Schizophrenia. Van Duppen - The Meaning and Relevance of Minkowsky Loss of Vital Contact With Reality, 2017
Schizophrenia. Van Duppen - The Meaning and Relevance of Minkowsky Loss of Vital Contact With Reality, 2017
Schizophrenia. Van Duppen - The Meaning and Relevance of Minkowsky Loss of Vital Contact With Reality, 2017
P
Abstract: Eugène Minkowski is among the most henomenological psychopathology
prominent figures in phenomenological psychopathol- is a research field that aims to investigate
ogy. His notion of the ‘loss of vital contact with reality’ and describe the subjective experience of
remains a key concept in the phenomenological descrip-
mental disorders. By suspending the assumptions
tion of schizophrenia. However, the precise meaning and
relevance of this concept is unclear. Consequently, its
about etiology and causality as much as possible,
use in psychopathological research is questionable. The and by focusing on the subjective experiences of
purpose of this article is to investigate the meaning of the patient, it is supposed to offer a profound
the concept, and to evaluate its relevance in the con- understanding of the patient’s suffering, and of
temporary research on intersubjectivity. The results of the disorder in general. Clarity in the description
this thematic interpretation show that the notion can of these experiences is, therefore, a necessity.
be deconstructed into three building blocks: ‘reality,’
Traditionally, phenomenological psychopathology
‘contact with reality,’ and ‘vital contact.’ Their respec-
tive philosophical and psychopathological meanings
was studied mostly by European, and particularly
are discussed in detail. This interpretation allows us by German and French psychiatrists, such as Karl
to challenge specific ideas on social cognition, and it Jaspers, Wolfgang Blankenburg, and Eugène
sheds a new light on the phenomenological description Minkowski. Today, psychopathologists like Josef
of schizophrenia as a self-disorder. Despite the inher- Parnas, Giovanni Stanghellini, Louis Sass, and
ent limitations, Minkowski’s notion provides tools for Thomas Fuchs represent the most recent move-
investigating the form and specificity of intersubjectivity ment of phenomenological psychopathology.
disturbances in schizophrenia. This article offers the first
One of the exciting results of their research is the
step in this process.
phenomenological description of schizophrenia
Keywords: Phenomenology, Minkowski, vital contact as a disorder of the self (Sass & Parnas, 2003).
with reality, schizophrenia, intersubjectivity, psycho- They explicitly refer to the authors and concepts
pathology
of the first generation of phenomenological psy-
chopathologists, including Minkowski. Today,
Minkowski is especially known for his work on
schizophrenia.
Minkowski was greatly inspired by the French tive components (Fuchs, 2010; Gallagher, 2014;
philosopher Henri Bergson (Urfer, 2001). This Parnas, Sass, & Zahavi, 2013; Stanghellini &
influence can be noted throughout his work. It is Lysaker, 2007). Both in phenomenological phi-
one of the reasons why his psychopathology was losophy and in psychopathology, central research
innovative, compared with his contemporaries. questions today concern intersubjectivity (Fuchs
According to Minkowski, the ultimate goal of phe- & De Jaegher, 2009; Kyselo, 2014; Maclaren,
nomenological psychopathology should be finding 2008; Sass, 2014; Zahavi, 2014). It is a serious
the “trouble générateur” (Minkowski, 1966, p. endeavor to describe a coherent hypothesis on the
53) of an illness, by ‘penetrating’ (Minkowski, disturbances of the self and intersubjectivity, based
1966, p. 461) through the superficial symptoms. on clinical experience. The question is whether
A variety of phenomenological authors have Minkowski’s notion can help us with this. As Urfer
written on Minkowski’s ideas in more detail (Bovet already remarked, Minkowski’s phenomenologi-
& Parnas, 1993 Lysaker & Lysaker, 2010; Passie, cal approach concerns the intersubjective space
1995; Stanghellini & Ballerini, 2007; Tatossian, of “entre deux” (2001, p. 281), and Minkowski
1979; Varga, 2012). Several key concepts in the might indeed prove to be a psychopathologist of
contemporary literature refer directly to his work, the in-between.
for example ‘schizophrenic autism’ (Parnas &
Bovet, 1991), ‘morbid rationality’ (Sass, 2001), Method
and ‘phenomenological compensation’ (Urfer,
2001). The ‘loss of vital contact with reality’ is To determine the meaning of Minkowski’s ‘loss
arguably the most central notion in his work. It of vital contact with reality’ for the contemporary
is often used to elucidate certain symptoms and discussion on intersubjectivity, I present a thematic
experiences of schizophrenic patients. Schwartz, interpretation. The notion is first deconstructed
Wiggins, Naudin, and Spitzer (2005, p. 110) un- into three ‘building blocks.’ These are the most
derstand it as a destruction of the “manifestness basic notion of ‘reality’, followed by ‘contact with
and coherence” of the person’s being-in-the-world. reality’, and lastly ‘vital contact with reality’. They
Louis Sass compares it to patients’ experiences are analyzed with reference to Minkowski’s psy-
of dulling of their subjective lives, and remarks chopathological works, particularly those dealing
that the negative symptoms do not capture what with schizophrenia. These include his most impor-
Minkowski means (Sass, 2001, p. 255). tant books, La Schizophrénie (Minkowski, 1927),
Despite the recent attention for Minkowski’s Le temps vécu (Minkowski, 1995), and Traité de
work, and for his notion of the ‘loss of vital contact Psychopathologie (Minkowski, 1966). The lit-
with reality’ more specifically, it remains unclear erature study includes, furthermore, three articles
what the latter exactly means. Consequently, the that help us to understand the philosophical back-
use of this notion to characterize certain aspects ground of this notion (Minkowski, 1921a, 1921b,
of schizophrenic experiences can be questioned. 1921c, 1926, 1958). The thematic interpretation
Even though two primary articles of Minkowski’s makes use of Minkowski’s own descriptions in
are solely dedicated at elucidating the ‘loss of vital the first place. The present article thus combines
contact with reality’ (Minkowski, 1921a, 1921b, a literature study and thematic interpretation as
1921c, 1995, pp. 58–71), his notion may com- method of inquiry into the meaning and relevance
plicate, rather than clarify, the phenomenological of the concept. A critical consideration of the
investigation. benefits and limitations of the chosen method is
The purpose of this article is to investigate the found in the discussion.
meaning of the notion, and to evaluate the role
it can play in contemporary phenomenological Results
research on schizophrenia. This research field has The Loss of Vital Contact with Reality
recently refocused its investigations of schizophre-
In one of his first noteworthy articles,
nia as a disorder of the self, toward its intersubjec-
Minkowski summarized Eugen Bleuler’s ideas
Van Duppen / Minkowski ■ 387
definition of speech disorganization in the Diag- that is considered beyond reality (“en dehors de
nostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders la réalité”; Minkowski, 1966, p. 156). This pa-
(American Psychiatric Association, 2013), and tient has lost the sense of rules that constitute the
empirical research today is focusing on the specific intersubjective reality.
schizophrenic language troubles as well (Stephan, This brings us to the third domain of reality,
Pellizer, & Fletcher, 2007; Tan, Thomas, & Ros- which is closely related to both language and
sel, 2014). In psychotherapy, finding a common rules, namely praxis. The term ‘praxis’ indicates
language with a patient is one of the earliest goals. the practical involvement of a person in his or
A common language supposes a common ground, her surroundings. In this regard, it is charac-
and, according to Minkowski, this is what the teristic for schizophrenic patients that they can
therapist should search for to bring a psychotic have difficulties to use certain knowledge in an
patient back into reality (Minkowski, 1966, p. 41). adequate way (Minkowski, 1927, p. 559). Not
The second domain of reality concerns rules. the cognitive part of an activity fails, but the use
We find the same phenomenon of vital contact or implementation of this knowledge itself. As
with reality in the feeling of measure and limits we saw earlier, Minkowski favored Bleuler’s idea
which surrounds all of our precepts like a living that schizophrenia should not be characterized
fringe in rendering them infinitely nuanced and as a cognitive deficiency. Rather, the loss of vital
infinitely human (Minkowski, 1970, p. 69). contact with reality can be expressed in particular
We sense the measure of things and the limits practical anomalies. As Minkowski’s example il-
of the possibilities of our actions even before the lustrates: If someone’s house was at the edge of
precepts are made explicit. ‘Vital contact with real- being flooded with water, formally it would be
ity’ is related to the sense of measure that others correct to state that a certain volume of H2O and
experience with regard to our own actions. Actions salts was flowing at a certain discharge. But, of
that are within the limits, or within good measure, course, this judgment would testify for an absence
are thought of as “realistic”, in contrast to the of pragmatic reasoning (Minkowski, 1921a, p.
“autistic” actions of schizophrenia (Minkowski, 254). Praxis, our immediate involvement in the
1927, p. 147; Urfer, 2001). Reality does not only world, is always an interaction. We would expect
depend on the explicit rules of conduct, but also on the person to flee the house, or warn the other in-
unwritten rules, and our implicit sense of them. In habitants, rather than describe the physical quali-
this regard, the attitude of stagnant overthinking ties or the molecular structure of the water. That
and over-structuring of situations that Minkowski means that our actions have meanings, not only to
calls morbid rationalism, is not per se a cognitive us, but to others as well, within a context. What
defect, but the expression of the loss of reality. we can and cannot do depends on this context.
The patient has lost the sense of measure and Minkowski’s idea on the role of praxis for real-
limits, and the rules have lost their dynamic char- ity is again comparable to Wittgenstein’s (1969,
acter, to become static and morbid (Minkowski, §204), who noted that our acting (praxis) lies at
1995, pp. 260–261). Rules, and especially our the bottom of the language-game that is reality.
use of them, define what is in accordance with
reality, and what is not. A prototypical example Reality: Contingency, Irrationality,
illustrates this: a man is impressed by a woman Ambiance
he sees on the street, so he runs home to sit on The three domains of reality are insufficient for
a chair, in the most symmetrical position he can a distinct view of Minkowski’s concept of reality.
find, reflecting on the question why women can We need to add three other notions that help to
have such an effect on men. The answer is clear define ‘reality’. The first is contingency. If a person
to him, because “everything in life, even sexual loses the awareness of contingency in her everyday
sensations, is reducible to mathematics” (Passie, experience of the world of which she is part, she
1995, p. 261). Consequently, he remains seated will lose contact with reality.
in the same position, motionless. This is an act
Van Duppen / Minkowski ■ 389
We are quite able to feel a pricking or see a [Imagination] lays a light veil on the hard
spark without relating these phenomena to a reality, in its materialistic sense. By covering it
conversation that we are able to hear at the same and penetrating in all of its parts, [imagination]
softens it, makes it lighter, less concrete, but not
time. We very well conceive of isolated facts and
less real than before. (Minkowski, 1966, p. 550)
objects whose simultaneous coexistence may be
purely contingent. (Minkowski, 1970, p. 425) According to Minkowski, imagination is a
For a schizophrenic patient, this coexistence vital part of reality. It makes the hard reality (“la
may not be so unproblematic, and “a mysterious dure réalité”) bearable. Our reality is not only
force” (Minkowski, 1995, p. 390) might seem contingent, but becomes meaningful through our
hidden behind the phenomena. The loss of con- imagination. We should not understand his views
tingency structures a world where essential parts on reality as the antinomy of rationality and ir-
of reality are excluded, such as the possibility of rationality, but rather as the blending together
chance, coincidence, meaninglessness, or the un- of these two in reality as we live it (Minkowski,
expected. A patient of Fuchs reported persistent 1966). On first sight, psychotic phenomena can
“events of duplicity” (2000, p. 142), that were manifest themselves as irrationalities, in the form
meant to signal him something. One day someone of perspectival rigidity, communicative break-
talked to the patient about a pistol, the next day a down, and existential solitude. However, what is
picture of a pistol was printed in the newspaper. essential to these, rather than the absence of ratio-
The meaning of this event of duplicity was clear: nality, as Parnas (2013a, p. 213) rightly writes, is
He had to shoot himself. the “dislocation from intersubjectivity.”
The overwhelming presence of meanings and The third notion is the ‘ambiance’ (Minkowski,
associations that all seem to point at the patient 1966, p. 75). Minkowski’s reality is not what is
may lead to an attitude of withdrawal and avoid- external to us, the objects and things surrounding
ance (Minkowski, 1966, p. 644). Reality, as us in their materialistic sense. Lived reality, rather,
Minkowski would describe it, thus requires an is what we experience through our contact with
attitude of the subject toward the world that is this ambiance. Minkowski notes that the German
characterized by contingency, rather than by the word ‘Umwelt’ as introduced by von Uexküll
subject’s own centrality. (1909) might fit the description better than ambi-
Second, Minkowski’s reality has to be differen- ance. In this surrounding world, the distinctions
tiated from rationality. Although we already saw dissolve between object and subject, or between
that praxis and rules play a role in Minkowski’s inside and outside. The inner world of a person can
concept of reality, this does not mean that these be just as real as the outer world. However, this
are entirely rational. As Bergson had pointed does not mean that ambiance is restricted to one
out, a distinction between the intellectual and the sole individual or to each individual separately.
instinctive allows us to acknowledge the presence Rather, it is a common ambiance that is relevant
of irrationality in reality (Minkowski, 1926, p. for reality (Minkowski, 1966, p. 107).
555). Time, for example, was famously divided In conclusion, the first building block,
into measurable or objective time on the one hand, Minkowski’s concept of reality, is expressed and
and lived time on the other (Minkowski, 1995, p. experienced in language, rules, and praxis. The
19). These two forms of time are both part of the coexistence of rationality and irrationality makes
reality of time, but are distinct nonetheless. reality a lived reality, which we experience as
Analogously, grasping every aspect of reality partly contingent. Rather than comparing reality
through rationality means excluding a part of it. to a realm of external objects, Minkowski’s reality
Reality is not entirely rational. Our capacity to is a common ambiance where our activities are
imagine the world around us, and to co-constitute meaningful to others.
it in this way, together with others and their
imagination, underlines this co-existence of both
rationality and irrationality in reality (Minkowski,
1966, p. 549).
390 ■ PPP / Vol. 24, No. 4 / December 2017
between. “The psychopathology that we are lin- light on the phenomenological ideas on schizo-
ing out is a psychopathology with two voices: it phrenia as a self-disorder. Some of the deficiencies
follows from the human encounter” (Minkowski, and difficulties of intersubjectivity that we have
1966, p. XIII). discussed earlier concern a social and narrative
What this article suggests is that a clarified and aspect of the subject. More concrete, they concern
concise use of Minkowski’s notion can help us, be- the person as a social being. The “crazy activities,”
cause it indicates a kind of disturbance that other for example, are expressions of a disturbance of
descriptions do not grasp. Useful as they may be this person to fit into the rules and expectations of
for other purposes, the Diagnostic and Statistical others. A first question is whether schizophrenia
Manual of Mental Disorders’ negative symptoms only affects intersubjectivity on this higher order
(American Psychiatric Association, 2013) describe of sociality and personality. Let us recall the role
distinct parts of schizophrenia, but they not ac- of contingency in reality. We concluded there
count for the nature of specific intersubjective that reality requires an attitude of the subject
disturbances. Research on social cognition, in toward the world that is not characterized by the
contrast, does explicitly study intersubjectivity subject’s own centrality. The psychopathological
disturbances in schizophrenia. Current prominent examples illustrated how this is not so much a
theories in this field are based on the ‘theory of narrative centrality, but an experiential central-
mind’ model. These theories consider human ity. In other words, already in our experience of
interactions as the results of processes like ‘mind- the world, we incorporate others, and experience
reading,’ ‘mentalization’ and ‘simulation’ (Fuchs intersubjectively (see also Husserl, 1973, p. 479).
& De Jaegher, 2009). Social understanding and The anomalies of intersubjectivity are thus not
interaction are thought of as projections of inner restricted to the social aspect of a person, but also
representations onto others. These ideas seem to involve an experiencing subject.
be confirmed by empirical research, showing that A second question is whether these intersubjec-
schizophrenic patients present dysfunctions of tive anomalies are all secondary to disturbances
particular social skills, such as emotion recogni- of a basic sense of self, of ‘ipseity’(Sass & Parnas,
tion, understanding the thoughts and intentions 2003, p. 428) as an experiential core self. If we
of others, and interpreting social cues (Pinkham, follow Minkowski’s claim that the ‘loss of vital
2014). The question is, however, whether these contact with reality’ is the “trouble générateur”
representational theories succeed in describing of schizophrenia, and, at the same time, we know
the complex disturbance of intersubjectivity in that all of the elements that constitute the ‘loss of
schizophrenia. It can be argued that one only vital contact with reality’ refer to specific inter-
explicitly theorizes about the actions, intentions, subjective deficiencies, then we are to conclude
and thoughts of others in situations of need. For that the original disorder concerns intersubjectiv-
some schizophrenic patients, social encounters ity primarily. With Minkowski one could argue
may indeed be described as such situations of need, that the disorder of ‘ipseity’ is tightly interwoven
in which they explicitly attempt to compensate for with deficiencies in intersubjectivity, or with a
their social difficulties. They may indeed engage particular experience of others. As we have seen,
in social interaction through a theory of mind. empirical research has shown that schizophrenic
This means, however, that the original disturbance patients can lack primary or bodily empathy, in
(“trouble générateur”) does not concern men- other words, that they can have difficulties in
talization or mindreading primarily. Rather, the understanding facial and gestural expressions of
disturbances of intersubjectivity find their origin others (Pinkham, 2014). Fuchs (2015) concludes
in a more basic ‘being-with-others’ that makes that one could say that they experience others’
social encounters problematic in the first place bodies more like objects.
(Van Duppen, 2017). This problem has, of course, already been
Minkowski’s notion does not only challenge the present in phenomenological debates on the
‘theory of mind’ model, but it may also shed new self, others, and empathy (Zahavi, 2001, 2014).
394 ■ PPP / Vol. 24, No. 4 / December 2017
A third significant question could follow from Practically, research on the primary disturbanc-
Minkowski’s thought. Namely, if both thematic es of intersubjectivity in schizophrenia could use
and non-thematic self-experience implies recog- the elements that this analysis has brought forward
nizing and distinguishing experiences as for-me or to examine their clinical correlates. Phenomeno-
mine (Zahavi, 2008, p. 128), then where does this logical psychopathology has always been inspired
distinction come from in the first place, but from by both clinical and philosophical insights. In this
the experience of not-self, of other? Experiencing case, Minkowski’s work can guide us in searching
intersubjectivity would thus be a necessity for for the form and selectivity of these disturbances.
experiencing one’s own subjectivity. Whether one Without this guidance, we might not know what
agrees with this argumentation or not, it is clear to look for. Second, it should evaluate whether
that the ‘loss of vital contact with reality,’ and its these correlates are present during psychotic and
wide recognition in phenomenological descrip- non-psychotic, prodromal, and residual phases of
tions, makes us rethink the role of intersubjectivity the illness. Certainly, the loss of vital contact with
in schizophrenia. reality does not entail a loss of intersubjectivity in
The implicit thesis brought forward by my general, but points out the parts of intersubjectiv-
interpretation of Minkowski’s notion is that ity that may be vulnerable in prodromal phases,
schizophrenia involves a particular disturbance and disturbed in actual morbid stages. If ‘the loss
of intersubjectivity, involving both a higher level of vital contact’ is to remain a noteworthy concept
of sociality that concerns the person, and a more in psychopathology, it will have to prove so in
basic level that relates to the experiencing subject. these investigations.
The original disturbance (“trouble générateur”)
does not concern mentalization or mindreading Limitations to the Notion
primarily, and the original disturbance is not re- Despite the clarity that the notion has gained by
stricted to a basic sense of self-disturbance. The analyzing the building blocks from the perspective
‘loss of vital contact with reality’ indicates, albeit of intersubjectivity, and despite the value the no-
in other terminology, that the original disturbance tion may have for contemporary research, it still
affects both ‘being-self’ and ‘being-with-others.’ It has its flaws. First, one can criticize the use of the
affects a space, which Minkowski would poetically notion by referring to it as a reification. Indeed,
refer to as the “entre deux,” or the in-between, without an investigation of its meaning, the persis-
where self and other originate. tent use of the notion is questionable. Minkowski’s
Complementary to Blankenburg’s ‘loss of description can function as a stop-gap solution for
natural self-evidence’ (Blankenburg, 1971), ‘the complex problems and phenomena that actually
loss of vital contact with reality’ can serve as a require in-depth exploration. A concise analysis
prototype for the exploration of these primary and a precise use in the description of psycho-
intersubjectivity disturbances of schizophrenia. pathological phenomena may, however, prevent
Indeed, Blankenburg’s psychopathology seems such reification.
to confirm Minkowski’s concept. Blankenburg Second, Minkowski’s view is based on a restrict-
specifies the difficulties with common sense (1971, ed form of schizophrenia. Both in his early work,
p. 113), which are comparable to the insights on and in later psychopathological descriptions, he
rules and praxis of Minkowski. He, furthermore, tends to minimize certain symptoms (Minkowski,
describes a temporal (Blankenburg, 1971, p. 90), 1966, p. 95). For some contemporary clinicians,
spatial (p. 124), and linguistic alienation (p. 80). it will be surprising that the positive symptoms of
Minkowski’s notion is thus at the same time firmly schizophrenia, such as hallucination and delusion,
grounded in the phenomenology of schizophrenia, play only an accessory role. In most diagnostic
and original and challenging with regard to the classifications, these two symptoms are considered
current debate on social cognition and intersub- important diagnostic criteria (American Psychi-
jectivity in schizophrenia. atric Association, 2013; World Health Organi-
zation, 1993). Minkowski does not justify this
Van Duppen / Minkowski ■ 395
view, but refers to Bleuler’s categorization. Sass disturbed experience of spatiality, whether it is
rightly notices that symptoms of disorganization, expressed in threatening closeness or in social
disturbances of thought, language and attention, distancing and detachment. A clinical application
and Schneider’s first-rank symptoms are hardly of his ideas does not require a vast philosophical
mentioned (Sass, 2001). At the time, Minkowski knowledge, as most of these elements are intui-
stood relatively alone with this view, as psychopa- tively accessible.
thologists like Karl Jaspers, Ludwig Binswanger,
and Kurt Schneider were developing their theories Conclusion
on delusions, and psychosis in general. Despite the
emphasis on positive symptoms in clinical praxis This article presents a thematic interpretation
and classifications, contemporary psychopatholo- of Minkowski’s notion of the ‘loss of vital contact
gists seem to agree with Minkowski’s view that with reality’. It aims at investigating the meaning
the disturbances of the self are more central, or of this notion, and at evaluating its relevance for
closer to the “trouble générateur” (Blankenburg, contemporary research on intersubjectivity. The
1971; Sass & Parnas, 2003; Nordgaard, Arnfred, analysis showed that the building blocks and the
Handest, & Parnas, 2008). more fundamental elements of this notion refer to
Third, this thematic interpretation could not philosophical and psychopathological meanings. A
completely discard the vagueness or obscurity of common factor to all these elements is their con-
the notion. The building blocks have been ana- nection to intersubjectivity. Considering the recent
lyzed into more fundamental elements. Some of refocusing of phenomenological research on the
these remain vague and incomprehensible to those investigation of the disturbances of intersubjectiv-
not familiar with the philosophical backgrounds ity in schizophrenia, this is where Minkowski’s
they stem from, such as the philosophies of notion proves its relevance. ‘The loss of vital
Henri Bergson, Edmund Husserl, and Max Sche- contact with reality’ can serve as a prototype for
ler (Minkowski, 1995). The question is whether the exploration of the primary intersubjectivity
a philosophical clarification could accurately disturbances of schizophrenia. It allowed us to
solve this problem. It may indeed be inherent challenge specific ideas on social cognition, and
to Minkowski’s style (Sass, 2001; Urfer, 2001). it could shed new light on the phenomenological
From today’s scientific perspective, this limits the description of schizophrenia as a self-disorder.
application and relevance of Minkowski’s work. This research is not restricted to phenomenologi-
Furthermore, our approach has limitations of its cal considerations, but it might have its relevance
own. The analytical distance might result in a for individual treatment as well. Patients indeed
lack of overarching coherence, and it might not often suffer from their interpersonal difficulties
do justice to the specific form of reflection that is and from social exclusion. Minkowski’s notion
so typical for Minkowski. Additionally, because can, therefore, provide us with the necessary tools
of our initial research interest in intersubjectivity, to investigate the form and specificity of these
certain elements of his work have received more disturbances. These tools can, furthermore, be
attention than others. I do not claim that this is used for the clinical evaluation of intersubjectiv-
the only correct way to interpret Minkowski or ity disturbances, concretely, of a patient’s experi-
the notion in particular, but I have suggested that ence of ‘being-with-others’. Consequently, once
it can prove its relevance mostly with regard to such clinical and phenomenological correlates
intersubjectivity. of Minkowski’s descriptions are found, they can
Last, these limitations make the clinical ap- function in the shaping and evaluation of phenom-
plication of Minkowski’s concept challenging. enologically based therapy. This article provides
Throughout the article, however, I have added the first step in this process. It is up to future
psychopathological descriptions that confirm research to connect these concepts to clinically
Minkowski’s ideas. With regards to lived space, applicable and empirically testable hypotheses.
for example, there are certainly several clinical Considering the notion’s conceptual richness, this
descriptions that illustrate the importance of a promises to be fruitful research.
396 ■ PPP / Vol. 24, No. 4 / December 2017
Parnas, J. (2013b). What is psychosis? Karl Jaspers the recovery of first- and second-person awareness.
and beyond. In T. Fuchs & G. Stanghellini (Eds). American Journal of Psychotherapy, 61, 163–179.
One Hundred Years of Karl Jaspers’ ”General Stephan, M., Pellizer, G., & Fletcher, C. (2007). Empiri-
Psychopathology” (pp. 208–228). Oxford: Oxford cal evaluation of language disorder in schizophrenia.
University Press. Journal of Psychiatry and Neuroscience, 32, 4,
Parnas, J., & Bovet, P. (1991). Autism in schizophrenia 250–258.
revisited. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 32, 7–21. Tan, E., Thomas, N., & Rossel, S. (2014). Speech dis-
Parnas, J., Sass, L. A., & Zahavi, D. (2013). Rediscov- turbances and quality of life in schizophrenia: Dif-
ering psychopathology: The epistemology and phe- ferential impacts on functioning and life satisfaction.
nomenology of the psychiatric object. Schizophrenia Comprehensive Psychiatry, 55, 3, 693–698.
Bulletin, 39, 2, 270–277. Tatossian, A. (1979). Phénoménologie des psychoses.
Passie, T. (1995). Phänomenologisch-anthropologische Paris: Masson.
Psychiatrie und Psychologie : eine Studie über den Urfer, A. (2001). Phenomenology and psychopa-
„Wengener Kreis“: Binswanger - Minkowski - von thology of schizophrenia: The views of Eugene
Gebsattel - Straus Stuttgart: Guido Plessner Verlag. Minkowski. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology,
Pinkham, A. (2014). Social cognition in schizophrenia. 8, 4, 279–289.
Journal of Clinical Psychiatry, 75, Suppl 2, 14–19. Varga, S. (2010). Vulnerability to psychosis, I-thou inter-
Ratcliffe, M. (2009). Existential feeling and psychopa- subjectivity and the praecox-feeling. Phenomenology
thology. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 16, and the Cognitive Sciences, 12, 131–143.
2, 179–194. Varga, S. (2012). Depersonalization and the sense of
Rümke, H. C. (1960). Psychiatrie, deel II: de Psychose. realness. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 19,
Amsterdam: Scheltema en Holkema NV. 2, 103–113.
Sass, L. A. (2001). Self and world in schizophrenia: Van Duppen, Z. (2017). The intersubjective dimension
Three classic approaches. Philosophy, Psychiatry, of schizophrenia. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychol-
& Psychology, 8, 4:251–270. ogy. 24, 4, 399–418
Sass, L. A. (2014). Self-disturbance and schizophrenia: von Uexküll, J. (1909). Umwelt und Innenwelt der
Structure, specificity, pathogenesis (current issues, Tiere. Berlin: Verlag von Julius Springer.
new directions). Schizophrenia Research, 152, 1, Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations.
5–11. Oxford: Blackwell.
Sass, L. A., & Parnas, J. (2003). Schizophrenia, con- Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On certainty. Oxford: Basil
sciousness, and the self. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 29, Blackwell.
3, 427–444. World Health Organization. (1993). The tenth revision
Schütz, A. (1945). On multiple realities. Philosophy and of the classification international diseases and related
Phenomenological Research, 5, 4, 533–576. health problems (ICD-10). Geneva: World Health
Schwartz, M., Wiggins, O., Naudin, J., & Spitzer, M. Organization.
(2005). Rebuilding reality: A phenomenology of Zahavi, D. (2001). Beyond empathy: Phenomenologi-
aspects of chronic schizophrenia. Phenomenology cal approaches to intersubjectivity. Journal of Con-
and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, 91–115. sciousness Studies, 8, 151–168.
Stanghellini, G., & Ballerini, M. (2007). Values in Zahavi, D. (2008). Subjectivity and selfhood. Investi-
persons with schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin, gating the first-person perspective. Cambridge, MA:
33, 1, 131–141. MIT Press.
Stanghellini, G., & Lysaker, P. (2007). The psycho- Zahavi, D. (2014). Self and other. Exploring subjectiv-
therapy of schizophrenia through the lens of phe- ity, empathy, and shame. Oxford: Oxford University
nomenology: Intersubjectivity and the search for Press.