E Special
E Special
E Special
Introduction sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav
DOI: 10.1177/0263276415600105
tcs.sagepub.com
Oliver Human
University of Amsterdam
Abstract
This E-Special Issue collects together 11 articles from the archives of Theory, Culture
& Society. These articles all articulate and debate the contribution of what some have
described as either ‘complex complexity’ or ‘general complexity’. In contrast to
reductionist or restricted attempts to understand complexity, the articles collected
here move away from the tendency to assume mastery of complexity by expounding
a set of universal and simple laws. Rather, the position of general complexity is that
we cannot grasp the complexity of the world in its complexity, and therefore depend
upon models which are always incomplete, provisional and contingent. Yet, these
models make knowledge and action possible, and it is therefore the contribution of
general complexity to provide the means through which we can ethically and prag-
matically engage with complexity in the hope of realizing alternative, perhaps better,
worlds.
Keywords
complexity, emergence, ethics, general, novelty, restricted, systems
defined as the belief that we are able to reduce ‘reality to ultimate par-
ticles as well as seeing ultimate particles, or simple systems, as represen-
tatives of wholes’ (Rasch, 1991: 77).
Under this view of science, the possibility of universal knowledge is
propagated, and the job of the scientist is to reveal the underlying prin-
ciples and essences which would explain all phenomena, everywhere, at
all times. It is this separation and reduction which has made possible vast
improvements in the state of the human condition. The different fields of
specialization allow us to produce knowledge about isolated phenomena
found within a given field. If we tried to comprehend the world in itself
we would be left with nothing more than a meditative state as the com-
plexity of what we witness renders us incapable of action. We therefore
need specialization to improve upon and further knowledge. As Laszlo
argues:
The problem we face with the current state of knowledge is that we need
a method through which we can understand the relationships between
different parts of a system (see Laszlo, 1996). What current processes of
globalization and global warming are bringing forth is a need to develop
means by which we can better understand the complexity of the world
around us, which is not reducible to some central or single essence. When
we attempt to face the relationships between different parts of a system
we come to the limits of the reductionist style of thought as it aims to
separate and reduce.
In critiquing the shortcomings of the reductionist approach, some
have proposed a holistic approach (see Fodor and Lepore, 1992;
Jackson, 2003; Lazlo, 1996). In brief, the holistic approach argues that
we cannot simply separate disciplines or reduce wholes to the parts which
constitute them. We must rather look at the whole itself in order to
further our understanding of the world. However, attempts at holism
often lead to some form of mysticism, which makes taking action in
the world difficult as the whole takes on incomprehensible dimensions.
A shortcoming of the holistic approach is that it is difficult to answer the
question as to what exactly the whole is and how one would deal with
such a high degree of complexity. Although providing an important
Human 423
number of parts and their interactions. It will be fair to say that the
interaction between a husband and wife is more complex than the inter-
action between the many parts which make up the engine in your motor
car. I can reduce the inner workings of a motor car to a manual which
can comprehensively describe the processes at work. I cannot, however,
reduce my relationship with my wife to a manual. Seen from this per-
spective, the ability to say anything about complex systems always rests
on a set of assumptions which one has to make in order to exclude some
of the complexity from our understanding (Allen, 2000: 80; Cilliers, 2001:
137). This implies that we can never have a comprehensive understanding
of a complex system; we can never have a model which completely
describes the system (for a good discussion of the characteristics of com-
plex systems see Cilliers, 1998: 2–7). This is a view of complexity that has
come to be known as ‘general’ (Morin, 2007) or ‘complex’ complexity
(Byrne, 2005) and largely, although not exclusively, draws inspiration
from the confluence of post-structural philosophy and the biological
sciences.
General Complexity
It is important to note that the approach or style of thinking general
complexity aims for does not argue against reductionism per se. It is
necessary to reduce in order for the world to be intelligible to us. We
need to create boundaries – exclude certain aspects of the system itself
and the environment of the system from the model we create – in order
for the system to be intelligible to us. We cannot understand the world in
its complexity. However, the boundaries we create of such systems are
always provisional and depend upon the uses to which we put our
models. Note, this does not mean that we can create just any boundary.
There must be boundaries and limits in order for a system to exist.
However, where you draw those boundaries and the status you accord
those boundaries is what is at issue here. General complexity is therefore
interested in the limits to our knowledge; it helps us to understand the
boundaries of our knowledge (see Allen, 2000; Cilliers, 2001: 140–142).
To begin with, when we are faced with a complex system we must
distinguish that system from its environment (Allen, 2000: 80). In con-
trast to reductionist complexity, general complexity argues that the
boundaries of a system are open rather than closed (Chu et al., 2003:
23). In other words, reductionist complexity, based upon the assumption
of some essential underlying law or principle, assumes that we can easily
separate a complex system from the environment in which we find it. The
boundaries of such a system are said to be closed as the system can exist
independently from the world. The argument from general complexity is
that a system cannot be neatly separated from its environment as it is
constituted by that environment. The system’s boundaries are open
426 Theory, Culture & Society 33(7–8)
[I]n real systems contextuality manifests itself often through the fact
that its elements play multiple roles, fulfilling several functions
across the boundaries of systems. In a certain sense, contextuality
is a ubiquitous phenomenon: Given any part of the world, it is
always possible to find a host of different partitions resulting in
different system definitions, i.e., establish some form of contextual-
ity. (Chu et al., 2003: 25)
Does this then imply that all knowledge is relative? This would be to
throw the baby out with the bath water.
A product of the relational understanding of complexity is that the
project to universalize or find an essential basis for knowledge is chal-
lenged. Rather, theorists adopting a general complexity lens argue that
knowledge about complex phenomena is always local (Cilliers, 1998), a
product of the conditions under which complexity arose and in which it
was understood (Byrne, 2005: 98). However, this does not imply that
knowledge is relative. As Donna Haraway (1988: 584) reminds us,
Human 431
A true relativist, i.e. somebody that argues that there are no grounds
for any form of knowledge is, in a way, nothing but a disappointed
foundationalist. If he cannot find objective and universal points of
reference to guarantee knowledge, then he may as well give up. The
argument between foundationalists and relativists is a dead end – a
family fight.
15 years the journal Theory, Culture & Society has provided an avenue of
publication for developing this position on complexity. Although there
are many other articles published by Theory, Culture & Society which
either deal with complexity directly or draw inspiration from the field or
reflect a sensitivity to the concerns of complexity, the articles selected for
this E-special are perhaps the ones that best represent the challenges
scholars face when they deal with complex systems. What is clear from
the work collected here is that the problems we face when dealing with
complex systems are far from solved. However, the developing field of
general complexity is starting to bear fruit as to the ethical and political
strategies we should adopt when faced with limited knowledge. The
chances are high that the problems of complexity may never be solved;
however, working out the ethics and benefits of such limitations may be
the most productive contribution studies in complexity can make
towards improving the conditions for life on this planet.
If complexity is constituted by the interaction of parts at a local level
and therefore cannot be reduced to a simple set of laws, Byrne (2005), in
his article in this E-special, argues that complexity theory provides the
basis through which we can understand the contingency of the world.
This epistemological shift for Byrne equals a political shift in social sci-
ence ‘as a basis for a knowledge-based politics at every level, but par-
ticularly that of popular participatory practice’ (p. 96). Because complex
problems cannot be described by simple rules, we should engage with
complexity through the sociological technique of comparative cases. This
insight shifts the role of the social sciences in relation to public policy
from being a technocratic handmaiden of power to one in which ‘social
action might produce one possible future rather than another’ (p. 101).
Therefore, in contrast to simplistic complexity, which ‘looks like the
property of an intellectual elite’, complex complexity offers ‘an historic-
ally grounded frame of reference which can be used to inform the organic
practice of intellectuals engaged in participatory research’ (p. 108). In this
sense complexity provides a position from which to engage ethically with
systems from within those systems.
Taking seriously the idea of an open system, Nigel Clark (2005: 166)
proposes the idea of an ‘ex-orbitant globality’ that ‘extends the destabil-
ization of regional or national boundedness by social theorists to the
perimeters of our planet’. The increasing awareness of the constitutive
role of global interconnectivity and feedback loops leads analysts to dis-
regard any possible outside to this global system. ‘If there is to be trans-
formation, by this logic, it can only come about through a realization of
possibilities that inhere in the system itself’ (p. 169). This condition is
exacerbated by recent theorizations of capitalism and the current lack of
alternatives to this global order. Such theorizations are based on what
Clark calls ‘global immanence’ and claim to a global condition without
an outside. However, this requires ‘a viewpoint that is itself removed
434 Theory, Culture & Society 33(7–8)
from the relationalities it presides over’ (p. 171) and therefore contradicts
the dynamical systems theory on which it draws. If we are then to engage
at a global level, we must take into consideration a planet which is not
closed to its surrounds. It is towards such a consideration that Clark’s
notion of ex-orbitant globality points and to the responsibilities we need
to maintain which are themselves ex-orbitant in the acknowledgement of
this excessive globality.
In his article ‘The Complexities of the Global’, John Urry (2005)
argues that many social scientists are either explicitly or implicitly apply-
ing the insights of complexity to the social sciences. Urry therefore exam-
ines the overlaps and interplays between analyses of the physical and
social worlds which are giving shape to what he terms a 21st century
‘social physics’ (p. 235). After describing what he terms ‘complex rela-
tionality’, which comprises those aspects of complexity theory which lend
themselves to the interplay of social and physical sciences, Urry proposes
that Marx provides us with the best example of complexity analyses
within the social sciences (p. 240). Although Marx’s argument prefigures
‘complex relationality’, he nonetheless illuminates the effects such rela-
tionality maintains through global capitalism. With this background in
mind, Urry argues that in relation to the complex and rich intertwining
of the global and local, ‘there is not so much a reductionist but a complex
relationality’ (p. 245). Here complexity theory provides some metaphors,
concepts and theories essential for analysing the ‘intractable disorderli-
ness’ of the global (p. 249). It is for this reason that complexity theory
may provide a more useful toolbox for understanding and escaping the
power dynamics which give shape to the ‘empire’ of the 21st century.
The toolbox which complexity theory provides us with is further ela-
borated by Urry (2006) in his article ‘Complexity’. Here he provides a
useful discussion of the various terms which complexity theory has
brought to the fore, especially the ‘complexity structure of feeling’ as
an approach not neatly defined by seeing complexity theory as simply
a utilitarian toolbox of concepts. This structure of feeling has been made
possible by an array of developments in 20th century science including
changes in conceptions of time and space, the notion of emergence, as
well as the influence of cybernetics and later notions of systems and
feedback loops. According to Urry, complexity provides the resources
for overcoming simplified and neat distinctions between nature and cul-
ture or the natural and social sciences and begins to chart a way forward
to understand the rich intertwining of worlds previously kept apart.
In this sense, Nigel Clark’s (2000) earlier article, also included in this
E-special, anticipates some of this intermingling between worlds modern-
ist science kept apart. Here, in contrast to reductionist attempts to under-
stand the city, Clark calls for a baroque understanding where the
metropolis is revitalized through exploring the ‘natural life’ of the city
as a fecund domain where the natural and the social meet. Such an
Human 435
Notes
1. Not being sealed off or independent from our environment but rather being
constituted by the relationships we maintain with our environment implies a
shift in the way we conceive of autonomy. As Edgar Morin (2007: 14) has
noted, ‘for a living being to be autonomous, it is necessary that it depends on
its environment, on matter and energy, and also on knowledge and informa-
tion. The more autonomy will develop, the more multiple dependencies will
develop.’ This has implications for how we conceive of political sovereignty
or indeed individualism in liberal societies.
2. For a discussion of the radical openness of complex systems see Chu et al.
(2003); for a discussion of observing complex systems see Rasch (1991).
438 Theory, Culture & Society 33(7–8)
3. See Allen (2000) for a useful description of the assumptions we make when we
reduce complexity.
4. For a discussion on nonlinearity see Clark (2005) and Knyazeva (2004).
5. For a discussion of emergence see Dekker et al. (2011) and Morin (1992); for
a discussion of the relationships between the parts and the whole see Morin
(2007).
References
Allen P (2000) Knowledge, ignorance and learning. Emergence 2(4): 78–103.
Allen P (2001) What is complexity science? Knowledge of the limits to know-
ledge. Emergence 3(1): 24–42.
Ashby WR (1957) An Introduction to Cybernetics. London: Chapman and Hall.
Boer R (2013) Revolution in the event: The problem of kairos. Theory, Culture &
Society 30(2): 116–134.
Borgo D and Goguen J (2005) Rivers of consciousness: The nonlinear dynamics
of free jazz. Proceedings of IAJE Conference, Long Beach, CA, 5–8 January
2004.
Byrne D (2005) Complexity, configurations and cases. Theory, Culture & Society
22(5): 95–111.
Capra F (2005) Complexity and life. Theory, Culture & Society 22(5): 33–44.
Chu D, Stran R and Fjellan R (2003) Theories of complexity: Common denom-
inators of complex systems. Complexity 8(3): 19–30.
Cilliers P (1998) Complexity and Postmodernism: Understanding Complex
Systems. London: Routledge.
Cilliers P (2000) What can we learn from a theory of complexity? Emergence
2(1): 23–33.
Cilliers P (2001) Boundaries, hierarchies and networks in complex systems.
International Journal of Innovation Management 5(2): 135–147.
Cilliers P (2005) Complexity, deconstruction and relativism. Theory, Culture &
Society 22(5): 255–267.
Cilliers P (2006) On the importance of a certain slowness. Stability, memory and
hysteresis in complex systems. Emergence: Complexity & Organization 8(3):
106–113.
Clark N (2000) Botanizing on the asphalt? The complex life of cosmopolitan
bodies. Body & Society 6(3–4): 12–33.
Clark N (2005) Ex-orbitant globality. Theory, Culture & Society 22(5): 165–185.
Dekker S, Cilliers P and Hofmyer JH (2011) The complexity of failure:
Implications of complexity theory for safety investigations. Safety Science
49: 939–945.
Fodor J and Lepore E (1992) Holism: A Shopper’s Guide. Oxford: Blackwell.
Haraway D (1988) Situated knowledges: The science question in feminism and
the privilege of partial perspective. Feminist Studies 14(3): 575–599.
Horgan J (1995) From complexity to perplexity. Scientific American 272(6):
104–120.
Human O (2013) Towards experimentation as praxis: Producing novelty without
the event. Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy
9(2): 68–85.
Human 439
Contents