2014 - Can We Relinquish The Transcendental
2014 - Can We Relinquish The Transcendental
2014 - Can We Relinquish The Transcendental
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Penn State University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Speculative
Philosophy.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 131.172.36.29 on Fri, 08 Jan 2016 05:41:42 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
jsp
Can We Relinquish the Transcendental?
Catherine Malabou
kingston university london
This content downloaded from 131.172.36.29 on Fri, 08 Jan 2016 05:41:42 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
c ondition to the issue I intend to deal with here,” Meillassoux says, “is
‘the relinquishing of transcendentalism’” (27). The French expression
is “l’abandon du transcendantal.”2 I think that “the relinquishing of the
transcendental” is better than “the relinquishing of transcendentalism.”
As for relinquish, it implies something softer, gentler, than abandon.
Abandonment means a definite separation, whereas relinquishing desig-
nates a negotiated rupture, a farewell that maintains a relationship with
what it splits from. Whether Meillassoux’s abandon means “relinquish-
ing” or “abandonment” will be examined later. For the moment I wish
to insist upon the fact that he proposes that we leave the transcendental,
and consequently also Kant, behind. What I intend to question is this very
gesture: Can we relinquish the transcendental, and consequently, can we
relinquish Kant?
The problem is all the more serious if we admit that Kantianism may
be considered the very origin, the very foundation, of European philosophy,
that is, of the continental tradition.3 So the “we” included in the question
“Can we relinquish the transcendental?” addresses all continental philoso-
phers. Its signification then becomes: Can we relinquish the transcendental
without relinquishing purely and simply continental philosophy? Without
putting at risk continental philosophy’s identity? Such is the immense
challenged raised by After Finitude.
First, I will examine the reasons for such a challenge, which will lead
me to expose Meillassoux’s main arguments. I will then discuss them.
Transcendental, says Kant in the introduction to the Critique of Pure
Reason, should be understood both as synonymous to a priori, meaning
“absolutely independent from all experience,” and as synonymous to the
condition of possibility in general: “The a priori possibility of cognition . . .
is transcendental.”4 The relinquishing of the transcendental, then, implies
a break with the a priori, with the idea of the condition of possibility, as well
as with their circularity.
Why should we proceed to such a rupture? Because, as Meillassoux
argues, this circularity was never able to entirely veil or hide its lack of
foundation. There can be no transcendental deduction of the transcenden-
tal. The a priori is just a presupposition. What Kant calls deduction is only
a description, a way to posit simple facts. The pure forms of knowledge and
thinking—categories, principles, ideas—are just decreed, posited, never
deduced or justified. In Kant, Meillassoux argues,
This content downloaded from 131.172.36.29 on Fri, 08 Jan 2016 05:41:42 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
This content downloaded from 131.172.36.29 on Fri, 08 Jan 2016 05:41:42 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
tal has always been, strictly, a transcategorical, that which could not be
received, formed, enclosed in any category internal to the system. The
vomit of the system.”12 What Derrida brings to light here is that the tran-
scendental is in a way that is arbitrarily imposed upon the system as its
form but remains itself exterior to the system, alien to it, coming from
nowhere.
As for Foucault, we know how complex his relationship with the tran-
scendental is. While leaving aside for considerations of time the detail of
the crucial analyses of Archaeology of Knowledge,13 as well as those developed
in What Is Enlightenment?14 I will just refer to a famous passage from his
conversation with Giulio Preti in 1972, “The Question of Culture”: “In all
of my work I strive . . . to avoid any reference to this transcendental as a
condition of the possibility for any knowledge. When I say that I strive to
avoid it, I do not mean that I am sure of succeeding. I try to historicize to
the utmost to leave as little space as possible to the transcendental. I cannot
exclude the possibility that one day I will have to confront an irreducible
residuum which will be, in fact, the transcendental.”15
We see, through these three examples, that the “break” with the tran-
scendental, to use another of Meillassoux’s expressions,16 is not exactly a
new and unexpected gesture; it is inscribed in what already appears as a
tradition.
Nevertheless, to come back to the distinction between relinquishing
and abandoning, I would say, contradicting the translator a little, that
Heidegger, Derrida, and Foucault relinquish the transcendental, whereas
Meillassoux abandons it. Continental philosophers until now, however
violent their reading of Kant, however radical their critique of the tran-
scendental, seem to have always preserved or maintained something of it
in the end, calling it “quasi transcendental,” for example,17 because even
if transcendental is too metaphysical a name, it nevertheless circumscribes
what may be seen as the minimal creed of continental philosophy. The
creed that exists is a set of structures of both theoretical and practical
experience that are irreducible to two extremes—to empirical material
data, on the one hand, and to purely formal logic entities or procedures,
on the other: a set of concepts that allow the real to exist and which could
not exist without the real. Foucault, in “On the Archaeology of the Sci-
ences,” gives a helpful definition. The transcendental is said to be “a play
of forms that anticipate all contents insofar as they have already rendered
them possible.”18
This content downloaded from 131.172.36.29 on Fri, 08 Jan 2016 05:41:42 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
This content downloaded from 131.172.36.29 on Fri, 08 Jan 2016 05:41:42 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1.
This content downloaded from 131.172.36.29 on Fri, 08 Jan 2016 05:41:42 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
2.
This content downloaded from 131.172.36.29 on Fri, 08 Jan 2016 05:41:42 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
This content downloaded from 131.172.36.29 on Fri, 08 Jan 2016 05:41:42 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
This content downloaded from 131.172.36.29 on Fri, 08 Jan 2016 05:41:42 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
challenge. Mathematics, freed from the Copernican revolution, lay bare the
ontological principles of a deserted world “where humanity is absent, a
world crammed with things and events that are not the correlates of any
manifestation” (26).
I totally share Meillassoux’s contention that all philosophical attempts
at opening philosophy to alterity have until now remained poetic. Let us
think of the “other thinking” in Heidegger (the nonmetaphysical thinking),
the utterly other in Levinas, or the arrivant in Derrida. Let us consider the
themes of the unforeseeable, the unanticipatable, the totally unheard of or
the absolutely surprising—all these motives have remained the poetic or
literary expressions of a new messianism. What I share with After Finitude
is that the Other has been said to be absolute out of the absolute impos-
sibility of our reason to prove its absoluteness. Meillassoux, then, is right
when he affirms: “By forbidding reason any claim to the absolute, the end
of metaphysics has taken the form of an exacerbated return of the reli-
gious” (45).
The attempt to define a new relationship to otherness through math-
ematical reasoning allows us to elaborate a rational concept of it. Thanks
to the transfinite, we can access a speculative notion of absolute otherness,
which has nothing to do with a promise, an expectation, an announcement,
but, rather, with the otherness of the real itself, the real otherness of the real
as it is, that is, according to its contingency. Here is the expression of this
radical otherness: “Everything could actually collapse: from trees to stars,
from stars to laws, from physical laws to logical laws; and this not by virtue
of some superior law whereby everything is destined to perish, but by virtue
of the absence of any superior law capable of preserving anything, no mat-
ter what, from perishing” (53).
To conclude on that concept, I think that Meillassoux has touched an
important point, which is that until now, all gestures of abandonment or
relinquishing of the transcendental have induced a separation between phi-
losophy and science, have ignored and despised the scientific deconstruc-
tions of the transcendental, and have just maintained the transcendental
in poeticizing it. I do think that this split between philosophy and science
urgently has to come to an end.
Nevertheless, this is what I would briefly like to develop to bring this
article to a close: I am not convinced by the way in which Meillassoux pro-
poses to overcome this split. Let me go back to the previous passage about
the meaning of contingency, of contingere: “The contingent, in a word, is
This content downloaded from 131.172.36.29 on Fri, 08 Jan 2016 05:41:42 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
This content downloaded from 131.172.36.29 on Fri, 08 Jan 2016 05:41:42 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
have to. It also means, then, that we have to relinquish the transfinite,
which is of an alterity that is only mathematically possible, as this
appears as another form of authenticity and irreducibility. We defi-
nitely have to relinquish the irreducible.
—Do you mean that nothing is irreducible, authentic, or uncondi-
tional?
—Yes, this is what I mean.
—Then can we remain continental philosophers if we open the door
of the irreducibility to the anything?
—No, if we follow Heidegger, Derrida, . . . or Meillassoux, no. Yes, if
we follow . . . if we follow Kant himself.
—Kant himself?
—Yes, Kant himself. The trajectory of the three Critiques coincides
with the most radical exposure of the transcendental to its own
destruction ever. When Kant deals with the living being, in the sec-
ond part of the Critique of the Power of Judging, he deals with the
nontranscendental, which is something that refuses to be judged,
or thought, which is in need of its determination. He then comes to
the conclusion that there are two types of necessities, mechanistic
and teleological. The Kantian deconstruction of the transcenden-
tal pertains to this pluralization of necessity. What does life do to
thought? “There are so many modifications of the universal tran-
scendental natural concepts left undetermined by the laws given a
priori,” says Kant in the preface to the third Critique.20 Life is what
modifies the transcendental, what relinquishes it by forcing it to
transform itself.
—To become plastic, you mean?
—Yes.
—We thus have to negotiate the relinquishing of the transcendental
with Kant’s own struggle with it.
—How, then?
—Well, in exploring a field that is so often despised by the
philosophers—we mentioned it, that of biology.
—In establishing that our categories are reducible to biological con-
cepts, for example?
—Yes, exactly.
—That the transcendental is in the brain?
—Yes, exactly.
This content downloaded from 131.172.36.29 on Fri, 08 Jan 2016 05:41:42 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
—Are you aware of being inauthentically Kantian when you say that?
—I am perfectly aware of it and not certain that Kant would have
rejected such an inauthentic approach to his philosophy.
notes
1. Quentin Meillassoux, After Finitude. An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency,
trans. Ray Brassier (London: Continuum, 2008); hereafter cited parenthetically in
the text by page number. See also Quentin Meillassoux, Après la finitude. Essai sur
la nécessité de la contingence (Paris: Seuil, 2006).
2. Meillassoux, Après la finitude, 38.
3. About the relationship between Kantianism and continental philosophy,
see Tom Rockmore, In Kant’s Wake: Philosophy in the Twentieth Century (Malden,
Mass.: Blackwell, 2006); and Lee Braver, A Thing of This World: A History of
Continental Anti-realism (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2007).
4. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, in The Cambridge Edition of the Works
of Immanuel Kant, ed. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, February 1999), “Introduction,” AK, III, 27, B3.
5. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. Joan Stanbaugh, rev. with a foreword
by Dennis J. Schmidt (New York: State University of New York Press, 2010).
6. Martin Heidegger, Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, trans. Richard Taft
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1997), in particular §§21–23, 32–34.
7. Extases is the name that Heidegger gives to the three moments of time—
present, past, and future—to the extent that they are constantly out of themselves
(from the Greek ek-stasis).
8. Martin Heidegger, The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, trans. Alfred
Hofstadter (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1988).
9. Martin Heidegger, Contributions to Philosophy. From Enowning, trans. Parvis
Emad and Kennet Maly (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1989), e.g.,
§§111–12.
10. Jacques Derrida, Voice and Phenomenon. Introduction to the Problem of the
Sign in Husserl’s Phenomenology, trans. Leonard Lawlor (Evanston: Northwestern
University Press, 2011), chap. VI in particular.
11. Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology, trans. Gayatri Spivak (Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins University Press, 1974), 20.
12. Jacques Derrida, Glas, trans. John P. Leavey Jr. and Richard Rand (Lincoln:
University of Nebraska Press, 1986), 183a.
13. Michel Foucault, Archaeology of Knowledge, trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith
(London: Routledge, 2002), see chap. V in particular.
14. Michel Foucault, What Is Enlightenment? in The Essential Foucault. Selections
from the Essential Works of Foucault, 1954–1984, ed. Paul Rabinow and Nikolas Rose
(New York: New Press, 2003), 43–57.
This content downloaded from 131.172.36.29 on Fri, 08 Jan 2016 05:41:42 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
15. Michel Foucault to Giulio Preti, in “The Question of Culture,” debate with
Giulio Preti, in Michel Foucault Live: Collected Interviews, 1961–1984, ed. Sylvère
Lotringer (1972; New York: Semiotext[e], 1996). Cf. Colin Koopman’s important
article “Historical Critique or Transcendental Critique in Foucault: Two Kantian
Lineages,” Foucault Studies 8 (February 2010): 100–121.
16. See Meillassoux, After Finitude, 28: “to break with the transcendental.”
17. Quasi transcendental is a term forged by Jacques Derrida and often used by
him, for example, in Glas, 183a.
18. Michel Foucault, “On the Archaeology of the Sciences: Response to the
Epistemology Circle,” in Rabinow and Rose, Essential Foucault, 392–423, at 421.
19. Immanuel Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, trans. Paul Guyer and Eric
Matthews, ed. Paul Guyer and Allan W. Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2000), “Introduction,” sec. II, “On the Domain of Philosophy in General.”
20. Ibid., “Introduction,” §4.
This content downloaded from 131.172.36.29 on Fri, 08 Jan 2016 05:41:42 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions