Roth 2013
Roth 2013
Situated cognition
Wolff-Michael Roth1∗ and Alfredo Jornet2
Following the cognitive revolution, when knowing and learning have come to
be theorized in terms of representations stored and processed in the mind,
empirical and theoretical developments in very different scholarly disciplines
have led to the emergence of the situated cognition hypothesis, which consists
of a set of interlocking theses: cognition is embodied, fundamentally social,
distributed, enacted, and often works without representations. We trace the
historical origins of this hypothesis and discuss the evidential support this
hypothesis receives from empirical and modeling studies. We distinguish the
question of where cognition is located from the question of what cognition is,
because the confounding of the two questions leads to misunderstandings in
the sometimes-ardent debates concerning the situated cognition hypothesis. We
conclude with recommendations for interdisciplinary approaches to the nature of
cognition. © 2013 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.
700
includes the following, generally interconnected but
Brown et al., 1989, Google
sometimes independently treated theses:
′Situated cognition′, ISI
600
1. Cognition arises from, and is connected to,
500 the interactions that the material body of an
agent entertains with its physical environment;
Citations/year
ontogenetic origins of these activities are those societal human cultural activities such as schooling and philo-
relations that the persons have lived through before in sophical discourses on logic.31,32 Thus, the relations
characteristic material settings. When such relations between subjects and their activities are constitutive,
are absent, as in deaf–blind children, even the most not causal: ‘The processes of living are enacted by the
fundamental human behaviors and inclinations are environment as truly as by the organism; for they are
absent.26 Researchers using this approach—working an integration’ (Ref 31, p. 25). The influence of Amer-
among others in neuropsychology—recognized that ican pragmatism on situated cognition is particularly
mental processes, such as speaking, thinking, reading, noticeable in the fields of education, to which Dewey
or writing need to be understood in terms of complex contributed a lot, and of the learning sciences.
ecologies (functional systems), that involve both (1)
fundamental neuromuscular and physiological pro-
cesses and (2) their cultural–historical origin and Theoretical Biology
nature.27 This line of work influenced those studies There is a long history of studies in (theoretical)
that are marked by adjectives such as ‘sociocultural’, biology and physiology that emphasize the irreducible
‘cultural–historical’, and ‘societal–historical’. nature of an organism-in-environment system.33,34
Some fundamental ideas from biology and physiology
are associated with enactivism and embodiment
Ecological Psychology theories, which emphasize the structural coupling
Insights and experimental findings from ecological between organism and environment.35 This structural
psychology28 also contributed to the institution of coupling—which expresses itself in the fact that
what is now collected under the ‘situated cognition’ ‘there is no possible distinction between internally
label. A key concept from ecological psychology is and externally generated states of nervous activity’
that of ‘affordance’, which denotes the possibilities (Ref 35, p. 23)—determines useful behavioral results.
for visually guided locomotion, rhythmic movement, Such generally ecological theories of cognition
and (grasping, wielding) action that arise for the emphasize that agents (organisms) cannot live without
agent from those aspects of the environment salient environment and that the environment has definite
in/to its perception. Here, organism–environment characteristics only with respect to the particular
couplings are the major determinants of behavior: organism.36,37 Especially philosophical approaches to
A ball-shaped doorknob, e.g., affords turning to the cognitive sciences draw inspiration from biological
an agent, who ‘directly’ perceives it as a physically and physiological studies.
possible way to open a door.29 Such affordance is
not inherent to the doorknob, but refers to a relation
between a material possibility and the perception of SUPPORT FROM EMPIRICAL STUDIES
it in the course of action. The agent does not need
to have a mental representation of a door; rather, The term ‘situated cognition’ emerged from discus-
the environment itself suggests what needs to be sions that occurred during the mid-1980s at the
done. Ecological psychology had a particularly strong Institute for Research and Learning and the XEROX
impact on the cognitive sciences concerned with the Palo Alto Research Center, which were influenced,
design of workplaces and human artifacts. among others, by ethnographic studies of mathemati-
cal performance in the everyday (work) world as well
as by studies in situation semantics (see insert) and
American Pragmatism Heideggerian artificial intelligence (AI; see below).
American pragmatism has been another major influ- Central issues concerned the question whether (men-
ence on the situated cognition hypothesis. As early as tal) representation is a requirement for explaining
1896, Dewey objected to the view of the ‘reflex arc’ as higher-order psychological function and the mediating
a mechanistic stimulus–response relation and argued role of culture in (individual, collective) cognition.
for an organic approach in which sensation, thought,
and action would form an irreducible unit. In his view,
‘sensory stimulus, central connections and motor Cognition and Representation
responses shall be viewed, not as separate and com- A central aspect of the situated cognition hypothesis
plete entities in themselves, but as divisions of labor, is that many of the complex human behaviors do not
functioning factors, within the single concrete whole’ necessitate the internal representation of the world
(Ref 30, p. 358). Later, Dewey would articulate the and its contents; instead, structures in the environment
notions of continuity of experience and transaction as account for structures in behavior. Knowing does not
fundamental, irreducible categories for understanding mean mentally representing facts and rules about the
world but refers to how an organism functions in the Learning and Solving Problems Without
world. Research on perception, memory, and learning Representations: The Question of Transfer
is shedding light on the ways in which behavior The emergence of the situated cognition hypothesis,
can be based in organism–environment couplings especially as it pertains to educational research,
rather than on mental (internal) descriptions of the can be traced to a number of ethnographic studies
external world. that moved research on learning and cognition
outside the laboratory and into everyday practice
Perceiving and Remembering Without settings.3,43 Lave’s Cognition in Practice44 —one of
Representing: The World as Memory the early, frequently cited examples of the situated
One of the strongest arguments for a nonrepresen- approach (over 6500 Google citations)—reports
tational basis of perception comes from research on studies of arithmetic practices across settings,
‘change blindness’.38 Change blindness refers to the including grocery shopping, simulation experiments of
empirical evidence that changes in an image often grocery shopping, and school-like tests. These studies
go unnoticed when the change occurs while the eye demonstrated important discontinuities in peoples’
blinks or when there is a changeover to another, ways of approaching ‘structurally identical’ tasks
almost identical image. Because an internal represen- as a function of the setting, suggesting an inherent
tation of the visual field would presuppose a complete situativity in problem solving, as different solution
replica of the real thing, blinking should not pre- strategies were enacted depending on the problem
vent us from noticing or reconstructing those changes. presentation. Lave proposed to locate cognition
A comparison of the representations of the images in practices, patterned actions that are specific to
prior to and following an eye blink would make certain cultural–historical settings and communities.
it possible to detect the change. Change blindness Following these early studies, a number of related
therefore provides empirical support for the situated works instituted a ‘practice turn’ in educational
cognition hypothesis according to which the world research, where groups of learners are considered to
stands for itself rather than being represented in the constitute communities of practice45 , and learning as
mind.39 Sustained and rich visual experience depend a process of legitimate peripheral participation and of
on the direct relation between the environment and cognitive apprenticeship.2
the body, which knows where to find the information One of the most controversial issues that
required for some next step. Seeing does not con- arose together with the practice turn was the
sist in exhaustively scanning the world and internally challenge that it posed to the notion of learning
representing it—e.g., as in the CaMeRa model of cog- transfer. The idea of transfer was fundamental to
nition related to graphs.40 Rather, it constitutes an educational research, because it assumed that the
active, situated, and experience-specific exploration curriculum contents (e.g., in science, mathematics,
of the surrounding world, where the organism can or geography) could be appropriated in the school
access any required information at every stage in an and later applied in other, within- and out-of-school
inquiry. situations.46,47 This assumption is not supported by
Research has also explored the idea that research evidence, which reports no or insignificant
remembering—a function that classical literature in correlations between number of, and achievement in,
cognitive science explicitly relates to the retrieval school-based mathematics courses and mathematical
of stored representations—may be explained without behavior in the everyday world.44 A debate emerged
resorting to the notion of ‘retrieving’. From a situated in which scholars from an information-processing
view, memory traces can be seen as ‘incomplete, approach interpreted the claims on situativity as a
partial, and context-sensitive, to be reconstructed negation of the possibility of transfer.48 Proponents of
rather than reproduced’ (Ref 41, p. 229). These the situated cognition hypothesis, on the other hand,
memory traces are complemented with situational deemed such accusation misled49 because it ignored
(social and environmental) aspects that again can be the fundamental difference in the premises on learning:
seen as integral rather than external to the cognitive in the context of the situated cognition hypothesis,
process of remembering. Nelson and Fivush42 , e.g., learning is not viewed as the acquisition of knowledge
review research that shows how the ways in which contents, but in terms of expanding the learner’s
parents structure conversations about past events with action possibilities in larger systems of activity. An
their children strongly influence how children come alternative to the classic transfer paradigm is based on
to construct their own narrative history, suggesting Gibson’s notion of ‘affordance’,28 and may be defined
that memory is culturally mediated and remembering as a question of whether individuals are attuned to
contingent to situations. constraints of a situation’s affordances.50 It is not an
internal model that transfers to another setting but around the world more generally.12,57 Shared bodily
a set of subject–environment relations. In line with experiences and the function of language to influence
this approach, some recent research conceptualizes the behavior of others makes language inherently a
learning transfer without explicitly resorting to cultural tool available to all members: it embodies
the notion of mental representation, but rather to a system of ideas (i.e., an ideology)58 or a system
situational aspects. Transfer has been explained as a of categorization of experiences in the world.56
result of ‘focusing frameworks’, where the situational However, this system is not deterministic, but evolves
objects that are noticed and made salient across together with and because of situated actions. The
situations are (1) a function of teacher–student signification of a word never is the same. Because
interactions51 and (2) highly influenced by the ways each experience transforms the objective conditions in
in which educational situations are ‘framed’.52 which further experiences are had,31,32 each utterance
becomes the seed for changing culture.59 Moreover,
because language embodies implicit rules for its own
Cognition as a Feature of Society use, competent speakers can situationally generate
Many social psychologists generally and activity statements on a topic even though they have never
theorists particularly accept K. Marx’s thesis that thought about this topic before and, consequently,
specifically human forms of cognition are not inher- without having a representation thereof.60 Again,
ited, but exist in society-specific cultural practices. from the situated cognition hypothesis these rules are
Thus, the founder of activity theory suggested that ‘the not considered formal symbolic relations stored in the
psychological nature of man is the totality of societal mind that then generate new language combinations.
relations shifted to the inside’ so that ‘development Language is learned by participating in societal
proceeds not toward socialization but toward indi- relations: it is a means for entertaining, and the result
vidualization of societal functions’ (Ref 24, p. 1023, of, societal relations. Language-use inescapably points
1025, original emphasis, underline added). Studies to the societal, shared nature of cognition.12,14,24
of tool use and practices among primates support
such suggestions.53,54 We exemplify this feature of Embodiment of the Social
the situated cognition hypothesis in the context of the Another way to investigate the forms in which
nature of language and the embodiment of the social. cognition is embodied and situated in the material
world is by looking at how people coordinate and
The Nature of Language organize their actions in society-specific activities. A
From the sociocultural and cultural–historical number of researchers from backgrounds as diverse
perspectives that underlie the situated cognition as linguistics, psycholinguistics, cognitive anthropol-
hypothesis, language is not a system of correspon- ogy, psychology, or computer science inquire into
dences between symbols and elements in the world, ways in which people constitute social order and
but a means for humans to coordinate their situated intercomprehension by investigating the embodied
actions3 with others and for agents to stimulate co-articulation of different semiotic fields during
their own minds.24 It has been suggested that signs55 face-to-face interactions.61 From this embodied inter-
generally and language24 specifically originally action perspective, language is not seen as an isolated
function to influence the behavior of others before the system, but as forming part of larger, multimodal
individual can use it to influence its own behavior. social intercourse, involving both the body (gestures,
This is especially the case because language arises postures) and the material elements of the situation
from, and is grounded in, bodily experiences that (objects being indexed or referred to). Many studies
are structured by the body and its movements; once exhibit the embodied, enacted, and distributed aspects
these movements are encoded in symbolic form, they of cognition in studies of communication in a variety
can be used as metaphors to describe and refer to of workplaces and everyday settings.62 This work sug-
other types of entities.56 For example, the experience gests that an exclusive focus on the representational
of something being inside or outside of a container properties of communication—e.g., inscriptions in
may be used to think or talk about the mind: The the form of charts, maps, graphs—interferes with
container metaphor suggests that there are things an appropriate understanding of how these entities
inside the mind (e.g., internal representations) and are embedded within collectively organized human
other things outside the mind (e.g., inscriptions, practices. Thus, for example, professional vision in
material representations). A pragmatic perspective archeology arises from and interacts with talk, writ-
supports the contention that there is no difference ing, and tools as people communicate—using words,
between knowing a language and knowing one’s way gestures, body position, and body orientation—over
and about salient issues (e.g., producing a map).63 of the tasks involved would exceed the capacities of
Other studies show how prosody (speech intensity, human cognition based on representations of kitchen,
volume, and pitch), intellectual disagreement, lan- tools, materials, orders, and so on. Rather, following
guage, body orientation, body position with respect Heidegger’s analysis that tools are ‘ready-to-hand’,
to the playing field, and emotion interact in the course a function that is an integral part of a what-for
of children’s playing a game of hopscotch.64 That orientation, the kitchen as a whole is taken as its own
is, an argument that plays out at the group level representation. Thus, e.g., a sandwich in a particular
simultaneously is reflected in body movements that state and at a particular place in the kitchen requires
the participants are not conscious of. Intonation, a specific action to move it into its next production
rhythm, and facial expressions of different speakers stage. The state of the kitchen itself suggests what
tend to be aligned in agreement, but are significantly needs to be done next. The cook is the agent who
different in disagreement not only over the outcome of enacts these transformations. As a result, many orders
games, but also during debates concerning conceptual can be worked on simultaneously without requiring
issues.65 Consistent with the notion of cognition mental representation and computation. This is
as socially situated and embodied, recent studies also important in learning, for ‘what the learner
in experimental psychology show for example that acquires through experience is not represented at all
(1) automaticity—response to threat with aggressive but is presented to the learner as more and more
(fight) or distancing behavior (flight)—is a function finely discriminated situations’ (Ref 70, p. 250). This
of the situation (subject in enclosed booth or in development does not require representation of the
open field)66 , (2) eye movements, gazing times, and environment in the agent’s mind, but may occur in
memory for images are highly responsive to being terms of the changing relations and the adaptation of
informed that others are looking at the same images a mental pointer system (‘deictic codes’).72
at the same time67 , and (3) place cognition is a
function of active perception.68
Situated Robotics
SUPPORT FROM MODELING STUDIES Important existent proofs that intelligent and complex
Support for the situated cognition hypothesis also behavior is possible without mental representation
comes from modeling studies in AI, robotics, artificial derives from situated robotics and other artificial
neural networks, and associated mathematical models life modeling endeavors. Situated robotics can be
(see Box 1). An important point of discussion understood as a valuable foil for (1) articulating
centers on the question of representation and whether and explaining the different aspects of the situated
it is necessary for the acting subject to have a cognition hypothesis73 and (2) studying the sufficient
representation of the world in its mind or whether conditions of cognition. It thereby constitutes a
other forms of relating to the world not only are meta-methodological tool for those natural sciences
possible, but also accomplish tasks that traditional concerned with cognition in its varying guises.6 In
AI and cognitive psychology have ascribed to mental the early years, robots were controlled by software
representations.69 There appears to be a general sense that represented the environment in which the robots
that modeling studies may be able to set constraints moved. These robots therefore could operate only in
on theories of cognition, e.g., concerning the need for fixed, pre-defined environments. As an alternative, sit-
representations to explain higher-order behavior. uated robotics focused on building robots that learned
and developed by moving around and interacting with
complex and dynamically changing environments
Heideggerian AI without explicit, stored representations.74 On the
One approach to AI and the modeling of human basis of Wittgenstein’s idea of language as a game,12
behavior took as its starting point Heidegger’s descrip- some designers of situated robotics work on the
tion of everyday ways of being.70 This approach relies problem of (1) not only allowing communication
on careful, phenomenological analyses of human between and with situated robots in their environment
experience for the purpose of designing computing and grounding communication (language) in the
systems consistent with the experience—e.g., the material world (2) but also developing suitable
absence of a mental representation of a hammer while language games from the bottom up.75 Another
hammering a nail into a wall. Researchers working in approach to the emergence of language focuses on
this direction modeled, for example, the activities in a the embodiment of meanings of symbolic forms
short-order kitchen, where a cook works on multiple and takes the communicative forms to be embodied
orders simultaneously.71 Accomplishing the entirety and emergent from collective activity.55 Because the
be bagged in the example above—and cognition.85 of cognition can be drawn in regard to how integral the
Cognition is produced by the brain; and the fact notions of body and environment are to the minimal
that extra-cranial aspects play a central role in a given unit of analysis.
cognitive function does not concede them the cognitive
‘credit’.86 Empirical investigations cannot solve the
problem, as these cannot distinguish between the two Self-Actional Models
perspectives, that is, between different claims about In the classical approach to cognition, the (sensory)
where cognition lies.81 experience in one or more situations gives rise to repre-
Another way of framing the question of situated sentations, which are the results of abstractions from
cognition involves defining first the range of phenom- the concrete situations (Figure 2(a)). As abstractions,
ena that we consider cognitive. Some psychologists they can be used in (applied to) all other situations
have warned long ago to consider higher psycholog- that are consistent with the structure retained in the
ical functions as structures inherent in nature rather abstraction. Representations are symbols stored in
than as human constructs, and not to confuse brain memory in the form of declarative and procedural
and person: it is the person controlling the brain ‘knowledge’ that describe objects in and transfor-
by means of external stimuli.24 This is consistent mations of the environment. The more abstract the
with empirical observations, where, for example, representation, the larger the set of situations to
situational characteristics such as the number and which it can be applied. From this view, relations with
arrangement of milk cartons on a pallet and the the environment involve the enactment of production
number of milk cartons that constitute the customer’s rules—abstractions of functional relations with the
order together determine what the actions of the environment—that are activated by environmental
person organizing the delivery will do and calculate.43 stimuli. In ‘turning to the left’ while driving a car,
Some present-day neuroscientists agree noting that for example, cognition involves the enactment of
‘brains do not experience—organisms do’ (Ref 87, production rules of the type ‘IF the road curves to the
p. 319). To understand cognition, therefore, we need left THEN turn to the left’. The body is considered,
to consider the agent in its ecological context, which as the environment, to be the ‘raw sensory input’ for
together allow us to understand the role that the cognitive processing. Cognitive phenomena include
processes inside the brain play—especially if under- encoding, retrieval, or processing of information.
stood as an evolutionary feature that represents an Because the elemental units of this model (represen-
advantage.88 tations) are used to explain the behavior of what is
defined as the cognitive system, we label this model as
self-actional.79
What Is Cognition?
How cognition is understood and modeled depends Interactional Models
on the categories used, the smallest units of analysis In much of the situated cognition literature, the
into which human behavior can be decomposed while application of representations is de-emphasized or
preserving the characteristics of the relevant whole. In absent. Rather, researchers focus on how a situation
recent years, there has been a shift from units defined presents itself to the subject (Figure 2(b)). No
by properties inherent to the brain to units defined boundary is drawn between environment, body, and
by correlations and dynamic patterns that include the mind. Research adopting this model emphasizes the
brain, body, and environment leading to the study mutually constitutive (dialectical) nature of situation
of cognitive ecosystems.89 In choosing a particular and presentation (activation).43,44 The minimal unit is
unit of analysis, the researcher actively defines the a unit of interaction between two entities: subject and
boundaries of the phenomenon and, thereby, situates environment. Cognitive phenomena are not restricted
cognition and frames the domain that needs to be to what happens inside the brain, but refer to
theorized: The unit of analysis determines what is the interactions within the person-in-situation unit.
to be understood as cognition and what lies outside Interactional models adopt a nondualist approach
it. Different models bear different implications for to agency. In the cognitive system, mind, body,
how the notion of representation is understood. and environment are considered both agent and
Notions such as distributed cognition arise as the structure: acting and acted-upon. However, these
result of taking, for example, ship navigation—a task models face a challenge in that the connections
involving a team of people and the coordination across situations are rarely addressed or explained,
of several representational devices—as the unit of making it difficult to theorize stability and long-
cognitive analysis.90 Different approaches to the study term growth to the extent that a representational
S1 S2 S1 S2 S1 S2
FIGURE 2 | Different units of analysis lead to different ways of conceptualizing the nature of cognition. (a) Classical representation approach. (b)
A nontransactional interpretation of the situated cognition approach. (c) Transactional, dialectical approach, where time is not external, but is
integrated with the units of analysis.
approach does. Time is often unaddressed or taken minimum units that preserve the characteristics of
as the context of the unit of analysis. Thus, for the whole have been proposed, including experience
example, models of situated construction of attitudes [pereživanie],32,87 activity,24,25 and consciousness.25
are good at explaining situated appropriateness In cultural–historical approaches, society constitutes
and differences across situations, but fail to the defining whole.24,25,95 A transactional unit of
address enduring characteristics.91 In fact, there is analysis allows accounting for the re-presentational
very little research that followed subjects across aspects of cognition without turning representations
time with changing conditions (situations). Lave’s into the cause of behavior. Thus, researchers working
study of mathematics in the supermarket, on within this frame can theorize cognitive processes
simulated shopping problems, and on best-buy both as parallel and as sequential.96 The parallel
word problems44 emphasizes discontinuities more so aspects highlight the conceptual nature of perception,
than continuities that arise from the same bodies where perceiving is both imposing certain structure
being involved in and moving between material on the world as well as letting the world guide percep-
settings. tion, involving affection at least as much as intention.
The sequential aspects highlight the spatiotemporal
Transactional Models extension of cognition, allowing representations to
A third type of model focuses on what is present in the reside both in the mind, the body, and the (material
consciousness of the subject, in subject–environment and social) environment; and it highlights a reflective
transactions, and, simultaneously, includes the trans- dimension that is not reduced to any single instant,
formed situation itself (Figure 2(c)). Time becomes but which implies internal temporal connections.
internal to the phenomenon rather than constituting Rather than an inherent representational function
an external factor. For example, a study investigating of the brain, re-presentational (imagistic, narrative)
students’ conceptual activities in a science learning functions emerge from the fact that time is inherent
activity showed how the problem itself was contin- to the unit of analysis. From this view it is possible
uously transformed, and, with it, the way in which and plausible to study the role of the body and the
the task presented itself.92 New problem and solution (material, social, and societal) environment in pre-
strategies emerge unpredictably, whereas previously senting and re-presenting the world during cognitive
stated problem definition and solution alternatives activity.
fell to the wayside. That is, the minimum analytic unit
contains the transformation (temporal dimension) and From Biology to Culture
the forces of development within itself. If a satisfac- A transactional unit of analysis involves a multiplicity
tory criterion for a good model states that the smallest of constitutive levels. Across the different academic
category is that unit which preserves properties of the fields where situated cognition approaches are used,
whole, then knowing and known have to be under- four levels of analysis may be identified (Table 1).
stood as constituting one, transactional system. As a The first level is concerned with the biology
consequence, there is an inner contradiction because (neural, physiological) and always inaccessible to
what in other models are different situations here are consciousness. The second level concerns the body and
part of the same minimum unit of analysis. Dynam- its fundamental operations that tend to be automatic
ical models in cognitive science, which focus on but can be brought into conscious awareness (e.g.,
continuous change (rather than states), the dynamical those movements of the body that are involved
coupling of environment and subject, and on alterna- in shifting gears but that tend to be unconscious
tive approaches to representation attempt to capture in the performances of competent drivers). At the
both continuity and discontinuity.93,94 Different third level are individual or collective agents that
pursue conscious goals, which they realize through studies reviewed are close to insights that had arisen
actions. The fourth, most global level is defined from phenomenological studies of space perception.
by culture (society), characterized by collective Other scholars relate their work concerning the role
practices (activities) that realize collective motives of mirror neurons in joint action and affect to the
(e.g., generalized provision of food, shelter, and other phenomenological studies (Husserl, Merleau-Ponty)
needs). The imaging-related metaphors of zooming of self-other identity and affect.99 There are mathe-
and focusing may assist understanding how the choice matical (catastrophe-theoretic) modeling approaches
of the analytic unit determines what enters into the that provide the mediating link between physical
analytic lens.97 Zooming limits what comes into the (scientific) and cognitive (computational vision)
picture, making invisible anything that lies outside and explanations of visual perception and phenomeno-
the connections between inside and outside; focusing logical descriptions thereof.100 Some researchers
refers to finding the appropriate method to provide concerned with aspects of situated cognition explicitly
the best image of the entities in the chosen field. suggest that ‘disciplined first-person accounts [of
experience] should be an integral element of the
validation of a neurobiological proposal, and not
CONCLUSION merely coincidental or heuristic information’ (Ref
One of the most significant implications that results 101, p. 344). The possibilities and implications of
from expanding the unit of analysis in situated such an approach remain to be explored and tested
cognition is that phenomena, which previously where empirically.
seen as epiphenomenal to cognition and therefore To understand intelligent behavior means
remained unexplained by cognitive accounts, are now accounting for the role of human experience, however
thoroughly explored with the aim of providing a sub- subjective it might appear, by any suitable means.
stantial (fundamental) contribution to understanding There are efforts to combine the rigorous study of
intelligent behavior. Perceiving, remembering, or human experience and the cognitive sciences,102 an
reasoning are not independent phenomena—to be effort sometimes referred to as the naturalization of
explored as operations of the brain alone—but phenomenology or the phenomenological mind.103
are integral to agents-in-their-context-acting-for-a- The perhaps most ardent advocate for an integration
purpose-and-with-tools. Because the unit of analysis of research approaches across all levels, F. J. Varela,
that the situated cognition hypothesis in the interac- proposed neurophenomenology.101 This approach is
tional and transactional versions proposes cuts across designed to deal with the ‘hard problem’ of cognitive
levels (see Table 1), the study of cognitive phenomena science, the interrelation of human experience and
thus understood requires interdisciplinary methods associated brain activity; it may thereby also address
capable of accounting for the connections between the ‘grounding problem’ of cognitive science, that is,
the levels. the question of how abstract (mental), nonphysical
There are already studies in the neurosciences representations are connected to physical actions of
recognizing philosophical studies that have antici- real people. Varela argues that studies of neural cor-
pated their results. Thus, a team studying the neural relates of experience require not only the methods
processes involved in spatial perception noted that of the neurosciences, but also rigorous approaches
the findings they reviewed were inconsistent with to the study of experience and invariants thereof.
traditional cognitive science, which is based on Attention, present-time consciousness, body image,
mental representations, but emphasized the role perceptual filling in and fringe/center, and emotion
of motor-to-sensory pathways in object and space are but some of the domains where careful scientific
perception.98 The authors note that the single neuron and first-person, phenomenological studies can lead to
concerted convergent accounts of an ‘embodied, situ- shows how symbolic behavior among bonobo (pygmy
ated, or enactive cognitive science’ (Ref 101, p. 346). chimpanzee) arises from movements designed to
Because of the embodiment that the situated engage in carrying behavior.55 Similarly, studies
cognition hypothesis postulates, a direct connection among teen-aged students in hands-on science show
between thought and affect—missing in other how hand-arm movements—initially modifying and
approaches to cognition—is established. Social aspects exploring the setting with the senses (i.e., ergotic,
of situatedness give rise to the shared nature of epistemic movements)—subsequently become iconic
affect (emotion), such as in experiences of empathy (symbolic) hand gestures the contents of which
or collective emotions (e.g., grief over the loss of a later are represented in symbolic (e.g., abstract
leader or ‘national’ elation over a win at some world physical model), linguistic, and pictorial forms.108
championship). Recent studies using a wide spectrum Both interdisciplinary field and laboratory studies are
of ethnographic methods, such as monitoring of required for testing the universality of such changes
pitch and speech intensity, have started to investigate in communicative behavior and the precise role that
the regulative functions of emotions in (mundane) language plays when communication is understood
situated cognitive activities such as during everyday more holistically: spread across bodies and situations.
work in a fish hatchery.104 Cognitive ethnographic In summary, the situated cognition hypothesis
studies are also being mobilized to account for the opens a horizon of research questions that bears great
connections between cultural practices and situated potential for expanding what cognitive science has to
collective conceptualizations.105 Further work needs say about competent and intelligent human behavior.
to be conducted in everyday settings similar to the To create new research, the cognitive sciences, which
early studies on the cognitive aspects of mathematics already span, as the editors of The Cambridge
in the everyday world. Handbook of Situated Cognition state, ‘a wide range
Solving the question of transfer from a situated of projects in philosophy, psychology, neuroscience,
perspective is still a challenge to accomplish. There anthropology, robotics, and other fields’ (Ref 109,
is a tension between the need to address change and p. 9) may find it useful to follow research in other
at the same time explain recurrence and stability. emerging fields—including biotechnology, nanoscale
Whereas the mentioned developments have been science and engineering, genomics, medicine, and
useful in advancing our understanding of how the other strategic disciplines—where theoretical and
subject–situation relations are involved in learning, methodological interdisciplinarity are correlated with
these have at some extent remained interactional in innovation.110 To encourage novel approaches in the
that explanations of learning have centered on intel- field, a special issue in Topics in Cognitive Science
lectual aspects, continuity across situations consisting on the theme of interdisciplinary approaches may
in structural relations of information structures. Other constitute an ideal starting point for launching this
approaches that have attempted to account for the topic anew. Of particular interest may be those
developmental aspects of change and continuity, for places where humans and machines (e.g., intelligent
example across the school and the world of work, have robots) come to relate and reconfigure each other—as
overlooked the mechanisms by which the intellectual intimated in the title of Suchman’s Human–Machine
aspects of conceptualization emerge and evolve.106,107 Reconfigurations.3
Furthermore, the role of the body in transfer consti-
tutes an important question that requires an answer
from the situated cognition hypothesis. NOTES
To solve questions concerning the role of a
Here we understand ‘support’ in terms of the
language, studies need to be conducted that document Bayesian approach, which (a) establishes probabilities
and explicate how communication with abstract p(H|D) for hypothesis H given the data D—in
symbols may arise from bodily behavior. It is contrast to the classical statistical approach that
only in this way that we can come to better establishes probabilities p(D|H) of data D given
understandings about how (linguistic, symbolic) hypothesis H—and (b) uses both quantitative and
behaviors have evolved from their evolutionary qualitative data (e.g., in determination of priors)
precedents and how (new) (linguistic, symbolic) in support for a hypothesis H or its alternate Halt :
communication arises in the course of development p(Halt |D) = 1 – p(H|D).
along the life span. Thus, for example, one study
REFERENCES
1. Barsalou LW. Grounded cognition: past, present, and 19. Roth W-M. Geometry as Objective Science in
future. Top Cogn Sci 2010, 2:716–724. Elementary Classrooms: Mathematics in the Flesh.
2. Brown JS, Collins A, Duguid P. Situated cognition and New York: Routledge; 2011.
the culture of learning. Educ Res 1989, 18:32–42. 20. Devlin K. Logic and Information. Cambridge, UK:
3. Suchman LA. Human–Machine Reconfigurations: Cambridge University Press; 1991.
Plans and Situated Actions. 2nd ed. Cambridge, UK: 21. Devlin K, Rosenberg D. Language at Work: Analyz-
Cambridge University Press; 2007. ing Communication Breakdown in the Workplace to
4. Smith ER, Semin GR. Socially situated cognition: Inform Systems Design. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publica-
cognition in its social context. Adv Exp Soc Psychol tions; 1996.
2004, 36:53–117. 22. Lin F. Situation calculus. In: van Hermelen F,
5. Clancey WJ, Sierhuis M, Seah C. Workflow agents Lifschitz V, Porter B, eds. Handbook of Knowledge
versus expert systems: problem solving methods in Representation. Amsterdam: Elsevier; 2008, 649–669.
work systems design. AI EDAM 2009, 23:357–371. 23. Lespérance Y, Levesque HJ. Indexical knowledge and
6. Almeida e Costa F, Rocha LM. Introduction to the robot action—a logical account. Artif Intell 1995,
special issue: Embodied and situated cognition. Artif 73:69–115.
Life 2005, 11:5–11. 24. Vygotskij LS. Psixologija Razvitija Čeloveka [Psy-
7. Newell A, Simon HA. Human Problem Solving. chology of Human Development]. Moscow, Russia:
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall; 1972. Eksmo; 2005.
8. Atkinson RC, Schiffrin RM. Human memory: a 25. Leont’ev AN. Activity, Consciousness and Personality.
proposed system and its control process. In: Spence Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall; 1978.
KW, Spence JT, eds. The Psychology of Learning and 26. Meshcheryakov A. Awakening to Life: On the
Motivation: Advances in Research and Theory. New Education of Deaf-blind Children in the Soviet Union.
York: Academic Press; 1968, 89–195. Moscow: Progress; 1979.
9. Kirshner D, Whitson JA, eds. Situated Cognition. 27. Luria AR. The Working Brain. New York: Basic Books;
Social, Semiotic and Psychological Perspectives. 1976.
Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates; 1997.
28. Gibson JJ. The Ecological Approach to Visual
10. Clancey WJ. Scientific antecedents of situated cogni- Perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin; 1979.
tion. In: Robbins P, Aydede M, eds. The Cambridge
29. Norman D. The Design of Everyday Things. New
Handbook of Situated Cognition. Cambridge, UK:
York: Basic Books; 1988.
Cambridge University Press; 2009, 11–34.
30. Dewey J. The reflex arc concept in psychology. Psychol
11. Heidegger M. Sein und Zeit [Being and Time].
Rev 1896, 3:357–370.
Tübingen: Max Niemeyer; 1977.
31. Dewey J. Logic–The Theory of Inquiry. New York:
12. Wittgenstein L. Philosophische Untersuchungen/
Henry Holt and Company; 1938.
Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell; 1997.
32. Dewey J. Experience and Education. New York:
13. Merleau-Ponty M. Phénoménologie de la Perception
Macmillan; 1938.
[Phenomenology of Perception]. Paris: Gallimard;
1945. 33. von Uexküll J. Theoretische Biologie [Theoretical
14. Husserl E. Husserliana Band XXXIX. Die Lebenswelt: Biology]. Frankfurt/M: Suhrkamp; 1973.
Auslegungen der vorgegebenen Welt und ihrer 34. von Weizsäcker V. Der Gestaltkreis [The Gestalt
Konstitution. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1916–1937) Circle]. Frankfurt/M: Suhrkamp; 1973.
[Husserliana vol. 39. The Lifeworld: Interpretations of 35. Maturana HR, Varela FJ. Autopoiesis and Cognition.
the Given World and its Constitutions. Texts from the The Realization of the Living. Dordrecht: D. Reidel;
Estate (1916–1937)]. Dordrecht: Springer; 2008. 1980.
15. Garfinkel H. Studies in Ethnomethodology. Englewood 36. Jarvilehto T. The theory of the organism-environment
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall; 1967. system: I. Description of the theory. Integr Phys Behav
16. Lakoff G, Núñez R. Where Mathematics Comes from: Sci 1998, 33:317–330.
How the Embodied Mind Brings Mathematics into 37. Jarvilehto T. The theory of the organism-environment
Being. New York: Basic Books; 2000. system: II. Significance of nervous activity in the
17. Sheets-Johnstone M. The Corporeal Turn: An organism-environment system. Integr Phys Behav Sci
Interdisciplinary Reader. Exeter: Imprint Academic; 1998, 33:331–338.
2009. 38. O’Regan JK, Noë A. A sensorimotor account of
18. Henry M. Incarnation: Une Philosophie de la Chair. vision and visual consciousness. Behav Brain Sci 2001,
Paris: Éditions du Seuil; 2000. 24:883–917.
39. Myin E, O’Regan K. Situated perception and sensation 55. Hutchins E, Johnson CM. Modeling the emergence of
in vision and other modalities: a sensorimotor language as an embodied collective activity. Top Cogn
approach. In: Robbins P, Aydede M, eds. The Sci 2009, 1:523–546.
Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition. New 56. Lakoff G. Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What
York: Cambridge University Press; 2009. Categories Reveal About the Mind. Chicago, IL:
40. Tabachneck-Schijf HJM, Leonardo AM, Simon HA. University of Chicago Press; 1987.
CaMeRa: a computational model for multiple 57. Davidson D. A nice derangement of epitaphs. In:
representations. Cogn Sci 1997, 21:305–350. Lepore E, ed. Truth and Interpretation. Oxford:
41. Sutton J. Remembering. In: Robbins P, Aydede M, Blackwell; 1986, 433–446.
eds. The Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition.
58. Voloshinov VN. Marxism and the Philosophy of
New York: Cambridge University Press; 2009,
Language. Cambridge, UK: Harvard University Press;
217–235.
1973 Mtejka L, Titunik IR, translators.
42. Nelson K, Fivush R. The emergence of autobiograph-
59. Bakhtin M. Rabelais and his World. Bloomington:
ical memory: a social cultural developmental theory.
Indiana University Press; 1984.
Psychol Rev 2004, 111:486–511.
60. Roth W-M. The nature of scientific conceptions: a
43. Lave J, Murtaugh M, de la Rocha O. The dialectic
discursive psychological perspective. Educ Res Rev
of arithmetic in grocery shopping. In: Rogoff B, Lave
2008, 3:30–50.
J, eds. Everyday Cognition: Its Development in Social
Context. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 61. Streeck J, Goodwin C, LeBaron C, eds. Embodied
1984, 17–35. Interaction. Language and Body in the Material World.
New York: Cambridge University Press; 2011.
44. Lave J. Cognition in Practice: Mind, Mathematics and
Culture in Everyday Life. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge 62. Engeström Y, Middleton D, eds. Cognition and
University Press; 1988. Communication at Work. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
45. Lave J, Wenger E. Situated Learning: Legitimate University Press; 1996.
Peripheral Participation. New York: Cambridge 63. Goodwin C. Practices of seeing, visual analysis: an
University Press; 1991. ethnomethodological approach. In: van Leeuwen T,
46. Gick ML, Holyoak KJ. Schema induction and Jewitt C, eds. Handbook of Visual Analysis. London:
analogical transfer. Cogn Psychol 1983, 15:1–38. Sage; 2000, 157–182.
47. Singley MK, Anderson JR. The Transfer of Cognitive 64. Goodwin C, Goodwin MH, Yaeger-Dror M. Multi-
Skill. Cambridge, UK: Harvard University Press; 1989. modality in girls’ game disputes. J Pragmatics 2002,
34:1621–1649.
48. Anderson JR. Acquisition of cognitive skill. Psychol
Rev 1982, 89:396–406. 65. Roth W-M, Tobin K. Solidarity and conflict:
aligned and misaligned prosody as a transactional
49. Greeno JG. Response: On claims that answer the wrong
resource in intra- and intercultural communication
questions. Educ Res 1997, 26:5–17.
involving power differences. Cult Stud Sci Educ 2010,
50. Greeno JG, Moore JL, Smith DR. Transfer of situated 5:805–847. doi: 10.1007/s11422-010-9272-8.
learning. In: Detterman DK, Sternberg RJ, eds. Transfer
66. Cesario J, Plaks JE, Hagiwara N, Navarrete CD,
on Trial: Intelligence, Cognition and Instruction.
Higgins ET. The ecology of automaticity: How
Norwood: Ablex; 1993, 99–167.
situational contingencies shape action semantics and
51. Lobato J, Rhodehamel B, Hohensee C. ‘Notic- social behavior. Psychol Sci 2010, 21:1311–1317.
ing’ as an alternative transfer of learning
67. Richardson DC, Street CNH, Tan JYM, Kirkham NZ,
process. J Learn Sci 2012, 21:433–482. doi:
Hoover MA, Cavanaugh AG. Joint perception: gaze
10.1080/10508406.2012.682189.
and social context. Front Hum Neurosci 2012, 6:194.
52. Engle RA. Framing interactions to foster generative doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2012.00194.
learning: a situative explanation of transfer in a
68. Miglino O, Ponticorvo M. Place cognition as an
community of learners classroom. J Learn Sci 2006,
example of situated cognition: a study with evolved
15:451–498.
agents. Cogn Process 2009, 10:S250–S252.
53. Whiten A, Goodall J, McGrew WC, Nishida T,
Reynolds V, Sugiyama Y, Tutin CEG, Wrangham 69. Chapman D. Vision, Instruction, and Action.
RW, Boesch C. Cultures in chimpanzees. Nature 1999, Cambridge, UK: MIT Press; 1991.
399:682–685. 70. Dreyfus H. Why Heideggerian AI failed and how fixing
54. van Schaik CP, Ancrenaz M, Borgen G, Galdikas B, it would require making it more Heideggerian. Artif
Knott CD, Singleton I, Suzuki A, Utami SS, Merrill Intell 2007, 171:1137–1160.
M. Orangutan cultures and the evolution of material 71. Agre P, Horswill I. Lifeworld analysis. J Artif Intell Res
culture. Science 2003, 299:102–105. 1997, 6:111–145.
72. Ballard DH, Hayhoe MM, Pook PK, Rao RPN. Deictic 90. Hutchins E. Cognition in the Wild. Cambridge, UK:
codes for the embodiment of cognition. Behav Brain MIT Press; 1995.
Sci 1997, 20:723–767. 91. Schwarz N. Attitude construction: Evaluation in
73. Clancey WJ. A boy scout, Toto, and a bird: how context. Soc Cogn 2007, 25:638–656.
situated cognition is different from situated robotics.
92. Roth WM. Designing as distributed process. Learn
In: Steels L, Brooks R, eds. The Artificial Life Route
Instruct 2001, 11:211–239.
to Artificial Intelligence: Building Embodied, Situated
Agents. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates; 93. van Gelder T. The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive
1995, 227–236. science. Behav Brain Sci 1998, 21:616–665.
74. Brooks R. Intelligence without reason. In: Steels L, 94. Elman J. Language as a dynamical system. In: Port RF,
Brooks R, eds. The Artificial Life Route to Artificial van Gelder T, eds. Mind as Motion: Explorations in the
Intelligence: Building Embodied, Situated Agents. Dynamics of Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press;
Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates; 1995, 1995, 195–223.
25–81. 95. Holzkamp K. Grundlegung der Psychologie. Frank-
75. Steels L. Language games for autonomous robots. IEEE furt/M: Campus; 1983.
Intell Syst 2001, 16:16–22. 96. Clancey WJ. Situated Cognition. On Human Knowl-
76. Elman JL. Learning and development in neural edge and Computer Representations. Cambridge, UK:
networks: the importance of starting small. Cognition Cambridge University Press; 1997.
1993, 48:71–99. 97. Roth W-M. Situating cognition. J Learn Sci 2001,
77. Roth W-M. Artificial neural networks for modeling 10:27–61.
knowing and learning in science. J Res Sci Teach 2000,
98. Rizzolatti G, Fadiga L, Fogassi L, Gallese V. The space
37:63–80.
around us. Science 1997, 277:190–191.
78. Raijmakers MEJ, van Koten S, Molenaar PCM. On
99. Gallese V. The roots of empathy: the shared manifold
the validity of simulating stagewise development by
hypothesis and the neural basis of intersubjectivity.
means of PDP networks: application of catastrophe
Psychopathology 2003, 36:171–180.
analysis and an experimental test of rule-like network
performance. Cogn Sci 1996, 20:101–136. 100. Petitot J. Phenomenology of perception, qualitative
79. Dewey J, Bentley AF. Knowing and the known. In: physics and sheaf mereology, philosophy and the
Handy R, Harwood EC, eds. Useful Procedures of cognitive sciences. In: Casati R, Smith B, White G,
Inquiry. Great Barrington, MA: Behavioral Research eds. Proceedings of the 16th International Wittgenstein
Council; 1999, 97–209. Symposium. Vienna: Verlag Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky;
1994, 387–408.
80. Robbing P, Aydede M. A short primer on Situated
Cognition. In: Robbins P, Aydede M, eds. The 101. Varela FJ. Neurophenomenology: a methodological
Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition. New remedy for the hard problem. J Conscious Stud 1996,
York: Cambridge University Press; 2009, 3–10. 3:330–350.
81. Barker MJ. From cognition’s location to the 102. Schmicking D, Gallagher S. Handbook of Phe-
epistemology of its nature. Cogn Syst Res 2010, nomenology and Cognitive Science. Dordrecht:
11:357–366. Springer; 2010.
82. Kirsh D. The intelligent use of space. Artif Intell 1995, 103. Petitot J, Varela FJ, Roy JM, Pachoud B, eds.
73:31–68. Naturalizing Phenomenology: Issues in Contemporary
83. Kirsh D, Maglio P. On distinguishing epistemic from Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. Stanford:
pragmatic action. Cogn Sci 1994, 18:513–549. Stanford University Press; 1999.
84. Clark A, Chalmers D. The extended mind. Analysis 104. Roth W-M. On the inclusion of emotions, identity,
1998, 58:7–19. and ethico-moral dimensions of actions. In: Daniels
H, Gutierrez KD, eds. Learning and Expanding
85. Aizawa K. The coupling-constitution fallacy revisited. with Activity Theory. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
Cogn Syst Res 2010, 11:332–342.
University Press; 2009, 53–74.
86. Rupert RD. Extended cognition and the priority of
105. Hutchins E, Saeko N. Collaborative construction of
cognitive systems. Cogn Syst Res 2010, 11:343–356.
multimodal utterances. In: Streeck J, Goodwin C,
87. Varela FJ. Consciousness: The inside view. Trends LeBaron C, eds. Embodied Interaction. Language and
Cogn Sci 2001, 5:318–319. Body in the Material World. New York: Cambridge
88. Vygotskij LS. Lekcii po Pedologii [Lectures on University Press; 2011, 29–43.
Pedology]. Izhevsk: Udmurdskij University; 2001. 106. Beach K. Consequential transitions: a sociocultural
89. Hutchins E. Cognitive ecology. Top Cognitive Sci 2010, expedition beyond transfer in education. Rev Res Educ
2:705–715. 1999, 24:101–139.
107. Konkola R, Tuomi-Gröhn T, Lambert P, Ludvigsen S. The Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition.
Promoting learning and transfer between school and Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press; 2009,
workplace. J Educ Work 2007, 20:211–228. 3–10.
108. Roth W-M, Lawless D. Signs, deixis, and the 110. Rogers JD, Youtie J, Kay L. Program level assessment
emergence of scientific explanations. Semiotica 2002, of research centers: contribution of nanoscale science
138:95–130. and engineering centers to US Nanotechnology
109. Robbins P, Aydede M. A short primer on National Initiative goals. Res Eval 2012, 21:368–380.
situated cognition. In: Robbins P, Aydede M, eds.
FURTHER READING
Agre P. Computation and Human Experience. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press; 1997.
Johnson M. The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Imagination, Reason, and Meaning. Chicago, IL: Chicago University
Press; 1987.
Robbins P, Aydede M, eds. The Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press;
2009.
Sheets-Johnstone M. The Primacy of Movement. 2nd ed. Amsterdam: John Benjamins; 2011.
Varela FJ, Thompson F, Rosch E. The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press; 1991.