision as
to have the most exact conception of the essence of each thing which he considers?
Certainly.
And he attains to the purest knowledge of them who goes to each with the mind alone, not
introducing or intruding in the act of thought sight or any other sense together with reason?
What you say has a wonderful truth in it, Socrates, replied Simmias.
And when real philosophers consider all these things, will they not express in words something like
the following? ‘Have we not found a path of thought which seems to bring us and our argument to the
conclusion, that while we are in the body, and while the soul is infected with the evils of the body, our
desire will not be satisfied? And our desire is of the truth. For the body is a source of endless trouble to
us and by reason of all these impediments we have no time to give to philosophy. The soul in herself
must behold things in themselves: and then we shall attain the wisdom which we desire.’
Undoubtedly, Socrates.
But, O my friend, if this is true, there is great reason to hope that, going whither I go, when I have
come to the end of my journey, I shall attain that which has been the pursuit of my life. And therefore I
go on my way rejoicing.
Certainly, replied Simmias.
And, as I was saying at first, there would be a ridiculous contradiction in men studying to live as
nearly as they can in a state of death, and yet repining when it comes upon them. Many a man has been
willing to go to the world below animated by the hope of seeing there an earthly love, or wife, or son,
and conversing with them. And will he who is a true lover of wisdom, and is strongly persuaded in like
manner that only in the world below he can worthily enjoy her, still repine at death? Will he not depart
with joy? Surely he will, O my friend, if he be a true philosopher.
He would, indeed, replied Simmias.
And when you see a man who is repining at the approach of death, is not his reluctance a sufficient
proof that he is not a lover of wisdom, but a lover of the body, and probably at the same time a lover of
either money or power, or both?
Quite so, he replied.
Well, he said, you are aware that death is regarded by men in general as a great evil.
Very true, he said.
And do not courageous men face death because they are afraid of yet greater evils?
That is quite true.
Then all but the philosophers are courageous only from fear, and because they are afraid; and yet
that a man should be courageous from fear, and because he is a coward, is surely a strange thing.
Very true.
And are not the temperate exactly in the same case? They are temperate because they are
intemperate—which might seem to be a contradiction, but is nevertheless the sort of thing which
happens with this foolish temperance. For there are pleasures which they are afraid of losing. And that is
what I mean by saying that, in a sense, they are made temperate through intemperance.
Such appears to be the case.
Yet the exchange of one fear or pleasure or pain for another fear or pleasure or pain, and of the
greater for the less, as if they were coins, is not the exchange of excellence. O my blessed Simmias, is
there not one true coin for which all things ought to be exchanged? And that is wisdom; and only in
exchange for this, and in company with this, is anything truly bought or sold, whether courage or
temperance or justice. And is not all true excellence the companion of wisdom, no matter what fears or
pleasures or other similar goods or evils may or may not attend her? But the excellence which is made
up of these goods, when they are severed from wisdom and exchanged with one another, is a shadow of
excellence only, nor is there any freedom or health or truth in her; but in the true exchange there is a
purging away of all these things, and temperance, and justice, and courage, and wisdom herself are the
purgation of them.
Cebes answered: I agree, Socrates, in the greater part of what you say. But in what concerns the soul,
men are apt to be incredulous; they fear that when she has left the body her place may be nowhere, and
that on the very day of death she may perish and come to an end—immediately on her release from the
body, issuing forth dispersed like smoke. But surely it requires a great deal of argument and many
proofs to show that when the man is dead his soul yet exists, and has any force or intelligence.
I reckon, said Socrates, that no one who heard me now, not even if he were one of my old enemies,
the Comic poets, could accuse me of idle talking about matters in which I have no concern. If you
please, then, we will proceed with the inquiry.
Suppose we consider the question whether the souls of men after death are or are not in the world
below. There comes into my mind an ancient doctrine which affirms that they go from hence into the
other world, and returning hither, are born again from the dead. Now if it be true that the living come
from the dead, then our souls must exist in the other world, for if not, how could they have been born
again? And this would be conclusive, if there were any real evidence that the living are only born from
the dead; but if this is not so, then other arguments will have to be adduced.
Very true, replied Cebes.
Then let us consider the whole question, not in relation to man only, but in relation to animals
generally, and to plants, and the proof will be easier. Are not all things which have opposites generated
out of their opposites? I mean such things as good and evil, just and unjust—I mean to say, for example,
that anything which becomes greater must become greater after being less.
Yes, he said.
Well, and is there not an opposite of life, as sleep is the opposite of waking?
Death, he answered.
Then the living, whether things or persons, Cebes, are generated from the dead?
That is clear, he replied.
Then the inference is that our souls exist in the world below?
That is true.
And that these admissions were not unfair, Cebes, he said, may be shown, I think, as follows: If
generation were in a straight line only, then you know that all things would at last have the same form
and pass into the same state, and there would be no more generation of them.
What do you mean? he said.
A simple thing enough, which I will illustrate by the case of sleep, he replied. You know that if there
were no alternation of sleeping and waking, the tale of the sleeping Endymion would in the end have no
meaning, because all other things would be asleep, too, and he would not be distinguishable from the
rest. And if all things which partook of life were to die, all would at last die, and nothing would be
alive—what other result could there be?
There is no escape, Socrates, said Cebes; and to me your argument seems to be absolutely true. Your
favorite doctrine, Socrates, that knowledge is simply recollection, if true, also necessarily implies a
previous time in which we have learned that which we now recollect. But this would be impossible
unless our soul had been in some place before existing in the form of man; here then is another proof of
the soul’s immortality.
But tell me, Cebes, said Simmias, interposing, what arguments are urged in favour of this doctrine of
recollection. I am not very sure at the moment that I remember them.
One excellent proof, said Cebes, is afforded by questions. If you put a question to a person in a right
way, he will give a true answer of himself, but how could he do this unless there were knowledge and
right reason already in him? And this is most clearly shown when he is taken to a diagram or to anything
of that sort.
But if, said Socrates, you are still incredulous, Simmias, I would ask you whether you may not agree
with me when you look at the matter in another way. We should agree, if I am not mistaken, that what a
man recollects he must have known at some previous time.
Very true.
And what is the nature of this knowledge or recollection? Recollection is most commonly a process
of recovering that which has been already forgotten through time and inattention.
And shall we proceed a step further, and affirm that there is such a thing as equality, not of one piece
of wood or stone with another, but that, over and above this, there is absolute equality? Shall we say so?
Say so, yes, replied Simmias, and swear to it, with all the confidence in life.
And do we know the nature of this absolute essence?
To be sure, he said.
And whence did we obtain our knowledge? Did we not see equalities of material things, such as
pieces of wood and stones, and gather from them the idea of an equality which is different from them?
For you will acknowledge that there is a difference. Or look at the matter in another way: Do not the
same pieces of wood or stone appear at one time equal, and at another time unequal?
That is certain.
But what would you say of equal portions of wood and stone, or other material equals? And what is
the impression produced by them? Are they equals in the same sense in which absolute equality is
equal? Or do they fall short of this perfect equality in a measure?
Yes, he said, in a very great measure too.
And must we not allow, that when I or any one, looking at any object, observes that the thing which
he sees aims at being some other thing, but falls short of, and cannot be, that other thing, but is inferior,
he who makes this observation must have had a previous knowledge of that to which the other, although
similar, was inferior?
Certainly.
Then we must have known absolute equality previously to the time when we first saw the material
equals, and reflected that all these apparent equals aim at this absolute equality, but fall short of it? From
the senses then is derived the knowledge that all sensible things aim at an absolute equality of which
they fall short?
Yes.
Then before we began to see or hear or perceive in any way, we must have had a knowledge of
absolute equality, or we could not have referred to that standard the equals which are derived from the
senses? For to that they all aspire, and of that they fall short.
No other inference can be drawn from the previous statements.
Whence, as I was saying, one of two alternatives follows: either we had this knowledge at birth, and
continued to know through life; or, after birth, those who are said to learn only remember, and learning
is simply recollection.
Yes, that is quite true, Socrates.
And which alternative, Simmias, do you prefer? Had we the knowledge at our birth, or did we
recollect the things which we knew previously to our birth?
I cannot decide at the moment.
At any rate you can decide whether he who has knowledge will or will not be able to render an
account of his knowledge? What do you say?
Certainly, he will.
But do you think that every man is able to give an account of these very matters about which we are
speaking?
Would that they could, Socrates, but I rather fear that to-morrow, at this time, there will no longer be
any one alive who is able to give an account of them such as ought to be given.
Then you are not of opinion, Simmias, that all men know these things? But when did our souls
acquire this knowledge? Not since we were born as men?
Certainly not.
And therefore, previously?
Yes.
Then, Simmias, our souls must also have existed without bodies before they were in the form of
man, and must have had intelligence.
Unless indeed you suppose, Socrates, that these notions are given us at the very moment of birth; for
this is the only time which remains.
Yes, my friend, but if so, when do we lose them? For they are not in us when we are born—that is
admitted. Do we lose them at the moment of receiving them, or if not at what other time?
No, Socrates, I perceive that I was unconsciously talking nonsense.
Then may we not say, Simmias, that if, as we are always repeating, there is an absolute beauty, and
goodness, and an absolute essence of all things; and if to this, which is now discovered to have existed
in our former state, we refer all our sensations, and with this compare them, finding these ideas to be
pre-existent and our inborn possession—then our souls must have had a prior existence, but if not, there
would be no force in the argument? There is the same proof that these ideas must have existed before we
were born, as that our souls existed before we were born; and if not the ideas, then not the souls.
Yes, Socrates; I am convinced that there is precisely the same necessity for the one as for the other.
Well, but is Cebes equally satisfied? For I must convince him too.
I think, said Simmias, that Cebes is satisfied: although he is the most incredulous of mortals, yet I
believe that he is sufficiently convinced of the existence of the soul before birth. But that after death the
soul will continue to exist is not yet proven even to my own satisfaction. I cannot get rid of the feeling of
the many to which Cebes was referring—the feeling that when the man dies the soul will be dispersed.
For admitting that she may have been born elsewhere, why after having entered in and gone out again
may she not herself be destroyed and come to an end?
Very true, Simmias, said Cebes; about half of what was required has been proven; the other half of
the proof is still wanting.
But that proof, Simmias and Cebes, has been already given, said Socrates, if you put the two
arguments together—I mean this and the former one, in which we admitted that everything living is born
of the dead. Still I suspect that you and Simmias would be glad to probe the argument further. Like
children, you are haunted with a fear that when the soul leaves the body, the wind may really blow her
away and scatter her.
Cebes answered with a smile: Then, Socrates, you must argue us out of our fears.
Socrates said: Let the voice of the charmer be applied daily until you have charmed away the fear.
And where shall we find a good charmer of our fears, Socrates, when you are gone?
Hellas, he replied, is a large place, Cebes, and has many good men, and there are barbarous races not
a few: seek for him among them all, far and wide, sparing neither pains nor money; for there is no better
way of spending your money. And you must seek among yourselves too; for you will not find others
better able to make the search.
The search, replied Cebes, shall certainly be made. And now, if you please, let us return to the point
of the argument at which we digressed.
Must we not, said Socrates, ask ourselves what is liable to be scattered, and about which we fear?
Very true, he said.
Now the compound or composite may be supposed to be naturally capable, as of being compounded,
so also of being dissolved; but that which is uncompounded, and that only, must be, if anything is,
indissoluble.
Yes; I should imagine so, said Cebes.
And the uncompounded may be assumed to be the same and unchanging, whereas the compound is
always changing and never the same.
I agree, he said.
Then now let us return to the previous discussion. Is that idea or essence, which in the dialectical
process we define as essence or true existence—whether essence of equality, beauty, or anything else—
are these essences, I say, liable at times to some degree of change? or are they each of them always what
they are, having the same simple self-existent and unchanging forms, not admitting of variation at all, or
in any way, or at any time?
They must be always the same, Socrates, replied Cebes.
And what would you say of the many beautiful—whether men or horses or garments or any other
things which are named by the same names and may be called equal or beautiful—are they all
unchanging and the same always, or quite the reverse?
The latter, replied Cebes; they are always in a state of change.
And were we not saying long ago that the soul, when using the body as an instrument of perception,
is then dragged by the body into the region of the changeable, and wanders and is confused; the world
spins round her, and she is like a drunkard, when she touches change?
Very true.
But when returning into herself she reflects, then she passes into the other world, the region of
purity, and eternity, and immortality, and unchangeableness, which are her kindred; then she ceases
from her erring ways, and being in communion with the unchanging is unchanging. And this state of the
soul is called wisdom?
That is well and truly said, Socrates, he replied.
And to which class is the soul more nearly alike and akin, as far as may be inferred from this
argument, as well as from the preceding one?
I think, Socrates, that, in the opinion of every one who follows the argument, the soul will be
infinitely more like the unchangeable—even the most stupid person will not deny that.
Then reflect, Cebes: of all which has been said is not this the conclusion? That the soul is in the very
likeness of the divine, and immortal, and intellectual, and uniform, and indissoluble, and unchangeable;
and that the body is in the very likeness of the human, and mortal, and unintellectual, and multiform, and
dissoluble, and changeable. Can this, my dear Cebes, be denied?
It cannot.
But if it be true, then is not the body liable to speedy dissolution? And is not the soul almost or
altogether indissoluble?
Certainly.
And do you further observe, that after a man is dead, the body is not dissolved or decomposed at
once, but may remain for a for some time, if the constitution be sound at the time of death, and the
season of the year favourable?
Yes.
And is it likely that the soul will be blown away and destroyed immediately on quitting the body, as
the many say? That can never be, my dear Simmias and Cebes. The truth rather is, that the soul which is
pure at departing, and which has been a true disciple of philosophy; and therefore has in fact been
always engaged in the practice of dying; that soul, I say, herself invisible, departs to the invisible
world—to the divine and immortal and rational: thither arriving, she is secure of bliss and is released
from the error and folly of men. Is not this true, Cebes?
Yes, said Cebes, beyond a doubt.
But the soul which has been polluted by the body and by the desires and pleasures of the body—do
you suppose that such a soul will depart pure and unalloyed?
Impossible, he replied.
She is held fast by the corporeal, which the continual association and constant care of the body have
wrought into her nature.
Very true.
What I mean is that men who have followed after gluttony, and wantonness, and drunkenness, and
have had no thought of avoiding them, would pass into asses and animals of that sort. What do you
think?
I think such an opinion to be exceedingly probable.
And those who have chosen the portion of injustice, and tyranny, and violence, will pass into
wolves, or into hawks and kites; whither else can we suppose them to go?
Yes, said Cebes; with such natures, beyond question.
No one who has not studied philosophy and who is not entirely pure at the time of his departure is
allowed to enter the company of the Gods, but the lover of knowledge only. And this is the reason,
Simmias and Cebes, why the true votaries of philosophy abstain from all fleshly lusts—because they
dread the dishonour or disgrace of evil deeds.
No, Socrates, that would not become them, said Cebes.
When Socrates had done speaking, for a considerable time there was silence; he himself appeared to
be meditating, as most of us were, on what had been said; only Cebes and Simmias spoke a few words to
one another. And Socrates observing them asked what they thought of the argument, and whether there
was anything wanting.
Simmias said: I must confess, Socrates, that doubts did arise in our minds, and each of us was urging
and inciting the other to put the question which we wanted to have answered.
Socrates replied with a smile: O Simmias, what are you saying? I am not very likely to persuade
other men that I do not regard my present situation as a misfortune, if I cannot even persuade you that I
am no worse off now than at any other time in my life. Will you not allow that I have as much of the
spirit of prophecy in me as the swans? For they, when they perceive that they must die, having sung all
their life long, do then sing more lustily than ever, rejoicing in the thought that they are about to go away
to the god whose ministers they are.
Very good, Socrates, said Simmias; then I will tell you my difficulty, and Cebes will tell you his. I
feel myself how impossible is the attainment of any certainty about questions such as these in the
present life. And yet I should deem him a coward who did not prove what is said about them to the
uttermost. And now, as you bid me, I will venture to question you, and then I shall not have to reproach
myself hereafter with not having said at the time what I think. For when I consider the matter, the
argument does certainly appear to me, Socrates, to be not sufficient.
Socrates answered: I dare say, my friend, that you may be right, but I should like to know in what
respect the argument is insufficient.
In this respect, replied Simmias: Suppose a person to use the same argument about harmony and the
lyre—might he not say that harmony is a thing perfect, divine, existing in the lyre which is harmonized,
but that the lyre and the strings are matter and composite, and akin to mortality? And when some one
breaks the lyre, or cuts the strings, then he would argue as you do, that the harmony survives and has not
perished—you cannot imagine, he would say, that the harmony, which is immortal has perished before
the mortal. The harmony must still be somewhere, and the wood and strings will decay before anything
can happen to that. Such is your conception of the soul; and that when the body is in a manner strung
and held together by the elements of hot and cold, wet and dry, then the soul is the harmony of them.
But if so, whenever the strings of the body are unduly loosened or overstrained through disease or other
injury, then the soul, though most divine, like other harmonies of music or of works of art, of course
perishes at once. And if any one maintains that the soul, being the harmony of the elements of the body,
is first to perish in that which is called death, how shall we answer him?
Socrates looked fixedly at us as his manner was, and said with a smile: Simmias has reason on his
side. There is force in his attack upon me. But perhaps, before we answer him, we had better also hear
what Cebes has to say.
Cebes said: I will tell you. My feeling is that the argument is open to the same objections which
were urged before; for I am ready to admit the existence of the soul before entering into the bodily form;
but the existence of the soul after death is still, in my judgment, unproven. Now I will ask you to
consider whether the objection, which, like Simmias, I will express in a figure, is of any weight. The
analogy is that of an old weaver, who dies, and after his death somebody says: He is not dead, he must
be alive; see, there is the coat which he himself wove and wore, and which remains whole and
undecayed. And then he proceeds to ask of some one who is incredulous, whether a man lasts longer, or
the coat which is in use and wear; and when he is answered that a man lasts far longer, thinks that he has
thus certainly demonstrated the survival of the man, who is the more lasting, because the less lasting
remains. But that is a mistake; any one can see that he who talks thus is talking nonsense. The weaver
aforesaid, having woven and worn many such coats, outlived several of them, and was outlived by the
last. For acknowledging not only that the soul existed before birth, but also that the souls of some exist,
and will continue to exist after death, and will be born and die again and again, and that there is a natural
strength in the soul which will hold out and be born many times—nevertheless, we may be still inclined
to think that she will weary in the labours of successive births, and may at last succumb in one of her
deaths.
All of us had an unpleasant feeling at hearing what they said. When we had been so firmly
convinced before, now to have our faith shaken seemed to introduce a confusion and uncertainty, not
only into the previous argument, but into any future one; either we were incapable of forming a
judgment, or there were no grounds of belief.
There I feel with you—by heaven I do, Phaedo, and when you were speaking, I was beginning to ask
myself the same question: What argument can I ever trust again? That the soul is a harmony is a doctrine
which has always had a wonderful attraction for me. Tell me, I implore you, how did Socrates proceed?
Often, Echecrates, I have wondered at Socrates, but never more than on that occasion. That he
should be able to answer was nothing, but what astonished me was, first, the gentle and pleasant and
approving manner in which he received the words.
What followed?
I was close to him on his right hand, seated on a sort of stool, and he on a couch which was a good
deal higher. He stroked my head, and pressed the hair upon my neck—he had a way of playing with my
hair; and then he said: To-morrow, Phaedo, I suppose that these fair locks of yours will be severed.
Yes, Socrates, I suppose that they will, I replied.
Not so, if you will take my advice.
What shall I do with them? I said.
To-day, he replied, and not to-morrow, if this argument dies and we cannot bring it to life again, you
and I will both shave our locks. Lest we become misologists, he replied, no worse thing can happen to a
man than this. For as there are misanthropists or haters of men, there are also misologists or haters of
ideas, and both spring from the same cause, which is ignorance of the world. Misanthropy arises out of
the too great confidence of inexperience; you trust a man and think him altogether true, and then he
turns out to be false. You must have observed this trait of character?
I have.
Is it not obvious that experience would have taught him that few are the good and few the evil, and
that the great majority are in the interval between them.
What do you mean? I said.
I mean, he replied that nothing is more uncommon than a very large or very small man; but many are
in the mean between them. Did you never observe this?
Yes, I said, I have.
And do you not imagine, he said, that if there were a competition in evil, the worst would be found
to be very few?
Yes, that is very likely, I said.
Arguments are unlike men—when a simple man who has no skill in dialectics believes an argument
to be true which he afterwards imagines to be false, and then another and another, he has no longer any
faith left, and great disputers come to think that they have grown to be the wisest of mankind; for they
alone perceive the utter unsoundness and instability of all arguments.
That is quite true, I said.
Yes, Phaedo, he replied, and how melancholy—that a man should have lighted upon some argument
or other which at first seemed true and then turned out to be false, and instead of blaming himself and
his own want of wit, should transfer the blame from himself to arguments in general.
Yes, indeed, I said; that is very melancholy.
Let us then, in the first place, he said, be careful of allowing or of admitting into our souls the notion
that there is no health or soundness in any arguments at all. Rather say that we have not yet attained to
soundness in ourselves, and that we must struggle manfully. Agree with me, if I seem to you to be
speaking the truth; or if not, withstand me might and main, that I may not deceive you as well as myself
in my enthusiasm, and like the bee, leave my sting in you before I die.
He proceeded: And did you deny the force of the whole preceding argument, or of a part only?
Of a part only, they replied.
But, rejoined Socrates, you will have to think differently, my Theban friend, if you still maintain that
harmony is a compound, and that the soul is a harmony which is made out of strings set in the frame of
the body; for you will surely never allow yourself to say that a harmony is prior to the elements which
compose it.
Never, Socrates.
But do you not see that this is what you imply when you say that the soul existed before she took the
form and body of man? And yet, he said, there surely ought to be harmony in a discourse of which
harmony is the theme.
There ought, replied Simmias.
But there is no harmony, he said, in the two propositions that knowledge is recollection, and that the
soul is a harmony. Which of them will you retain?
I think, he replied, that I have a much stronger faith, Socrates, in the first than in the latter, which has
not been demonstrated at all.
And does not the nature of every harmony depend upon the manner in which the elements are
harmonized?
I do not understand you, he said.
I mean to say that a harmony admits of degrees.
True.
But does the soul admit of degrees? Or is one soul in the very least degree more or less, or more or
less completely, a soul than another? Surely of two souls, one is said to have intelligence and excellence,
and to be good, and the other to have folly and vice, and to be an evil soul: and this is said truly?
Yes, truly.
But what will those who maintain the soul to be a harmony say of this presence of virtue and vice in
the soul? Will they say that here is another harmony, and another discord, and that the virtuous soul is
harmonized, and herself being a harmony has another harmony within her, and that the vicious soul is
inharmonical and has no harmony within her?
I cannot tell, replied Simmias; but I suppose that something of the sort would be asserted by those
who say that the soul is a harmony.
And we have already admitted that no soul is more a soul than another; which is equivalent to
admitting that harmony is not more or less harmony, or more or less completely a harmony? And having
neither more nor less of harmony or of discord, one soul has no more vice or virtue than another, if vice
be discord and virtue harmony?
Then, if all souls are equally by their nature souls, all souls of all living creatures will be equally
good?
I agree with you, Socrates, he said.
And can all this be true, think you? He said; for these are the consequences which seem to follow
from the assumption that the soul is a harmony?
It cannot be true.
Once more, he said, what ruler is there of the elements of human nature other than the soul, and
especially the wise soul? Do you know of any?
Indeed, I do not.
And is the soul in agreement with the affections of the body? Or is she at variance with them? For
example, when the body is hot and thirsty, does not the soul incline us against drinking? And when the
body is hungry, against eating? And this is only one instance out of ten thousand of the opposition of the
soul to the things of the body.
Very true.
But we have already acknowledged that the soul, being a harmony, can never utter a note at variance
with the tensions and relaxations and vibrations and other affections of the strings out of which she is
composed; she can only follow, she cannot lead them?
It must be so, he replied.
And yet do we not now discover the soul to be doing the exact opposite—leading the elements of
which she is believed to be composed; almost always opposing and coercing them in all sorts of ways
throughout life, sometimes more violently with the pains of medicine and gymnastic; then again more
gently; now threatening, now admonishing the desires, passions, fears, as if talking to a thing which is
not herself, as Homer in the Odyssey represents Odysseus doing in the words—
‘He beat his breast, and thus reproached his heart: Endure, my heart; far worse hast thou endured!’
Do you think that Homer wrote this under the idea that the soul is a harmony capable of being led by
the affections of the body, and not rather of a nature which should lead and master them—herself a far
diviner thing than any harmony?
Yes, Socrates, I quite think so.
Then, my friend, we can never be right in saying that the soul is a harmony, for we should contradict
the divine Homer, and contradict ourselves.
True, he said.
Here lies the point: You want to have it proven to you that the soul is imperishable and immortal,
and the philosopher who is confident in death appears to you to have but a vain and foolish confidence.
And whether the soul enters into the body once only or many times, does not, as you say, make any
difference in the fears of individuals. For any man, who is not devoid of sense, must fear, if he has no
knowledge and can give no account of the soul’s immortality. This, or something like this, I suspect to
be your notion, Cebes.
Said Cebes, as far as I see at present, I have nothing to add or subtract: I mean what you say that I
mean.
Socrates paused awhile, and seemed to be absorbed in reflection. At length he said: You are raising a
tremendous question, Cebes.
I should very much like, said Cebes, to hear what you have to say.
Then I will tell you, said Socrates. When I was young, Cebes, I had a prodigious desire to know that
department of philosophy which is called the investigation of nature; to know the causes of things, and
why a thing is and is created or destroyed appeared to me to be a lofty profession. There was a time
when I thought that I understood the meaning of greater and less pretty well; and when I saw a great
man standing by a little one, I fancied that one was taller than the other by a head; or one horse would
appear to be greater than another horse: and still more clearly did I seem to perceive that ten is two more
than eight, and that two cubits are more than one, because two is the double of one.
And what is now your notion of such matters? said Cebes.
I should be far enough from imagining, he replied, that I knew the cause of any of them; for I cannot
satisfy myself that, when one is added to one, the one to which the addition is made becomes two, or
that the two units added together make two by reason of the addition. I cannot understand how, when
separated from the other, each of them was one and not two, and now, when they are brought together,
the mere juxtaposition or meeting of them should be the cause of their becoming two. Nor am I any
longer satisfied that I understand the reason why one or anything else is either generated or destroyed or
is at all, but I have in my mind some confused notion of a new method.
Then I heard some one reading, as he said, from a book of Anaxagoras, that mind was the disposer
and cause of all, and I was delighted at this notion, which appeared quite admirable. And I rejoiced to
think that I had found in Anaxagoras a teacher of the causes of existence such as I desired. What
expectations I had formed, and how grievously was I disappointed! As I proceeded, I found my
philosopher altogether forsaking mind or any other principle of order, but having recourse to air, and
ether, and water, and other eccentricities. I might compare him to a person who began by maintaining
generally that mind is the cause of the actions of Socrates, but who, went on to show that I sit here
because my body is made up of bones and muscles; and the bones, as he would say, are hard and have
joints which divide them, and the muscles are elastic, and they cover the bones—that is what he would
say, and he would have a similar explanation of my talking to you, which he would attribute to sound,
and air, and hearing, and he would assign ten thousand other causes of the same sort, forgetting to
mention the true cause, which is, that the Athenians have thought fit to condemn me, and accordingly I
have thought it better and more right to remain here and undergo my sentence. But as I have failed either
to discover myself, or to learn of any one else, the nature of the best, I will exhibit to you, if you like,
what I have found to be the second best mode of enquiring into the cause.
I should very much like to hear, he replied.
Socrates proceeded: There is nothing new, he said, in what I am about to tell you; but only what I
have been always and everywhere repeating in the previous discussion and on other occasions. I shall
have to go back and first of all assume that there is an absolute beauty and goodness and greatness, and
the like; grant me this, and I hope to be able to show you the nature of the cause, and to prove the
immortality of the soul.
Cebes said: You may proceed at once with the proof, for I grant you this.
Well, he said, then I should like to know whether you agree with me in the next step; for I cannot
help thinking, if there be anything beautiful it can be beautiful only in as far as it partakes of absolute
beauty—and I should say the same of everything. Do you agree in this notion of the cause?
Yes, he said, I agree.
And that by greatness only great things become great and greater greater, and by smallness the less
become less?
Very true, he said.
Again, would you not be cautious of affirming that the addition of one to one, or the division of one,
is the cause of two? I will let alone puzzles of division and addition—wiser heads than mine may answer
them.
True.
And if Phaedo exceeds Simmias in size, this is not because Phaedo is Phaedo, but because Phaedo
has greatness relatively to Simmias, who is comparatively smaller?
That is true.
Yet once more let me ask you to consider the question from another point of view, and see whether
you agree with me: There is a thing which you term heat, and another thing which you term cold?
Certainly.
But are they the same as fire and snow?
Most assuredly not.
And in some cases the name of the idea is not only attached to the idea in an eternal connection. I
will try to make this clearer by an example: The odd number is always called by the name of odd?
Very true.
But is this the only thing which is called odd? Are there not other things which are called odd,
although not the same as oddness—that is what I mean to ask—whether numbers such as the number
three are not of the class of odd. Would you not say, for example, that three may be called by its proper
name, and also be called odd? Do you agree?
Of course.
Then now mark the point at which I am aiming: not only do essential opposites exclude one another,
but also concrete things. Will not the number three endure annihilation sooner than be converted into an
even number, while remaining three?
Very true, said Cebes.
Then not only do opposite ideas repel the advance of one another, but also there are other natures
which repel the approach of opposites. To return then to my distinction of natures which are not
opposed, and yet do not admit opposites, perhaps you may be able to arrive at the general conclusion,
that not only opposites will not receive opposites, but also that nothing which brings the opposite will
admit the opposite of that which it brings. You will agree?
Yes, he said, I entirely agree and go along with you in that.
Tell me, then, what is that of which the inherence will render the body alive?
The soul, he replied.
And is there any opposite to life?
Death.
Then the soul, as has been acknowledged, will never receive the opposite of what she brings.
Impossible, replied Cebes.
If the immortal is also imperishable, the soul when attacked by death cannot perish. And the same
may be said of the immortal: if the immortal is also imperishable, then the soul will be imperishable as
well as immortal; but if not, some other proof of her imperishableness will have to be given. Then when
death attacks a man, the mortal portion of him may be supposed to die, but the immortal retires at the
approach of death and is preserved safe and sound?
True.
Then, Cebes, beyond question, the soul is immortal and imperishable, and our souls will truly exist
in another world!
I am convinced, Socrates, said Cebes, and have nothing more to object.
But then, O my friends, he said, if the soul is really immortal, what care should be taken of her, not
only in respect of the portion of time which is called life, but of eternity! And the danger of neglecting
her from this point of view does indeed appear to be awful. If death had only been the end of all, the
wicked would have had a good bargain in dying, for they would have been happily quit not only of their
body, but of their own evil together with their souls. But now, inasmuch as the soul is manifestly
immortal, there is no release or salvation from evil except the attainment of the highest excellence and
wisdom. For the soul when on her progress to the world below takes nothing with her but nurture and
education; and these are said greatly to benefit or greatly to injure the departed, at the very beginning of
his journey thither. Every pure and just soul which has passed through life in the company and under the
guidance of the gods has also her own proper home.
Now the earth has divers wonderful regions, and is indeed in nature and extent very unlike the
notions of geographers, as I believe on the authority of one who shall be nameless.
What do you mean, Socrates? said Simmias.
Well, then, he said, my conviction is, that the earth is a round body in the centre of the heavens, and
therefore has no need of air or any similar force to be a support, but is kept there and hindered from
falling or inclining any way by the equability of the surrounding heaven and by her own equipoise.
Also I believe that the earth is very vast, and that we who dwell in the region extending from the
river Phasis to the Pillars of Heracles inhabit a small portion only about the sea, like ants or frogs about
a marsh, and that there are other inhabitants of many other like places; for everywhere on the face of the
earth there are hollows of various forms and sizes, into which the water and the mist and the lower air
collect. I can tell you a charming tale, Simmias, which is well worth hearing.
And we, Socrates, replied Simmias, shall be charmed to listen to you.
The tale, my friend, he said, is as follows: In the first place, the earth, when looked at from above, is
in appearance streaked like one of those balls which have leather coverings in twelve pieces, and is
decked with various colours, of which the colours used by painters on earth are in a manner samples.
But there the whole earth is made up of them, and they are brighter far and clearer than ours; there is a
purple of wonderful lustre, also the radiance of gold, and the white which is in the earth is whiter than
any chalk or snow. Of these and other colours the earth is made up, and they are more in number and
fairer than the eye of man has ever seen; the very hollows (of which I was speaking) filled with air and
water have a colour of their own, and are seen like light gleaming amid the diversity of the other
colours, so that the whole presents a single and continuous appearance of variety in unity. And in this
fair region everything that grows—trees, and flowers, and fruits—are in a like degree fairer than any
here; and there are hills, having stones in them in a like degree smoother, and more transparent, and
fairer in colour than our highly-valued emeralds and sardonyxes and jaspers
Such is the nature of the whole earth, and of the things which are around the earth; and there are
divers regions in the hollows on the face of the globe everywhere. The rivers flowing in either direction
can descend only to the centre and no further, for opposite to the rivers is a precipice.
Now these rivers are many, and mighty, and diverse, and there are four principal ones. The fourth
river goes out on the opposite side, and falls into a wild and savage region, which is all of a dark-blue
colour, like lapis lazuli; and this is that river which is called the Stygian river, and falls into and forms
the Lake Styx, and after falling into the lake and receiving strange powers in the waters, passes under the
earth.
Such is the nature of the other world; and when the dead arrive at the place to which the genius of
each severally guides them, first of all, they have sentence passed upon them, as they have lived well
and piously or not. Wherefore, Simmias, seeing all these things, what ought not we to do that we may
obtain excellence and wisdom in this life? Fair is the prize, and the hope great!
A man of sense ought not to say, nor will I be very confident, that the description which I have given
of the soul and her mansions is exactly true. But I do say that, inasmuch as the soul is shown to be
immortal, he may venture to think, not improperly or unworthily, that something of the kind is true.
Wherefore, I say, let a man be of good cheer about his soul. You, Simmias and Cebes, and all other men,
will depart at some time or other. Me already, as the tragic poet would say, the voice of fate calls. Soon I
must drink the poison; and I think that I had better repair to the bath first, in order that the women may
not have the trouble of washing my body after I am dead.
When he had done speaking, Crito said: And have you any commands for us, Socrates—anything to
say about your children, or any other matter in which we can serve you?
Nothing particular, Crito, he replied: only, as I have always told you, take care of yourselves.
We will do our best, said Crito: And in what way shall we bury you?
In any way that you like. Then he turned to us, and added with a smile, I cannot make Crito believe
that I am the same Socrates who have been talking and conducting the argument; he fancies that I am the
other Socrates whom he will soon see, a dead body—and he asks, How shall he bury me?—these words
of mine, with which I was comforting you and myself, have had, as I perceive, no effect upon Crito. And
therefore I want you to be surety for me to him now, as at the trial he was surety to the judges for me:
but let the promise be of another sort; for he was surety for me to the judges that I would remain, and
you must be my surety to him that I shall not remain, but go away and depart; and then he will suffer
less at my death, and not be grieved when he sees my body being burned or buried. I would not have
him sorrow at my hard lot, or say at the burial, Thus we lay out Socrates, or, Thus we follow him to the
grave or bury him; for false words are not only evil in themselves, but they infect the soul with evil. Be
of good cheer, then, my dear Crito, and say that you are burying my body only, and do with that
whatever is usual, and what you think best.
When he had spoken these words, he arose and went into a chamber to bathe; Crito followed him
and told us to wait. So we remained behind, talking and thinking of the subject of discourse, and also of
the greatness of our sorrow; he was like a father of whom we were being bereaved, and we were about
to pass the rest of our lives as orphans. When he had taken the bath his children were brought to him—
(he had two young sons and an elder one); and the women of his family also came, and he talked to them
and gave them a few directions in the presence of Crito; then he dismissed them and returned to us.
Now the hour of sunset was near, for a good deal of time had passed while he was within. When he
came out, he sat down with us again after his bath, but not much was said. Soon the jailer, who was the
servant of the Eleven, entered and stood by him, saying, To you, Socrates, whom I know to be the
noblest and gentlest and best of all who ever came to this place, I will not impute the angry feelings of
other men, who rage and swear at me, when, in obedience to the authorities, I bid them drink the
poison—indeed, I am sure that you will not be angry with me; for others, as you are aware, and not I, are
to blame. And so fare you well, and try to bear lightly what must needs be—you know my errand. Then
bursting into tears he turned away and went out.
Socrates looked at him and said: I return your good wishes, and will do as you bid. Then turning to
us, he said, How charming the man is: since I have been in prison he has always been coming to see me,
and at times he would talk to me, and was as good to me as could be, and now see how generously he
sorrows on my account. We must do as he says, Crito; and therefore let the cup be brought, if the poison
is prepared: if not, let the attendant prepare some.
Yet, said Crito, the sun is still upon the hill-tops, and I know that many a one has taken the draught
late, and after the announcement has been made to him, he has eaten and drunk, and enjoyed the society
of his beloved; do not hurry—there is time enough.
Socrates said: Yes, Crito, and they of whom you speak are right in so acting, for they think that they
will be gainers by the delay; but I am right in not following their example, for I do not think that I
should gain anything by drinking the poison a little later; I should only be ridiculous in my own eyes for
sparing and saving a life which is already forfeit. Please then to do as I say, and not to refuse me.
Crito made a sign to the servant, who was standing by; and he went out, and having been absent for
some time, returned with the jailer carrying the cup of poison. Socrates said: You, my good friend, who
are experienced in these matters, shall give me directions how I am to proceed. The man answered: You
have only to walk about until your legs are heavy, and then to lie down, and the poison will act. At the
same time he handed the cup to Socrates, who in the easiest and gentlest manner, without the least fear
or change of colour or feature, looking at the man with all his eyes, Echecrates, as his manner was, took
the cup and said: What do you say about making a libation out of this cup to any god? May I, or not?
The man answered: We only prepare, Socrates, just so much as we deem enough. I understand, he said:
but I may and must ask the gods to prosper my journey from this to the other world—even so—and so
be it according to my prayer. Then raising the cup to his lips, quite readily and cheerfully he drank off
the poison. And hitherto most of us had been able to control our sorrow; but now when we saw him
drinking, and saw too that he had finished the draught, we could no longer forbear, and in spite of
myself my own tears were flowing fast; so that I covered my face and wept, not for him, but at the
thought of my own calamity in having to part from such a friend. Nor was I the first; for Crito, when he
found himself unable to restrain his tears, had got up, and I followed; and at that moment, Apollodorus,
who had been weeping all the time, broke out in a loud and passionate cry which made cowards of us
all. Socrates alone retained his calmness: What is this strange outcry? he said. I sent away the women
mainly in order that they might not misbehave in this way, for I have been told that a man should die in
peace. Be quiet, then, and have patience. When we heard his words we were ashamed, and refrained our
tears; and he walked about until, as he said, his legs began to fail, and then he lay on his back, according
to the directions, and the man who gave him the poison now and then looked at his feet and legs; and
after a while he pressed his foot hard, and asked him if he could feel; and he said, No; and then his leg,
and so upwards and upwards, and showed us that he was cold and stiff. And he felt them himself, and
said: When the poison reaches the heart, that will be the end. He was beginning to grow cold about the
groin, when he uncovered his face, for he had covered himself up, and said—they were his last words—
he said: Crito, I owe a cock to Asclepius; will you remember to pay the debt? The debt shall be paid,
said Crito; is there anything else? There was no answer to this question; but in a minute or two a
movement was heard, and the attendants uncovered him; his eyes were set, and Crito closed his eyes and
mouth.
Such was the end, Echecrates, of our friend; concerning whom I may truly say, that of all the men of
his time whom I have known, he was the wisest and justest and best.
Plato: Phaedo, decoded
Aristotle was Plato’s student. The three greatest philosophers ever, then, came one after another:
Socrates, Plato, Aristotle.
It is absolutely impossible to overstate Aristotle’s genius. He wrote about meteorology, biology,
science, logic, astronomy, philosophy, and even veterinary science. He was so good that for 2000 years
he was known as “The Philosopher”, as if there were only one.
In this book, Aristotle discusses how a person should live.
The differences between Aristotle and Plato are quite striking. While Plato refers to an other-
worldly, heavenly realm (the realm of The Forms), Aristotle says, in short, the good life is whatever
good people do. Obviously, this is a bit circular (how do good people know what to do?). It is also just
about right on the money if you ask me.
Aristotle is generally like that: a close-enough kind of guy. He knows that the perfect is the enemy of
the good, and he is commonly taught as the first scientist or “empiricist”. Empiricists are people who
look to the external world to discover truth.
Most people are empiricists now, so it may be helpful to consider some examples that throw
empiricism into doubt. Imagine I asked you to tell me how many degrees are in the interior angles of a
triangle. How would you go about it?
As an empiricist, you might get a protractor and measure a triangle. But this really doesn’t answer
the question; among many other problems, you’ve only told me about one triangle, not all triangles.
You’ll also never measure to exactly 180º, so you should say that triangles have only approximately that
many.
A rationalist (the opposite of an empiricist) says that counting or measuring is uncertain or worse.
There are ways to prove, without doubt, that all triangles have exactly 180º. And amazingly,
astonishingly, incredibly, the proof can be done entirely in one’s own mind, without even drawing or
measuring any actual triangles. The truth is found only through deductive reasoning.
Descartes, Plato and Kant (whom we’ll see later) are rationalists; they believe in a priori truth:
questions are tested within the mind. Aristotle and Mill (later) are empiricists; they believe in a
posteriori truth: questions are tested by experiment.
In this reading, Aristotle tells us what the good life is. Unsurprisingly, he looks outward to see what
good people do. To Aristotle, the question of the good life, is that eternal question of philosophy: what is
the meaning of life. He thinks that we have a purpose, and when we fulfil it, we are living well.
Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics, Books 1 and 2, edited
BOOK I
If, then, there is some end of the things we do, which we desire for its own sake (everything else
being desired for the sake of this), and if we do not choose everything for the sake of something else (for
at that rate the process would go on to infinity, so that our desire would be empty and vain), clearly this
must be the good and the chief good. Will not the knowledge of it, then, have a great influence on life?
Shall we not, like archers who have a mark to aim at, be more likely to hit upon what is right? If so, we
must try, in outline at least, to determine what it is, and of which of the sciences or capacities it is the
object. It would seem to belong to the most authoritative art and that which is most truly the master art.
And politics appears to be of this nature; for it is this that ordains which of the sciences should be
studied in a state, and which each class of citizens should learn and up to what point they should learn
them. These, then, are the ends at which our inquiry aims, since it is political science, in one sense of
that term.
Our discussion will be adequate if it has as much clearness as the subject-matter admits of, for
precision is not to be sought for alike in all discussions, any more than in all the products of the crafts. In
the same spirit, therefore, should each type of statement be received; for it is the mark of an educated
man to look for precision in each class of things just so far as the nature of the subject admits; it is
evidently equally foolish to accept probable reasoning from a mathematician and to demand from a
rhetorician scientific proofs.
Verbally there is very general agreement; for both the general run of men and people of superior
refinement say that the final good is happiness, and identify living well and doing well with being
happy; but with regard to what happiness is they differ, and the many do not give the same account as
the wise. For the former think it is some plain and obvious thing, like pleasure, wealth, or honour; they
differ, however, from one another—and often even the same man identifies it with different things, with
health when he is ill, with wealth when he is poor; but, conscious of their ignorance, they admire those
who proclaim some great ideal that is above their comprehension.
To judge from the lives that men lead, most men, and men of the most vulgar type, seem (not
without some ground) to identify the good, or happiness, with pleasure; which is the reason why they
love the life of enjoyment. For there are, we may say, three prominent types of life—that just mentioned,
the political, and thirdly the contemplative life. Now the mass of mankind is evidently quite slavish in
their tastes, preferring a life suitable to beasts, but they get some ground for their view from the fact that
many of those in high places share the tastes of Sardanapallus. A consideration of the prominent types of
life shows that people of superior refinement and of active disposition identify happiness with honour;
for this is, roughly speaking, the end of the political life. But it seems too superficial to be what we are
looking for, since it is thought to depend on those who bestow honour rather than on him who receives
it, but the good we divine to be something proper to a man and not easily taken from him. Further, men
seem to pursue honour in order that they may be assured of their goodness; at least it is by men of
practical wisdom that they seek to be honoured, and among those who know them, and on the ground of
their excellence; clearly, then, according to them, at any rate, excellence is better. And perhaps one
might even suppose this to be, rather than honour, the end of the political life. But even this appears
somewhat incomplete; for possession of excellence seems actually compatible with being asleep, or with
lifelong inactivity, and, further, with the greatest sufferings and misfortunes; but a man who was living
so no one would call happy, unless he were maintaining a thesis at all costs. But enough of this; for the
subject has been sufficiently treated even in the current discussions. Third comes the contemplative life,
which we shall consider later.
Since there is evidently more than one end, and we choose some of these for the sake of something
else, clearly not all ends are final ends; but the chief good is evidently something final. Therefore, if
there is only one final end, this will be what we are seeking, and if there are more than one, the most
final of these will be what we are seeking.
Now such a thing happiness, above all else, is held to be; for this we choose always for self and
never for the sake of something else.
Presumably, however, to say that happiness is the chief good seems a platitude, and a clearer account
of what it is still desired. This might perhaps be given, if we could first ascertain the function of man.
For just as for a flute-player, a sculptor, or an artist, and, in general, for all things that have a function or
activity, the good and the ‘well’ is thought to reside in the function, so would it seem to be for man, if he
has a function. Have the carpenter, then, and the tanner certain functions or activities, and has man
none? Is he born without a function? Or as eye, hand, foot, and in general each of the parts evidently has
a function, may one lay it down that man similarly has a function apart from all these? What then can
this be? Life seems to be common even to plants, but we are seeking what is peculiar to man. Let us
exclude, therefore, the life of nutrition and growth. Next there would be a life of perception, but it also
seems to be common even to the horse, the ox, and every animal. There remains, then, an active life of
the element that has a rational principle. Now if the function of man is an activity of soul which follows
or implies a rational principle, and we state the function of man to be a certain kind of life, and this to be
an activity or actions of the soul implying a rational principle, and the function of a good man to be the
good and noble performance of these, and if any action is well performed when it is performed in
accordance with the appropriate excellence: if this is the case, human good turns out to be activity of
soul in accordance with excellence, and if there are more than one excellence, in accordance with the
best and most complete.
But we must add ‘in a complete life.’ For one swallow does not make a summer, nor does one day;
and so too one day, or a short time, does not make a man blessed and happy.
Let this serve as an outline of the good; for we must presumably first sketch it roughly, and then
later fill in the details. For the beginning is thought to be more than half of the whole, and many of the
questions we ask are cleared up by it.
Now for most men their pleasures are in conflict with one another because these are not by nature
pleasant, but the lovers of what is noble find pleasant the things that are by nature pleasant; and virtuous
actions are such, so that these are pleasant for such men as well as in their own nature. Their life,
therefore, has no further need of pleasure as a sort of adventitious charm, but has its pleasure in itself.
For, besides what we have said, the man who does not rejoice in noble actions is not even good; since no
one would call a man just who did not enjoy acting justly, nor any man liberal who did not enjoy liberal
actions; and similarly in all other cases. If this is so, virtuous actions must be in themselves pleasant. But
they are also good and noble, and have each of these attributes in the highest degree, since the good man
judges well about these attributes; his judgment is such as we have described. Happiness then is the best,
noblest, and most pleasant thing in the world, and these attributes are not severed as in the inscription at
Delos-
Most noble is that which is justest, and best is health;
But pleasantest is it to win what we love.
For all these properties belong to the best activities; and these, or one—the best—of these, we
identify with happiness.
Yet evidently, as we said, it needs the external goods as well; for it is impossible, or not easy, to do
noble acts without the proper equipment. In many actions we use friends and riches and political power
as instruments; and there are some things the lack of which takes the lustre from happiness, as good
birth, goodly children, beauty; for the man who is very ugly in appearance or ill-born or solitary and
childless is not very likely to be happy, and perhaps a man would be still less likely if he had thoroughly
bad children or friends or had lost good children or friends by death. As we said, then, happiness seems
to need this sort of prosperity in addition; for which reason some identify happiness with good fortune,
though others identify it with excellence.
For this reason also the question is asked, whether happiness is to be acquired by learning or by
habituation or some other sort of training, or comes in virtue of some divine providence or again by
chance. Now if there is any gift of the gods to men, it is reasonable that happiness should be god-given,
and most surely god-given of all human things inasmuch as it is the best. But this question would
perhaps be more appropriate to another inquiry; happiness seems, however, even if it is not god-sent but
comes as a result of excellence and some process of learning or training, to be among the most godlike
things; for that which is the prize and end of excellence seems to be the best thing in the world, and
something godlike and blessed.
It will also on this view be very generally shared; for all who are not maimed as regards their
potentiality for excellence may win it by a certain kind of study and care. But if it is better to be happy
thus than by chance, it is reasonable that the facts should be so, since everything that depends on the
action of nature is by nature as good as it can be, and similarly everything that depends on art or any
rational cause, and especially if it depends on the best of all causes. To entrust to chance what is greatest
and most noble would be a very defective arrangement.
It is natural, then, that we call neither ox nor horse nor any other of the animals happy; for none of
them is capable of sharing in such activity. For this reason also a boy is not happy; for he is not yet
capable of such acts, owing to his age; and boys who are called happy are being congratulated by reason
of the hopes we have for them. For there is required, as we said, not only complete excellence but also a
complete life, since many changes occur in life, and all manner of chances, and the most prosperous may
fall into great misfortunes in old age, as is told of Priam in the Trojan Cycle; and one who has
experienced such chances and has ended wretchedly no one calls happy.
Since happiness is an activity of soul in accordance with perfect excellence, we must consider the
nature of excellence; for perhaps we shall thus see better the nature of happiness. By human excellence
we mean not that of the body but that of the soul; and happiness also we call an activity of soul. But if
this is so, clearly the student of politics must know somehow the facts about soul, as the man who is to
heal the eyes or the body as a whole must know about the eyes or the body; and all the more since
politics is more prized and better than medicine; but even among doctors the best educated spend much
labour on acquiring knowledge of the body. The student of politics, then, must study the soul, and must
study it with these objects in view, and do so just to the extent which is sufficient for the questions we
are discussing; for further precision is perhaps something more laborious than our purposes require.
Some things are said about it, adequately enough, even in the discussions outside our school, and we
must use these; e.g. that one element in the soul is irrational and one has a rational principle. Whether
these are separated as the parts of the body or of anything divisible are, or are distinct by definition but
by nature inseparable, like convex and concave in the circumference of a circle, does not affect the
present question.
Of the irrational element one division seems to be widely distributed, and vegetative in its nature, I
mean that which causes nutrition and growth; for it is this kind of power of the soul that one must assign
to all nurslings and to embryos, and this same power to full-grown creatures; this is more reasonable
than to assign some different power to them. Now the excellence of this seems to be common to all
species and not specifically human; for this part or faculty seems to function most in sleep, while
goodness and badness are least manifest in sleep (whence comes the saying that the happy are not better
off than the wretched for half their lives; and this happens naturally enough, since sleep is an inactivity
of the soul in that respect in which it is called good or bad), unless perhaps to a small extent some of the
movements actually penetrate to the soul, and in this respect the dreams of good men are better than
those of ordinary people. Enough of this subject, however; let us leave the nutritive faculty alone, since
it has by its nature no share in human excellence.
There seems to be also another irrational element in the soul—one which in a sense, however, shares
in a rational principle. For we praise the rational principle of the continent man and of the incontinent,
and the part of their soul that has such a principle, since it urges them aright and towards the best
objects; but there is found in them also another element naturally opposed to the rational principle,
which fights against and resists that principle. For exactly as paralyzed limbs when we intend to move
them to the right turn on the contrary to the left, so is it with the soul; the impulses of incontinent people
move in contrary directions. But while in the body we see that which moves astray, in the soul we do
not. No doubt, however, we must none the less suppose that in the soul too there is something contrary
to the rational principle, resisting and opposing it. In what sense it is distinct from the other elements
does not concern us. Now even this seems to have a share in a rational principle, as we said; at any rate
in the continent man it obeys the rational principle and presumably in the temperate and brave man it is
still more obedient; for in him it speaks, on all matters, with the same voice as the rational principle.
Therefore the irrational element also appears to be two-fold. For the vegetative element in no way
shares in a rational principle, but the appetitive and in general the desiring element in a sense shares in
it, in so far as it listens to and obeys it; this is the sense in which we speak of ‘taking account’ of one’s
father or one’s friends, not that in which we speak of ‘accounting’ for a mathematical property. That the
irrational element is in some sense persuaded by a rational principle is indicated also by the giving of
advice and by all reproof and exhortation. And if this element also must be said to have a rational
principle, that which has a rational principle (as well as that which has not) will be twofold, one
subdivision having it in the strict sense and in itself, and the other having a tendency to obey as one does
one’s father.
Excellence too is distinguished into kinds in accordance with this difference; for we say that some of
the excellences are intellectual and others moral, philosophic wisdom and understanding and practical
wisdom being intellectual, liberality and temperance moral. For in speaking about a man’s character we
do not say that he is wise or has understanding but that he is good-tempered or temperate; yet we praise
the wise man also with respect to his state of mind; and of states of mind we call those which merit
praise excellent.
BOOK II
Excellence, then, being of two kinds, intellectual and moral, intellectual excellence in the main owes
both its birth and its growth to teaching (for which reason it requires experience and time), while moral
excellence comes about as a result of habit, whence also its name (ethike) is one that is formed by a
slight variation from the word ethos (habit). From this it is also plain that none of the moral excellences
arises in us by nature; for nothing that exists by nature can form a habit contrary to its nature. For
instance the stone which by nature moves downwards cannot be habituated to move upwards, not even if
one tries to train it by throwing it up ten thousand times; nor can fire be habituated to move downwards,
nor can anything else that by nature behaves in one way be trained to behave in another. Neither by
nature, then, nor contrary to nature do the excellences arise in us; rather we are adapted by nature to
receive them, and are made perfect by habit.
Again, of all the things that come to us by nature we first acquire the potentiality and later exhibit
the activity (this is plain in the case of the senses; for it was not by often seeing or often hearing that we
got these senses, but on the contrary we had them before we used them, and did not come to have them
by using them); but the excellences we get by first exercising them, as also happens in the case of the
arts as well. For the things we have to learn before we can do them, we learn by doing them, e.g. men
become builders by building and lyre players by playing the lyre; so too we become just by doing just
acts, temperate by doing temperate acts, brave by doing brave acts.
This is confirmed by what happens in states; for legislators make the citizens good by forming habits
in them, and this is the wish of every legislator, and those who do not effect it miss their mark, and it is
in this that a good constitution differs from a bad one.
Again, it is from the same causes and by the same means that every excellence is both produced and
destroyed, and similarly every art; for it is from playing the lyre that both good and bad lyre-players are
produced. And the corresponding statement is true of builders and of all the rest; men will be good or
bad builders as a result of building well or badly. For if this were not so, there would have been no need
of a teacher, but all men would have been born good or bad at their craft. This, then, is the case with the
excellences also; by doing the acts that we do in our transactions with other men we become just or
unjust, and by doing the acts that we do in the presence of danger, and being habituated to feel fear or
confidence, we become brave or cowardly. The same is true of appetites and feelings of anger; some
men become temperate and good-tempered, others self-indulgent and irascible, by behaving in one way
or the other in the appropriate circumstances. Thus, in one word, states of character arise out of like
activities. This is why the activities we exhibit must be of a certain kind; it is because the states of
character correspond to the differences between these. It makes no small difference, then, whether we
form habits of one kind or of another from our very youth; it makes a very great difference, or rather all
the difference.
Since, then, the present inquiry does not aim at theoretical knowledge like the others (for we are
inquiring not in order to know what excellence is, but in order to become good, since otherwise our
inquiry would have been of no use), we must examine the nature of actions, namely how we ought to do
them; for these determine also the nature of the states of character that are produced, as we have said.
First, then, let us consider this, that it is the nature of such things to be destroyed by defect and
excess, as we see in the case of strength and of health; both excessive and defective exercise destroys the
strength, and similarly drink or food which is above or below a certain amount destroys the health, while
that which is proportionate both produces and increases and preserves it. So too is it, then, in the case of
temperance and courage and the other excellences. For the man who flies from and fears everything and
does not stand his ground against anything becomes a coward, and the man who fears nothing at all but
goes to meet every danger becomes rash; and similarly the man who indulges in every pleasure and
abstains from none becomes self-indulgent, while the man who shuns every pleasure, as boors do,
becomes in a way insensible; temperance and courage, then, are destroyed by excess and defect, and
preserved by the mean.
But not only are the sources and causes of their origination and growth the same as those of their
destruction, but also the sphere of their actualization will be the same; for this is also true of the things
which are more evident to sense, e.g. of strength; it is produced by taking much food and undergoing
much exertion, and it is the strong man that will be most able to do these things. So too is it with the
excellences; by abstaining from pleasures we become temperate, and it is when we have become so that
we are most able to abstain from them; and similarly too in the case of courage; for by being habituated
to despise things that are terrible and to stand our ground against them we become brave, and it is when
we have become so that we shall be most able to stand our ground against them.
We must take as a sign of states of character the pleasure or pain that ensues on acts; for the man
who abstains from bodily pleasures and delights in this very fact is temperate, while the man who is
annoyed at it is self-indulgent, and he who stands his ground against things that are terrible and delights
in this or at least is not pained is brave, while the man who is pained is a coward. For moral excellence is
concerned with pleasures and pains; it is on account of the pleasure that we do bad things, and on
account of the pain that we abstain from noble ones. Hence we ought to have been brought up in a
particular way from our very youth, as Plato says, so as both to delight in and to be pained by the things
that we ought; for this is the right education.
We measure even our actions, some of us more and others less, by the rule of pleasure and pain. For
this reason, then, our whole inquiry must be about these; for to feel delight and pain rightly or wrongly
has no small effect on our actions.
Again, it is harder to fight with pleasure than with anger, to use Heraclitus’ phrase, but both art and
excellence are always concerned with what is harder; for even the good is better when it is harder.
Therefore for this reason also the whole concern both of excellence and of political science is with
pleasures and pains; for the man who uses these well will be good, he who uses them badly bad.
The question might be asked, what we mean by saying that we must become just by doing just acts,
and temperate by doing temperate acts; for if men do just and temperate acts, they are already just and
temperate, exactly as, if they do what is in accordance with the laws of grammar and of music, they are
grammarians and musicians.
Or is this not true even of the arts? It is possible to do something that is in accordance with the laws
of grammar, either by chance or at the suggestion of another. A man will be a grammarian, then, only
when he has both done something grammatical and done it grammatically; and this means doing it in
accordance with the grammatical knowledge in himself.
Again, the case of the arts and that of the excellences are not similar; for the products of the arts
have their goodness in themselves, so that it is enough that they should have a certain character, but if
the acts that are in accordance with the excellences have themselves a certain character it does not
follow that they are done justly or temperately. The agent also must be in a certain condition when he
does them; in the first place he must have knowledge, secondly he must choose the acts, and choose
them for their own sakes, and thirdly his action must proceed from a firm and unchangeable character.
These are not reckoned in as conditions of the possession of the arts, except the bare knowledge; but as a
condition of the possession of the excellences, knowledge has little or no weight, while the other
conditions count not for a little but for everything, i.e. the very conditions which result from often doing
just and temperate acts.
Actions, then, are called just and temperate when they are such as the just or the temperate man
would do; but it is not the man who does these that is just and temperate, but the man who also does
them as just and temperate men do them. It is well said, then, that it is by doing just acts that the just
man is produced, and by doing temperate acts the temperate man; without doing these no one would
have even a prospect of becoming good.
But most people do not do these, but take refuge in theory and think they are being philosophers and
will become good in this way, behaving somewhat like patients who listen attentively to their doctors,
but do none of the things they are ordered to do. As the latter will not be made well in body by such a
course of treatment, the former will not be made well in soul by such a course of philosophy.
How this is to happen we have stated already, but it will be made plain also by the following
consideration of the specific nature of excellence. In everything that is continuous and divisible it is
possible to take more, less, or an equal amount, and that either in terms of the thing itself or relatively to
us; and the equal is an intermediate between excess and defect. By the intermediate in the object I mean
that which is equidistant from each of the extremes, which is one and the same for all men; by the
intermediate relatively to us that which is neither too much nor too little—and this is not one, nor the
same for all. For instance, if ten is many and two is few, six is the intermediate, taken in terms of the
object; for it exceeds and is exceeded by an equal amount; this is intermediate according to arithmetical
proportion. But the intermediate relatively to us is not to be taken so; if ten pounds are too much for a
particular person to eat and two too little, it does not follow that the trainer will order six pounds; for this
also is perhaps too much for the person who is to take it, or too little—too little for Milo, too much for
the beginner in athletic exercises. The same is true of running and wrestling. Thus a master of any art
avoids excess and defect, but seeks the intermediate and chooses this—the intermediate not in the object
but relatively to us.
If it is thus, then, that every art does its work well—by looking to the intermediate and judging its
works by this standard (so that we often say of good works of art that it is not possible either to take
away or to add anything, implying that excess and defect destroy the goodness of works of art, while the
mean preserves it; and good artists, as we say, look to this in their work), and if, further, excellence is
more exact and better than any art, as nature also is, then excellence must have the quality of aiming at
the intermediate. I mean moral excellence; for it is this that is concerned with passions and actions, and
in these there is excess, defect, and the intermediate. For instance, both fear and confidence and appetite
and anger and pity and in general pleasure and pain may be felt both too much and too little, and in both
cases not well; but to feel them at the right times, with reference to the right objects, towards the right
people, with the right motive, and in the right way, is what is both intermediate and best, and this is
characteristic of excellence. Similarly with regard to actions also there is excess, defect, and the
intermediate. Now excellence is concerned with passions and actions, in which excess is a form of
failure, and so is defect, while the intermediate is praised and is a form of success; and being praised and
being successful are both characteristics of excellence. Therefore excellence is a kind of mean, since, as
we have seen, it aims at what is intermediate.
Again, it is possible to fail in many ways (for evil belongs to the class of the unlimited, as the
Pythagoreans conjectured, and good to that of the limited), while to succeed is possible only in one way
(for which reason also one is easy and the other difficult—to miss the mark easy, to hit it difficult); for
these reasons also, then, excess and defect are characteristic of vice, and the mean of virtue:
For men are good in but one way, but bad in many.
Virtue, then, is a state of character concerned with choice, lying in a mean, i.e. the mean relative to
us, this being determined by a rational principle, and by that principle by which the man of practical
wisdom would determine it. Now it is a mean between two vices, that which depends on excess and that
which depends on defect; and again it is a mean because the vices respectively fall short of or exceed
what is right in both passions and actions, while excellence both finds and chooses that which is
intermediate. Hence in respect of its substance and the definition which states its essence excellenceis a
mean, with regard to what is best and right an extreme.
But not every action nor every passion admits of a mean; for some have names that already imply
badness, e.g. spite, shamelessness, envy, and in the case of actions adultery, theft, murder; for all of
these and suchlike things imply by their names that they are themselves bad, and not the excesses or
deficiencies of them. It is not possible, then, ever to be right with regard to them; one must always be
wrong. Nor does goodness or badness with regard to such things depend on committing adultery with
the right woman, at the right time, and in the right way, but simply to do any of them is to go wrong. It
would be equally absurd, then, to expect that in unjust, cowardly, and voluptuous action there should be
a mean, an excess, and a deficiency; for at that rate there would be a mean of excess and of deficiency,
an excess of excess, and a deficiency of deficiency. But as there is no excess and deficiency of
temperance and courage because what is intermediate is in a sense an extreme, so too of the actions we
have mentioned there is no mean nor any excess and deficiency, but however they are done they are
wrong; for in general there is neither a mean of excess and deficiency, nor excess and deficiency of a
mean.
We must, however, not only make this general statement, but also apply it to the individual facts. For
among statements about conduct, those which are general apply more widely, but those which are
particular are more genuine, since conduct has to do with individual cases, and our statements must
harmonize with the facts in these cases. We may take these cases from our table. With regard to feelings
of fear and confidence courage is the mean; of the people who exceed, he who exceeds in fearlessness
has no name (many of the states have no name), while the man who exceeds in confidence is rash, and
he who exceeds in fear and falls short in confidence is a coward. With regard to pleasures and pains—
not all of them, and not so much with regard to the pains—the mean is temperance, the excess self-
indulgence. Persons deficient with regard to the pleasures are not often found; hence such persons also
have received no name. But let us call them ‘insensible’.
With regard to giving and taking of money the mean is liberality, the excess and the defect
prodigality and meanness. In these actions, people exceed and fall short in contrary ways; the prodigal
exceeds in spending and falls short in taking, while the mean man exceeds in taking and falls short in
spending. (At present we are giving a mere outline or summary, and are satisfied with this; later these
states will be more exactly determined.) With regard to money there are also other dispositions—a
mean, magnificence (for the magnificent man differs from the liberal man; the former deals with large
sums, the latter with small ones), an excess, tastelessness and vulgarity, and a deficiency, niggardliness;
these differ from the states opposed to liberality, and the mode of their difference will be stated later.
With regard to honour and dishonour the mean is proper pride, the excess is known as a sort of ‘empty
vanity’, and the deficiency is undue humility; and as we said, liberality was related to magnificence,
differing from it by dealing with small sums, so there is a state similarly related to proper pride, being
concerned with small honours while that is concerned with great. For it is possible to desire honour as
one ought, and more than one ought, and less, and the man who exceeds in his desires is called
ambitious, the man who falls short unambitious, while the intermediate person has no name.
That moral excellence is a mean, then, and in what sense it is so, and that it is a mean between two
vices, the one involving excess, the other deficiency, and that it is such because its character is to aim at
what is intermediate in passions and in actions, has been sufficiently stated. Hence also it is no easy task
to be good. For in everything it is no easy task to find the middle, e.g. to find the middle of a circle is not
for every one but for him who knows; so, too, any one can get angry— that is easy— or give or spend
money; but to do this to the right person, to the right extent, at the right time, with the right motive, and
in the right way, that is not for every one, nor is it easy; wherefore goodness is both rare and laudable
and noble.
Hence he who aims at the intermediate must first depart from what is the more contrary to it, as
Calypso advises
Hold the ship out beyond that surf and spray.
For of the extremes, one is more erroneous, one less so; therefore, since to hit the mean is hard in the
extreme, we must as a second best, as people say, take the least of the evils; and this will be done best in
the way we describe. But we must consider the things towards which we ourselves also are easily carried
away; for some of us tend to one thing, some to another; and this will be recognizable from the pleasure
and the pain we feel. We must drag ourselves away to the contrary extreme; for we shall get into the
intermediate state by drawing well away from error, as people do in straightening sticks that are bent.
Now in everything the pleasant or pleasure is most to be guarded against; for we do not judge it
impartially. We ought, then, to feel towards pleasure as the elders of the people felt towards Helen, and
in all circumstances repeat their saying; for if we dismiss pleasure thus we are less likely to go astray. It
is by doing this, then, (to sum the matter up) that we shall best be able to hit the mean.
But this is no doubt difficult, and especially in individual cases; for it is not easy to determine both
how and with whom and on what provocation and how long one should be angry; for we too sometimes
praise those who fall short and call them good-tempered, but sometimes we praise those who get angry
and call them manly. The man, however, who deviates little from goodness is not blamed, whether he
does so in the direction of the more or of the less, but only the man who deviates more widely; for he
does not fail to be noticed. But up to what point and to what extent a man must deviate before he
becomes blameworthy it is not easy to determine by reasoning, any more than anything else that is
perceived by the senses; such things depend on particular facts, and the decision rests with perception.
So much, then, is plain, that the intermediate state is in all things to be praised, but that we must incline
sometimes towards the excess, sometimes towards the deficiency; for so shall we most easily hit the
mean and what is right.
Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics, Books 1 and 2, decoded
BOOK 1
We choose everything for the sake of happiness. Happiness is the only thing we choose for itself. Of
course, this sounds quite empty—it has not answered the important question, what is happiness?
A man is happy when he fulfills his function.
Yes, man has a function. Life is common to many things, like plants and animals, so the human
purpose is not merely to survive. Perception, too, is common; so our purpose is not merely to wander
around perceiving. We are the only creature that has a rational element. Our function, then, is the
activity of soul which follows the rational principle. A good man is a man that functions well.
Of course, we must add ‘in a complete life’. For one swallow does not make a summer. Being a
good person takes time.
Still, let this be a rough outline. Smart people do not ask for more detail than the subject matter
allows, and this subject will only allow rough outlines.
The best people find good things to be pleasant. Good activities are not good because they are
pleasant; they are pleasant (to a good person) because they are good.
Of course, even though the good life is simple, it requires some external effects. It may be
impossible for someone who is suffering to be good. A solitary, ugly, childless person will find it very
hard. Happiness seems to require some modest amount of prosperity.
Happiness and good functioning comes from habituation. It can be won through study and care. In
fact, this is the only way to be truly happy. A boy is not happy. No animal is happy. Happiness requires
not only complete virtue, but a complete life.
Happiness then, is a life of activity and excellence.
We are growing close, but we must discover, then, what the nature of excellenceis. Plato said that
one part of the soul is irrational and one part is rational. I agree. The irrational part is also divided into
the nutritive and willful. All animals have the nutritive element; they know how to eat and grow. The
willful part is the part that rebels against the rational part of the soul. It has something in common with
the intellect, but it is not quite rational; sometimes it seems to even spite the rational element, as when
we might tell a paralyzed limb to move to the left only to find it turn contrary to our will to the right.
Excellence is divided similarly. There are two kinds of excellence: intellectual and moral.
BOOK 2
Intellectual excellence comes from birth, and it grows from teaching. It requires experience and
time. Moral excellence comes about as a result of habit. None of the moral excellences is in us naturally;
we do not need to practice what comes naturally. Nothing that is natural can be changed. A stone cannot
be made to fall up by throwing it ten thousand times. No, nature gives us the capacity to develop
excellences, but we develop them through habit.
Just as someone becomes a guitar player by playing guitar, so too do we become good by doing
good things. People become good or bad by behaving well or badly. We become courageous by facing
danger, and temperate by facing temptations. It makes no small difference, then, whether we form habits
of one kind or of another from our very youth; it makes a very great difference, or rather all the
difference.
Of course, while this may answer how one becomes good, it does not explain what a good act is. Let
us consider that next.
Things are destroyed by excess and defect, as we see in strength and health. Too much exercise
destroys strength. Too little does as well. Too much food destroys health. Too little does as well. A
person needs just the right amount. It is the same with all the other excellences. A man who always runs
away becomes a coward. A man who always stands his ground becomes rash. A woman who indulges
every pleasure becomes self-indulgent. A woman who indulges none becomes a boor. All excellences
are destroyed by excess and defect and preserved by the mean.
We can judge a person’s character by the pleasure or pain she receives from an act. A woman who is
pained by going to work is lazy. A woman who takes too much delight may be a busybody. Moral
excellence is concerned with developing the right pleasures and pains. We do bad things on account of
the pleasure they bring us. We abstain from good ones because (until we develop) they cause us pain.
And, because it is especially hard to fight with pleasure, we should structure our politics to encourage
taking pleasure from good activities.
What I say seems strange, I know. I say men become just by doing just acts and temperate by doing
temperate acts. Surely they are already just and temperate if they do these things. A person acting in
accordance with grammar is grammatical, and behaving musically is musical, so surely a person
behaving justly is already just.
Not so. A person can be grammatical by accident or by monkeying someone else. A woman will be
a grammarian only if she does something grammatical and does it grammatically. She must do it with
knowledge of grammar. Likewise, a person truly behaving well must be behaving with knowledge of
what she is doing.
Moreover, a man must act in a certain condition. He must have knowledge. He must choose his acts,
and, most importantly, his action must come from a firm and unchangeable character.
Actions, then, are called just and temperate when they are such as the just or the temperate man
would do. A man is not good if he simply does good acts; he must also do them as a good man does
them. A good man is made by doing good.
Most people find it too hard to be good. They talk about doing good but do not do it. They call
themselves philosophers and think that they will be good by discussing theory. It is somewhat like a
person who listens to her doctor but does not follow the instructions.
Again, good actions are those between an excess and a defect. This is the mean. The arithmetic mean
is equidistant from two extremes; 6 is the mean of 10 and 2. But the mean relative to us is not taken so.
While 10 pounds is too much food and 2 too little, 6 may be too much for me and too little for Chuck
Liddell. The good person avoids what is too much and too little relative to herself, the good teacher
relative to her pupil.
All arts are the same. Nothing can be taken away nor added to a great work of art. Likewise, moral
excellence aims at the intermediate. Fear and confidence, pleasure and pain, indulgence and restraint: all
may be felt too much and too little. The good person feels them at the right times in the right amount,
with reference to the right things, toward the right people, and with the right motive. Moderation is
characteristic of excellence. Excellence aims at the moderate.
It is possible to fail in many ways, though, for evil is unlimited and goodness is limited. Failure is
easy, and success is difficult.
Excellence, then, is a state of character concerned with choice, lying in a mean relative to us. The
mean is determined by a rational principle, as a man of practical wisdom would determine it.
Some actions do not have means. Spite, shamelessness, envy, adultery, theft, murder and so on are
always bad. It is not possible to strike a mean about these things; one is always wrong. One cannot
commit adultery with the right woman at the right time and in the right way.
Here are a few examples of excellence. With regard to fear, courage is the mean. Rashness is the
excess and cowardliness the deficiency. With regard to money, the mean is liberality. Prodigality is the
excess and cheapness the defect. With regard to honour and dishonour, proper pride is the mean. Undue
humility is as bad as empty vanity.
It is, as I said, easy to go wrong. Sometimes we find the mean through experimentation and through
aiming at the second best. Some of us tend towards one error and must be dragged away from it.
Pleasure is particularly dangerous. We should dismiss it. We would be less likely to err.
A person who errs a little is not blamed, nor is one who errs infrequently. Up to what point a person
is allowed to err is not easy to determine. The judgment will depend, as these things do, on the
circumstances of the case.
Epicurus
After the Big Three (Socrates, Plato and Aristotle), philosophy fell to pieces for 2000 years or so. It
took Descartes to pep it up again. Epicurus was the just about the last of the Athenian philosophers, and
I think you’ll be able to discern the decline.
While most philosophers try to come up with a few guiding rules to govern our actions, Epicurus
came up with 40. More is not better. More is worse. Epicurus’ doctrines are a mad jumble of clearly
contradictory ideas.
Still, I like him. I like Epicurus because I can quote him to my wife when we go shopping. I ask her
whenever she wants to buy something crappy: “Is this natural and necessary, natural and unnecessary, or
neither natural nor necessary?” Of course, it gets me nowhere, but as she never studied philosophy, she
does not know that marriage is merely a contract for mutual benefit (Epicurus again) and, when she
gives me the silent treatment, I get to the absence of pain for a while. That’s good!
Epicurus studied Plato as a young man, experimented as a Lesbosian in his early 30s, and finally
moved to Athens, where he lived until his death.
He started a commune there. People made fun of him, but they still came by quite a bit—no surprise,
since ‘The Garden’ was the only school to admit women and had a saying on the front door: “Stranger,
stay as long as you like. Pleasure is our highest good.”
Epicurus was an atomist. He believed that the universe is composed of only two things: atoms and
void. That is a pretty radical idea, and Epicurus had the intellectual fortitude to see it through to its
conclusion: there is no soul, so death is the end.
Epicurus died because he couldn’t pee. He was quite cheerful about it.
Epicurus: Principal Doctrines, unedited
1. A blessed and indestructible being has no trouble himself and brings no trouble upon any
other being; so he is free from anger and partiality, for all such things imply weakness.
2. Death is nothing to us; for that which has been dissolved into its elements experiences no
sensations, and that which has no sensation is nothing to us.
3. The magnitude of pleasure reaches its limit in the removal of all pain. When such pleasure is
present, so long as it is uninterrupted, there is no pain either of body or of mind or of both
together.
4. Continuous bodily pain does not last long; instead, pain, if extreme, is present a very short
time, and even that degree of pain which slightly exceeds bodily pleasure does not last for
many days at once. Diseases of long duration allow an excess of bodily pleasure over pain.
5. It is impossible to live a pleasant life without living wisely and honorably and justly, and it is
impossible to live wisely and honorably and justly without living pleasantly. Whenever any
one of these is lacking, when, for instance, the man is not able to live wisely, though he lives
honorably and justly, it is impossible for him to live a pleasant life.
6. In order to obtain protection from other men, any means for attaining this end is a natural
good.
7. Some men want fame and status, thinking that they would thus make themselves secure
against other men. If the life of such men really were secure, they have attained a natural
good; if, however, it is insecure, they have not attained the end which by nature's own
prompting they originally sought.
8. No pleasure is a bad thing in itself, but the things which produce certain pleasures entail
disturbances many times greater than the pleasures themselves.
9. If every pleasure had been capable of accumulation, not only over time but also over the
entire body or at least over the principal parts of our nature, then pleasures would never differ
from one another.
10. If the things that produce the pleasures of profligate men really freed them from fears of the
mind concerning celestial and atmospheric phenomena, the fear of death, and the fear of
pain; if, further, they taught them to limit their desires, we should never have any fault to find
with such persons, for they would then be filled with pleasures from every source and would
never have pain of body or mind, which is what is bad.
11. If we had never been troubled by celestial and atmospheric phenomena, nor by fears about
death, nor by our ignorance of the limits of pains and desires, we should have had no need of
natural science.
12. It is impossible for someone to dispel his fears about the most important matters if he doesn't
know the nature of the universe but still gives some credence to myths. So without the study
of nature there is no enjoyment of pure pleasure.
13. There is no advantage to obtaining protection from other men so long as we are alarmed by
events above or below the earth or in general by whatever happens in the boundless universe.
14. Protection from other men, secured to some extent by the power to expel and by material
prosperity, in its purest form comes from a quiet life withdrawn from the multitude.
15. The wealth required by nature is limited and is easy to procure; but the wealth required by
vain ideals extends to infinity.
16. Chance seldom interferes with the wise man; his greatest and highest interests have been, are,
and will be, directed by reason throughout his whole life.
17. The just man is most free from disturbance, while the unjust is full of the utmost disturbance.
18. Bodily pleasure does not increase when the pain of want has been removed; after that it only
admits of variation. The limit of mental pleasure, however, is reached when we reflect on
these bodily pleasures and their related emotions, which used to cause the mind the greatest
alarms.
19. Unlimited time and limited time afford an equal amount of pleasure, if we measure the limits
of that pleasure by reason.
20. The flesh receives as unlimited the limits of pleasure; and to provide it requires unlimited
time. But the mind, intellectually grasping what the end and limit of the flesh is, and
banishing the terrors of the future, procures a complete and perfect life, and we have no
longer any need of unlimited time. Nevertheless the mind does not shun pleasure, and even
when circumstances make death imminent, the mind does not lack enjoyment of the best life.
21. He who understands the limits of life knows that it is easy to obtain that which removes the
pain of want and makes the whole of life complete and perfect. Thus he has no longer any
need of things which involve struggle.
22. We must consider both the ultimate end and all clear sensory evidence, to which we refer our
opinions; for otherwise everything will be full of uncertainty and confusion.
23. If you fight against all your sensations, you will have no standard to which to refer, and thus
no means of judging even those sensations which you claim are false.
24. If you reject absolutely any single sensation without stopping to distinguish between opinion
about things awaiting confirmation and that which is already confirmed to be present,
whether in sensation or in feelings or in any application of intellect to the presentations, you
will confuse the rest of your sensations by your groundless opinion and so you will reject
every standard of truth. If in your ideas based upon opinion you hastily affirm as true all that
awaits confirmation as well as that which does not, you will not avoid error, as you will be
maintaining the entire basis for doubt in every judgment between correct and incorrect
opinion.
25. If you do not on every occasion refer each of your actions to the ultimate end prescribed by
nature, but instead of this in the act of choice or avoidance turn to some other end, your
actions will not be consistent with your theories.
26. All desires that do not lead to pain when they remain unsatisfied are unnecessary, but the
desire is easily got rid of, when the thing desired is difficult to obtain or the desires seem
likely to produce harm.
27. Of all the means which wisdom acquires to ensure happiness throughout the whole of life, by
far the most important is friendship.
28. The same conviction which inspires confidence that nothing we have to fear is eternal or
even of long duration, also enables us to see that in the limited evils of this life nothing
enhances our security so much as friendship.
29. Of our desires some are natural and necessary, others are natural but not necessary; and
others are neither natural nor necessary, but are due to groundless opinion.
30. Those natural desires which entail no pain when unsatisfied, though pursued with an intense
effort, are also due to groundless opinion; and it is not because of their own nature they are
not got rid of but because of man's groundless opinions.
31. Natural justice is a pledge of reciprocal benefit, to prevent one man from harming or being
harmed by another.
32. Those animals which are incapable of making binding agreements with one another not to
inflict nor suffer harm are without either justice or injustice; and likewise for those peoples
who either could not or would not form binding agreements not to inflict nor suffer harm.
33. There never was such a thing as absolute justice, but only agreements made in mutual
dealings among men in whatever places at various times providing against the infliction or
suffering of harm.
34. Injustice is not an evil in itself, but only in consequence of the fear which is associated with
the apprehension of being discovered by those appointed to punish such actions.
35. It is impossible for a man who secretly violates the terms of the agreement not to harm or be
harmed to feel confident that he will remain undiscovered, even if he has already escaped ten
thousand times; for until his death he is never sure that he will not be detected.
36. In general justice is the same for all, for it is something found mutually beneficial in men's
dealings, but in its application to particular places or other circumstances the same thing is
not necessarily just for everyone.
37. Among the things held to be just by law, whatever is proved to be of advantage in men's
dealings has the stamp of justice, whether or not it be the same for all; but if a man makes a
law and it does not prove to be mutually advantageous, then this is no longer just. And if
what is mutually advantageous varies and only for a time corresponds to our concept of
justice, nevertheless for that time it is just for those who do not trouble themselves about
empty words, but look simply at the facts.
38. Where without any change in circumstances the things held to be just by law are seen not to
correspond with the concept of justice in actual practice, such laws are not really just; but
wherever the laws have ceased to be advantageous because of a change in circumstances, in
that case the laws were for that time just when they were advantageous for the mutual
dealings of the citizens, and subsequently ceased to be just when they were no longer
advantageous.
39. The man who best knows how to meet external threats makes into one family all the
creatures he can; and those he can not, he at any rate does not treat as aliens; and where he
finds even this impossible, he avoids all dealings, and, so far as is advantageous, excludes
them from his life.
40. Those who possess the power to defend themselves against threats by their neighbors, being
thus in possession of the surest guarantee of security, live the most pleasant life with one
another; and their enjoyment of the fullest intimacy is such that if one of them dies
prematurely, the others do not lament his death as though it called for pity.
Epicurus: Principal Doctrines, decoded
1. Do not cause trouble for yourself or for others. This lets you be free from anger and bias. These
are signs of weakness.
2. Death is nothing to us. Once we become dissolved atoms, we don’t experience anything. We’re
gone. Why worry if you can’t experience anything?
3. Maximum pleasure is feeling no pain.
4. Even the worst pains do not last long. In the long run, life is more pleasant than unpleasant, even
if you have a nasty disease.
5. You have to be good to be happy. You have to be happy to be good.
6. It is good to be protected from other men.
7. Some people want to be famous so that they can be independent. If that worked, I would
approve. But I doubt that fame leads to independence.
8. All pleasures are good. Most pleasures, however, lead to disturbances that are worse than the
pleasure. Stay focused and do not get caught up in the pursuit of these pleasures.
9. If pleasures added up, then pleasures would never differ from one another. We need some pain to
feel pleasure.
10. If wealth made people unafraid of death, disease, famine and war, then wealth would be good. If
wealth taught people to be satisfied with a simple life, then I could not complain. But it does not.
11. We developed science to get rid of our fears of death, disease, famine and war.
12. You can’t enjoy wealth or security if you don’t understand science.
13. Wealth and power lead to security to some degree. But a quiet, solitary life is the best way to be
secure.
14. You want much, but need little.
15. Being good means you won’t have to worry. The evil must worry.
16. When needs are gone, bodily pleasure is just an assortment of minor variations. Mental pleasure,
however, reaches its limit when we look back on how worried we were about those needs.
17. Your mind can limit your wants. You only need a little, but at first, everyone wants an unlimited
amount. Stop worrying about the future. Try not to want the things you do not really need, and
you will find you will not need to try everything. Limiting wants removes worries of death. And
remember: even when you are dying, life is still pleasant.
18. You can’t always get what you want. But if you try sometimes, you just might find, you can get
what you need.
19. You do not need something unless you are in actual pain when that ‘need’ goes unfulfilled. If
you are not in pain, then get rid of that want.
20. Friends will protect you against insecurity.
21. There are three kinds of want:
a. Natural and necessary,
b. Natural and unnecessary, and
c. Neither natural nor necessary.
22. Don’t be dumb: if you aren’t in actual pain without something, you don’t need it. You just think
you do. Of course, many people go through much trouble to get things they don’t really need.
23. ‘Justice’ is really only a contract that I won’t hurt you and you won’t hurt me.
24. If you didn’t get it in writing, it is your own fault if you got ripped off. Don’t blame the other
guy.
25. There is no one perfect set of laws. There are many imperfect systems of justice.
26. There is nothing inherently wrong with breaking the law, but it will make you unhappy because
you will be afraid of getting caught.
27. The same thing can be just and unjust in different places.
28. If a law never led to happiness, it was never just. If a law stopped leading to happiness, it stopped
being just.
Marcus Aurelius
Marcus Aurelius was an honest-to-god emperor of Rome. He was also a great guy. He is said to have
been “by nature a saint and sage, by profession a warrior and ruler”.
Despite being the most powerful man in the world, Marcus Aurelius lived a simple life. He
advocated working hard and wanting little; in all likelihood he was miserable, though. His life was
tragic. Four of his five sons died, and the survivor was Commodus, who became an emperor himself.
Commodus was a dick. He liked to have ostriches and lions tied up so that he could kill them in front of
a coliseum full of spectators. Manly, huh? Of course, if my dad had named me “Toiletus”, I might be a
little off too.
As if a son like that were not a heavy enough burden for Marcus to bear, his time as emperor saw
Rome blighted by fire, floods, earthquakes and war. It was in one of these wars that Marcus’ beloved
wife, Faustina, died. Marcus himself died of chickenpox while lost in a Hungarian marsh fighting
barbarians. Seriously.
Marcus Aurelius’ book is called Meditations. You and I were not meant to read it; it was his diary.
As you might expect of a diary, it is a bit wordy. I have edited it down to what I think are the essentials.
Like Epicurus, the book has many principles, and is not what most philosophers would call good
philosophy. Still, it is my favourite ethical philosophy—if I were to call myself anything, I would (rather
immodestly) call myself a stoic.
Roughly speaking, stoics think that we make our own problems. I always use the example of a
speeding ticket. If you get one, you are likely to be angry with the justice system, the cop, or even (if
you’re like me) the whole world. Stoics would say that you are just making things worse: the ticket is
something that happened. You cannot control it now that you have it. You can, however, control your
reactions to it. Worrying about it just makes it worse.
Marcus Aurelius: Medita'ons, edited
BOOK TWO
Begin the morning by saying to thyself, I shall meet with the busy-body, the ungrateful, arrogant,
deceitful, envious, unsocial. All these things happen to them by reason of their ignorance of what is
good and evil. But I who have seen the nature of the good that it is beautiful, and of the bad, that it is
ugly, and the nature of him who does wrong, that it is akin to me, not only of the same blood or seed, but
that it participates in the same intelligence and the same portion of the divinity, I can neither be injured
by any of them, for no one can fix on me what is ugly, nor can I be angry with my kinsman, nor hate
him. For we are made for co-operation, like feet, like hands, like eyelids, like the rows of the upper and
lower teeth. To act against one another then is contrary to nature; and it is acting against one another to
be vexed and to turn away.
Whatever this is that I am, it is a little flesh and breath, and the ruling part. Throw away thy books;
no longer distract thyself: it is not allowed; but as if thou wast now dying, despise the flesh; it is blood
and bones and a network, a contexture of nerves, veins, and arteries. See the breath also, what kind of a
thing it is, air, and not always the same, but every moment sent out and again sucked in. The third then
is the ruling part: consider thus: Thou art an old man; no longer let this be a slave, no longer be pulled
by the strings like a puppet to unsocial movements, no longer either be dissatisfied with thy present lot,
or shrink from the future.
Though thou shouldst be going to live three thousand years, and as many times ten thousand years,
still remember that no man loses any other life than this which he now lives, nor lives any other than this
which he now loses. The longest and shortest are thus brought to the same. For the present is the same to
all, though that which perishes is not the same; and so that which is lost appears to be a mere moment.
For a man cannot lose either the past or the future: for what a man has not, how can any one take this
from him? These two things then thou must bear in mind; the one, that all things from eternity are of like
forms and come round in a circle, and that it makes no difference whether a man shall see the same
things during a hundred years or two hundred, or an infinite time; and the second, that the longest liver
and he who will die soonest lose just the same. For the present is the only thing of which a man can be
deprived, if it is true that this is the only thing which he has, and that a man cannot lose a thing if he has
it not.
The soul of man does violence to itself, first of all, when it becomes an abscess and, as it were, a
tumour on the universe, so far as it can. For to be vexed at anything which happens is a separation of
ourselves from nature, in some part of which the natures of all other things are contained. In the next
place, the soul does violence to itself when it turns away from any man, or even moves towards him
with the intention of injuring, such as are the souls of those who are angry. In the third place, the soul
does violence to itself when it is overpowered by pleasure or by pain. Fourthly, when it plays a part, and
does or says anything insincerely and untruly. Fifthly, when it allows any act of its own and any
movement to be without an aim, and does anything thoughtlessly and without considering what it is, it
being right that even the smallest things be done with reference to an end; and the end of rational
animals is to follow the reason and the law of the most ancient city and polity.
Of human life the time is a point, and the substance is in a flux, and the perception dull, and the
composition of the whole body subject to putrefaction, and the soul a whirl, and fortune hard to divine,
and fame a thing devoid of judgment. And, to say all in a word, everything which belongs to the body is
a stream, and what belongs to the soul is a dream and vapour, and life is a warfare and a stranger’s
sojourn, and after-fame is oblivion. What then is that which is able to conduct a man? One thing and
only one, philosophy. But this consists in keeping the daemon within a man free from violence and
unharmed, superior to pains and pleasures, doing nothing without purpose, nor yet falsely and with
hypocrisy, not feeling the need of another man’s doing or not doing anything; and besides, accepting all
that happens, and all that is allotted, as coming from thence, wherever it is, from whence he himself
came; and, finally, waiting for death with a cheerful mind, as being nothing else than a dissolution of the
elements of which every living being is compounded. But if there is no harm to the elements themselves
in each continually changing into another, why should a man have any apprehension about the change
and dissolution of all the elements? For it is according to nature, and nothing is evil which is according
to nature.
BOOK THREE
We ought to observe also that even the things which follow after the things which are produced
according to nature contain something pleasing and attractive. For instance, when bread is baked some
parts are split at the surface, and these parts which thus open, and have a certain fashion contrary to the
purpose of the baker’s art, are beautiful in a manner, and in a peculiar way excite a desire for eating.
And again, figs, when they are quite ripe, gape open; and in the ripe olives the very circumstance of their
being near to rottenness adds a peculiar beauty to the fruit. And the ears of corn bending down, and the
lion’s eyebrows, and the foam which flows from the mouth of wild boars, and many other things—
though they are far from being beautiful, if a man should examine them severally—still, because they
are consequent upon the things which are formed by nature, help to adorn them, and they please the
mind; so that if a man should have a feeling and deeper insight with respect to the things which are
produced in the universe, there is hardly one of those which follow by way of consequence which will
not seem to him to be in a manner disposed so as to give pleasure. And so he will see even the real
gaping jaws of wild beasts with no less pleasure than those which painters and sculptors show by
imitation; and in an old woman and an old man he will be able to see a certain maturity and comeliness;
and the attractive loveliness of young persons he will be able to look on with chaste eyes; and many
such things will present themselves, not pleasing to every man, but to him only who has become truly
familiar with nature and her works.
What hast thou now in thy thoughts? With perfect openness thou mightest, immediately answer,
This or That; so that from thy words it should be plain that everything in thee is simple and benevolent,
and such as befits a social animal, and one that cares not for thoughts about pleasure or sensual
enjoyments at all, nor has any rivalry or envy and suspicion, or anything else for which thou wouldst
blush if thou shouldst say that thou hadst it in thy mind. For the man who is such and no longer delays
being among the number of the best, is like a priest and minister of the gods, using too the deity which is
planted within him, which makes the man uncontaminated by pleasure, unharmed by any pain,
untouched by any insult, feeling no wrong, a fighter in the noblest fight, one who cannot be
overpowered by any passion, dyed deep with justice, accepting with all his soul everything which
happens and is assigned to him as his portion; and not often, nor yet without great necessity and for the
general interest, imagining what another says, or does, or thinks. For it is only what belongs to himself
that he makes the matter for his activity; and he constantly thinks of that which is allotted to himself out
of the sum total of things, and he makes his own acts fair, and he is persuaded that his own portion is
good. For the lot which is assigned to each man is carried along with him and carries him along with it.
And he remembers also that every rational animal is his kinsman, and that to care for all men is
according to man’s nature; and a man should hold on to the opinion not of all, but of those only who
confessedly live according to nature. But as to those who live not so, he always bears in mind what kind
of men they are both at home and from home, both by night and by day, and what they are, and with
what men they live an impure life. Accordingly, he does not value at all the praise which comes from
such men, since they are not even satisfied with themselves.
A man then must stand erect, not be kept erect by others.
BOOK FOUR
If thou workest at that which is before thee, following right reason seriously, vigorously, calmly,
without allowing anything else to distract thee, but keeping thy divine part pure, as if thou shouldst be
bound to give it back immediately; if thou holdest to this, expecting nothing, fearing nothing, but
satisfied with thy present activity according to nature, and with heroic trust in every word and sound
which thou utterest, thou wilt live happy, and there is no man who is able to prevent this.
Men seek retreats for themselves, houses in the country, sea-shores, and mountains; and thou too art
wont to desire such things very much. But this is altogether a mark of the most common sort of men, for
it is in thy power whenever thou shalt choose to retire into thyself. For nowhere either with more quiet
or more freedom from trouble does a man retire than into his own soul, particularly when he has within
him such thoughts that by looking into them he is immediately in perfect tranquility; and I affirm that
tranquility is nothing else than the good ordering of the mind.
It is natural that these things should be done by such persons, it is a matter of necessity; and if a man
will not have it so, he will not allow the fig-tree to have juice. But by all means bear this in mind, that
within a very short time both thou and he will be dead; and soon not even your names will be left
behind.
Take away thy opinion, and then there is taken away the complaint, “I have been harmed.” Take
away the complaint, “I have been harmed,” and the harm is taken away.
That which does not make a man worse than he was, also does not make his life worse, nor does it
harm him either from without or from within.
Consider that everything which happens, happens justly, and if thou observest carefully, thou wilt
find it to be so. I do not say only with respect to the continuity of the series of things, but with respect to
what is just, and as if it were done by one who assigns to each thing its value. Observe then as thou hast
begun; and whatever thou doest, do it in conjunction with this, the being good, and in the sense in which
a man is properly understood to be good. Keep to this in every action.
Many grains of frankincense on the same altar: one falls before, another falls after; but it makes no
difference.
Within ten days thou wilt seem a god to those to whom thou art now a beast and an ape, if thou wilt
return to thy principles and the worship of reason.
Do not act as if thou wert going to live ten thousand years. Death hangs over thee. While thou livest,
while it is in thy power, be good.
How much trouble he avoids who does not look to see what his neighbour says or does or thinks, but
only to what he does himself, that it may be just and pure; or as Agathon says, look not round at the
depraved morals of others, but run straight along the line without deviating from it.
Do not be whirled about, but in every movement have respect to justice, and on the occasion of
every impression maintain the faculty of comprehension or understanding.
Everything harmonizes with me, which is harmonious to thee, O Universe. Nothing for me is too
early nor too late, which is in due time for thee. Everything is fruit to me which thy seasons bring, O
Nature: from thee are all things, in thee are all things, to thee all things return. The poet says, Dear city
of Cecrops; and wilt not thou say, Dear city of Zeus?
Occupy thyself with few things, says the philosopher, if thou wouldst be tranquil. But consider if it
would not be better to say, Do what is necessary, and whatever the reason of the animal which is
naturally social requires, and as it requires. For this brings not only the tranquility which comes from
doing well, but also that which comes from doing few things. For the greatest part of what we say and
do being unnecessary, if a man takes this away, he will have more leisure and less uneasiness.
Accordingly on every occasion a man should ask himself, Is this one of the unnecessary things? Now a
man should take away not only unnecessary acts, but also, unnecessary thoughts, for thus superfluous
acts will not follow after.
Try how the life of the good man suits thee, the life of him who is satisfied with his portion out of
the whole, and satisfied with his own just acts and benevolent disposition.
Be like the promontory against which the waves continually break, but it stands firm and tames the
fury of the water around it.
BOOK FIVE
In the morning when thou risest unwillingly, let this thought be present—I am rising to the work of a
human being. Why then am I dissatisfied if I am going to do the things for which I exist and for which I
was brought into the world? Or have I been made for this, to lie in the bed-clothes and keep myself
warm? Dost thou exist then to take thy pleasure, and not at all for action or exertion? Dost thou not see
the little plants, the little birds, the ants, the spiders, the bees working together to put in order their
several parts of the universe? And art thou unwilling to do the work of a human being?
How easy it is to repel and to wipe away every impression which is troublesome or unsuitable, and
immediately to be in all tranquility.
I go through the things which happen according to nature until I shall fall and rest, breathing out my
breath into that element out of which I daily draw it in, and falling upon that earth out of which my
father collected the seed, and my mother the blood, and my nurse the milk; out of which during so many
years I have been supplied with food and drink; which bears me when I tread on it and abuse it for so
many purposes.
One man, when he has done a service to another, is ready to set it down to his account as a favour
conferred. Another is not ready to do this, but still in his own mind he thinks of the man as his debtor,
and he knows what he has done. A third in a manner does not even know what he has done, but he is
like a vine which has produced grapes, and seeks for nothing more after it has once produced its proper
fruit. As a horse when he has run, a dog when he has tracked the game, a bee when it has made the
honey, so a man when he has done a good act, does not call out for others to come and see, but he goes
on to another act, as a vine goes on to produce again the grapes in season.
Accept everything which happens, even if it seems disagreeable, because it leads to this, to the
health of the universe and to the prosperity and felicity of Zeus. For he would not have brought on any
man what he has brought, if it were not useful for the whole. Neither does the nature of anything,
whatever it may be, cause anything which is not suitable to that which is directed by it. For two reasons
then it is right to be content with that which happens to thee; the one, because it was done for thee and
prescribed for thee, and in a manner had reference to thee, originally from the most ancient causes spun
with thy destiny; and the other, because even that which comes severally to every man is to the power
which administers the universe a cause of felicity and perfection, nay even of its very continuance. For
the integrity of the whole is mutilated, if thou cuttest off anything whatever from the conjunction and the
continuity either of the parts or of the causes. And thou dost cut off, as far as it is in thy power, when
thou art dissatisfied, and in a manner triest to put anything out of the way.
The same things happen to another, and either because he does not see that they have happened or
because he would show a great spirit, he is firm and remains unharmed. It is a shame then that ignorance
and conceit should be stronger than wisdom.
Things themselves touch not the soul, not in the least degree; nor have they admission to the soul,
nor can they turn or move the soul: but the soul turns and moves itself alone, and whatever judgements it
may think proper to make, such it makes for itself the things which present themselves to it.
Art thou angry with him whose armpits stink? Art thou angry with him whose mouth smells foul?
What good will this danger do thee? He has such a mouth, he has such arm-pits: it is necessary that such
an emanation must come from such things—but the man has reason, it will be said, and he is able, if he
takes pain, to discover wherein he offends—I wish thee well of thy discovery.
BOOK SIX
The best way of avenging thyself is not to become like the wrong doer.
Some things are hurrying into existence, and others are hurrying out of it; and of that which is
coming into existence part is already extinguished. Motions and changes are continually renewing the
world, just as the uninterrupted course of time is always renewing the infinite duration of ages. In this
flowing stream then, on which there is no abiding, what is there of the things which hurry by on which a
man would set a high price? It would be just as if a man should fall in love with one of the sparrows
which fly by, but it has already passed out of sight. Something of this kind is the very life of every man,
like the exhalation of the blood and the respiration of the air. For such as it is to have once drawn in the
air and to have given it back, which we do every moment, just the same is it with the whole respiratory
power, which thou didst receive at thy birth yesterday and the day before, to give it back to the element
from which thou didst first draw it.
I do my duty: other things trouble me not; for they are either things without life, or things without
reason, or things that have rambled and know not the way.
It is a shame for the soul to be first to give way in this life, when thy body does not give way.
He who has seen present things has seen all.
No man will hinder thee from living according to the reason of thy own nature: nothing will happen
to thee contrary to the reason of the universal nature.
BOOK SEVEN
From Plato: But I would make this man a sufficient answer, which is this: Thou sayest not well, if
thou thinkest that a man who is good for anything at all ought to compute the hazard of life or death, and
should not rather look to this only in all that he does, whether he is doing what is just or unjust, and the
works of a good or a bad man.
Another may be more expert in casting his opponent; but he is not more social, nor more modest, nor
better disciplined to meet all that happens, nor more considerate with respect to the faults of his
neighbours.
Look within. Within is the fountain of good, and it will ever bubble up, if thou wilt ever dig.
How do we know if Telauges was not superior in character to Socrates? For it is not enough that
Socrates died a more noble death, and disputed more skilfully with the sophists, and passed the night in
the cold with more endurance, and that when he was bid to arrest Leon of Salamis, he considered it more
noble to refuse, and that he walked in a swaggering way in the streets—though as to this fact one may
have great doubts if it was true. But we ought to inquire, what kind of a soul it was that Socrates
possessed, and if he was able to be content with being just towards men and pious towards the gods,
neither idly vexed on account of men’s villainy, nor yet making himself a slave to any man’s ignorance,
nor receiving as strange anything that fell to his share out of the universal, nor enduring it as intolerable,
nor allowing his understanding to sympathize with the affects of the miserable flesh.
BOOK EIGHT
Remember that as it is a shame to be surprised if the fig-tree produces figs, so it is to be surprised if
the world produces such and such things of which it is productive; and for the physician and the
helmsman it is a shame to be surprised, if a man has a fever, or if the wind is unfavourable.
It is satisfaction to a man to do the proper works of a man. Now it is a proper work of a man to be
benevolent to his own kind, to despise the movements of the senses, to form a just judgement of
plausible appearances, and to take a survey of the nature of the universe and of the things which happen
in it.
Speak both in the senate and to every man.
If thou didst ever see a hand cut off, or a foot, or a head, lying anywhere apart from the rest of the
body, such does a man make himself, as far as he can, who is not content with what happens, and
separates himself from others, or does anything unsocial. Suppose that thou hast detached thyself from
the natural unity—for thou wast made by nature a part, but now thou hast cut thyself off—yet here there
is this beautiful provision, that it is in thy power again to unite thyself. God has allowed this to no other
part, after it has been separated and cut asunder, to come together again. But consider the kindness by
which he has distinguished man, for he has put it in his power not to be separated at all from the
universal; and when he has been separated, he has allowed him to return and to be united and to resume
his place as a part.
Say nothing more to thyself than what the first appearances report. Suppose that it has been reported
to thee that a certain person speaks ill of thee. This has been reported; but that thou hast been injured,
that has not been reported. I see that my child is sick. I do see; but that he is in danger, I do not see. Thus
then always abide by the first appearances, and add nothing thyself from within, and then nothing
happens to thee. Or rather add something, like a man who knows everything that happens in the world.
A cucumber is bitter. Throw it away. There are briars in the road. Turn aside from them. This is
enough. Do not add, And why were such things made in the world? For thou wilt be ridiculed by a man
who is acquainted with nature, as thou wouldst be ridiculed by a carpenter and shoemaker if thou didst
find fault because thou seest in their workshop shavings and cuttings from the things which they make.
And yet they have places into which they can throw these shavings and cuttings, and the universal nature
has no external space; but the wondrous part of her art is that though she has circumscribed herself,
everything within her which appears to decay and to grow old and to be useless she changes into herself,
and again makes other new things from these very same, so that she requires neither substance from
without nor wants a place into which she may cast that which decays. She is content then with her own
space, and her own matter and her own art.
Generally, wickedness does no harm at all to the universe; and particularly, the wickedness of one
man does no harm to another. It is only harmful to him who has it in his power to be released from it, as
soon as he shall choose.
Suppose that men kill thee, cut thee in pieces, curse thee. What then can these things do to prevent
thy mind from remaining pure, wise, sober, just? For instance, if a man should stand by a limpid pure
spring, and curse it, the spring never ceases sending up potable water; and if he should cast clay into it or
filth, it will speedily disperse them and wash them out, and will not be at all polluted. How then shalt
thou possess a perpetual fountain and not a mere well? By forming thyself hourly to freedom conjoined
with contentment, simplicity and modesty.
BOOK NINE
Labour not as one who is wretched, nor yet as one who would be pitied or admired: but direct thy
will to one thing only, to put thyself in motion and to check thyself, as the social reason requires.
Termination of activity, cessation from movement and opinion, and in a sense their death, is no evil.
Turn thy thoughts now to the consideration of thy life, thy life as a child, as a youth, thy manhood, thy
old age, for in these also every change was a death. Is this anything to fear? Turn thy thoughts now to
thy life under thy grandfather, then to thy life under thy mother, then to thy life under thy father; and as
thou findest many other differences and changes and terminations, ask thyself, Is this anything to fear?
In like manner, then, neither are the termination and cessation and change of thy whole life a thing to be
afraid of.
Quarrels of little children and their sports, and poor spirits carrying about dead bodies, such is
everything; and so what is exhibited in the representation of the mansions of the dead strikes our eyes
more clearly.
The universal cause is like a winter torrent: it carries everything along with it. How worthless are all
these poor people who are engaged in matters political, and, as they suppose, are playing the
philosopher! All drivellers.
Enough of this wretched life and murmuring and apish tricks. Why art thou disturbed? What is there
new in this? What unsettles thee? Is it the form of the thing? Look at it. Or is it the matter? Look at it.
But besides these there is nothing. Towards the gods, then, now become at last more simple and better. It
is the same whether we examine these things for a hundred years or three.
Observe what thy nature requires, so far as thou art governed by nature only: then do it and accept it,
if thy nature, so far as thou art a living being, shall not be made worse by it.
BOOK TEN
No longer talk at all about the kind of man that a good man ought to be, but be such.
There is no man so fortunate that there shall not be by him when he is dying some who are pleased
with what is going to happen.
BOOK ELEVEN
To expect bad men not to do wrong is madness.
Socrates used to call the opinions of the many by the name of Lamiae, bugbears to frighten children.
When a man kisses his child, said Epictetus, he should whisper to himself, “To-morrow perchance
thou wilt die.” But those are words of bad omen. "No word is a word of bad omen,” said Epictetus,
“which expresses any work of nature; or if it is so, it is also a word of bad omen to speak of the ears of
corn being reaped.”
BOOK TWELVE
All those things at which thou wishest to arrive by a circuitous road, thou canst have now, if thou
dost not refuse them to thyself. And this means, if thou wilt take no notice of all the past, and trust the
future to providence, and direct the present only conformably to piety and justice.
If it is not right, do not do it: if it is not true, do not say it.
Man, thou hast been a citizen in this great state. What difference does it make to thee whether it is
for five years or three? “But I have not finished the five acts, only the three of them.”—Thou sayest
well, but in life, the three acts are the whole drama. Depart then satisfied, for he who releases you is
satisfied.
Marcus Aurelius: Medita'ons, decoded
BOOK 2
Say this to yourself every morning: “Today, I will meet the busybodies, the ungrateful, the arrogant
and the unsocial. It’s not their fault: they do not know about good and evil. I do know. I know that the
good is beautiful and the bad is ugly. I know that these churls are just like me, but they cannot harm me.
They cannot make me feel ugly, nor can they make me hate them. In truth, we are like fingers on a
hand.”
I am nothing but flesh and breath. I must hate my flesh as if I were dying. It is nothing but blood and
bones. I am a mind, too; I am an old man and I should no longer be a slave, a puppet on strings. I will no
longer be dissatisfied, nor will I shrink from the future.
No person can die more than once. No person can live in the past or in the future. The longest life
and the shortest life are, therefore, the same: you cannot lose what you cannot have.
There are only five ways to be hurt:
1. Hate. Do not hate anything; everything that happens is a part of nature. You are a part of
nature, too.
2. Turning away from your fellow man—or worse, turning to him with anger and the intention
to harm.
3. Being overpowered by pleasure or pain.
4. Telling lies.
5. Acting purposelessly.
Life is short. Our minds are dull. Our bodies are weak. Fate is unkind. Life is a kind of warfare, and
our minds are cloudy. There is only one thing that can guide a man: philosophy. Philosophy can free us
from passions and keep us from pain and pleasure. Philosophy teaches us that we cannot change
anything, and that everything happens for a reason. For nothing is evil which is according to nature, not
even death.
BOOK 3
Everything is beautiful. Cracks in bread, gaping figs, and olives near to rotten are beautiful. A man
needs to learn to see the beauty and to feel deeply those things that the universe presents.
A good man thinks honest, pure thoughts. He would not be ashamed to show them to others, as if
they were a picnic lunch. A man like this feels no insults and acts rightly. He values only the praise of
men like himself.
A man has to stand on his own two feet.
BOOK 4
If you work at what is before you, and if you do what is right, and do it calmly, vigorously, and
purely; if you do this while expecting nothing in return and fearing nothing at all, and if you are truthful,
then you will be live happily. Nobody can prevent this.
Some men want cottages and vacations at the sea or in the mountains. You do not need to go
somewhere to find quiet; you can find quiet within yourself. Tranquility comes from a well ordered
mind.
Do not try to change others. What happens happens from necessity. To stop it is to not allow the fig
to have juice. Remember this when you feel the urge to change another person: soon you will both be
dead and not even your names will be left behind.
Do not suppose that you have been hurt, and the harm will vanish.
The only things that really injure are the things that make a person worse than she was before.
Everything happens for a good reason. If you stop to observe events unfolding, you will see both
why they must happen and why they are good. In fact, you can see that the logic of events is goodness‚
and then do what you should and must do.
Many grains of incense are thrown into the fire. One is annihilated before, another after. It makes no
difference.
Do what is good and do what is necessary. The people who thought you an ass will think you a god.
Death hangs over you. Be good while you can.
Do not be whirled about. Understand everything.
If it is good for you, sweet universe, it is good for me. Nothing is early or late for you. Nor will it be
for me. Your seasons bring fruit. Your seasons bring death. Everything comes from you. Everything will
return to you.
Do what is necessary. Do what people require. Doing so makes a man tranquil.
A good woman is satisfied with her portion and satisfied with herself.
Be a pier against which the waves break.
BOOK 5
Say this to yourself when you are tempted to laze in bed: I am rising to do the work of a person.
Why should I be angry about that? Was I made for this? Was I made for pleasure, or was I made for
action? Look around. Do the plants doze? Do the ants cuddle? Don’t the bees work for one another and
to fulfill their part in the universe? Are you unwilling to do the part of human?
It is easy to wipe away troublesome impressions and to be in all tranquility.
I will work for the universe until I fall and rest, breathing out into the world the same breath just
given me.
One woman does a favour and wants you to be grateful. Another sees it as a debt to be repaid. The
best one, though, does not know what she has done; she is like a vine producing grapes. A horse runs, a
dog hunts. They don’t ask to be repaid. Do it; move on.
You are a part of the universe. Therefore, what happens to you happens for you. What happens to
you goes on from you.
Stupid men and conceited men are often successful because they do not see or will not admit the
obstacles they face. It is a shame that ignorance and conceit are sometimes better than wisdom.
Nothing touches your soul. Your soul judges but does not touch.
Do you hate people who smell bad? Do you detest the ugly, uncool, or weird? Why? What good will
it do? They are who they are. Good luck changing them.
BOOK 6
The best way of avenging yourself is not to become like the person who wronged you.
Some things are hurrying into existence. Some things are hurrying out of it. Nothing remains for
long. A woman should not love sparrows that fly by and pass out of sight. She should not cling to life
either. Give back freely that breath that was freely given to you.
I do my duty. Other things do not bother me because they are out of my control.
It is a shame when the soul gives up before the body does.
He who has seen present things has seen all.
Nobody can stop you from following your reason. Nothing will happen to you that was not planned
by nature.
BOOK 7
Stand up, or someone else will make you stand up.
From Plato: A man who is good for anything at all ought not to measure the value of life or death,
and should only care about one thing: whether he is doing something just or unjust, doing the work of a
good or a bad man.
Another may be more expert in throwing her opponent, but that does not make her a better person.
She may not be more social, more modest, or better disciplined. She may not be as kind to her
neighbours.
Look within. There is a fountain of good, and it will bubble up forever, if you can just keep digging.
Why do we love Socrates? It was his soul. He was content with being just towards men and pious
towards the gods. He never despaired that other men were villains, nor did he allow himself to become a
slave. He never found anything strange, and he never found anything unendurable. He never allowed his
mind to sympathize with his miserable flesh.
BOOK 8
Remember that as it shameful to be surprised if the fig-tree produces figs, so it is shameful to be
surprised that the world moves on.
It is satisfying to do the work a man should do. A man should be kind, despise his senses, think
carefully, and study the universe.
Speak the same way to the important and the unimportant.
A woman who fights the nature of the world is like a foot cut off the body. However, there is a
beautiful provision: while a foot cannot be reattached, a person can rejoin the body politic.
Do not extrapolate from small facts. Say you hear rumors that your friend has been slighting you
behind your back. Maybe she has been. People talk. Maybe she has not been. You simply do not know
for sure.
You get a parking ticket. Pay it. Do not get upset with the laws, or angry that you did something
wrong—or worse, did nothing wrong. Pay it and move on. The universe still works as it should.
Wickedness does not harm the universe; in particular, it does not harm any other person. Wickedness
only harms the wicked.
Suppose you are being insulted. Suppose you are being beaten. So? What is stopping you from
keeping your mind pure, wise, sober and just? Imagine throwing mud into a spring. It lingers only a
moment and then is carried away. Be simple, free, modest and content, and you will be like the spring.
BOOK 9
Do not labour like a student, always looking over your shoulder as if you deserve pity or admiration
for all the work you have to do. Get on with it.
Do not fear change. Was there anything to fear when you became a youth or a man? No. Nor is there
anything to fear about the final change into death.
Children’s arguments and games, mansions of the dead, spirits carrying around dead bodies. This is
everything.
The universe is a river swollen with the spring thaw. Politics and the common philosophy are idiotic.
They are drivel.
Enough of this wretched life, gossip, and stupid gaming. Why not? What is there new in this? Look
at it. Besides this there is nothing.
Observe what you need, then do it and accept it. There is little to fear from doing what you must.
BOOK 10
Stop talking about what a good man is. Be a good man.
No matter how good you are, somebody will be happy to hear you are dead.
BOOK 11
To expect bad men not to do wrong is madness.
Socrates used to call the opinion of the many ‘The Boogeyman’ because it is used to frighten
children.
When a man kisses his child, said Epictetus, he should whisper to himself, “Tomorrow you may
die.”
BOOK 12
Everything you want you can have now. Forget the past, trust in the future, and be pious and good in
the present.
If it is not right, do not do it; if it is not true, do not say it.
Man, you have been a citizen of this great universe. What difference does it make to you whether it
has been for five years or three? “But I have not finished the five acts, only three of them.”—Yes, but in
life, three acts are the whole drama. Depart satisfied, for he your director is satisfied.
Nicolo Machiavelli
You may have heard of Machiavelli. He’s the subject of rap songs, I understand, and he’s given his
name to an adjective, “Machiavellian”, to describe evil, scheming people.
That’s unfortunate, since Machiavelli seems to have been a pretty nice guy. He was quite famous as
a playwright, diplomat, and military commander, but he had the good sense to have his magnum opus,
The Prince, published only after his death. It was this book that made him immortal.
The Prince is a guidebook to young up-and-comers who would seize political power, and, though it
can seem a little tame now, it was scandalizing when it was published in 1532. To understand why, it
helps to think about our preconceptions about politicians.
Bill Clinton was besieged for much of his presidency because he had an affair with an intern, and he
is just one of many politicians who has been embroiled in a sex scandal. But why does the public care
about politicians’ privates? I think we do because we expect our leaders to be both excellent public
managers and examples of morality. We expect our leaders to be good people as well as good rulers.
Machiavelli was the first writer to blow this conjunction apart. He knew that it was important to look
good; he also knew that it was often important to be bad. A prince has to do all kinds of nasty things to
stay in power.
The section of the book from which these chapters are drawn describes the ideal qualities of a
prince: generosity, kindness, and fame. Yet, according to Machiavelli, a perfect prince would appear
good but be ready to do bad.
Truly excellent philosophers are always taking their thoughts one step further. Machiavelli turns the
old ideas on their heads: he says that what appears good can actually be bad, and what appears bad can
actually be good. A kind prince who is generous with money, for instance, can bankrupt the state and
leave it vulnerable. A miserly prince would have conserved its power. Likewise, a magnanimous prince
can erode the rule of law by giving pardons. A strict prince will appear cruel but will, in the end, ensure
that his people are protect from disorder by punishing offenders.
Nicolo Machiavelli: The Prince, Edited
CHAPTER XV — CONCERNING THINGS FOR WHICH MEN, AND ESPECIALLY PRINCES, ARE PRAISED OR
BLAMED
It remains now to see what ought to be the rules of conduct for a prince towards subject and friends.
And as I know that many have written on this point, I expect I shall be considered presumptuous in
mentioning it again, especially as in discussing it I shall depart from the methods of other people. But, it
being my intention to write a thing which shall be useful to him who apprehends it, it appears to me
more appropriate to follow up the real truth of the matter than the imagination of it; for many have
pictured republics and principalities which in fact have never been known or seen, because how one
lives is so far distant from how one ought to live, that he who neglects what is done for what ought to be
done, sooner effects his ruin than his preservation; for a man who wishes to act entirely up to his
professions of virtue soon meets with what destroys him among so much that is evil.
Hence it is necessary for a prince wishing to hold his own to know how to do wrong, and to make
use of it or not according to necessity. Therefore, putting on one side imaginary things concerning a
prince, and discussing those which are real, I say that all men when they are spoken of, and chiefly
princes for being more highly placed, are remarkable for some of those qualities which bring them either
blame or praise; and thus it is that one is reputed liberal, another miserly, using a Tuscan term (because
an avaricious person in our language is still he who desires to possess by robbery, whilst we call one
miserly who deprives himself too much of the use of his own); one is reputed generous, one rapacious;
one cruel, one compassionate; one faithless, another faithful; one effeminate and cowardly, another bold
and brave; one affable, another haughty; one lascivious, another chaste; one sincere, another cunning;
one hard, another easy; one grave, another frivolous; one religious, another unbelieving, and the like.
And I know that every one will confess that it would be most praiseworthy in a prince to exhibit all the
above qualities that are considered good; but because they can neither be entirely possessed nor
observed, for human conditions do not permit it, it is necessary for him to be sufficiently prudent that he
may know how to avoid the reproach of those vices which would lose him his state; and also to keep
himself, if it be possible, from those which would not lose him it; but this not being possible, he may
with less hesitation abandon himself to them. And again, he need not make himself uneasy at incurring a
reproach for those vices without which the state can only be saved with difficulty, for if everything is
considered carefully, it will be found that something which looks like virtue, if followed, would be his
ruin; whilst something else, which looks like vice, yet followed brings him security and prosperity.
CHAPTER XVII — CONCERNING CRUELTY AND CLEMENCY, AND WHETHER IT IS BETTER TO BE LOVED
THAN FEARED
Coming now to the other qualities mentioned above, I say that every prince ought to desire to be
considered clement and not cruel. Nevertheless he ought to take care not to misuse this clemency.
Cesare Borgia was considered cruel; notwithstanding, his cruelty reconciled the Romagna, unified it,
and restored it to peace and loyalty. And if this be rightly considered, he will be seen to have been much
more merciful than the Florentine people, who, to avoid a reputation for cruelty, permitted Pistoia to be
destroyed. Therefore a prince, so long as he keeps his subjects united and loyal, ought not to mind the
reproach of cruelty; because with a few examples he will be more merciful than those who, through too
much mercy, allow disorders to arise, from which follow murders or robberies; for these are wont to
injure the whole people, whilst those executions which originate with a prince offend the individual
only.
And of all princes, it is impossible for the new prince to avoid the imputation of cruelty, owing to
new states being full of dangers. Hence Virgil, through the mouth of Dido, excuses the inhumanity of
her reign owing to its being new, saying:
Nevertheless he ought to be slow to believe and to act, nor should he himself show fear, but proceed
in a temperate manner with prudence and humanity, so that too much confidence may not make him
incautious and too much distrust render him intolerable.
Upon this a question arises: whether it be better to be loved than feared or feared than loved? It may
be answered that one should wish to be both, but, because it is difficult to unite them in one person, it is
much safer to be feared than loved, when, of the two, either must be dispensed with. Because this is to
be asserted in general of men, that they are ungrateful, fickle, false, cowardly, covetous, and as long as
you succeed they are yours entirely; they will offer you their blood, property, life, and children, as is
said above, when the need is far distant; but when it approaches they turn against you. And that prince
who, relying entirely on their promises, has neglected other precautions, is ruined; because friendships
that are obtained by payments, and not by greatness or nobility of mind, may indeed be earned, but they
are not secured, and in time of need cannot be relied upon; and men have less scruple in offending one
who is beloved than one who is feared, for love is preserved by the link of obligation which, owing to
the baseness of men, is broken at every opportunity for their advantage; but fear preserves you by a
dread of punishment which never fails.
Nevertheless a prince ought to inspire fear in such a way that, if he does not win love, he avoids
hatred; because he can endure very well being feared whilst he is not hated, which will always be as
long as he abstains from the property of his citizens and subjects and from their women. But when it is
necessary for him to proceed against the life of someone, he must do it on proper justification and for
manifest cause, but above all things he must keep his hands off the property of others, because men
more quickly forget the death of their father than the loss of their patrimony. Besides, pretexts for taking
away the property are never wanting; for he who has once begun to live by robbery will always find
pretexts for seizing what belongs to others; but reasons for taking life, on the contrary, are more difficult
to find and sooner lapse. But when a prince is with his army, and has under control a multitude of
soldiers, then it is quite necessary for him to disregard the reputation of cruelty, for without it he would
never hold his army united or disposed to its duties.
Among the wonderful deeds of Hannibal this one is enumerated: that having led an enormous army,
composed of many various races of men, to fight in foreign lands, no dissensions arose either among
them or against the prince, whether in his bad or in his good fortune. This arose from nothing else than
his inhuman cruelty, which, with his boundless valour, made him revered and terrible in the sight of his
soldiers, but without that cruelty, his other virtues were not sufficient to produce this effect. And short-
sighted writers admire his deeds from one point of view and from another condemn the principal cause
of them. That it is true his other virtues would not have been sufficient for him may be proved by the
case of Scipio, that most excellent man, not only of his own times but within the memory of man,
against whom, nevertheless, his army rebelled in Spain; this arose from nothing but his too great
forbearance, which gave his soldiers more license than is consistent with military discipline. For this he
was upbraided in the Senate by Fabius Maximus, and called the corrupter of the Roman soldiery. The
Locrians were laid waste by a legate of Scipio, yet they were not avenged by him, nor was the insolence
of the legate punished, owing entirely to his easy nature. Insomuch that someone in the Senate, wishing
to excuse him, said there were many men who knew much better how not to err than to correct the errors
of others. This disposition, if he had been continued in the command, would have destroyed in time the
fame and glory of Scipio; but, he being under the control of the Senate, this injurious characteristic not
only concealed itself, but contributed to his glory.
Returning to the question of being feared or loved, I come to the conclusion that, men loving
according to their own will and fearing according to that of the prince, a wise prince should establish
himself on that which is in his own control and not in that of others; he must endeavour only to avoid
hatred, as is noted.
CHAPTER XV — CONCERNING THINGS FOR WHICH MEN, AND ESPECIALLY PRINCES, ARE PRAISED OR
BLAMED
Most people who write about politics write about kingdoms of the imagination, places that have
never existed but which we wish had. I will write about how how a prince ought to rule in a real
kingdom. A prince who focuses on what should be done instead of what is done will soon end up dead.
A prince who wishes to hold his own ought to know how to do bad things, even if he chooses not to.
It would be nice if a prince could be liberal, kind, faithful, bold, chaste and sincere—but nobody is
perfect. A prince who was not good—but not bad either—would be second best. And, if that is not
possible, a prince should try to be bad in the best way: some vices will get a man killed and pushed from
power. Others are just kinks. Finally, a prince should never worry about doing evil things, if that means
saving the state; some virtues will get a man killed, too. Other things, which look like vices, will make a
man rich and safe.
CHAPTER XVII — CONCERNING CRUELTY AND CLEMENCY, AND WHETHER IT IS BETTER TO BE LOVED
THAN FEARED
Every prince should want to appear forgiving and not cruel. Nevertheless he ought to be careful
using clemency. Cesare Borgia was considered cruel; but his cruelty reconciled the Romagna, unified it,
and restored it to peace and loyalty. Seen rightly, Borgia was actually kinder and more merciful than the
Florentines, who allowed Pistoia to be destroyed in a riot, rather than crack down and seem cruel.
Therefore a prince, as long as he keeps his subjects united and loyal, should not mind it if people call
him cruel; he will almost always end up being more merciful than those who are soft-hearted and allow
their citizens to get away with murder and robbery. Murder and robbery affect everyone; executions
only kill one person.
New princes will have to seem cruel because new states are dangerous places. The great poet Virgil
says,
Nevertheless a prince should act slowly and consider all the facts. He should not take pleasure in
causing pain, but should always act with humanity. Otherwise his citizens will think that he is
untrustworthy.
Is it better to be loved than feared or feared than loved? It would be lovely to be both, but few people
are. Most people are jerks, and they will promise the moon until the time comes to deliver. It is easier to
break a promise to someone you love than someone you fear; for that reason, it is better to be feared
than loved.
It is possible, though, to be feared and not hated. A prince who is feared, not hated, and who does
not touch the property of women of his subjects, can stay in power for a very long time. People will
forget the death of their father faster than they will forget the loss of the inheritance he left, so it is
crucial that a prince keeps his hands off his subjects’ property. Besides which, there are infinite pretexts
for stealing, and once you are known as a robber, you will always find a reason to continue.
When you lead an army, however, you must be cruel. Armies can only be kept united by fear.
Hannibal, who led a huge army of many races across many foreign lands, had no dissension in the ranks.
He was inhumanly cruel and incredibly brave. His soldiers revered and feared him, and his cruelty held
the army together. Other writers disparage his cruelty while lauding his victories; they do not see that his
cruelty lead to his victories.
Finally, you cannot make someone love you. You can make someone fear you.
CHAPTER XXI — HOW A PRINCE SHOULD CONDUCT HIMSELF SO AS TO GAIN RENOWN
Nothing is better for a prince than doing something flashy. The King of Spain, for instance, is one of
the greatest kings in the world. As soon as he took power, he attacked Granada, and that victory laid the
foundation for his other wars. He always uses religion as a cover; with pious cruelty, he drove the Moors
out of Spain. This is the perfect example. Yet, under this same cloak, he attacked Africa, Italy and
France; and, in doing, kept his people in suspense and admiration. He has made all these attacks so
quickly that nobody has had the time to work against him.
A prince ought to do some remarkable things inside the country too. Never miss the opportunity to
reward or punish someone lavishly. This kind of thing will make people think you are a great and
remarkable person.
A prince should also always be either a true friend or downright enemy. Never take a middle ground
or nuanced position. You have nothing to gain by being neutral when your neighbours are at war. If you
choose the wrong side, and your allies are defeated, then, yes, your country may be destroyed. But if had
remained neutral, your country would still be destroyed; your conqueror has no reason not to destroy
you if you did not support him.
If you fight strenuously and gallantly beside your allies and they win, they will likely not destroy
you. Your victorious neighbour will be indebted to you, and no ruler wants to be known forever as the
ungrateful king.
If two of your smaller neighbours are at war, and you know for certain who the victor will be, there
is no doubt that you should join in the fight on the side of the victor. When you win, your ally will owe
you. However, if at all possible, you should avoid the help of more powerful countries if you are at war.
If you win, you will owe your larger neighbour, and princes should try to avoid owing anyone.
You will never be able to choose perfectly safe paths. You will always have doubts and troubles.
The trick is to take the lesser of evils.
You should also try to encourage talent. Never let your citizens feel afraid that whatever they gain
will be taken away from them. Instead, reward the successful.
Further, a prince should have festivals and spectacles throughout the year. He should make friends
with unions and groups and associate himself with them now and then. A prince should, though, always
appear courteous and generous while remaining dignified. Retaining your dignity is critical.
Thomas Hobbes
Hobbes was a late bloomer; until his forties, he wrote bad books on physics. Once he got started on
philosophy, though, he had real momentum.
It is easy to ‘psychologize’ Hobbes’ work—to try to explain it based on his social milieu. In The
Leviathan, he says that we should all obey an absolute monarch, one so powerful that he is deemed
essentially infallible. That he should give up so much (like democratic rights and freedoms) in the name
of stability might not be surprising. Hobbes lived through civil wars and terrible strife in 17th century
England; a tyrannical King embroiled in foreign conflicts was executed and replaced with a genocidal
parliament. Hobbes himself was chased out of England and had to flee to France. He then got chased out
of France and had to flee back to England. Small wonder, perhaps, that he should so highly value order.
Hobbes’ best idea is that of the ‘social contract’. This is the idea that we all give up a bit of freedom
in exchange for stability and long life. I promise to not kill you, and you promise to not kill me;
eventually, we all make that promise, and off we go: society gets rolling, and the rule of law spreads.
Agreeing to give up some freedom is perfectly sensible when you consider the alternative: the ‘state
of nature’, where there is no law, and every person must fend for herself. Life is, Hobbes says with flair,
“solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short.”
The leap from the state of nature to tyranny is pretty short for Hobbes. He considers that there might
be other suitable forms of government, but rejects them for want of stability and efficiency. A despot
just gets stuff done.
Hobbes himself seems to have been a bit of a jerk. He feuded with just about everyone. Descartes
hated him. The inventor of the infinity sign hated him. The House of Commons thought he was a
blasphemer and atheist, and he probably was. He died old, rich, and famous, though, at the age of 91.
Thomas Hobbes: The Leviathan, edited
CHAPTER XIV: OF THE FIRST AND SECOND NATURAL LAWS, AND OF CONTRACTS
The right of nature, which writers commonly call jus naturale, is the liberty each man hath to use his
own power as he will himself for the preservation of his own nature; that is to say, of his own life; and
consequently, of doing anything which, in his own judgement and reason, he shall conceive to be the
aptest means thereunto.
A law of nature, lex naturalis, is a precept, or general rule, found out by reason, by which a man is
forbidden to do that which is destructive of his life, or taketh away the means of preserving the same,
and to omit that by which he thinketh it may be best preserved. For though they that speak of this subject
used to confound jus and lex, right and law, yet they ought to be distinguished, because right consisteth
in liberty to do, or to forbear; whereas law determineth and bindeth to one of them: so that law and right
differ as much as obligation and liberty, which in one and the same matter are inconsistent.
And because the condition of man (as hath been declared in the precedent chapter) is a condition of
war of every one against every one, in which case every one is governed by his own reason, and there is
nothing he can make use of that may not be a help unto him in preserving his life against his enemies; it
followeth that in such a condition every man has a right to every thing, even to one another’s body. And
therefore, as long as this natural right of every man to every thing endureth, there can be no security to
any man, how strong or wise soever he be, of living out the time which nature ordinarily alloweth men
to live. And consequently it is a precept, or general rule of reason: that every man ought to endeavour
peace, as far as he has hope of obtaining it; and when he cannot obtain it, that he may seek and use all
helps and advantages of war. The first branch of which rule containeth the first and fundamental law of
nature, which is: to seek peace and follow it. The second, the sum of the right of nature, which is: by all
means we can to defend ourselves.
From this fundamental law of nature, by which men are commanded to endeavour peace, is derived
this second law: that a man be willing, when others are so too, as far forth as for peace and defence of
himself he shall think it necessary, to lay down this right to all things; and be contented with so much
liberty against other men as he would allow other men against himself. For as long as every man holdeth
this right, of doing anything he liketh; so long are all men in the condition of war. But if other men will
not lay down their right, as well as he, then there is no reason for anyone to divest himself of his: for that
were to expose himself to prey, which no man is bound to, rather than to dispose himself to peace. This
is that law of the gospel: Whatsoever you require that others should do to you, that do ye to them. And
that law of all men, quod tibi fieri non vis, alteri ne feceris.
Whensoever a man transferreth his right, or renounceth it, it is either in consideration of some right
reciprocally transferred to himself, or for some other good he hopeth for thereby. For it is a voluntary
act: and of the voluntary acts of every man, the object is some good to himself.
The mutual transferring of right is that which men call contract.
If a covenant be made wherein neither of the parties perform presently, but trust one another, in the
condition of mere nature (which is a condition of war of every man against every man) upon any
reasonable suspicion, it is void: but if there be a common power set over them both, with right and force
sufficient to compel performance, it is not void. For he that performeth first has no assurance the other
will perform after, because the bonds of words are too weak to bridle men’s ambition, avarice, anger,
and other passions, without the fear of some coercive power; which in the condition of mere nature,
where all men are equal, and judges of the justness of their own fears, cannot possibly be supposed. And
therefore he which performeth first does but betray himself to his enemy, contrary to the right he can
never abandon of defending his life and means of living.
But in a civil estate, where there a power set up to constrain those that would otherwise violate their
faith, that fear is no more reasonable; and for that cause, he which by the covenant is to perform first is
obliged so to do.
Men are freed of their covenants two ways; by performing, or by being forgiven. For performance is
the natural end of obligation, and forgiveness the restitution of liberty, as being a retransferring of that
right in which the obligation consisted.
A former covenant makes void a later. For a man that hath passed away his right to one man today
hath it not to pass tomorrow to another: and therefore the later promise passeth no right, but is null.
A covenant not to defend myself from force, by force, is always void. For (as I have shown before)
no man can transfer or lay down his right to save himself from death, wounds, and imprisonment, the
avoiding whereof is the only end of laying down any right; and therefore the promise of not resisting
force, in no covenant transferreth any right, nor is obliging. For though a man may covenant thus, unless
I do so, or so, kill me; he cannot covenant thus, unless I do so, or so, I will not resist you when you come
to kill me. For man by nature chooseth the lesser evil, which is danger of death in resisting, rather than
the greater, which is certain and present death in not resisting. And this is granted to be true by all men,
in that they lead criminals to execution, and prison, with armed men, notwithstanding that such criminals
have consented to the law by which they are condemned.
A covenant to accuse oneself, without assurance of pardon, is likewise invalid. For in the condition
of nature where every man is judge, there is no place for accusation: and in the civil state the accusation
is followed with punishment, which, being force, a man is not obliged not to resist. The same is also true
of the accusation of those by whose condemnation a man falls into misery; as of a father, wife, or
benefactor. For the testimony of such an accuser, if it be not willingly given, is presumed to be corrupted
by nature, and therefore not to be received: and where a man’s testimony is not to be credited, he is not
bound to give it. Also accusations upon torture are not to be reputed as testimonies. For torture is to be
used but as means of conjecture, and light, in the further examination and search of truth: and what is in
that case confessed tendeth to the ease of him that is tortured, not to the informing of the torturers, and
therefore ought not to have the credit of a sufficient testimony: for whether he deliver himself by true or
false accusation, he does it by the right of preserving his own life.
The force of words being (as I have formerly noted) too weak to hold men to the performance of
their covenants, there are in man’s nature but two imaginable helps to strengthen it. And those are either
a fear of the consequence of breaking their word, or a glory or pride in appearing not to need to break it.
This latter is a generosity too rarely found to be presumed on, especially in the pursuers of wealth,
command, or sensual pleasure, which are the greatest part of mankind. The passion to be reckoned upon
is fear; whereof there be two very general objects: one, the power of spirits invisible; the other, the
power of those men they shall therein offend. Of these two, though the former be the greater power, yet
the fear of the latter is commonly the greater fear.
CHAPTER 14: THE FIRST AND SECOND NATURAL LAWS, AND CONTRACTS
Natural justice is the freedom of each person to preserve her own life, and to do the things required
to stay alive.
Laws are not rights. The difference between a right and a law is this: rights allow the freedom to do
or not to do. Laws require adherence or action. Laws and rights are like obligations and liberties. This is
a law: No person can destroy herself or take away the things that keep her alive. This is a right: each
person has the right to stay alive.
And because a person at war can make use of absolutely everything to preserve her own life, in a
state of war, everyone has rights to everything, even to another’s life or body. For as long as we are at
war with one another, there is no security, even for the wise and strong. It is, therefore, a universal rule
of reason that every person should work for peace as long as she has a chance of obtaining it. If she has
no chance, then she is free to do what he must. The first law of nature, then, is this: seek peace and
follow it. The first right of nature is this: do all you can to defend yourself.
The second law of nature is derived from the first: a person must be willing (when others are too) to
end a war. She must also be willing to waive her right to all things and be happy with only as many
rights as she would allow others to have. Of course, as long as one person is unwilling to embrace peace,
there is no reason for anyone to do so; otherwise the holdout would become a hawk among doves.
Nonetheless, it is the law of the gospel: do unto others as you would have them do unto you. When
others are willing to lay down their rights, we all must be willing.
People give up their rights out of self-interest, not kindness. We might give one right away to get
another in exchange. We give up rights voluntarily, and all voluntary rights are done out of self-interest.
A contract is when parties mutually transfer rights.
If two people make promises for the future while in the state of nature (i.e. war), the contract is void.
But if there is a common power that can prevail over them both, then the contract holds. In war, though,
nobody can expect to be repaid, since promises are just empty words.
But when there is a government, where there a power set up to restrain those people that would lie
and cheat, there is no reasonable fear of being betrayed.
Covenants entered into by fear in the state of war are binding. If I promise to pay a ransom, I must
keep my promise. It is a contract like any other. Unless there is a new cause of fear that would renew the
war, I must keep my promise. Even when there is a government, I am bound to pay debts accrued in
fear, at least until the legitimate law exonerates me. A contract is a contract.
An earlier contract trumps a later contract. The same right cannot be given away twice.
It is impossible to promise to not defend oneself. I can’t say “I swear on my life”, because when the
time comes for you to kill me, I’ll take my chances with resisting (where at least I have a chance),
instead of letting you kill me (when I would obviously have none).
Similarly, I cannot admit to being guilty of a crime unless I will be entirely pardoned. I can never be
obliged to admit to force being used on me. Likewise, the testimony given under torture cannot be
trusted. The tortured are trying to preserve their lives and end their misery.
There are only two reasons a person keeps her word: fear and pride. Pride cannot be relied on,
especially when it comes to people who pursue wealth, power and pleasure, which is to say, most of us.
Fear is the only guarantor of performance, and there are two things people generally fear: God and
punishment. God is more powerful, but punishment is more persuasive.
There is something about English philosophers that I really love. Germans? An angry people. The
French are incomprehensible. Americans are wrong but figure they’re close enough. But the English?
They do philosophy right. They are all gentlemanly, modest, charming—and correct.
Locke is no exception, and he stands astride English philosophy and history like a giant. He may be
the greatest English philosopher ever, and it’s a competitive field. He wrote brilliantly about politics,
epistemology, and economics. He was a great doctor and tried to have the King of England assassinated
in his spare time. For a lark, he became father of America (the Constitution is based on his ideas).
Apart from the Constitution, if you ask me, Locke’s most important contribution is his defense of
empiricism and his idea of the soul. He takes the idea of the soul away from the religious and the wacky,
and he wipes it clean; if you don’t see yourself as tainted with sin or capable of learning everything
important without leaving the house, you have Locke to thank.
In this passage from An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Locke is doing epistemology, and
he is attacking some of those philosophical nutters—people like Descartes. They are called ‘rationalists’,
and they believe (more or less) that the truest knowledge can be found through introspection and pure
thought. They do not believe in science, or ‘empiricism’—the practice of basing our ideas on external
facts.
Locke is going after ‘innate ideas’. These are ideas that we are all supposed to have, or are all
supposed to be able to discover with a little introspection.
Ethical, logical, geometric, and mathematical ideas are the kinds of things that seem innate. Locke,
though, thinks that they cannot be. He believes that when we are born, our minds are ‘blank slates’, or
‘tabula rasa’, and everything we know, we learned. You, if you’re like almost everyone I know, agree.
John Locke: An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, edited
BOOK I, CHAPTER I
There is nothing more commonly taken for granted, than that there are certain principles, both
speculative and practical (for they speak of both) universally agreed upon by all mankind: which
therefore, they argue, must needs be constant impressions, which the souls of men receive in their first
beings, and which they bring into the world with them, as necessarily and really as they do any of their
inherent faculties.
This argument, drawn from universal consent, has this misfortune in it, that if it were true in matter
of fact, that there were certain truths, wherein all mankind agreed, it would not prove them innate, if
there can be any other way shewn, how men may come to that universal agreement, in the things they do
consent in; which I presume may be done.
But, which is worse, this argument of universal consent, which is made use of to prove innate
principles, seems to me a demonstration that there are none such; because there are none to which all
mankind give a universal assent. I shall begin with the speculative, and instance in those magnified
principles of demonstration; “whatsoever is, is;” and, “it is impossible for the same thing to be, and not
to be;” which, of all others, I think have the most allowed title to innate. These have so settled a
reputation of maxims universally received, that it will, no doubt, be thought strange, if any one should
seem to question it. But yet I take liberty to say, that these propositions are so far from having a
universal assent, that there are a great part of mankind to whom they are not so much as known.
For, first, it is evident, that all children and idiots have not the least apprehension or thought of them;
and the want of that is enough to destroy that universal assent, which must needs be the necessary
concomitant of all innate truths: it seeming to me near a contradiction, to say, that there are truths
imprinted on the soul, which it perceives or understands not; imprinting, if it signify any thing, being
nothing else, but the making certain truths to be perceived. For to imprint any thing on the mind, without
the mind’s perceiving it, seems to me hardly intelligible. If therefore children and idiots have souls, have
minds, with those impressions upon them, they must unavoidably perceive them, and necessarily know
and assent to these truths: which since they do not, it is evident that there are no such impressions. For if
they are not notions naturally imprinted, how can they be innate? and if they are notions imprinted, how
can they be unknown? To say a notion is imprinted on the mind, and yet at the same time to say, that the
mind is ignorant of it, and never yet took notice of it, is to make this impression nothing. No proposition
can be said to be in the mind, which it never yet knew, which it was never yet conscious of. For if any
one may, then, by the same reason, all propositions that are true, and the mind is capable of ever
assenting to, may be said to be in the mind, and to be imprinted: since, if any one can be said to be in the
mind, which it never yet knew, it must be only, because it is capable of knowing it, and so the mind is of
all truths it ever shall know. Nay, thus truths may be imprinted on the mind, which it never did, nor ever
shall know: for a man may live long, and die at last in ignorance of many truths, which his mind was
capable of knowing, and that with certainty. So that if the capacity of knowing, be the natural impression
contended for, all the truths a man ever comes to know, will, by this account, be every one of them
innate; and this great point will amount to no more, but only to a very improper way of speaking; which,
whilst it pretends to assert the contrary, says nothing different from those, who deny innate principles.
….
To avoid this, it is usually answered, That all men know and assent to them, when they come to the
use of reason, and this is enough to prove them innate. I answer,
Doubtful expressions that have scarce any signification, go for clear reasons, to those, who being
prepossessed, take not the pains to examine, even what they themselves say. For to apply this answer
with any tolerable sense to our present purpose, it must signify one of these two things; either, that, as
soon as men come to the use of reason, these supposed native inscriptions come to be known, and
observed by them: or else, that the use and exercise of men’s reason assists them in the discovery of
these principles, and certainly makes them known to them.
If they mean, that by the use of reason men may discover these principles; and that this is sufficient
to prove them innate: their way of arguing will stand thus, (viz.) that, whatever truths reason can
certainly discover to us, and make us firmly assent to, those are all naturally imprinted on the mind;
since that universal assent, which is made the mark of them, amounts to no more but this; that by the use
of reason, we are capable to come to a certain knowledge of, and assent to them; and, by this means,
there will be no difference between the maxims of the mathematicians, and theorems they deduce from
them; all must be equally allowed innate; they being all discoveries made by the use of reason, and
truths that a rational creature may certainly come to know, if he apply his thoughts rightly that way.
But how can these men think the use of reason necessary, to discover principles that are supposed
innate, when reason (if we may believe them) is nothing else but the faculty of deducing unknown truths
from principles, or propositions, that are already known? That certainly can never be thought innate,
which we have need of reason to discover; unless, as I have said, we will have all the certain truths, that
reason ever teaches us, to be innate. We may as well think the use of reason necessary to make our eyes
discover visible objects, as that there should be need of reason, or the exercise thereof, to make the
understanding see what is originally engraven on it, and cannot be in the understanding before it be
perceived by it. So that to make reason discover those truths, thus imprinted, is to say, that the use of
reason discovers to a man what he knew before: and if men have those innate impressed truths
originally, and before the use of reason, and yet are always ignorant of them, till they come to the use of
reason, it is in effect to say, that men know, and know them not, at the same time.
It will here perhaps be said, that mathematical demonstrations, and other truths that are not innate,
are not assented to, as soon as proposed, wherein they are distinguished from these maxims, and other
innate truths. I shall have occasion to speak of assent, upon the first proposing, more particularly by and
by. I shall here only, and that very readily, allow, that these maxims and mathematical demonstrations
are in this different; that the one have need of reason, using of proofs, to make them out, and to gain our
assent; but the other, as soon as understood, are, without any the least reasoning, embraced and assented
to. But I withal beg leave to observe, that it lays open the weakness of this subterfuge, which requires
the use of reason for the discovery of these general truths: since it must be confessed, that in their
discovery there is no use made of reasoning at all. And I think those, who give this answer, will not be
forward to affirm, that the knowledge of this maxim, “That it is impossible for the same thing to be, and
not to be,” is a deduction of our reason. For this would be to destroy that bounty of nature they seem so
fond of, whilst they make the knowledge of those principles to depend on the labour of our thoughts. For
all reasoning is search, and casting about, and requires pains and application. And how can it with any
tolerable sense be supposed, that what was imprinted by nature, as the foundation and guide of our
reason, should need the use of reason to discover it?
Those who will take the pains to reflect with a little attention on the operations of the understanding,
will find, that this ready assent of the mind to some truths, depends not, either on native inscription, or
the use of reason; but on a faculty of the mind quite distinct from both of them, as we shall see hereafter.
Reason, therefore, having nothing to do in procuring our assent to these maxims, if by saying, that men
know and assent to them, when they come to the use of reason, be meant, that the use of reason assists
us in the knowledge of these maxims, it is utterly false; and were it true, would prove them not to be
innate.
If by knowing and assenting to them, when we come to the use of reason, be meant, that this is the
time when they come to be taken notice of by the mind; and that, as soon as children come to the use of
reason, they come also to know and assent to these maxims; this also is false and frivolous. First, It is
false: Because it is evident these maxims are not in the mind so early as the use of reason: and therefore
the coming to the use of reason is falsely assigned, as the time of their discovery. How many instances
of the use of reason may we observe in children, a long time before they have any knowledge of this
maxim, “That it is impossible for the same thing to be, and not to be?” And a great part of illiterate
people, and savages, pass many years, even of their rational age, without ever thinking on this, and the
like general propositions. I grant, men come not to the knowledge of these general and more abstract
truths, which are thought innate, till they come to the use of reason; and I add, nor then neither. Which is
so, because, till after they come to the use of reason, those general abstract ideas are not framed in the
mind, about which those general maxims are, which are mistaken for innate principles; but are indeed
discoveries made, and verities introduced and brought into the mind by the same way, and discovered by
the same steps, as several other propositions, which nobody was ever so extravagant as to suppose
innate. This I hope to make plain in the sequel of this discourse. I allow therefore a necessity, that men
should come to the use of reason before they get the knowledge of those general truths; but deny, that
men’s coming to the use of reason is the time of their discovery.
In the mean time it is observable, that this saying, That men know and assent to these maxims, when
they come to the use of reason, amounts in reality of fact to no more but this, That they are never known
or taken notice of, before the use of reason, but may possibly be assented to, some time after, during a
man’s life; but when, is uncertain: and so may all other knowable truths, as well as these; which
therefore have no advantage nor distinction from others, by this note of being known when we come to
the use of reason; nor are thereby proved to be innate, but quite the contrary.
But, secondly, were it true, that the precise time of their being known, and assented to, were, when
men come the use of reason, neither would that prove them innate. This way of arguing is as frivolous,
as the supposition of itself is false. For by what kind of logic will it appear, that any notion is originally
by nature imprinted in the mind in its first constitution, because it comes first to be observed and
assented to, when a faculty of the mind, which has quite a distinct province, begins to exert itself? And
therefore, the coming to the use of speech, if it were supposed the time that these maxims are first
assented to (which it may be with as much truth, as the time when men come to the use of reason) would
be as good a proof that they were innate, as to say, they are innate, because men assent to them, when
they come to the use of reason. I agree then with these men of innate principles, that there is no
knowledge of these general and self-evident maxims in the mind, till it comes to the exercise of reason:
but I deny that the coming to the use of reason is the precise time when they are first taken notice of; and
if that were the precise time, I deny that it would prove them innate. All that can with any truth be meant
by this proposition, that men assent to them when they come to the use of reason, is no more but this,
that the making of general abstract ideas, and the understanding of general names, being a concomitant
of the rational faculty, and growing up with it, children commonly get not those general ideas, nor learn
the names that stand for them, till, having for a good while exercised their reason about familiar and
more particular ideas, they are, by their ordinary discourse and actions with others, acknowledged to be
capable of rational conversation. If assenting to these maxims, when men come to the use of reason, can
be true in any other sense, I desire it may be shewn; or at least, how in this, or any other sense, it proves
them innate.
The senses at first let in particular ideas, and furnish the yet empty cabinet; and the mind by degrees
growing familiar with some of them, they are lodged in the memory, and names got to them. Afterwards
the mind, proceeding farther, abstracts them, and by degrees learns the use of general names. In this
manner the mind comes to be furnished with ideas and language, the materials about which to exercise
its discursive faculty: and the use of reason becomes daily more visible, as these materials, that give it
employment, increase. But though the having of general ideas, and the use of general words and reason,
usually grow together; yet, I see not, how this any way proves them innate. The knowledge of some
truths, I confess, is very early in the mind; but in a way that shows them not to be innate. For, if we will
observe, we shall find it still to be about ideas, not innate, but acquired: It being about those first which
are imprinted by external things, with which infants have earliest to do, which make the most frequent
impressions on their senses. In ideas thus got, the mind discovers that some agree, and others differ,
probably as soon as it has any use of memory; as soon as it is able to retain and perceive distinct ideas.
But whether it be then, or no, this is certain, it does so, long before it has the use of words, or comes to
that, which we commonly call “the use of reason.” For a child knows as certainly, before it can speak,
the difference between the ideas of sweet and bitter (i.e. that sweet is not bitter) as it knows afterwards
(when it comes to speak) that wormwood and sugar-plums are not the same thing.
A child knows not that three and four are equal to seven, till he comes to be able to count seven, and
has got the name and idea of equality: and then, upon explaining those words, he presently assents to, or
rather perceives the truth of that proposition. But neither does he then readily assent, because it is an
innate truth, nor was his assent wanting till then, because he wanted the use of reason; but the truth of it
appears to him, as soon as he has settled in his mind the clear and distinct ideas, that these names stand
for: and then he knows the truth of that proposition, upon the same grounds, and by the same means, that
he knew before, that a rod and a cherry are not the same thing; and upon the same grounds also, that he
may come to know afterwards, “that it is impossible for the same thing to be, and not to be,” as shall be
more fully shown hereafter. So that the later it is before any one comes to have those general ideas,
about which those maxims are; or to know the signification of those general terms that stand for them; or
to put together in his mind the ideas they stand for; the later also will it be before he comes to assent to
those maxims, whose terms, with the ideas they stand for, being no more innate than those of a cat or a
weasel, he must stay till time and observation have acquainted him with them; and then he will be in a
capacity to know the truth of these maxims, upon the first occasion that shall make him put together
those ideas in his mind, and observe whether they agree or disagree, according as is expressed in those
propositions. And therefore it is, that a man knows that eighteen and nineteen are equal to thirty-seven,
by the same self-evidence, that he knows one and two to be equal to three: yet a child knows this not so
soon as the other; not for want of the use of reason, but because the ideas the words eighteen, nineteen,
and thirty-seven stand for, are not so soon got, as those which are signified by one, two, and three.
But we have not yet done with assenting to propositions at first hearing and understanding their
terms; it is fit we first take notice, that this, instead of being a mark that they are innate, is a proof of the
contrary; since it supposes, that several, who understand and know other things, are ignorant of these
principles, till they are proposed to them; and that one may be unacquainted with these truths, till he
hears them from others. For if they were innate, what need they be proposed in order to gaining assent,
when by being in the understanding, by a natural and original impression, (if there were any such) they
could not but be known before? Or doth the proposing them, print them clearer in the mind than nature
did? If so, then the consequence will be, that a man knows them better, after he has been thus taught
them, than he did before. Whence it will follow, that these principles may be made more evident to us by
others teaching, than nature has made them by impression; which will ill agree with the opinion of
innate principles, and give but little authority to them; but, on the contrary, makes them unfit to be the
foundations of all our other knowledge, as they are pretended to be. This cannot be denied, that men
grow first acquainted with many of these self-evident truths, upon their being proposed: but it is clear,
that whosoever does so, finds in himself, that he then begins to know a proposition, which he knew not
before; and which, from thenceforth, he never questions: not because it was innate, but because the
consideration of the nature of the things contained in those words, would not suffer him to think
otherwise, how, or whensoever he is brought to reflect on them. And if whatever is assented to at first
hearing and understanding the terms, must pass for an innate principle, every well-grounded
observation, drawn from particulars into a general rule, must be innate. When yet it is certain, that not
all, but only sagacious heads light at first on these observations, and reduce them into general
propositions, not innate, but collected from a preceding acquaintance, and reflection on particular
instances. These, when observing men have made them, unobserving men, when they are proposed to
them, cannot refuse their assent to.
To conclude this argument of universal consent, I agree with these defenders of innate principles,
that if they are innate, they must needs have universal assent. For that a truth should be innate, and yet
not assented to, is to me as unintelligible, as for a man to know a truth, and be ignorant of it, at the same
time. But then, by these men’s own confession, they cannot be innate; since they are not assented to by
those who understand not the terms, nor by a great part of those who do understand them, but have yet
never heard nor thought of those propositions; which, I think, is at least one half of mankind. But were
the number far less, it would be enough to destroy universal assent, and thereby show these propositions
not to be innate, if children alone were ignorant of them.
BOOK II.
Every man being conscious to himself that he thinks, and that which his mind is applied about,
whilst thinking, being the ideas that are there, it is past doubt, that men have in their minds several ideas,
such as are those expressed by the words, Whiteness, Hardness, Sweetness, Thinking, Motion, Man,
Elephant, Army, Drunkenness, and others. It is in the first place then to be inquired, how he comes by
them. I know it is a received doctrine, that men have native ideas, and original characters, stamped upon
their minds, in their very first being. This opinion I have, at large, examined already; and, I suppose,
what I have said, in the foregoing book, will be much more easily admitted, when I have shewn, whence
the understanding may get all the ideas it has, and by what ways and degrees they may come into the
mind; for which I shall appeal to every one’s own observation and experience.
Let us then suppose the mind to be, as we say, white paper, void of all characters, without any ideas;
how comes it to be furnished? Whence comes it by that vast store which the busy and boundless fancy
of man has painted on it, with an almost endless variety? Whence has it all the materials of reason and
knowledge? To this I answer, in one word, from experience; in all that our knowledge is founded, and
from that it ultimately derives itself. Our observation employed either about external sensible objects, or
about the internal operations of our minds, perceived and reflected on by ourselves, is that which
supplies our understandings with all the materials of thinking. These two are the fountains of
knowledge, from whence all the ideas we have, or can naturally have, do spring.
First, Our senses, conversant about particular sensible objects, do convey into the mind several
distinct perceptions of things, according to those various ways wherein those objects do affect them: and
thus we come by those ideas we have, of Yellow, White, Heat, Cold, Soft, Hard, Bitter, Sweet, and all
those which we call sensible qualities; which when I say the senses convey into the mind, I mean, they
from external objects convey into the mind what produces there those perceptions. This great source of
most of the ideas we have, depending wholly upon our senses, and derived by them to the
understanding, I call sensation.
Secondly, The other fountain, from which experience furnisheth the understanding with ideas, is the
perception of the operations of our own mind within us, as it is employed about the ideas it has got;
which operations, when the soul comes to reflect on and consider, do furnish the understanding with
another set of ideas, which could not be had from things without; and such are Perception, Thinking,
Doubting, Believing, Reasoning, Knowing, Willing, and all the different actings of our own minds;
which we being conscious of and observing in ourselves, do from these receive into our understandings
as distinct ideas, as we do from bodies affecting our senses. This source of ideas every man has wholly
in himself; and though it be not sense, as having nothing to do with external objects, yet it is very like it,
and might properly enough be called internal sense. But as I call the other sensation, so I call this
reflection, the ideas it affords being such only as the mind gets by reflecting on its own operations
within itself. By reflection then, in the following part of this discourse, I would be understood to mean
that notice which the mind takes of its own operations, and the manner of them; by reason whereof there
come to be ideas of these operations in the understanding. These two, I say, viz. external material things,
as the objects of sensation; and the operations of our own minds within, as the objects of reflection; are
to me the only originals from whence all our ideas take their beginnings. The term operations here I use
in a large sense, as comprehending not barely the actions of the mind about its ideas, but some sort of
passions arising sometimes from them, such as is the satisfaction or uneasiness arising from any thought.
The understanding seems to me not to have the least glimmering of any ideas, which it doth not
receive from one of these two. External objects furnish the mind with the ideas of sensible qualities,
which are all those different perceptions they produce in us: and the mind furnishes the understanding
with ideas of its own operations.
These, when we have taken a full survey of them and their several modes, combinations, and
relations, we shall find to contain all our whole stock of ideas; and that we have nothing in our minds
which did not come in one of these two ways. Let any one examine his own thoughts, and thoroughly
search into his understanding; and then let him tell me, whether all the original ideas he has there, are
any other than of the objects of his senses, or of the operations of his mind, considered as objects of his
reflection; and how great a mass of knowledge soever he imagines to be lodged there, he will, upon
taking a strict view, see that he has not any idea in his mind, but what one of these two have imprinted;
though perhaps, with infinite variety compounded and enlarged by the understanding, as we shall see
hereafter.
He that attentively considers the state of a child, at his first coming into the world, will have little
reason to think him stored with plenty of ideas, that are to be the matter of his future knowledge: It is by
degrees he comes to be furnished with them. Light and colours are busy at hand every-where, when the
eye is but open; sounds and some tangible qualities fail not to solicit their proper senses, and force an
entrance to the mind: but yet, I think, it will be granted easily, that if a child were kept in a place where
he never saw any other but black and white till he were a man, he would have no more ideas of scarlet or
green, than he that from his childhood never tasted an oyster or a pineapple has of those particular
relishes.
Men are differently furnished with these, according to the different objects they converse with.
Men then come to be furnished with fewer or more simple ideas from without, according as the
objects they converse with afford greater or less variety; and from the operations of their minds within,
according as they more or less reflect on them. For though he that contemplates the operations of his
mind cannot but have plain and clear ideas of them; yet unless he turns his thoughts that way, and
considers them attentively, he will no more have clear and distinct ideas of all the operations of his
mind, and all that may be observed therein, than he will have all the particular ideas of any landscape, or
of the parts and motions of a clock, who will not turn his eyes to it, and with attention heed all the parts
of it. The picture or clock may be so placed, that they may come in his way every day; but yet he will
have but a confused idea of all the parts they are made up of, till he applies himself with attention to
consider them each in particular.
And hence we see the reason why it is pretty late before most children get ideas of the operations of
their own minds; and some have not any very clear or perfect ideas of the greatest part of them all their
lives: because though they pass there continually, yet, like floating visions, they make not deep
impressions enough to leave in their mind clear, distinct, lasting ideas, till the understanding turns
inward upon itself, reflects on its own operations, and makes them the objects of its own contemplation.
Children when they come first into it, are surrounded with a world of new things, which, by a constant
solicitation of their senses, draw the mind constantly to them, forward to take notice of new, and apt to
be delighted with the variety of changing objects. Thus the first years are usually employed and diverted
into looking abroad. Men’s business in them is to acquaint themselves with what is to be found without:
and so growing up in a constant attention to outward sensation, seldom make any considerable reflection
on what passes within them till they come to be of riper years; and some scarce ever at all.
Follow a child from its birth, and observe the alterations that time makes, and you shall find, as the
mind by the senses comes more and more to be furnished with ideas, it comes to be more and more
awake; thinks more, the more it has matter to think on. After some time it begins to know the objects,
which, being most familiar with it, have made lasting impressions. Thus it comes by degrees to know the
persons it daily converses with, and distinguish them from strangers; which are instances and effects of
its coming to retain and distinguish the ideas the senses convey to it. And so we may observe how the
mind, by degrees, improves in these, and advances to the exercise of those other faculties of enlarging,
compounding, and abstracting its ideas, and of reasoning about them, and reflecting upon all these; of
which I shall have occasion to speak more hereafter.
If it shall be demanded then, when a man begins to have any ideas; I think the true answer is, when
he first has any sensation. For since there appear not to be any ideas in the mind, before the senses have
conveyed any in, I conceive that ideas in the understanding are coeval with sensation; which is such an
impression or motion, made in some part of the body, as produces some perception in the understanding.
It is about these impressions made on our senses by outward objects, that the mind seems first to employ
itself in such operations as we call perception, remembering, consideration, reasoning, &c.
In time the mind comes to reflect on its own operations about the ideas got by sensation, and thereby
stores itself with a new set of ideas, which I call ideas of reflection. These are the impressions that are
made on our senses by outward objects that are extrinsical to the mind, and its own operations,
proceeding from powers intrinsical and proper to itself; which when reflected on by itself, becoming
also objects of its contemplation, are, as I have said, the original of all knowledge. Thus the first
capacity of human intellect is, that the mind is fitted to receive the impressions made on it; either
through the senses by outward objects; or by its own operations when it reflects on them. This is the first
step a man makes towards the discovery of any thing, and the ground-work whereon to build all those
notions which ever he shall have naturally in this world. All those sublime thoughts which tower above
the clouds, and reach as high as heaven itself, take their rise and footing here: in all that good extent
wherein the mind wanders, in those remote speculations, it may seem to be elevated with, it stirs not one
jot beyond those ideas which sense or reflection have offered for its contemplation.
In this part the understanding is merely passive; and whether or no it will have these beginnings, and
as it were materials of knowledge, is not in its own power. For the objects of our senses do, many of
them, obtrude their particular ideas upon our minds whether we will or no; and the operations of our
minds will not let us be without, at least, some obscure notions of them. No man can be wholly ignorant
of what he does when he thinks. These simple ideas, when offered to the mind, the understanding can no
more refuse to have, nor alter, when they are imprinted, nor blot them out, and make new ones itself,
than a mirror can refuse, alter, or obliterate the images or ideas which the objects set before it do therein
produce. As the bodies that surround us do diversely affect our organs, the mind is forced to receive the
impressions, and cannot avoid the perception of those ideas that are annexed to them.
Though the qualities that affect our senses are, in the things themselves, so united and blended, that
there is no separation, no distance between them; yet it is plain, the ideas they produce in the mind enter
by the senses simple and unmixed. For though the sight and touch often take in from the same object, at
the same time, different ideas; as a man sees at once motion and colour; the hand feels softness and
warmth in the same piece of wax: yet the simple ideas, thus united in the same subject, are as perfectly
distinct as those that come in by different senses: the coldness and hardness which a man feels in a piece
of ice being as distinct ideas in the mind, as the smell and whiteness of a lily; or as the taste of sugar,
and smell of a rose. And there is nothing can be plainer to a man, than the clear and distinct perception
he has of those simple ideas; which, being each in itself uncompounded, contains in it nothing but one
uniform appearance, or conception in the mind, and is not distinguishable into different ideas.
These simple ideas, the materials of all our knowledge, are suggested and furnished to the mind only
by those two ways above-mentioned, viz. sensation and reflection. When the understanding is once
stored with these simple ideas, it has the power to repeat, compare, and unite them, even to an almost
infinite variety; and so can make at pleasure new complex ideas. But it is not in the power of the most
exalted wit, or enlarged understanding, by any quickness or variety of thought, to invent or frame one
new simple idea in the mind, not taken in by the ways aforementioned: nor can any force of the
understanding destroy those that are there. The dominion of man, in this little world of his own
understanding, being much-what the same as it is in the great world of visible things; wherein his power,
however managed by art and skill, reaches no farther than to compound and divide the materials that are
made to his hand; but can do nothing towards the making the least particle of new matter, or destroying
one atom of what is already in being. The same inability will every one find in himself, who shall go
about to fashion in his understanding any simple idea, not received in by his senses from external
objects, or by reflection from the operations of his own mind about them. I would have any one try to
fancy any taste, which had never affected his palate; or frame the idea of a scent he had never smelt: and
when he can do this, I will also conclude that a blind man hath ideas of colours, and a deaf man true
distinct notions of sounds.
When children have, by repeated sensations, got ideas fixed in their memories, they begin by
degrees to learn the use of signs. And when they have got the skill to apply the organs of speech to the
framing of articulate sounds, they begin to make use of words, to signify their ideas to others. These
verbal signs they sometimes borrow from others, and sometimes make themselves, as one may observe
among the new and unusual names children often give to things in the first use of language.
The use of words then being to stand as outward marks of our internal ideas, and those ideas being
taken from particular things, if every particular idea that we take in should have a distinct name, names
must be endless. To prevent this, the mind makes the particular ideas received from particular objects to
become general; which is done by considering them as they are in the mind such appearances, separate
from all other existences, and the circumstances of real existence, as time, place, or any other
concomitant ideas. This is called abstraction, whereby ideas taken from particular beings become
general representatives of all of the same kind; and their names general names, applicable to whatever
exists conformable to such abstract ideas. Such precise, naked appearances in the mind, without
considering how, whence, or with what others they came there, the understanding lays up (with names
commonly annexed to them) as the standards to rank real existences into sorts, as they agree with these
patterns, and to denominate them accordingly. Thus the same colour being observed to-day in chalk or
snow, which the mind yesterday received from milk, it considers that appearance alone, makes it a
representative of all of that kind; and having given it the name whiteness, it by that sound signifies the
same quality wheresoever to be imagined or met with; and thus universals, whether ideas or terms, are
made.
We have hitherto considered those ideas, in the reception whereof the mind is only passive, which
are those simple ones received from sensation and reflection before mentioned, whereof the mind cannot
make one to itself, nor have any idea which does not wholly consist of them. But as the mind is wholly
passive in the reception of all its simple ideas, so it exerts several acts of its own, whereby out of its
simple ideas as the materials and foundations of the rest, the other are framed. The acts of the mind,
wherein it exerts its power over its simple ideas, are chiefly these three: 1. Combining several simple
ideas into one compound one, and thus all complex ideas are made. 2. The second is bringing two ideas,
whether simple or complex, together, and setting them by one another, so as to take a view of them at
once, without uniting them into one; by which way it gets all its ideas of relations. 3. The third is
separating them from all other ideas that accompany them in their real existence; this is called
abstraction: and thus all its general ideas are made. This shows man’s power, and its ways of operation,
to be much what the same in the material and intellectual world. For the materials in both being such as
he has no power over, either to make or destroy, all that man can do is either to unite them together, or
to set them by one another, or wholly separate them. I shall here begin with the first of these in the
consideration of complex ideas, and come to the other two in their due places. As simple ideas are
observed to exist in several combinations united together, so the mind has a power to consider several of
them united together as one idea; and that not only as they are united in external objects, but as itself has
joined them. Ideas thus made up of several simple ones put together, I call complex; such as are beauty,
gratitude, a man, an army, the universe; which though complicated of various simple ideas, or complex
ideas made up of simple ones, yet are, when the mind pleases, considered each by itself as one entire
thing, and signified by one name.
In this faculty of repeating and joining together its ideas, the mind has great power in varying and
multiplying the objects of its thoughts, infinitely beyond what sensation or reflection furnishes it with;
but all this still confined to those simple ideas which it received from those two sources, and which are
the ultimate materials of all its compositions: for simple ideas are all from things themselves, and of
these the mind can have no more, nor other than what are suggested to it. It can have no other ideas of
sensible qualities than what come from without by the senses; nor any ideas of other kind of operations
of a thinking substance than what it finds in itself; but when it has once got these simple ideas, it is not
confined barely to observation, and what offers itself from without: it can, by its own power, put
together those ideas it has, and make new complex ones, which it never received so united.
John Locke: An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, decoded
BOOK 2, CHAPTER 2
Rationalist philosophers think that we have ‘innate ideas’—ideas that we are born with, or which
were stamped into our minds. I think I can explain how we have these ideas without having to say they
are innate. If I can do that, then I think everyone will agree that we do not have innate ideas at all.
Nature is too parsimonious to duplicate faculties. There would be no reason to put ideas of colour in our
minds when we have the faculty of sight.
The rationalists think that there are certain principles that are universally agreed to, and therefore
that we must have been born with them. These ideas have ‘universal assent’.
This idea of universal assent does not prove anything of the kind, if I can show that there are other
ways we could have got these ideas. And I can.
Worse, the rationalists’ own argument can be turned against them. If there is no such thing as
universal assent, then there are no innate ideas. There are two propositions that everyone is said to agree
to: “What is, is,” and “It is impossible for the same thing to be and not to be”. The problem is, not
everyone agrees to these two propositions—and therefore, these propositions show that there is no such
thing as an innate idea. I think that most people have not even heard that “What is, is” and “It is
impossible for the same thing to be and not to be”.
Children and idiots, for instance, do not know those propositions. And that is that! A single counter-
example is enough to disprove this idea of universal assent and the idea of innate truths. It seems like a
contraction to me to say that there are truths imprinted in our minds that we do not know about, or that
there are truths we know but cannot perceive or understand. If imprinting means anything, it means that
there are truths we know and perceive. If, therefore, children and idiots have souls or minds with those
impressions upon them, they must perceive them. They must know and assent to these truths. Since they
don’t, it is evident that there are no such impressions—it just doesn’t make sense to say that we possess
some truth in our minds but do not know it. Minds are for knowing.
Some rationalists will say that we have an innate capacity to know, and that this capacity for
knowing is innate, and therefore that our ideas are innate. That is cheating. If we talk like that,
everything a person ever comes to know through education and life was always actually innate, and, in
fact, all the things she never came to know were innate, too.
Let me be clear: if we know something, we know that we know it. We cannot have knowledge that is
unperceived or not understood.
To avoid this criticism, my opponents usually say that people know and assent to innate ideas when
the are old enough to use reason. I answer:
Rationalists must mean one of two things: either people become aware of these innate ideas when
they start to think, or the use of reason helps them find innate ideas.
If they mean that reason helps them discover these principles, their argument, clearly stated, is this:
If reason discovers a truth, and if reason makes us firmly believe it, then that truth is an innate idea and
was naturally imprinted on the mind. Universal assent, the characteristic of innate ideas, amounts to no
more than this: innate ideas are those certain facts we conclude. That means that all the truths of
mathematics, for instance, no matter how obscure, are innate.
But how could reason be necessary to discover things that are supposed to be innate? Innate ideas
are the very ideas that we are not supposed to need to discover. Innate means ‘No need to discover’! We
may as well say that reason is necessary for the eyes to see. If we have innate ideas that we need reason
to find, then we are really saying that we both know things and do not know them.
The rationalist might say mathematical proofs and other truths are not obvious, and that makes them
different from other innate truths. I agree! Maxims and mathematical demonstrations are different from
each other. Math requires proof; maxims are obvious and do not require proof. But this makes the
rationalist’s subterfuge clear: no reasoning at all is required for a priori truths, and math is not a priori.
Limiting the innate ideas to the obvious destroys the bounty of nature that rationalists are so fond of.
Rationalists say that we know innate ideas when we come to “when we come to the use of reason”.
As soon as children become intelligent, they also know and assent to these maxims, in other words. This
is false and ridiculous. First, obviously, a priori truths are not in the mind when we start to reason.
Children learn to think long before they learn “It is impossible for the same thing to be and not to be”. In
fact, the illiterate and savages grow quite old not knowing that “It is impossible for the same thing to be
and not to be”. I do think that reason is necessary to discover ideas like these, but I do not think that
these ideas arrive in the mind at the same time as the faculty of reason.
What the rationalist really means is this: nobody knows a priori truths until after they learn to think.
But that doesn’t prove very much.
Even learning innate ideas at the same time as we learned to think would not prove that innate ideas
are innate. If we started to speak at the same time that we learned these innate ideas, would rationalists
say that speaking proved them to be innate?
I agree that we do not know self-evident maxims until we begin to use reason. But I deny that they
spring to mind when we start to use reason, and I deny that that would prove them to be innate.
What we really mean when we say people “assent to these ideas when they come to the use of
reason,” is this: Abstract ideas and general names come after children practice on more familiar and
particular things, and after adults realize that their kids are capable of rational conversation. Obviously,
this does not show that these abstract ideas are innate.
The mind actually works much differently. First, the senses let in particular ideas and furnish the
‘empty cabinet’ of our minds or memories. The mind grows more familiar with the ideas bit by bit, and
some get lodged in our long-term memory, and they get names. Next, the mind abstracts from the
particular ideas and by degrees learns the general names of things. This is how the mind gets ideas and
language, and gets the objects on which it uses its discursive faculty—the faculty that uses
argumentation and logic.
In a child, the use of reason become more and more obvious day by day as it learns about greater
numbers of things. If we watch someone learning, though, we see that their ideas are not innate.
Children learn about the things they see most often, and they learn that some things are alike and some
things are different. They learn this even before they can speak or think—certainly about the things that
matter to them, ideas like sweet and bitter.
We assent to clear ideas, not ideas that are innate. A child does not learn that 3+4=7 until she learns
about seven and equality. Once she knows these ideas, she will assent to the equation, but not because
the idea is innate. She will assent because the idea is obvious and because she has learned what each of
the terms means. Our minds move from the small to the large, too; a man knows that 18+19=37 in the
same way that he knows 1+2=3, but a child learns one before the other, because the ideas of ‘eighteen’,
‘nineteen’, and ‘thirty-seven’ take longer to get to.
The fact that propositions need to be heard and understood before being assented to shows that ideas
are never innate. Most people do not know the innate ideas they are supposed to possess until they hear
them proposed by someone else. Then they assent to them. Doesn’t this show that proposing an idea
prints it clearer in the mind than nature did? If so, then a person knows a fact better after he has been
taught it. If this is so, then it would be very unwise to make innate ideas the foundation of our
knowledge, as rationalists want to do.
Obviously, people first learn of these self-evident truths when they are taught them. Anyone taught
them must know that he can no longer deny them—not because they are innate, but because they are
true, and he could no longer think otherwise.
To conclude, I agree with these defenders of innate principles—that if they are innate, they must
have universal assent. If something is innate, then all people will assent to it. But, by their own
confession, rationalists cannot hold that there are innate principles, because these ‘innate’ ideas are not
universally assented to. People who do not understand and people who would understand but have not
yet heard to propositions do not give their assent.
BOOK 2
Every person knows that she thinks, and what she thinks about. We think about whiteness, hardness,
sweetness, thinking, motion, man, elephants, armies, and drunkenness.
How do we get these ideas? Many people say that we get them stamped upon our minds before we
are born. I think that what I have already said about this will be more accepted once I have proved my
theory.
Imagine the mind is a white piece of paper. How does it come to get ideas? Where do we get all the
variety of human thought? In a word: experience. All our knowledge is about either objects of sensation
or the operation of our own minds. That is all. These are the two fountains of our knowledge, and from
them all ideas spring.
First, our senses give our minds several different perceptions of things, according the the ways that
things affect the senses. We have ideas of yellow, white, heat, cold, hard, soft, bitter and sweet, and all
the other sensible qualities. External things give us these ideas. Most of the ideas we have come straight
from our senses. I call this source of ideas, ‘sensation’.
The other fountain from which experience furnishes the understanding with ideas is the perception
of the operations of our own minds. This gives us another set of ideas, such as perception, thinking,
doubting, believing, reasoning, knowing, willing, and so on. Every person has the source of these ideas
within herself, in a kind of internal sense, which is similar to the external sense. So, since I call the other
sense, ‘sensation’, I call this one ‘reflection’. By this, I mean the notice the mind takes of its own
operations.
These two, sensation and reflection, are the sources of all ideas. I include emotions, too, as a kind of
reflection.
The understanding has no other source of ideas.
Nobody can find an idea within themselves that did not originally come from one of these two
sources.
Children do not come with innate ideas. They find them everywhere. When their eyes and ears are
open, senses force themselves on the child. And if, for instance, a child were raised in a black-and-white
world, she would have no more idea of scarlet or green than she has of the taste of an oyster or
pineapple.
We only get new ideas from new objects.
The more things we encounter, and the more diverse they are, and the more we think about those
things, the more ideas we get. The operations of our minds are plan and clear once we start to
contemplate them, but it is easy to just go through life without stopping to think about how we think. We
can spend our whole lives walking a clock every morning without ever wondering how it works. Our
minds are just the same.
Most children do not think about their own minds, and some people never stop to think about
themselves. Youth is full of diversion and novelty, and it is only in old age that we have the time to
think about thinking, and even then many do not.
If you follow a child from its birth, you will find that it gradually awakens to the world as it
experiences more things. After a while, it comes to know objects, then friends and strangers. And so, by
degrees, the child enlarges, compounds, and abstracts ideas, and reflects on these operations.
When do people start to have ideas? When the start to sense. An impression on some part of the
body produces a sensation in the mind. These are the building blocks of perception, remembering,
consideration, reasoning, etc.
In time the mind comes up with new ideas: the ideas of reflection. Still, all the towers of intellect
have their foundations in sensation and reflection. No matter where the mind wanders, it always started
here.
In this part the understanding is passive; whether it gets this foundation for knowledge is not in its
power. Other sensations stick themselves into our minds, and no person is ever totally ignorant of them.
The mind can simply neither forget nor ignore some simple ideas any more than a mirror can refuse to
reflect.
Though all the qualities of an object are mixed together in the thing itself, when they reach us, they
enter the mind alone and unmixed. When I hold a candle, I sense many things from only one object:
whiteness, coolness, softness. I see motion, and colour, and all of these ideas are distinct. The simple
ideas, even though they are all mixed together in the same object, are as perfectly distinct as if they
came from different objects. The coolness and hardness in one piece of ice is as distinct as the smell and
the whiteness in a lily or the taste of sugar and the smell of a rose. Simple ideas each have a single
uniform appearance or conception in my mind, and cannot be broken down into other ideas.
These simple ideas come into the mind in only one of those two ways. The understanding can repeat,
compare, and unite them and can create new and complex ideas, but it cannot create any completely new
simple idea. Not even a genius can create a new simple idea; nor can a genius take one apart. The power
of man is to compound and divide the material of in his mind, but he does not have the power to create
new matter or to destroy even an atom of the ideas already there. Try to imagine a flavour you have
never tasted, or a scent you have never smelled. Blind people have no ideas of colours, nor do deaf
people have any idea of sounds.
Once children begin to remember ideas, they learn to use signs, and when they learn to speak and
make sounds, they use words to show others their ideas. Children sometimes learn words and sometimes
make them up, as anyone who spends time with them will know.
We do not have an infinite number of names, though, so we cannot create a new word for each
particular thing. Eventually, we generalize and start creating general names by abstraction. The mind
considers particular things away from their circumstances in time and place and so on. We take ideas
from particular things and make them representatives of their kind through abstraction, then give them
general names. So, we see that chalk is white and snow is white, so we come up with the idea of
whiteness. We use these simple concepts to organize and sort real things.
So far, we have only been concerned with the simple ideas that the mind receives passively. But the
mind can frame and create new ideas from these building blocks by combining simple ideas, comparing
them side by side, or by separating them from their accompanying ideas by abstraction.
Combined simple ideas are ‘complex’ ideas. These are ideas like beauty, gratitude, a man, an army,
and the universe. These are simple ideas all rolled together and baked into one big idea that we consider
one thing and call by one name.
This faculty of the mind is very powerful. The mind can build infinitely from the blocks sensation
gave it. Still, all the ideas is builds with came from only two places: from things themselves and from
the mind’s recombination of those simple ideas.
David Hume
Hume was one smart guy. He started university at 10. He wrote one of the greatest books of
philosophy when he was 26.
His early life, though, seems to have been a bit of a disaster. His father died when David was only
two. Nobody liked his first book—the important one—and after he graduated, because he was sick all
the time, he couldn’t keep a job.
When Hume applied for the “Chair of Pneumatics and Moral Philosophy” (a job title I would kill
for), he was turned down. He applied for another professorship, and was turned down again. Out of
desperation, he tutored the Marquess of Annandale—but he turned out to be insane.
Hume then tried to fight against the French in Quebec, but the boats never made it. He tried to fight
the French in France, but the raid failed. He went to work as a librarian, but got fired for ordering porn
for the library.
While a librarian, though, Hume wrote the book that made him rich, a History of England.
Unsurprisingly, he became vastly more popular, and, oddly, especially with the French, who he had only
recently tried to kill. Apparently, French women just loved him. He did eventually move home to
England, but he never stopped having parties with the young and beautiful.
In his late fifties, he fell in love with Nancy Orde, who was a total fox, smart, and by all accounts a
real catch. Orde loved him in return, and they may even have been engaged. Hume died, however, of
stomach cancer—cheerfully though, as usual.
Hume was the last of the triumvirate of British empiricists. Empiricists believe that we attain
knowledge through our senses and by studying the external world.
To us, of course, this seems obvious. Recall, though, Descartes belief: the senses are plainly fallible,
and it is impossible to build a sound science upon them. In the following selection, Hume builds the
argument in reverse: he takes the senses seriously and trusts them. Surprisingly, thoughtful empiricism
brings us right back to a point very near skepticism: almost everything is thrown into doubt. And so,
despite being separated by a century, a language, and an ideology, Hume and Descartes turn out to have
something in common.
David Hume: An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, edited
PART I
All the objects of human reason or enquiry may naturally be divided into two kinds, to wit, Relations
of Ideas, and Matters of Fact. Of the first kind are the sciences of Geometry, Algebra, and Arithmetic;
and in short, every affirmation which is either intuitively or demonstratively certain. That the square of
the hypotenuse is equal to the square of the two sides, is a proposition which expresses a relation
between these figures. That three times five is equal to the half of thirty, expresses a relation between
these numbers. Propositions of this kind are discoverable by the mere operation of thought, without
dependence on what is anywhere existent in the universe. Though there never were a circle or triangle in
nature, the truths demonstrated by Euclid would for ever retain their certainty and evidence.
Matters of fact, which are the second objects of human reason, are not ascertained in the same
manner; nor is our evidence of their truth, however great, of a like nature with the foregoing. The
contrary of every matter of fact is still possible; because it can never imply a contradiction, and is
conceived by the mind with the same facility and distinctness, as if ever so conformable to reality. That
the sun will not rise to-morrow is no less intelligible a proposition, and implies no more contradiction
than the affirmation, that it will rise. We should in vain, therefore, attempt to demonstrate its falsehood.
Were it demonstratively false, it would imply a contradiction, and could never be distinctly conceived
by the mind.
It may, therefore, be a subject worthy of curiosity, to enquire what is the nature of that evidence
which assures us of any real existence and matter of fact, beyond the present testimony of our senses, or
the records of our memory. This part of philosophy, it is observable, has been little cultivated, either by
the ancients or moderns; and therefore our doubts and errors, in the prosecution of so important an
enquiry, may be the more excusable; while we march through such difficult paths without any guide or
direction. They may even prove useful, by exciting curiosity, and destroying that implicit faith and
security, which is the bane of all reasoning and free enquiry. The discovery of defects in the common
philosophy, if any such there be, will not, I presume, be a discouragement, but rather an incitement, as is
usual, to attempt something more full and satisfactory than has yet been proposed to the public.
All reasonings concerning matter of fact seem to be founded on the relation of Cause and Effect. By
means of that relation alone we can go beyond the evidence of our memory and senses. If you were to
ask a man, why he believes any matter of fact, which is absent; for instance, that his friend is in the
country, or in France; he would give you a reason; and this reason would be some other fact; as a letter
received from him, or the knowledge of his former resolutions and promises. A man finding a watch or
any other machine in a desert island, would conclude that there had once been men in that island. All our
reasonings concerning fact are of the same nature. And here it is constantly supposed that there is a
connexion between the present fact and that which is inferred from it. Were there nothing to bind them
together, the inference would be entirely precarious. The hearing of an articulate voice and rational
discourse in the dark assures us of the presence of some person: Why? because these are the effects of
the human make and fabric, and closely connected with it. If we anatomize all the other reasonings of
this nature, we shall find that they are founded on the relation of cause and effect, and that this relation is
either near or remote, direct or collateral. Heat and light are collateral effects of fire, and the one effect
may justly be inferred from the other.
If we would satisfy ourselves, therefore, concerning the nature of that evidence, which assures us of
matters of fact, we must enquire how we arrive at the knowledge of cause and effect.
I shall venture to affirm, as a general proposition, which admits of no exception, that the knowledge
of this relation is not, in any instance, attained by reasonings a priori; but arises entirely from
experience, when we find that any particular objects are constantly conjoined with each other. Let an
object be presented to a man of ever so strong natural reason and abilities; if that object be entirely new
to him, he will not be able, by the most accurate examination of its sensible qualities, to discover any of
its causes or effects. Adam, though his rational faculties be supposed, at the very first, entirely perfect,
could not have inferred from the fluidity and transparency of water that it would suffocate him, or from
the light and warmth of fire that it would consume him. No object ever discovers, by the qualities which
appear to the senses, either the causes which produced it, or the effects which will arise from it; nor can
our reason, unassisted by experience, ever draw any inference concerning real existence and matter of
fact.
This proposition, that causes and effects are discoverable, not by reason but by experience, will
readily be admitted with regard to such objects, as we remember to have once been altogether unknown
to us; since we must be conscious of the utter inability, which we then lay under, of foretelling what
would arise from them. Present two smooth pieces of marble to a man who has no tincture of natural
philosophy; he will never discover that they will adhere together in such a manner as to require great
force to separate them in a direct line, while they make so small a resistance to a lateral pressure. Such
events, as bear little analogy to the common course of nature, are also readily confessed to be known
only by experience; nor does any man imagine that the explosion of gunpowder, or the attraction of a
loadstone, could ever be discovered by arguments a priori. In like manner, when an effect is supposed to
depend upon an intricate machinery or secret structure of parts, we make no difficulty in attributing all
our knowledge of it to experience. Who will assert that he can give the ultimate reason, why milk or
bread is proper nourishment for a man, not for a lion or a tiger?
But the same truth may not appear, at first sight, to have the same evidence with regard to events,
which have become familiar to us from our first appearance in the world, which bear a close analogy to
the whole course of nature, and which are supposed to depend on the simple qualities of objects, without
any secret structure of parts. We are apt to imagine that we could discover these effects by the mere
operation of our reason, without experience. We fancy, that were we brought on a sudden into this
world, we could at first have inferred that one Billiard-ball would communicate motion to another upon
impulse; and that we needed not to have waited for the event, in order to pronounce with certainty
concerning it. Such is the influence of custom, that, where it is strongest, it not only covers our natural
ignorance, but even conceals itself, and seems not to take place, merely because it is found in the highest
degree.
But to convince us that all the laws of nature, and all the operations of bodies without exception, are
known only by experience, the following reflections may, perhaps, suffice. Were any object presented to
us, and were we required to pronounce concerning the effect, which will result from it, without
consulting past observation; after what manner, I beseech you, must the mind proceed in this operation?
It must invent or imagine some event, which it ascribes to the object as its effect; and it is plain that this
invention must be entirely arbitrary. The mind can never possibly find the effect in the supposed cause,
by the most accurate scrutiny and examination. For the effect is totally different from the cause, and
consequently can never be discovered in it. Motion in the second Billiard-ball is a quite distinct event
from motion in the first; nor is there anything in the one to suggest the smallest hint of the other. A stone
or piece of metal raised into the air, and left without any support, immediately falls: but to consider the
matter a priori, is there anything we discover in this situation which can beget the idea of a downward,
rather than an upward, or any other motion, in the stone or metal? And as the first imagination or
invention of a particular effect, in all natural operations, is arbitrary, where we consult not experience;
so must we also esteem the supposed tie or connexion between the cause and effect, which binds them
together, and renders it impossible that any other effect could result from the operation of that cause.
When I see, for instance, a Billiard-ball moving in a straight line towards another; even suppose motion
in the second ball should by accident be suggested to me, as the result of their contact or impulse; may I
not conceive, that a hundred different events might as well follow from that cause? May not both these
balls remain at absolute rest? May not the first ball return in a straight line, or leap off from the second
in any line or direction? All these suppositions are consistent and conceivable. Why then should we give
the preference to one, which is no more consistent or conceivable than the rest? All our reasonings a
priori will never be able to show us any foundation for this preference.
In a word, then, every effect is a distinct event from its cause. It could not, therefore, be discovered
in the cause, and the first invention or conception of it, a priori, must be entirely arbitrary. And even
after it is suggested, the conjunction of it with the cause must appear equally arbitrary; since there are
always many other effects, which, to reason, must seem fully as consistent and natural. In vain,
therefore, should we pretend to determine any single event, or infer any cause or effect, without the
assistance of observation and experience.
Hence we may discover the reason why no philosopher, who is rational and modest, has ever
pretended to assign the ultimate cause of any natural operation, or to show distinctly the action of that
power, which produces any single effect in the universe. It is confessed, that the utmost effort of human
reason is to reduce the principles, productive of natural phenomena, to a greater simplicity, and to
resolve the many particular effects into a few general causes, by means of reasonings from analogy,
experience, and observation. But as to the causes of these general causes, we should in vain attempt their
discovery; nor shall we ever be able to satisfy ourselves, by any particular explication of them. These
ultimate springs and principles are totally shut up from human curiosity and enquiry. Elasticity, gravity,
cohesion of parts, communication of motion by impulse; these are probably the ultimate causes and
principles which we shall ever discover in nature; and we may esteem ourselves sufficiently happy, if,
by accurate enquiry and reasoning, we can trace up the particular phenomena to, or near to, these general
principles. The most perfect philosophy of the natural kind only staves off our ignorance a little longer:
as perhaps the most perfect philosophy of the moral or metaphysical kind serves only to discover larger
portions of it. Thus the observation of human blindness and weakness is the result of all philosophy, and
meets us at every turn, in spite of our endeavours to elude or avoid it.
Nor is geometry, when taken into the assistance of natural philosophy, ever able to remedy this
defect, or lead us into the knowledge of ultimate causes, by all that accuracy of reasoning for which it is
so justly celebrated. Every part of mixed mathematics proceeds upon the supposition that certain laws
are established by nature in her operations; and abstract reasonings are employed, either to assist
experience in the discovery of these laws, or to determine their influence in particular instances, where it
depends upon any precise degree of distance and quantity. Thus, it is a law of motion, discovered by
experience, that the moment or force of any body in motion is in the compound ratio or proportion of its
solid contents and its velocity; and consequently, that a small force may remove the greatest obstacle or
raise the greatest weight, if, by any contrivance or machinery, we can increase the velocity of that force,
so as to make it an overmatch for its antagonist. Geometry assists us in the application of this law, by
giving us the just dimensions of all the parts and figures which can enter into any species of machine;
but still the discovery of the law itself is owing merely to experience, and all the abstract reasonings in
the world could never lead us one step towards the knowledge of it. When we reason a priori, and
consider merely any object or cause, as it appears to the mind, independent of all observation, it never
could suggest to us the notion of any distinct object, such as its effect; much less, show us the
inseparable and inviolable connexion between them. A man must be very sagacious who could discover
by reasoning that crystal is the effect of heat, and ice of cold, without being previously acquainted with
the operation of these qualities.
PART II
But we have not yet attained any tolerable satisfaction with regard to the question first proposed.
Each solution still gives rise to a new question as difficult as the foregoing, and leads us on to farther
enquiries. When it is asked, What is the nature of all our reasonings concerning matter of fact? The
proper answer seems to be, that they are founded on the relation of cause and effect. When again it is
asked, What is the foundation of all our reasonings and conclusions concerning that relation? It may be
replied in one word, Experience. But if we still carry on our sifting humour, and ask, What is the
foundation of all conclusions from experience? This implies a new question, which may be of more
difficult solution and explication. Philosophers, that give themselves airs of superior wisdom and
sufficiency, have a hard task when they encounter persons of inquisitive dispositions, who push them
from every corner to which they retreat, and who are sure at last to bring them to some dangerous
dilemma. The best expedient to prevent this confusion, is to be modest in our pretensions; and even to
discover the difficulty ourselves before it is objected to us. By this means, we may make a kind of merit
of our very ignorance.
I shall content myself, in this section, with an easy task, and shall pretend only to give a negative
answer to the question here proposed. I say then, that, even after we have experience of the operations of
cause and effect, our conclusions from that experience are not founded on reasoning, or any process of
the understanding. This answer we must endeavour both to explain and to defend.
It must certainly be allowed, that nature has kept us at a great distance from all her secrets, and has
afforded us only the knowledge of a few superficial qualities of objects; while she conceals from us
those powers and principles on which the influence of those objects entirely depends. Our senses inform
us of the colour, weight, and consistence of bread; but neither sense nor reason can ever inform us of
those qualities which fit it for the nourishment and support of a human body. Sight or feeling conveys an
idea of the actual motion of bodies; but as to that wonderful force or power, which would carry on a
moving body forever in a continued change of place, and which bodies never lose but by communicating
it to others; of this we cannot form the most distant conception. But notwithstanding this ignorance of
natural powers and principles, we always presume, when we see like sensible qualities, that they have
like secret powers, and expect that effects, similar to those which we have experienced, will follow from
them. If a body of like colour and consistence with that bread, which we have formerly eat, be presented
to us, we make no scruple of repeating the experiment, and foresee, with certainty, like nourishment and
support. Now this is a process of the mind or thought, of which I would willingly know the foundation.
It is allowed on all hands that there is no known connexion between the sensible qualities and the secret
powers; and consequently, that the mind is not led to form such a conclusion concerning their constant
and regular conjunction, by anything which it knows of their nature. As to past Experience, it can be
allowed to give direct and certain information of those precise objects only, and that precise period of
time, which fell under its cognizance: but why this experience should be extended to future times, and to
other objects, which for aught we know, may be only in appearance similar; this is the main question on
which I would insist. The bread, which I formerly eat, nourished me; that is, a body of such sensible
qualities was, at that time, endued with such secret powers: but does it follow, that other bread must also
nourish me at another time, and that like sensible qualities must always be attended with like secret
powers? The consequence seems nowise necessary. At least, it must be acknowledged that there is here
a consequence drawn by the mind; that there is a certain step taken; a process of thought, and an
inference, which wants to be explained. These two propositions are far from being the same, I have
found that such an object has always been attended with such an effect, and I foresee, that other objects,
which are, in appearance, similar, will be attended with similar effects. I shall allow, if you please, that
the one proposition may justly be inferred from the other: I know, in fact, that it always is inferred. But
if you insist that the inference is made by a chain of reasoning, I desire you to produce that reasoning.
The connexion between these propositions is not intuitive. There is required a medium, which may
enable the mind to draw such an inference, if indeed it be drawn by reasoning and argument. What that
medium is, I must confess, passes my comprehension; and it is incumbent on those to produce it, who
assert that it really exists, and is the origin of all our conclusions concerning matter of fact.
This negative argument must certainly, in process of time, become altogether convincing, if many
penetrating and able philosophers shall turn their enquiries this way and no one be ever able to discover
any connecting proposition or intermediate step, which supports the understanding in this conclusion.
But as the question is yet new, every reader may not trust so far to his own penetration, as to conclude,
because an argument escapes his enquiry, that therefore it does not really exist. For this reason it may be
requisite to venture upon a more difficult task; and enumerating all the branches of human knowledge,
endeavour to show that none of them can afford such an argument.
All reasonings may be divided into two kinds, namely, demonstrative reasoning, or that concerning
relations of ideas, and moral reasoning, or that concerning matter of fact and existence. That there are no
demonstrative arguments in the case seems evident; since it implies no contradiction that the course of
nature may change, and that an object, seemingly like those which we have experienced, may be
attended with different or contrary effects. May I not clearly and distinctly conceive that a body, falling
from the clouds, and which, in all other respects, resembles snow, has yet the taste of salt or feeling of
fire? Is there any more intelligible proposition than to affirm, that all the trees will flourish in December
and January, and decay in May and June? Now whatever is intelligible, and can be distinctly conceived,
implies no contradiction, and can never be proved false by any demonstrative argument or abstract
reasoning a priori.
If we be, therefore, engaged by arguments to put trust in past experience, and make it the standard of
our future judgement, these arguments must be probable only, or such as regard matter of fact and real
existence, according to the division above mentioned. But that there is no argument of this kind, must
appear, if our explication of that species of reasoning be admitted as solid and satisfactory. We have said
that all arguments concerning existence are founded on the relation of cause and effect; that our
knowledge of that relation is derived entirely from experience; and that all our experimental conclusions
proceed upon the supposition that the future will be conformable to the past. To endeavour, therefore,
the proof of this last supposition by probable arguments, or arguments regarding existence, must be
evidently going in a circle, and taking that for granted, which is the very point in question.
In reality, all arguments from experience are founded on the similarity which we discover among
natural objects, and by which we are induced to expect effects similar to those which we have found to
follow from such objects. And though none but a fool or madman will ever pretend to dispute the
authority of experience, or to reject that great guide of human life, it may surely be allowed a
philosopher to have so much curiosity at least as to examine the principle of human nature, which gives
this mighty authority to experience, and makes us draw advantage from that similarity which nature has
placed among different objects. From causes which appear similar we expect similar effects. This is the
sum of all our experimental conclusions. Now it seems evident that, if this conclusion were formed by
reason, it would be as perfect at first, and upon one instance, as after ever so long a course of experience.
But the case is far otherwise. Nothing is so like as eggs; yet no one, on account of this appearing
similarity, expects the same taste and relish in all of them. It is only after a long course of uniform
experiments in any kind, that we attain a firm reliance and security with regard to a particular event.
Now where is that process of reasoning which, from one instance, draws a conclusion, so different from
that which it infers from a hundred instances that are nowise different from that single one? This
question I propose as much for the sake of information, as with an intention of raising difficulties. I
cannot find, I cannot imagine any such reasoning. But I keep my mind still open to instruction, if any
one will vouchsafe to bestow it on me.
Should it be said that, from a number of uniform experiments, we infer a connexion between the
sensible qualities and the secret powers; this, I must confess, seems the same difficulty, couched in
different terms. The question still recurs, on what process of argument this inference is founded? Where
is the medium, the interposing ideas, which join propositions so very wide of each other? It is confessed
that the colour, consistence, and other sensible qualities of bread appear not, of themselves, to have any
connexion with the secret powers of nourishment and support. For otherwise we could infer these secret
powers from the first appearance of these sensible qualities, without the aid of experience; contrary to
the sentiment of all philosophers, and contrary to plain matter of fact. Here, then, is our natural state of
ignorance with regard to the powers and influence of all objects. How is this remedied by experience? It
only shows us a number of uniform effects, resulting from certain objects, and teaches us that those
particular objects, at that particular time, were endowed with such powers and forces. When a new
object, endowed with similar sensible qualities, is produced, we expect similar powers and forces, and
look for a like effect. From a body of like colour and consistence with bread we expect like nourishment
and support. But this surely is a step or progress of the mind, which wants to be explained. When a man
says, I have found, in all past instances, such sensible qualities conjoined with such secret powers: And
when he says, Similar sensible qualities will always be conjoined with similar secret powers, he is not
guilty of a tautology, nor are these propositions in any respect the same. You say that the one
proposition is an inference from the other. But you must confess that the inference is not intuitive;
neither is it demonstrative: Of what nature is it, then? To say it is experimental, is begging the question.
For all inferences from experience suppose, as their foundation, that the future will resemble the past,
and that similar powers will be conjoined with similar sensible qualities. If there be any suspicion that
the course of nature may change, and that the past may be no rule for the future, all experience becomes
useless, and can give rise to no inference or conclusion. It is impossible, therefore, that any arguments
from experience can prove this resemblance of the past to the future; since all these arguments are
founded on the supposition of that resemblance. Let the course of things be allowed hitherto ever so
regular; that alone, without some new argument or inference, proves not that, for the future, it will
continue so. In vain do you pretend to have learned the nature of bodies from your past experience.
Their secret nature, and consequently all their effects and influence, may change, without any change in
their sensible qualities. This happens sometimes, and with regard to some objects: Why may it not
happen always, and with regard to all objects? What logic, what process of argument secures you against
this supposition? My practice, you say, refutes my doubts. But you mistake the purport of my question.
As an agent, I am quite satisfied in the point; but as a philosopher, who has some share of curiosity, I
will not say scepticism, I want to learn the foundation of this inference. No reading, no enquiry has yet
been able to remove my difficulty, or give me satisfaction in a matter of such importance. Can I do
better than propose the difficulty to the public, even though, perhaps, I have small hopes of obtaining a
solution? We shall at least, by this means, be sensible of our ignorance, if we do not augment our
knowledge.
I must confess that a man is guilty of unpardonable arrogance who concludes, because an argument
has escaped his own investigation, that therefore it does not really exist. I must also confess that, though
all the learned, for several ages, should have employed themselves in fruitless search upon any subject,
it may still, perhaps, be rash to conclude positively that the subject must, therefore, pass all human
comprehension. Even though we examine all the sources of our knowledge, and conclude them unfit for
such a subject, there may still remain a suspicion, that the enumeration is not complete, or the
examination not accurate. But with regard to the present subject, there are some considerations which
seem to remove all this accusation of arrogance or suspicion of mistake.
It is certain that the most ignorant and stupid peasants—nay infants, nay even brute beasts—improve
by experience, and learn the qualities of natural objects, by observing the effects which result from
them. When a child has felt the sensation of pain from touching the flame of a candle, he will be careful
not to put his hand near any candle; but will expect a similar effect from a cause which is similar in its
sensible qualities and appearance. If you assert, therefore, that the understanding of the child is led into
this conclusion by any process of argument or ratiocination, I may justly require you to produce that
argument; nor have you any pretence to refuse so equitable a demand. You cannot say that the argument
is abstruse, and may possibly escape your enquiry; since you confess that it is obvious to the capacity of
a mere infant. If you hesitate, therefore, a moment, or if, after reflection, you produce any intricate or
profound argument, you, in a manner, give up the question, and confess that it is not reasoning which
engages us to suppose the past resembling the future, and to expect similar effects from causes which
are, to appearance, similar. This is the proposition which I intended to enforce in the present section. If I
be right, I pretend not to have made any mighty discovery. And if I be wrong, I must acknowledge
myself to be indeed a very backward scholar; since I cannot now discover an argument which, it seems,
was perfectly familiar to me long before I was out of my cradle.
David Hume: An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, decoded
PART 2
We still haven’t reached the end of our questioning, though. Every time we answer a question,
another one comes up. We ask, how do we reason about matters of fact? The answer is, all of our
thoughts are all founded on the relation of cause and effect. Then we ask, how do we know about cause
and effect? The answer: Experience. But how do we draw conclusions from experience? This is a very
hard question.
Actually, this question is only hard if we try to answer it with a positive answer. It’s easy if we admit
our limitations. I will give a negative answer: we cannot draw conclusions from experience.
Nature hides many things from us. For instance, we can see a ball moving, but we cannot see
whether it can impart that movement onto another ball. That power is hidden. We eat brown bread, and
it seems to nourish us. But how can we know that the next loaf will nourish us in the same way? We
cannot. We imagine that we can, but there is nothing in the appearance of the bread that tells us it will.
Of course, it always has, and it probably always will, but there is no way that I can see to actually prove
it.
Even if you doubt me, you must admit that there is a difference between these two propositions
I have always found this cause to have that effect, and
This cause will always have that effect
I know that everyone always infers the second proposition from the first, but I do not know what
reasoning leads to the inference. There is no obvious connection between these two propositions.
I think that this argument will become more convincing once other philosophers have tried to prove
me wrong. In the meantime, though, it might become more convincing if we examine the different
branches of knowledge, and show how none of them could connect these two propositions.
There are two kinds of reasoning: demonstrative and probable. Demonstrative reasoning explains
relations of ideas. There are clearly no demonstrative reasons that would show we could extrapolate
from the past to the future; nature may change. I can imagine that things that have fallen will rise, that
snow will taste hot, or that trees will flower in December.
There is an obvious but deceptive argument:
1. The future always resembled the past.
2. If the future always resembled the past, the future will resemble the past.
3. Therefore, the future will resemble the past.
This is arguing in a circle, though; we need to prove that the future will resemble the past. Premise 2
is really the same as the conclusion, and it is the very point we are trying to prove. It can’t be assumed
without creating a circular argument.
There is another counter-argument. We need to see many instances of cause and effect before we
judge the relation to be true. Who would believe that chickens lay eggs the first time they observed it? If
the effect were judged by reason, one observation would be enough.
Perhaps we observe the hidden capacities of things after a number of experiments. This seems to
have the same difficulties, though. How do we infer what the capacities are? Why do we admit the
nourishing capacity of bread after many instances, but not on the first? And how do we determine that
bread will always possess the ability in the future?
Of course, you may say that I am a bit of a hypocrite: I eat bread and trust that the sun will rise. I
look both ways when I cross the street, because I don’t doubt that traffic retains the ability to kill me. As
a person, I am quite satisfied that I should continue eating. Yet as a philosopher, and as a skeptic, I want
to know why.
Only the arrogant think that the things they can’t see don’t exist. It might even be that philosophers
will look for ages before finally concluding I am wrong. Still, there are some considerations that might
remove all doubt.
Infants and animals learn from experience. Even a baby knows learns from one accident that she
cannot touch a flame. If a baby learns from reason or argument, I would like you to produce the reasons
and the argument. If you can’t, well, the baby is smarter than you. And, of course, if you can, and if I am
wrong, well, the baby is smarter than me.
Immanuel Kant
Kant, supposedly, was the most boring person to have ever lived. He walked the same path at the
same time every day with the same person. He was a merely decent student and never married. He never
went farther than 65 miles (110 kilometers) from his home town. He died quietly: no poison, no
barbarians, and no bursting bladders. My students take a kind of glee in this. What a bunch of bores and
weirdo’s philosophers are!
And yeah, sure, they are. But Kant could have lived in his grandmother’s bedroom, even slept in her
nighty for all it matters. Kant is the most important philosopher to have ever lived. If his ideas are not
exciting, no ideas are. He put the world on a different footing. He is a mountain that casts a shadow over
all of philosophy—and would cast one over science, too if only scientists would listen.
He is also incomprehensible.
Kant wrote two huge and insanely difficult books. Then he wrote two small and insanely difficult
books to make the big ones easier to understand. They don’t. They’re just shorter. Still, nobody now
reads the big ones.
Kant’s book on ethics one is called the Metaphysics of Morals and the metaphysics one is called The
Prolegomena. See how confusing he is? Not even his titles make sense.
Kant’s ethics
In ancient philosophy (everything before Descartes), ethics was about personal life. It was about
your own happiness and leading a life of meaning. Aristotle had a few good rules, Epicurus had 40, and
Marcus Aurelius had hundreds.
Modern ethics has nothing to do with that namby-pamby, personal-fulfilment nonsense. Modern
ethics is all about judging, and, instead of having hundreds of guidelines, each of the two main schools
of thought (we’ll get to the other school, Utilitarianism, in a bit) has only one rule.
They have a single rule for a simple reason: one rule never contradicts itself. Ethical dilemmas
happen when rules come into conflict. Take, for instance, the rules of Salvatore Lo Piccolo, the boss of
bosses of the Sicilian Mafia. He was a murderer, drug trafficker, and extortionist. Oddly, though, he was
captured with a list of ten ethical commandments for Mafiosi. Here are two: ‘“Always be available for
Cosa Nostra, even if your wife is about to give birth”, and “Wives must be treated with respect”.
Well these are good rules, especially for a murderer, but they clearly conflict. If the caporegime calls
while your wife is having birth, you can’t win. You will have to break one of the rules.
You might think that adding another rule, “Wives are more important than capos” might help. It
does not. An eleventh rule only creates more problems further down the line. Having only one ethical
rule is the way out. A single ethical rule cannot come into conflict with itself.
Part of an ethicist’s challenge, then, is coming up with a single rule to govern (and judge) all human
action. This is tough, because there are a few tensions. The rule must be big enough to cover everything
(“Thou shalt not covet thy neighbour’s wife” won’t work) but powerful enough to decide actions (“Do
the right thing” is hopelessly vague). It has to avoid the most obvious contradictions with common
sense (“Do whatever makes you happy” will make other people very unhappy) but also be a guide that is
better than your gut.
There has been one good rule passed down through millennia, the Golden Rule: “Do unto others as
you would have them do unto you”. This is surprisingly great. It requires you to treat yourself no better
than others, and it dictates exactly what you should do. If you want to steal, for instance, you have to
reckon with the fact that your action creates harm and that others have the same feelings and
entitlements as you do.
Kant’s ethical rule is almost the same as the Golden Rule. He says, “Act only according to that
maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law.”
A “maxim” is a generalized rule to govern your actions. To judge an ethical action, Kant says I
should:
1. Isolate my action
2. Consider the rule governing my action
3. Make that maxim ‘universal’
4. And see if it leads to contradiction
5. If it does, I am forbidden to act in that way
Kant’s metaphysics
Kant’s metaphysical theory is harder to understand. Hume (he’s also in this book) destroyed any
hope of understanding metaphysical ideas, and Kant said that Hume had “woken me from my dogmatic
slumber”. Kant set about prove him wrong. His solution is not very grandiose or sweeping, but it is just
about right; he says, in short, that we see the world through metaphysical lenses—for example, our
experiences are always in three dimensions, forward in time, and with causes and effects.
Wait, you say. Don’t we learn things? Yes. But if knowledge comes from the senses, how can we
trust it? And what do we really know?
1. Human senses are terrible, and
2. Extrapolating from them is impossible
You might think that the first problem is the big one; after all, our senses are wrong all the time.
Things that seem small are actually big and far away; a warm pool seems cold when you have been
sitting on the deck; I can’t hear my wife, even though I can see her mouth moving.
The second problem, though, is a killer. Hume said, in short, you have never seen one thing cause
another thing.
You’ve probably heard that drinking a glass of wine a day prevents heart disease; that joyful fact is
printed over and over again, year after year, because it shows how just how kind the universe can be. It’s
a shame it isn’t true. Some third thing causes people to drink wine and live longer. It’s money. Rich
people live better, can afford better health care and gym memberships, and they also can buy good
hooch. Wine and longevity are correlated, not causally related.
Hume takes this idea and runs with it. When have you ever seen a cause? You haven’t. All you ever
see is correlation—even when you see one billiard ball crash into another, you do not see the first ball
cause the second ball to move. There are two events, and we assume that one causes the other.
This drove Kant nuts. Without causality, there is no science. And, obviously, if we have no science,
we know very little indeed.
If causality is not observable, it is probably ‘metaphysical’. Metaphysical questions are really
frustrating, because they are important but unanswerable. What is a law of nature? What is a substance?
What is the soul? How infinitesimally small things does it take to make a finite small thing? Is
nothingness something?
Metaphysics is a graveyard of good ideas. Oceans of ink have been spilt on these questions, and not
a single truth has floated to the surface. It is enough to make any sensible person despair of ever finding
an answer. Kant, though, is not sensible.
He thinks that it might be possible that some of these questions (like ‘what is causality?’) make
sense, while some ideas (what is nothingness?) do not. The good ideas have something in common, and
he tries to explain what it is.
Kant doesn't want to solve these problems. He wants to just say which ones are answerable and
which ones are not. He hopes to save metaphysics and put it on a secure, more scientific footing. Saving
causality is a very important part.
Metaphysics turns out to be a lot like math: it comes from within our own minds, and we can learn
things from introspection. This helps Kant a little--but how do we get to universal truths, true for every
person, if we are looking only within our own minds?
If Kant were alive in the 21st century, he would say that we have neurological or cerebral structures
that limit the way we see the world: we see it (and can only see it) in three dimensions, going forward in
time, and logically.
What can we learn from these structures? Quite a bit, he says. All of geometry is in there (it is the
science of dimensions), as is arithmetic. Metaphysics and logic are in our minds as well
Immanuel Kant: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, I-II, edited
First section
Nothing can possibly be conceived in the world, or even out of it, which can be called good, without
qualification, except a good will. Intelligence, wit, judgement, and the other talents of the mind,
however they may be named, or courage, resolution, perseverance, as qualities of temperament, are
undoubtedly good and desirable in many respects; but these gifts of nature may also become extremely
bad and mischievous if the will which is to make use of them, and which, therefore, constitutes what is
called character, is not good. The coolness of a villain not only makes him far more dangerous, but also
directly makes him more abominable in our eyes than he would have been without it.
A good will is good not because of what it performs or effects, not by its aptness for the attainment
of some proposed end, but simply by virtue of the volition; that is, it is good in itself. Even if with its
greatest efforts it should yet achieve nothing, and there should remain only the good will (not, to be sure,
a mere wish, but the summoning of all means in our power), then, like a jewel, it would still shine by its
own light, as a thing which has its whole value in itself.
I omit here all actions which are already recognized as inconsistent with duty, although they may be
useful for this or that purpose. I also set aside those actions which really conform to duty, but to which
men have no direct inclination, performing them because they are impelled thereto by some other
inclination. For example, it is always a matter of duty that a dealer should not over charge an
inexperienced purchaser; and wherever there is much commerce the prudent tradesman does not
overcharge, but keeps a fixed price for everyone, so that a child buys of him as well as any other. Men
are thus honestly served; but this is not enough to make us believe that the tradesman has so acted from
duty and from principles of honesty: his own advantage required it. The action was done neither from
duty nor from direct inclination, but merely with a selfish view.
There are many minds so sympathetically constituted that, without any other motive of vanity or
self-interest, they find a pleasure in spreading joy around them and can take delight in the satisfaction of
others so far as it is their own work. But I maintain that in such a case an action of this kind, however
proper, however amiable it may be, has nevertheless no true moral worth, but is on a level with other
inclinations. For the maxim lacks the moral import, namely, that such actions be done from duty, not
from inclination.
It is in this manner, undoubtedly, that we are to understand those passages of Scripture also in which
we are commanded to love our neighbour, even our enemy. For love, as an affection, cannot be
commanded, but beneficence for duty’s sake may; even though we are not impelled to it by any
inclination—nay, are even repelled by a natural and unconquerable aversion.
An action done from duty derives its moral worth, not from the purpose which is to be attained by it,
but from the maxim by which it is determined, and therefore does not depend on the realization of the
object of the action, but merely on the principle of volition by which the action has taken place, without
regard to any object of desire.
Duty is the necessity of acting from respect for the law. I may have inclination for an object as the
effect of my proposed action, but I cannot have respect for it, just for this reason, that it is an effect and
not an energy of will.
But what sort of law can that be, the conception of which must determine the will, even without
paying any regard to the effect expected from it, in order that this will may be called good absolutely
and without qualification? As I have deprived the will of every impulse which could arise to it from
obedience to any law, there remains nothing but the universal conformity of its actions to law in general,
which alone is to serve the will as a principle, i.e., I am never to act otherwise than that I could also will
that my maxim should become a universal law.
The common reason of men in its practical judgements perfectly coincides with this and always has
in view the principle here suggested. Let the question be, for example: May I when in distress make a
promise with the intention not to keep it? I readily distinguish here between the two significations which
the question may have: Whether it is prudent, or whether it is right, to make a false promise? The former
may undoubtedly of be the case. Now it is a wholly different thing to be truthful from duty and to be so
from apprehension of injurious consequences. In the first case, the very notion of the action already
implies a law for me; in the second case, I must first look about elsewhere to see what results may be
combined with it which would affect myself. The shortest way, however, and an unerring one, to
discover the answer to this question whether a lying promise is consistent with duty, is to ask myself,
“Should I be content that my maxim (to extricate myself from difficulty by a false promise) should hold
good as a universal law, for myself as well as for others?” and should I be able to say to myself, “Every
one may make a deceitful promise when he finds himself in a difficulty from which he cannot otherwise
extricate himself?” Then I presently become aware that while I can will the lie, I can by no means will
that lying should be a universal law. For with such a law there would be no promises at all, since it
would be in vain to allege my intention in regard to my future actions to those who would not believe
this allegation, or if they over hastily did so would pay me back in my own coin. Hence my maxim, as
soon as it should be made a universal law, would necessarily destroy itself.
Second section
Although many things are done in conformity with what duty prescribes, it is nevertheless always
doubtful whether they are done strictly from duty, so as to have a moral worth. In fact, it is absolutely
impossible to make out by experience with complete certainty a single case in which the maxim of an
action, however right in itself, rested simply on moral grounds and on the conception of duty. We cannot
from this infer with certainty that it was not really some secret impulse of self-love, under the false
appearance of duty, that was the actual determining cause of the will.
Nor could anything be more fatal to morality than that we should wish to derive it from examples.
For every example of it that is set before me must be first itself tested by principles of morality.
From what has been said, it is clear that all moral conceptions have their seat and origin completely
a priori in the reason, and that, moreover, in the commonest reason just as truly as in that which is in the
highest degree speculative; that they cannot be obtained by abstraction from any empirical, and therefore
merely contingent, knowledge; that it is just this purity of their origin that makes them worthy to serve
as our supreme practical principle, and that just in proportion as we add anything empirical, we detract
from their genuine influence and from the absolute value of actions. It would not only be vain to
determine the moral element of duty in right actions for purposes of speculative criticism, but it would
be impossible to base morals on their genuine principles, even for common practical purposes,
especially of moral instruction, so as to produce pure moral dispositions, and to engraft them on men’s
minds to the promotion of the greatest possible good in the world.
Everything in nature works according to laws. Rational beings alone have the faculty of acting
according to the conception of laws, that is according to principles, i.e., have a will. Since the deduction
of actions from principles requires reason, the will is nothing but practical reason.
The conception of an objective principle, in so far as it is obligatory for a will, is called a command
(of reason), and the formula of the command is called an imperative.
All imperatives are expressed by the word ought, and thereby indicate the relation of an objective
law of reason to a will, which from its subjective constitution is not necessarily determined by it (an
obligation).
Now all imperatives command either hypothetically or categorically. If now the action is good only
as a means to something else, then the imperative is hypothetical; if it is conceived as good in itself and
consequently as being necessarily the principle of a will which of itself conforms to reason, then it is
categorical.
If it were only equally easy to give a definite conception of happiness, the imperatives of prudence
would correspond exactly with those of skill, and would likewise be analytical. For in this case as in
that, it could be said: “Whoever wills the end, wills also (according to the dictate of reason necessarily)
the indispensable means thereto which are in his power.” But, unfortunately, the notion of happiness is
so indefinite that although every man wishes at it, yet he never can say definitely and consistently what
it is that he really wishes and wills. The reason of this is that all the elements which belong to the notion
of happiness are altogether empirical, i.e., they must be borrowed from experience, and nevertheless the
idea of happiness requires an absolute whole, a maximum of welfare in my present and all future
circumstances. Now it is impossible that the most clear-sighted and at the same time most powerful
being (supposed finite) should frame to himself a definite conception of what he really wills in this.
Does he will riches, how much anxiety, envy, and snares might he not thereby draw upon his shoulders?
Does he will knowledge and discernment, perhaps it might prove to be only an eye so much the sharper
to show him so much the more fearfully the evils that are now concealed from him, and that cannot be
avoided, or to impose more wants on his desires, which already give him concern enough. Would he
have long life? who guarantees to him that it would not be a long misery? would he at least have health?
how often has uneasiness of the body restrained from excesses into which perfect health would have
allowed one to fall? and so on. In short, he is unable, on any principle, to determine with certainty what
would make him truly happy; because to do so he would need to be omniscient. We cannot therefore act
on any definite principles to secure happiness, but only on empirical counsels, e.g. of regimen, frugality,
courtesy, reserve, etc., which experience teaches do, on the average, most promote well-being.
We shall therefore have to investigate a priori the possibility of a categorical imperative, as we have
not in this case the advantage of its reality being given in experience, so that the elucidation of its
possibility should be requisite only for its explanation, not for its establishment.
In this problem we will first inquire whether the mere conception of a categorical imperative may
not perhaps supply us also with the formula of it, containing the proposition which alone can be a
categorical imperative.
When I conceive a hypothetical imperative, in general I do not know beforehand what it will contain
until I am given the condition. But when I conceive a categorical imperative, I know at once what it
contains. For as the imperative contains besides the law only the necessity that the maxims shall
conform to this law, while the law contains no conditions restricting it, there remains nothing but the
general statement that the maxim of the action should conform to a universal law, and it is this
conformity alone that the imperative properly represents as necessary.
A maxim is a subjective principle of action, and must be distinguished from the objective principle,
namely, practical law. The former contains the practical rule set by reason according to the conditions of
the subject (often its ignorance or its inclinations), so that it is the principle on which the subject acts;
but the law is the objective principle valid for every rational being, and is the principle on which it ought
to act that is an imperative.
There is therefore but one categorical imperative, namely, this: Act only on that maxim whereby
thou canst at the same time will that it should become a universal law.
Now if all imperatives of duty can be deduced from this one imperative as from their principle, then,
although it should remain undecided what is called duty is not merely a vain notion, yet at least we shall
be able to show what we understand by it and what this notion means.
We will now enumerate a few duties:
A man reduced to despair by a series of misfortunes feels wearied of life, but is still so far in
possession of his reason that he can ask himself whether it would not be contrary to his duty to himself
to take his own life. Now he inquires whether the maxim of his action could become a universal law of
nature. His maxim is: “From self-love I adopt it as a principle to shorten my life when its longer duration
is likely to bring more evil than satisfaction.” It is asked then simply whether this principle founded on
self-love can become a universal law of nature. Now we see at once that a system of nature of which it
should be a law to destroy life by means of the very feeling whose special nature it is to impel to the
improvement of life would contradict itself and, therefore, could not exist as a system of nature; hence
that maxim cannot possibly exist as a universal law of nature and, consequently, would be wholly
inconsistent with the supreme principle of all duty.
Another finds himself forced by necessity to borrow money. He knows that he will not be able to
repay it, but sees also that nothing will be lent to him unless he promises stoutly to repay it in a definite
time. He desires to make this promise, but he has still so much conscience as to ask himself: “Is it not
unlawful and inconsistent with duty to get out of a difficulty in this way?” Suppose however that he
resolves to do so: then the maxim of his action would be expressed thus: “When I think myself in want
of money, I will borrow money and promise to repay it, although I know that I never can do so.” Now
this principle of self-love or of one’s own advantage may perhaps be consistent with my whole future
welfare; but the question now is, “Is it right?” I change then the suggestion of self-love into a universal
law, and state the question thus: “How would it be if my maxim were a universal law?” Then I see at
once that it could never hold as a universal law of nature, but would necessarily contradict itself. For
supposing it to be a universal law that everyone when he thinks himself in a difficulty should be able to
promise whatever he pleases, with the purpose of not keeping his promise, the promise itself would
become impossible, as well as the end that one might have in view in it, since no one would consider
that anything was promised to him, but would ridicule all such statements as vain pretenses.
A third finds in himself a talent which with the help of some culture might make him a useful man in
many respects. But he finds himself in comfortable circumstances and prefers to indulge in pleasure
rather than to take pains in enlarging and improving his happy natural capacities. He asks, however,
whether his maxim of neglect of his natural gifts, besides agreeing with his inclination to indulgence,
agrees also with what is called duty. He sees then that a system of nature could indeed subsist with such
a universal law although men (like the South Sea islanders) should let their talents rest and resolve to
devote their lives merely to idleness, amusement, and propagation of their species—in a word, to
enjoyment; but he cannot possibly will that this should be a universal law of nature, or be implanted in
us as such by a natural instinct. For, as a rational being, he necessarily wills that his faculties be
developed, since they serve him and have been given him, for all sorts of possible purposes.
A fourth, who is in prosperity, while he sees that others have to contend with great wretchedness and
that he could help them, thinks: “What concern is it of mine? Let everyone be as happy as Heaven
pleases, or as be can make himself; I will take nothing from him nor even envy him, only I do not wish
to contribute anything to his welfare or to his assistance in distress!” Now no doubt if such a mode of
thinking were a universal law, the human race might very well subsist and doubtless even better than in
a state in which everyone talks of sympathy and good-will, or even takes care occasionally to put it into
practice, but, on the other side, also cheats when he can, betrays the rights of men, or otherwise violates
them. But although it is possible that a universal law of nature might exist in accordance with that
maxim, it is impossible to will that such a principle should have the universal validity of a law of nature.
For a will which resolved this would contradict itself, inasmuch as many cases might occur in which one
would have need of the love and sympathy of others, and in which, by such a law of nature, sprung from
his own will, he would deprive himself of all hope of the aid he desires.
If now we attend to ourselves on occasion of any transgression of duty, we shall find that we in fact
do not will that our maxim should be a universal law, for that is impossible for us; on the contrary, we
will that the opposite should remain a universal law, only we assume the liberty of making an exception
in our own favour or (just for this time only) in favour of our inclination. Consequently if we considered
all cases from one and the same point of view, namely, that of reason, we should find a contradiction in
our own will, namely, that a certain principle should be objectively necessary as a universal law, and yet
subjectively should not be universal, but admit of exceptions.
Now I say: man and generally any rational being exists as an end in himself, not merely as a means
to be arbitrarily used by this or that will, but in all his actions, whether they concern himself or other
rational beings, must be always regarded at the same time as an end. Beings whose existence depends
not on our will but on nature’s, have nevertheless, if they are irrational beings, only a relative value as
means, and are therefore called things; rational beings, on the contrary, are called persons, because their
very nature points them out as ends in themselves, that is as something which must not be used merely
as means, and so far therefore restricts freedom of action (and is an object of respect). These, therefore,
are not merely subjective ends whose existence has a worth for us as an effect of our action, but
objective ends, that is, things whose existence is an end in itself; an end moreover for which no other
can be substituted, which they should subserve merely as means, for otherwise nothing whatever would
possess absolute worth; but if all worth were conditioned and therefore contingent, then there would be
no supreme practical principle of reason whatever.
If then there is a supreme practical principle or, in respect of the human will, a categorical
imperative, it must be one which, being drawn from the conception of that which is necessarily an end
for everyone because it is an end in itself, constitutes an objective principle of will, and can therefore
serve as a universal practical law. The foundation of this principle is: rational nature exists as an end in
itself. Man necessarily conceives his own existence as being so; so far then this is a subjective principle
of human actions. But every other rational being regards its existence similarly, just on the same rational
principle that holds for me: so that it is at the same time an objective principle, from which as a supreme
practical law all laws of the will must be capable of being deduced. Accordingly the practical imperative
will be as follows: So act as to treat humanity, whether in thine own person or in that of any other, in
every case as an end withal, never as means only.
Looking back now on all previous attempts to discover the principle of morality, we need not
wonder why they all failed. It was seen that man was bound to laws by duty, but it was not observed that
the laws to which he is subject are only those of his own giving, though at the same time they are
universal, and that he is only bound to act in conformity with his own will; a will, however, which is
designed by nature to give universal laws.
The conception of the will of every rational being as one which must consider itself as giving in all
the maxims of its will universal laws, so as to judge itself and its actions from this point of view—this
conception leads to another which depends on it and is very fruitful, namely that of a kingdom of ends.
By a kingdom I understand the union of different rational beings in a system by common laws. Now
since it is by laws that ends are determined as regards their universal validity, hence, if we abstract from
the personal differences of rational beings and likewise from all the content of their private ends, we
shall be able to conceive all ends combined in a systematic whole (including both rational beings as ends
in themselves, and also the special ends which each may propose to himself), that is to say, we can
conceive a kingdom of ends, which on the preceding principles is possible.
For all rational beings come under the law that each of them must treat itself and all others never
merely as means, but in every case at the same time as ends in themselves. Hence results a systematic
union of rational being by common objective laws, i.e., a kingdom which may be called a kingdom of
ends, since what these laws have in view is just the relation of these beings to one another as ends and
means. It is certainly only an ideal.
A rational being belongs as a member to the kingdom of ends when, although giving universal laws
in it, he is also himself subject to these laws. He belongs to it as sovereign when, while giving laws, he
is not subject to the will of any other.
We can now end where we started at the beginning, namely, with the conception of a will
unconditionally good. That will is absolutely good which cannot be evil—in other words, whose maxim,
if made a universal law, could never contradict itself. This principle, then, is its supreme law: “Act
always on such a maxim as thou canst at the same time will to be a universal law”; this is the sole
condition under which a will can never contradict itself; and such an imperative is categorical. Such then
is the formula of an absolutely good will.
Immanuel Kant: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, I-II, decoded
FIRST SECTION
The only good thing is a good will. Intelligence, wit, courage and wealth can be misused. A clever,
calculating villain is worse than a stupid one.
A good will is just plain good. It is not good because it leads to good things; it is good in itself, and it
cannot be abused. Even if a good person has bad luck and accomplishes nothing, her good will shines,
like a jewel, by its own light.
It is possible to do the same action with different motivations. If you own a store and do not cheat
your customers, you might be honest, or you might be acting honestly because cheating them is bad
business in the long run. In this case, you are not acting on the principle of honesty; you are acting out of
long-term selfishness.
Similarly, many people take joy in being kind to others. However nice these people are, they are not
good people. If people act to make themselves happy, they are being selfish; that they are helping an old
woman across the street should not make their actions more noble. A person who brings happiness to
others because it makes her happy is a selfish jerk just like everyone else.
An action’s moral worth does not come from its consequences. An action is good if it is done
according the right ‘maxim’, if it is done for the right reason, if it is done with a good will. The will is
between the idea of what should be done and the actual accomplishment of that idea. A person who
wants (and tries) to bring the idea into reality is doing the right thing.
Suppose my wife is pregnant, and I am racing to get her to the hospital. On the way, I run over my
neighbour’s dog. Did I do something bad? No. I was trying to do the right thing—to bring life safely
into the world—and it didn’t work out according to plan. But I wanted it to, and my will is what matters.
I did not intend to do anything wrong, and so I should not be blamed.
Duty is acting out of respect for the laws of morality. As I showed above, consequences cannot be
predicted. They are the effects of the will, but not the energy of the will. Wanting the right thing is what
really matters. But what are the right things to want?
I’ve already removed any consequences that might be motivations. I should not want, for example,
to keep the peace, make people happy, help good people, or punish bad ones. All of these are the results
of actions. The only thing that remains is this: I should want to be a good person. My will should be to
act out of respect for the laws of morality.
What, then, are the laws? First, a real law must determine my duty and tell me what to will. Second,
a real law obviously cannot depend on who I am. Laws apply to everyone; that is what makes them
laws. Finally, a good law cannot depend on the effects of my actions.
Since I have removed all the the good consequences that would come out of respecting the law, I can
only want one thing: to conform to the law, out of pure respect for lawfulness. This principle can guide
me and delineate all my duties: I am never to act otherwise than so that I could also will that my maxim
should become a universal law.
This means, in short, that there is one law that makes all the others. The one law is this: Act
according to the law. In other words, do unto others as you would have them do unto everyone else.
Imagine that a man wanted to break a promise. His maxim would be “False promises are
acceptable”. If we put this to the test, we imagine applying this maxim to everyone. Can everyone make
false promises? No. If everyone made false promises, promises would be worthless, so a promise would
not be a promise. The maxim, as soon as it is made universal, destroys itself in a contradiction.
No matter how inexperienced I am in the ways of the world, no matter how dumb I am, I can always
find out the answer to any ethical quandary. I only need to ask myself this: Could I make my decision a
rule for everyone to follow? If not, then it must be rejected.
SECOND SECTION
Although many actions look ethical, far fewer are ethical. Many actions are done from selfishness.
In fact, it is impossible to say that any action has ever been done purely out of duty and not at all out of
selfishness. We simply cannot tell.
All moral ideas must come only from within. They must, in other words, be completely a priori.
This is how they get their power. If they were not a priori, they would come from abstraction from
circumstances in the world, and when those circumstances changed, so too would the laws.
The process of going from a law to an ‘ought’ is making ‘imperatives’. Imperatives are commands
of reason. Because they come from universal laws, imperatives are objective. They do not depend on
who you are, and everyone will agree to them. Sometimes our wills are weak, and sometimes we choose
how to act out of selfishness instead of doing what is rational. Nonetheless, it is always clear what
should have been done.
There are two kinds of imperatives: categorical and hypothetical. Hypothetical imperatives are of
this kind: if x then y. X is the goal. Y is the step to take. If you want a good job, go to school is an
example of a hypothetical imperative.
If we were like God and could know in advance with perfect certainly how everything would work
out, the obligations of hypothetical and categorical imperatives would be the same. The things that make
me happy would be the things that I am required to do, and the actions required by duty would make me
happy. Obviously, though, this is not the case. People think that money will make them happy, but they
forget about the envy and anxiety that money creates. People want to live forever, but who would want
to live forever in misery? Empirical ethics is, at best, only a rough guide: be frugal, be kind, work hard,
that sort of thing. Therefore we must look for an a priori categorial imperative.
Categorical imperatives are hard to explain. Categorical imperatives are ‘good in themselves’. They
are the commands of the will according to reason, which in turn is in accordance with the universal and
objective laws. “Be good to your mother” is a categorical imperative. There’s something disgusting
about saying “If you want a cookie, be good to your mother”. Everyone should always be good to their
mothers. That is categorical.
A categorical imperative applies to everyone. It cannot be contradicted—otherwise, of course, it
would not be categorical and it would not be imperative. By stripping away all the “if... thens” of
hypothetical imperatives, I can see what the categorical imperative is. What is the one rule that all
people must follow? It is this: Everyone must follow the rules.
That, in short, is the categorical imperative. I can be more precise, though: “Act only on that maxim
whereby thou canst at the same time will that it should become a universal law.” I can also be a bit less
precise but more clever: “Do unto others as you would have them do unto everyone else.”
All duties can be derived from the categorical imperative. Here are a few examples.
A husband would like to sleep around on his wife. The maxim of his action will be: “Everyone
should commit adultery.” But this cannot be a universal rule. If all people cheated on their spouses,
cheating would no longer be cheating. Adultery requires that a spouse not know. If everyone slept
around, every spouse would know, and adultery would become not adultery. This would be a
contradiction.
A woman would like to borrow money and not repay it. Her maxim will be: “Promises must be
broken.” This cannot be a universal law. If everyone were allowed to break promises, a promise would
not be a promise. That too is a contradiction.
A woman would like to capriciously hit her son. The maxim is “people may hit one another to make
themselves feel better.” This cannot work: if everyone hit one another, we would all feel worse. The
action we had undertaken to feel better would lead to agony, a contradiction.
A poor man would like to buy a new Ferrari, impoverishing his family. His maxim “Everyone
should go into debt to make themselves happy.” The contradiction is obvious: not everyone can go into
debt; some people must be creditors for others to be debtors. He cannot ethically go into debt.
Sometimes we want an exception from the universal law. We want to get away with something we
know is wrong. Then there is a contradiction in our own wills: we want there to be a law, but do not
want it for ourselves.
All rational things are ends-in-themselves, and none should be used as a means or as a stepping
stone to some other goal. Irrational beings have value only as means. That is why they are called
‘things’. Rational beings have absolute worth. That is why they are not things, but are human beings.
Things have prices; ends do not have prices.
Every person thinks of herself as an end and worthy of respect, and every person knows that all other
people deserve our full respect—even if we are sometimes reluctant to admit it. Because this is true for
all people, this principle is objective, just like the categorical imperative. Accordingly, the practical
imperative will be: Treat everyone (including yourself) as an end, never as a means.
If we look back on other ethical philosophies, it is easy to see why they failed. They all held that
people were bound by laws. They did not see that the only laws that people are bound by are those they
make for themselves. A person can be compelled to act in a certain way, but she cannot be compelled to
will a certain way. She might be made do things that lead to good consequences, but she cannot be made
to want the right things to happen. Therefore, nobody can be made to truly follow the law. Every person
must choose to follow the laws.
Every person must be her own lawmaker. This may sound like everyone will choose to make and
follow laws that lead to her own advantage. But, as I said, the laws are derived from the categorical
imperative, and so they will be objective. In other words, everyone must, due to logic, agree on the laws.
All rational beings must agree that they must treat themselves and everyone else as ends-in-themselves.
This results in a systematic union of common, objective laws. It results in what I call “a kingdom of
ends”. Of course it is only an ideal.
Still, when a person is a member of the kingdom of ends, she gives laws, and she is subject to them
at the same time. She is a ruler who chooses to be a subject ... subject to the rules. This is what freedom
of will allows. Freedom of will lets us be lawmakers and law-followers at the same time.
We can now end where we started, with the unconditionally good will. An unconditionally good will
would act in such a way that the maxim of its actions could be a universal law and never contradict
itself. The only way a will can never contradict itself is by following the supreme law, the categorical
imperative, “Act always on that maxim that you can will to be a universal law”. This, then, is the
formula for an absolutely good will.
Immanuel Kant: Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, edited
1 This is some of the toughest philosophy. Kant is a simply terrible writer. What he's trying to say, I
think, is this: science covers our senses. Metaphysics is about the non-sensible realm. Science can't tell
us what time or space are; only metaphysics can.
2
A priori A posteriori
Synthetic Are these real? He'll answer. No problem
Analytic No problem Don’t exist, he says
1. Judgments of experience are always synthetic. It would be absurd to found an analytic judgment
on experience, as it is unnecessary to go beyond my own conception in order to construct the judgment,
and therefore the confirmation of experience is unnecessary to it. That a body is extended is a
proposition possessing a priori certainty, and no judgment of experience. For before I go to experience I
have all the conditions of my judgment already present in the conception, out of which I simply draw the
predicate in accordance with the principle of contradiction, and thereby at the same time the necessity of
the judgment may be known, a point which experience could never teach me.
2. Mathematical judgments are in their entirety synthetic.
It must be first of all remarked that essentially mathematical propositions are always a priori, and
never empirical, because they involve necessity, which cannot be inferred from experience. Should any
one be unwilling to admit this, I will limit my assertion to pure mathematics, the very conception of
which itself brings with it the fact that it contains nothing empirical, but simply pure knowledge a priori.
At first sight, one might be disposed to think the proposition 7+5=12 merely analytic, resulting from
the conception of a sum of seven and five, according to the principle of contradiction. But more closely
considered it will be found that the conception of the sum of 7 and 5 comprises nothing beyond the
union of two numbers in a single one, and that therein nothing whatever is cogitated as to what this
single number is that comprehends both the others. The conception of twelve is by no means already
cogitated when I think merely of the union of seven and five. One’s conception is therefore really
enlarged by the proposition 7+5=12; in other words, arithmetical propositions are always synthetic, a
truth which is more apparent when we take rather larger numbers.
Solution of the general problem of the prolegomena. How is metaphysics possible as science.
This much is certain: he who has once tried criticism will be sickened for ever of all the dogmatic
trash he was compelled to content himself with before, because his reason, requiring something, could
find nothing better for its occupation. Criticism stands to the ordinary school-metaphysics exactly in the
same relation as chemistry to alchemy, or as astronomy to fortune-telling astrology. I guarantee that no
one who has comprehended and thought out the conclusions of criticism, even in these Prolegomena,
will ever return to the old sophistical pseudo-science. He will rather look forward with a kind of pleasure
to a metaphysics, certainly now within his power, which requires no more preparatory discoveries, and
which alone can procure for the reason permanent satisfaction. For this is an advantage upon which
metaphysics alone can reckon with confidence, among all possible sciences; namely, that it can be
brought to completion and to a durable position, as it cannot change any further, nor is it susceptible of
any increase through new discoveries.
Metaphysics must be a science, not alone as a whole, but in all its parts, else it is nothing; because in
speculation of the pure reason, nothing has a standing but universal notions. But, apart from this,
probability and healthy human understanding have their useful and justifiable employment, but on their
own special principles, whose validity always depends on their relation to the practical.
This it is which I hold myself justified in demanding of a system of metaphysics, as science.
Immanuel Kant: Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, edited
What metaphysical thinking is. The difference between analytic and synthetic judgments
There are two kinds of a priori judgments. Some are ‘analytic’ and are explanatory. Some are
‘synthetic’ and add new information to the things we are thinking about.
Analytic judgments are definitions or clarifications. Someone could ask me, “What do you mean
when you say ‘physical things have extension?’”. I would reply, “Physical things take up space”. I am
defining and explaining “extension” but I am adding nothing to the idea. This is ‘analytic’.
On the other hand, if I declare “some physical things do not have mass”, I am adding information. If
I analyze the idea ‘physical things’, I don’t think ‘massless’. Masslessness is a new idea, not a
definition, and it does not come from analysis of physicality. It is ‘synthetic’.
All analytic propositions are a priori, even if are about empirical things. “Gold is a metal” is an
empirical a priori idea (it is not about an innate idea) and it is analytic (when I dissect my idea of gold,
one of the things I know is that it is a metal. In fact, I do not know what gold is if I do not know that it is
a metal).
The second part of the main transcendental problem: How is pure natural science possible?
Natural science, a priori and certain, binds nature. There are universal principles, too, such as the
proposition that substance is permanent, or that everything has a cause. These are perfectly good laws of
physics. How do we know them?
I am not concerned with things in themselves (I’ll get to those in a minute). I am thinking instead
about the things we experience, or, to put it another way, the objects of possible experience. Our
experiences follow regular laws, too; how do we know them?
We should start at the beginning. There are two types of experience: judgments of perception and
judgments of experience,.
That the room is warm, that orange juice is sweet and tonic is bitter: these are 'subjectively valid
judgments of perception'. Someday, I—or someone else—might experience things differently. After
brushing my teeth, orange juice could taste bad. I could come in from a warm summer day and find this
room cold. When I express subjectively valid thoughts, I am expressing something more than my
opinion, but it is not much more than “I feel this now”.
With judgments of experience, it is totally different. I am asserting that I—and everyone else—will
know these facts always. Air is elastic, space has three dimensions, light follows a straight line: these are
things that are universally valid.
There are twelve possible aspects of experiences that are presented to the mind. I’ll give an example.
Imagine I see puppies in a canoe floating towards a waterfall. I can see that the water is putting the
puppies in real danger, but that there are no people in the canoe. Right away, I can see that if I do not
save the puppies, no person will be harmed.
The river flowing over the waterfall is the source of danger, but I do not know what caused the
puppies to get into the canoe. I know, though, that they are not making this situation better by barking
and being afraid of the water. They need to swim to shore, and they need to do that now.
If I jump in, I might save them. If I do not, I know that they will die. There is only one way to tell
whether they can be saved—I'll have to try.
This example illustrates the twelve categories of judgment:
• According to quantity
o Unity
§ I can count the things in the scene. There are individual puppies and one canoe.
o Plurality
§ Puppies
o Totality
§ All of the puppies are in danger
• According to quality
o Reality
§ The danger is real
o Negation
§ But there are no people in the boat
o Limitation
§ And no people will be harmed
• According to relation
o Substance
§ The water makes up the waterfall
o Cause
§ The waterfall endangers the puppies
o Reciprocity
§ They are also putting themselves in danger
• According to modality
o Necessity
§ The puppies will die if I don’t act
o Possibility
§ And might if I do
o Actuality
§ Only by trying will I find out if I could save them
This may seem complicated, but at root it is simple: I am not trying to explain the origin of
experience, but what lies behind it and makes it possible.
The senses sense, and the mind unites these experiences into a consciousness, either subjective
(relative to oneself) or objective (for all people everywhere), and either analytically or synthetically.
New experiences, because they are combined with old ones, are always synthetic, and they are always in
terms of the ideas of metaphysics.
Metaphysics gives us the shapes of thought, and it governs all possible experiences. I cannot imagine
the time before the big bang, nor can I visualize five dimensions. Metaphysics says that all of my
thoughts and experiences will have a certain shape, and it gives us the most a priori of a priori ideas.
There is nowhere deeper for us to go.
These axioms of possible experience are the universal laws of nature, and we can discover them a
priori. Thus, we answer the question "How is pure natural science possible?".
There is a hierarchy of systems. Logic is the most basic. The rules of logic (such as "if a statement is
not-not true, then it is true") underpin everything. The axioms of metaphysics (like "There are no
uncaused events") rest on top of logic. The laws of nature rest, in turn, on top of metaphysics.
But this is important: we do not know much about nature. Take, for instance, a daisy. To us, it looks
white. To a bee (which can see in ultraviolet) it looks different, much like a bullseye. So what colour is a
daisy, actually? In fact, the question is a bit absurd. All metaphysics can say is that a flower, like every
other visible thing, has a colour. Which colour? We cannot say. We cannot go directly from logic to the
world.
Let's return now to Hume's problem with causes. He said that we have never actually observed one
thing causing another. When two billiard balls collide, we do not see the first imparting its momentum
onto the second. We only see one move, then the other move. Also, because Hume was an empiricist, he
said, therefore, that we have no real idea of causality. And without causality, we have no science.
Logic gives me the outline of the idea of cause, though. I get from it the idea of the antecedent and
the consequent: if A, then B. If a stone is left out in the sun, then it will become warm. I make this a
general statement of experience: Sunlight makes objects warm. This is not quite a law of physics, but it
is a law of possible experience. Any time, anyone leaves anything in the sun, we expect it to become
warmer.
I do not have within me any idea of what causality is in-itself, unobserved, in the wild. I can only
make sense of causality as a necessary connection between two experiences. I see the world in terms of
causes; antecedents cause consequents, and they do so in my experience. I can only observe what I can
observe, and I can only see it in the way that I do.
In fact, I do not have any idea of anything that is not experienced. There is a 'noumenal' world and a
'phenomenal' one. If the real world (ie the noumenal world) were 5 dimensional, or without causality, or
lacked time, I could not know it. I only know experiences (phenomena) and their necessary connections
and presentation (metaphysics).
Hence, when we try to talk about 'substance', 'infinity', the 'Big Bang', or the end of space, we are
truly talking nonsense: We are trying to talk about things that we could not sense, we could not
experience.
This has confused philosophers from the very beginning, back to Plato, who proposed that there was
a special world of noumenal Forms. He thought that reality was the intelligible essence. Because he
came from an earlier epoch, he should be excused.
From the earliest ages of philosophy, investigators of the pure reason have postulated, beyond the
sensible essences (phenomena) which constitute the world of sense, special essences of the
understanding (noumena) which are supposed to constitute a world of understanding; and since they
held appearance and illusion for the same thing, which in an undeveloped epoch is to be excused,
ascribed reality to the intelligible essence alone.
This does not mean I do not believe in an external world. Quite the contrary. When I say that there is
an object of sense and a noumenal object, I am conceding that there is an external world, apart from us,
existing in-itself. I just don't think we know anything about what it actually is; we only know how it is
presented to us.
Solution of the general problem of the prolegomena: How is metaphysics possible as science?
This much is certain: once you've tried my metaphysics, you will never go back to the dogmatic
trash of souls and infinities. My criticism is to old metaphysics as astronomy is to astrology, or
chemistry is to alchemy. The new metaphysics is finite and durable, and is capable of being completed.
Metaphysics must be a science, from bottom to top. Speculation and probability have their places,
but not in metaphysics. It must be certain, universal, and true.
This what I demand of metaphysics.
Friedrich Nietzsche
Nietzsche is the only philosopher who is truly infamous. If you’ve ever heard of the Übermensch, or
superman, that’s Nietzsche’s idea. He makes Ayn Rand look like a candy striper, and came up with the
bumper-sticker quote, “God is dead”. He was also Hitler’s favourite philosopher.
Don’t hold all that against him, though! Nietzsche is brilliant. He is probably the best literary stylist
of philosophers, and while that can make him hard to understand, he is never boring. He is outrageous,
hyperbolic, manic, moralistic... and right.
If you ask me, Nietzsche is at his best when he attacks philosophers’ conceits and deflates their
puffery. He tries to turn philosophy (and especially ethics) on its head. Philosophers say that they value
truth—Nietzsche demands to know why. Is falsity not every bit as good? Ethicists are concerned with
right and wrong—Nietzsche says that ‘good’ is merely what benefits the herd, and ‘evil’ is what harms
it. The best men would pay no attention to the cautious ideas of philosophers; the Übermensch charge
ahead. Ideas like ‘good’ and ‘evil’ mean nothing to them; they are concerned only with effective and
ineffective.
Nietzsche adores the ambitious, egoist, willful and psychopathic; he loathes the cautious, traditional
and inward. Oddly, though, Nietzsche himself was a bit of a baby. He had serious man-crush on the
composer Richard Wagner. He suffered from such terrible tummy aches and migraines that he couldn’t
hold a job. He lost his mind in his forties, and spent the rest of his life being taken care of by his mother
and sister. His sister, apparently, was a real piece of work; she was such a thorough-going racist that she
tried, with her husband, to establish a racially pure, Aryan colony—in Paraguay of all places. She also
made Nietzsche popular with the Nazis, in part by forging his work.
Nietzsche can still be easily understood by modern readers; like us, he was scientific and secular. To
me, he is the first really modern philosopher. He writes about social changes still occurring, and the
germs of existentialism and post-modernism—philosophies that took 75 years to mature—are in his
work.
Friedreich Nietzsche: Beyond Good and Evil, edited
The Four Errors. Man has been reared by his errors: firstly, he saw himself always imperfect;
secondly, he attributed to himself imaginary qualities; thirdly, he felt himself in a false position in
relation to the animals and nature; fourthly, he always devised new tables of values, and accepted them
for a time as eternal and unconditioned, so that at one time this, and at another time that human impulse
or state stood first, and was ennobled in consequence. When one has deducted the effect of these four
errors, one has also deducted humanity, humaneness, and “human dignity.”
Herd-Instinct. Wherever we meet with a morality we find a valuation and order of rank of the human
impulses and activities. These valuations and orders of rank are always the expression of the needs of a
community or herd: that which is in the first place to its advantage and in the second place and third
place is also the authoritative standard for the worth of every individual. By morality the individual is
taught to become a function of the herd, and to ascribe to himself value only as a function. As the
conditions for the maintenance of one community have been very different from those of another
community, there have been very different moralities; and in respect to the future essential
transformations of herds and communities, states and societies, one can prophesy that there will still be
very divergent moralities. Morality is the herd-instinct in the individual.
The Herd’s Sting of Conscience. In the longest and remotest ages of the human race there was quite
a different sting of conscience from that of the present day. At present one only feels responsible for
what one intends and for what one does, and we have our pride in ourselves. All our professors of
jurisprudence start with this sentiment of individual independence and pleasure, as if the source of right
had taken its rise here from the beginning. But throughout the longest period in the life of mankind there
was nothing more terrible to a person than to feel himself independent. To be alone, to feel independent,
neither to obey nor to rule, to represent an individual that was no pleasure to a person then, but a
punishment; he was condemned “to be an individual.” Freedom of thought was regarded as discomfort
personified. While we feel law and regulation as constraint and loss, people formerly regarded egoism as
a painful thing, and a veritable evil. For a person to be himself, to value himself according to his own
measure and weight that was then quite distasteful. The inclination to such a thing would have been
regarded as madness; for all miseries and terrors were associated with being alone. At that time the “free
will” had bad conscience in close proximity to it; and the less independently a person acted, the more the
herd-instinct, and not his personal character, expressed itself in his conduct, so much the more moral did
he esteem himself. All that did injury to the herd, whether the individual had intended it or not, then
caused him a sting of conscience and his neighbour like wise, indeed the whole herd! It is in this respect
that we have most changed our mode of thinking.
Benevolence. Is it virtuous when a cell transforms itself into the function of a stronger cell? It must
do so. And is it wicked when the stronger one assimilates the other? It must do so likewise: it is
necessary, for it has to have abundant indemnity and seeks to regenerate itself. One has therefore to
distinguish the instinct of appropriation and the instinct of submission in benevolence, according as the
stronger or the weaker feels benevolent. Gladness and covetousness are united in the stronger person,
who wants to transform something to his function: gladness and desire-to-be-coveted in the weaker
person, who would like to become a function. The former case is essentially pity, a pleasant excitation of
the instinct of appropriation at the sight of the weak: it is to be remembered, however, that “strong” and
“weak” are relative conceptions.
No Altruism! I see in many men an excessive impulse and delight in wanting to be a function; they
strive after it, and have the keenest scent for all those positions in which precisely they themselves can
be functions. Among such persons are those women who transform themselves into just that function of
a man that is but weakly developed in him, and then become his purse, or his politics, or his social
intercourse. Such beings maintain themselves best when they insert themselves in an alien organism; if
they do not succeed they become vexed, irritated, and eat themselves up.
The Element of Moral Scepticism in Christianity. Christianity also has made a great contribution to
enlightenment, and has taught moral scepticism in a very impressive and effective manner, accusing and
embittering, but with untiring patience and subtlety; it annihilated in every individual the belief in his
virtues: it made the great virtuous ones, of whom antiquity had no lack, vanish forever from the earth,
those popular men, who, in the belief in their perfection, walked about with the dignity of a hero of the
bull-fight. When, trained in this Christian school of scepticism, we now read the moral books of the
ancients, for example those of Seneca and Epictetus, we feel a pleasurable superiority, and are full of
secret insight and penetration, it seems to us as if a child talked before an old man, or a pretty, gushing
girl before La Rochefoucauld: we know better what virtue is! After all, however, we have applied the
same scepticism to all religious states and processes, such as sin, repentance, grace, sanctification, &c.,
and have allowed the worm to burrow so well, that we have now the same feeling of subtle superiority
and insight even in reading all Christian books: we know also the religious feelings better! And it is time
to know them well and describe them well, for the pious ones of the old belief die out also; let us save
their likeness and type, at least for the sake of knowledge.
Knowledge, more than a Means. Also without this passion—I refer to the passion for knowledge—
science would be furthered: science has hitherto increased and grown up without it. The good faith in
science, the prejudice in its favour, by which states are at present dominated (it was even the Church
formerly), rests fundamentally on the fact that the absolute inclination and impulse has so rarely
revealed itself in it, and that science is regarded not as a passion, but as a condition and an “ethos.”
Indeed, amour-plaisir of knowledge (curiosity) often enough suffices, amour-vanite suffices, and
habituation to it, with the afterthought of obtaining honour and bread; it even suffices for many that they
do not know what to do with a surplus of leisure, except to continue reading, collecting, arranging,
observing and narrating; their “scientific impulse” is their ennui. Pope Leo X once (in the brief to
Beroaldus) sang the praise of science; he designated it as the finest ornament and the greatest pride of
our life, a noble employment in happiness and in misfortune; “without it”, he says finally, “all human
undertakings would be without a firm basis — even with it they are still sufficiently mutable and
insecure!” But this rather sceptical Pope, like all other ecclesiastical panegyrists of science, suppressed
his ultimate judgment concerning it. If one may deduce from his words what is remarkable enough for
such a love of art, that he places science above art, in all, however, only from politeness that he omits to
speak of that which he places high above all science: the “revealed truth,” and the “eternal salvation of
the soul,” what are ornament, pride, entertainment and security of life to him, in comparison thereto.
“Science is something of secondary rank, nothing ultimate or unconditioned, no object of passion”—
this judgment was kept back in Leo’s soul: a truly Christian judgment concerning science! Antiquity—
its dignity and appreciation—were lessened by the fact that, even among its most eager disciples, the
striving after virtue stood foremost and that people thought they had given the highest praise to
knowledge when they celebrated it as the best means to virtue. It is something new in history that
knowledge claims to be more than a means.
In the Horizon of the Infinite. We have left the land and have gone aboard ship! We have broken
down the bridge behind us, nay, more, the land behind us! Well, little ship! look out! Beside thee is the
ocean; it is true it does not always roar, and sometimes it spreads out like silk and gold and a gentle
reverie. But times will come when thou wilt feel that it is infinite, and that there is nothing more
frightful than infinity. Oh, the poor bird that felt itself free, and now strikes against the walls of this
cage! Alas, if home sickness for the land should attack thee, as if there had been more freedom there,
and there is no “land” any longer!
The Madman. Have you ever heard of the madman who on a bright morning lighted a lantern and
ran to the market-place calling out unceasingly: “I seek God! I seek God!” As there were many people
standing about who did not believe in God, he caused a great deal of amusement. “Why! Is he lost?”
said one. “Has he strayed away like a child?” said another. “Or does he keep himself hidden? Is he
afraid of us? Has he taken a sea-voyage? Has he emigrated?” the people cried out laughingly, all in a
hubbub. The insane man jumped into their midst and transfixed them with his glances. “Where is God
gone?” he called out. “I mean to tell you! We have killed him— you and I! We are all his murderers!
But how have we done it? How were we able to drink up the sea? Who gave us the sponge to wipe away
the whole horizon? What did we do when we loosened this earth from its sun? Whither does it now
move? Whither do we move? Away from all suns? Do we not dash on unceasingly? Backwards,
sideways, forwards, in all directions? Is there still an above and below? Do we not stray, as through
infinite nothingness? Does not empty space breathe upon us? Has it not become colder? Does not night
come on continually, darker and darker? Shall we not have to light lanterns in the morning? Do we not
hear the noise of the grave-diggers who are burying God? Do we not smell the divine putrefaction? for
even Gods putrefy! God is dead! God remains dead! And we have killed him! How shall we console
ourselves, the most murderous of all murderers? The holiest and the mightiest that the world has hitherto
possessed, has bled to death under our knife, who will wipe the blood from us? With what water could
we cleanse ourselves? What lustrums, what sacred games shall we have to devise? Is not the magnitude
of this deed too great for us? Shall we not ourselves have to become Gods, merely to seem worthy of it?
There never was a greater event, and on account of it, all who are born after us belong to a higher history
than any history hitherto!” Here the madman was silent and looked again at his hearers; they also were
silent and looked at him in surprise. At last he threw his lantern on the ground, so that it broke in pieces
and was extinguished. “I come too early,” he then said, “ I am not yet at the right time. This prodigious
event is still on its way, and is travelling, it has not yet reached men’s ears. Lightning and thunder need
time, the light of the stars needs time, deeds need time, even after they are done, to be seen and heard.
This deed is as yet further from them than the furthest star, and yet they have done it!” It is further stated
that the madman made his way into different churches on the same day, and there intoned his Requiem
aeternam deo. When led out and called to account, he always gave the reply: “What are these churches
now, if they are not the tombs and monuments of God?”
Friedrich Nietzsche: The Joyful Wisdom, 115–125, decoded.
The Four Errors. Man has been created by his errors. First, he sees himself as imperfect. Second, he
gives himself imaginary qualities. Third, he sees himself in a false position in regards to animals and
nature. Fourth, he has always invented new systems of morality that he accepted. When one has
eliminated the effects of these four errors, one has also eliminated humanity and human dignity.
Herd-Instinct. Moralities always rank human impulses and activities. The ranking expresses the
needs of the herd. Morality teaches a person to become a sheep, and to value herself merely as a
function. Because cultures and their needs are different, moralities are different.
The Herd’s Sting of Conscience. We are proud of ourselves for being independent, but this has not
always been the case. For most of history, feeling independent was the worst possible feeling for a
person. Individuality was a punishment, and to be left alone ‘in solitary’ was a terrifying and miserable.
Freedom of thought was punishment too. The more one helped the herd, the more one thought of
oneself. It is in this respect that we have most changed our way of thinking.
Benevolence. Is it wicked for a lion to eat a lamb? Is it virtuous for a lamb to give its wool to the
farmer? They must do so. One must not think that submission is good and covetousness is bad. Gladness
and covetousness are united in the strong person; gladness and a desire-to-be-coveted are united in the
weak one.
No Altruism! Many people want to be used, to be a function. Among them are women who want to
be a man’s accessory. These people are parasites. They survive on the strength of their hosts.
The Madman. Have you ever heard of the madman who on a bright morning lit a lantern and ran to
the market, yelling: “I seek God! I seek God!” The people there laughed at him. “Why! is he lost?” said
one. “Has he wandered away like a child?” said another. The insane man stared. “Where is God gone?
We have killed him— you and I! We are all his murderers! But how have we done it? How were we
able to drink up the sea? What did we do when we pulled the earth from the sun? God is dead! God
remains dead! And we have killed him! Won’t we now have to become Gods? This is the greatest event
in history!” He fell silent and looked the crowds. They returned his stare. “I have come too early,” he
said, “You cannot understand me yet.” He went from church to church and, when forced out, would
scream: “These churches are merely the tombs of God!”
Karl Marx
It’s hard to like Karl Marx. His ideas have led to the deaths of hundreds of millions of people. Stalin
and Mao starved and tortured their people while mouthing phrases from the Manifesto.
Of course, Marx can hardly be held culpable for the sins of his followers. Yet Marx was himself an
ass. He kept his family in poverty while he followed dreams of being a journalist. He sponged off his
friend Engels—who was rich only because he could stomach the hypocrisy of owning a cotton mill that
exploited children and women in the very way that he claimed to deplore. While penurious and keeping
his wife and children in a tiny apartment, Marx slept with the housekeeper and knocked her up. He was
a scum-bag.
Still, while he is vile, he is important. Hold your nose. If it helps you, remind yourself that before he
died, Marx got hemorrhoids; puss-filled abscesses on his butt, neck and torso; and toothaches.
The Communist Manifesto has ingredients of all of Marx’s philosophy—and Marx’s philosophy is
huge. Notably, though, Marx never says what you think he does; he never says that we should have a
revolution. He’s too clever for that.
In short, Marx says that capitalism is about to end. It must, because it is self-destructive, in a strict
and literal sense. Capitalism must destroy itself, because competition and profits (the two essential
ingredients of capitalism) cannot co-exist.
Karl Marx: Communist Manifesto, I-II
We have proceeded from the premises of political economy. We have accepted its language and its
laws. We presupposed private property, the separation of labor, capital and land, and of wages, profit of
capital and rent of land—likewise division of labor, competition, the concept of exchange value, etc. On
the basis of political economy itself, in its own words, we have shown that the worker sinks to the level
of a commodity and becomes indeed the most wretched of commodities; that the wretchedness of the
worker is in inverse proportion to the power and magnitude of his production; that the necessary result
of competition is the accumulation of capital in a few hands, and thus the restoration of monopoly in a
more terrible form; and that finally the distinction between capitalist and land rentier, like that between
the tiller of the soil and the factory worker, disappears and that the whole of society must fall apart into
the two classes—property owners and propertyless workers.
Political economy starts with the fact of private property; it does not explain it to us. It expresses in
general, abstract formulas the material process through which private property actually passes, and these
formulas it then takes for laws. It does not comprehend these laws—i.e., it does not demonstrate how
they arise from the very nature of private property. Political economy throws no light on the cause of the
division between labor and capital, and between capital and land. When, for example, it defines the
relationship of wages to profit, it takes the interest of the capitalists to be the ultimate cause, i.e., it takes
for granted what it is supposed to explain. Similarly, competition comes in everywhere. It is explained
from external circumstances. As to how far these external and apparently accidental circumstances are
but the expression of a necessary course of development, political economy teaches us nothing. We have
seen how exchange itself appears to it as an accidental fact. The only wheels which political economy
sets in motion are greed, and the war amongst the greedy—competition.
Precisely because political economy does not grasp the way the movement is connected, it was
possible to oppose, for instance, the doctrine of competition to the doctrine of monopoly, the doctrine of
craft freedom to the doctrine of the guild, the doctrine of the division of landed property to the doctrine
of the big estate—for competition, freedom of the crafts and the division of landed property were
explained and comprehended only as accidental, premeditated and violent consequences of monopoly,
of the guild system, and of feudal property, not as their necessary, inevitable and natural consequences.
Now, therefore, we have to grasp the intrinsic connection between private property, greed, the
separation of labor, capital and landed property; the connection of exchange and competition, of value
and the devaluation of man, of monopoly and competition, etc.—the connection between this whole
estrangement and the money system.
Do not let us go back to a fictitious primordial condition as the political economist does, when he
tries to explain. Such a primordial condition explains nothing; it merely pushes the question away into a
grey nebulous distance. The economist assumes in the form of a fact, of an event, what he is supposed to
deduce—namely, the necessary relationship between two things—between, for example, division of
labor and exchange. Thus the theologian explains the origin of evil by the fall of Man—that is, he
assumes as a fact, in historical form, what has to be explained.
We proceed from an actual economic fact.
The worker becomes all the poorer the more wealth he produces, the more his production increases
in power and size. The worker becomes an ever cheaper commodity the more commodities he creates.
The devaluation of the world of men is in direct proportion to the increasing value of the world of
things. Labor produces not only commodities; it produces itself and the worker as a commodity—and
this at the same rate at which it produces commodities in general.
This fact expresses merely that the object which labor produces—labor’s product—confronts it as
something alien, as a power independent of the producer. The product of labor is labor which has been
embodied in an object, which has become material: it is the objectification of labor. Labor’s realization
is its objectification. Under these economic conditions this realization of labor appears as loss of
realization for the workers; objectification as loss of the object and bondage to it; appropriation as
estrangement, as alienation.
So much does the labor’s realization appear as loss of realization that the worker loses realization to
the point of starving to death. So much does objectification appear as loss of the object that the worker is
robbed of the objects most necessary not only for his life but for his work. Indeed, labor itself becomes
an object which he can obtain only with the greatest effort and with the most irregular interruptions. So
much does the appropriation of the object appear as estrangement that the more objects the worker
produces the less he can possess and the more he falls under the sway of his product, capital.
Political economy conceals the estrangement inherent in the nature of labor by not considering the
direct relationship between the worker (labor) and production. It is true that labor produces for the rich
wonderful things—but for the worker it produces privation. It produces palaces—but for the worker,
hovels. It produces beauty—but for the worker, deformity. It replaces labor by machines, but it throws
one section of the workers back into barbarous types of labor and it turns the other section into a
machine. It produces intelligence—but for the worker, stupidity, cretinism.
The direct relationship of labor to its products is the relationship of the worker to the objects of his
production. The relationship of the man of means to the objects of production and to production itself is
only a consequence of this first relationship—and confirms it. We shall consider this other aspect later.
When we ask, then, what is the essential relationship of labor we are asking about the relationship of the
worker to production.
Till now we have been considering the estrangement, the alienation of the worker only in one of its
aspects, i.e., the worker’s relationship to the products of his labor. But the estrangement is manifested
not only in the result but in the act of production, within the producing activity, itself. How could the
worker come to face the product of his activity as a stranger, were it not that in the very act of
production he was estranging himself from himself? The product is after all but the summary of the
activity, of production. If then the product of labor is alienation, production itself must be active
alienation, the alienation of activity, the activity of alienation. In the estrangement of the object of labor
is merely summarized the estrangement, the alienation, in the activity of labor itself.
What, then, constitutes the alienation of labor?
First, the fact that labor is external to the worker, i.e., it does not belong to his intrinsic nature; that in
his work, therefore, he does not affirm himself but denies himself, does not feel content but unhappy,
does not develop freely his physical and mental energy but mortifies his body and ruins his mind. The
worker therefore only feels himself outside his work, and in his work feels outside himself. He feels at
home when he is not working, and when he is working he does not feel at home. His labor is therefore
not voluntary, but coerced; it is forced labor. It is therefore not the satisfaction of a need; it is merely a
means to satisfy needs external to it. Its alien character emerges clearly in the fact that as soon as no
physical or other compulsion exists, labor is shunned like the plague. External labor, labor in which man
alienates himself, is a labor of self-sacrifice, of mortification. Lastly, the external character of labor for
the worker appears in the fact that it is not his own, but someone else’s, that it does not belong to him,
that in it he belongs, not to himself, but to another. Just as in religion the spontaneous activity of the
human imagination, of the human brain and the human heart, operates on the individual independently
of him—that is, operates as an alien, divine or diabolical activity—so is the worker’s activity not his
spontaneous activity. It belongs to another; it is the loss of his self.
As a result, therefore, man (the worker) only feels himself freely active in his animal functions—
eating, drinking, procreating, or at most in his dwelling and in dressing-up, etc.; and in his human
functions he no longer feels himself to be anything but an animal. What is animal becomes human and
what is human becomes animal.
Certainly eating, drinking, procreating, etc., are also genuinely human functions. But taken
abstractly, separated from the sphere of all other human activity and turned into sole and ultimate ends,
they are animal functions.
We have considered the act of estranging practical human activity, labor, in two of its aspects. (1)
The relation of the worker to the product of labor as an alien object exercising power over him. This
relation is at the same time the relation to the sensuous external world, to the objects of nature, as an
alien world inimically opposed to him. (2) The relation of labor to the act of production within the labor
process. This relation is the relation of the worker to his own activity as an alien activity not belonging
to him; it is activity as suffering, strength as weakness, begetting as emasculating, the worker’s own
physical and mental energy, his personal life—for what is life but activity?—as an activity which is
turned against him, independent of him and not belonging to him. Here we have self-estrangement, as
previously we had the estrangement of the thing.
We have still a third aspect of estranged labor to deduce from the two already considered.
Man is a species-being, not only because in practice and in theory he adopts the species (his own as
well as those of other things) as his object, but—and this is only another way of expressing it—also
because he treats himself as the actual, living species; because he treats himself as a universal and
therefore a free being.
The life of the species, both in man and in animals, consists physically in the fact that man (like the
animal) lives on organic nature; and the more universal man (or the animal) is, the more universal is the
sphere of inorganic nature on which he lives. Just as plants, animals, stones, air, light, etc., constitute
theoretically a part of human consciousness, partly as objects of natural science, partly as objects of
art—his spiritual inorganic nature, spiritual nourishment which he must first prepare to make palatable
and digestible—so also in the realm of practice they constitute a part of human life and human activity.
Physically man lives only on these products of nature, whether they appear in the form of food, heating,
clothes, a dwelling, etc. The universality of man appears in practice precisely in the universality which
makes all nature his inorganic body—both inasmuch as nature is (1) his direct means of life, and (2) the
material, the object, and the instrument of his life activity. Nature is man’s inorganic body—nature, that
is, insofar as it is not itself human body. Man lives on nature—means that nature is his body, with which
he must remain in continuous interchange if he is not to die. That man’s physical and spiritual life is
linked to nature means simply that nature is linked to itself, for man is a part of nature.
In estranging from man (1) nature, and (2) himself, his own active functions, his life activity,
estranged labor estranges the species from man. It changes for him the life of the species into a means of
individual life. First it estranges the life of the species and individual life, and secondly it makes
individual life in its abstract form the purpose of the life of the species, likewise in its abstract and
estranged form.
For labor, life activity, productive life itself, appears to man in the first place merely as a means of
satisfying a need—the need to maintain physical existence. Yet the productive life is the life of the
species. It is life-engendering life. The whole character of a species, its species-character, is contained in
the character of its life activity; and free, conscious activity is man’s species-character. Life itself
appears only as a means to life.
The animal is immediately one with its life activity. It does not distinguish itself from it. It is its life
activity. Man makes his life activity itself the object of his will and of his consciousness. He has
conscious life activity. It is not a determination with which he directly merges. Conscious life activity
distinguishes man immediately from animal life activity. It is just because of this that he is a species-
being. Or it is only because he is a species-being that he is a conscious being, i.e., that his own life is an
object for him. Only because of that is his activity free activity. Estranged labor reverses the
relationship, so that it is just because man is a conscious being that he makes his life activity, his
essential being, a mere means to his existence.
In creating a world of objects by his personal activity, in his work upon inorganic nature, man proves
himself a conscious species-being, i.e., as a being that treats the species as his own essential being, or
that treats itself as a species-being. Admittedly animals also produce. They build themselves nests,
dwellings, like the bees, beavers, ants, etc. But an animal only produces what it immediately needs for
itself or its young. It produces one-sidedly, whilst man produces universally. It produces only under the
dominion of immediate physical need, whilst man produces even when he is free from physical need and
only truly produces in freedom therefrom. An animal produces only itself, whilst man reproduces the
whole of nature. An animal’s product belongs immediately to its physical body, whilst man freely
confronts his product. An animal forms only in accordance with the standard and the need of the species
to which it belongs, whilst man knows how to produce in accordance with the standard of every species,
and knows how to apply everywhere the inherent standard to the object. Man therefore also forms
objects in accordance with the laws of beauty.
It is just in his work upon the objective world, therefore, that man really proves himself to be a
species-being. This production is his active species-life. Through this production, nature appears as his
work and his reality. The object of labor is, therefore, the objectification of man’s species-life: for he
duplicates himself not only, as in consciousness, intellectually, but also actively, in reality, and therefore
he sees himself in a world that he has created. In tearing away from man the object of his production,
therefore, estranged labor tears from him his species-life, his real objectivity as a member of the species
and transforms his advantage over animals into the disadvantage that his inorganic body, nature, is taken
from him.
Similarly, in degrading spontaneous, free activity to a means, estranged labor makes man’s species-
life a means to his physical existence.
The consciousness which man has of his species is thus transformed by estrangement in such a way
that species becomes for him a means.
Estranged labor turns thus:
(3) Man’s species-being, both nature and his spiritual species-property, into a being alien to him,
into a means of his individual existence. It estranges from man his own body, as well as external nature
and his spiritual aspect, his human aspect.
(4) An immediate consequence of the fact that man is estranged from the product of his labor, from
his life activity, from his species-being, is the estrangement of man from man. When man confronts
himself, he confronts the other man. What applies to a man’s relation to his work, to the product of his
labor and to himself, also holds of a man’s relation to the other man, and to the other man’s labor and
object of labor.
In fact, the proposition that man’s species-nature is estranged from him means that one man is
estranged from the other, as each of them is from man’s essential nature.
The estrangement of man, and in fact every relationship in which man stands to himself, is realized
and expressed only in the relationship in which a man stands to other men.
Hence within the relationship of estranged labor each man views the other in accordance with the
standard and the relationship in which he finds himself as a worker.
We took our departure from a fact of political economy—the estrangement of the worker and his
production. We have formulated this fact in conceptual terms as estranged, alienated labor. We have
analyzed this concept—hence analyzing merely a fact of political economy.
Let us now see, further, how the concept of estranged, alienated labor must express and present itself
in real life.
If the product of labor is alien to me, if it confronts me as an alien power, to whom, then, does it
belong?
To a being other than myself.
Who is this being?
The gods? To be sure, in the earliest times the principal production (for example, the building of
temples, etc., in Egypt, India and Mexico) appears to be in the service of the gods, and the product
belongs to the gods. However, the gods on their own were never the lords of labor. No more was nature.
And what a contradiction it would be if, the more man subjugated nature by his labor and the more the
miracles of the gods were rendered superfluous by the miracles of industry, the more man were to
renounce the joy of production and the enjoyment of the product to please these powers.
The alien being, to whom labor and the product of labor belongs, in whose service labor is done and
for whose benefit the product of labor is provided, can only be man himself.
If the product of labor does not belong to the worker, if it confronts him as an alien power, then this
can only be because it belongs to some other man than the worker. If the worker’s activity is a torment
to him, to another it must give satisfaction and pleasure. Not the gods, not nature, but only man himself
can be this alien power over man.
We must bear in mind the previous proposition that man’s relation to himself becomes for him
objective and actual through his relation to the other man. Thus, if the product of his labor, his labor
objectified, is for him an alien, hostile, powerful object independent of him, then his position towards it
is such that someone else is master of this object, someone who is alien, hostile, powerful, and
independent of him. If he treats his own activity as an unfree activity, then he treats it as an activity
performed in the service, under the dominion, the coercion, and the yoke of another man.
Every self-estrangement of man, from himself and from nature, appears in the relation in which he
places himself and nature to men other than and differentiated from himself. For this reason religious
self-estrangement necessarily appears in the relationship of the layman to the priest, or again to a
mediator, etc., since we are here dealing with the intellectual world. In the real practical world self-
estrangement can only become manifest through the real practical relationship to other men. The
medium through which estrangement takes place is itself practical. Thus through estranged labor man
not only creates his relationship to the object and to the act of production as to powers that are alien and
hostile to him; he also creates the relationship in which other men stand to his production and to his
product, and the relationship in which he stands to these other men. Just as he creates his own
production as the loss of his reality, as his punishment; his own product as a loss, as a product not
belonging to him; so he creates the domination of the person who does not produce over production and
over the product. Just as he estranges his own activity from himself, so he confers upon the stranger an
activity which is not his own.
We have until now considered this relationship only from the standpoint of the worker and later on
we shall be considering it also from the standpoint of the non-worker.
Through estranged, alienated labor, then, the worker produces the relationship to this labor of a man
alien to labor and standing outside it. The relationship of the worker to labor creates the relation to it of
the capitalist (or whatever one chooses to call the master of labor). Private property is thus the product,
the result, the necessary consequence, of alienated labor, of the external relation of the worker to nature
and to himself.
Private property thus results by analysis from the concept of alienated labor, i.e., of alienated man, of
estranged labor, of estranged life, of estranged man.
True, it is as a result of the movement of private property that we have obtained the concept of
alienated labor (of alienated life) in political economy. But on analysis of this concept it becomes clear
that though private property appears to be the reason, the cause of alienated labor, it is rather its
consequence, just as the gods are originally not the cause but the effect of man’s intellectual confusion.
Later this relationship becomes reciprocal.
Only at the culmination of the development of private property does this, its secret, appear again,
namely, that on the one hand it is the product of alienated labor, and that on the other it is the means by
which labor alienates itself, the realization of this alienation.
This exposition immediately sheds light on various hitherto unsolved conflicts.
(1) Political economy starts from labor as the real soul of production; yet to labor it gives nothing,
and to private property everything. Confronting this contradiction, Proudhon has decided in favor of
labor against private property. We understand, however, that this apparent contradiction is the
contradiction of estranged labor with itself, and that political economy has merely formulated the laws
of estranged labor.
We also understand, therefore, that wages and private property are identical. Indeed, where the
product, as the object of labor, pays for labor itself, there the wage is but a necessary consequence of
labor’s estrangement. Likewise, in the wage of labor, labor does not appear as an end in itself but as the
servant of the wage. We shall develop this point later, and meanwhile will only draw some conclusions.
An enforced increase of wages (disregarding all other difficulties, including the fact that it would
only be by force, too, that such an increase, being an anomaly, could be maintained) would therefore be
nothing but better payment for the slave, and would not win either for the worker or for labor their
human status and dignity.
Indeed, even the equality of wages, as demanded by Proudhon, only transforms the relationship of
the present-day worker to his labor into the relationship of all men to labor. Society would then be
conceived as an abstract capitalist.
Wages are a direct consequence of estranged labor, and estranged labor is the direct cause of private
property. The downfall of the one must therefore involve the downfall of the other.
(2) From the relationship of estranged labor to private property it follows further that the
emancipation of society from private property, etc., from servitude, is expressed in the political form of
the emancipation of the workers; not that their emancipation alone is at stake, but because the
emancipation of the workers contains universal human emancipation—and it contains this because the
whole of human servitude is involved in the relation of the worker to production, and all relations of
servitude are but modifications and consequences of this relation.
Just as we have derived the concept of private property from the concept of estranged, alienated
labor by analysis, so we can develop every category of political economy with the help of these two
factors; and we shall find again in each category, e.g., trade, competition, capital, money only a
particular and developed expression of these first elements.
Karl Marx: Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844: Estranged Labour, decoded
I have followed the ‘laws’ of economists. I have learned what they have to teach. And, according to
even orthodox economics, the worker becomes a thing, a commodity. The worker becomes the most
wretched of commodities. As her job gets worse and worse, she becomes more and more like a thing or
a tool. Competition makes a few factory owners rich, and gives them the power of monopoly.
Eventually, competition means that there will be only two kinds of people: the people who own
companies, and the people who work in them.
The field of political economy starts with the fact of private property; it does not explain it to us. It
never explains how or why some people get rich while others get poor, or why some people own
factories while others own nothing. No, economics pretends that these are laws. It does not comprehend
how they arise from the very nature of private property. Economics does not explain land, labour and
capital; it merely accepts them. When economists try to explain the relationship between wages and
profit, they assume that that profit determines wages; in this way, they assume the very thing that they
are trying to explain. Similarly, competition is ‘exogenous’; it is an assumption. No economist explains
what causes competition, or how it, like all of capitalism, is the result of history. Political economy is
used to justify capitalism; it sets the wheels of greed in motion.
Economists set up dichotomies that do not exist: between competition and monopoly, craftsperson
and unionist, feudalism and farmers’ ownership. Economists cannot see that monopoly, unions, and
landowning farmers are the inevitable consequences of the systems that precede them.
Therefore, we must see the connection between the estrangement of labour and the money system:
the connection between money and greed, exchange and the devaluation of workers, private property,
and the division of land, labour, and capital.
We do not need to go back to the fictitious ‘original condition’. That explains nothing. It merely
pushes the question away in to a grey, nebulous distance. The economist is forever assuming what she is
trying to prove—namely, the relationships between, for example, division of labour an exchange. This is
just arguing in a circle.
We proceed from an actual economic fact.
Workers become poorer the more wealth they produce. The more a worker produces, the richer her
employer gets. The more a worker produces, the cheaper she becomes. We diminish ourselves as we
strengthen the world of things. Labour makes things, yet labour makes labour itself into a thing to be
sold.
The things we produce at work are foreign to us. They confront us; they are hostile to us. Our labour
is embodied in these objects, and when we work for the capitalist, the things we work on become
symbols of our oppression.
We work and produce these foreign objects, and they enrich our oppressors. As we work, we lose
our own power—we even lose the power to work. By working, we put ourselves out of work.
Economists do not consider the ways that workers and employers relate to each other. The worker
produces wonderful things, but the rich enjoy them. The worker builds palaces—but not for herself. She
produces beauty—and deforms herself. One worker produces the very machines that will replace other,
throwing some of them onto the street, and turning the rest into button-pushing robots.
The rich see the products of work differently than the poor do. We will consider the rich later, but
now I want to address how workers see the things they produce.
We have been considering the estrangement of a worker from the things she produces, but we should
also consider the alienation of a worker from the process of production. The product is only the final
part; the product of labour is alienation, but production is alienation to. It is the activity of alienation.
The object merely sums that alienation up.
What, then, is the alienation of labor?
First, the alienation is the fact that the labor is external to the worker; it does not belong to her
intrinsic nature. A worker does not affirm herself in her work. Instead, she denies who she is, and feels
unhappy. She does not develop her physical and mental energy; she ruins her body and her mind. The
worker only feels like a person when she is not working. She only feels at home when she is not
working. She does not work voluntarily; she is coerced to work by money. She does not work to satisfy
an internal need; she works to satisfy external needs. We can tell that modern work is alienated because
nobody would do it unless they were being paid. As soon as the whistle blows, workers flee their
workplace. Work like this is sacrifice, not vital. Work is alienated because the worker’s product does not
belong to her. It belongs to her employer. The employer is like a demon sitting on the worker’s shoulder,
watching everything she does, making her work ever harder. She is a puppet, and he is the puppeteer.
Workers only feel free when they behave like animals, when they eat, drink, and fuck. They do not
feel like people when they do the most human of activities: produce things with tools. What is animal
becomes human and what is human becomes animal.
Certainly eating, drinking, and fucking are real human functions. But taken alone, as the goal of life,
they are animal functions.
We have considered how people become alienated from the things they produce and from the act of
working. But there is a third aspect of alienated labour to consider.
People are a species-beings. A person thinks of other people when she works, and treats herself as if
she were the whole species. She thinks of herself as a complete person, a ‘universal’, and as a free being.
Humans eat and consume the world’s resources. So do plants and animals. But nature is more than
just our sustenance; it is a part of our consciousness, the object of our art and science, and a spiritual
sustenance. We are a part of nature.
Labour estranges us from nature and ourselves. Labour makes our own life activity foreign to us. We
see each other as means to our own satisfaction. We see each other as enemies. We start to think of
others as existing for us, not with us.
We see work as the way to keep ourselves alive, instead of life’s activity. People produce; that is
what we do. It is the essentially human activity. Yet, when we labour, we see work as a means to life—
life appears to be a means to life.
Animals live in the moment. They are always ‘living’. People think about their lives, take a step
back, and make their lives into projects, and think about their life activities. People are conscious of their
lives; they do not merge into the flow of living. This is what makes us people. It is also what makes us
species-beings. Or perhaps it is the other way around. But being conscious of our work frees us from it.
We are not robots or animals. We can choose what we want to produce—except when we are labouring.
Estranged labour turns us back into animals, unable to choose, and means that we are conscious of
making our life’s work just plain work—a means to our existence.
Humans produce, and they create a world of objects. They prove that they are conscious species-
beings by doing this. I admit that some animals build nests and such, but an animal produces for now
and for itself and its young. Animals produce for physical need. Only humans produce universally, and
even when we are free from need—in fact, we can only produce freely when we are not producing
something we need. People also produce art.
When we work on the natural world, we show ourselves to be species-beings with species-life. A
free worker makes nature her work and her reality. She thing she creates is part of her; it is her. She puts
her soul into the work and the world she creates, and she creates things for other people to see, to show
herself and her world to them. Estranged labour tears the work away from her, and tears her away from
her species.
Estranged labour also makes work a means to life, instead of an essential part of life. It turns other
people into means for the survival of each individual.
Estranged labour turns a person’s species-being into something other than how she sees herself, into
something foreign. She does not see herself as a member of the human race. It also estranges a person
from her own body, her own nature, and her own spirit—her humanity.
Therefore we are estranged from each other. When we look in the mirror, we see how others see us.
When we look at our work, we see how others see it. When we look at another’s work, we do not see the
person; we see a thing.
Let us now see how the estranged, alienated labor shows up in real life.
To whom does my work belong?
To a being other than myself.
To the gods? A long time ago, maybe, people worked to serve the gods, but no longer. Now my
work belongs to someone, a person.
My work torments me it is because it belongs to someone else. It torments be because it brings
another person pleasure.
A person knows herself by the work she does. Thus, if the work is a foreign object, hostile to her,
then she must see someone else as owning it—and as owning her. If her activity is not really her own,
then she is not her own person; her act of creation was done for another person’s benefit. She created,
but not freely; she created because she had to, because she was enslaved.
All estrangement is the same. For instance, religious self-estrangement happens when the laity have
a relationship with priests. In the real world, self-estrangement happens when people have a practical
relationship with one another. A practical relationship is one of work. Work divides people into classes,
and one class dominates the other. Some people own, but do not produce; they have status and
dominion. They have the power to seize the work of another.
I have only discussed the standpoint of the worker, not the non-worker. I will soon.
Alienated labour creates a relationship with the capitalist. Private property is the result of alienated
labour, not its cause. The capitalist owns what the worker produces.
Private property thus comes from alienated labour, from alienated man, from estranged labor, from
an estranged life.
True, I am arguing in a circle. Before, I said that private property leads to alienated labour, and now
I am saying that alienated labour leads to private property. But, by analyzing the concept, we see that
private property is the consequence, not the cause, of alienation. Only later does the relationship become
reciprocal, and it is only when capitalism is at its peak that the circle of cause and effect becomes clear
again.
A few conflicts are solved by this exposition:
First, economists worship private property. Proudhon thought that labour should triumph against
private property. We understand that there is a third way, and we do not need to choose one over the
other. Private property and labour create each other.
We also understand, therefore, that wages and private property are identical. Wages pay for
estrangement, and wages get people working.
A wage increase (which would not be sustainable, since it would have to be done by force), would
be merely better payment for the slave. It would not return dignity to work. Even wage equality would
not work. It would make society the capitalist and all of us slaves.
Estranged labour causes wages and private property. The downfall of one must be the downfall of
both.
Second, since all forms of servitude are forms of alienation, emancipating workers emancipates
everyone. Alienation leads to private property, and it also leads to all of economic theory: trade,
competition, capital, money—these are all just other expressions of the same idea.
John Stuart Mill
Mill was one of the most rock-and-roll guys of the nineteenth century. He learned to speak ancient
Greek before he was three years old. By the time he was eight, he was reading the old geometers in
Latin. He was a brilliant logician and economist by his teens. To call him a very great genius is a huge
understatement.
Mill’s father, who was somewhat famous himself, had put him through a brutal education. Not
surprisingly, Mill had a nervous breakdown when he left home. Mill recovered, though, and became a
women’s-lib and antislavery writer, an eminent philosopher, political thinker, Member of Parliament,
and cultivator of third-degree sideburns. He married his lifelong sweetheart when he was 45, after she
had finally divorced her deadbeat first husband.
Like Kant, Mill is trying to come up with a single rule of ethics. Mill, though, is a consequentialist.
He believes that consequences matter and intentions do not. Like Epicurus and Aristotle, Mill is a
hedonist. All three believe that humans do (or should) strive for happiness. Unlike the Greeks, though,
Mill believes that we should try to make everyone happy, not just ourselves. Good actions, then, are
those that create the most happiness for the most people—that, in a nutshell, is his whole philosophy,
called “utilitarianism”
Utilitarianism has been enormously influential, not least because it is so easy to sum up. It provides a
philosophical foundation for law, democracy, and economics that still pervades western life.
John Stuart Mill: U'litarianism, Chapter 2
What utilitarianism is
The Greatest Happiness Principle is this: actions are right if they tend to promote happiness, wrong
if they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness I mean pleasure, and the absence of pain;
by unhappiness, pain, and the absence of pleasure.
Pleasure and freedom from pain are the only things people really want. Everything else we only
want because it brings us pleasure or prevents pain.
Of course, many smart people think that I am wrong. They think that utilitarianism is a doctrine for
pigs and partiers, since utilitarians put pleasure above everything else. Many think that ours is a
philosophy of crassness and simplicity.
The Epicureans responded simply. If you think that men can only find pleasure in the same things as
pigs, you are crass, and you are simple. Epicureans (and utilitarians) think that many noble things are
pleasant. Intellect, sentiment, emotions, imagination, and morality are all pleasant.
That said, I admit that most utilitarians have said the intellectual goods are better only because the
bodily pleasures are fleeting or expensive. We certainly could have done better.
Some types of pleasure are of a higher quality than other types. We know this because there are
some pleasant things that we would never trade for any amount of another, yet worse, pleasant thing.
Nobody, for instance, would give away her intellect and be changed into an animal, even for all the
beast’s pleasures. No poor genius would like to be changed into a rich idiot. No ethical person would be
selfish, stupid and base, even if it came with some—or even many—advantages. Because no quantity of
base pleasure adds up to even the smallest quantity of higher pleasure, the two pleasures are clearly of
different qualities.
Certainly, a smart person is harder to make happy and easier to make sad. Still, nobody would prefer
to be stupid. Perhaps it is pride; maybe it is love of liberty. I think that it is a sense of dignity that
prevents the intelligent from wishing they were not.
It is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied; better to be Socrates dissatisfied than
a fool satisfied. And if the fool, or the pig, are a different opinion, it is because they only know their own
side of the question. The other party to the comparison knows both sides.
Of course, I know that some good, noble, educated people do succumb to lower pleasures. They do it
because have weak characters, and they usually do so only momentarily. Of course, some young
idealists become selfish, lazy, and obnoxious. Nor does this disprove my point. Sensitivity is like a
tender plant, easily killed. We must all take care to ensure that our aspirations and our intellectual tastes
are not damaged or destroyed when our way is blocked or our ambitions are thwarted by the workings of
the world.
So it is settled. There are different types of pleasure, some higher, and some lower. As it turns out,
though, this past discussion is not entirely necessary. The utilitarian standard is not one’s own happiness,
but everyone’s happiness in total. The best actions lead to the greatest happiness for all people.
Some people say that renunciation of all desire is preferable. First, they say, happiness is
unattainable. Second, they ask, what right have you to be happy? A good point, I suppose. Yet even if
we cannot be happy, we can be not unhappy. Further, a good life is not a life of constant bliss. It has its
ups and downs. But only a very few of us have a good life right now; the rest of us work in demonic
industries and get no chance at happiness whatsoever.
Perhaps human beings, if they were taught to consider the happiness of all people as their goal,
would only want a small share for themselves. Great numbers of humanity have been satisfied with
much less.
It seems to me that every person born in a civilized country could have an intellectual life of
pleasure. In a world in which there is so much of interest, so much to enjoy, and so much also to correct
and improve, everyone who has even a moderate amount of moral and intellectual ability is capable of a
wonderful life. There is almost no great cause of human suffering that could not be fixed if we directed
our attention to it.
Of course, nobody needs to be happy. The great bulk of us are not happy, even in the parts of the
world not knee-deep in barbarism. In fact, being able to do without happiness is probably the best
strategy for finding it. Only that kind of attitude can make a person aware of the chances of life, and
make him or her immune to ill fate and evil.
Again, it is not a person’s own happiness that matters. It is the happiness of all. A person should try
to be an objective spectator. She should count herself and her own happiness as one among many. Jesus
said to do as you would be done by, and to love your neighbour as yourself. That is our ideal, too. We
believe that laws and social arrangements should harmonize individual interests with the interests of the
whole, and that education should establish in each person the association between her own happiness
and everyone’s happiness.
Some say that it is too hard to be a utilitarian. They think that it is impossible to act with society’s
interests in mind all the time. That is a mistake: the Greatest Happiness Principle is a standard, not a rule
that needs to always be followed. Ninety-nine percent of our actions will be motivated by other
considerations. We can always judge the actions, though, by the Greatest Happiness Principle. Motive,
though, has nothing to do with the morality of an action. He who saves a fellow creature from drowning
does what is morally right, whether his motive is duty or the hope of being paid.
Other critics say that it is impossible to calculate the outcomes for all people and for all time. Most
of us never need to do this. It is enough to just keep in mind the people nearest the action you are
considering. You do not need to stop to consider, for instance, whether you are rescuing a saint or a
monster from icy water.
Finally, some critics say that utilitarians are cold. They say this because we are interested only in the
outcomes of an action, not who does the action. We think that this is a virtue. If the pope does wrong,
we will say so. If Hitler did good, we would say so. In the long run, however, the best proof of a good
character is good actions. On average, a good person will do good things; a bad person will do bad
things. Sometimes, a good person will do a bad thing. We alone will say so.
Jean Paul Sartre
Sartre was one of those intolerable geniuses who was born great (I prefer mine to suffer for
greatness). He was, until his death in 1980, a truly public figure known the world over. If you think
philosophers wear berets and smoke pipes, Sartre is the reason. Less well known, however, is that he
drank liters of booze and smoked two packs a day—and he nursed an impressive amphetamine habit. I
sometimes wonder if I’m not a great genius because I don’t drink, smoke, and do enough speed.
Sartre went to the very best schools in France and did well, except for the time he failed the most
important exam in the country, the exam that makes and breaks careers: the Agrégration. He said he
failed it because he gave original answers while the graders were looking for rote ones. He took the
exam again the next year and passed. In fact, he placed first in the country and proposed to the woman
who had come second, Simone de Beauvoir. She turned him down. (They did go on to have a famous
and decades-long love affair.)
Very few philosophers ever enter the public mind, but Sartre did. He was an icon of France, of
philosophy, and of an engaged intellectual. He was also a man of principle: when he was offered the
Nobel Prize (and $400,000!), he turned it down, believing that it was too bourgeois. He probably didn’t
need the money, though. One of his plays, Nausea, sold more than a million copies in his lifetime—and
doesn’t it say something wonderful about the French that they would buy a million copies of an
existentialist play?
Despite the booze, smokes, women, and drugs, Sartre lived a long, productive life. He died, at 74, in
Paris, the city in which he was born and in which he lived almost his entire life.
Jean Paul Sartre, Existen'alism is a Humanism, edited
Texts
Aristotle. “Nicomachean Ethics.” The Internet Classics Archive | Nicomachean Ethics by Aristotle,
n.d. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/nicomachaen.1.i.html.
Descartes, René. “Descartes’ Meditations.” Translated by John Veitch. Descartes’ Meditations, n.d.
http://www.wright.edu/cola/descartes/mede.html.
Epicurus. “Principal Doctrines.” Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew. The Internet Classics Archive |
Principal Doctrines by Epicurus, n.d. http://classics.mit.edu/Epicurus/princdoc.html.
Hobbes, Thomas. “Leviathan.” Leviathan, by Thomas Hobbes, October 11, 2009.
http://www.gutenberg.org/files/3207/3207-h/3207-h.htm.
Hume, David. “An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding.” The Project Gutenberg eBook of
An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, by David Hume., n.d.
http://www.gutenberg.org/files/9662/9662-h/9662-h.htm.
Kant, Immanuel. “Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals.” Translated by Thomas
Kingsmill Abbott. Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals by Immanuel Kant - Project
Gutenberg, n.d. http://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/5682.
———. “Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics.” Translated by Paul Carus. Full Text of “Kant’s
Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics”, n.d.
http://www.archive.org/stream/kantsprolegomena00kantuoft/kantsprolegomena00kantuoft_djvu.txt.
Locke, John. “An Essay Concerning Human Understanding.” An Essay Concering Human
Understanding, n.d. http://marxists.org/reference/subject/philosophy/works/en/locke.htm.
Machiavelli, Nicolo. “The Prince.” Translated by W. K. Marriott. The Prince, by Nicolo
Machiavelli, n.d. http://www.gutenberg.org/files/1232/1232-h/1232-h.htm.
Marcus Aurelius. “The Internet Classics Archive | The Meditations by Marcus Aurelius.” Translated
by Long, George, n.d. http://classics.mit.edu/Antoninus/meditations.html.
Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels. “Manifesto of the Communist Party.” Manifesto of the
Communist Party, 2000. http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1848/communist-manifesto/.
Mill, John Stuart. “Utilitarianism.” Utilitarianism by John Stuart Mill, n.d.
http://www.utilitarianism.com/mill2.htm.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. “Beyond Good and Evil.” Translated by Helen Zimmern. Beyond Good and
Evil, by Friedrich Nietzsche, n.d. http://www.gutenberg.org/files/4363/4363-h/4363-h.htm.
Plato. “Phaedo.” Translated by Benjamin Jowett. The Internet Classics Archive | Phaedo by Plato,
n.d. http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/phaedo.html.
———. “The Apology of Socrates.” Translated by Jowett, Benjamin. The Apology of Socrates.
Plato. 1909-14. The Apology, Phædo and Crito. The Harvard Classics, 2001.
http://www.bartleby.com/2/1/1.html.
———. “The Republic.” Translated by Benjamin Jowett. The Internet Classics Archive | The
Republic by Plato, n.d. http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/republic.3.ii.html.
Russell, Bertrand. “The Reading Selection from Problems of Philosophy.” Reading for Philosophical
Inquiry: A Brief Introduction to Philosophical Thinking Ver. 0.21; An Open Source Reader, n.d.
http://philosophy.lander.edu/intro/introbook2.1/x2093.html.
Sartre, Jean Paul. “L’existentialisme Est Un Humanisme.” Translated by Adam Norman and Google,
n.d. http://www.danielmartin.eu/Textes/Existentialisme.htm.