A Conception of Teaching
A Conception of Teaching
A Conception of Teaching
Nathaniel L. Gage
A Conception of Teaching
Dr. Nathaniel L. Gage
Stanford University
School of Education
Stanford, CA
USA
springer.com
To Maggie
“Besides being a superb scholar and an e xacting editor, Nate Gage was a consum-
mate gentleman of the old school. I remember a meeting of the “Invisible College”
at Syracuse University in the early 1980s. Nate was reporting on the procedures he
had used in his planning and preparation for the National Institute of Education’ s
1974 Conference on Studies in Teaching, which he chaired. He showed a slide of a
chalkboard used during the planning process. On the chalkboard he had listed the
ten panels that were to make up the conference, along with the chairs and members
of each panel. I was struck by the fact that all the male participants were identified
by last name only , while the female participants were identif ied by both f irst and
last name. Given the concerns about gender equity of that time period, I w ondered
if this could be an instance of se xism. But when I ask ed him to e xplain the
difference in recording of the names, he said that he thought it w ould be rude
to refer to women by their last name only. He clearly cared about issues of gender
vii
viii Tribute
any single study may not be con vincing. This might be due to small sample sizes
(often the case in dissertations), or there may be heterogeneity in the data. However,
the composite of the studies seem to point in one direction. Nate’ s question w as
whether this disparate e vidence could be combined in a statistically rigorous w ay
so as to yield a convincing conclusion. Statistical methods for combining the results
of independent studies ha ve been called meta-analysis, and Nate’ s question w as a
catalyst for me to be gin working on the development of statistical methods for the
analysis of such data.
Nate had a kind sense of humor. He had a number of sentences that he liked and
which he would repeat. One such would come out at faculty meetings after I would
make some comment involving numbers. Nate would say, “Ingram, you know that
you are no good with numbers.” This w as also said when we had to check the bill
at a restaurant.
For the last 45 years Nate has been a friend, a colleague, and an intellectual
stimulus. Most recently, he expressed concern that the education community recog-
nize that teaching had a scientif ic foundation. This book represents his le gacy in
showing that such a foundation e xists.”
Ingram Olkin
Professor of Statistics and Education, Stanford University
“When I first met Nate Gage in 1972, he w as described as the “f ather of research
on teaching.” I didn’ t quite kno w what that meant at the time, being a ne w staff
member at the National Institute of Education, just completing my dissertation on
students’ achievement motivation. I soon learned. Nate Gage w orked relentlessly
on developing and sustaining research on teaching and bringing to it the prestige
required to be accepted as an educational research f ield. Nate’s strong focus on
research on teaching, its concept, conduct, power, and use continued throughout his
lifetime. He was a humble man: one who never placed himself in front of the pack,
and would converse with anyone—young or older academics, school people, poli-
ticians—with respect and grace. His knowledge of the field was simply remarkable.
He was, indeed, the Father of Research on Teaching, and will be sorely missed.”
Virginia Richardson
Professor of Education Emerita, University of Michigan
“Nate was a mentor and safe harbor during my graduate student days at Stanford
(1968-1970) and then a colleague and good friend throughout the remainder of his
career. Many memories come flooding back, but two stand out as a graduate student
and are still vi vid. The f irst memory is that of a big f ight Nate and I got into at a
meeting of the Psychological Studies in Education faculty. He was a chaired profes-
sor; I w as a graduate student representati ve. The f ight was whether psychological
principles were general or subject-matter specif ic. Nate held the former vie w and
I held the latter. We got into a real match... so much so that Lee Cronbach caught
up with me after the meeting saying that it w as apparent that senior faculty as well
as graduate students could mak e fools of themselv es! The “debate” w as quickly
forgotten and had no bearing on Nate as a mentor and friend.
x Tribute
The second memory is of Nate at home. Nate and Maggie often invited graduate
students over for wine, cheese, and con versation. On one such occasion I learned
that Nate w as on volume Q of the Enc yclopedia Britannica. Nate w as reading the
encyclopedia from A to Z, no doubt editing as he went along!
Two memories of Nate stand out as a colleague. The f irst: I had written a paper
to present at a conference and ask ed Nate to read it. He did, editing copiously as
was his want. He allowed as how it was a good paper but wasn’t ready for publica-
tion. I told him I didn’t plan to publish the paper. He told me that he never wrote a
paper he didn’ t intend to publish and that stuck with me throughout my career ...
inhibiting some writing, but, alas, not enough! The second: While I was dean at the
Stanford University School of Education (1995-2000), a retired Nate came to talk
to me—Nate w as working for me, no longer vice v ersa! He w as concerned about
finding funding for his ne xt project... a book inte grating research on teaching and
research on instruction. I suggested he apply for a small grant from the Spencer
Foundation. He did so and recei ved funding. He came to my of fice to report the
grant with a smile that made the Cheshire cat look as if it were pouting. And best
of all for Nate, his receiving this grant meant he was still in close competition with
his brother who, like Nate, was famous in his own field. As fate would have it, our
paths crossed in mysterious ways. Nate held the Margaret Jacks chair in Education;
I now hold that chair... and it feels good that Nate sat in it as well. ”
Richard J. Shavelson
Margaret Jacks Professor of Education, Stanford University
“Good philosophical training culti vates a sk eptical e ye, and good philosophical
training in education often uses educational research to train one’ s skeptical eye.
When I f irst began to read Nate Gage, I presumed his w ork would be grist of the
mill for my ne wly culti vated sk epticism. Instead, something quite dif ferent hap-
pened. I realized that his work was “really good stuff,” and if I was going to critique
it I w ould have to w ork very hard. Thus be gan nearly three decades of back-and-
forth exchanges between us that I kno w were f ar more benef icial to me than the y
were for Nate.”
Gary D. Fenstermacher
Professor of Education Emeritus, University of Michigan
Preface
The only Theory that can be proposed and ever will be proposed that absolutely will
remain inviolate for decades, certainly centuries, is a Theory that is not testable. All
Theories are wrong. One doesn’ t ask about Theories, can I sho w that the y are
wrong or can I sho w that the y are right, b ut rather one asks, ho w much of the
empirical realm can it handle and ho w must it be modif ied and changed as it
matures? (Festinger, 1999, p. 383)
If the history of science pro ves anything, it is that all Theories pro ve eventually
to be wrong (even if “wrong” only means incomplete or standing in need of elabo-
ration). (Phillips, in Phillips & Burb ules, 2000, p. 31)
A word about gender: For millennia, all people, including females, were referred
to as “he.” I recognize that times have changed by referring to all teachers as “she.”
Male teachers should accept the error as a compensation for the earlier one.
xi
Acknowledgments
My first three years of work on this book were supported by a small research grant
from The Spencer Foundation, which I wholeheartedly thank. For the whole work,
the data presented, the statements made, and the vie ws e xpressed are solely my
responsibility. I am, of course, thankful to the scholars and research w orkers on
whose work I have drawn, as noted in the te xt and list of References. W ithout the
products of their w ork, especially those of the last half-century , when research on
teaching began to flourish, this w ork would have been impossible.
Professor S. Alan Cohen of the Uni versity of San Francisco generously made
available to me various publications and other materials that greatly f acilitated my
becoming informed on the concept of instructional alignment. Se veral Stanford
colleagues answered my queries related to their specialties: Professor Denis C.
Phillips, on philosophy of science; Professor Ingram Olkin, on meta-analysis;
Professor Deck er W alker, on instructional design. The late Professor K enneth
Sirotnik of the Uni versity of Washington was altogether cooperative in giving me
information about “A Study of Schools,” the tour de force led by John Goodlad.
Janet Rutherford, my superb administrati ve assistant, saved me from months of
wandering in the stacks of the Stanford libraries, solved problems with my compu-
ter, and provided much highly intelligent general helpfulness. Barbara Celone and
Kelly Roll, of Stanford’ s Cubberley Education Library , and Mary-Louise Munill,
of the Interlibrary-Borro wing Services of the Stanford Libraries, obtained man y
books and articles and, in doing so, occasionally performed seeming miracles.
Dean Richard Shavelson and, later, Dean Deborah Stipek, of Stanford’ s School
of Education, helped me by acting on their f aith that, although I w as retired, I was
making appropriate use of a Stanford Uni versity office.
Professors David C. Berliner of Arizona State Uni versity, Barak Rosenshine of
the University of Illinois, and Raymond L. Debus of the University of Sydney, have
been friends of the kind that e very author needs. I am immensely grateful for their
long-term friendship, encouragement, and criticism. The editorial w ork of Cynthia
Haven saved me from awkwardnesses and obscurities.
Finally, the lo ve and support of my late wife, Mar garet, and our children –
Elizabeth, Tom, Sarah, and Anne – ha ve kept me steady over the years.
xiii
Contents
1 An Agenda ................................................................................................. 1
Choices Among Alternative ....................................................................... 2
A Theory of Teaching Rather than Instruction .................................... 2
A Theory of Teaching That is Both Descriptive and Prescriptive ....... 3
A Conception of Teaching for Both Cognitive
and Affective Objectives of Education ................................................ 4
A Broadly Valid, Rather than Specif cally Valid, Theory .................... 4
A Theory of Teaching Actions and Teacher Characteristics................ 6
A Theory of Classroom Teaching Rather Than Any
of the Challenges to Classroom Teaching ............................................ 6
An Overview of Chapters 2–9 ................................................................... 7
Chapter 2 .............................................................................................. 7
Chapter 3 .............................................................................................. 7
Chapter 4 .............................................................................................. 8
Chapter 5 .............................................................................................. 8
Chapter 6 .............................................................................................. 9
Chapter 7 .............................................................................................. 9
Chapter 8 .............................................................................................. 9
Chapter 9 .............................................................................................. 10
xv
xvi Contents
After everything else has been done and pro vided – the mone y raised; the schools
erected; the curricula de veloped; the administrators, supervisors, and teachers
trained; the parents and other citizens consulted – we come to teaching, where all
of it makes contact with students, and the teacher influences students’ kno wledge,
understanding, appreciations, and attitudes in what we hope will be desirable ways.
Teaching is well-nigh the point of the whole educational enterprise and establish-
ment aimed at producing student learning.
Teaching is also important in terms of a kind of ethical imperative. Nations require
that their young people ha ve frequent contact, for long periods, with adults called
teachers. When such a relationship is legally imposed on young people, it seems only
fair that society should do whatever it can to make that relationship a beneficial one.
The literature of the behavioral and social sciences is full of conceptions and research
on learning and memory. Teaching is comparatively a stepchild, neglected by those who
have built a formidable body of conceptions of learning and memory. The uses of learning
conceptions for teaching constitute a tool-kit that has been left to rust. It is as if the theo-
retical work of, say , Faraday, had ne ver given birth to the tremendous applications of
electrical energy so that when Einstein turned on his lamp, he could read his notes. This
book seeks to give teaching the kind of attention that learning and memory have received.
Teaching is where learning and memory conceptions should pay of f.
Finally, teaching is worth studying simply because of the intrinsic interest of the
phenomena to which teaching gi ves rise. Ev en if such research had no practical
value, it would be worthwhile for the same reasons that astronomy and archaeology
are worthwhile. As part of our universe and our human condition, teaching cries out
to be studied and understood.
Conceptions are both the guide and the outcome of research, including research
on teaching. Research is the process of seeking relationships between v ariables.
That simple def inition applies to an y science, whether it is in the natural or the
behavioral sciences. To explain, we search for logical relationships; e.g., if time is
indispensable for learning, lack of time prevents learning. To predict, we search for
temporal relationships; e.g., kno wing a teacher’s high school grade-point a verage,
we can predict with better than chance accuracy, her grade-point average as a college
freshman. To control or improve, we search for causal relationships; e.g., kno wing
that teachers who receive training in question-asking do better than similar teachers
who do not receive such training, we can use that kno wledge to bring about better
teaching. Explanation, prediction, and control, or one or more of these, are the
purposes of all scientific research, including research on teaching.
And what is teaching? W e can def ine it as one person’ s influence aimed at
improving the learning of other persons. Usually, we think of teaching as occurring
in face-to-face interaction between the teacher and the learner, but it can also occur
when a teacher creates influential e vents, in which he or she does not participate.
In that w ay, the authors of books and the de velopers of computer programs may
also be considered teachers. But we will restrict our concern to teaching that occurs
while a teacher is in the presence of students.
So research on teaching may be def ined as the search for relationships between
variables where at least one of the variables is a behavior, a thought, or a character-
istic of teachers. The teacher v ariable may be an independent v ariable, e.g., a w ay
of teaching; or a dependent v ariable, e.g., the teacher’ s response to advice; or an
intervening v ariable; e.g., a teacher’ s thoughts during a student’ s response to a
question, a classroom situation, or some other kind of v ariable. But at least one
teacher variable must be involved if the research is to be research on teaching.
The study of teaching as a concern of the beha vioral and social sciences has
matured from its philosophical beginnings in antiquity to its present robust youth at
the recent turn of the millennium. It is still young, having begun to thrive only dur-
ing the 1950s. But it is now flourishing with an abundance of scholarly publications
by a large number of active researchers on teaching. The result o ver the centuries,
especially the last half-century , has been an accumulation of ideas, concepts, dis-
tinctions, insights, empirical findings, and conceptual formulations that seem ready
for an attempt at a theory of teaching. Notice the indef inite article: “A.” It signifies
that mine is just one of an indef inite number of concei vable theories. The v arious
models of teaching described by Jo yce, Weil, and Calhoun (2000) could be theo-
rized, i.e., explained in terms of “covering laws,” of the kind described in Chap. 8.
Why do the authors of the models consider them to be ef fective, in what ways?
This chapter sketches the development and scope of the conceptions of teaching
to be presented. After discussing the choices I ha ve made among v arious possible
emphases and directions, I will summarize each chapter to provide a brief introduc-
tion to the rest of the book.
The theory to be proposed in this book reflects choices made in the early stages of
its development.
The differences between the terms teaching and instruction reside mostly in their
connotative meanings. But those dif ferences are clear enough to be rele vant to the
Choices Among Alternative 3
scope of this monograph. “T eaching” is the term used more in formal educational
settings, namely, in elementary schools, secondary schools, colle ges, and graduate
schools. “Instruction” is used more in sharply focused out-of-school training in
business, industry, and the armed forces.
One way to distinguish the tw o terms w as offered by R. M. Gagné and Briggs
(1979), leaders in the field known as instructional design :
Why do we speak of “instruction,” rather than “teaching”? It is because we wish to
describe all of the e vents which may ha ve a direct ef fect on the learning of a human
being, not just those set in motion by an indi vidual who is a teacher . Instruction may
include events that are generated by a page of print, by a picture, by a tele vision pro-
gram, or by a combination of physical objects, among other things. Or… the learners
may be able to manage instructional e vents themselves. Teaching, then, may be con-
sidered as only one form of instruction, albeit a signally important one (p. 3).
But research on teaching puts teaching, rather than the more general “instruction,” at
the center because it is the teacher who arranges for the students’ interaction with all the
media mentioned by Gagné, et al. T ypically, the teacher o versees the students in their
reading, interaction with computer programs, viewing of films and television, as well as
the recitations, discussions, lectures, explanations, and tutoring that occur in schools.
Typically, the teacher directs all aspects of teaching, except for the content of
the curriculum, which is usually prescribed for the teacher in v arying degrees.
The manner, style, and mode of teaching typically f all under the almost com-
plete control of the teacher , especially the use of teaching materials other than
the textbook, such as slides, audio tapes, mo vies, videotapes, digital video dis-
plays (DVDs), and computers. Teachers also control the use and arrangement of
out-of-school learning experiences, such as excursions and visits to museums.
Instructors have less autonomy; the y are more lik ely to follo w the curriculum
and materials appro ved by the or ganization that emplo ys them. T eachers are for -
mally trained in teacher education programs in colle ges or graduate schools.
Instructors are usually trained in the business, industrial, or military organization in
which they will do their work.
In all of these w ays, teaching differs from instruction, not in an y formal, legal-
ized, tightly regulated way, but rather in the connotati ve meanings of the terms as
they have come to be used in the United States since at least the mid-nineteenth
century when public schools became prevalent.
The theory will serv e both the descripti ve and prescriptive aspects of theory. That
is, it will describe how teaching does occur and also prescribe how it should occur
to optimize student achievement.
The idea that there are tw o kinds of theory , descripti ve and prescripti ve, is
widely accepted (see, for example, Bruner, 1966; Reigeluth, 1999, p. 2). Descriptive
theory describes a process as it does go on. Prescripti ve theory describes ho w the
process should go on if it is to be optimized according to some v alues.
4 1 An Agenda
But the distinction blurs when we realize that the same descripti ve theory – its
concepts and their relationships – can serv e both descripti ve and prescripti ve pur -
poses. That is, when we find that the relationship of variable x to variable y affects an
outcome z (a descripti ve theory), that relationship can be used to optimize z ( a pre-
scriptive theory). The optimization requires that we seek certain v alues of x and y .
For example, we can describe ho w teachers e xplain the Pythagorean Theorem.
But if we e valuate the ef fectiveness of the e xplanation in terms of student under -
standing, we can use the e xplanation-understanding relationship to prescribe ho w
the explanation should be made.
The theory of teaching will focus on both the cogniti ve and the affective objectives of
education. Of course, a good deal of teaching, especially in elementary schools, is
concerned with the emotional and social development of students as well as with their
cognitive development (see R. B. Smith, 1987). Still, teachers’ concern with emotional
development typically may tend to decrease gradually from the 1st to the 12th grades.
The theory will apply to many varieties of teaching and have broad validity. It will
formulate a set of widely v alid concepts or v ariables to describe teaching and the
widely occurring relationships between those concepts or variables. The breadth of
the theory signifies its attempt to describe and explain teaching’s many dimensions:
the teaching of man y kinds of subject matter at man y levels of student maturity ,
toward man y sets of cognitive educational objectives, to students of an y gender,
social class, or ethnicity, in man y school or classroom settings, by many kinds of
teachers, in many cultures. B. O. Smith (1963) expressed an even bolder aspiration
toward a universally valid theory of teaching:
Our most general notion is that teaching is everywhere the same, that it is a natural
social phenomenon and is fundamentally the same from one culture to another and
from one time to another in the same culture. Teaching is a system of action involving
an agent, a situation, and an end-in-view, and two sets of factors in the situation: one
set over which the agent has no control (for e xample, size of classroom and physical
characteristics of pupils) and one set which the agent can modify with respect to the
end-in-view (for example, assignments and ways of asking questions) (p. 4).
Any attempt at universality in a conception of teaching runs into the great variety
of subject matters taught. For example, a book on subject-specific teaching (Brophy,
2001) included 14 chapters, each by a specialist on teaching methods and activities
Choices Among Alternative 5
for a specific subject: beginning reading, content area reading and literature, writing,
mathematics of number , school geometry, biological literac y, physics, representa-
tions, earth science, history , physical geography , cultural geography , citizenship,
and economics. W ithin each of these subjects, there are presumably optimal
instructional methods specific to particular kinds of content. W e can make further
breakdowns for specif ic kinds of students in terms of their cultural backgrounds,
levels of cognitive capability, cultures, communities, and so on.
Against the assumption underlying the Brophy-edited v olume is the vie w of
R. M. Gagné (1976) : “Learning is not unique to subject matter . There is no sound
rational basis for such entities as ‘mathematics learning, ’ ‘science learning,’ ‘lan-
guage learning,’ or ‘history learning,’ except as divisions of time” (p. 30).
Gage (1979) proposed that the generality-specificity issue be resolved by creat-
ing a hierarchy of levels of generality shown in Table 1.1.
The theory to be proposed takes the highly general tack. Although much of this
book will seem to have been aimed at only elementary and secondary school teach-
ing, it may also apply to colle ge teaching, as w as implied when Bellack (1976)
noted that his formulation of the process of teaching had also been observ ed at the
college level (see pp. 5–31). As Sirotnik (1983) observed, we can never understand
teaching if we need a separate theory to e xplain each of the myriad forms that
teaching can tak e in types of subject matters taught, of students, of community
contexts, and of resources available.
The term “teacher actions” refers to what teachers do: explain, ask questions, etc.
The term “teacher characteristics” refers to what teachers are: recently trained,
experienced, etc.
The term “teaching effectiveness” implies that the teacher’s actions, such as her
ways of explaining and questioning, account for her ef fects on students. The term
“teacher effectiveness” implies that it is her characteristics and personality traits,
such as her intelligence, kno wledge, and emotional stability , that account for the
teacher’s effects on student achievement.
Much early research, re viewed by Getzels and Jackson (1963), sho wed that
teacher-characteristic variables account for little of the variance in student achieve-
ment. More recent studies, however, reverse that trend. For example, Ehrenberg and
Brewer (1995) found that teachers’ v erbal aptitudes boosted student achie vement
gains. Monk (1994) found that secondary school teachers’ preparation in mathe-
matics and science raised student gains in mathematics and science. Strauss and
Sawyer (1986) sho wed that the cogniti ve abilities of teachers not only af fected
student achievement but also lowered student dropout rates.
The proposed theory will assume that the teachers’ verbal aptitudes, preparation
in the subject matter, and cognitive abilities affect their decisions and behavior – all
of which influence student achievement substantially. Accordingly, the theory will
address both actions in “teaching” and characteristics of the “teacher .”
Classroom teaching has long been decried and challenged. John De wey’s progres-
sive education w as an early challenger . As Cuban (1992) sho wed, it ne ver took
hold.
B. F. Skinner’s (1968) programmed – and, later, computer-assisted – instruction
has been greatly strengthened by the ongoing computer re volution, b ut it still is
used by only a minority of teachers (H. Beck er, 2000). Cuban (1986, 2001) has
continued to f ind relati vely little use of computers in classrooms. In a possible
exception to this trend, H. Becker reported relatively abundant use of computers by
the students of teachers who had at least five computers in the classroom, had some
competence with computers, and were well abo ve average in the strength of their
belief in a constructivist (described in Chap. 5) teaching philosophy. So only under
special conditions of teacher preparation do classrooms appear to be dif ferent than
they have been for many decades.
Fred Keller’s (1968) “personalized system of instruction” in the 1970s, Benjamin
Bloom’s (1968) “mastery approach” in the 1970s, Ann Bro wn’s (1989, 1996) and
others’ “reciprocal teaching” in the 1980s, and Robert Slavin’s (1990) “cooperative
learning” in the 1990s, ha ve not, in the absence of e vidence to the contrary , been
An Overview of Chapters 2–9 7
adopted by the vast majority of 3.5 million U.S. elementary and secondary school
teachers (National Center for Educational Statistics, 2000), to say nothing of teach-
ers abroad.
The ubiquity and tenacious survi val of con ventional-direct-recitation (CDR)
teaching (described in Chap. 5) is the main reason for my decision to focus on it to
develop a conception. (F or a brief summary of the early research on the survi val
power of conventional-direct-recitation teaching, see Sirotnik 1983.)
Observational studies in the United States (for e xample, Bellack, Kliebard,
Hyman, & Smith, 1966; Hoetker & Ahlbrand, 1969; Mehan, 1979; Goodlad, 1984)
have agreed in showing that, when they examine the observational evidence about
what goes on in classrooms, con ventional-direct-recitation (CDR) teaching pre-
vails. In the recitation cycle, (a) the teacher “structures” the subject of the discus-
sion, (b) then asks a question, (c) then either calls on a volunteer or selects a student
to respond, and (d) f inally reacts to the student’ s response. Although these c ycles
are repeated for much of a class period, the teacher may provide time for individual
students to work alone or in a small group on an assigned task.
The following sections briefly describe the subsequent chapters. The y orient the
reader to the work as a whole and sketch the context into which I place the elements
of the argument.
Chapter 2
I first describe the need in terms of the man y affirmations from philosophers and
behavioral scientists o ver the years. In the process, I consider whether scientif ic
research requires a prior theory – a theory spelled out before any data are collected.
The issue is resolved with ideas from Conjectures and Refutations by the philoso-
pher of science Karl Popper (1963) .
Chapter 3
This section – an updating of Gage (1996) – is relati vely technical and not indis-
pensable to a comprehension of the book as a whole. It deals with the ne gative
responses to the possibility-of-theory question. Among others, two behavioral scientists
8 1 An Agenda
Chapter 4
The proposed paradigm – or model of a scientif ic field – comprises six basic cate-
gories of related concepts that underlie the proposed theory. Because these concepts
can tak e forms that v ary qualitati vely, quantitati vely, or both, the y will also be
called variables. I describe and illustrate the v ariables in terms of ho w they have
entered into analytical (logical) and empirical studies of teaching.
The chapter presents these concepts in the historical order in which the cate go-
ries were developed. But they are arranged spatially in a “pedagogical” order that
makes sense for all amounts of teaching – whether the y last a fe w minutes or a
school term. In that order , some cate gories of concepts, logically at least, must
precede others
The categories of concepts can be di vided into two sets: (a) those that are logi-
cally prior to a teacher’s teaching, i.e., her presentation of the process-and-content
of teaching, and (b) those that logically occur after her teaching.
Chapter 5
This chapter discusses the thoughts and beha viors of teachers as the y seek to
foster their students’ achie vement of the objecti ves of the teaching. Man y
models of teaching ha ve attracted some attention, b ut only one seems to ha ve
won the allegiance of the vast majority of teachers in elementary and second-
ary schools. The chapter describes that model and the e vidence of its wide
usage – not only recently , but in the whole twentieth century; not only in the
United States, b ut in other countries; and not only in a fe w subjects, b ut in
many. The chapter also e xamines the reasons for the persistence and pre va-
lence of this model.
An Overview of Chapters 2–9 9
Chapter 6
This chapter presents a concept – instructional alignment – that has pro ven useful
in a v ariety of conte xts in which the content of teaching has played a part. These
contexts consist largely of the roles content plays in teaching and also in assessing
achievement. This discussion leads to an e xamination of the issue of teaching-to-
the-test content, as in Popham’ s (1993) “measurement-dri ven-instruction,” versus
testing-to-the-content-taught. The issue is resolved in terms of making the curricu-
lum dominate both teaching and testing.
Chapter 7
Cognitive capabilities consist of (a) the general cogniti ve ability (IQ) of students,
(b) their multiple intelligences, and (c) their prior kno wledge of the content being
taught. Students in an y class dif fer in their cogniti ve capabilities. The dif ferences
among students raise the problems of maximizing teaching’ s appropriateness to
those differences. The chapter e xamines ways in which teachers can achie ve that
appropriateness. At its end, the chapter examines the behavioral and cognitive ways
of influencing student motivation.
Chapter 8
The chapter be gins with a presentation of the role of po verty in creating much of
the problem of classroom management. The problem is much greater in schools and
classrooms that serv e students from impo verished f amilies and neighborhoods.
Classroom management is aimed at the proper use of classroom time: maximizing
instructional time and minimizing counterproductive time. The model of classroom
learning developed by Carroll (1963) lends itself to focusing on time as a basis for
defining student aptitude, opportunity to learn, and perse verance in terms of time.
Students’ thought processes are important aspects of instructional time because
they provide a criterion of effectiveness in use of time. The y are regarded as inter-
vening variables, occurring between teaching and achievement.
Productive and counterproducti ve use of time can be related to classroom
management practices. Research has identif ied such practices in elementary and
secondary schools.
10 1 An Agenda
Chapter 9
The chapter be gins with the ideas of the philosopher of science Hempel (1965)
concerning ho w a conception can consist of sub-conceptions. I illustrate sub-
conceptions with an analogy: four sub-conceptions serving as an e xplanation of an
automobile’s motion.
Sub-Conceptionsof Process
Sub-Conceptionsof Content
He also showed that the particle-physics consistencies were similar to other physi-
cal science consistencies (e.g., in atomic weights, constants in quantum mechanics)
and that the beha vioral science consistencies were similar to other behavioral sci-
ence consistencies (e.g., in gender dif ferences, effectiveness of methods of teaching
writing, the validity of personnel selection tests).
On consistency of results, then, the widespread ne gative view of the behavioral
sciences is questionable. The beha vioral-science main ef fects that Hedges e xam-
ined were about as consistent as the results found in one branch of physics. Even if
particle physics is weaker than most physical sciences in its consistencies, the f act
that any behavioral science consistencies can come close to those of an y respected
physical science should alleviate despair.
Table 2.1 Frequency of smoking in lung cancer patients and matched controls
Patients with lung cancer Matched patients with other
Smokingstatus (N = 518) diseases (N = 518)
Smokers 96% 89%
Nonsmokers 4% 11%
Total 100% 100%
From Cancer Epidemiology: Methods of Study (p. 78), by Lilienthal et al. (1967). Adapted with
permission.
1,900 men randomly assigned to the group that recei ved propranolol, 7% had died
after 30 months, while of the 1,900 in the group that recei ved a placebo, 9.5% had
died. The difference of 2.5% between the two percentages was taken very seriously
as support for underlying theory and as a basis for medical practice.
In another experiment (Lipid Research Clinics Program, 1984), 3,806 men were
assigned at random to a cholesterol lo wering drug or to a placebo. As sho wn in
Table 2.3, it w as found, after a nine-year follo w-up, that 8.1% of the 1,906 men
receiving the cholesterol-lowering drug had had a heart attack, as against 9.8% of
the 1,900 who took the placebo, for a dif ference of 1.7%. An article in Science
stated that these results w ould “affect profoundly the practice of medicine in this
country” (Kolata, 1984, p. 380).
A retrospecti ve, hence non-e xperimental, study (Goldstein, Andre ws, Hall,
& Moss, 1992) of the ef fects of aspirin on heart attacks w as done with patients at
15 heart research centers. It found, as shown in Table 2.4, that of those who had not
16 2 The Desirability and Possibility of a Theory of Teaching
Table 2.4 Incidence of fatalities from heart attacks in aspirin- and nonaspirin-using patients
Status after 2 years Aspirin users ( N = 751) Aspirin nonusers ( N = 185)
Dead 1.6% 5.4%
Alive 98.4% 94.6%
Total 100.0% 100.0%
Adapted from “Reduction in Long-Term Cardiac Deaths with Aspirin after a Coronary Event,” by
R. E. Goldstein et al. (1992). Adapted with permission.
been taking a small daily dose of common aspirin (N = 185), 5.4% had a fatal heart
attack. Of those ( N = 752) who had been taking aspirin, only 1.6% had a f atal
heart attack. Thus the no-aspirin patients were 3.4 times (5.4/1.6) more lik ely to
have a deadly heart attack than those who had tak en aspirin. (Medical researchers
often determine the dif ference between the control-group incidence [%cl and the
treatment-group incidence [~°el as a percentage of %c; thus: [%C–%e]/%C. In this
aspirin study, that procedure yielded a 70% mortality reduction associated with
taking the aspirin. But, of course, this procedure can yield hard-to-interpret results
when %c is small; see W eissler, Miller , & Boudoulas, (1989). Lipse y and
Wilson (1993) e xamined the results of 15 meta-analyses of medical-treatment
effects on mortality and other medical and psychological outcomes. They concluded
that in assessing meta-analytic estimates of the ef fects of psychological, educa-
tional, and behavioral treatment, we cannot arbitrarily dismiss statistically modest
values (e ven 0.10 or 0.20 SDs) as ob viously tri vial ... [C]omparable numerical
values are judged to represent benef its in the medical domain, e ven when similar
outcome variables are at issue. (p. 1199) It might be ar gued that the medical main
effects are taken seriously because the dependent variables are extremely important,
often matters of life and death. But man y behavioral-science dependent v aria-
bles – school achievement, dropout rates, mental health, recidi vism, occupational
adjustment, personal relationships, and group ef fectiveness – are also clearly
important. In an y case, apart from the practical importance of the dependent
variables, the medical examples suggest that small main effects can have scientific
significance – in both medical and beha vioral science. The implication is that the
results of present-day beha vioral science research, in the form of main ef fects,
provide a good basis for beha vioral-science theory and practice. The medical
experiments and surv eys yielded “small” main ef fects because the treatments
worked for some patients but not for others. Why? Presumably because these inde-
pendent variables interacted with other v ariables, such as patients’ physiological
characteristics. Such interactions are not re garded as precluding the possibility of
medical science. The present ar gument applies the same reasoning to uphold the
possibility of behavioral science.
Recognizing interaction effects, medical practitioners do not act unthinkingly on
a main effect; they use judgment, based on e verything else they know about medi-
cine and the patient, including those patient characteristics that might interact with
a treatment to produce undesirable ef fects (see, e.g., Bro wn, Viscoli, & Horwitz,
1992). Similarly, applications of behavioral science main effects in teaching, counseling,
Evaluating the Magnitude of Main Effects 17
generalizability is more per suasive when the replications meta-analyzed are more
heterogeneous in the types of persons, measures, and conte xts represented. Thus,
the same results obtained in 20 highly similar studies carry less weight for general-
izability than such same results in studies whose subjects vary in, for e xample, eth-
nicity and educational level, whose measures come from both tests and observations,
and whose contexts extend from the laboratory to real-life situations.
In mentioning Thomas’s opposition to theory, I find his argument further weakened
when we realize that “theory” is synon ymous with “explanation.” For example, one
collection of papers on theory by philosophers of science is titled Theories of
Explanation (Pitt, 1988). Gi ving up the search for a theory of teaching is equi valent
to giving up the search for explanations of educational phenomena. Although Thomas
(2007) is willing to accept and respect theory in the natural sciences, his position
against theory for phenomena in education, such as teaching, means that he is willing
to give up the search for e xplanations of phenomena found in teaching. T o provide
explanations of teaching – explanations of why and how it works and why some kinds
of teaching work better than others – is the purpose of this book.
In the natural sciences, the desirability of theory has gone unquestioned for
centuries in the writings of philosophers and scientists. Scientists re gard v alid
theory as the ultimate goal of scientif ic research. Among the achie vements of
physical scientists ha ve been such triumphs as the theory of motion, electromag-
netic theory, relativity theory, quantum theory, and the theory of the chemical bond.
The biological sciences point with pride to Darwin’s theory of evolution, Pasteur’s
germ theory of disease, Mendel’s genetics, the Watson-Crick double-helix structure
of DNA, and much more.
Until recently, the same unanimity about the v alue of theory pre vailed in the
social and beha vioral sciences, e ven though their theoretical achie vements were
less glorious or well-established. In psychology , some e xamples are the general
factor (g) theory of intelligence, attribution theory, classical and operant condition-
ing theory, construct theory, and the theory of cognitive dissonance. Major volumes
(e.g., Koch, 1959–1963) ha ve brought together some of psychology’ s attempts at
theory. In sociology, we find social mobility theory, the theory of group structure,
and much more, as well as v olumes devoted to the de velopment of theory (e.g.,
Berger & Zelditch, 1993; Cohen, 1989; Dubin, 1969; Glaser & Strauss, 1967).
Thus, for a long time, to question whether v alid theory was desirable was nearly
unthinkable. Until the last few decades, natural and social scientists and philosophers
regarded valid theory as the pinnacle of scholarly and scientif ic achievement.
The general and centuries-old con viction among scientists and scholars agreed
with the aphorism, “There is nothing so practical as a good theory” (K urt Lewin,
quoted in Marrow, 1969, p. viii). But Le win’s statement calls for the specif ication
of the practical values that theory serv es. For example, the theories of astronomy
– however valid, enlightening, and exquisite as explanations of the location, motion,
clustering, and composition of heavenly bodies have value only for the guidance of
astronomers engaged in further searches for understanding. Except for use in na vi-
gation and meteorology, astronomical theory has little or no practical value, in the
sense of being useful in the e veryday affairs of persons who are not astronomers.
Evaluating the Magnitude of Main Effects 19
In other natural sciences, theory has indeed had practical value, that is, has served as
a basis for the development of technology that meets human needs. T ransistors, devel-
oped out of solid-state theory, made possible computers, space exploration, and medical
tools. Lasers, based on radiation theory, made possible valuable innovations in medical
diagnosis and treatment. Magnetic resonance induction theory made possible more
detailed e xamination of the human body’ s interior. The theory that portrays DN A’s
double-helix structure made possible the mapping of the human genome and a growing
host of practical applications in medicine, agriculture, genealogy, and criminology.
Despite this esteem of theory in science, the philosophy of science, in the manner
of all philosophy , consists of “a record of criticism and countercriticism; through
such a dialectic philosophers come closer to whate ver truth is to be found in their
subject matter” (Gewirth, 1991, p. 1). Often, however, those who might be expected
to engage themselv es with the philosophy of science pay little attention to it. As
Scriven (1968) noted,
Curiously enough... man y scientists reject the philosophy of science as irrele vant to their
own activities although the y constantly talk it and teach it and illustrate its rele vance in
their own w ork, sometimes under the title ‘methodology’ and sometimes just as advice
without a label. (p. 84)
would have done any of the things which in fact led, before a generation had passed, to our
giant and indispensable electrical industry....
Thus far, we have argued the case for theory of teaching. But what is the case for a
theory of teaching done by human beings? Since at least the 1960s, teaching by
nonhumans, i.e., by programmed booklets, machines, and computers, has been
developed and promulgated. At first, “programmed instruction,” developed by B. F.
Skinner (1957) and brought together in a lar ge v olume of writings edited by
Lumsdaine and Glaser (1960) caused concern that “a specter is haunting research
Conceptions of Theory 21
on teaching the specter of programmed instruction” (Gage & Unruh, 1967). That
vision was expressed again by Adams (1971):
The suggestion has been made else where that classroom research, in the f ace of the
“specter” of automated education, is the ultimate gesture in futility. After all, what virtue can
inhere in researching a phenomenon that tomorro w will be as dead as a dodo? (p. 101)
Writing a theory of teaching early in the twenty-f irst century might have the same
fate as that of a theory of medicine written in the years (about the 1850s) before
Pasteur’s germ theory of disease revolutionized medicine. Adams offered a possible
consolation: Even if human teaching disappeared, we should “redouble our ef forts
– not indeed in order to solv e pedagogical problems, but so that a quaint form of
twentieth century ritual can be preserv ed for posterity’s interest, edif ication, and
amusement (p. 101).”
The present effort rests on a dif ferent vision – that nonhuman teaching will not
replace human teaching. Rather , it has been a gradual de velopment characterized
by teachers’ learning ho w to use computers and their programs in some what the
same way in which they learned to use textbooks, tests, chalkboards, libraries, labo-
ratories, w orkbooks, slides, f ilms, portfolios, and, more recently , digital video
displays (D VDs). Despite all these additions to the teacher’ s tools, the human
teacher has retained her central role in education. Cuban (1993) convincingly docu-
mented the w ays in which all these inno vations, including computers, could be
summed up with a headline: “Computers Meet Classroom: Classroom W ins.”
The present effort rests on a dif ferent vision – that nonhuman teaching will not
replace human teaching. Although nonhuman teaching has become more prevalent
since the 1960s, its gains have not replaced teachers (Cuban, 2001). Its gro wth has
not had the pace of a re volution. As Cuban put it, after a thorough in vestigation of
many aspects of the issue, “When it comes to higher teacher and student productivity
and a transformation of teaching and learning, ho wever, there is little ambiguity .
Both must be tagged as failures. [italics added] Computers have been oversold and
underused, at least for now” (p. 178).
Conceptions of Theory
There are many usages of the term “theory,” and they vary widely. Almost all con-
ceivable implicit def initions have appeared in one place or another at one time or
another. Chambers (1992, pp. 7–27) identif ied f ifteen usages, which he put into
nine clusters: (1) Theory as contrasted with f act; (2) Theory as contrasted with
practice; (3) Theory as e volving e xplanation; (4) Practical theory that guides a
profession or art; (5) Theory as hypothesis; (6) Theory as ontological or observ a-
tional presupposition; (7) Normati ve theory , such as doctrine or dogma; (8)
Empiricist theory; (9) Scientific theory.
Of these, only the last tw o – empiricist theory and scientif ic theory – are considered
here. An empiricist theory , according to Chambers (1992), is one in which generaliza-
tions about observable variables are related to one another in w ays that accord with
22 2 The Desirability and Possibility of a Theory of Teaching
empirical observations. A scientif ic theory, Chambers (1992) wrote, is one that relates
abstract (e.g., mathematically or logically manipulable, but not observable) concepts and
their variables in logical or rational ways that accord with empirical observations.
Chambers obtained his conception of science from the sociologists W iller and
Willer (1973), who referred to two types of thought – theoretical and observational
– as shown in Fig. 2.1.
The observational level deals only with empirical categories, and the theoretical
level deals only with abstract concepts. Connections on only the observational level
are empirical connections, those on only the theoretical le vel are rational connec-
tions, and connections between the empirical and abstract le vels are abstractive .
Thus the W illers (and Chambers) held that science and empiricism are both
concerned with observ ed empirical e vents, b ut “The logical form of science is
much more complex” (Willer & Willer, 1973, p. 15).
Scientific knowledge, then, consists not only of successful rational connections
between concepts, not only of successful observ ational connections, b ut also of
abstractive connections, which are rational connections that correspond to observa-
tional connections.
The Willer-Chambers conception of theory may ha ve stemmed from assump-
tions that only the theories of the physical sciences are genuine theories and that
only mathematically expressed theories were to be considered theories. Chambers
used as examples only theories from the physical sciences: Copernicus’s classical
mechanics, Kepler’s laws of planetary motion, Galileo’s laws of motion, Lavoisier’s
role of gases in chemical reactions, Crick’ s and W atson’s structure of the DN A
molecule, and Wegener’s continental drift. Chambers apparently considered claims
to theory outside the physical sciences to represent mere pretension.
This conception of theory is not held by all scientists and philosophers of
science. Thus the philosopher of science Nagel (1979) wrote that
The requirements for being a genuine science tacitly assumed in most of the challenges [to
the scientific status of the social sciences] lead to the unenlightening result that apparently
none but a few branches of physical inquiry merit the honorif ic designation. (p. 449)
Theoretical
Observational
Empiricism Science
Fig. 2.1 Difference in logical form between empirical and scientif ic knowledge (Source: Willer
& Willer, 1973, p. 19).
Must Scientific Research Be Theory-Driven? 23
the generalizations of social inquiry do not appear to differ radically from generalizations currently
advanced in domains usually re garded as unquestionably respectable subdi visions of natural sci-
ence – for example, in the study of turbulence phenomena and in embryology. (p. 449)
In any case, our present goal is to set forth a theory of teaching that will explain
in logical, or intuiti vely reasonable, terms the empirical relationships between
important concepts, or variables, that characterize teaching.
As we noted above, one widely held conception of theory in both the natural and
social sciences is that theory must explain the empirical phenomena, such as the
relationships between concepts and v ariables. Examples of relationships in
psychology would be explanations of (a) the universally found positive correlation
between the socioeconomic status of individuals and their cognitive ability, and (b)
the higher correlation between the IQs of identical twins than that between the IQs
of fraternal twins.
But, because “e xplanation” can mean man y things, it needs to be def ined.
Accordingly, a substantial literature on theories of e xplanation, written mostly by
philosophers of science, has appeared (see e.g., Pitt, 1988). And in that literature,
one widely accepted conception of e xplanation is the “co vering law explanation”
(Hempel & Oppenheim, 1948). Their f irst example of such an e xplanation is that
of a mercury thermometer rapidly immersed in hot w ater.
There occurs a temporary drop [italics added] of the mercury column, which is then followed
by a quick rise. How is this phenomenon to be explained? The increase in temperature affects
at first only the glass tube of the thermometer; it expands and thus provides a larger space for
the mercury inside, whose surface therefore drops. As soon as by heat conduction the rise in
temperature reaches the mercury, however, the latter expands, and as its coefficient of expan-
sion is considerably lar ger than that of glass, a rise of mercury le vel results. This account
consists of statements of two kinds. Those of the first kind indicate certain conditions which
are realized prior to, or at the same time as, the phenomenon to be e xplained; we shall refer
to them briefly as antecedent conditions. In our illustration, the antecedents include, among
others, the f act that the mercury thermometer consists of a glass tube which is partly f illed
with mercury, and that it is immersed into hot w ater. The statements of the second kind
express certain general laws; in our case, these include the la ws of the thermic e xpansion of
mercury and of glass, and a statement about the small thermic conductivity of glass. The two
sets of statements, if adequately formulated, e xplain the phenomenon under consideration;
they entail the consequence that the mercury will f irst drop, then rise . Thus the event under
discussion is explained by subsuming it under [covering it with] general laws, that is, by
showing that it occurred in accordance with those laws, in virtue of the realization of certain
specified antecedent conditions. (Pitt, 1988, pp. 9–10)
Accordingly, a theory of teaching should explain how it is that students learn from
teaching and do so by invoking more general “covering laws” of human behavior.
In relation to scientif ic research, the value of theory can be dif ferentiated between
(a) theory formulated and used before the collection and analysis of empirical
observations, i.e., “theory-driven research,” and (b) theory produced after the collection
and analysis of observations.
24 2 The Desirability and Possibility of a Theory of Teaching
One argument in favor of theory is that prior theory is a necessary tool of scientific
research. Some writers ha ve gone so f ar as to claim that nothing scientif ic can be
learned from research conducted without a prior theory that drove the research.
Lewin (1931), the protagonist of “f ield theory” in psychology , labeled as
“Galilean” the theory-dri ven conception of scientif ic research, because he held
Galileo to ha ve been a prime e xemplar of that approach. In contrast, his
“Aristotelian” science – the science of Aristotle as interpreted by Thomas Aquinas
(Martin & Sugarman, 1993, p. 18) – sought generalizations deri ved empirically on
the basis of no prior theory . “Aristotle viewed scientific inquiry as a progression
from observations to general principles and back to observ ations” (Losee, 1980,
p. 6). Akin to Galileian principles, Garrison and Macmillan (1984) stated that
It is only when the research is theory-dri ven from within that the theories themselv es are
supported or falsified; and only when this is done can there be better theories for the expla-
nation and direction of pedagogical practice. (p. 3)
Thus these writers claim that a theory is necessary at the beginning, before observa-
tions are collected, analyzed, and interpreted. Similarly, Chambers (1989) held that
[I]mprovement of [scientific] enterprises does not derive from the accumulation of further facts.
It derives from the introduction of theory of v arious types which can be used both to say what
count as facts, to make sense out of them, and to test them in various ways. (p. 84) [U]ntil very
recently, Process-Outcome researchers [on teaching] do appear to ha ve been una ware of the
manifold significance of theory... in science ... The y are, for e xample, still largely unaware of
the effects of theory on what is observ ed, and thus on what can count as a f act. (p. 86)
The same position was taken, somewhat vehemently, by Ball (1995) in regard to
educational research:
I wish to argue that the absence of theory lea ves the researcher prey to unexamined, unre-
flexive preconceptions and dangerously nai ve ontological and epistemological a prioris .
I shall w ail and curse at the absence of theory and ar gue for theory as a w ay of sa ving
educational studies from itself. (pp. 365–366)
Martin and Sugarman (1993) described the distinction between Aristotelian and
Galilean approaches to scientif ic research as a contrast between the Aristotelian
focus on observed regularities and the Galilean focus on constructing hypothetical
models of underlying realities. Aristotelian forms of scientif ic thought focus on
identifying the essential qualities of objects associated. Aristotelian science discovers
concepts inductively, from analysis of observations, while Galilean science invents
concepts and relies on prior theory.
The alternative position is that, although valid theory is the supremely desirable outcome
of scientific research, prior theory is not indispensable. In support of that position, Gage
(1994b) pointed to the problems that the “prior -theory-is-indispensable” position runs
Must Scientific Research Be Theory-Driven? 25
into in the light of (a) the concept of implicit theory , (b) the positions of some philoso-
phers of science, (c) the serendipity , or theoryless research, that has led to important
scientific discoveries, and (d) the history of research on teaching.
The first reply refers to the idea of implicit guiding theory. The critics apparently
reject the possibility that scientif ic research can proceed without prior formulation
of an e xplicit theory and its associated hypotheses. No matter ho w well what the
scientist does satisfies other ideals of scientific method (maximized rationality and
objectivity, precision of definitions, public character, replicability, and falsifiability),
if the prior theory has not been e xplicitly formulated, say these critics, the whole
enterprise cannot be considered scientific.
It seems that scientif ic research, in the vie w of these critics, cannot e volve
through a process mo ving from implicit, ill-def ined, perhaps ad hoc, and explora-
tory, b ut nonetheless influential theory , and not requiring prior theories that are
explicitly formulated, and then survive attempts to falsify the theories with empiri-
cal e vidence. The critics used no detailed kno wledge of such relati vely early
research on teaching as that of Mitzel (1960), Flanders (1970), and Medley (1977),
among others, who did process-outcome research on teaching before the 1980s.
They also did not look carefully at the more recent process-outcome research on
teaching. So they seem unfamiliar with the reasoning (that is, the implicit theory),
either openly stated or readily inferred, underlying the researchers’ choice of con-
cepts, variables, and measuring instruments, and thus the easily inferred implicit
theories that these researchers were testing. In short, they do not seem to have ben-
efited from the admonition by the philosopher of science Hanson (1958, p. 3):
“Profitable philosophical discussion of any science depends on a thorough familiar-
ity with its history and its present state. ”
Marland (1995) examined the concept of implicit theory from the standpoints of
the student, the teacher in training, the practicing teacher, and the teacher educator.
All of these use implicit theories of teaching in the form of metaphors: the teacher
as “cook, entertainer, counselor, timekeeper, engineer, preacher, conductor, mother
figure, horticulturist, actor, and ship’s captain” (p. 134).
More such metaphors come readily to mind:the teacher as explainer, chairperson,
prosecuting attorney, and even
“The teacher as a Bayesian sheep dog. ” The resulting image is of a barking collie propel-
ling his b ulging flock along a path by successi ve statistical estimation and adjustment of
the flock’s average direction, while racing to keep diverging individuals contained with the
group. (Snow, 1973, p. 89)
Implicit theories can also, said Marland (1995), take the form of images whereby
the teacher or researcher might see “the classroom as a home” (Clandinin, 1986)
with all of the home’s attendant feelings and emotions.
In considering research on teaching that has not been explicitly theory-driven to
be ipso facto unscientific, the critics ignored the strong probability that it has been
driven by implicit theories. Whenever investigators choose v ariables and de velop
ways of measuring them, they operate on at least an implicit theory if not an explicit one.
The philosopher of science Hanson (1958) had such a conception of implicit theory
in mind when he wrote that
There is a sense, then, in which seeing is a “theory-laden undertaking.” Observation of x is
shaped by prior kno wledge of x. Another influence on observ ations rests in the language
or notation used to e xpress what we kno w, and without which there w ould be little we
could recognize as knowledge. (p. 19)
So it follows not only that the in vestigator must have at least an implicit theory
so as to be able to carry out the necessary research steps in a nonrandom w ay but
also that atheoretical educational science is impossible, as was asserted by Garrison
and Macmillan(1987) . Researchers may not be a ware of their theory , but they act
on it nonetheless.
Such implicit theory is easily seen in the dimensions of teaching specified in the
classroom-interaction-analysis categories used by Flanders (1970); those categories
reflect the implicit theory that classroom climate along a direct-indirect influence
dimension is related to student achie vement and attitude. Such implicit theory is
also e vident in the dimensions in vestigated by Brophy and Ev ertson (1976) –
dimensions that were based on the readily inferred theory that classroom manage-
ment, that is, w ays of holding student attention and minimizing academically
counterproductive use of time, was related to student achievement. A third example
is the widely applied instrument developed by Stallings (1975) to reveal the degree
of implementation of ten dif ferent “theoretical” models of teaching de veloped as
planned variations in Project Follow Through; each model had been developed and
rationalized by a separate team.
To anyone who looks into the background of the observation-of-process schemes
used in process-outcome research on teaching, their underlying implicit theories are
evident even though the y vary in the e xplicitness with which the y are stated. The
assumption that process-outcome research has been atheoretical seems to result
from f ailure to e xamine these authors’ writings and their process-observ ation
instruments. In none of the philosophical criticisms is there any evidence of a care-
ful reading of the details of the process-outcome research reports. It is as if, unless
researchers used the word “theory,” these critics were unable to see the theory .
Philosophers of Science on Scientific Method. A second reply refers to what phi-
losophers of science have written on the idea of f ixed and firm conceptions of sci-
entific method. Much could be found in their writings to raise questions about the
rigid notions of these critics concerning the nature of scientif ic method. Here are a
Must Scientific Research Be Theory-Driven? 27
few such statements, be ginning with that of Peter Meda war, not because he w as a
philosopher b ut because he w as a Nobel laureate who w as quoted by one critic
(Chambers, 1989, pp. 83–84) as an authority on the nature of science. Chambers
ignored Medawar’s statement that
There is indeed no such thing as “the” scientif ic method. A scientist uses a v ery great
variety of e xploratory stratagems, and although a scientist has a certain address to his
problems – a certain way of going about things that is more likely to bring success than the
gropings of an amateur – he uses no procedure of disco very that can be logically scripted.
(Medawar, 1984, p. 51)
These statements mean the opposite of what the philosophical critics of research
on teaching have insisted upon, namely, the inescapable requirement that scientific
research be explicitly theory-driven.
These critics have also ignored the possibility of replicating a study , using as a
basis for a hypothesis a finding of a first study. Such replication with theory on the
basis of results that were not pre viously e xplicitly hypothesized has occurred
frequently in the history of science and in process-outcome research on teaching.
The atheoretical first study’s finding leads to a theory confirmed or disconfirmed in
a subsequent study.
Serendipity in the History of Science. A third reply deals with empirical e vidence
on the necessity of prior theory in scientific research. That evidence is found in the
history of science – a history that re veals many important e xceptions to the ar gu-
ment that scientific research must be explicitly theory-driven.
Especially noteworthy here is the literature onserendipity. The critics of research
have ignored the long and important history of the role of serendipity in scientif ic
research (see, e.g., Kantero vich & Néeman, 1989). That history demonstrates that
extremely important scientific discoveries have been made without any prior theory
or hypothesis. Among such disco veries are X-rays, the electricity-magnetism
connection, penicillin, cosmic micro wave background radiation, and pulsars.
(See Table 2.5 .)
28 2 The Desirability and Possibility of a Theory of Teaching
Accordingly, the subsequent process-outcome w ork did not arise from the
thoughtless, theory-free thrashing-about seemingly imputed to such studies by the
critics. It arose from discouraging experience with presage variables, from the reali-
zation that better results might come from looking at what happens in the class-
room, and from careful thought about what v ariables in classroom process might
make a dif ference in what students learned. Only a careful reading of process-
outcome research reports w ould permit an yone to judge the de gree to which the
research was theory-laden.
30 2 The Desirability and Possibility of a Theory of Teaching
The philosopher of science Karl Popper (1963 ) spoke to the issue of whether all
scientific research must be theory-driven by substituting the concept of conjecture1*
for “theory.” The conjecture should, of course, stem from the best e vidence and
logic available to the in vestigator. A conjecture claims much less than a theory ; it
is an assumption, a guess, a hunch, a speculation, a supposition, a surmise, a
jumped-to-conclusion.
Popper held that inducti ve logic cannot serv e as a w ay to prove the truth of a
conclusion. Even a phenomenon, such as the setting of the sun in the west, that has
been observed to occur predictably in the same w ay, without e xception, innumer-
able times, over many millennia, cannot prove, by inductive logic alone, without the
support of deductive-logical principles, that the sun will al ways set in the west. As
Popper (1963) told it,
Thus I w as led by purely logical considerations to replace the psychological theory of
induction by the follo wing view. Without waiting, passively, for repetitions to impress or
impose regularities upon us, we actively try to impose re gularities upon the world. We try
to discover similarities in it, and to interpret it in terms of la ws invented by us. W ithout
waiting for premises we jump to conclusions. These may have to be discarded later should
observation show that they are wrong.
This was a theory of trial and error – of conjectures and refutations. It made it
possible to understand why our attempts to force interpretations upon the w orld
were logically prior to the observation of similarities. (p. 60)
Popper’s phrases – “try to impose re gularities upon the w orld ... to disco ver
similarities in it to interpret it in terms of laws invented by us ... jump to conclusions
... force interpretations upon the w orld that were logically prior” – are Popper’ s
modest equi valents of “theory .” But, whereas “theory” connotes formality and
rigor, “conjecture” has an informal and fallible flavor. Indeed, Popper’s conception
of scientif ic method, stated in his book’ s title, Conjectures and Refutations,
expresses something similar to the notion of implicit theory – a conjecture to be
subjected to strong ef forts at refutation and to be accepted only as long as it sur -
vives those efforts.
The ar guments on both sides of the Aristotelian v ersus Galilean issue seem
eminently reasonable. Philosophers and scientists hold strong opinions on the
basis of impressionistic and case-study e vidence. But empirical research on
1*
“The formation or e xpression of an opinion or theory without suf ficient evidence or proof. ”
(Random House, Webster’s College Dictionary ,1991).
An Empirical Approach to Controversies About Scientific Method 31
scientific methods and their outcomes might sho w which side is more v alid in
terms of its results.
Consequently, F aust and Meehl (1992) proposed that scientif ic method be used to
resolve questions in the history and philosophy of science. Such an ef fort would entail
(a) identifying representati ve samples of scientif ic projects in a domain, (b) def ining
theoretically promising characteristics of the projects, such as whether or not the y were
theory-driven, (c) measuring the de gree to which the projects manifested these charac-
teristics, (d) e valuating those projects as to the scientif ic value of their yield, and then
(e) determining the degree to which the various characteristics correlated with the scien-
tific v alue of their outcomes and actually dif ferentiated between the projects on the
dimension of scientif ic v alue. The sample selection, the e valuation of yield, and the
identification of the characteristics of the projects represented in their samples, are feasi-
ble undertakings, especially in relation to the importance of the issues to be resolv ed.
In any event, the Faust-Meehl proposal sharpens appreciation of the logical invalidity
of the Chambers (1992) approach to the determination of the source and content of the
abstract concepts – their discovery and manipulation – in his conception of science. As
already noted, e ven if research on the characteristics of successful physical science
yielded intellectually significant findings, we would want, of course, to kno w whether
those f indings hold for the biological, social, and beha vioral sciences, all of which
Chambers ignored in displaying e xamples of science. Further , Chambers used what
might be called his “clinical judgment” in appraising both the track record and the
promise of approaches to research on teaching. But, as F aust and Meehl (1992)
remarked, such judgment has, with great consistenc y, had much less success, as com-
pared with actuarial methods, in predicting all sorts of outcomes. The huge body of
research on clinical versus actuarial judgment convincingly shows that even crude, non-
optimized decision procedures that combine information in a linear manner consistently
equal or exceed the accuracy of human judges (Faust & Meehl, 1992, pp. 197–198).
The Faust-Meehl proposal could be used for impro ving prediction of the scien-
tific payoff of v arious approaches to doing science, including such approaches as
formulating abstract concepts without being influenced by observ ations, which
Chambers (1992) sees as the method of great physical scientists. Even if the Faust-Meehl
proposal is ne ver carried out, it signals the untrustw orthiness on these matters of
strong opinions based on inadequate empirical e vidence.
and historians of science ha ve used the term science. Thus one is led to ask, What
is the consensus among such think ers?
An example of how a philosopher of science re gards the scientific status of the
social sciences is pro vided by Glymour (1983). He f irst dismissed the notion that
“all really scientific explanations follow the pattern of a sort of logicized celestial
mechanics.” Then he asserted that
Social sciences are in large part applied sciences, closely tied to our wish to know the effects
of social policies or the causes of social phenomena. Much of the w ork in contemporary
sociology, educational research, political science, and econometrics is directed to wards such
ends, and what it produces are causal explanations ... of particular social phenomena, and
descriptions of the causal relations among social phenomena. By and large, the explanations
and descriptions produced are of a kind, and are b uttressed by the sort of ar guments that we
recognize as scientif ically rational, and their content is often useful and surprising. Social
scientific w ork of this kind produces e xplanations, causal e xplanations; and kno wledge,
causal knowledge, without producing general la ws, at least not the sort of general la ws the
critics of social science demand. In doing as much, social science follo ws a pattern that is
common throughout the sciences. It is a pattern most common in applied sciences, in epide-
miology, in biology, and in engineering. It is least common, b ut scarcely absent, in physics.
(pp. 127–128)
During the decades after World War II, American federal research agencies – such
as the National Science F oundation and the National Institutes of Health – were
established. Those agencies supported quests for theory in the physical and biological
sciences on the well-founded assumption that practical applications of scientif ic
theory would eventually contribute to society’s welfare.
Theory as the Outcome of Research 33
In recent decades, calls for theory in educational research have been frequent. In his
presidential address to the American Educational Research Association, the phi-
losopher of science Patrick Suppes (1974) offered five kinds of argument:
1. Analogy. “The obvious and universally recognized importance of theory in the
more mature sciences, e.g., economics and psychology” can be analogized to the
“importance of theory in educational research. ” Adequate theory is generally
regarded as the basis for the distinction between empiricism and science.
2. Reorganization of experience. Theory “changes our perspective on what is impor-
tant and what is superf icial,” as when the ob vious (the sun re volves around the
earth) is replaced by the nonob vious truth (the earth revolves around the sun).
3. Recognizing complexity. Seeking theory leads to investigating how and why one
method of, say , teaching reading is better than another be yond the merely
empirical determination of the difference in their effectiveness.
4. Problem solving. By comparison with De weyan problem solving, theory mak es
it unnecessary to “begin afresh” whenever one is confronted with new problem.
5. The triviality of bare empiricism. The mere recording of f acts without generali-
zation or theory operates so that there can be no transfer of understanding from
one situation or problem to another.
Students of research on teaching ha ve often noted the lack of theory as an out-
come. “Theoretical impo verishment” w as the term used by Dunkin and Biddle
34 2 The Desirability and Possibility of a Theory of Teaching
Carroll (1963) e xpressed a further call for a theory of teaching in his influential
“model of school learning” – a model to be described in Chap. 8. His model pro-
posed five basic classes of v ariables that w ould account for v ariations in student
achievement. Three of these components were e xpressed in terms of time. One of
the tw o “non-time” v ariables in Carroll’ s model, which he also assumed to be
related to achie vement, was Quality of Instruction. Thus, “The model is not v ery
specific about the characteristics of high quality of instruction” (Carroll, 1989,
p. 26). Here Carroll was implicitly affirming the need for theory of teaching. To the
extent that instruction is less than optimal, time needed for learning is increased.
His model mentions that teachers must (a) tell students clearly what the y are to
learn, (b) put students into adequate contact with learning materials, and (c) care-
fully plan and order students’ steps in learning.
In the present context, it is noteworthy that Carroll defined quality of instruction
only briefly, and his statement provides an implicit argument for the desirability of
a theory of teaching . A quarter -century later , Carroll (1989) reaf firmed his
position:
Questionings of the Value of Theory 35
Perhaps because the Carroll model of school learning does not deal e xtensively with
elements involved in quality of instruction, it has not been particularly influential in these
studies [of quality of instruction]. (p. 29)
That the Carroll model should deal with quality of instruction more “extensively,”
perhaps through a theory of teaching, is a logical inference from the state of af fairs
that Carroll described.
observed events by appealing to e vents “taking place some where else, at some other
level of observ ation, described in dif ferent terms, and measured, if at all, in dif ferent
dimensions” (Skinner, 1964, p. 385). In Skinner’s view, attributing behavior to a neural
or mental e vent, real or conceptual, tended (a) to mak e us for get that we still need to
account for the neural or mental e vent, real or conceptual, because such attrib utions
were, at least in Skinner’ s day, unobservable neural and cogniti ve explanations, and
gave us unwarranted satisfaction with the state of our kno wledge.
But Skinner raised no questions about the desirability of theories of beha vior –
theories that e xplained beha vior of one kind in terms of connections between
observable behavior and observ able stimuli. Indeed, he de voted his career to the
development of such theory . And he presumably w ould have had no objection to
cognitive or neural theory that stayed at the mental or neural level, without attributing
mental or neural events to other levels.
Levels of Theory
Theories can deal with phenomena at dif ferent levels of natural science: physics,
chemistry, neurology, behavioral, and mental. Theories at the le vel of physics deal
with such concepts as force, mass, and atomic particles (e.g., electrons, protons,
neutrons, neutrinos, positrons) in w ays needed to describe and e xplain certain
phenomena, such as X-rays or the motions of physical bodies. At the level of chem-
istry, theory refers to elements (e.g., oxygen, chlorine) and compounds (e.g.,
acetylcholine) needed to e xplain such chemical processes as digestion, cardiac
rhythm, and brain acti vity. At the le vel of neurology, theories deal with the neural
structures (e.g., synapses) and pathw ays (e.g., af ferent and ef ferent) in volved in
sensing, perceiving, and remembering. At the level of behavior, theories refer to the
observable (visible, audible) actions, such as those in volved in responding,
approaching or withdrawing, positive and negative conditioning. Finally, theories at
the mental-process le vel use such concepts as w orking-memory and long-term
memory (Atkinson & Shif frin, 1968), cognitive dissonance (Festinger, 1957), and
cognitive load (Sweller, 1999), all in volved in learning, comprehending, problem-
solving, and teaching.
Reductionism
Despite all the fore going ar guments in f avor of theory , some writers ha ve tak en
positions against theory. They have had in mind theories in the natural sciences and
the behavioral sciences.
In Natural Science
Some anti-theory ar guments in the natural sciences hold that theory operates
against the need for thinking flexibly in doing research and imposes constraints on
creativity. Thus Paul Feyerabend (1993), an iconoclast and self-labeled “anarchist”
in the philosophy of science, saw theory as keeping thinking away from the “accidents
and conjunctures and curious juxtapositions of e vents” (quoted by Fe yerabend,
1993, p. 9, from Butterf ield, 1966, p. 66) that characterize original thinking.
“Science is essentially an anarchic enterprise, and theoretical anarchism is more
humanitarian and more lik ely to encourage progress than its la w-and-order alterna-
tives” (p. 9). As Feyerabend (1993) put it,
For e xample, we may use hypotheses that contradict well-conf irmed theories or well-
established experimental results or both. We may advance science by proceeding counter -
inductively ... Hypotheses contradicting well-conf irmed theories gi ve us e vidence that
cannot be obtained in an y other w ay. Proliferation of theories is benef icial for science,
while uniformity impairs its critical power. (p. 5)
Here Feyerabend is, however, arguing not against theory b ut against premature
“uniformity” in holding theories. His ar gument calls to mind philosophy , a disci-
pline that may be said to deal with nothing b ut theory. Yet philosophy does not
stagnate. In support of his antitheoretical position, Fe yerabend quoted Lenin, who
wrote that “History as a whole is al ways more varied ... than is imagined by e ven
the best parties” and asserted that its lessons should apply to scientists and method-
ologists as well as “parties and revolutionary vanguards” (1993, p. 9). He also noted
38 2 The Desirability and Possibility of a Theory of Teaching
Hegel’s writing that “What history teaches us is this, that nations and go vernments
have never learned an ything from history.” And he quoted Albert Einstein (1951)
to the effect that
The external conditions which are set for [the scientist] by the f acts of e xperience do not
permit him to let himself be too much restricted, in the construction of his conceptual
world, by the adherence to an epistemological system. He, therefore, must appear to the
systematic epistemologist as a type of unscrupulous opportunist.
In Literary Studies
Although the f ield of literary studies is not a science, either natural or social, it is
noteworthy that controversies about theory’s desirability, similar in tone to those in
the natural and social sciences, have arisen in that field. A volume edited by Mitchell
(1985) contained an opening chapter titled “Against Theory,” which was followed by
twelve chapters that the editor considered to be “ A Defense of Theory.”
In Educational Research
In an y case, the dif ferences between the natural sciences and the social and
behavioral sciences might be considered to diminish the force of arguments, such
as Fe yerabend’s, based on what has happened in the natural sciences. But the
arguments of a sociologist of education (Thomas, 1997) against the desirability
of theory in educational research, although not addressed specifically to theory of
teaching and not intuiti vely plausible, deserv e attention. The y fly in the f ace of
long-accepted doctrine about the uses and consequences of theory . First Thomas
notes the ambiguity of the term “theory” – its “multiplicity of meanings” (p. 75).
It is highly re garded because of its success “in other f ields [such as the natural
sciences]” that have “no congruence in education” (p. 76). He ar gues that
theory of any kind is thus a force for conservatism, for stabilizing through the circumscrip-
tion of thought within a hermetic set of rules, procedures, and methods.... [Theory is] an
instrument for reinforcing an existing set of practices and methods in education.[It] circum-
scribes methods of thinking about educational problems and it inhibits creati vity among
researchers, policy makers, and teachers. (pp. 76–77)
Rajagapolan (1998) replied by holding that “in ar guing against theory, Thomas
himself … ends up ha ving to rely on certain well-entrenched theoretical orienta-
tions, thus pro viding an e xcellent example of the ubiquity of theory in e verything
we humans do” (p. 337). Also, he wrote, “Underlying Thomas’ s complaint [about
the ambiguity, well-nigh meaninglessness of the w ord “theory”] is the theory that
“every signifier must be attached to one and only one signif ied” (p. 343). Thomas
(1999) then replied, f irst, that Rajagopalan’ s vie w of theory as applying to all
Knowledge Outcome and Knowledge Use 39
It is not true that, in the history of the natural and social sciences, theory has inhibited
creativity, originality, flexibility, and intellectual freedom. These assertions face the
factual contradiction that, in the natural and social sciences, as the history of major
and minor theories sho ws, and as Popper (1965) contended, theories ha ve indeed
provoked indefatigable and creative efforts to falsify them. And theories have survived
only when those efforts have failed.
As a precursor of research, theory may serv e knowledge production as a stimu-
lus of (a) researchable questions, (b) questions deri ved from previous thought, (c)
hypotheses whose testing increases the lik elihood of f indings that mak e sense in
relation to prior thought and in vestigation, and (d) hypotheses that mak e research
findings less in need of an impossible number of confirming replications. So theory
is not an indispensable precursor of outcomes of research, although it can be a valu-
able guide to research that will ha ve scientific payoff.
For knowledge users, theory has the inestimable v alue of making e vents or proc-
esses understandable. Theory can crystallize otherwise e xtremely unwieldy stores
of factual knowledge into applicable forms. Without theory, we would have, at best,
only empirical generalizations that w ould remain unexplained, isolated from other
40 2 The Desirability and Possibility of a Theory of Teaching
phenomena, and unrelated to a co vering law into which the y can be fitted. Theory
ties together in an e xplanatory framework the inf initude of particular instances of
the operation of the theory and thus mak es them make sense. Theory, in this w ay,
serves knowledge use.
As w as easily predictable from where this discussion is located – in a w ork
devoted to the presentation of a theory of teaching – we reject Fe yerabend’s and
Thomas’s arguments against theory. To give up the quest for theory means to gi ve
up the goal of understanding why the students of some teachers achie ve the objec-
tives of teaching at a higher le vel than the students of other teachers, e ven when
non-teaching factors affecting student achie vement – such as student intelligence,
home background, and community economic status – are controlled. These differences
in student achievement are the cause of much concern, w orry, soul-searching, and
policy-examining on the part of the millions of parents of the low-achieving students.
To abandon the search for relevant theory is tantamount to abandoning the hope of
understanding teaching and of impro ving teaching for those students who most
need the improvement.
The arguments against theory will win some acceptance until a v alid theory of
teaching is de veloped. In the meantime, the ef fort should continue. The present
attempt may adv ance education either by survi ving attempts at refutation or by
stimulating the de velopment of better theory that survi ves in its turn further
attempts at refutation.
Chapter 3
The Evolution of a Paradigm for the Study
of Teaching
theory presented here. Variables are concepts whose referents can take on forms or
values that dif fer from one another , qualitati vely or quantitati vely. F or e xample,
gender is a concept that varies “qualitatively.” Height is a concept that varies “quan-
titatively.” In this chapter the variables will be described and illustrated in terms of
how they have entered into logical and empirical studies of teaching.
In research on teaching, the paradigm has e volved from the cumulati ve contribu-
tions of students of teaching in the period from the 1890s to the 1980s. The e volu-
tion began with a paradigm implicit in the empirical research design used by Joseph
Mayer Rice (1897; reprinted in Rice, 1913). The subsequent insertion and modif i-
cation of additional categories took place as successive thinkers filled in the overall
conception of what needed to be considered in a full attempt to e xplain teaching.
Rice (1897; see also Banerji, 1988) studied the relationship between v ariables in
two categories that would later be called process and achievement. In his study the
process variable was the amount of time teachers devoted to teaching spelling. The
achievement variable was the average score of the teacher’ s students on a spelling
test. The study of this relationship w as later termed the “process-product para-
digm,” shown in Fig. 3.1a, whose two boxes contain the two categories of variables,
and the arrow represents the relationship between them.
Later, una ware of Rice’ s w ork, I identif ied the similar “criterion-of-teacher -
effectiveness” paradigm, shown in Fig. 3.1b (Gage, 1963, p. 114). It dif fered from
Rice’s process-product paradigm in allo wing for mere correlates, such as promis-
ing predictors of teaching ef fectiveness in the form of teacher characteristics, in
addition to the teaching process variables, such as Rice’s, that connoted determiners
Process
Student
Variables in
Achievement
Teaching
Potential
Correlates of Criteria of
Criteria of Teacher
Teacher Effectiveness
Effectiveness
Presage
Variables
Process Outcome
Variables Variables
Fig. 3.2 The paradigm resulting from the insertion of presage v ariables.
of the achievement variables. Also, it admitted criteria of teaching other than stu-
dent achie vement – criteria such as principals’ ratings of teachers and teachers’
length of experience in teaching.
Presage Variables
Mitzel (1960) introduced the concept of presage v ariables. The term denotes
dimensions of teacher personality and teachers’ e xperience in teacher education
programs that are considered to be potential predictors, or “presages, ” of teaching
effectiveness (Fig. 3.2). As Mitzel (1960) described them,
presage variables, so-called here because of their origin in guessed-at-predict ive-value, are
from a logical standpoint completely removed from the goals of education. Their relevance
depends on an assumed or conjectured relationship to other criteria, either process or prod-
uct... There are at least four types of presage v ariables... (a) teacher personality attrib utes,
(b) characteristics of teachers in training, (c) teacher kno wledge and achievement, and (d)
in-service teacher status characteristics. (p. 1484)
Context Variables
Mitzel (1957, cited in Gage, 1963, p. 121) also introduced the cate gory consisting
of context v ariables, or , as Mitzel named them, “contingenc y f actors.” These
44 3 The Evolution of a Paradigm for the Study of Teaching
describe the setting, or en vironment, in which the teaching goes on: the rele vant
characteristics of the culture in the nation, re gion, community, school, classroom,
family, and student body.
Adding this cate gory to the pre vious three resulted in the four -category para-
digm used by Biddle (1964) with dif ferent terminology. For the presage cate gory,
Biddle’s term was “teachers’ properties and formati ve experiences.” He called the
context category “school and community contexts” and “classroom situations.” For
the process category, his terms were “teacher behaviors” and “immediate effects on
pupil responses.” F or the achie vement cate gory, his term w as “long-term conse-
quences,” including pupil achievement and adjustment.
But Dunkin and Biddle (1974), in their comprehensi ve, insightful re view of
research on teaching, adopted Mitzel’ s terminology: presage, conte xt, process, and
achievement (see Fig. 3.3). More recently, the Center for Research on the Context of
Teaching (McLaughlin & Talbert, 2001), described one of its monographs as dealing
with teachers’ professional communities in American high schools at the end of the
twentieth century... We describe ho w the w ork of teaching dif fered – in classroom
practice, in colleague relations, and in e xperienced careers – across three dif ferent
types of communities we found in high schools and subject departments ... (p. 2).
B. O. Smith (1961, p. 92) contrib uted the category for teachers’ thought processes
when he called attention, in his “pedagogical model,” to what he called the teacher’s
“intervening v ariables,” namely , the teacher’s thought processes, which foll owed
Presage
Variables
Process Outcome
Variables Variables
Context
Variables
Fig. 3.3 The paradigm resulting from the addition of conte xt variables (Mitzel, 1957).
The Teacher’s-Thought-Processes Category 45
upon the presage and conte xt variables and were antecedents of the process v aria-
bles. Shulman (1975) and his fello w members of a planning conference panel on
“Teaching as Clinical Information Processing” at the National Institute of
Education’s National Conference on Studies in T eaching (Gage & Viehover, Eds.,
1975), brought this cate gory to the fore by elaborating on its potential theoretical
significance:
Thus an understanding of ho w teachers cogniti vely construct the reality of teaching and
learning remains central to the achievement of NIE’s overall goal of developing the means
to improve the provision, maintenance, and utilization of high quality teaching personnel.
A teacher may possess the full range of rele vant instructional skills, b ut if he is unable to
diagnose situations in which a particular set of those skills is needed, the skills alone will
be insufficient. (Shulman et al., 1975, p. 2)
Presage
Variables
Teachers'
Process Product
Thought
Variables Variables
Processes
Context
Variables
Fig. 3.4 The paradigm as modified by the addition of Teacher’s Thought Processes (B. O. Smith,
1961; Shulman et al., 1975) and the Content of T eaching (Shulman, 1986a) .
46 3 The Evolution of a Paradigm for the Study of Teaching
This category consists of the actions and interactions of teachers and students in
the classroom (process) and the subject-matter taught (content). Content w as clas-
sified by A Taxonomy for Learning, Teaching, and Assessing (Anderson et al.,
2001). It distinguished between four types of kno wledge to be learned: f actual
knowledge, conceptual kno wledge, procedural kno wledge, and metacogniti ve
knowledge. (These types will be described belo w.)
The Taxonomy also distinguished between six cate gories of cogniti ve process:
remember, understand, apply, analyze, evaluate, and create. Because of our empha-
ses, described and justif ied in Chap. 8, we spell out only the tw o subcategories of
remember: recognize and recall, and only one of the six subcategories of cognitive
process: understand.
B. O. Smith (1961) also included in his model the students’ thought processes. He
considered these processes to follo w classroom process v ariables and precede
achievement variables. When students’ thought processes are considered as stable
characteristics, such variables are considered conte xt variables – part of the situa-
tion in which the teaching occurs.
When such processes occur momentarily during classroom discourse, the y are
considered “student’s thought processes. ” Winne (1982, 1987, 1995), W inne and
Marx (1983), and Marx and W inne (1987) reviewed pertinent research and de vel-
oped a detailed rationale for their concern with the thought processes of students
(Fig. 3.5). They wrote:
Presage
Process
Teacher and Student Student
Thought Content Thought Achieve-
Processes of Processes ment
Teaching
Context
Fig. 3.5 The paradigm as modified by the addition of student’s thought processes (B. O. Smith
et al., 1967 ; Doyle, 1977; Marx & Winne, 1987).
The Variables in the Categories 47
Put briefly, between the teacher beha vior and students’ accomplishments assessed after
teaching, we inserted an e xplicit place for students’ cognitions to occur ... The cognitive
mediational model [so termed by Marx and W inne,1987] also recast the locus of causa-
tion in the performance-based model. Instead of teacher beha viors serving as the causes
of students’ learning, teacher behaviors in the cognitive mediation model became signals
for the students to use certain cognitions to learn content. The students’ cognitions were
considered the causes for learning. (Marx & W inne, 1987, pp. 270–271)
The long-o verdue realization that what the teacher teaches deserv es as much
attention in research on teaching as how she teaches should lead to a major revision
in the approach to research on teaching. Also, the terms “process–product” or
“process–outcome,” with their f actory-like connotations, should be dropped. The
term “process ↔content–achievement” should replace them. (The bidirectional
arrow is intended to symbolize the interaction between process and content.) That
is, the content of teaching should no longer be omitted from the term that describes
the research concerned with relationships between teaching and student achie ve-
ment. Accordingly, it follo ws that process ↔content–achievement research should
henceforth be the term for research aimed at disco vering relationships between
teaching – how and what teachers teach – and what students learn.
As Fig. 3.6 shows, the six categories are labeled with Capital letters. The catego-
ries can be categorized into two sets: (a) those – Categories A, B, C – that are logi-
cally antecedent of Cate gory D: and (b) Cate gories E and F that are logically
subsequent to Category D.
The relationships between all 15 pairs of categories that are either logically prior
or logically subsequent to the process ↔content events of teaching are represented
by the tw o-way arrows numbered 1–15 connecting pairs of cate gories. For exam-
ple, student achievement can affect subsequent student’s thought processes, and the
prior process↔content of teaching can influence subsequent teacher’ s thought
processes.
This cate gory consists of such characteristics of the teacher as gender , age, and
years of experience. It also comprises traits (stable characteristics, such as intelli-
gence, knowledge about w ays of teaching, and intro version-extraversion) both in
general and in the context of a specific subject matter. The teacher’s cognitive abili-
ties af fect her grasp of the subject matter in all its v ariations and comple xities,
48 3 The Evolution of a Paradigm for the Study of Teaching
including the pre viously identified pedagogical content kno wledge introduced by
Shulman (1986b).
The teacher’s knowledge of the subject she is teaching – her content knowledge
– affects the w ay she presents, e xplains, illustrates, and demonstrates the content
she wants her students to learn. The teacher’ s experiences in a teacher -education
program may influence her conceptions of teaching and her implicit v alues about
how teaching should proceed. Her pre vious experience as a teacher influences her
security and optimism about teaching.
The presage category also includes the teacher’s stable affective characteristics:
intentions, beliefs, attitudes, v alues, appreciations, and the lik e, as traits that the
teacher has acquired from e xperience, including experience in a teacher education
program.
Her personality may af fect the general demeanor of her engagement with her
tasks and students. Currently , the so-called “Big Fi ve,” dimensions of personality ,
widely accepted by psychologists (see, for e xample, Cutchin, 1999), illustrate one
way in which personality is given dimensions. Its five dimensions are the degree to
which a teacher tends to be (a) hostile versus agreeable, (b) intro verted versus
extroverted, (c) impulsi ve versus conscientious, (d) neurotic versus emotionally
stable, and (e) intellectually narrow versus intellectually open.
This category comprises the momentary thought processes that deal with cognitive
aspects of her teaching – such as the content being taught, its organization, its facts,
concepts, and principles. Her thought processes also deal with af fective aspects of
her teaching: her attitudes, motivations, and values, and emotionally loaded behav-
iors. Her thought processes deal especially with her momentary use of pedagogical
content knowledge.
When the teacher’s thought processes are a stable characteristic of the teacher ,
the teacher’s thoughts become presage variables – how her ideas about process and
content interact to affect her teaching. When they occur in the midst of the process
The Variables in the Categories 49
of teaching, they are transitory states. Both stable and transitory thought processes
occur before, during, and after the teacher interacts with her students. Jackson
(1968) identified two kinds of teacher thought processes: preactive and interactive.
Preactive thought processes, such as planning, occur before she interacts with her
students. They call upon her kno wledge, beliefs, and values about teaching, learn-
ing, and the curriculum. The successes and failures of recent interactions affect the
teacher thought processes in planning for the ne xt round of teaching.
Interactive thought processes, occur during her interactions with students, which
Jackson found to occur as often as a thousand times per day. She thinks, for exam-
ple, about the e xplanation she is gi ving, the questions she asks, her students’
responses, and her reactions to students’ responses. She also thinks about the suc-
cess of a recent e xchange with students, about her students’ comprehension, and
about the next few steps in her teaching.
Post-interactive thought processes are those she engages in after she has had a
class period with students. These thoughts deal with such things as her satisf action
with the w ay the lesson has gone; whether she needs to change her approach; her
perception of students’ interest, attention, moti vation, and comprehension. Clark
and Peterson (1986) re viewed research on teachers’ planning, interacti ve thought
processes, and post-interactive thought processes.
As noted earlier , only the v erbal (and not the non verbal) aspects of process
will be given detailed attention. Note that we ha ve distinguished between two
types of process: (a) cognitive processes, which refer to the student’ s mental
activities while learning and (b) teaching processes, which refer to what the
teacher is doing: v erbal beha vior; cogniti ve or social-emotional interactions
with students; interactions with the whole class, subgroups of the class, or
individual students. Of these we gi ve special attention to the types of v erbal
interaction.
The verbal process part. The v erbal aspects of the process of teaching will be
those identified by Bellack, Kliebard, Hyman, & F . L. Smith (1966), Hoetk er and
Ahlbrand (1969), and, with different terminologies, by Mehan (1979) and Goodlad
(1984):
(a)structuring (typically by a teacher, setting forth and organizing the content),
(b)soliciting (typically by a teacher asking questions of students) ,
(c)responding (typically by a student answering a teacher’ s question), and
(d)reacting (typically by a teacher after a student’ s response).
The content part. The subject-matter will be as specific as the teacher’s purposes
require. Examples of possible subject-matter -specific process v ariables are those
used in teaching paragraph analysis in reading, in teaching the use of the semicolon
in writing, in teaching the addition of numbers in arithmetic, in teaching the gas
50 3 The Evolution of a Paradigm for the Study of Teaching
laws in science, in teaching Shak espeare’s metaphors, and in teaching the checks
and balances in the U.S. Constitution.
Berliner (1989) argued for the study of teacher’s thought processes in relation to
student achievement. The question to be answered w as, Do contrasting groups of
teachers, that is, high and lo w groups of teachers on an y teacher-thought-process
variable, have different effects on student achievement by virtue of their connection
with kinds of teacher beha vior? Research on the ef fects of teacher thinking could
study the thought processes of groups of teachers selected for their dif fering
degrees of ef fectiveness in fostering student achie vement. Such research w ould
yield knowledge of T ype 12 connections, that is, relationships between teacher’ s
thought processes and student achievement. In the process, the research could also
throw light on relationships of T ype 10 (between teacher’ s thought processes and
process ↔ content of teaching) and Type 11 (between teacher’s thought processes
and student’s thought processes).
All these take the form of momentary states, not long-lasting traits.
This cate gory represents the goal of all the fore going cate gories. It includes
achievement of cognitive objectives and can also refer to achie vement of social-
emotional objecti ves (e.g., adjustment and attitude) and psychomotor objectives
(e.g., gymnastics and dancing ). As was noted in Chap. 2, the present theory deals
only with cognitive achievement.
At the end of some teaching, do the students know, in the sense of being able to
recall or recognize, what the y should kno w? Do the y understand in the sense of
being able to summarize, explain, translate, and apply what they should be able to?
Beyond the cognitive objectives of a specif ic lesson, or course of study , educators
also value metacognitive skills: students’ abilities to monitor and control their o wn
thought processes for the purpose of fostering their o wn achievement.
This category contains the e vidence of the student’ s achievement of the objec-
tives at which the teaching w as aimed. The Taxonomy for Learning, Teaching, and
Assessing (Anderson, Krathwohl et al., 2001) describes student achievement along
two dimensions:
The Change from “Process” to “Process ´ Content” 51
A
Presage
5
Variables 12
(Teacher
4
Characteristics)
3
11
2
C
D
Teacher E F
Process
Thought Students' Student
Processes Thought Achieve-
1 10 Content of 13 15
(Planning, Processes ment
Teaching
Deciding)
6
7 8
9 14
B
Context
Variables
(Teaching
Situation)
Fig. 3.6 The paradigm with all six categories, lettered A-F, and all 15 two-way arrows, numbered
1–15, indicating the two-way influences between all possible pairs of cate gories.
52 3 The Evolution of a Paradigm for the Study of Teaching
The revised version of this category includes the Content of Teaching along with
the Process of Teaching so as to result in a cate gory labeled (Process ↔ Content),
which refers to both the teaching process and the content being taught. But “peda-
gogical content knowledge” suggests that it is merely the content of the teacher’s
mind. Here, however, content is part of the teacher’s action and behaviors. We
hypothesize that this category will improve the explanatory power, the predictive
power, and the improvability of student achievement beyond that produced by
process-product (without content) research.
Here is how the teacher teaches. Those actions and interactions tak e such forms as
the recitation and the discussion group. Here the v ariables take such forms as the
comprehensibility of explanations, the cognitive level of the questions the teacher
asks (ranging from remembering,... to creating), w ait-time (the number of seconds
the teacher waits after asking a question (see Ro we, 1974), and the helpfulness of
the teacher’s reaction to the student’s response to a question. On the students’ side,
these variables include the amount of academic learning time, or the time during
which a student attends to learning tasks that permit high success rates and are
relevant to academic objecti ves (Berliner , 1990). Af fective components of the
teacher’s actions and interactions tak e such forms as the teachers’ w armth, sup-
portiveness, permissiveness, and authoritarianism.
The classroom processes also comprise the students’ interactions with other
students and the ways in which they influence one another. Nuthall and Alton-Lee,
(1998) described careful studies of students’ interactions with other students.
Here belongs what the teacher teaches – the subject matter: the f acts, concepts,
procedures, and metacognitions in the form in which the y are specified in the cur-
riculum of the subject being taught. Here one major variable is instructional align-
ment (S. A. Cohen, 1987, 1995 ), or the degree to which the content taught and the
content assessed (tested) are congruent with each other and with the objecti ves of
the teaching. The term assessment is used here to stand for all kinds of assessment:
multiple-choice tests, essay tests, observations of student performance, interviews,
portfolios (collections of students’ products), norm-referenced tests (tests that
compare one student’ s performance with that of a norm group of students), and
criterion-referenced tests (tests that compare onestudent’ s performance with an
established standard).
An example of the potential importance of combining content with process, so
as to replace process-product research with (process ↔content)-product research
The Change from “Process” to “Process ´ Content” 53
can be seen in the “somewhat disappointing” (D. W. Ryan et al., 1989, p. 28) results
of the massive process-product investigation of teaching in nine countries. Carried
out by the International Association for the Evaluation of Educational Achievement
(IEA), the research dwarfed previous efforts to find relationships between teaching
and achievement.
In seeking to explain the disappointing results, we note the first of D. W. Ryan’s
“generalizations”: “Within countries, teachers differ greatly in what they teach rela-
tive to what is tested” (p. 29). Thus, the study collected data primarily on teachers’
processes, and found those processes disappointingly related to student achie ve-
ment, which was, of course, affected by the content of the teacher’s teaching, or the
degree to which that content ga ve her students “opportunity to learn. ” In Chap. 6,
we refer to “instructional alignment,” or the degree to which what is taught is simi-
lar to what is tested. The teacher’ s teaching should be described not only in terms
of her process but also in terms of her content.
A variable related to instructional alignment is transfer demand (S. A. Cohen,
1987), or “the de gree to which the stimulus conditions of instruction match the
stimulus conditions of assessment” of achie vement. This variable is considered to
be inversely related to instructional alignment; the higher the alignment, the lo wer
the transfer demand.
Another major content v ariable, further considered in Chap. 8, is cognitive
load (Sweller, 1999), or the de gree to which the (process ↔content) of teaching
(a) requires the students to split their attention, that is, pay attention to tw o or
more sources of stimuli at the same time, such as a visual presentation and a
not-closely-integrated oral presentation, (b) presents tasks with interacti ve
elements, or concepts and ideas that cannot be understood one at a time because
the meaning of one depends on the meaning of one or more others; or (c)
requires conventional problem solving as against letting students study w orked-
out examples.
Similarly, a strong case can be made for concern with student’ s thought proc-
esses in attempts to e xplain, predict, or impro ve student achie vement. Winne and
Marx (1987), in particular , argued for the v alue of incorporating data on student’ s
thought processes (Cate gory E) in the search for impro ved explanations of teach-
ing’s effects on student achievement.
The teacher’ s kno wledge of the content being taught matures as the teacher
acquires experience. As Gage (1979) put it,
Experienced teachers have often noted that their years of teaching ha ve given them exten-
sive repertoires of ef fective e xplanations, demonstrations, illustrations, e xamples, dia-
grams, and anecdotes for the myriads of concepts and principles that the y teach and the
many understandings and skills that the y help their students acquire. Just as medicine and
engineering have not shrunk from these levels of complexity in their research and develop-
ment, so research on teaching may also need to do the f ine-grained work that will yield
better ways of teaching a specif ic skill (such as long di vision) to a specif ic kind of pupil
(such as an anxious fifth-grader). (p. 273)
Pedagogical content knowledge manifests itself in the degree to which the teach-
ing of a particular segment of content reflects such kinds of kno wledge as
(a) the main, or most frequently taught, concepts in the content area,
(b) different conceptions of the subject, such as ho w it has been changing o ver
time, what topics have been recently become prominent, and which ones are on
the way out;
(c) metaphors, similar to similes, without the “lik e,” for e xplaining a concept or
principle;
(d) analogies that help clarify a particular concept or principle by lik ening it to a
more familiar or better understood concept or principle;
(e) examples, which give concrete and familiar instances of a particular concept or
principle;
(f) mnemonics, or memory aids, for remembering such things as the rhyming
scheme of a sonnet (abab, cdcd, efef, gg); and
(g) the difficulty of various topics, or the de gree to which students f ind them hard
to understand and the reasons for which the y are difficult.
Gess-Newsome and Lederman (1999) pro vided applications of pedagogical
content knowledge to science education.
So the present conception of teaching is that it becomes the proper subject of theory
development when it is specif ied for the purpose of fostering a certain kind of
learning appropriate to a certain kind of curriculum. Figure 3.6 brings together the
resulting six cate gories of variables. The tw o-way arrows connecting pairs of cat-
egories denote relationships between the concepts in each pair of categories – rela-
tionships of the kind that can be re vealed by case studies, correlational studies, or
experiments.
A Paradigm for the Study of Teaching 55
The fifteen possible relationships sho wn by the arro ws in Fig. 3.6 need to be
evaluated as to their promise for theory and research. It is concei vable that strong
theoretical and empirical relationships could be found in all f ifteen cases.
9. Context >< Student Achievement. Reducing class size seemed to impro ve stu-
dent achie vement. Or lo w student achie vement in writing made the school
board willing to improve school libraries.
10.Teachers’ Thought Processes >< Process↔Content of Teaching. A teacher who
pondered about how to improve her classroom management skills was then able
to keep her class more engaged in learning acti vities. Or the teacher’s success in
fostering a genuine discussion made her think about why it had gone so well.
11.
Teachers’ Thought Processes >< Student’s Thought Processes. A teacher’s high
expectations of her students’ performance may raise the students’ aspirations.
Or students’ formulations of the content may influence their teacher’ s percep-
tions of her students.
12.Teachers’ Thought Processes >< Student Achievement. Teachers’ beliefs about
the importance of certain scientific facts may influence student comprehension
of that content . Or student achievement of high-level cognitive objectives may
make the teachers value that content more.
13.The Process↔Content of Teaching >< Student’s Thought Processes. Teachers’
interactions with students may influence their students’ aspirations. Or students’
interest in the content may mak e teachers use the same approach ne xt time.
14.The Process↔Content of Teaching><Student Achievement. A debate between
the two groups of students resulted in impro ved student understanding of the
issue. Or students’inability to apply a principle influenced the teacher to
arrange for an exhibit of illustrative applications.
15.Student’s Thought Processes><Student Achievement. Students’ pessimism
affected their learning to multiply fractions. Or student achievement of the abil-
ity to apply a principle raised their moti vation to learn the subject matter.
right to the v ery next category of the paradigm. This means that relationships will
be considered in detail only between the follo wing sets of categories:
1. Categories A and B in relation to Cate gory C
2. Cate
gory C in relation to Category D
3. Cate
gory D in relation to Category E
4. Cate
gory E in relati on to Category F
1. The relationships of Cate gories A (presage variables) and B (conte xt variables)
to Cate gory C (teacher’ s thought process): Psychologists ha ve often endorsed
the proposition that behavior is a function of the personality interacting with the
environment.
One basis for developing theory would be to classify teaching methods and prac-
tices and mak e profiles of them on the basis of specif ied dimensions. These could
then be used as descriptions of the classroom processes used by teachers.
How do the three components of the ternary relationship – teaching, learning,
and curriculum – fit into this paradigm? The answer is that the conceptual anteced-
ents of teaching are the presage, conte xt, and teacher’s thought-process categories.
That is, all of the v ariables in these cate gories shape the content and processes of
teaching. And the classroom processes, in turn, influence the students’ thought
processes and achievement.
The theory of teaching should particularly e xplain the relationships between
classroom process ↔content and student achie vement. The relationships between
presage v ariables, conte xt v ariables, teacher’ s thought processes and the
process↔content of teaching ha ve been addressed by Schoenfeld (1998). In his
Toward a Theory of Teaching-in-Context, he attempted to “provide a detailed theo-
retical account of ho w and why teachers do what the y do ‘online,’ – that is, while
they are engaged in the art of teaching” (p. 1). He was concerned with “the ways in
which the teachers’ goals, beliefs, and knowledge interact, resulting in the teachers’
moment-to-moment decision-making and actions” (p. 1). He w as engaged in
“explaining, at a f ine-grained level of detail, ho w and why teachers mak e specific
decisions and take specific actions as they are engaged in teaching” (p. 1).
Other categories of the paradigm – presage, context, and teacher’s thought proc-
ess – are central to Schoenfeld’ s focus on teachers’ specific decisions and specific
actions as the dependent variable. Connection between these cate gories and the
heart of teaching, what goes on in the classroom, is e xtremely consequential. The
present focus is on teachers’ decisions and actions as the independent v ariables
with student achievement as the dependent variable. Thus, the process ↔content-
achievement paradigm will be the focus of the present theory of teaching.
The category that interv enes between classroom process ↔content and student
achievement consists of student’ s thought processes. Although Student’ s Thought
Processes are neither visible nor audible and, hence, are not directly observ able,
they can be studied by inferences from other kinds of data described in Chap. 8.
Depending on the specif ic forms of each of these processes, the y can either foster
or hamper learning.
58 3 The Evolution of a Paradigm for the Study of Teaching
Intra-Category Relationships
Each cate gory contains man y concepts. Relationships between concepts can be
intra-category, that is, relationships between concepts within a single cate gory, or
inter-category, relationships between concepts in different categories.
Intra-category relationships elucidate the structure of the cate gory – its dimen-
sions and divisions. Thus, within the presage cate gory we could seek relationships
between the teacher’s scholastic aptitude and her pedagogical content kno wledge,
or between her socioeconomic background and her sensitivity to social-class differ-
ences among students.
Inter-Category Relationships
Multivariate Relationships
Relationships can also be multi variate in the sense that tw o or more v ariables can
correlate with a third, as in a multiple correlation. An e xample would be Rx.yz , the
correlation between x (achievement) and the student’s (y) scholastic aptitude and (z )
prior knowledge. Or the relationship between two variables can be studied in terms
of how a third v ariable is held constant, as in partial correlation, rxy,z. An example
would be the correlation between x (achievement) and y (scholastic aptitude) with
z (socioeconomic status) held constant.
The lar ge number of concepts or v ariables within each of the six cate gories
indicates the enormous number of relationships that could possibly be studied. This
enormousness requires that only a few of these relationships be chosen for theoriz-
ing, that is, for an attempt to e xplain their relationships. Choices here will reflect
the investigators’ interests and concerns.
Ways of Describing the Process of Teaching 59
Instructional alignment
But one variable characteristic of the content that is hypothesized to correlate with
student achievement of the objectives of the teaching in that content is the content’s
“instructional alignment. ” This term designates the similarity , or congruence,
between the content taught and the assessments of achievement in that content area.
60 3 The Evolution of a Paradigm for the Study of Teaching
One hypothesizes that achie vement will be high. If the instructional alignment is
high. That is, there should be a positive correlation between the instructional align-
ment of the teaching and the student achie vement of the objecti ves of that
teaching.
The process component of the process↔content category refers, to put it sim-
ply, to the way in which the teaching has gone on. Here, the number of descriptive
concepts is also indefinitely large. But the one on which we focus first is instruc-
tional time, or the aspects of the duration of time during which the teaching of a
particular part of subject matter , or content, has proceeded (Ben-P aretz &
Bromme, 1990).
Another concept in the content part of the process ↔content cate gory, is the
resultant of the teacher’ s pedagogical content knowledge (Shulman, 1986a; 1987;
Gess-Newsome & Lederman, Eds., 1999). Such pedagogical content kno wledge
manifests itself in the degree to which the teaching of a particular se gment of con-
tent reflects (a) the main, or most frequently taught concepts in the content area, (b)
different conceptions of the subject such as ho w it has been changing o ver time,
what topics have been recently become prominent, and which ones are on the w ay
out; (c) metaphors, similar to similes, without the “lik e,” (d) analogies that helped
clarify a particular concept by lik ening it to a more f amiliar or better understood
concept or principle; (e) examples, which give concrete and familiar instances of a
particular concept or principle, (f) mnemonics, or memory aids, for remembering
such things as the rhyming scheme of a sonnet (abab, cdcd, efef, gg); and (g) the
difficulty of various, i.e., topics or the de gree to which students f ind them hard to
understand.
Chapter 4
A Conception of the Process of Teaching
How teaching happens, what the teacher and students say and do, what students
experience as the y see and hear the teacher and their classmates in the classroom
– all these and more add up to the process of teaching. “Teaching” encompasses
what teachers do in helping their students learn and perform the tasks – listening,
thinking, speaking, reading, writing, solving problems, answering questions, inves-
tigating, and so on – as prescribed, recommended, or suggested by the teacher. The
process of teaching should be inte grated with the content of teaching. The f acts,
ideas, knowledge, understandings, concepts, principles, acti vities, theories, proce-
dures, and the like, help students understand the curriculum.
Since antiquity, Plato and other philosophers ha ve devised, demonstrated, and
advocated various processes of teaching. Broudy (1963) de veloped the historical
narrative on processes of teaching into the nineteenth century .
One e xample of eighteenth century writing on the process of teaching is
Rousseau’s Émile, which e xemplified a “romantic” vie w of good teaching – one
that gave students well-nigh complete freedom to explore on their own. Wallen and
Travers (1963) wrote about Rousseau and his predecessor , Froebel, as follows:
Like Rousseau …. [Froebel was influenced by the concept that development will proceed
harmoniously of its o wn accord if the child is pro vided with a suitable en vironment.
Emphasis w as placed on the indi vidual w orth of each child, and teacher beha vior had
to be such that it did not do violence to the natural la ws of the gro wing organism. The
teacher must be permissive so that the natural process of development will not be violated.
(p. 455)
Skinner (1974), the f amous beha viorist, of fered this comment on Rousseau’ s Émile :
His name is Émile. He w as born in the middle of the eighteenth century in the f irst flush
of the modern concern for personal freedom. His f ather was Jean-Jacques Rousseau. But
he had man y foster parents, among them Pestalozzi, Froebel, and Montessori, do wn to
A. S. Neill and Ivan Ilich. He is an ideal student. Full of goodwill to ward his teachers and
his peers, he needs no discipline. He studies because he is naturally curious. He learns
things because they interest him.
Unfortunately, he is imaginary. He was quite explicitly so with Rousseau, who put his
own children into an orphanage and preferred to say ho w he w ould teach his f ictional
hero, but the modern version of the free and happy student to be found in books by P aul
Goodman, John Holt, Jonathan K ozol, or Charles Silberman is also imaginary .
Occasionally a real example seems to turn up. There are teachers who would be success-
ful anywhere – as statesmen, therapists, businessmen, or friends – and there are students
who scarcely need to be taught, and together they sometimes seem to bring Émile to life.
And unfortunately the y do so often enough to sustain the old dream. But Émile is a
willow-the-wisp, who has led many teachers into a conception of their role which could
prove disastrous. (p. 3)
Even in the relatively short history of empirical research on teaching, that is, in the
second half of the twentieth century , empirical researchers have formulated, advo-
cated, and studied man y kinds of teaching. Empirical research be gan in the 1890s
with the pioneering w ork of Joseph Mayer Rice (1897), b ut cited in Rice (1913) .
Since then, researchers have developed and studied a large array of different kinds
of process. Rice found no correlation between amount of time used by the teachers
for teaching spelling and the achie vement of their students on a spelling test. He
used this finding to inveigh against “the spelling grind.”
A model of the process of teaching is a specific and integrated set of teaching prin-
ciples and practices for use by teachers who accept the model’ s implicit or explicit
conception of effective teaching. Models often contain special materials and manu-
als for the teacher using the model. Books describing collections of models of
teaching have brought together, defined, and described groups of models. One fre-
quently updated collection – Models of Teaching (Joyce, Weil, & Calhoun, 2000)
– identified, categorized, and described four “families” of models containing a total
of 20 models of teaching shown in Table 4.1.
Researchers have studied some of these varieties of process to see how effective
they are in helping students achie ve cogniti ve objecti ves. Some models are also
designed to foster the achievement of social and emotional objectives.
Probably none of these 20 models of teaching, with one exception discussed below,
has been studied and used by more than a fe w thousand of the 3.5 million U.S.
teachers (National Center for Education Statistics, 2000, p. 48).* We make it easier
to understand these models by putting them into tw o cate gories, namely ,
Progressive-Discovery-Constructivist models in grades 1–12 and Con ventional-
Direct-Recitation models.
*
I was unable to find a statistical survey of how often these or other models are used.
Two Categories of Models 63
Progressive–Discovery–Constructivist Teaching
to the means by which one constructed it …. Hearing a lecture – in the e vent that one is
understanding it – requires an active construction of meaning. Listening, like reading, is far
from being a passive, purely receptive activity. (p. 134)
issue has pro vided o verwhelming and unambiguous e vidence that minimal guidance
during instruction is signif icantly less ef fective and ef ficient than guidance specif ically
designed to support the cognitive processing necessary for learning. (p. 76)
Further,
After a half-century of adv ocacy associated with instruction using minimal guidance, it
appears that there is no body of research supporting the technique. In so f ar as there is any
evidence from controlled studies, it almost uniformly supports direct, strong instructional
guidance rather than constructivist-based minimal guidance during the instruction of no v-
ice-to-intermediate learners. Ev en for students with considerable prior kno wledge, strong
guidance while learning is most often found to be equally effective as unguided approaches.
Not only is unguided instruction normally less ef fective; there is also evidence that it may
have negative results when students acquire misconceptions or incomplete or disorganized
knowledge. (pp. 83–84)
The question of whether the comparisons between PDC and CDR were made on
the basis of assessments that w ould be considered f air to PDC teaching can be
considered in terms of the kinds of outcomes measured in the studies cited by
Kirschner et al., (2006). Here a typical statement, of a kind that occurs repeatedly ,
is the following:
Klahr and Nigam (2004), in a very important study, not only tested whether science learn-
ers learned more via a discovery versus direct instruction route but also, once learning had
occurred, whether the quality of learning differed. Specifically, they tested whether those
who had learned through discovery were better able to transfer their learning to new con-
texts. The f indings were unambiguous. Direct instruction, in volving considerable guid-
ance, including examples, resulted in vastly more learning than discovery. Those relatively
few students who learned via disco very showed no signs of superior quality of learning.
(pp. 79–80)
problem-based learning “does indeed deemphasize guidance” (p. 115) and thereby
increase cogniti ve load. The second (Hmelo-Silv er, Duncan, & Chin, 2007)
objected to the characterization of problem-based learning and inquiry learning as
unguided disco very learning which increases cogniti ve load because “Surely the
raison d’etre of problem-based learning is to deemphasize direct instructional
guidance (p. 115). The third (Kuhn, 1962) objected to the Kirschner-Sweller-Clark
argument on the grounds that it ignored the problem of what to teach by focusing
on the less important issue of how to teach. The three papers lea ve the case for
conventional-direct-recitation (CDR) teaching still ar guable in a w ay that calls
for the sharpening of the issue by means of further e xperimentation. The case
against the desirability of a theory of PDC teaching gets stronger when we consider
studies of how most teachers actually teach, as summarized belo w.
Conventional–Direct–Recitation Teaching
As we’ve already noted, observations and other evidence suggest that most, by far,
of 3.5 million U.S. teachers in grades 1–12 are still using a different model, namely,
Conventional-Direct-Recitation (CDR) teaching. CDR designates a contrasting,
non-PDC f amily of teaching. The term “con ventional” refers to the ubiquity of
CDR teaching since early in the twentieth century in the United States. vestigations
In
of how teachers have taught (for example, Cuban, 1984, 1988; Goodlad, 1984), and
are presumably still teaching, have supported the inference that most U.S. teachers
practice CDR teaching.
The term “direct” refers to teaching that is teacher-directed and structured, so that
the teacher chooses most student activities. The term “recitation” refers to the almost
universal pattern whereby the teachers ask questions, and the students respond.
The CDR model flourished in the U.S. throughout the twentieth century ,
even as alternati ves of the PDC kind were widely discussed and adv ocated.
Rosenshine (1987) described CDR teaching as “explicit,” and listed its compo-
nents as follows:
• Begin a lesson with a short statement of goals.
• Begin a lesson with a short re view of previous, prerequisite learning.
• Present new material in small steps, with student practice after each step.
• Give clear and detailed instructions and e xplanations.
• Provide a high level of active practice for all students and obtain responses from
all students.
• Guide students during initial practice.
• Provide systematic feedback and corrections.
• Provide explicit instruction and practice for seatwork exercises and, when necessary,
monitor students during seatwork.
• Continue practice until students are independent and conf ident (p. 76).
Two Categories of Models 67
Rosenshine and Meister (1995, pp. 143–149) identified five variations of “direct
teaching”:
(a) theteacher-led meaning;
(b) the teacher effectiveness meaning, that is, a set of teaching actions derived from
empirical research on teacher effectiveness;
(c) the cogniti ve strate gies meaning, in which researchers de veloped w ays of
teaching cognitive strategies – such as summarizing, reading comprehension,
and question-generation – and labeled their teaching “direct teaching”;
(d) the DISTAR (Direct Instructional Systems in Arithmetic and Reading) meaning,
which referred to (i) an explicit step-by-step strategy; (ii) development of mastery
at each step in the process; (iii) specific strategy corrections for student errors; (iv)
gradual transition from teacher -directed activities toward independent w ork; (v)
use of adequate and systematic practice through a range of e xamples of the task;
(vi) many classroom settings in which instruction is led by the teacher, particularly
settings in which the teacher lectures and the students sit passi vely, and (vii) the
undesirable-teaching meaning, which refers to direct teaching as “authoritarian, ”
“regimented,” “fact accumulation at the e xpense of thinking-skill de velopment,”
and “focusing on tests.” (Rosenshine & Meister, 1995, pp. 143–149);
(e) Another usage of “direct instruction,” referred to a model developed by Engelmann
(1980) that emphasizes the use of carefully prepared lessons, designed around a
highly specified knowledge base and a well-def ined set of skills for each subject.
A central element of the theory underlying Direct Instruction is that clear instruc-
tion eliminates misinterpretations and can greatly improve and accelerate learning.
(American Institutes for Research, 1999, p. 63);
(f) Cuban (1988) used the term “teacher-centered instruction” as his label for what
was essentially CDR:
A cumbersome phrase, teacher -centered instruction tries to capture a common
form of instruction where teachers generally teach to the whole group of
students in a class, sho w high concern for whether students are listening, con-
centrate mostly on subject matter and academic skills, and, in general, control
what is taught, when, and under what conditions. (p. 27);
(g) Jo
yce et al. (2000) provided another description:
The most prominent features [of CDR teaching] are an academic focus, a high
degree of teacher direction and control, high e xpectations of pupil progress, a sys-
tem for managing time, and an atmosphere of relati vely neutral affect. (p. 338);
(h) Burns (1984) summarized “descriptors of direct instruction gleaned from the recent
reviews of research on teaching” (p. 106). His compilation is sho wn in Table 4.4.
In short, CDR teaching is relati vely highly structured, and the student plays a
seemingly, but not actually, passive role along lines established by the teacher . Of
the 20 models described by Jo yce et al. (2000), CDR is probably by f ar the most
widely used. Cuban’s history, How Teachers Taught (1984) described CDR as the
almost universal process of teaching in the United States between 1890 and 1980.
Goodlad’s A Place Called School (1984) , in describing the process of teaching
68 4 A Conception of the Process of Teaching
Table 4.4 Snapshot data: rank order of activities by probability of students having been observed
participating in each at any particular moment
Early elementary activity % Upper elementary activity %
Writtenwork 28.3 Writtenwork 30.4
Listening to explanations/lectures 18.2 Listening to explanations/lectures 20.1
Preparation for assignments 12.7 Preparation for assignments 11.5
Practice/performance – physical 7.3 Practice/performance – physical 7.7
Use of AV equipment 6.8 Use of AV equipment 5.5
Reading 6.0 Reading 5.3
Student non-task behavior – 5.7 Student non-task behavior – 4.9
no assignment no assignment
Discussion 5.3 Discussion 4.8
Practice/performance – verbal 5.2 Practice/performance – verbal 4.4
Taking tests 2.2 Taking tests 3.3
Watching demonstrations 1.5 Watching demonstrations 1.0
Beingdisciplined 0.5 Beingdisciplined 0.4
Stimulation/roleplay 0.2 Stimulation/roleplay 0.3
Junior high activity % Senior high activity %
Writtenwork 21.9 Writtenwork 25.3
Listening to explanations/lectures 20.7 Listening to explanations/lectures 17.5
Preparation for assignments 15.9 Preparation for assignments 15.1
Practice/performance – physical 14.7 Practice/performance – physical 12.8
Use of AV equipment 5.5 Use of AV equipment 6.9
Reading 4.2 Reading 5.8
Student non-task behavior – 4.2 Student non-task behavior – 5.1
no assignment no assignment
Discussion 4.1 Discussion 4.5
Practice/performance – verbal 3.6 Practice/performance – verbal 2.8
Taking tests 2.8 Taking tests 1.9
Watching demonstrations 1.5 Watching demonstrations 1.6
Beingdisciplined 0.2 Beingdisciplined 0.1
Stimulation/roleplay 0.2 Stimulation/roleplay 0.1
Source: Burns (1984, p. 107)
A Historical Study
Cuban’s How Teachers Taught (1984) provided historical information on what kind
of teaching occurred in U.S. classrooms during the twentieth century . Cuban used
an array of non-observational kinds of evidence:
how classroom furniture and space were arranged, what manner of grouping for instruction
the teacher used (whole class, small groups, and so forth), classroom talk by teacher and
students, activities that students and teacher engaged in (recita tion, discussion, reports, tests,
film, lecture, and so forth), and the amount of physical movement allowed the student within
the classroom. These cate gories were visible signs of ho w teacher-centered the class w as.
As it turned out, the de grees of difference over the decades were quite small (pp. 28–29).
Cuban inferred that, from 1890 to 1980, despite widespread and intense discus-
sion, advocacy, and rationalizing rhetoric f avoring PDC teaching – the majority of
U.S. teachers continued to use CDR. In summary , Cuban (1984) wrote:
Drawn from a large number of varied sources in diverse settings, over nearly a century, the
data show striking convergence in outlining a stable core of teacher -centered instructional
activities in the elementary school and, in high school classrooms, a remarkably pure and
durable version of the same set of acti vities. (p. 238)
Observational Studies
Researchers’ observations of classrooms were rare until about 1960. Some of the
better kno wn observ ational studies were done by Bellack, Kliebard, Hyman, &
Smith (1966), Hoetk er and Ahlbrand (1969), Mehan (1979), and Goodlad (1984).
Although the researchers used different terminologies, the overall portrait suggested
great uniformity in how teaching went on throughout the twentieth century for virtu-
ally all grade levels and subject matters. CDR teaching apparently pre vailed.
Within the uniformity of the CDR model of teaching, we f ind what Bellack et al.
(1966) called, in the title of their extraordinarily thorough monograph, The Language
70 4 A Conception of the Process of Teaching
Table 4.6
1. STR
2. STR SOL
3. STR REA
4. STR REA REA…
5. STR SOL RES…
6. STR SOL RES RES…
7. STR SOL REA
8. STR SOL REA REA…
9. STR SOL RES REA
10. STR SOL RES REA REA…
11. STR SOL RES REA RES…
12. STR SOL RES REA RES… REA …
13. SOL
14. SOL RES
15. SOL RES
16. SOL REA
17. SOL REA REA…
18. SOL RES
19. REA REA REA
20. REA REA…
21. SOL RES REA RES…REA
…REA …
STR structuring, SOL soliciting, RES responding, REA reacting
pare Bellack et al. ’s Soliciting]. A rhetorical question, on the other hand, is commonly under -
stood to be uttered for its dramatic or rhetorical ef fect, but some do serve to trigger discussion.
When a reply is made to a direct question [compare Bellack et al. ’s Responding], it is also a
convention that the reply itself be acknowledged in some way, at least by word or gesture if not
by further responding commentary or questioning [compare Bellack et al. ’s Reacting]. (p. 14)
Table 4.7 Comparisons between selected mean measures of classroom v erbal beha vior in
Bellack, et al. (1966) and Hoetk er and Ahlbrand (1969)
Bellack Hoetker
et al. and Ahlbrand
Measure (1966) * (1969)
A. Percentage of teacher talk, mo ves 61.7 65.7
B. Percentage of teacher talk, lines of typescript 72.1 74.5
C. Distribution of teacher moves, as percentage of all mo ves
STRUCTURING 4.8 3.6
SOLICITING 28.8 32.3
RESPONDING 3.5 1.8
REACTING 24.3 27.0
D. Distribution of pupil moves, as percentage of all mo ves
STRUCTURING 0.4 0.3
SOLICITING 4.4 2.0
RESPONDING 25.0 30.4
REACTING 5.7 1.1
E. Distribution of teacher moves, as percentage of total lines
of typescript
STRUCTURING 14.5 22.4
SOLICITING 20.3 20.6
RESPONDING 5.0 4.3
REACTING 24.8 31.4
F. Distribution of pupil moves, as percentage of total lines
of typescript
STRUCTURING 3.0 3.4
SOLICITING 2.5 1.2
RESPONDING 15.6 13.1
REACTING 5.1 0.6
G. Percentage of teacher questions calling for memory processes 80.8* 87.9
The evidence gathered by Hoetk er and Ahlbrand (1969) strongly suggests that this class-
room language game has had a long and persistent history. Records of observational studies
from the turn of the nineteenth century indicate that the game has not changed substantially
in approximately 60 years. (p. 52)
Mehan (1979)
Studying a single class of pupils in grades 1–3 for a whole school year , Mehan
(1979) reported that the class exhibited three of Bellack et al.’s four components of
a teaching cycle: (a) “initiation” (compare the structuring and soliciting of Bellack
et al.), (b) “responding,” typically by students (compare the responding of Bellack
et al.), and (c) “evaluating” (compare the reacting of Bellack et al.).
Empirical Studies of the Process of Teaching 73
Goodlad (1984)
These findings represent a departure from the findings of Bellack et al., concern-
ing teachers’ reacting, in that Goodlad’ s teachers’ reactions betoken mere general,
non-specific acknowledgment of students’ responses.
In summary , the typical classroom patterns – as reported in A Place Called
School – consisted of the teacher’s (a) explaining or lecturing to the whole class or
to a single student (compare structuring), (b) asking direct, factual questions on the
subject matter, or monitoring students (compare soliciting), (c) the students’ ostensibly
listening to the teacher and responding to teacher -initiated interaction (compare
responding) and (d) the teacher’ s providing non-specific acknowledgement of stu-
dents’ responses.
We can sort Sirotnik’s descriptions according to the cate gories of Bellack et al.
(1966). Such sorting indicates that the f indings of A Study of Schools (Sirotnik,
1983) agree well with the structuring-soliciting-responding-reacting analysis of
classroom teaching constructed by Bellack et al. (1966), and confirmed by Hoetker
and Ahlbrand (1969) and Mehan (1979).
74 4 A Conception of the Process of Teaching
Working with the data from Goodlad’ s study of 1,017 teachers, Sirotnik (1983)
summarized some of the f indings, in ways that can be aligned with the cate gories
of Bellack et al. (1966):
(a) Structuring. “Nearly 70 percent of the total class time in volves verbal interaction, or
‘talk’ …. Less than a f ifth of the time involves student talk.” (Sirotnik, 1983, p. 20)
(b)Soliciting. “[W]e find that barely five percent of the instructional time is spent on direct
questioning — questioning which anticipates a specif ic response lik e ‘yes, ’ ‘no, ’
‘Columbus,’ or ‘1492. ’ Less than 1 percent of that time is de voted to open questions
which call for more complex cognitive or affective responses.” (Sirotnik, 1983, p. 20)
(c)Responding. “[T]he most frequently occurring single interaction, is one of students
responding to the teacher …. This occurs roughly 15 percent and 10 percent of the time
at the elementary and secondary levels, respectively.” (Sirotnik, 1983, p. 20)
(d)Reacting. “[L]ess than 5 percent of teacher’ s time is spent responding to students,
which, as will be seen shortly, is less than the percentage of time students are observed
initiating interaction with the teacher …. Providing corrective feedback in combination
with additional information designed to help students understand and correct their
mistakes is almost none xistent. In f act, reinforcement of an y kind is rarely noticed,
whether in the form of specif ic task-related ackno wledgement and praise or general
support and encouragement.” (Sirotnik, 1983, p. 20)
In summary, according to Sirotnik (1983, pp. 20–21),
The model classroom pattern consists of the teacher’s (a) [structuring, that is,] explaining
or lecturing to the whole class or to a single student; (b) [soliciting, that is,] then asking
direct, factual questions on the subject matter , or monitoring students; (c) [responding, that
is,] the students ostensibly listening to the teacher or responding to a teacher -initiated inter-
action; and (d) [reacting, that is,] mere acknowledgement of students’ responses rather than
the teacher’s indicating whether the student’ s response w as correct and going on to other
relevant comments.
So we can sort these quotations from Goodlad’s large-scale study according to the
Bellack et al. categories. Doing so indicates that the findings of A Place Called School
(Goodlad, 1984; Sirotnik, 1983) – concur substantially with the structuring-soliciting-
responding-reacting analysis of classroom teaching constructed by Smith et al.
(1962), and Bellack et al. (1966), Hoetk er and Ahlbrand (1969), and Mehan (1979).
Apparently, the CDR conception of the teaching process is not unique to classroom
teaching, b ut has more general applicability . It is similar to the conception of
instruction discernible in the “frames” of computer -assisted instruction. In the fol-
lowing comparisons, material quoted from Computer Based Instruction (Alessi &
Trollip, 1985) is italicized:
(a) Suchframes begin with “a piece of instruction,” ranging in size from a sentence to a
long paragraph, concerning some aspect of the subject matter being taught [compare
Bellack et al.’s “structuring”];
(b) The next part of the frame is a “ question or problem addressed to the student ” [com-
pare Bellack et al.’s “soliciting”];
The Generalizability of the CDR Model 75
(c) Thestudent then “replies” to this question or problem [compare Bellack et al. ’s
“responding”];
(d) The cycle is completed by gi ving the student an “ evaluation of response” (“Right” or
“Wrong”) [compare Bellack et al.’s “reacting”].
Classroom observations have suggested that teaching in U.S. schools consists typi-
cally of a series of c ycles, or e xchanges between the teacher and students, of the
kind originally described by Smith et al., (1962) on logical grounds and subsequently
by Bellack et al., (1966), Hoetk er and Ahlbrand (1969), Mehan (1979), and, by
inference, Sirotnik (1983), and the frames of computer -assisted instruction.
The cycle repeats – sometimes with modifications such as those shown in Table
4.5, which do not change the essential character of the process: Structuring leads to
soliciting which leads to responding which leads to reacting.
So far, we have presented evidence on CDR teaching only from U.S. studies. Does
it also predominate in other countries, in other cultures? Smith et al., (1962)
assumed it does:
Teaching is here assumed to be a social phenomenon, fundamentally the same from one
culture to another [italics added]. It has its o wn elements, forms, re gularities, and prob-
lems. It tak es place under what seems to be a relati vely constant set of conditions—time
limits, authority figures, student ability limits, institutional structures, etc. (p. 2)
The IEA Classroom Environment Study (Anderson, Ryan, & Shapiro, 1989) –
conducted under the auspices of the International Association for the Evaluation of
Educational Achievement (IEA) – studied precisely this question. The ten partici-
pating political entities were Australia, Canada (Ontario, English), Canada (Ontario,
French), Canada (Quebec), Hungary, Israel, South Korea, the Netherlands, Nigeria,
and Thailand.
Classroom observation while teaching is underw ay provides the best e vidence
on the process of teaching – b ut it is also e xpensive. So only f ive of the re gions
provided such e vidence: Australia, Canada (Ontario, English), Canada (Ontario,
French), Canada (Quebec), and Hungary. The subject taught and therefore observed
76 4 A Conception of the Process of Teaching
in four of these five political entities was mathematics (Ryan, Hildyard, & Bourke,
1989, p. 48). In Hungary, physics was taught. All five of these political entities used
the same observation schedules, trained observers the same way, and obtained sub-
stantial agreement between observers. Mandeville (1989) summarized the teaching
in these five political entities as follows:
First, most lessons were di vided into two or more segments, lasting an average of 10 to 15
minutes each. Second, during review, oral practice, lecture, and discourse segments, teachers
typically assumed a v ery directive, interactive role with their students. During written or
laboratory seatwork segments, however, role differentiation between teachers in many coun-
tries w as evident. In many seatwork segments, teachers engaged in what may be termed
“teaching” (that is, they explained concepts and skills to their students, asked questions and
reacted to their responses).
Third, teachers generally spent a great deal of time providing explanations, asking ques-
tions, and reacting to answers to those questions during the entire lesson. These behaviors
were fairly common in review, oral practice, lecture, and discourse segments [italics
added]. (p. 145)
The studies of CDR teaching in the U. S. dealt with subject matter that is e xpressed
primarily in w ords – namely , international trade (Bellack et al., 1966), English
(Hoetker & Ahlbrand, 1969), and the v aried content of a class for combined grades
1–3 (Mehan, 1979), So we might question whether the CDR model also pre vails for
largely nonverbal subjects, such as mathematics and science. Here again, The IEA
Classroom Environment Study is helpful, because the subject taught in four of the five
participating political entities – Australia, Canada (Ontario, English), Canada (Ontario,
French), Canada (Quebec) – was mathematics. In the fifth (Hungary), it was physics.
Since the IEA study did not report that their findings differed from those for
verbal subjects, as taught outside the United States, we can reasonably infer
that the same teaching processes were observ ed for mathematics and physics.
Present Status of the Search for the Prevalent Model of Teaching 77
So the IEA Study’s findings further support the ubiquity of CDR teaching. The
IEA study dealt with man y aspects of teaching other than its process, such as
content taught, student characteristics, school v ariables, and v ariables in stu-
dents’ homes.
In summarizing what the IEA Study’ s observers learned about the structure of
lessons, Mandeville (1989) reported:
[T]eachers generally spent a great deal of time pro viding explanations, asking questions,
and reacting [italics added] to answers to those questions during the entire lesson. These
behaviors were f airly common in re view, oral practice, lecture, and discourse se gments.
Although not as predominant, these behaviors also were evident while students worked on
assigned tasks at their seats. (p. 145)
The close resemblance of this description in the f ive U.S. observational studies
(Bellack et al., 1966; Cuban, 1984; Goodlad, 1984; Hoetk er & Ahlbrand, 1969;
Mehan, 1979) suggests that teachers of both v erbal and highly non-v erbal subject
matter follow the same conventional model of teaching.
Perhaps the most persuasive basis for accepting the prevalence of CDR teaching in
U.S. schools is not to be found in research of an y kind, however valid. Rather, its
well-established ascendanc y may reside in the memories of this book’ s readers,
recalling their o wn classes on their w ay to earning a high school diploma. Those
recollections assure us that we ha ve not erred in selecting CDR teaching as the
model for our theory and our attempt to explain its effectiveness. A comment from
Goodlad (1984) should ring a bell for man y readers:
The classrooms we observ ed were more lik e than unlike those in the old images so man y
of us share. Usually we sa w desks or tables arranged in ro ws, oriented toward the teacher
at the front of the room. Instructional amenities such as library corners, occasionally
present in elementary classrooms, were rarely observed in secondary classes. The homelike
chairs and rugs sometimes seen in primary classes rapidly became rare with upw ard pro-
gression through the grades…. The central focus is on teachers’ pedagogical practices –
grouping, individualizing, using time, making decisions. (p. 94)
When all is said and done, we must question our conclusions about CDR. We have
used inductive logic, in compiling e vidence on its pre valence. That is, if repeated
observations yield the same result, namely , the pre valence of CDR, can it be
regarded as proven to be true?
78 4 A Conception of the Process of Teaching
As philosophers (Hume, 1758; Popper, 1965) famously pointed out, inductive logic
cannot prove the ine vitability of a conclusion. No matter ho w much e vidence –
stenographic, historical, observ ational, or remembered personal e xperience – is
accumulated, we cannot logically conclude, on the basis of inductive logic, that we
have identified the model of teaching used by most teachers in the United States
and elsewhere. In other words, just because the sun has risen e very morning in the
East for untold millennia, we cannot logically prove that it will al ways do so. Just
because we have accumulated much evidence that CDR teaching prevails, we have
not proved that it does prevail.†
Also, the common sense of anyone familiar with the abundance of the literature of
research on teaching should dissuade us from any firm conclusion. For example, the
foregoing body of evidence is not based on thorough analyses of how teaching var-
ies as a function of grade le vel, subject matter, students’ SES, students’ scholastic
aptitude, teachers’ years of e xperience, and other f actors, including combinations
and permutations of these factors.
Similarly, the e xistence of professional or ganizations and their journals – each
devoted to adv ancing research on teaching and teacher education on particular
grade levels, such as elementary (Elementary School Journal) or secondary (School
Review) – should mak e us cautious before generalizing about the pre valent model
of teaching. Those journals carry many papers advancing proposals for the improve-
ment of teaching in their grade le vels.
The same caution should follow from the work by specialists in the teaching of
particular school subjects (see Brophy , 2001), such as English (for e xample, The
English Journal), history (for e xample, Teaching Social Studies in an Age of
Crisis), mathematics (for example, The Arithmetic Teacher), or science (for exam-
ple, Journal of Research in Science Teaching ).
†
Lakatos (1968) edited a v olume of papers by philosophers that raised man y questions about
Popper’s formulations of inducti ve logic. The present acceptance of Popper’ s position may need
revision in the light of those papers.
Why the Persistence of CDR Teaching? 79
Given such ca veats, and follo wing the advice of philosopher of science Karl
Popper, we re gard our present decision to focus our theory on CDR teaching as a
conjecture (Popper, 1965). Pending the de velopment of bases in deducti ve logic,
supported by inducti ve evidence, for formulating the model of teaching that will
serve as the focus of a theory of teaching, our decision is a matter of con venience
– a jumping to a conclusion. It can be accepted as long as it survi ves rigorous
attempts at its refutation (Popper , 1965) . Such attempts could tak e the form of
strong evidence, supported by deducti ve logic, that some other model of teaching
is more prevalent than CDR teaching.
The CDR model of teaching comprises those models in which the teaching is
highly structured, and the student plays a role that only seems to be passi ve. The
apparent passivity is lik ely to conceal the students’ vigorous cogniti ve processes
along lines set by the teacher.
Of the models described by Joyce et al., (2000), we shall proceed on the question-
able assumption that none except CDR has in all likelihood achieved predominant use
by the millions of grade 1–12 teachers in U.S. elementary and secondary schools. The
CDR model has persisted throughout the twentieth century , while alternatives of the
PDC kind were widely championed b ut not used nearly as often. CDR teaching,
presumably, will prevail in at least the early decades of the twenty-f irst century.
John Dewey and other influential thinkers led the revolutionary movement that envi-
sioned progressive education. Classroom observers did not expect to find CDR teach-
ing’s pre vlence because of w ork by the authors and adv ocates of the man y other
models of teaching that were described by Joyce et al., (2000) and older volumes such
as The Passing of the Recitation (Thayer, 1928). The “passing” that Thayer and many
others predicted and hoped for has been belied by research on the teaching that w as
actually going on–including historical descriptions not based on observations (Cuban,
1984; Lamm, 1976, pp. 1–6) and observ ation-based descriptions (Bellack
et al., 1966; Goodlad, 1984; Hoetk er & Ahlbrand, 1969; and Mehan, 1979).
Despite De wey’s ef forts to o verthrow CDR teaching, a non-De weyan w ay of
teaching persisted from teacher to teacher , from grade le vel to grade le vel, from
subject matter to subject matter, from region to region, from decade to decade, and
from nation to nation. Yet what we have seen and what we continue to see is little
change in the way teaching goes on. Cuban (1982) e xpressed a common dismay:
What nags at me is the puzzling durability of this teaching at all le vels of schooling b ut
most clearly and uniformly at the high school, decade after decade, in spite of changes in
teacher preparation, students’ knowledge and skills, and continuous reform ferv or to alter
this form of instruction. (p. 28)
80 4 A Conception of the Process of Teaching
Sirotnik (1983), on the basis of observ ations in 1,017 classrooms, reported the
same uniformity:
What we have seen and what we continue to see in the American classroom—the proc-
ess of teaching and learning—appears to be one of the most consistent and persistent
phenomena known in the social and beha vioral sciences. To put it succinctly, the “modus
operandi” of the typical classroom is still didactics, practice, and little else (pp. 16–17).
In his attempt to e xplain the persistence, Nuthall (2005, p. 895) in voked the
concept of societal culture by quoting Stie gler and Hiebert (1999, p. 87): “Despite
changing teacher education programs and many attempts to reform teaching meth-
ods, the core of the ritual remains largely unchanged, sustained by a ‘stable web of
beliefs and assumptions that are part of the [wider] culture. ’”
CDRs Apparent Adequacy. Until recently, CDR teaching seemed to w ork well
enough for the middle-class students who made up the majority of U.S. students.
Cuban (1984) sa w that reality as the cause of the “persistence of the ine vitable”
namely, CDR teaching. If U.S. teaching were as grossly inadequate as some critics
hold, most U.S. adults w ould be incompetent as citizens and as w orkers, and most
U.S. students w ould be mark edly inferior to those in other industrialized countries
in their achievement test scores.
Yet the U. S. polity, in which the citizens taught à la CDR have participated, is
one of the most democratic, enlightened, and demanding of cognitive skills among
the nations of the w orld. The U.S. economy in which the y w ork is among the
world’s most efficient and productive. Berliner and Biddle (1995) brought together
abundant evidence against the “attack” on U.S. public schools.
Excessive Demands of Alternatives to CDR. Progressi ve education, open educa-
tion, constructivist education, and other kinds of proposed impro vements, simply
demand more than what most teachers can pro vide by w ay of skill, stamina, and
Why the Persistence of CDR Teaching? 81
conviction. Schools may resist teachers’ departures from the uniformity that has
been so widely observed for so long. Cremin (1964) , a Pulitzer prize-winning his-
torian of U.S. education, illuminated some of the reasons why PDC w as ne ver
widely practiced:
From the beginning, progressivism cast the teacher in an almost impossible role: he was to
be an artist of consummate skill, properly knowledgeable in his field, meticulously trained
in the art of pedagogy, and thoroughly imbued with a zeal for social impro vement. It need
hardly be said that here as else where on the educational scene of the [eighteen] nineties,
the gap between real and ideal w as appalling. (p. 168)
It means a teacher can take the class around the world electronically to look at the development
of civilizations in Egypt, Greece, Rome, Latin America. A Spanish class in Idaho can talk to
students in Bilbao. It means linking biology students in Chicago with a researcher at a micro-
scope in San Francisco, history students with a curator at the National Portrait Gallery, technol-
ogy students with the National Air and Space Museum in W ashington. (p. 68)
But D. K. Cohen (1988) added four additional possible reasons for the persist-
ence of CDR:
The Great Autonomy of U.S. School Systems. The United States has no national
curriculum and no prescribed teaching practices. This situation mak es it easy for
teachers to resist change.
The Conditions of Teaching. Teachers have to use a curriculum the y did not
develop, according to an imposed schedule, under hea vy w orkloads including
extracurricular acti vities, with lo w pay and little prestige. These conditions
weaken teachers’ moti vation to adopt ne w w ays of teaching. But, as Cohen
pointed out, this reasoning does not e xplain why teachers in pri vate schools and
colleges taught in much the same way as teachers in public schools – even though
their teaching loads were lighter , pay w as better, and the y had more freedom to
develop curriculum.
Flaws in Reform. Reform ef forts had to cope with inadequate resources and
school administrators’ insensitivity to teachers’ needs. Yet even when such condi-
tions improved greatly, Cohen noted, efforts to change teaching had little success.
Weak Incentives for Change. Because public schools had little competition,
their administrators and teachers were not moti vated to change.
In Cohen’s (1988, p. 36) vie w, his own explanations “do not seem suf ficient to
explain the glacial pace of change in teaching”. Ev en when these obstacles to
change were absent, as in pri vate schools and colle ges, teaching remained for the
most part unchanged.
Despite all the e vidence to the contrary , some writers continue to assert that pro-
gressive education – a major component of the PDC model – is not only wide-
spread, but has caused American schools to “go wrong” (Evers, 1998) and become
altogether unlik e “the schools we need” (Hirsch, 1996). These writers seem to
contradict what we have characterized as the predominant style of teaching in U.S.
schools and thus our conclusion that progressi ve education is absent from U.S.
classrooms.
Evers (1998, pp. 1–2) wrote that “School reformers today are still trying to put
into effect the turn-of-the-century progressi ve education ideas of John De wey and
others – often these days under the banner of ‘disco very learning.’” Progressi ve
education, he said, v anished for a fe w decades be ginning in the mid-1950s “But
progressive education came back and is quite influential today in its contemporary
incarnation of discovery learning.”
Is Progressive Education Still Around? 83
We should note that Evers referred to what “school reformers,” not teachers, are
doing. And Hirsch similarly referred to “the training and certification of teachers in
our teacher training schools, ” b ut not to ho w and what teachers were teaching.
Thus, their criticism refers to what goes on in U.S . teacher education programs,
rather than what teachers have been observed doing in their classrooms.
But, as W allen and T ravers (1963, p. 453) pointed out, “Principals commonly
voice the opinion that most teachers do not teach in accordance with the pattern
prescribed by teacher -training institutions, b ut in the pattern the y observed when
they were pupils …. ” Similarly, Labaree (2004, pp. 129–169) elaborated on the
difference between teacher education and teaching. He described what he called
“the Ed School’s romance with progressivism.” He saw teacher education programs
in the United States as strongly biased to wards progressivism for man y years. He
wrote, “[T]he ed schools could indeed cause damage in schools if it were in the
hands of an institution that w as powerful enough to implement this vision, but the
ed school is too weak to do so” [italics added] (p. 130).
Thus the Evers-Hirsch portrayal may be accurate if it is applied to teacher educa-
tion programs, or at least what these programs adv ocate. But the historical and
observational evidence belies their vie ws and tells us that progressi vism has been
missing from U.S. classrooms for a long time.
Chapter 5
A Conception of the Content of Teaching
Passing along the content of a society’s culture is what education is for. The content
of teaching is derived from conceptions of the objectives of teaching – what people
should know, understand, and be able to do. It is what mak es education important
to a society in fostering freedom and well-being, useful to indi viduals in achieving
their economic roles, and, in a democrac y, essential to the competence of citizens
in making their system of go vernment work.
We turn now to a formulation of the ways in which the content of teaching bears
upon a theory of teaching. The formulation will support change in research on teaching,
i.e., in the kinds of questions in vestigated and the kinds of data collected.
As research on teaching began to flourish in the 1960s, one of its most active para-
digms came to be known as “process-product research” – the search for relationships
between teaching processes (what teachers did) and the products of teaching (what
students learned). No similarly acti ve research mo vement developed to study the
other main component of teaching – its content. Thus there was no similar level of
research with what might have been called “(process ↔ content)-product research,”
where the ↔ symbol denotes the interaction between process and content. This
chapter will e xplore e xplanations of this ne glect and some of the alternati ve
approaches to a concern with content that ha ve developed. Those approaches will
bear upon a theory of teaching, that is, an explanation of the ways in which teaching
brings about students’ achievement of the objectives of teaching.
The omissions and mistreatments of content in studies of teaching have been the
subject of philosophical insights and also, by way of proposed remedies, the observations
by educators.
Gage and Needels (1989), lacking guidance from the philosophers, erroneously
considered “intentionality” to refer to the intention, or purpose, of teachers. Their
confusion w as e ventually resolv ed by a helpful entry on “intentionality” in The
Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy (Audi, 1995):
intentionality, aboutness. Things that are about other things exhibit intentionality. Beliefs
and other mental states e xhibit intentionality, but so, in a deri ved way, do sentences and
books, maps and pictures, and other representations. The adjecti ve “intentional” in this
philosophical sense is a technical term not to be confused with the more f amiliar sense,
characterizing something done on purpose. Hopes and fears, for instance, are not things we
do, not intentional acts in the latter , familiar sense, but they are intentional phenomena in
the technical sense: hopes and fears are about various things. ... Phenomena with intention-
ality thus point outside of themselv es to something else: whate ver they are of or about. ...
All and only mental phenomena e xhibit intentionality. (p. 381)
It can be readily understood that teaching must be about something, namely, the con-
tent of teaching. (The “beliefs and mental states” of teachers are embraced by the category
labeled “Teachers’ Thought Processes” in the paradigm presented in Chap. 3.)
The problem of determining the intentionality of teachers’ behaviors is generally
solved, by both students and researchers, by using the process of inference: “the
process of dra wing a conclusion from premises or assumptions” (Audi, 1995,
p. 369). When observing the verbal or nonverbal behavior of a teacher, the student
or researcher usually has little dif ficulty in inferring the teaching’ s intentionality,
including her beliefs and mental states. That they are able to do so results from their
abundant experience in making such inferences in daily life. Indeed, daily life in
any society would become chaotic if people were not typically correct in inferring
intentionality from beha vior. Researchers f avor lo w-inference descriptions of
behaviors not to reduce the level of inference in interpreting behavior as to content
or intentionality. Rather, they do so to impro ve the communicability to teachers of
the behaviors and intentions desired by either researchers or teacher educators.
But many researchers on teaching, in focusing on the process of teaching, ha ve
neglected what teaching was about, namely, its content. The successive editions of
the Handbook of Research on Teaching (Gage, 1963; T ravers, 1973; W ittrock,
The Neglect of Content in Process–Product Research on Teaching 87
1986a; Richardson, 2001) did not completely bypass content. But the y considered
it only briefly, as in the following passage from Shulman (1986a):
The content and the purposes for which it is taught are the v ery heart of the teaching-
learning processes. [B. O.] Smith (1983) put it clearly when he asserted that the “teacher
interacts with the student in and through the content, and the student interacts with the
teacher in the same way” (p. 491). Although the content transmitted for particular purposes
has rarely been a central part of studies of teaching, it certainly deserv es a place in our
comprehensive map, if only to remind us of its ne glect. (p. 8)
That the shift to ward a concern with the content taught has been considered
pertinent to research on teaching, w as made explicit by Doyle (1995) as follows:
The framing of pedagogical research as a question about teacher ef fectiveness and the
grounding of this research in behavioral psychology led to an increasingly generic view of
pedagogy. The language of behavioral psychology focused on overt actions, and the effec-
tiveness question focused on teachers or teaching methods as the direct causes of outcomes.
Taken together, these frame works excluded students and curriculum [italics added] from
the analysis. Methods became treatments, e.g., lecture versus discussion, devoid of the rich
theoretical propositions about the nature of content and its acquisition that had characterized
19th-century discussions of method. In process-product research, behaviors rather than
content were measured during classroom observations. ... Questions about what was being
taught to whom slipped into the background. [italics added] (p. 491)
Fig. 5.1 A formula for the standardized size of the teachers’ ef fect on the experimental group as
compared with the teachers’ effect on the control group .
88 5 A Conception of the Content of Teaching
The magnitude of the correlation coef ficient or the ef fect size can tell us, in a
quantitative sense, ho w well we “e xplain” the connection between teaching and
achievement. (This form of e xplanation is analogous to the statistical concept of
amount of variance in outcome accounted for, i.e., “e xplained,” by the dif ference
in teaching.)
The proposed change – the inclusion of a content-of-teaching variable – will end
a def iciency that has been e vident in the v ery label of such research until no w:
process-product research (PPR). In the future that kind of research should tak e the
form of (process ↔ content)-product research. (The ↔ symbol stands for the joint
consideration of process and content). The change will reflect an appreciation of a
long-overdue insight, namely, that what is taught is at least as important for student
achievement as how it is taught, if our purpose is to understand what it is in teaching
that affects how well students perform on assessments of their achie vement.
Content Variation
Content could not help e xplain dif ferences in teaching ef fectiveness if it were a
constant. A constant, by def inition, lacks v ariance and therefore cannot e xplain
variance in a variable, such as student achievement.
Content varies even in a single subject matter, such as arithmetic or history, in a
single curriculum of that subject matter, in a single state, school district, school, or
classroom. Even under research conditions, unless the researcher presents the con-
tent via some physical medium, such as a book or a computer , the same subject’ s
content will v ary from teacher to teacher . Even the same teacher will present the
content so that it differs from one time to another.
This inevitability of content v ariability makes content dif ficult to control. That
difficulty may e xplain the ne glect of content in research on teaching. It may ha ve
led researchers to mak e the false assumption that v ariance in student achie vement
within a single subject-matter, such as fourth-grade arithmetic, could be e xplained
solely on the basis of between-teacher dif ferences in the process of teaching.
Instructional Alignment
Several authors ha ve developed, independently of one another and with dif ferent
terminologies, the same substantive advancement in research on teaching: concern
with the content of teaching. The y have introduced that concern as distinguished
from concern with the process of teaching.
Although they used different terms for what they were emphasizing, all of their
terms designate what S. A. Cohen (1987) called instructional alignment :the degree
of fit between (a) the content taught and (b) the content tested in assessing student
achievement. That researchers on teaching ha ve neglected content shows up in the
Instructional Alignment 89
absence of “instructional alignment” and its various synonyms from the indexes of
all four editions of the Handbook of Research on Teaching. S. A. Cohen’ s (1987)
labeling instructional alignment a “magic bullet” is easy to understand; (process ↔
content)-product research should increase the ability of research on teaching to
explain, to predict, and to control, i.e., impro ve, how well students achieve.
Instructional alignment was almost completely absent from the variables studied in
research on teaching until now. But it has, in various forms, a substantial history in
the thinking of educational research w orkers in other f ields as against the f ield
called research on teaching. In that history, a variety of terms and methods identified
ideas similar to instructional alignment.
Content and Curricular Validity. Educational measurement has long used the
terms content validity and curricular validity to designate a property of an assess-
ment, namely, “the degree to which assessment questions are representati ve of the
knowledge, skills, or attitudes to be learned as a result of a given teaching or course
of study” (English & English, 1958, p. 575). Or “the extent to which a test meas-
ures a representative sample of the subject matter or beha vior under investigation”
(VandenBos, 2007, p. 224).
Opportunity-to-Learn. Husén (1967) reported on an international study of
mathematics achie vement in twelv e countries. His report used the concept of
opportunity-to-learn. It w as measured by the a verage of teachers’ ratings of each
item on an achievement assessment as to the degree to which the teacher had gi ven
her students preparation for answering the assessment-item correctly.
The various participating nations were understandably sensiti ve to the f airness of
the mathematics test used. No country wanted its students to be disadvantaged because
they had not been taught any part of the knowledge or skills measured by the test.
Teachers within each of the 12 countries also v aried in how well the content of
their teaching fitted the content of the achievement test. It was reasonable to expect
such variability between the average ratings of the teachers of different countries to
be much greater than that within countries.
L. W. Anderson (1987) reported on a subsequent international study in nine
countries. That study e xamined ho w teacher beha vior w as related to student
achievement. Anderson also used the term opportunity-to-learn in of fering the
generalization that:
Within countries, teachers dif fer greatly in what the y teach relati ve to what w as tested.
As a national option teachers were ask ed to indicate the extent to which their students had
had opportunity-to-learn the content included in each item on the post test. On the basis of
their responses, an O TL [opportunity-to-learn] inde x w as derived for each teacher . This
index represented the percentage of items on the posttest that the teachers belie ved their
students had had an opportunity to learn during the conduct of the study ... [T]he difference
between the classrooms in which the students had the most OTL and the classrooms which
had the least OTL is never less that 50 percent in an y country. (pp. 78–79)
90 5 A Conception of the Content of Teaching
The issue of “opportunity to learn” was recognized by Needels (1988) when she
noted that “because the traditional [process-product] design requires that the same
test items must be used for all classes, no consideration can be given to whether all
content contained in the test items was actually taught by the teacher” (p. 504). She
developed a process-product design, presented in Chap. 8, that permitted including
only test items related to the content actually taught.
Facet Similarity. Bar-On and Perlberg (1985) used the facet theory of Guttman
(1959) in developing a theory of instruction. They derived the hypothesis that the
more similar two v ariables (“structuples”) were in terms of their components
(“structs”), the more highly the y w ould correlate. Thus, Higher correlations are
expected between items dif fering b y only one struct [component of a v ariable]
rather than between structuples [variables consisting of more than one component]
differing by tw o structs. That is, the e xpected correlation between a 1 b1 and a 1 b2 is
higher than the expected correlation between a1 b1 and a 2 b2 (p. 99).
It is easy to regard the two variables (structuples) as “teaching (a1 b1 )”and “student
achievement (a1 b2 ).”
Measurement-Driven Instruction. Popham (1985, 1993) used the term “measure-
ment-driven instruction” to designate teaching whose content w as shaped by the test
that would be used to e valuate achievement. That is, the content of the test w ould be
developed first – either by the teacher or by the developers of a standardized test – and
then teachers will be “dri ven” by knowledge of that test to align the content of their
teaching with the content of the test.
Instructional Alignment. S. A. Cohen (1987, 1991, 1995) coined the term
“instructional alignment” to des ignate a characteristic of teaching, namely , the
degree to which the content of the teaching matched the content of the assessment
used to evaluate achievement resulting from that teaching.
Measuring the Content of Instruction. A. C. Porter (2002) de veloped quantita-
tive measures and graphic displays of content taught that permitted comparisons
between separate bodies of content. The quantif ication used the follo wing
formula:
Alignment index = 1– (sum of x–y / 2)
where x denotes cell proportions in one matrix and y denotes cell proportions in
another matrix.
The “matrices” here are tw o-dimensional tables, with the v arious “content top-
ics” in the ro ws and v arious “categories of cogniti ve demand,” or what we ha ve
called “cognitive processes,” in the columns. Porter’s illustrative “Content Matrix,”
with six content topics and five categories of cognitive demand has 6 times 5, or 30,
cells. In each cell is a proportion of all the items in the teaching content or the test
content. If two teachers were being compared, one w ould be X and the other Y . If
the proportions of items in each cell were the same for the tw o teachers, their
“alignment inde x” w ould equal 1, signifying perfect alignment between the tw o
teachers.
Instructional Alignment 91
The term instructional alignment refers to the similarity between the content taught
and the content of the assessment of achievement of the objectives of the teaching.
The content taught consists of the facts, concepts, procedures, and self-understandings
(metacognitions) that students should kno w, understand, and be able to use in
various ways, as a result of the teaching. That content should conform to the curricu-
lum that has been constructed by the persons and or ganizations authorized by
public or private interests to define the curriculum. The curriculum often, especially
in schools, should include some means – such as tests, observations, interviews, and
portfolios (collections of things written or made by students) – for determining how
well students have achieved the objectives set forth in the curriculum.
It seems obvious that the more the teaching’s content resembles the assessment’s
content, the higher the achie vement measure will be. Despite this ob viousness,
research on teaching has proceeded for man y decades without attention to instruc-
tional alignment. The ob viousness of the connection between opportunity-to-learn
and student achievement may make it susceptible to disrespect by the general public.
But such obviousness does not lessen its importance.
Fig. 5.2 Scattergram of mean test scores (TEST) and percentages of opportunity to learn (O TL)
for 15 countries (Adapted from Pelgrum et al., 1986, p. 9.) .
For example, the Roman numeral lesson taught subjects ho w to write the Roman numeral
for arabic numerals (e. g., “Write the Roman numeral for 10.”). The aligned test requested
the same kind of behavior, arabic to Roman numeral. In the less aligned test, half the items
reversed the request asking the subject to write the arabic numeral for the Roman numeral.
In the least aligned treatment, all the items were from Roman to arabic numerals, a transfer
task. (Koczor, 1984)
In this experiment, another variable was student aptitude. The results suggested
that the influence of instructional alignment on achie vement was greater for lo w-
aptitude students than for high-aptitude students, perhaps because the aptitude variable
was the equi valent of ability to cope with the dif ferent demands for transfer of
learning imposed by the different levels of instructional alignment. This finding is,
of course, an example of aptitude-treatment interaction (Cronbach & Snow, 1977),
in that the effect of the treatments (different degrees of instructional alignment) was
different for students differing in aptitude.
Measurement-Driven Instruction. A fourth aspect of instructional alignment is
measurement-driven instruction (MDI) (Popham, 1985, 1993). When such “driven-
ness” occurs, i.e., when the alignment of the teaching content with the achievement-
assessment content, designed in advance, is very high, achievement should also be
high. But if the teaching w as not “dri ven” by what the subsequent assessment
would measure, the alignment of the teaching with the assessment w ould be lo w,
and achievement would be low.
The proper alignment of the teaching content with the assessment content was argued
in the classic statement by T yler (1951) on the desirable relationship between teaching
and testing – a relationship that might be labeled “instruction-driven-measurement”
(IDM):
Viewed in this w ay, instruction involves several steps. The f irst of these is to decide what
ends to seek, that is, what objecti ves to aim at or , stated more precisely , what changes in
94 5 A Conception of the Content of Teaching
students’ behavior to try to bring about. The second step is to determine what content and
learning experiences can be used that are likely to attain these ends, these changes in student
behavior. The third step is to determine an ef fective organization of these learning e xperi-
ences such that their cumulati ve effect will be such as to bring about the desired changes
in an ef ficient f ashion. Finally, the fourth step is to appraise the effects of the learning
experiences to find out in what way they have been effective and in what respects they have
not produced the results desired. [italics added] (p. 48)
be high. But it could not be judged in comparison with that of other teachers, who
teach and test in their o wn distinctive ways, except in terms of a percentage of the
“items” taught that are similar to the items tested.
Standardized tests are useful for comparing the achievement of many classes for
two purposes: research on teaching and high-stak es assessment. F or research on
teaching, the scores are used to compare teaching practices as to their effect on student
achievement. In high-stak es testing, test scores af fect important matters such as
student promotion or the e valuation of a teacher . Research on teaching uses the
same test, constructed or selected by the researcher , for all the teachers studied so
that the researcher can compare teachers’ classes with one another, and the correlates
of the achievement of the teachers’ classes can be determined. High-stakes assessment
leaves the content of the assessment inthe hands of measurement experts – employed
by states, counties, or cities – who construct standardized assessments for assessing
the achie vement of all the comparable classes of a specif ied grade-le vel. Here
again the individual teacher does not determine the instructional alignment; it is left,
usually to an unknown degree, to the unforeseeable similarity between the teacher’s
content and the content of the high-stakes assessment. If the teachers learn in detail
the content of the high-stak es assessment, they will understandably try to increase
their instructional alignment, i.e., to engage in “teaching to the test. ”
To lea ve the curriculum entirely in the hands of the indi vidual teacher , as
instruction-driven measurement w ould have it, is to abandon the idea of a f airly
uniform curriculum for the students in all of the fifty states of the U.S. Such a solution
makes the curriculum determine, i.e., serve as the arbiter of, the content of both the
teaching and the testing.
Does high-stakes testing influence the curriculum taught by individual teachers?
Some writers ha ve proposed that high-stak es assessments should emphasize
critical thinking, a kind of achie vement that has typically been ne glected in both
standardized and teacher -made assessments. Teaching to such assessments w ould
be desirable as a way of reducing the emphasis of both teacher-made and standard-
ized assessments on memorized knowledge and increasing the emphasis on critical
thinking.
Such desirable ne w emphases in teacher -made and standardized assessments
would include the kinds of higher cogniti ve processes carefully def ined in the
Taxonomy of Learning, Teaching, and Assessing (Anderson, 2001), namely, under-
standing, applying, analyzing, evaluating, and creating. T eaching to ward such
assessments would, many writers hold, improve the content of teaching. But, as we
note in Chap. 9, Hirsch (1996) has ar gued against the desirability of teaching for
critical thinking on the grounds that critical thinking requires lar ge stores of rele-
vant knowledge attainable only via large expenditures of time.
How can instructional alignment be achie ved without teaching-to-the-test of an
obviously unethical kind? We can put the issue as a question of transfer demand , or
the amount of transfer from an item that w as taught to what is demanded by an item
in the subsequent achievement-test. Transfer is “change in ability to perform a gi ven
act as a direct consequence of ha ving performed another act relevant or related to it”
(English & English, 1958, p. 562). T ransfer demand w ould be at a minimum if the
96 5 A Conception of the Content of Teaching
teacher taught directly to the test, providing training in answering the identical ques-
tions in both the teaching and the testing. But if the test content requires some transfer
of what w as taught to what the test calls for , teaching-to-the-test becomes increas-
ingly desirable. Then it is equivalent to teaching for positive transfer, that is, teaching
content and skills that will f acilitate answering questions, performing tasks, or solv-
ing problems presenting transfer demand from those that were taught.
Thus teaching-to-the-test is desirable insof ar as the “assessment” imposes a
reasonable transfer demand. T eaching and assessing for critical thinking w ould
require a reasonable transfer demand, inasmuch as critical thinking by def inition
requires ar gumentation on issues not pre viously encountered and thus a suitable
amount of transfer demand. So we can resolv e the apparent conflict between
desirable instructional alignment and undesirable teaching-to-the-test insofar as the
assessment imposes a transfer demand that is reasonable in the light of the student’s
maturity and the teacher’s educational objectives.
Categorizations of Content
What students are taught is customarily put into the well-kno wn categories called
school subjects. In elementary schools, the subjects customarily include reading,
writing, arithmetic, social studies (history , geography), science, art, music, and
physical education. In secondary schools, the subjects include English (composi-
tion and literature), mathematics (algebra, geometry , trigonometry, and, in recent
decades, calculus), social studies (history , civics), foreign languages, and science
(biology, chemistry, physics).
For each of these subjects, there are subject-matter , or curriculum, specialists
who have created bodies of scholarship and research (e.g., Brophy , 2001; Jackson,
1992) on the content that is best included (and e xcluded). Various journals serv e
their authors. Issues arise, controversies flourish, and schisms form.
The treatment of content cate gorization in this chapter will not dra w upon the
work of subject-matter specialists. Rather it will deal with the ideas of educational
psychologists who have focused on the general phenomena of learning and teaching
– phenomena that occur in the form and of problems and their solutions, that cut
across subject matters. These psychologists ha ve de veloped cate gorizations of
content – categorizations to which we now turn.
Taxonomies
Bloom’s Taxonomy
The first of these w as the famous Taxonomy of educational objectives. The classi-
fication of educational goals. Handbook 1: Cognitive domain (Bloom, Engelhart,
Furst, Hill, & Krathwohl, 1956). It was developed to serve examiners – developers
of achievement tests – who needed carefully de veloped definitions and categoriza-
tions of the kinds of achievement that their examinations – consisting of test items,
questions, and problems – would seek to evaluate. Its categories are summarized in
Table 5.1 .
Table 5.1 Categories of the bloom taxonomy of educational objecti ves in the cognitive domain
Knowledge
1.00Knowledge
1.10 Knowledge of specifics
1.11 Knowledge of terminology
1.12 Knowledge of specific facts
1.20 Knowledge of ways and means of dealing with specif ics
1.21 Knowledge of conventions
1.22 Knowledge of trends and sequences
1.23 Knowledge of classifications and categories
1.24 Knowledge of criteria
1.25 Knowledge of methodology
1.30 Knowledge of the universals and abstractions in a f ield
1.31 Knowledge of principles and generalizations
1.32 Knowledge of theories and structures
Intellectual abilities and skills
2.0Comprehension
2.10Translation
2.11Comprehension
2.12Extrapolation
3.00Application
4.00Analysis
4.10 Analysis of elements
4.20 Analysis of relationships
4.30 Analysis of organizational principles
5.00Synthesis
5.10 Production of a unique communication
5.20 Production of a plan, or a proposed set of operations
5.30 Derivation of a set of abstract relations
6.00Evaluation
6.10 Judgments in terms of internal e vidence
6.20 Judgments in terms of e xternal criteria
Source: Bloom et al. (1956)
98 5 A Conception of the Content of Teaching
This taxonomy, developed by Anderson et al. (2001), aimed to serv e not only the
purposes of assessing but also those of learning and teaching. Their w ork led them
to set up four cate gories of Kno wledge: Factual, Conceptual, Procedural , and
Metacognitive .(Their five categories of Cognitive Process are treated in Chap. 8 ).
Table 5.2 gives the subcategories of the four categories of Knowledge.
Types of Knowledge
The teacher’ s structuring can state f actual kno wledge, conceptual kno wledge,
procedural knowledge, or metacognitive knowledge.
Factual Knowledge. This cate gory consists of information about what is true or
false. It takes such forms as propositions (Bill Clinton has been President; An even
number is di visible by tw o), images (Alaska is northwest of Canada; Giraf fes are
taller than elephants), and linear orderings (The glider w as invented before the air -
plane; Vowels are usually listed as a-e-i-o-u- and sometimes y) .
Conceptual Knowledge. This cate gory includes general ideas (honesty , mass,
democracy), principles (mass equals force times acceleration), distinctions (rights
differ from obligations).
Procedural Knowledge. This cate gory comprises w ays of doing things, such as
behavioral (Walk carefully; Start sentences with capital letters) and mental (Think
before you respond; Summarize after you’ ve described; Re view after you’ ve
studied).
Categorizations of Content 99
The process and content of teaching must be appropriate to two major categories of
factors – the students’ cognitive capabilities and the students’ motivation. Concern
with students’ cognitive capabilities and motivation should take place early in an y
teacher’s thinking about the process and content of teaching.
Cognitive capabilities are tw o-sided. They comprise (a) the student’ s intelligence
and (b) the student’ s prior kno wledge of what is being taught. The intelligence
component applies to content in general. Prior knowledge consists of what students
know, before being taught, about some specific kind of content.
Intelligence
We also call intelligence by such other names as intelligence quotient (IQ), general
intellectual capability , scholastic aptitude, cogniti ve ability (Carroll, 1993), and
multiple intelligences (Gardner, 1983). It has a general form – general intelligence
– that applies to all kinds of cogniti ve tasks, and a number of more specif ic forms
that apply to more specific kinds of intellectual tasks, such as verbal, mathematical,
and spatial.
The special abilities ha ve been identif ied in tw o ways: (a) f actor analysis – “a
mathematical procedure for reducing a set of intercorrelations to a small number of
descriptive or e xplanatory concepts” (V andenBos, 2007). This statistical method
was used on a lar ge scale by Carroll (1993) for determining the cate gories, or
“factors,” into which v arious kinds of cogniti ve abilities f all. Such cate gorization
was also performed by Gardner (1983) using a “multiple-intelligences” approach
described below.
Cognitive capabilities, called “mental age” by the original de velopers of intel-
ligence tests, make up the numerator in the traditional definition of the intelligence
quotient, or IQ, which equals Mental age divided by Chronological age. Mental age
is “the le vel of de velopment in intelligence, e xpressed as equi valent to the life
[chronological] age at which the a verage child attains that le vel” (English &
English, 1958, p. 18).
Factor Analysis. Factor analysis is the statistical analysis of the intercorrelations
between scores on a considerable number of tests, all of which, for the purposes
of this chapter , meas ure some aspect of intelligence. Its purpose, as considered
here, is to search for f actors, or clusters of tests, that measure the same kind of
mental ability. It yields special and general factors. The special factors appear when
factor analysis identif ies clusters of tests that measure to a high de gree the same
underlying, abstract kind of special ability , such as v erbal ability, mathematical
ability, and spatial ability. The tests within a factor correlate more highly with other
tests in the same f actor than the y do with tests in other f actors. The basis for the
concept of general intelligence, dubbed “ g” by its disco verer (Spearman, 1904),
rests on the f act that all the special abilities ha ve always been found to correlate
positively with one another. That is, people who score at a gi ven level on one abil-
ity, say verbal, tend to score at approximately the same level on other abilities, say,
mathematical and spatial. Those positi ve correlations taken together betok en an
underlying general ability that can w ork well on all of the kinds of cogniti ve
content.
Carroll’s (1993) integration of the f indings of factor analyses yielded the kinds
of special abilities listed in Table 6.1 .
Multiple Intelligences. Special abilities were also identif ied by Gardner (1983)
from a v ariety of kinds of e vidence: literary accounts, neurological e vidence,
descriptions of genius and def iciency, and anthropological reports. His f indings,
termed multiple intelligences, resemble and also dif fer from Carroll’s, as is shown
in Table 6. 1 .
Prior Knowledge
The other part of cognitive capabilities is the student’s prior knowledge of the con-
tent being taught. Students often v ary in prior kno wledge according to their inter -
ests, self-education, pre vious schooling, and random e xperiences. Whate ver the
content, or subject matter , of the teaching may be, it is reasonable to assume that
students will differ, sometimes substantially, in their prior kno wledge of that con-
tent. Those differences should influence the effectiveness of the process and content
of the teaching aimed at those students.
The Russian psychologist Vygotsk y (1978) recognized the importance of prior
knowledge in his concept of “zone of proximal development” (ZPD), formulated in
the 1920s. The ZPD consists of the difference between the knowledge, or problem-
solving ability, of the student before receiving instruction and the student’s capabili-
ties after receiving the guidance and assistance of a teacher . Ausubel (1968, p. i v)
recognized the reasonableness of the assumption that prior knowledge is important
when he stated that “If I had to reduce all of educational psychology to just one
principle, I would say this: The most important single factor influencing learning is
what the learner already kno ws. Ascertain this and teach him accordingly .” Or, as
R. M. Gagné (1985) made the same point,
One set of factors contributing to learning is the capabilities that already e xist in the indi-
vidual before an y particular ne w learning be gins. The child who is learning to tie shoe-
laces does not begin this learning “from scratch” but already knows how to hold the laces,
how to loop one over the other, how to tighten the loop, and so on. (p. 16)
Prior knowledge consists, for any subject matter, of the same types of kno wl-
edge (factual, conceptual, procedural, and metacognitive) and the same cognitive
processes (remember , understand, apply , analyze, e valuate, and create) that
appear in A Taxonomy for Teaching, Learning, and Assessing (Anderson &
Krathwohl, 2001). Students’ prior kno wledge almost al ways v aries whene ver
students are assessed as to their prior achievement of the objectives of the teach-
ing. Typically, students’ scores on a pretest of achie vement correlate positi vely
with their scores on a posttest. That is, students who had more of the types of
knowledge and cogniti ve-process capabilities before the teaching tend to score
higher after the teaching on an assessment of that content kno wledge and cogni-
tive-process capability.
By the time 5- or 6-year -olds enter school, the y have developed well past the inf ant
and early childhood stages of cognitive capabilities described by Piaget and Inhelder
(1973) and others. R. L. Atkinson, R. C. Atkinson, E. E. Bem, & S. Nolen-Hoeksema
(2000, p. 77) summarized the abilities of typical kindergarten and first-grade children
as follows. Such children can typically
• differentiate themselves from objects,
• recognize themselves as agents of action and act intentionally ,
• realize that things continue to e xist when no longer visible or audible,
• use language to represent images and w ords,
• differentiate themselves from others,
• take the viewpoint of others, and
• classify objects by one or more features and arrange them in some order .
Then, between the ages of about se ven to twelve, they become able to
• think logically about objects and events
• realize that objects stay the same in number and weight even when they differ in
position, shape, or color,
• classify objects according to several features and order them in series on a single
dimension, such as size,
• think logically about abstract propositions and test hypotheses systematically ,
• become concerned with the hypothetical, the future, and ideological problems.
What these research findings on intelligence mean is that the a verage student is
well able to cope with the elementary- and secondary-school curricula that ha ve
become well established around the world. But the students differ in the speed and
facility with which the y can learn what is usually taught in those grades. Students
eventually succeed if they are not too far below the average level of cognitive capa-
bilities for their age.
Here we develop connections between (a) the various levels of cognitive capabilities
that occur in grades 1 to 12 or at the colle ge level and (b) the dif ferent ways of
teaching that become appropriate for students at different levels of cognitive capabilities
relative to the average level for their grade level.
The psychology of individual differences, which is the study of the psychological
ways in which individuals and groups differ from one another, was early seen as a
source of knowledge that would be useful for teachers in coping with the f act that
each of their students differed in cognitive capabilities from their other students. We
turn now to attempts to develop ways of dealing with this unavoidable characteristic
of classrooms-full of students.
Adjusting Teaching to Students’ Cognitive Capabilities 105
Simplifying
One effective way of teaching for different levels of cognitive capabilities within a
single grade level is simplification. It can take various forms:
Reduce the Number and Length of the Items Encountered. or F example, the
teacher can reduce (a) the number of lines of a poem to be memorized; (b) the number
of chemical atomic weights to be remembered; (c) the number of words in a single
sentence of an explanation; (d) the number of sentences spoken by the teacher with-
out pausing or allo wing interruptions; (e) the number of sen tences that refer to a
given topic; (f) the length of reading assignments; (g) the number of problems
assigned for homework, (h) the duration of uninterrupted teacher talk; (i) the time
gap between the content of recent teacher discourse and the occurrence of teachers’
questions on that discourse.
Use Simpler and More Familiar Words. Examples: “hide” rather than “con-
ceal;” “make unclear” rather than “obfuscate.”
Provide Mnemonic Devices. Example a: Mnemonic de vice HOMES for the
names of the Great Lak es (Huron, Ontario, Michigan, Erie, Superior). Example b:
Mnemonic Device: MVEMJSUNP = My Very Earnest Mother Just Served Us Nine
Pickles. F or the names of the planets, in order of their distance from the sun:
Mercury, Venus, Earth, Mars, Jupiter , Saturn, Uranus, Neptune, Pluto. Example
106 6 Conceptions of Students’ Cognitive Capabilities and Motivation
c: Mnemonic Device: ROY G. BIV (a made-up name) for the colors of the rainbow,
in order: Red, Orange, Yellow, Green, Blue, Indigo, Violet. – OR – Richard Of York
Gave Battle In Vain.
Provide Algorithms, or Sets of Rules, for Solving Problems. Example a: A set of
steps for multiplying by tw o or more digits, whereby the product of the multipli-
cand (the number to be multiplied), e.g., 250, and the first digit (2) of the multiplier,
e.g., 72, is written on the first line and the product of the multiplicand and the sec-
ond digit of the multiplier is written on the second line and indented one space to
the left, and so on for the multiplier’s remaining 1750
250
×72
500
1750
18000
The de gree to which a learning situation requires the student to e xert cogniti ve
effort has been termed cognitive load by Sweller (1999). As the term suggests, the
concept is concerned with the “consequences of difficulty in dealing with the elements
of a task, ” and “dif ficulty in holding and processing man y elements in a limited
working memory” (Sweller, 1999, p. 36).
Sweller (1999) elaborated on f actors affecting cognitive load, namely, (a) inter-
activity, (b) split attention, (c) w orked e xamples, and (d) redundanc y. He also
suggested w ays of coping with dif ferences in cogniti ve capabilities by reducing
cognitive load in ways set forth in Chap. 8.
A Clinical Approach
The term “clinical” refers to the diagnosis and treatment of psychological prob-
lems, such as the adjustment of teaching to the needs of individual students. (It also
refers to medical or psychiatric processes.) The teacher , in using these w ays of
meeting the needs of their less cognitively capable students, must momentarily treat
them in w ays that are dif ferent from those suitable for the other students in her
class. Cronbach (1967) captured the way in which teachers typically – on the evidence
of one’s own memories of classroom teachers’ processes – cope with the inevitable
differences among their students:
The teacher adapts instructional method to the indi vidual on both the micro (small) and
macro (large) levels. He barely ackno wledges the comment one pupil mak es in class dis-
cussion, and stops to praise a lesser contribution from another who (he [the teacher] thinks)
A Clinical Approach 107
needs special encouragement. He turns away from one pupil who asks for help – “You can
find the answer by yourself if you k eep at it” – and w alks the length of the classroom to
offer help to another, because he has decided to encourage the independence of the former
pupil and to minimize the frustration of the latter . On the lar ger scale, he not only allo ws
options for a term paper, but may custom tailor a project for the student with special abili-
ties or limitations.
The significant thing about these adaptations is their informality [italics added]. The
teacher picks up some cues from the pupil’s test record and his daily w ork, and other cues
from rather casual observation of his social interactions. The teacher forms an impression
of the pupil from the cues, usually without an e xplicit chain of reasoning. He proceeds on
the basis of the impression to alter the instruction; the adaptation too is intuiti ve, without
any explicit theory. No doubt the decisions tend to be beneficial, but there is reason to think
that intuitive adaptations of this kind will be inef ficient and occasionally may be harmful.
(pp. 28–29)
Tutoring
Tutoring consists of the teacher’s working with a single student or a small number
of students who impress the teacher as needing special attention. That need can
arise because the student is finding the content as presented too difficult or too easy
as compared with the majority of students in the class.
For students having difficulty, the tutoring can be organized according to the same
structuring, soliciting, responding, and reacting that occur in re gular CDR teaching.
Structuring can provide simpler and shorter explanations of content, using the simpli-
fication de vices described abo ve. Soliciting can pro vide easier -to-answer-correctly
questions. The student’ s responding can be strongly encouraged, and the teacher’ s
reaction can be warm and patient. The teacher may insure that students have adequate
time-on-task, encourage students to try harder, and assure students of her expectations
of their eventual success.
How should the teaching process be formulated in vie w of the e vidence of multiple
intelligences? Must radically different processes be used for students known to differ
in the strength of the various intelligences? Or can the Conventional-Direct-Recitation
(CDR) process, delineated in Chap. 4, serv e and be adapted to students’ multiple
intelligences?
108 6 Conceptions of Students’ Cognitive Capabilities and Motivation
The kinds of questions ask ed by the teacher after her structuring should also be
appropriate to the students’ linguistic, logical-mathematical, spatial, and musical
intelligences. Adjustments of soliciting for linguistic intelligence result from varying
the same f actors as those identif ied in structuring, namely , sentence structure,
transition between paragraphs, complexity, demand for prior knowledge, and duration.
Questions can be adjusted for logical-mathematical intelligence by v arying the
factual, conceptual, procedural, and metacognitive knowledges asked for. Questions
can take spatial intelligence into account by varying the size, complexity, perspec-
tive, color, and detail to which the questions refer . Differences in musical intelli-
gence can call upon the teacher to vary her questions about the musical compositions
she uses in fostering music appreciation. F or students qualif ied for instruction in
some form of musical performance, she can ask for performances appropriate to the
student’s level of skill.
We combine the treatments of responding and reacting to recognize their close psycho-
logical and temporal relationship in the practice of teaching . That close relationship
makes it appropriate to discuss them together . Sirotnik (1983, p. 20) reported that, in
The Study of Schools, “[T]he most frequently occurring single interaction is one of
students responding to the teacher .... This occurs roughly 15 percent and 10 percent
of the time at the elementary and secondary le vels, respectively.”
After hearing one of the kinds of questions described abo ve, students will
respond in w ays that thro w light on their multiple intelligences. Their responses
will guide the teacher to ward improved understanding of their students’ capability
in the kind of intelligence tapped by the question. Then the teacher will tak e steps
to remedy any shortcomings revealed by the student’s response.
Students’ cognitive capabilities may be re garded as tools that students can use for
the purpose of learning. The concept of moti vation refers to the de gree to which
students use those tools. Student achie vement depends on students’ moti vation as
well as it does on their cogniti ve capabilities. Unmoti vated bright students may
learn less than well-moti vated students who ha ve less cogniti ve capability . The
110 6 Conceptions of Students’ Cognitive Capabilities and Motivation
teacher’s task includes maximizing the degree to which students use their cognitive
capabilities for the purpose of achie ving the objecti ves set forth in the content of
teaching.
That students dif fer in their moti vation is easily and widely recognized. Some
students f ind school w ork interesting and challenging, The y enjo y hearing and
reading about ne w ideas, and the y find their classroom sessions enjo yable. Other
students have the opposite reactions to their classroom experiences, which they find
dull, frustrating, and irrelevant to their interests.
Teachers learn to hope for the first kind of students and to dread the second kind.
The first kind makes teachers feel successful, and the second kind frustrates teachers.
The influences that affect student motivation are of several kinds. One kind consists
of the f amily background. Better educated parents more often influence their
children to v alue education more and to tak e advantage of opportunities to learn.
Less well educated parents pass on to their children less respect for what schools
offer. Similar influences come from a student’ s siblings and friends. Harris (1998)
brought together much e vidence that children are influenced more by their peers
than by their parents.
What makes these differences occur? One place to look for the causes of these
differences is the homes of the students. Some students’ parents create home en vi-
ronments that foster high respect for what schools of fer, and that respect mak es
their children more highly motivated to do well at school. Similar influences come
from the student’ s peers, who pass their attitudes to ward schooling on to their
friends.
We shall focus here on the approaches that teachers can tak e to moti vate their
students. The approaches fall into the same two major categories of approaches that
characterized the science of psychology during the twentieth century: behavioristic
approaches and cognitive approaches.
Behavioristic Approaches
Cognitive Approaches
During the last third of the twentieth century , psychologists o vercame their hesitanc y
about theorizing with variables that were not directly observable behaviors. They became
willing to work with cognitions: “all forms of kno wing and awareness, such as perceiv-
ing, concei ving, remembering, reasoning, judging, imagining, and problem solving”
(VandenBos, 2007, p. 187). When it came to understanding motivation, they saw a moti-
vated person “as someone with cognitions or beliefs that lead to constructi ve achieve-
ment beha vior, such as e xerting ef fort or persisting in the f ace of dif ficulty” (Stipek,
2002, p. 10).
Teachers can af fect cogniti ve aspects of moti vation through what the y say to
students about their o wn expectations of students. The teacher’ s genuine e xpecta-
tion that a student can succeed at a task will moti vate the student to e xert effort to
meet the teacher’s expectations. Teachers can influence their students’ perception
of learning tasks: the task’s relevance to students’ values, its value for understand-
ing the logical aspects of reading, its usefulness in using arithmetic and other
aspects of mathematics in occupational and recreational acti vities.
112 6 Conceptions of Students’ Cognitive Capabilities and Motivation
Increasing a student’s level of success with school tasks will lower the probability
of the student’ s becoming unmoti vated. Here the teacher’ s sensiti vity to e very
student’s successes and f ailures in meeting the demands of the curriculum can
guide the teacher’ s treatment of the student. The student’ s f ailure to understand
something should become a signal calling forth the teacher’ s increased ef fort to
bring about the understanding. In short, the teacher’ s v arious cognitions should
guide the teacher’s effort to help every student succeed.
Chapter 7
A Conception of Classroom Management
Poverty
Before we consider classroom management at the classroom level, we must not shy
away from a crucial aspect of the context of teaching – one that shapes the problem
of teaching in areas of society where classroom management is most difficult. That
aspect is po verty – the po verty of students, of their f amilies, and of their
neighborhoods.
Berliner (2005) con vincingly described po verty as a major f actor that troubles
classroom management in the U.S. According to authoritati ve statistics cited by
Berliner, poverty is more widespread and longer -lasting in the U.S. than in compa rably
prosperous countries. And, in the U.S., po verty is associated with lo w scholastic
achievement, especially among African-American and Hispanic students. As is
shown in Tables 7.1 and 7.2, the average achievement of students from low-income
African-American and Hispanic families is substantially lower than that of middle-
class white American students and of students in other countries. Po verty-afflicted
family environments and neighborhood environments prevent the realization of the
genetic potential of students from low-income families, while middle-class students
are able to achieve at their genetic potential (Turkheimer, Haley, Waldron, D’Onofrio,
& Gottesman, 2003). The medical problems that impair scholastic achievement and
opportunities beyond the school years occur more often and more se verely among
students from low-income families and neighborhoods.
Table 7.1 Mathematics scores (mean = 500) ( Source: PISA* 2000: Lemke et al., 2003)..
Country Score
Japan 557
Korea, Republic of 547
New Zealand 537
Finland 536
Australia 533
Canada 533
United States Average Score of White Students 530
Switzerland 529
United Kingdom 529
Belgium 520
France 517
Austria 515
Denmark 514
Iceland 514
Sweden 510
Ireland 503
Norway 499
Czech Republic 498
United States Average Score 493
Germany 490
Hungary 488
Spain 476
Poland 470
Italy 457
Portugal 454
Greece 447
Luxembourg 446
United States Average Score for Hispanic Students 437
United States Average Score for African American Students 423
Mexico 387
*PIMA = Program on International Student Achie vement Source: Berliner, 2005, p. 20
Poverty 115
Table 7.2 Literacy scores (mean=500) from PISA * 2000 (Lemke et al., 2003)
Country Score
Korea, Republic of 552
Japan 550
United States Average Score of White Students 538
Finland 538
UnitedKingdom 532
Canada 529
New Zealand 528
Australia 528
Austria 519
Ireland 513
Sweden 512
CzechRepublic 511
France 500
Norway 500
United States Average Score 499
Hungary 496
Iceland 496
Belgium 496
Switzerland 496
Spain 491
Germany 487
Poland 483
Denmark 481
Italy 478
Greece 461
Portugal 459
United States Average Score for Hispanic Students 449
United States Average Score for African American Students 445
Luxembourg 443
Mexico 422
*PIMA=Program on International Student Achievement
Source: Berliner, 2005, p. 21
Accordingly, the test scores of students from low-income families and neighbor-
hoods.in the U.S. are substantially lo wer than that of middle-class American stu-
dents and middle-class students in other countries. Po verty-afflicted f amily and
neighborhood environments prevent the realization of the genetic potential of students
from low-income families, while middle-class students are able to achie ve at their
genetic potential, Also the medical problems that impair scholastic achie vement
and employment opportunities beyond the school years occur more often and more
severely among students from low-income families and neighborhoods.
Most important, as Berliner states, seemingly modest decreases in the po verty
level of lo w-income f amilies result in impro ved student beha vior and scholastic
achievement. Poverty seriously restricts the potential of school reform for impro v-
ing how students behave and how much they learn. He describes a study (Dearing,
McCartney, & T aylor, 2001), that used, as a measure of po verty, the ratio of income-
116 7 A Conception of Classroom Management
available to the [f inancial] needs faced by a f amily. A ratio of 1.00 means that the
family is just making it, that its f amily income and needs such as housing, food,
transportation, etc., are matched. A ratio of 3.00 w ould be more lik e that of a
middle-class family, and a ratio of 0.8 w ould indicate poverty of some magnitude.
A large and reasonably representati ve sample of poor and non-poor f amilies were
followed for 3 years, and their income-to-needs ratios were computed re gularly, as
were their children’s scores on various social and academic measures. It was found
was that, as poor families went from poor to a lot less poor, for whatever reasons,
their children’s performance began to resemble that of the never-poor children with
whom they were matched (Berliner, 2005, p. 44).
Berliner’s argument implies that one ef fective, and hitherto well-nigh unused,
way to impro ve schools and achie vement in the U.S. is to reduce the po verty of
low-income families and their children . In the words of Dearing et al. (2001),
Nearly 17% of children in the United States li ve in po verty (U.S. Bureau of the Census,
1999); thus, the importance of these findings, especially with respect to risk and prevention,
is great from an incidence v alidity perspective (see F abes, Martin, Harish, & Upde graff,
2000). The findings of the present study showed that naturally occurring decreases in fam-
ily income-to-needs were associated with worse developmental outcomes for children from
poor f amilies. Conversely, naturally occurring increases in family income-to-needs were
associated with better developmental outcomes for children from poor families .
[italics added] (p. 1791)
Consistent with Berliner’s portrayal of the way poverty affects classroom manage-
ment is the description by Merrow (2004) of the difficulties of obtaining successful
superintendents of big-city schools, such as those of T ucson, St. Louis, Houston,
and Pittsburgh, where man y of the students come from lo w-income f amilies. As
Merrow described it,
Typically, a new superintendent arrives in a city, hailed as the answer to e very problem –
low test scores, poor attendance, embarrassing graduation rates. When change does not
occur overnight, or perhaps at all, disappointment sets in. The superintendent departs for
the next school district, and the c ycle begins anew. (p. B-1)
Instructional Time
The study of classroom management has been formulated in terms of the concept
of instructional time, or the ways in which time is used or misused in the classroom.
A body of theoretical and empirical literature on the v ariables relevant to instruc-
tional time has emerged. The concept of instructional time provides an explanation
for the positive correlation between the many kinds of classroom management and
student achievement. Classroom management deals with techniques that minimize
the amount of time spent in making transitions from one subject or acti vity to
another and the amount of time spent in housekeeping and logistical activities, such
as passing papers around or getting materials ready .
The instructional-time approach stems from influential publications by Carroll
(1963, 1985, 1989), who proposed that three of five major factors in school learning
– the student’ s aptitude , opportunity to learn, and perseverance – could be
expressed in terms of time. Only the fourth factor, ability to understand instruction ,
and the fifth factor, instructional quality, could not be so e xpressed.
1. Student aptitude. The amount of time ordinarily required by a student for learn-
ing content in some domain, such as mathematics or science, other things being
equal.
2. Opportunity to learn. The amount of time allowed for student learning by a pro-
gram, school schedule, or teacher.
3. Perseverance. The amount of time a student is willing to spend on learning a task
or unit of instruction, other things being equal.
4. Ability to understand instruction. In interaction with the method of instruction,
especially in situations where the learner is left to infer for himself the concepts
and relationships to be learned.
5. Quality of instruction. A v ariable that could not be e xpressed in terms of time
but is considered to require that students be told clearly what the y are to learn,
that students must be put into adequate contact with learning materials, and that
steps in learning must be carefully planned and ordered. (p. 714) .
Carroll’s model ga ve birth to a producti ve “instructional-time mo vement” in
education, resulting in, among others, managerial applications to such v ariables as
118 7 A Conception of Classroom Management
length of the school year and the school day . It was an important part of the basis
for Mastery Learning (Bloom, 1968), an influential model of teaching during the
1970s. Other applications took the form of signif icant research on instructional
time, that is, on w ays in which teachers could use classroom management so as to
optimize the use of classroom time and, thus, the level of student achievement (see,
e.g., Ben-Peretz & Bromme, 1990; Berliner , 1987; Denham & Lieberman, 1980;
Fisher & Berliner, 1985). But Gage (1978) pointed to a signif icant gap in Carroll’s
conception of time in the classroom:
Academic learning time, in the form of allocated and engaged learning time is, in a sense,
a psychologically empty quantitative concept. [italics added] W e need better analyses
of how that time is filled, of what learning processes go on during academic learning time.
(p. 75)
Do students actually seek cues for their learning during the teacher’s discourse? On
this question, Winne and Marx (1983) wrote
Do students seek out signals about cognitions? Our answer sho wed that students notice
cues for cognitions that their teachers use during instruction. Ho wever, this does not dem-
onstrate that students actively look for cues. One w ay to show that students seek out cues
is to locate places in lessons where teachers do not claim that a cue w as used. Then, if
students tell us that the y observ ed a cue there nonetheless, we ha ve e vidence that the y
actively look for cues.
Occasionally, we stopped the replay of a lesson for a teacher because we thought a cue
had been given but had not been identif ied. On some of these occasions, the teachers said
that they were not sure that the y really used a cue at that point. On others, the y were sure
that a cue had been used but they gave ambiguous descriptions about the cue that they were
trying to guide students to apply .... When we intervie wed students, we replayed the vide-
otape, stopping it at all these types of situations. The e vidence supporting our contention
that students are active seekers of cues comes from their responses to incidents where their
teacher either was ambiguous about whether a cue was delivered or was certain that no cue
had been used. (pp. 274–275)
The significance of the f inding that students use cues in the teacher beha vior
they witness is that it points to the possibility of using students’ thought processes
as the basis for conjectures as to what is going on during instructional time. Such
conjectures can be illustrated by holding that (a) students are paying attention to
what the teacher is saying, (b) the y understand the curriculum-rele vant features
of what she is saying and what the y have read, (c) their participation in the “lan-
guage game” of Bellack, Kliebard, Hyman, and Smith (1966) enables them to
respond, either audibly or silently, to the teacher’s solicitations, and (d) in formu-
lating their responses the y use cogniti ve processes of the kind re viewed by
Wittrock (1986b).
As the study of instructional time developed, it became clear that instructional time
could be categorized. Berliner (1990) formulated the following:
Allocated time: “The amount of time a state, district, school, or teacher provides the student
for instruction” in a given subject. (p. 4)
Engaged time. “[T]he time that students appear to be paying attention. ” (p. 4)
Time-on-task.”[E]ngaged time on particular learning tasks.” (p. 5)
Academic learning time. “[T]hat part of allocated time in a subject-matter area.... in which
a student is engaged successfully in the acti vities or with the materials to which he or she
is exposed, and in which those activities and materials are related to educational outcomes.
[i.e., are in instructional alignment] with assessments of outcome. ” (p. 5)
Transition time: “[T]he noninstructional time before and after some instructional acti vity.” (p. 5)
Waiting time. “[T]he time a student must w ait to receive some instructional help.” (p. 6)
Pace. “[T]he amount of content co vered during some time period.” (p. 6)
Off-task time. To Berliner’s list we add a kind of time that classroom management should
minimize: time spent in such ways as the aforementioned irrelevant talk between students,
disruptive noise-making, and distracting movement.
120 7 A Conception of Classroom Management
In terms of the definitions of these time variables, our conjectures would be that
student achievement will be
– positively correlated with amounts of allocated time, engaged time, time-on-task, aca-
demic learning time, and pace, and
–negatively correlated with amounts of transition time, w aiting time, and off-task time.
The implication is, of course, that the teacher should aim classroom manage-
ment at increasing the positively-correlated-with-achievement kinds of time and at
reducing the negatively-correlated -with-achievement kinds of time. Some research-
based findings on classroom management can be translated into “teacher should”
statements.
The follo wing e xamples of these f indings in elementary school classrooms were
developed by Brophy and Evertson (1976) and paraphrased by Gage (1978, p. 39):
Teachers should have a system of rules that allo w students to attend to their
personal and procedural needs without having to check with the teacher.
Teachers should move around the room a lot, monitoring students’ seatwork and
communicating to their students an a wareness of their behavior, while also attend-
ing to their academic needs.
When students work independently, teachers should insure that the assignments
are interesting and worthwhile yet still easy enough to be completed by each third
grader without teacher direction.
Teachers should keep to a minimum such acti vities as gi ving directions and
organizing the class for instruction. Teachers can do this by writing the daily sched-
ule on the board, insuring that students kno w where to go, what to do, etc.
In selecting students to respond to questions, teachers should call on a child by
name before asking the question as a means of insuring that all students are gi ven
an equal number of opportunities to answer questions.
With less academically oriented students, teachers should al ways aim at getting
the child to gi ve some kind of response to a question. Rephrasing, gi ving cues, or
asking a new question can be useful techniques for bringing forth some answer from
a previously silent student or one who says, “I don’ t know” or answers incorrectly.
During reading-group instruction, teachers should gi ve a maximal amount of
brief feedback and provide fast-paced activities of the “drill” type.
Emmer and his co-w orkers (Emmer, Sanford, Clements, & Martin, 1982; Emmer ,
Evertson, Sanford, Clements, & W orsham, 1984) de veloped comparable f indings
concerning classroom management for junior and senior high school teachers
Avoiding Biases toward Students 121
Examples of the results of their research are pieces of advice to teachers with such
titles as “keys to room arrangement,” “planning your classroom rules,” and “moni-
toring student work in progress.”
On the important problem of managing inappropriate beha vior, Emmer et al.
(1984) offered the following recommendations:
1. When the student is of f task – that is, not w orking on an assignment – redirect
his attention to the task: “Robert, you should be writing no w.” Or, “Becky, the
assignment is to complete all the problems on the page. ” Check the students’
progress shortly thereafter to make sure they are continuing to work.
2. Make eye contact with or mo ve closer to the student. Use a signal, such as a
finger to the lips or a head shak e, to prompt the appropriate beha vior. Monitor
until the student complies.
3. If the student is not follo wing a procedure correctly, simply reminding the stu-
dent of the correct procedure may be ef fective. You can either state the correct
procedure or ask the student if he or she remembers it.
4. Ask or tell the student to stop the inappropriate beha vior. Then monitor the stu-
dent until it stops and the student be gins constructive activity. (p. 100)
Another realization about classroom management research is that, ho wever
obvious some of its findings may seem, many teachers at all grade levels have failed
at classroom management. And the y have been helped (e.g., Anderson, Ev ertson,
& Brophy, 1979) to do a better job when gi ven training based on the f indings of
research showing how more effective classroom managers behave differently from
those who are less effective.
Research has shown that teachers, usually unintentionally, exhibit biases of various kinds
concerning students – biases that reduce students’ ability to stay on task. Accordingly ,
avoiding such bias is also a signif icant aspect of classroom management.
The bias may stem from teachers’ unwittingly dif ferentiating disadvantageously
against students on the basis of their gender , or ethnicity, or socio-economic status.
Perhaps most difficult bias to avoid is that against low-achieving students.
Biases show up when students get treated dif ferently by teachers in such w ays as
how often students are called upon,
how teachers react to students’ responses,
how long teachers will wait for students to respond to a question,
how often students in dif ferent parts of the classroom – say , the rear and the sides
– may be called upon,
how often teachers give justified praise or reproof to students.
Since the bias is usually unintentional, teachers tend to be una ware of it. If so,
merely mentioning bias may tend to reduce it. Another possibly helpful practice
122 7 A Conception of Classroom Management
calls upon Teacher A to invite Teacher B to observe in Teacher A’s classroom, and
perhaps count the occurrences of an y of the abo ve-mentioned biases. Analyzing
such data might make Teacher A aware of her biases.
The concept of instructional time provides an e xplanation for the positi ve cor-
relation between the many kinds of classroom management and student achievement.
Classroom management deals with techniques that minimize the amount of time
spent in making transitions from one subject or acti vity to another and the amount
of time spent in housek eeping and logistical acti vities, such as passing papers
around or getting materials ready.
Chapter 8
Integrating the Conceptions
The notion of a single theory that does full justice to the phenomenon being
explained is, of course, attractive but infeasible for teaching. An example of a single
adequate theory is Isaac Ne wton’s second la w of motion; it embraces only three
variables (force, mass, and acceleration), related as f = ma, or force equals mass
times acceleration. Ev en so, it held only for frictionless surf aces and motion in a
vacuum. In the e veryday world, without the v acuum and with friction, matters get
more complicated.
Typically, scientif ic theories refer to relationships between man y v ariables.
In the behavioral sciences, theories of complex phenomena are abundant. Behavior
theory (Skinner, 1953) relates dri ve, behavior, reinforcement, e xtinction, response
generalization, and operant conditioning. Cognitive learning theory (Levine, 1975)
deals with short-term memory (w orking memory), long-term memory , and its
rehearsal, decoding, and retrie val processes. Cogniti ve-abilities theory (Carroll,
1993; Detterman, 1994; Gardner , 1983; Neisser , 1998) deals with general ability
(g), group abilities, special abilities, and IQ change. Cogniti ve dissonance theory
(Festinger, 1957; Harmon-Jones & Mills, 1999) speaks of relationships between
dissonance ratio, psychological comfort, a versive consequences, self-af firmation,
and dissonance magnitude.
Sub-Theories
[A] deducti ve-nomological [D-N] e xplanation is not concei ved as in voking only one
covering law; and our illustrations sho w how indeed many different laws may be invoked
in explaining one phenomenon. A purely logical point should be noted here, however. If an
explanation is of the form (D-N), then the la ws L 1 , L2, …, L r invoked in its e xplanans
[explaining ideas] logically imply a la w L which by itself w ould suf fice to e xplain the
explanandum [thing to be e xplained] event by reference to the particular conditions noted
in the sentences C 1 , C2, …, C k. This law L is to the ef fect that whenever conditions of the
kind described in the sentences C 1 , C2, …, C k are realized then an e vent of the kind
described by an explanandum-sentence occurs. (p. 346)
*
Written in collaboration with Thomas Burro ws Gage.
Sub-Theories of the Process of Teaching 125
The follo wing presentations of sub-theories f irst pro vide an example of the
phenomenon to be explained and then a covering law explaining that phenom-
enon. The term example signif ies that the pedagogical phenomenon has not
necessarily been as well established as if, for instance, it had been demonstrated
by successive valid meta-analyses. That requirement could not have been met, in
view of the lack of suf ficient research-based evidence. Instead, only an e xample
of the phenomenon is presented, and the proposed co vering la w is of fered to
indicate what the e xplanation could ha ve been if the phenomenon had been
well established.
The term covering law was used by Hempel (1965, pp. 345–346) to refer to the
deductive-nomological explanation of the phenomenon. Unlike his explanations of
phenomena in the physical sciences, the covering laws used in the present theory of
teaching are not strong deducti ve-nomological laws. Rather, they may be a logical
law, such as a v alid syllogism. Or the y may be a uni versally accepted common-
place, such as the desirability of rationality . Or the y may be well-established
empirical generalizations, such as the positive correlation between students’ socio-
economic status and their academic achie vement. Each of these possibilities may
be used to e xplain a phenomenon that occurs in teaching. The e xplanation of the
phenomenon is deduced from the co vering law.
Sub-Theories of Structuring
We turn now to sub-theories for each of the four components – structuring, soliciting,
responding, and reacting – of the process of CDR teaching. Each of these can be
the subject of a sub-theory. We begin with Bellack’s definition.
1.1 Structuring (STR). Structuring moves serve the function of setting the context for
subsequent behavior by (1) launching or halting-excluding interactions between teacher
and students, and (2) indicating the nature of the interaction in terms of the dimensions of
time, agent, activity, topic and cognitive process, regulations, reasons, and instructional
aids. A structuring move may set the contest for the entire classroom game or a part of the
game. (Bellack, Kliebard, Hyman, & Smith, 1966, pp. 16–17)
Examples of brief structuring. Everyone who has been a student has experienced
a teacher’s structuring. We readily think of e xamples, embracing both process
and content, of what teachers ha ve done in “setting the conte xt for subsequent
behavior or performance.” Table 8.1presents brief examples.
The length and duration of teacher structuring can be much lar ger than these
examples as teachers “set the conte xt,” “con vey an implicit directi ve,” “launch
classroom discussion in specif ied directions, ” and “focus on topics, subjects or
problems to be discussed, or procedures to be follo wed.”
Functions of Structuring
Our … categorization divides memory into three structural components: the sensory register,
the short-term store, and the long-term store. Incoming sensory information first enters the
sensory register, where it resides for a very brief period of time then decays and is lost. The
short-term store is the subject’ s w orking memory; it recei ves selected inputs from the
sensory re gister and also from the long-term store. Information in the short-term store
decays completely and is lost within a period of about 30 seconds, b ut a control process
called rehearsal can maintain a limited amount of information in this store as long as the
subject desires. The long-term store is a fairly permanent repository for information, infor-
mation which is transferred from the short-term store. (pp. 90–91)
The covering law: Role theory (e.g., Biddle, 1979; Johnson & Johnson, 1995;
Newcomb, 1950) e xplains this student acceptance as resulting from the superior
status of the teacher – a status deri ved from the teacher’ s social position in the
classroom, the school, the community , and the society – and the role (e xpected
behavior) that accompanies that position. Students’ perceptions of the teacher’s role
result in students’ expectations that the teacher will tak e responsibility for guiding
students as they seek to achieve objectives specified in the curriculum.
Example 1 of the phenomenon to be explained: The teacher can guide students’
cognitive processes by suggesting that students focus on some content – an e vent,
phenomenon, problem-solution, or other intellectual entity relevant to the objectives
of the lesson. The teacher can suggest that students monitor their o wn intellectual
processes, that is, use metacognition, by asking themselv es such questions as “Do
I really understand what the teacher or the book has said?” or “Can I apply this
principle?” or “Should I review this material again?”
Example 2 of the phenomenon to be explained: Metacognitive training can
improve mathematical reasoning, as illustrated by an e xperiment (Kramarski &
Mevarech, 2003a, b) in which eighth-graders received metacognitive training consist-
ing of three sets of self-addressed metacognitive questions: comprehension questions,
strategic questions, and connection questions. As Kramarski and Me varech (2003b)
put it,
The comprehension questions were designed to prompt students to reflect on a problem
before solving it.... The strate gic questions were designed to prompt students to consider
which strategies were appropriate for solving or completing a gi ven problem or task and
for what reasons …. The connection questions were designed to prompt students to focus
on similarities and dif ferences between the immediate problem or task and problems or
tasks that they had already completed successfully. (p. 286)
Compared with an untrained control group, the trained group sho wed improved
achievement of mathematical reasoning.
Example 3 of the phenomenon to be explained: Another version of metacogni-
tive effects occurs when students are advised to use “chunking” to f acilitate their
ability to remember a series of numbers, letters, or w ords. The chunking breaks up
a series of, say , 15 items (w ords, numbers, names, etc.) into, say three groups of
five items, i.e., small groups that are easier to remember .
The covering law: Metacognition, or students’ monitoring of their o wn cogni-
tive processes, improves achievement by providing the student with covert practice,
self-guidance, and rewards.
Structuring as Lecturing
Structuring lends itself to further analysis through the kinds of research that ha ve
been done on lecturing. The teacher, in structuring the discourse that sets the stage
for the subsequent components of the teaching c ycle, may gi ve a brief lecture –
typically, an uninterrupted monolog.
Sub-Theories of the Process of Teaching 129
So there must be a place for an unsimplif ied, and so more or less unsystematic,
logic of the natural counterparts of these de vices; this logic may be aided and
guided by the simplified logic of the formal devices but cannot be supplanted by it;
indeed, not only do the tw o logics dif fer, but sometimes the y come into conflict;
rules that hold for a formal de vice may not hold for its natural counterpart (p. 43).
Grice’s argument makes room for the analysis of natural language in terms of its
“communicative logic.” The natural language studied by Needels (1988) w as that
Sub-Theories of the Process of Teaching 131
of the lesson’s objectives, namely, (a) comprehension of the lesson content and (b)
interest in the content of the lesson.
The unit of analysis of the data w as the test item. The results for the f irst analysis
of teachers’ initial, that is, not self-corrected, violations of the logic of classroom dis-
course showed “no consistenc y [across test items] in the direction (positi ve or ne ga-
tive)” of the correlations between the teachers’ illogicality measures on the subject
matter of a test item and their students’ percentage of correct responses to that item.
But then the teachers were scored for their subsequently (during the same presen-
tation) corrected-by-themselves versions of their communicative illogic. After such
corrections, consistent across-items negative relationships (determined with a test of
the significance of combined results) were found between (a) the teacher’ s self-cor-
rected degree of illogicality on Confusing Syntax rele vant to a given item of the les-
son-comprehension test and (b) their high-aptitude students’ percentage of correct
responses on that item of the test. Apparently, only the high-aptitude students became
confused by their teacher’s illogic and understood that item of the test less well.
Also, the correlation between (a) frequenc y of illogical discourse and (b) the
students’ mean favorability of attitude toward the lesson content w as determined.
It suggested that “a greater de gree of communicati ve illogic on the teacher’ s part
was associated with less f avorable student attitudes to ward the lesson content”
(Needels, 1988, p. 522).
A Second Study of Communicative Logic. Huh (1985) carried out a study similar
to that of Needels. The main dif ference was that it w as conducted in Seoul, South
Korea, not the U.S. Huh also def ined, in form, ten kinds of illogic: (a) confusing
syntax, (b) vagueness, (c) verbal mazes, (d) incomplete e xplanation, (e) irrelevance,
(f) gaps in definition, (g) incoherence, (h) inconsistency, (i) incorrect explanation, and
(j) analytical errors.
Ten sixth-grade teachers taught their students tw o 1-hr lessons on se ven topics
about light: reflection, refraction, properties of light, lenses, absorption, prisms, and
color. The audio-recorded lessons, transcribed and analyzed, yielded scores for each
teacher on each of the ten kinds of illogic. The teachers’ scores on the measures of
illogicality differed significantly from one another and correlated negatively (r =-.24)
with their students’ total scores on tw o tests of lesson comprehension.
In short, these two studies suggest that structuring, like all oral communication,
is comprehensible to the de gree that it conforms to the principles of “communica-
tive” logic.
The covering law: Valid communicati ve logic meets the listener’ s needs and
expectations acquired through experience in everyday discourse.
i.e., deriving by reasoning or judging from premises or evidence – that the observer
or auditor of teaching beha vior must use in judging the occurrence or amount of
that behavior variable. Some behaviors require relatively little inference; examples
of these are the numbers of times a teacher calls on girls or boys and the frequency
with which the teacher writes on a chalkboard. Other behaviors require a consider-
able inference from what is seen or heard in the classroom, such as the de gree to
which the teacher is partial v ersus fair, autocratic v ersus democratic, aloof v ersus
warm, or the de gree to which students are apathetic v ersus alert, or obstructi ve
versus cooperative.
Thus inference-le vel becomes important in teacher education when oral or
printed advice is gi ven to teachers on ho w the y should perform in order to act
appropriately on the need for , say , comprehensibility . It becomes important in
studying teaching when observers must judge, say, comprehensibility. A high level
of inference causes the w ords presented to be susceptible to man y interpretations,
i.e., vague and ambiguous. A low level occurs when the words are explicit, readily
interpreted, and precise as to their references to beha vior.
Typically, high-inference features of teaching are e valuated with a rating scale,
that is, “an instrument used to assign scores to persons or objects on some numerical
dimension” (V andenBos, 2007, p. 769). Lo w-inference features are typically
estimated by counting observ ers’ tallies of the occurrences of the beha vior being
measured. It is sometimes held that high-inference instructions are the more effective
for communicating “molar,” or comprehensive, abstract aspects of action or behavior
and that low-inference instructions are more effective for communicating “molecular,”
or specific, components of action or beha vior.
High-Inference Variables. McConnell and Bowers (1979) furnished examples of
high-inference variables; they included ratings of teacher clarity, teacher variability,
teacher enthusiasm, teacher use of student ideas, teacher pro vision of opportunity
to learn, and teacher task-orientation. Such ratings call for much inference from the
terms used to the action designated, often resulting in ambiguity and confusion for
the recipient of the advice.
Low-Inference Variables. When the amount of inference from the advice is lo w,
determiners of comprehensibility are more unambiguously expressed, understood, and
acted upon. The following list, drawn from McConnell and Bowers (1979), illustrates
low-inference variables:
Teacher statements were classif ied as af fective, substantive, or procedural. Interchanges,
particularly those relating to content, were classif ied as to entry and e xit. An entry to an
interchange could be a pupil question, a teacher question get ting a student to elaborate,
a teacher question intending to elicit pupil thought and di vergent response, or a teacher
question aimed at a specif ic response. The e xits were based on teacher responses to the
student portion of the interchange: acceptance, disappro val, or neutral. (p. 6)
Inference Level and Outcome Prediction. The inference level of teacher-action
variables may be signif icant not only for the communicability of advice to, or
observation of, teachers. It may also af fect the value of a teacher-behavior vari-
able for correlating with, or predicting, student achie vement and attitude.
Example of the phenomenon to be explained: McConnell and Bo wers (1979)
compared high- and low-inference measures of teaching behaviors as to their value
134 8 Integrating the Conceptions
Sub-Theories of Soliciting
1.2. Soliciting (SOL). Moves in this category typically take the form of questions intended
to elicit (a) an active verbal response on the part of the persons addressed; (b) a cognitive
response, e.g., encouraging persons addressed to attend to something; or (c) a physical
response. (Bellack et al., 1966, p. 18)
As the CDR model specifies, the next step in an episode of teaching is soliciting.
The term “soliciting” is used, rather than its more common near-synonym questioning,
because soliciting need not take grammatically interrogative form. “Although these
[soliciting] moves may take all grammatical forms – declarative, interrogative, and
imperative – the interrogative occurs most frequently” (Bellack et al., 1966, p. 18).
A soliciting mo ve may be a declarati ve sentence that be gins with an emphasis
(Magellan discovered America?) or ends with an upward lilt (17 + 13 = 30 ?).Such
forms of soliciting serve the same purposes as questions.
Goodlad (1984), in his observ ational study of 1,017 classrooms, found that
“Less than 1% of [soliciting] time is devoted to open questions which call for more
complex cogniti ve or af fective responses [by students]” (Sirotnik, 1983, p. 20).
Observations of CDR teaching indicate that teachers uniformly , in all grade le vels
and subject matters, ask about 90% of the questions in classroom discourse.
Students do a correspondingly high percentage of the responding (Dillon, 1988).
Pedagogical moves occur in classroom discourse in certain cyclical patterns and combinations,
which are designated teaching cycles. A teaching cycle begins either with a structuring mo ve
or with a solicitation that is not preceded by a structuring mo ve. (Bellack et al., 1966, p. 19)
The question serves (a) to focus the students’ attention on some part of the struc-
turing, and (b) to engage the students in discovering how well they have understood
the structuring.
Teacher Questions During Discussions. In discussions, students’ utterances are
longer than those in recitations, are aimed at fellow participants (classmates), and are
mostly steered by the students themselves. Teachers often ask questions, or solicit,
when they want students to participate in a discussion of a topic, issue, or phenom-
enon. Teachers’ questions should obviously call forth students’ responses.
Sub-Theories of the Process of Teaching 135
Fig. 8.1 After teacher questions (Qs), students’ utterances become briefer, but after teacher non-
questions (Xs), students’ utterances are longer (Adapted from Dillon, 1985, p. 116) .
136 8 Integrating the Conceptions
Redfield and Rousseau (1981) follo wed Winne’s review with “a meta-analysis
[quantitative synthesis] of experimental research on teacher questioning behavior.”
138 8 Integrating the Conceptions
Those authors added one e xperiment to the 18 re viewed by Winne and computed
measures of “ef fect size” (rather than the less informati ve measures of statistical
significance used by W inne; see Kline, 2004). Redf ield and Rousseau concluded
that their analysis “demonstrates that, re gardless of type of study or de gree of
experimental validity, teachers’ predominant use of higher cogniti ve questions has
a positive effect on student achievement” (p. 244).
A second quantitative synthesis of mostly the same literature w as performed by
Samson, Strykowski, Weinstein, and Walberg (1987). Their conclusion, stemming
from modifications in the selection and analysis of the data, was that “higher cogni-
tive questioning strategies have a small positive median effect on learning measures
but not as lar ge as has been suggested by the pre vious meta-analysis [by Redf ield
and Rousseau (1981)].”
The conclusion from these three re views of e xperiments on question-outcome
relationships is that the superiority of higher -order questions for promoting achie ve-
ment is hard to demonstrate. The effect sizes in their favor are unreliable, and teachers
who ask higher-order questions are not rewarded by higher student achievement.
Hirsch’s Defense of “Knowledge Questions.” Hirsch (1987) questioned the
value of higher -order questions. He reasoned that so- called lower-order ques-
tions that ask students (merely?) for their kno wledge (things remembered) ha ve
greater educational v alue than the supporters of higher -order objecti ves ha ve
granted them. He ar gued that the higher intellectual skills depend on specif ic
knowledge and are therefore specific to particular domains.
In Hirsch’s view, critical thinkers and problem solvers in one field, such as math-
ematics or history , usually f all short in other f ields because the think ers lack the
necessary knowledge. The chess champion may be a duffer in politics; the brilliant
logician may be simple-minded about ethics. The reason for this specificity of critical
thinking ability is that enormous amounts of time are necessary for one to acquire
the knowledge needed for expertise in any complex domain. So it becomes unrealistic
to hope for any great accomplishments as a result of general, or non-domain-specific,
training in critical thinking and problem solving. T raining that produces good
thinkers across many different domains is not yet validated.
Accordingly, the importance of kno wledge, def ined as ability to remember
(recall or recognize) something heard, read, or otherwise e xperienced, should not
be disparaged. Hirsch (1987), acting on his appreciation of kno wledge, formulated
the concept of “cultural literacy: specific knowledge needed by every member of a
society for participating fully in its af fairs.” The follo wing sample of items from
Hirsch’s 62-page list of about 2,600 items illustrates what, in Hirsch’ s conception
of cultural literacy, adult Americans should know about:
Archimedes, biofeedback, cabinet (government), composite materials, Death of
a Salesman, diffraction, Emancipation Proclamation, The grass is al ways greener
on the other side, Grimm Brothers, Joshua, memento mori [a reminder of death,
such as a skull], paragraph, relative humidity, Stalinism, V-E Day.
All this is not to de-emphasize the importance of the “higher” cogniti ve objec-
tives. Rather , it recognizes the inordinate dif ficulty of seeking to achie ve such
Sub-Theories of the Process of Teaching 139
objectives without insuring that the student has the prior or concurrent body of
knowledge on which those higher mental processes can operate.
Wait-Time in Asking Questions. Another aspect of soliciting is wait-time ,defined
by Rowe (1974) as being of tw o kinds:
Wait-time 1—the number of seconds a teacher waits after asking a question before calling
on a student to answer it, and W ait-time 2—the number of seconds after the student’ s
response before the teacher reacts in some w ay.
Rowe reported that the a verage teacher’s two wait-times tended to be e xceed-
ingly short, a veraging 1 second. She found that increasing w ait-times by a fe w
seconds tended to (a) increase students’ response length, (b) elicit more unsolicited
appropriate responses, (c) impro ve student conf idence, (d) raise the frequenc y of
speculative responses, (e) enhance the thoughtfulness of responses, and (f) increase
the frequenc y of student-to-student data comparisons, e vidence-inference state-
ments, student questions, and responses from relati vely slow students.
Giaconia (1988) found that, in her sample of nine f ifth- and sixth-grade teachers,
Rowe’s conclusions about the duration of w ait-time were not entirely accurate.
Giaconia’s technology for measuring w ait-time yielded, for the nine teachers she
recorded, averages from 1.45 to 3.45 second for w ait-time 1 and 0.63 to 2.15 second
for wait-time 2. “Most of these w ait-times were about twice as lar ge as the ‘typical’
wait-time 1 value of 1.0 second reported by Ro we (1974)” (Giaconia, 1988, p. 251).
But the important question is not whether these dif ferences in fractions of a second
between Rowe’s and Giaconia’ s findings make a dif ference in student performance
and achievement. Rather it is whether any extended wait-time 1 or 2 of the kind f irst
studied by Rowe (1974) makes a difference in student behavior or achievement as com-
pared with that of students whose teachers were una ware of the issue of wait-time.
Giaconia’s (1988) descripti ve, that is, non-interv entional, study, reported that
“The role of w ait-time appeared subordinate to that of question characteristics in
predicting these [desirable] response characteristics” (p. 253). The response charac-
teristics were syntactical comple xity, length, and cogniti ve le vel of students’
responses to questions. That is, questions that had higher cogniti ve le vels, were
divergent (i.e., had several correct answers) rather than convergent (had only one correct
answer), and open-ended rather than closed-ended, had a greater ef fect on the
students’ response characteristics than wait-time did.
Example of the phenomenon to be explained: Pond and Ne wman (1988) found
that a wait-time of five seconds increased the number of correct responses to textu-
ally implicit material on standardized reading tests b ut not for te xtually e xplicit
material. The authors surmised that the effect resulted from the students’ awareness
of and involvement in the strate gy. They also concluded that student a wareness of
the wait-time strategy, from hearing explanations of it and using it extensively, was
advantageous. Similarly, increasing the w ait-times 1 and 2 of teachers’ soliciting
increases the frequency, length, appropriateness, confidence, originality, thorough-
ness, and speculativeness of students’ responses.
The covering law: Cognitive processes, including responding to questions, may
be re garded as responses to more or less comple x eliciting stimuli, and reaction
140 8 Integrating the Conceptions
time – the time interv al between the onset of a stimulus and the onset of an o vert
response – is positively correlated with stimulus complexity.
Since students do almost all of the responding, in what w ay does responding fit
into a theory of teaching? The answer is that student responses pro vide teachers
with feedback. Ho w teachers percei ve and respond to that feedback f alls into the
category of what a theory of teaching should embrace. And that feedback inevitably
shapes ho w the teacher reacts .The student’s response has se veral characteristics,
such as the student’ s (a) f actual correctness v ersus error, (b) conf idence v ersus
hesitancy of response, (c) economy v ersus superfluity of w ords and ideas, and (d)
originality versus triteness. Each of these provides the teacher with useful information.
Factual Correctness Versus Incorrectness. If the student’s response is correct, it
tells the teacher one or more of such things as: The student already kne w or could
do, prior to being taught, what the question ask ed for . Or the student has just
learned what the question ask ed for. Or the student made a luck y guess. Or the
teacher’s question was extremely low in difficulty. Or the teacher’s prior structuring
was comprehended. The teacher may react to the correctness with a positi ve
comment, such as “Good,” “Correct,” “That’s right.”
If the student’s response is incorrect, the response tells the teacher one or more
of such things as: The student had not read the assignment. Or the student w as not
paying attention. Or the teacher’s structuring was not comprehended by the student.
Or the student did not understand the te xtbook.
The covering law: The teacher’s reaction to the student’s response. How the
teacher reacts to the student’s response may be understood in terms of perceptual
Sub-Theories of the Content of Teaching 141
control theory (Powers, 1973; Runkel, 2003). In brief, perceptual control theory
holds that persons’ behavior is and should be aimed at their control of their per-
ceptions. When a person’s perceptions are close to a pre-defined reference point
set by the person’ s needs or desires, the percei ver acts so as to main tain the
existing situation. When those perceptions are distant from, or unlik e, the refer-
ence point, the percei ver operates so as to mo ve the perception closer to the
reference point, that is, to change the existing situation to something that will be
perceived as closer.
Accordingly, suppose a teacher’s reference point for what she wants to perceive
is a student’ s correct response. If the student mak es an incorrect response, the
teacher – trying to optimize her perception – should e xperience pressure to correct
the student’s response. She can do so by gi ving the student an e xplanation of why
the response w as incorrect and ho w the student’s subsequent responses to similar
questions can be correct. But Sirotnik (1983), reporting on the data from Goodlad’s
(1984) large-scale observational study, A Place Called School, held that
Providing corrective feedback in combination with additional information designed to help
students understand and correct their mistakes is almost nonexistent. [italics added] In fact,
reinforcement of any kind is rarely noticed [italics added] whether in the form of specif ic
task-related acknowledgement and praise or general support and encouragement (p. 20) ….
In summary, the typical classroom patterns consist of (1) the teacher’s explaining or lectur-
ing to the whole class or to a single student, asking direct, factual questions on the subject
matter, or monitoring students; and (2) the students ’ ostensibly listening to the teacher and
responding to teacher-initiated interaction. (pp. 20–21)
Thus it is possible to sort these quotations from Sirotnik according to the cate gories
of Bellack et al., (1966). Doing so indicates that the f indings of A Place Called School
(Goodlad, 1984) agree well with the Structuring-Soliciting-Responding-Reacting
analysis of classroom teaching constructed by Bellack et al., (1966), and conf irmed by
Hoetker and Ahlbrand (1969) and Mehan (1979).
We turn now to sub-theories of the content of teaching. This treatment will draw
upon the conception of content set forth in Chap. 5. In that chapter , a central con-
cept was instructional alignment – the similarity between the content taught and the
content assessed.
Instructional Alignment
(a) in a subject matter , (b) during a specif ic term of teaching, (c) to students of a
specified kind. It is the curriculum that should reign over, i.e., serve as the criterion
for, the content of both the teaching and the assessment of student achie vement.
That is, the curriculum should be the criterion by which the v alidity of the content
of teaching and the content of assessment should be judged.
As the criterion, the curriculum should be determined, in the f irst place, by the
nature of the subject matter, e.g., whether it is of the physical sciences (chemistry,
mathematics, physics), the biological sciences (botany, genetics, physiology, zool-
ogy), the humanities (reading, art, composition, literature, music), or the social
sciences (anthropology, civics, geography, history, psychology, sociology). These
categories determine the kind of kno wledge taught and the corresponding objec-
tives at which the teaching should be aimed.
The curriculum should also be af fected by the societal and personal v alues that
the teaching should serve. The societal values are those determined by the needs of
the society in which the education occurs. The personal v alues are those of the
students and their teacher.
(a)
Theoretical, the discovery of true knowledge and comprehension for their own
sake,
(b)Economic, usefulness, practicality, the accumulation of wealth,
(c)Aesthetic, the creation and appreciation of form, harmon y, and beauty,
(d)Social, helping other people,
(e)Political, acquiring power and leadership, not necessarily in politics, and
(f)Religous, achieving mystical or spiritual union with a deity .
The various subject-matter curricula may serve these values in varying degrees.
Among these are such affinities as
(a) science,mathematics, and history with theoretical values;
(b) economics,business administration, and accounting with economic values;
(c) literature,music, and art with aesthetic values;
(d)subjects leading to nursing, social work, and medical work with social values;
(e) vics,
ci political science, and leadership with political values;
(f) ethicsand theology with religious values.
But the signif icance of v alues for education lies not only in the curriculum.
Allport et al., (1960) used Spranger’ s categories to de velop a questionnaire for
ranking these values in an individual’s personality. Such a ranking of a teacher‘s
values, which constitute presage variables, affects the subtleties of her processes
in teaching the content. When that content is congruent with her values, it is likely
that she displays more enthusiasm than when teaching content less closely
associated with her values. These differences are not lost upon her students. The
teacher’s enthusiasm has a considerable history of importance in the research on
teaching of the last half-century.
Examples of a phenomenon requiring explanation: (a) Rosenshine (1971)
brought together five studies in which observers’ ratings of teacher enthusiasm cor-
related .37 to .56 with student achie vement. (b) Colle ge students who recei ved
144 8 Integrating the Conceptions
enthusiastically delivered lectures reported greater intrinsic moti vation and experi-
enced higher levels of vitality (Patrick, Hisley, & Kempler, 2000).
Covering Law 1:Role theory (e.g., Biddle, 1979; Johnson & Johnson, 1995;
Newcomb, 1961) focuses on the teacher’ s superior status in the classroom, so that
the teacher’s enthusiasm about what is being taught makes that content have greater
value in the perceptions of the students.
Covering Law 2: The teacher behaviors that betoken her enthusiasm – gesturing,
varying intonation, mo ving back and forth, e xciting analogies and e xamples, and
humor – arouse student interest by their contrast with the typically sober tenor
and subject matters of classroom events.
Until now we have taken teaching apart. Now it is time to put it together. The parts
have been (a) the teaching’ s process: the teacher’ s structuring and soliciting, the
students’ responding, and the teacher’s reacting; (b) the content of the teaching: its
types of knowledge and the cognitive processes applied to that type of kno wledge;
and (c) the students’ cogniti ve capability and moti vation: above-average, average,
and below-average.
Putting it together consists of sho wing how the various elements of process are
related to those of content, and how both must be appropriate to the students’ cogni-
tive capability and motivation.
One way to put teaching together, that is, to show this integration, or interrelat-
edness, is to consider process, content, and cognitive capability as the three dimen-
sions of a rectangular solid, shown in Fig. 8.2 .
Rectangular solid sho wing three dimensions, each di vided into se gments (a)
Process (structuring, soliciting, and reacting), (b) Content (four types of content and
two types of cogniti ve process: kno wledge and understanding), and (c) Student
Cognitive Capability and Motivation (below average, average, and above average).
We consider the process dimension of the solid to be divided into three teacher-
performed segments: structuring, soliciting, and reacting. The content dimension
of the solid has eight se gments: one for each of the eight possible pairings of the
four types of kno wledge (factual, conceptual, procedural, metacogniti ve), and two
types of cognitive process (knowing and understanding). The cognitive capability
and motivation dimension is arbitrarily divided into three segments: above-average,
average, and below-average.
Within this 3 × 8 × 3 solid, we can visualize 72 cells, each of which represents
a particular combination of one se gment of the three dimensions. Some of these
Integrating the Sub-Theories 147
Content
Knowledge Understanding
Meta- Meta-
Factual Conceptual Procedural Factual Conceptual Procedural
cognitive cognitive
Process
Structuring
Soliciting
Below
Average
Reacting Average
Above
Average
Cognitive
Capability
and Motivation
cells will, in actuality, have many more occurrences of teaching cycles than others.
But in theory , each of them is a possible conjunction of a type of process with a
type of content for a le vel of cognitive capability and motivation. Table 8.2 shows
examples of teaching c ycles consisting of dif ferent segments of the three dimen-
sions of teaching.
Example 1. Ms. Eugster may engage in structuring a kind of factual knowl-
edge that she w ants her students of average cognitive capability to remember .
Here the process se gment is structuring, the content se gment is factual knowl-
edge, and the cogniti ve processing se gment is remembering. The structuring
consists of informing all her students that the Declaration of Independence w as
signed on July 4, 1776, and that she w ants all her students to remember this
important date in U.S. history.
Example 2. Ms. Halfpenn y may engage in soliciting an answer to a question
about conceptual knowledge from a student of above-average cognitive capability.
Here the process se gment is soliciting, the content se gment is conceptual knowl-
edge, the cognitive process segment is understanding, and the cognitive capability
segment is above-average. The soliciting consists of asking an above-average stu-
dent to show his understanding by deriving the Pythagorean theorem.
Example 3. Ms. Bollenbacher reacts to the erroneous response of a below-average
student to a question about procedural knowledge. Here the process se gment is
reacting, the content segment is “how to punctuate a quotation,” and cognitive capa-
bility segment is below-average. The reacting consists of saying, “Come on, you can
do better. Think of how a quotation looks on the page of a book. T ake your time.”
Example 4. Ms. Ross structures by telling all her students to apply the concept
of metacognitive knowledge to their o wn studying for a quiz. Here the process
148 8 Integrating the Conceptions
I intend the theory presented in the fore going chapters to belong to the beha vioral
sciences. That is, it is intended to set forth relationships between v ariables – rela-
tionships that cohere as (a) phenomena in teaching that ha ve been or could be
observed empirically, and (b) e xplanations of those phenomena. In the beha vioral
sciences, such relationships are not as mathematically tight as the relationships in
the physical sciences. Rather, as was noted in Chap. 3, the y are probabilistic.
The theory should not be re garded as a formula or recipe for good teaching.
Rather, as I put it in 1978,
Teaching is an art — a useful, or practical, art rather than one dedicated to the creation of
beauty and the e vocation of aesthetic pleasure as ends in themselv es. As a practical art,
teaching must be recognized as a process that calls for intuition, creati vity, improvisation,
and expressiveness — a process that lea ves room for departures from what is implied by
rules, formulas, and algorithms. In teaching, by whate ver method it proceeds, there is a
need for artistry: in the choice and use of moti vational devices, clarifying definitions [and
explanations], pace, redundancy, and the like. (p. 15)
Artistic influences operate in man y other kinds of w ork that are go verned by
bodies of theory. In music, the scores of concertos and symphonies govern perform-
ances altogether tightly , b ut the performers and conductors are permitted, e ven
expected, to modify the performance with artistry —their own subtleties of volume,
rhythm, and tempo. The star violinist in a music school follows the notes faithfully,
but he does not come close to the artistry of a f amous virtuoso, a Jascha Heifetz.
In aeronautics, a graduate student in aeronautical engineering can obey the laws of
aerodynamics, just as all engineers must obey those laws. But an American group of
engineers designs a four-jet airliner, say, the Boeing 747, that differs in artistic detail
from a European group’ s four-jet Airbus. In poetry, the form of all sonnets must be
the same – 14 lines made up of an octave (a stanza of eight lines) and a sestet (the last
six lines) – all embodying the statement and resolution of a single theme. Ob viously,
the restrictions of that form allow abundant room for artistry.
A theory of teaching is analogous to the sonata composer’s score, the engineer’s laws
of aerodynamics, and the poet’ s rules of some forms of poetry . The teachers who
follow the implications of the covering laws used in the present theory of teaching will
not lack freedom to adjust their performance to their insights and intuitions. The y will
be free to depart from the co vering laws of our conceptions of the process of teaching,
the content of teaching, the cognitive capabilities and motivation of students, and class-
room management. As Schön (1983) put it, the y can use “reflection-in-action (the
‘thinking about what the y are doing while the y are doing it’) that practitioners some-
times bring to situations of uncertainty, uniqueness, and conflict” (p. xi). Scöhn (1987)
also wrote of “educating the reflecti ve practitioner .” The practitioner’ s reflections
The Culmination: Using the Theory 149
consist of his attempts to mer ge his kno wledge of the theory underlying his practice
with whatever artistry can enhance his practice.”
The teacher will learn from experience when she should stay close to the impli-
cations of the covering laws and when to depart from them. And she will learn from
experience whether the structure of the present theory helps her think constructively
about her teaching.
References
151
152 References
Beck
er , B.J. (1996) .Thegeneralizability of empirical research results .In C. P. Benbo w &
D. Lubinski (Eds.), Intellectual talent: Psychometric and other issues (pp. 362 – 383 ).
Baltimore :JohnsHopkins University Press .
Becker, H. J. (2000). Findings from the teaching, learning, and computing survey: Is Larry Cuban
right? Educational Policy Analysis Archives. http://epaa.asu.edu/epaa/v8n51
Bellack, A. A. (1976). Studies in the language of the classroom. Paper presented at the First Invitational
Conference on Teaching. Memorial University of Newfoundland, St. John’s, May 25.
BellackA.,A. , Kliebard H. , M. , Hyman R. , T. &
, Smith .F,L. (1966)The . language of the class-
room .Ne w York : Teachers College Press .
Ben-Peretz M. , &, Bromme R. , (Eds.). (1990) The . nature of time in schools: Theoretical con-
cepts, practitioner perceptions .Ne w York : T eachers College Press .
Ber
ger , J.&, Zelditch M. , (Eds.). (1993)Theoretical
. research programs .Stanford,CA : Stanford
University Press .
Berliner, D.C. (1987) .Simpleviews of effective teaching and a simple theory of classroom
instruction In . D.
C. Berliner& B. V. Rosenshine(Eds.), Talks to teachers 93 – 110 Ne
w. York :
RandomHouse .
Berliner, D.C. (1989) .Theplace of process-product research in developing the agenda for
research on teacher thinking . Educational Psychologist, 24 ,324 – 344 .
Berliner, D.C. (1990) .What’ s all the fuss about instructional time? In M.Ben-Peretz& R.
Bromme(Eds.), The nature of time in schools: Theoretical concepts, practitioner perceptions
3 – 35Ne w. York : T
eachers College Press .
Berliner, D. C. (2005). Our impo verished view of educational reform. Teachers College Record ,
published August 2, 2005. Retrieved October 30, 2005, from http://www.tcrecord.org/content.
asp?contentid = 12106.
Berliner, D.C. & , Biddle B. , J. (1995) The . manufactured crisis . Ne w York : Addison-W esley
(Republished by Harper Collins).
Beta Block er Heart Attack T rial Research Group (1982). A randomized trial of propranolol in
patients with acute inf arction. 1. Mortality results. Journal of the American Medical
Association, 247 ,1707–1714.
Biddle B., J. (1964) .Theintegration of teacher effectiveness research .In B. J. Biddle& W . J.
Ellena(Eds.), Contemporary research on teacher effectiveness (pp.1 – 40Ne ).w York : Holt,
Rinehart & Winston .
Biddle B., J. (1979) Role
. theory: Expectations, identities, and behaviors . Ne w York : Academic
Press .
BloomB.,S. (1964)Stability
. and change in human characteristics .Ne w York : W
iley .
BloomB.,S. (1968) Learning
. for mastery Evaluation
. comment, 1 (2) Los
. Angeles : University of
California Center for the Study of Ev aluation.
BloomB.,S. , Engelhart M. , D. , Furst E., J. , Hill W ,. H. &, Krathw ohl , D.R. (1956)Taxonomy
. of
educational objectives. The classification of educational goals. Handbook 1: Cognitive
domain .Ne w York : Longmans,Green .
Blosser, P. et al. (1973). A review of research on teacher. Association for the Education of Teachers
in Science, Columbus, OH: ERIC Information Analysis Center for Science, Mathematics, and
Environmental Education.
Bor
g ,W . R. & , Gall M. , D. (1983) Educational
. research: An introduction (4thed.) . Ne w York :
Longman .
Boring E. , G. (1957) A. history of experimental psychology (2nded.) . Ne w York : Appleton-
Century-Crofts .
Brace
y , G.W. (1987a) .Measurement-dri ven instruction: Catchy phrase, dangerous practice .Phi
Delta Kappan, 68 ,683 – 686 .
Brace
y , G.W. (1987b) .Themuddles of measurement-driven instruction .Phi Delta Kappan, 68,
688 – 689 .
Brophy , J.E. (2001) Subject-specific
. instructional methods and activities . Ne w York : Else vier
Science .
References 153
Brophy , J.E. & , Ev ertson , C.N. (1976) Learning. from teaching: A developmental perspective.
Boston :Allynand Bacon .
Brophy , J.E. & , Good T .,L. (1986) T .eacher behavior and student achievement In . M.
C. W ittrock
(Ed.), Handbook of research on teaching .(3rded ., pp.328 – 375 Ne ).w York : Macmillan .
Broudy , H. (1963) .Historicexemplars of teaching method .In N. L. Gage(Ed.), Handbook of
research on teaching 1 – 43 Chicago :RandMcNally .
Bro
wn , A.L. & , Campione J.,C. (1996) .Psychologicaltheory and the design of innovative learning
environments: On procedures, burns principles, and systems .In L.Schauble& R. Glaser(Eds.),
Innovations in learning: New environments for education (pp.289 – 325)Mahw . ah, NJ : Erlbaum .
Bro
wn , A.L. & , alincsar
P , A.S. (1989) .Guidedcooperative learning and individual knowledge
acquisition .In L. B. Resnick(Ed.), Knowing, learning and instruction: Essays in honor of
Robert Glaser .Hillsdale,NJ : Erlbaum .
Bro
wn , E.Y. , iV scoli , C.M. & , Horwitz R. , I. (1992) .Pre
ventive health strategies and the policy
makers’ paradox .Annals of Internal Medicine, 116 ,593 – 597 .
Bruner , J.S. (1966)Toward. a theory of instruction .Cambridge,MA : Harv ard University Press .
Budin H. , (1999) .Essayreview: The computer enters the classroom .Teachers College Record,
100 ,656 – 669 .
BurnsR.,B. (1984) The . process and context of teaching: A conceptual framework Evaluation . in
Education: An International Review Series, 8 (2) 95 , – 112 .
Butterf
ield , H. (1966)The . Whig interpretation of history .Ne w York : Norton .
Cardinal principles of secondary education (1918). A report of the Commission on the
Reorganization of Secondary Education, appointed by the National Education Association.
Washington, DC: Government Printing Office.
CarrollJ.B. , (1963) .Amodel of school learning .Teachers College Record, 64 ,723 – 733 .
Carroll J.,B. (1985) .Themodel of school learning: Progress of an idea .In C. W. Fisher& D . C.
Berliner(Eds.), Perspectives on instructional time (pp.29 – 58 Ne ).w York and London : Longman .
Carroll J., B. (1989) . The Carroll model: A 25-year retrospective and prospective view .
Educational Researcher, 18 (1),25 – 31 .
CarrollJ.B. , (1993)Human . cognitive abilities .Cambridge,UK : CambridgeUniversity Press .
Case,R. (1985) .Intellectual development: Birth to adulthood.
ChambersJ.H. , (1989) .Unacceptablenotions of science held by process-product researchers .In
R.P
age (Ed.), Proceedings of the forty-fifth annual meeting of the Philosophy of Education
Society (pp.81 – 95)Normal, . IL : Philosophyof Education Society .
Chambers J.H. , (1992) Empiricist
. research on teaching: A philosophical and practical critique
of its scientific pretensions .Boston :Kluwer.
Clandinin D. , J. (1986) Classroom
. practice: Teacher images in action . Philadelphia :F almer
Press .
Clark C. , M. & , Peterson .P, L. (1986) .T eachers’ thought processes .In M. C. W ittrock (Ed.),
Handbook of research on teaching (3rded ., pp.255 – 296)Ne .w York : Macmillan .
CohenB.,P. (1989)Developing
. sociological knowledge: Theory and method (2nded.) . Chicago :
Nelson-Hall .
CohenD.,K. (1988) .T eaching practice: Plus que ça change .In . W. P Jackson(Ed.), Contributing
to educational change: Perspectives on research and practice (pp. 27 – 84 Berk ). eley, CA :
McCutchan .
Cohen S. , A. (1987) . Instructional alignment: Searching for the magic bullet . Educational
Researcher, 16 (8) 16 , – 20 .
CohenS.,A. (1991) Can . fantasies become facts ?Educational Measurement: Issues and Practice,
10 (1) 20 , – 23 .
CohenS.,A. (1995) Instructional
. alignment In . L.Anderson(Ed.), International encyclopedia of
teaching and teacher education ( 2nded ., pp.200 – 204 T a).rrytown, NY : Else vier .
CookT . ,D. , Cooper, H. ,Cordray, D.S. , Hartman H. , ,Hedges L. , V. , Ligh
t , R.J. , Louis T ., A. & ,
Mosteller, .F (1992) Meta-analysis
. for explanation: A casebook . Ne w York : RussellSage
Foundation .
154 References
Ehrenber g , R.G. & , Brewer , D.J. (1995) .Didteachers’ verbal ability and race matter in the
1960s? Coleman revisited. Economics of Education Review, 14 (1) 1, – 21 .
Einstein A. , (1951) .Autobiography.In . P Schilpp (Ed.), Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist,
(pp.683 – 684)Ne .w York : Harper& Row .
Eisner, E. W . (2004). “ Artistry in teaching”, Cultural Commons , http://www.culturalcommons.
org/eisner.htm/2span. Accessed: February 11, 2005.
Emmer, E. T., Sanford, J. P., Clements, B. S., & Martin, J. (1982). Improving classroom management
and organization in junior high schools. (ERIC Document Reproduction Service No. ED261053)
Emmer , E.T. , Ev ertson , C.M. , Sanford J. , P. , Clements B. , S. & , W
orsham , M.E. (1984) .
Classroom management for secondary teachers .Engle wood Cliffs, NJ : Prentice-Hall .
Engelmann S. , (1980) Direct . instruction . Engle wood Cliffs, NJ : Educational Technology
Publication .
English H. , B. & , English A. , C. (1958) A. comprehensive dictionary of psychological and psy-
choanalytical terms: A guide to usage .Ne w York : Da vid McKay .
EnnisR.,H. (1969)Logic . in teaching .Engle wood Cliffs, NJ : Prentice-Hall .
Ev
ers , W . M. (1998) What’s . gone wrong in America’s classrooms . Stanford,CA : Hoo ver
Institution Press .
Ev
ertson , C.M. & , W einstein (2006) Looking . into learning-centered classrooms: Implications
for classroom management .W ashington, DC : NEA .
EysenckH.,J. (1995) .Meta-analysissquared—Does it still make sense ?American Psychologist,
50 ,110 – 111 .
abes
F , R.A. , Martin C. , L. , Harish L. , D. & , Upde graff , K.A. (2000) .Criteriafor evaluating the
significance of de velopmental research in the twenty-f irst century: F orce and counterforce .
Child Development, 71 ,212 – 221 .
aust
F , D.&, Meehl .PE. , (1992) Using . scientific methods to resolve enduring questions within the
history and philosophy of science: Some illustrations . Behavior Therapy, 23 ,195 – 211 .
Festinger , L. (1957)A. theory of cognitive dissonance Stanford, . CA : StanfordUniversity Press .
yerabend
Fe , .P (1963) Ho . w to be a good empiricist—A plea for tolerance in matters epistemologi-
cal In
. . H. P Nidditch(Ed.), Philosophy of science (pp.12 – 39)Oxford, . UK : OxfordUniversity
Press .
yerabend
Fe , .P (1993)Against
. method (3rded.) . Ne w York : V erso .
FinnC.,E. (2000) .Astatement for the B. Fordham Foundation .In Two paths to quality teaching:
Implications for policy makers .Che yenne, WY : EducationCommission of the States .
Fisch S.,M. & , ruglio
T , R.T. (Eds.). (2001) “G” . is for growing: Thirty years of research on
children and Sesame Street .Mahw ah, NJ : Erlbaum .
Fisher, C.W. & , Berliner, D.C. (1985)Perspectives . on instructional time .New York : Longman .
FlandersN., (1970)Analyzing. teacher behavior .Reading,MA : Addison-W esley .
osnot
F , C.T. (Ed.). (1996) Constructivism:
. theory, perspectives, and practice . Ne w York :
Teachers College Press .
Gage, N. L. (1960). Metatechnique in educational research. Proceedings, Research Résumé,
Twelfth Annual Conference on Educational Research. (pp. 1–12). Burlingame, CA: California
Teachers Association.
Gage N. , L. (1963) .P aradigms for research on teaching .In N. L. Gage(Ed.), Handbook of
research on teaching (pp.94 – 141)Chicago . :Rand-McNally.
GageN.,L. (1969) .T eaching methods .In R. L. Ebel(Ed.), Encyclopedia of educational research
4thed. , pp.1446 – 1458London . :Macmillan .
Gage N. , L. (1978) The . scientific basis of the art of teaching . Ne w York : Teachers College
Press .
Gage N. , L. (1979) .Thegenerality of dimensions of teaching .In . L. P Peterson& H.J. W alberg
(Eds.), Research on teaching: Concepts, findings, and implications . (pp.264 – 288) Berk . eley,
CA : McCutchanPublishing Corp .
Gage N. , L. (1994a) .Thescientific status of research on teaching .Educational Theory, 44,
371 – 383 .
156 References
Marx,R.W .,& W inne , . PH. (1987) .Thebest tool teachers have—Their students’ thinking .In
D.
C. Berliner& B.V. Rosenshine(Eds.), T alks to teachers (pp.267 – 304)Ne .w York: Random
House .
MastermanM. , (1970). Thenature of a paradigm. In I.Lakatos& A .Musgra ve (Eds.), Criticism
and the growth of knowledge (pp.59 – 89 Ne ).w York : CambridgeUniversity Press .
McConnell, J. W., & Bo wers, N. D. (1979). A comparison of high-inference and low-inference
measures of teacher behaviors as predictors of pupil attitudes and achievements . (ERIC
Document Reproduction Service No. ED171780).
McLaughlin M. , W. & , albert,
T J.E. (2001) Professional
. communities and the work of high
school teaching . Chicago :Uni versity of Chicago Press .
McLaughlinT . ,F., & W illiams , R.L .(1988) .Thetoken economy .In J.C.W itt , S.N. Elliott&, .F
M. Gresham(Eds.), Handbook of behavior therapy in education (pp.469 – 487) Ne .w York :
PlenumPress .
Medawar , .PB. (1984)The . limits of science .Ne w York : Harperand Row .
Medley , D.M. (1977)Teacher . competence and teacher effectiveness: A review of process-product
research .W ashington, DC : AmericanAssociation of Colleges for Teacher Education.
Medle
y , D.M. & , Mitzel H. , E. (1963) .Measuringclassroom behavior by systematic observation .In
N.
L. Gage(Ed.), Handbook of research on teaching (pp.247 – 328)Chicago . :RandMcNally .
MehanH. , (1979) Learning
. lessons: The social organization of the classroom .Cambridge,MA :
Harvard University Press .
Merrow, J. (2004). Can D. C.’s search make the grade? The Washington Post, August 8, Page B-01.
MertonR.,K. (1955) .Aparadigm for the study of the sociology of knowledge .In Lazarsfeld.P,F .&
Rosenber g , M.(Eds.), The language of social research. (pp.498 – 510)Glencoe, . IL : FreePress.
Mitchell W ., T. (Ed.). (1985) Against. theory: Literary studies and the new paradigm . Chicago :
University of Chicago Press .
MitzelH.,E. (1957)A. behavioral approach to the assessment of teacher effectiveness .Ne w York :
Division of Teacher Education, College of the City of Ne w York, (Mimeographed).
Mitzel H., E .(1960) .T eacher effectiveness .In C. W. Harris(Ed.), Encyclopedia of educational
research ( 3rded., pp. 1481 – 1486)Ne w. York : Macmillan .
MonkD.,H. (1994) .Subjectarea preparation of secondary mathematics and science teachers and
student achievement .Economics of Education Review, 13 (2) 125 , – 145 .
Morsh, J. E., & Wilder, E. W. (1954). Identifying the effective instructor: A review of the quantita-
tive studies: 1900–1953, Research Bulletin AFPATRC-TR-54–44, Lackland Air F orce Base,
TX: Air Force Personnel and Training Research Center.
Nagel E., (1977) .Re view of Against Method by Paul Feyerabend .American Political Science
Review, 71 ,12 – 39 .
Nagel E, (1979)
. . structure of science: Problems in the logic of scientific explanation (2nd
The
ed.) . Indianapolis,IN : Hack ett .
National Center for Education Statistics. (2000). Digest of education statistics. Washington, DC:
Office of Educational Research and Impro vement, U. S. Department of Education.
Needels M. , C .(1984,September) . Therole of logic in the teacher’s facilitation of student
achievement .Dissertation Abstracts International-A 45 03 791 , .
Needels M. , C. (1988) .Anew design for process-product research on the quality of discourse in
teaching .American Educational Research Journal, 25 (4) 503 , – 526 .
Needels M. , C. & , Gage N. , L. (1991) .Essenceand accident in research on teaching .In H. C.
Waxman & H.J. W alberg (Eds.), Effective teaching: Current research 3 – 31Berk . eley, CA :
McCutchan .
Neisser, U. (1998) The . rising curve: Long-term gains in IQ and related measures . W ashington,
DC: AmericanPsychological Association .
Ne
wby , T . J. (1991) . Classroom motivation: Strategies of first-year teachers . Journal of
Educational Psychology, 83 (2) 195 , – 200 .
Ne
wcomb , T . M. (1950)Social . psychology . w NeYork : DrydenPress .
Ne
wcomb , T . M .(1961) .Theacquaintance process . Ne w York: Holt , Rinehartand Winston .
160 References
Nichols S.,L. & , Berliner, D.C .(2007) Collateral. damage: How high-stakes testing corrupts
America’s schools .Cambridge,MA : Harv ard Education Press .
NuthallG., (2005) .Thecultural myths and realities of classroom teaching and learning .Teachers
College Record, 107 (5) 895 , – 934 .
NuthallG., (2007)The . hidden lives of learners .W ellington, New Zealand : Ne w Zealand Council
for Educational Research .
Nuthall, G. A., & Alton-Lee, A. G. (1998).Understanding learning in the classroom: understand-
ing learning and teaching project 3. Report to the Ministry of Education. Wellington: Ministry
of Education.
Nuthall G. , &, Alton-Lee A. , (1993) .Predictinglearning from student experience of teaching: A
theory of student kno wledge construction in classrooms . American Educational Research
Journal, 30 (4) 799 , – 840 .
Nuthall, G., & Snook, I. A. (1973). Models in educational research. In R. M. W. Travers’s Second
handbook of research on teaching; A project of the American Educational Research
Othanel Smith, B., Meux, M., Coombs, J., Nuthall, G.A., & Precians, R. (1967). A study of the
Strategies of teaching. Urbana: Bureau of Educational Research, Uni versity of Illinois.
Patrick, B. C., Hisley, J., & Kempler, T. (2000). ‘What’s everybody so excited about?’: The effects
of teacher enthusiasm on student intrinsic moti vation and vitality . Journal of Experimental
Education.
Pelgrum , W . J. (1989) Educational
. assessment: Monitoring, evaluation and the curriculum.
Unpublisheddoctoral dissertation. Enschede , TheNetherlands : Uni versity of Twente .
Pelgrum W ., J. , Eggen T ., H. J. M. & , Plomp TJ. , (1986) The. implemented and attained mathe-
matics curriculum: A comparison of eighteen countries . Enschede ,TheNetherlands: T.H.
(prepared for the National Council for Educational Statistics, W ashington, DC).
Phillips D., C. (1985) Perspectives
. on learning . Ne w York : T eachers College, Columbia
University .
PhillipsD.,C. & , Burb ules , N.C. (2000)Postpositivism
. and educational research . Lanham, MD :
Rowman & Littlefield Publishers .
PiagetJ.,&, Inhelder, B. (1973)Memory . and intelligence .Ne w York : BasicBooks .
Pitt,
Joseph C.(Ed.). (1988) .Theories of explanation .Oxford,UK : OxfordUniversity Press .
Pond, M. R., & Ne wman, I. (1988). Differential effects of wait-time on textually explicit and
implicit responding: Interactional Explanation. (ERIC 293864.)
PophamW ., (1993) Measurement-dri
. ven instruction as a “quick-fix” reform strategy Measurement
.
and Evaluation in Counseling and Development, 26 (9) 31 , – 34 .
PophamW .,J. , Cruse K. , L. , Rankin S.,C. , Sandifer, .PD. &, W illiams , .PL . (1985) Measurement-
.
driven instruction: It’s on the road . Phi Delta Kappan, 66 ,628 – 634 .
Popk
ewitz (1984) P a.radigm and ideology in educational research: The social functions of the
intellectual . Ne w York : F almer Press .
Popper , K. (1963) Conjectures
. and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge . Routledge,
London .
Popper , K. (1965)Conjectures
. and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge (2nded.) .
Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Porter, A.C. (2002) .Measuringthe content of instruction: Uses in research and practice .
Educational Researcher, 31 (7) 3, – 14 .
Po
wers , W . T. (1973)Behavior:
. The control of perception .Ne w York : Aldine .
RajagopalanK., (1998) .Onthe theoretical trappings of the thesis of anti-theory; or, why the idea
of theory may not, after all, be all that bad: A reply to Gary Thomas . Harvard Educational
Review, 68 ,335 – 352 .
Random House Webster’s College Dictionary. (1991). New York: Random House.
Redf
ield , D.L. & , Rousseau E. , W. (1981) .Ameta-analysis of experimental research on teacher
questioning behavior .Review of Educational Research, 51 ,237 – 245 .
Reigeluth C., M. (1999) Instructional-design
. theories and models: A new paradigm of instruc-
tional theory ,ol.V2 . Mahw ah, NJ : Erlbaum .
References 161
Rice J.,M. (1897) .Thefutility of the spelling grind . Reprintedin J. M. Rice (1913) .Scientific
management in education (pp.65 – 99 Ne ).w York : Hinds,Noble & Eldredge .
RichardsonV . , (1997)Constructivist
. teacher education .W ashington, DC : TheFalmer Press .
Richardson V ., (Ed.). (2001) Handbook . of research on teaching (4thed.) . W ashington, DC :
AmericanEducational Research Association .
Ridenour , L. (1950) Educational
. research and technological change .Paper presented at the
annual meeting of the American Educational Research Association . Washington, DC :
AmericanEducational Research Association .
Rosenshine B. , (1971) Teaching. behaviours and student achievement . Slough,UK : National
Foundation for Educational Research in England and Wales.
RosenshineB.,V. (1987) .Explicitteaching .In D. C. Berliner& B.V. Rosenshine(Eds.), Talks to
teachers 75 – 92Ne w. York : RandomHouse .
Rosenshine B. , &, Meister, C. (1995) .Directinstruction .In L.Anderson(Ed.), International
encyclopedia of teaching and teacher education (. 2nded. ,pp. 143 – 149T arrytown,
). NY :
Else
vier Science .
RosenthalR., (1994) .P arametric measures of effective size .In H.Cooper& L.V. Hedges(Eds.),
Handbook of research synthesis (pp. 231 – 244 Ne ).w York : RussellSage Foundation .
Rothenber g , J. (1989) . The open classroom reconsidered . Elementary School Journal, 90,
69 – 86 .
Ro
we , M.B. (1974) W . ait-time and rewards as instructional variables: Their influence on language,
logic, and fate-control, Part 1. Wait-time. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 11 ,81 – 94 .
Ro
we, M.B. (1978) .W ait, wait, wait .School Science and Mathematics, 28 (3) 207 , – 216 .
Runk
el , .PJ. (2003)People . as living things: The psychology of perceptual control .Hayw ard, CA :
Li
ving Control Systems Publishing .
Ryan D. , W. , Hildyard A. , &, Bourk e , S. (1989) .Descriptionof classroom teaching and school
learning .In L. W. Anderson ,D.W. Ryan&, B.J. Shapiro(Eds.), The IEA classroom environ-
ment study (pp.71 – 126)Ne w. York : Per gamon Press .
RyansD. , G. (1960)Characteristics
. of teachers .W ashington, DC : AmericanCouncil on Education .
Samson, G. E., Stryk owski, B., W einstein, T., & W alberg, H. J. (1987) .The ef fects of teacher
questioning levels on student achievement: A quantitative synthesis. The Journal of Educational
Research, 80, 290–295.
Schmidt W ,. H. (1978) Measuring . the content of instruction . ResearchSeries No. 35. East
Lansing, MI: Institute of Research on Teaching, Michigan State University.
Schmidt.F,L. (1992) .Whatdo data really mean? Research findings, meta-analysis, and cumula-
tive knowledge in psychology. American Psychologist, 47 ,1173 – 1181 .
Schmidt H. , G. , Lo yens , S.M. M. , an V Gog , T . &, aasP , .F (2007) .Problem-basedlearning is
compatible with human cogniti ve architecture: Commentary on Kirschner , Sweller, & Clark
(2006) .Educational Psychologist, 42 (2) 91 , – 97 .
SchoenfeldA.,H. (1998) .T oward a theory of teaching-in-context .Issues in Education, 4 ,1 – 94 .
SchönD.,A. (1983)The . reflective practitioner .SanFrancisco : Josse y-Bass .
SchönD.,A. (1987)Educating . the reflective practitioner .SanFrancisco : Josse y-Bass .
Scri
ven , M. (1968) .Thephilosophy of science .In D. L. Sills(Ed.), International encyclopedia of
the social sciences ( V ol. 14 ,p. 84 ).Ne w York : Macmillanand Free Press .
ShulmanL.,S. (1986a) .P aradigms and research programs in the study of teaching: A contempo-
rary perspective In . M.C. W ittrock (Ed.), Handbook of research on teaching ( 3rded. pp. , 3 – 36) .
New York : Macmillan .
Shulman L.,S. (1986b) .Thosewho understand: A conception of teacher knowledge .American
Educator, 10 (1) 9, – 15, 43–44 .
Shulman L. , S. (1987) .Knowledge and teaching: Foundations of the new reform .Harvard
Educational Review, 57 (1) 1, – 22 .
Shulman L. , S. et, al (Chair). .(1975) Teaching
. as clinical information processing (Report of
Panel 6, National Conference on Studies in Teaching, National Institute of Education).
Washington, DC : U.S.Department of Health, Education and Welfare .
162 References
Sirotnik K. , A. (1983) .Whatyou see is what you get—Consistency, persistency, and mediocrity
in classrooms .Harvard Educational Review, 53 ,16 – 31 .
Skinner , B.F. (1938) The . behavior of organisms (7thprinting) . Ne w York : Appleton-Century-
Crofts .
Skinner, B. F. (1950). Are theories of learning necessary? Psychological Re view, 57, 193-216
Skinner , B.F. (1953)Science . and human behavior .Ne w York : MacMillan .
Skinner, B. F. (1957). Schedules of reinforcement, with C.B. Ferster , 1957. ISBN 0-13-792309-0.
Skinner , B.F. (1964) .Skinneron theory .Science, 145 ,1385,1387 .
Skinner , B.F. (1968)The . technology of teaching New . York : Appleton-Century-Crofts .
Skinner , B.F. (1974)About . behaviorism .Ne w York : V intage Books .
Sla
vin , R. (1990) Cooperative
. learning: Theory, research, and practice Englewood
. Cliffs, NJ :
Prentice-Hall .
Smith B. , O. (1961) .Aconcept of teaching. In B. O. Smith& R. Ennis(Eds.) , Language and
concepts in education (pp. 86 – 101Chicago . :RandMcNally .
SmithB.,O. (1963) T .oward a theory of teaching. In A. A. Bellack (Ed.),
Theory and research in teach-
ing (pp.1 – 10 Ne ).w York : Bureauof Publications, Teachers College, Columbia University .
SmithB.,O. (1983) Some . comments on educational research in the twentieth century Elementary
.
School Journal, 83 (4) 488 , – 492 .
Smith B.,O. , Meux M. , O. , Coombs, J. ,Eierdam D. , &, Szoke , R (1962)Astudy
. of the logic of
teaching. Unpublished study a vailable from the Bureau of Educational Research, Colle ge of
Education, University of Illinois : Urbana,IL .
Smith, B. O., Meux, M., Coombs, J., Nuthall, G. A., & Precians, R. (1967). A study of the strate-
gies of teaching. Urbana: Bureau of Educational Research, Uni versity of Illinois, 1967.
Smith, B. O., Meux, M. O., et al. (1967).
Smith R., B. (1987) The . teacher’s book of affective instruction : A competency based approach.
Lanham,MD : Uni versity Press of America .
Sno
w , R.E. (1973) .Theoryconstruction for research on teaching In R. M. W. T ravers (Ed.),
Second handbook of research on teaching ( 2nded. , pp.77 – 112 Chicago ). :RandMcNally .
SohnD., (1995) .Meta-analysisas a means of discovery .American Psychologist, 47 ,108 – 110 .
Spearman C. , (1904) .“Generalintelligence” objectively determined and measured .American
Journal of Psychology, 15 ,201 – 293 .
Spranger , E. (1928) Types. of men: The psychology and ethics of personality . Halle,Germany :
M.Niemeyer .
StallingsJ.A., (1975) .Implementationand child effects of teaching practices in Follow Through
classrooms .Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, 40 (7 – 8 ).
Stallings J., A. & , Kaskowitz , D. (1974) F ollow-Through classroom observation evaluation ,
1972–1973 (SRIProject NRU–7370) Stanford,CA : StanfordResearch Institute .
Stigler
, J.W. & , Hiebert J., (1999) The . teaching gap: Best ideas from the world’s teachers for
improving education in the classroom New . York : TheFree Press .
Stipek D. , (2002) Motivation
. to learn: Integrating theory and practice (4thed.) .Boston : Allyn
and Bacon .
Strauss R. , P. &, Sawyer , E.A. (1986,February) .Some new evidence on teacher and student
competencies .Economics of Education Review Elsevier, 5 (1) 41 , – 48 .
Suppes.P, (1966) .Theuses of computers in education .Scientific American, 215 (3) 206 , – 216 .
Suppes .P, (1974) .Theplace of theory in educational research. Educational Researcher, 3 (6) ,
3 – 10 .
Sweller, J. (1999) Instructional
. design in technical areas : Australian Education Review No. 3.
Camberwell,Victoria, Australia : AustralianCouncil for Educational Research Press .
Sweller, J. ,Kirschner, .PA. & , Clark R. , E. (2007) .Whyminimally guided teaching techniques
do not work: A reply to commentaries . Educational Psychologist, 42 (2)115 , – 121 .
Thayer ,V. T. (1928)The . passing of the recitation .Boston :Heath .
ThomasG., (1997) .What’ s the use of theory? Harvard Educational Review, 67 (1)75, – 104 .
Thomas G. , (1999) .Hollo w theory: A reply to Rajogopalan .Harvard Educational Review, 69,
51 – 66 .
References 163
165
166 Author Index
P
M P
aas, F., 65
MacIntyre,A., 12 P
atrick, 147
Macmillan, C. J. B., 24, 86 Pedersen, E., 14, 15
Mandeville, G. K., 76, 77 Pelgrum, W. J., 92, 93
Marland, P. W., 25, 26 Perlber g, A., 90
Marrow, A. J., 18 Peterson, P. L., 45, 49
Martin, C. L., 118 Phillips, D. C., 26, 39, 41, 63
Martin,J., 24 Piaget, J., 39, 104
Marx, R. W., 46, 47, 53, 120, 121 Pintrich, P. R., 46, 50, 98, 99, 131
Masterman,M., 41 Pitt, J. C., 18, 23
Mayer, R. E., 46, 50, 96, 98, 99, 131 Plomp, T. J., 92, 93
168 Author Index
U
S Unruh,W., 21
Sanford, J. P., 122 Upde
graff, K. A., 118
Sawyer, E. A., 6
Schmidt, F. L., 17
Schmidt, H. G., 65 V
Schmidt, W. H., 93 Van Gog, T., 65
Schoenfeld, A. H., 57 VandenBos, G. R., 26, 89, 101, 112,
Schon, D. A., 152 136, 140
Scohn,152 Vernon, P. E., 146
Scri
ven, M., 19 Viscoli, C. M., 16
Shapiro, B. J., 75 Vygotsk y, L. S., 103
Shiffrin, R. M., 36, 129
Shulman, L. S., 34, 45, 48, 53, 54, 58, 60,
87, 146 W
Sirotnik, K. A., 5, 7, 73–75, 80, 110, 137, W
alberg, H., 13
143, 144 Walberg, H. J., 141
Skinner, B. F., 6, 20, 35, 36, 41, 61, 125 W
aldron, M., 116
Sla
vin, R., 6 Wallen, N. E., 61, 80, 83
Smith, B. O., 4, 61, 70, 74, 75, 87, 127 Weil, M., 2, 62, 63, 67,
Smith, E. E., 104 79, 149
Smith, F. L., 7, 49, 69–77, 79, 121, 127 W
einstein, 115, 141
Smith, R. B., 4 Weissler, A. M., 16
Snook, I. A., 71 Wennberg, J. E., 59
Snow, R. E., 25, 94 Wiersma, W., 63, 64
Sohn,D., 13 Wilder, E. W., 29
Spearman,C., 102 W
iller, D., 22
Author Index 169
W
iller, J., 22 Y
Williams, R. L., 112 Yekovich, C. W., 120
Wilson, D. B., 12, 13, 16 Y
ekovich, F. R., 120
Winne, P. H., 34, 46, 47, 53, 120, 121,
140, 141
Wittrock, M. C., 50, 86, 120, 121 Z
Wittrock, M. W., 46, 50, 98, 99, 131 Zelditch,M., 18
W
orsham, M. E., 122 Zuck
erman, M., 82
Subject Index
A Conventional-direct-recitation (CDR)
Anderson–Krathwohl taxonomy for learning, teaching, 108
teaching, and assessment, 98 across nations, 75–76
Aphorism, 18. See also Teaching theory apparent adequacy of, 80–81
Aptitude-treatment-interactions(ATIs) Bellack model for computer-assisted
approach, 105 instruction frames similarity, 74–75
components of, 66, 125, 127–128
computers in classrooms, effects, 81–83
B as conjecture, 79
Bloom’
s taxonomy, 97–98 demands of alternatives, 81
generalizability of, 75–77
inheritance of, 80
C reader’s memory and, 77
The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, 86 and subject matters, 76–77
Carroll’s model of school learning, 34–35 variations of direct teaching, 67
Classroom management, 125, 126, 152 Criterion-of-teacher-effectiveness paradigm,
avoiding biases toward students, 123–124 42–43
in elementary schools, 122 Cronbach clinical processes, 107
instructional time, 119 Curricularknowledge, 45
categories of, 121–122
empty quantitative concept, 120
in secondary schools, 122 D
recommendations for inappropriate Descripti
ve theory, 3–4
behavior, 123 Direct instructional systems in arithmetic
students and reading (DISTAR), 67
poverty, 115–118 Disco
very learning statements, 65
thought processes, 120–121
sub-theory of, 148–149
Classroom teaching analysis, 145 E
Cognitive-ability factors, Carroll and Gardner Education
comparisons, 102 educational adaptation patterns, 149
Cognitive dissonance and learning theory, 125 generalizations and, 12
Community characteristics and context objectives, 139
category, 48 psychology, 103
Conjectures and Refutations, 30
Constructivist teaching inventory, 64
Context variables category, 43. See also G
Teaching study, paradigm Garrison-Macmillancritiques, 86–88
and characteristics, 44, 48 Gricecooperative principles, 133–134
171
172 Subject Index
H S
Handbook of Classroom Management, 115 School characteristics and context category, 48
Handbook of Research on Teaching, Serendipity in history of science,
86, 120 27bibliography on, 28
Ho
w Teachers Taught, 67–68 Studentperseverance, 128
Students. See also Teaching
processesachievement category
I cognitive objectives, achievement,
The IEA Classroom Environment Study, 75 50dimensions for, 51
Implicit theory and classroom-interaction- attention-focusing process, 129
analysis, 26 big five dimensions of personality, 48
Intelligence quotient (IQ), 101–102 cognitive capabilities, 101
Interactive thought processes, 49 adjusting teaching in, 103–104
International Association for Evaluation intelligence,101–102
of Educational Achievement and prior knowledge, 103
(IEA), 53 teaching processes and, 104–105
cognitive capabilities and motivation,
150–151sub-theories of, 147–148
K cognitive process dimension and
Kno
wledge achievement category, 51
dimension and student achievement intellectual processes, 130
category, 51 motivation approaches
factual and conceptual, 99 behaviorism, 111–112
procedural and metacognitive, 99–100 cognitive aspects of, 112–113
learning tasks, 113
poverty of, 115
N literacy scores, 117
Naturalsciences mathematics scores, 116
anti-theory arguments in, 37–38 and superintendency, 118
and desirability of theory, 18 sub-theories of cognitive capabilities
practicalvalue, 19 and motivation, 147–148
achievement and attitudes measures,
136–137
P personalities and rationality, 129
P
article-physics consistencies, 14 socioeconomic status and academic
Pedagogical content knowledge content side achievement, 127
of teaching, 53–54 thought processes category
Pedagogicalknowledge, 45 and achievement, 50
A Place Called School, 67–68 categories, 47
Post-interactive thought processes, 49 paradigm,46
Presage variables concept, 43. See also Subject matter knowledge, 45. See also
Teaching study, paradigm Teaching contents
stable characteristics in, 47–48 Suspendingjudgment reasons
Prescripti
ve theory, 3–4 inadequacy of evidence, 78
Problem-basedlearning, 66 inductive logic’s inadequacy, 78
Process-achie vement paradigm, 42
Process-productparadigm. See
Process-achievement paradigm T
Progressive–discovery–constructivist (PDC) Taxonomy for Learning, Teaching,
teaching, 63–66 and Assessing, 139
The Taxonomy for Learning, Teaching,
and Assessing, 50
R A Taxonomy for Teaching, Learning,
Researchprocess, 1 and Assessing, 103
Subject Index 173
T
eachers teachers’ ratings of opportunity-to-learn,
agenda setting, 130 92–93
behavioral variables, 135 knowledge types of, 99–100
characteristics and student process–productresearch
achievement, 6 Garrison-Macmillan critiques, 86–88
communicability and comprehensibility- omissions and mistreatments, 85
affecting actions teacher’s intentionality, 86
high and low inference variables, 136 sub-theoriesof
inference level and outcome prediction, choice of content, 145–147
136–137 cognitive capabilities and motivation,
comprehensibility-affecting actions 147–148
high-inference variables, 136 instructional alignment, 145
inference level and outcome prediction, variation in, 88
136–137 T
eaching processes, 61
low-inference variables, 136 and cognitive capabilities, 104–105
education,135 conditions of, 82
illogicality measures, 134 culmination theory, 151–152
instructional alignment, 146 cycle of, 131, 132, 151
pedagogical content knowledge, 146 historical study, 69
performed segments, 150 models
personal values, 46–147 categories for, 62–68
presage variables, personality and modelsfor
characteristics, 29 conventional–direct–recitation (CDR)
problem handling approaches, 149 teaching, 66–68
questions during discussions, 137–139 families of, 63
soliciting progressive–discovery–constructivist
type of question asked and learning (PDC) teaching, 63–66
affected, 138–139 with multiple intelligences, 108
T
eacher’s-thought-processes category, 44 awakening and amplifying, 108–109
cognitive process categories, 46 musical,109–110
knowledge types, 46 responding and reacting for, 109
momentary thought processes, 48 soliciting for, 110
paradigm,45 teaching and transferring, 109
stable and transitory thought processes, 49 objectives of, 103
Teaching contents, 111, 145 observational studies
Anderson–Krathwohl taxonomy, 98 Bellack study, 69–71
Bloom’s taxonomy, 97–98 Goodlad’s study, 73–74
categorizations of, 97 Hoetker and Ahlbrand, 71–72
cognitive load content side of, 53 Mehan study, 72
content side of, 52–54 practicefor
and curricular validity, 89 factual correctness versus incorrectness,
instructional alignment for, 88 144–145
approaches to, 89–91 A Place Called School, 144
content analysis, 93 responding and reacting, 143–144, 150
content and curricular validity, 89 progressive education, 83–84
experimental manipulation, 93–94 simplification levels, 105
facet similarity and instructional mnemonic devices, algorithms, 106
alignment, 90 reduce number and length, 106
high-stakes assessment for, 94–97 reducing cognitive load, 106–107
instruction measurement, 91 simpler and familiar word, usage of, 106
measurement-driven instruction (MDI), sub-theories of, 125–126
90, 94 classroom management and, 148–149
opportunity-to-learn,89–90 content of teaching, 145–147
studying methods of, 91 culmination and, 151–152
174 Subject Index