Eclipse of Darwinism
Eclipse of Darwinism
Eclipse of Darwinism
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Philosophical Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to Transactions of the American Philosophical Society
Mark A. Largent
Introduction
In discussing the emergence and development of evolutionary biology, historians
biology typically divide the nineteenth and twentieth centuries into four eras. T
first, the pre-Darwinian period, came prior to publication of the Origin of Speci
1859, and it includes evolutionary theorizing by figures like Lamarck and Chamb
The second period focused on the reception and reaction to Darwin's work by
public, religious authorities, and natural scientists. This period lasted from 18
about 1880 and is best characterized by works that systematically examine the re
tion of Darwin's ideas across different countries (Glick, 1974). Beginning about 1
and lasting through most of the 1930s is a period widely described as the "eclipse
Darwinism" or the "eclipse of Darwin."1 Biologists and historians of biology
have described this period as one during which many theories competed for statu
During these years, Darwinian evolutionary theory was supposedly obscured,
ultimately discarded, as speculative and old-fashioned natural history. Finally, be
ning about 1940, a collection of geneticists, organismal biologists, and statisti
produced what Julian Huxley termed the modern "evolutionary synthesis," w
brought together Darwinism and Mendelism, mutationism and modern genetics.
This paper focuses on the period of so-called eclipse. Unfortunately, much of o
understanding of this eclipse comes from scientists of the synthesis era and histor
who have been unduly influenced by them. For example, in Evolution: The M
Synthesis, Huxley (1942) explained that during the 1910s evolutionary scientists w
scattered, confused, and contradictory. Huxley explained how Mendelians co
dicted the neo-Lamarckians, mutationists fought with Weismannians who were a
fighting with the neo-Lamarckians, experimental embryologists opposed the
cal recapitulatory theories of development, and the followers of newer discipline
There is a recent tendency with some biologists to depreciate Darwin and his method
of approach in favor of more metaphysical conceptions of Evolution unconditioned by
environment. The process of induction is slow and laborious, it has even been con
demned as "Mid-Victorian," while that of deduction may be speeded up on demand.
Discoveries connected with the physical basis of Heredity, and (subsequently) of Men
delian processes in variation and crossing have given an immense impetus to the study of
Genetics. From these came the conception of "genes" or "unit characters" as transmit
ted through heredity, each one unchanged, but the mass forming with each generation
new combinations and evoking new possibilities. Moreover, as no one man can compass
and weigh all kinds of evidence that derived from field study, from species study and
from classification has been overlooked and undervalued by many investigators working
along other lines. But however much evolutionists have at times seemed to drift away
from Darwin's conclusions, it seems to me that the broadest research, the most accurate
observation and the sanest thought come nearest to the conclusions in [ On] the Origin
of Species. The body of fact has grown enormously year by year, but the conclusions we
must accept are substantially those laid down by Darwin himself. The chief modification
which appears necessary is the recognition of isolation with segregation as a separate fac
tor in Evolution co-existent with Natural Selection itself.b
Jordan's use of the phrase "eclipse of Darwin" clearly emphasized a drift by some
biologists away from Darwin's "method of approach" and toward an explanation of
evolution that resulted from forces internal to the organisms instead of being caused
by the environment. Jordan, who had long been active in defending what he called
"old-fashioned natural history" against claims by the increasing number of exper
imental biologists, was clearly interested in preserving the reputation of inductive
methods in the biological sciences against what he believed were the deductive meth
ods of experimentalism (see Jordan, 1916). For Jordan, the metaphor of the eclipse
was not that of the astronomical variety, but the second meaning of the term: to fall
into disuse.6 Nonetheless, Jordan's employment of the term demonstrates that scien
tists used it prior to Huxley (1942).
While Huxley did not create the phrase, his use in 1942 is the first in print, and
his particular use set the tone for all later scientists and historians of science. The first
chapter of Evolvition concluded with a section titled "The eclipse of Darwinism,"
which traced the rise of Mendelian mutationism as a challenge to Darwinian natural
selection during the early twentieth century. Throughout the 1920s and 1930s, Hux
ley explained, a number of new disciplines that had previously worked in comparative
isolation had "become a more unified science," and with their synthesis "there has
been a rebirth of Darwinism." However, the Darwinism of Julian Huxley's day was
not that of his grandfather's: "The Darwinism thus reborn is a modified Darwin
ism, since it must operate with facts unknown to Darwin; but it is still Darwinism in
the sense that it aims at giving a naturalistic interpretation of evolution, and that its
upholders, while constantly striving for more facts and more experimental results, do
not, like some cautious spirits, reject the method of deduction." Finally, the section,
which began with the metaphor of the eclipse, ended with a similarly deterministic
metaphor: "It is with this reborn Darwinism, this mutated phoenix risen from the
ashes of the pyre kindled by men so unlike as Bateson and Bergson, that I propose
to deal in succeeding chapters of this book" (Huxley, 1942, pp. 22-28). Like the
moon's shadow passing over the earth or the phoenix rising from the ashes, Huxley's
metaphor suggested the inevitability of the return to prominence of Darwin's theory
of evolution by natural selection, as well as his inductive methodology.
Much more recently, the phrase "eclipse of Darwinism" was employed as the title of
Peter Bowler's (1983) book on anti-Darwinian theories in circulation around 1900.
Bowler accepted Huxley's notion of the astronomical metaphor of an eclipse by dem
onstrating how Darwin's work, once widely accepted by biological scientists, came
under increasing attack beginning in the 1890s. From T. H. Huxley's defense of the
Darwinian theory of evolution against claims made by the Marquis of Salisbury at the
1894 meeting of the British Association for the Advancement of Science to doubts
raised by self-described Darwinists, including Alfred Russel Wallace and E. Ray Lank
ester, Bowler asserted that Darwinian natural selection appeared on the decline at
the turn of the century. Orthogenesis, mutationism, and especially Lamarckianism
directly attacked the primacy of the selection mechanism in evolutionary theory. With
the coming of the synthesis, Bowler explained, Darwin emerged victorious. While
Bowler's use of the term "eclipse" mirrored Huxley's, Bowler's goals in applying it
were quite different. His exploration of evolutionary theories that challenged Darwin
ian natural selection was motivated by claims from late twentieth-century opponents
of Darwinism, including Arthur Koestler and the Creation Research Society?both
portrayed "themselves as fighting against a theory that the scientific community has
never allowed to be challenged." Bowler hoped a better understanding of evolution
ary biology during the early twentieth century, in particular a better understanding of
the theories of evolutionary change competing with Darwinism, would "alter the way
in which some people perceive modern Darwinism by showing that the theory has
indeed faced and survived major scientific opposition within this century." (Bowler,
1983, p. 5) In contrast to the claim of creation scientists that evolutionary biologists
religiously adhered to Darwinism and refused to challenge it openly, Bowler's explo
ration of the variety of evolutionary theories at the beginning of the twentieth century
was a demonstration of how Darwinists successfully defended natural selection against
competing theories of evolutionary change.
Employment of the phrase "eclipse of Darwinism" has served particular purposes
in the hands of various scientists and historians of science. For D. S. Jordan, it was a
rallying cry to preserve Darwin's inductive methodology against challenges by experi
mental biologists. For J. Huxley, it allowed for a sharp differentiation between his
work and that of the previous generations' research and writings, as well as a return
to what he believed was the true essence of Darwinism, albeit mutated to include
Mendelism. For Bowler, the term was a recognition of the vigorous debates in the
early twentieth century that challenged Darwinian natural selection and from w
Darwinism emerged generally victorious. The term has served their needs quite w
but it did so at the expense of our understanding of the research, conclusions
worldviews of early twentieth-century American evolutionists. What was the stat
Darwin's theory of evolution by natural selection among American biologists duri
the era of the so-called eclipse of Darwinism?
formed Stanford University in California, where he came to know and work close
with David Starr Jordan.
It was at Stanford that Kellogg did the bulk of his scientific research, continuing
morphological and taxonomic work that he had done while at Kansas, Cornell,
Leipzig. After the turn of the century, Kellogg was the first American biologist to
duct long-term breeding experiments to investigate Mendelian inheritance throug
detailed breeding experiments with silkworms to test for the inheritance of anato
cal structures, life span, and susceptibility to starvation. He also studied heliotrop
in honeybees and inchworms, helped area farmers and breeders in pest-eradicatio
efforts, and taught entomology and evolution courses. Among the most popular o
his courses was his course titled "Bionomics," which included sections on evolution
eugenics, and nature study and seems to have been taken by nearly every student
Stanford from 1895 until about 1912.
At the start of World War I, Kellogg left Stanford to join his former student,
bert Hoover, in the humanitarian effort to feed the civilians trapped in Germ
occupied Belgium and northern France. When he returned to the United State
1917, Kellogg took the job as the first permanent secretary of the National Resea
Council, a position he held until the end of his life.9
Kellogg's Darwinism To-Day was written at the height of his career as a scientif
researcher. After having studied in Germany under Leuckart in 1892, Kellogg cam
believe that his German colleagues were at the cutting edge of evolutionary resear
and he returned once in 1898 and again from 1904 to 1906 to study with them. K
logg later wrote, "As a teacher Leuckart has been for years the best known and m
besought zoologist of the world," and his students included many notable America
and European scientists, including Carl Friedrich Wilhelm Claus, Otto B?tschli, Ka
Chun, Charles Whitman, Erwin Baur, William Patten, Henry Sherring Pratt,
George Howard Parker.10 During his third trip to Leipzig, Kellogg wrote Darwinis
To-Day. He had traveled to Europe in preparation for writing his portion of Evolu
and Animal Life, 2l book he and Jordan were preparing. Kellogg spent a year and
half, from 1904 to 1906, in and around Leipzig. Originally he hoped to includ
the textbook a comprehensive analysis of the status of Darwinism, but under press
from the book's publisher he decided to simplify his analysis in Evolution and An
Life and write an entirely different book that would survey the status of various
lutionary theories. In a letter to Jordan, Kellogg explained that his other book w
be an amplified discussion of "certain parts or phases" of evolution. He eventu
titled it Darwinism To-Day and considered it "a second step in the 'Stanford Ev
tion Series.'"11
In Darwinism To-Day Kellogg concluded that Darwinian natural selection was the f
arbiter in evolutionary change, and the book demonstrated the shortcomings of cla
made by Darwinists, neo-Darwinists, and anti-Darwinists, as well as the role of natural sele
tion in evolutionary change. Understanding the state of Darwinian evolutionary thou
in the early twentieth century requires an awareness of precisely what these terms mean
Kellogg and his colleagues. Broadly speaking, biologists who studied evolution accep
the theory of descent, the belief that "the various living as well as the now extinct speci
organisms are descended from one another and from common ancestors." Acceptanc
evolution as a natural phenomenon summarily dismisses the theories of spontaneous
eration of species and divine creation, replacing them with a mechanism for evolutio
change, but not with an explanation for the ultimate origin of life. The theory of descent,
Kellogg explained, existed long before Darwin in the work of Goethe, Erasmus Darwin
(Charles Darwin's grandfather), Lamarck, and Chambers. Darwin's work gave the theory
of descent widespread acceptance among biologists as it offered a "certain rational, causo
mechanical (hence, non-teleologic) explanation of the origin of new species." It rested,
Kellogg explained, on the observed facts of the geometrical increase in the number of
individuals, the apparent variation that existed among all individuals, and the transmission
of these variations from parents to offspring.
Central to Darwinism was the theory of natural selection, which predicted that
slight variations would allow for a greater chance of survival and reproduction and
therefore be passed to successive offspring. In his writings, Kellogg used the terms and
phrases Darwinism, the theory of natural selection, and the selection theory some
what interchangeably. By the end of Darwinism To-Day it became clear that Kellogg
believed that the mechanisms of selection were undoubtedly involved in evolutionary
change, while recognizing several shortcomings in Darwin's work. These shortcom
ings centered on Darwin's inability to explain the origin of new variations or the pre
cise mechanisms involved in the inheritance of selected traits (Kellogg, 1907, p. 11).
Kellogg's goal in writing the book was to identify these shortcomings and to offer a
research plan that would address them.
Throughout Darwinism To-Day Kellogg described a spectrum of beliefs about
the engine of evolutionary change, with Darwinians standing in the middle of the
spectrum, flanked on either side by neo-Darwinians and anti-Darwinians. Kellogg
described how European debates over evolution were dominated by the polemics of
neo-Darwinians, who believed that selection alone accounted for evolutionary change
and attacked those who claimed that acquired characteristics could in any way affect
successive generations of offspring. He also described the response by anti-Darwin
ists, who attacked selection theories of all stripes and generally emphasized the role
of the environment in evolutionary change. Kellogg posited a moderate position for
Darwinists interested in defending themselves against both extreme selectionists and
aggressive anti-Darwinians, asserting that Weismann's followers took Darwin's work
too far by claiming that selection alone accounted for all aspects of evolution. This
was, Kellogg was quick to point out, a position that even Darwin did not hold. Spe
cifically, Kellogg attacked Weismann and his followers, who "proposed the doctrine
of the Allmacht [omnipotence] of natural selection; that is, that natural selection
alone is capable of explaining all the phenomena and facts of species-forming and
descent." In another passage, Kellogg wrote, "It is strange, but wholly true, that the
modern reaction and revolt against Darwinism is chiefly due to the activity and atti
tude taken by certain of its over-ardent friends." He referred to Weismann and his fol
lowers as "neo-Darwinians" or "ultra-Darwinians" and concluded, "Darwin himself
claimed no Allmacht for selection. Darwin may well cry to be saved from his friends."
In letters to Jordan, Kellogg made it clear that, while he believed neo-Darwinians
pushed natural selection too far, he still accepted the validity of Darwin's work, and
he explained, "I believe N[atural] Selection] to be the controlling factor influence in
determining descent."12 Clearly, Kellogg was a Darwinian, but in no way an advocate
of Weismann's claims about the potency of selection alone.
In addition to demonstrating Kellogg's loyalty to Darwinism, Darwinism To-Day
illustrated national differences among evolutionary theorists. Kellogg claimed that
Europeans, especially the Germans and the French, were responsible for both the
irrational transformation of Darwinism into neo-Darwinism and the correspond
ing rash of anti-Darwinian claims. Luckily, the neo-Darwinian and anti-Darwinian
"philosophic turmoil and wordy strife" had not yet found its way across the Atlantic
and into American bookstores. However, he warned, "just as certainly as the many
material things cmade in Germany' have found their way to us so will come soon the
echoes and phrases of the present intellectual activity in evolutionary affairs." The
real danger, Kellogg explained, would be realized if "the first of these echoes to come
across the water to us prove to be, as wholly likely, those from the more violent and
louder debaters, they may lead to undue dismay and panic on our part. Things are
really in no such desperate way with Darwinism as the polemic vigour [sic] of the
German and French anti-Darwinians leads them to suggest." Chief among Darwin's
detractors was the Russian botanist Korschinsky and the Germans Hans Driesch and
Gustov Wolff, who asserted that natural selection was nonexistent, was a vagary, a
form of speech, or a negligible influence in descent. In his correspondence to Jordan,
Kellogg bluntly expressed his view on the French and German anti-Darwinists and
his frustration over their attacks on natural selection, calling them "pesky flies that are
sucking the blood of natural selection theory."13
In the book's introduction, Kellogg presented several examples of "absurdity of
expression" regarding the status of Darwinism. The book began with the title of a
recent German pamphlet "Vom Sterhelager Des Darwinismuf [The Deathbed of Dar
winism], which he dismissed with the explanation that "ever since there has been
Darwinism there have been occasional death beds of Darwinism on title pages of pam
phlets, addresses and sermons."14 He quoted Driesch's statement, "Darwinism now
belongs to history, like that other curiosity of our century, the Hegelian philosophy;
both are variations on the theme: how one manages to lead a whole generation by the
nose" along with his comments about "the softening of the brain of Darwinians." He
translated another anti-Darwinian, Eberhard Dennert, as, "We [anti-Darwinians] are
now standing by the death-bed of Darwinism, and making ready to send the friends
of the patient a little money to insure a decent burial of the remains." Kellogg claimed
that Wolff was "no less intemperate and indecent" when he referred to the "epi
sode of Darwinism" and suggested that biologists should remember Darwin "as if he
had never existed." These quotations have served as the basis for some historians to
assert mistakenly that Kellogg himself was an anti-Darwinian, when in reality Kellogg
believed these statements were absurd, and one of his primary motivations in writing
Darwinism To-Day was to dispute them.15
One might counter that the mere fact that these claims existed and that Kellogg
defended against them is evidence enough that Darwinism was on the ropes in the early
twentieth century; but these claims were rare and Kellogg repeated them only to sup
port his ultimate claim that any panic about the status of Darwinism was unwarranted,
because the critiques were "injudicious and intemperate" and "the whole anti-Darwin
ian movement will be discredited and given no attention" (Kellogg, 1907, p. 6).
It is in misunderstanding or misrepresenting Kellogg's position relative to the occa
sional European anti-Darwinians that historians have erroneously concluded that Dar
winism To-Day represented the "sad state of Darwinism at the turn of the century"
(Smocovitis, 1996, p. 117). Take for example, Degler's selective quotation that made
Kellogg appear to have claimed that Darwinian selection theories had lost all standing
among biologists. In full, Kellogg wrote, "The fair truth is that the Darwinian selec
tion theories, considered with regard to their claimed capacity to be an independently
sufficient mechanical explanation of descent, stand to-day seriously discredited in the
biological world" (Degler, 1991, p. 23; Kellogg, 1907, p. 5). Throughout the book,
Kellogg argued that Darwinian natural selection alone could not account for evolution
ary change as Weismann and his followers argued; but he also insisted that "Darwin
himself claimed no Allmacht for selection," so Kellogg's explanation that selection was
not "an independently sufficient mechanical explanation of descent" is hardly tanta
mount to claiming the demise of Darwinism.
Likewise, Smocovitis's assertion that Kellogg's book demonstrated the corrosive
effects of experimental biologists' methodological scrutiny of the work done by natu
ral historians proves problematic. The growing doubts about Darwinism that she saw
in the claims found in the introduction of Darwinism To-Day were merely Kellogg's
mocking of zealous anti-Darwinists, and they must be considered alongside his claim
that "ever since there has been Darwinism there have been occasional deathbeds of
Darwinism" (Kellogg, 1907, p. 1). A glance at the book's final chapter, titled "Dar
winism's Present Standing," clearly reflected Kellogg's beliefs about the actual state of
Darwinism in the early twentieth century: "Darwinism, then, as the natural selection
of the fit, the final arbiter in descent control, stands unscathed, clear and high above
the obscuring cloud of battle" (Kellogg, 1907, p. 374).
Among the extreme neo-Darwinians and their equally intemperate opponents, Kellogg
was happy to discover Ludwig Plate's (1903) book, ?ber die Bedeutung der Darwin'schen
Selectionsprinzip und Pr?bleme der Artbildung [Concerning the Meaning of the Darwin
ian Selection Principle and the Problem of Development], which he called "mostly quite
fair and unprejudiced" (Kellogg, 1907, p. 165). In November 1906, he wrote to Jor
dan explaining how "Plate has?with great care and thoroughness gone over all the work
and literature of the objections to Darwinism?abstracted them, analyzed and answered
them, or admitted their validity." In a single sentence Kellogg simultaneously portrayed the
polemic nature of the debate in Europe and his general irritation with German biologists:
"[Plate's book] is singularly impartial for a German and he puts the natural selection theory
on a footing which will be satisfactory to all but rabid Weismannians and yet is practically
unassaultable [sic] by the modern host of anti-Darwinians."
A month later he again wrote to Jordan explaining his plan to write an American
version of Plate's book, and he wrote to his editor explaining the great need of a book
that would serve as "a means of orientation for American students and general read
ers on the present day biological work and thought." Kellogg intended to address
Darwinism To-Day to laypeople and explained that it would be easily readable and
written without too many technical terms, making it an "easy club and woman's
pocket guide to heterogenesis, orthogenesis, metagenesis, and other awful words." In
January 1906, Kellogg sent a draft of the preface and a detailed table of contents to
Luther Burbank along with a note that described the book as "a fair and comprehen
sive statement of the status of the selection factors (Darwinism) in biological science
today as an explanation of evolution and a clear statement and brief critical discussion
of the various auxiliary and substitutionary theories that have been offered up to date
to aid or to replace the selection theories."16
The majority of Darwinism To-Day consisted of Kellogg's analysis of the attacks
against and defenses of Darwinism and the theories that biologists have offered to
that natural selection could operate. The recognition of this problem originated from
Fleeming Jenkin's criticisms of Darwin's theory; Jenkin argued that lone variations
could not survive because they would quickly be overwhelmed and statistically annihi
lated as "no single variation could survive being blended back into an ocean of normal
peers." Third, Kellogg explained "the great need of explaining adaptation," environ
mentally caused transmutations that appeared to support Lamarckian explanations
of evolution. Many "apparently nonsignificant ontogenetic differences or variations
appear as direct result of environmental influence or stimulus." Therefore, he argued,
evolutionary scientists needed to examine the possible effects of the environment in
stimulating or directing the evolution of organisms.17 Claims by some historians that
Darwinism To-Day demonstrated the naturalist-experimentalist dichotomy overlook
the fact that Kellogg saw the solution for Darwinism's shortcoming in the experimen
tal work that was being done on variation and heredity.
Book reviews contemporary with the publication of Darwinism To-Day clearly
indicated that Kellogg succeeded in convincing readers that Darwinism was alive and
well. The anonymous review in the Annals of the American Academy asserted, "The
final conclusion reached is, that while obviously many of Darwin's ideas were errone
ous, that Darwinism is far from dead. . . . The opponents of natural selection have
failed to displace it" (Anonymous, 1908). Likewise, in his review of the book in the
American Naturalist, Frank Lutz (1908) quoted Kellogg's statement that "Darwin
ism, then, as the natural selection of the fit, the final arbiter in descent-control, stands
unscathed, clear and high above the obscuring cloud of batde." Jordan, one man who
must surely have known Kellogg's intentions in writing Darwinism To-Day, asserted
in his review of the book that Kellogg was "even-handed" and "steady-headed" in his
acceptance of Darwinism as an explanation of the origin of new species.18
While Kellogg concluded that Darwinism was not dead, he was obliged to admit
that it was also not left unscathed by the attacks on it. He acknowledged that Dar
win's theory of natural selection alone could not explain the beginnings of change,
the source or sources of new variations on which Darwinian natural selection, sex
ual selection, and artificial selection could operate. With that recognition, Kellogg
attempted to improve the quality of evolutionary studies by positing a research pro
gram that would "relieve Darwinism of its necessity of asking natural selection to find
in the fluctuation of individual variations a handle for its action." This, he believed,
demanded an intensive study of variation, what he called the experimental study of
the stimuli, external and internal, and the influences, extrinsic and intrinsic, which are
the factors and causes of variation. "The neglect on the part of the selectionists to pay
sufficient attention to the origin and causes of the variation," he argued, "has been
one of the most obvious reasons for the present strong reaction against the selection
theories of Kellogg" (1907, pp. 374, 378-379).
Kellogg's concern for the status of Darwinian evolutionary theories was intricately
connected with his promotion of the practical applications for evolutionary science.
He explained that educated citizens, scientific laymen, sociologists, philosophers, and
even theologians are "bound to be disturbed and unsetded by rumours [sic] from the
camp of professional biologists of any weakness or mortal illness of Darwinism." He
was further concerned that the supposed weaknesses of Darwinism were grossly over
stated, especially by German anti-Darwinians: "We have only just got ourselves and
our conceptions of nature, of sociology and philosophy, well oriented and adjusted
with regard to Darwinism. And for relentiess hands now to come and clutch away
our foundations is simply intolerable. Zum Teufel [To the devil] with these German
professors!" Darwinism To-Day was Kellogg's attempt to wrestle control of the pub
lic's perception of evolution from what he viewed as two evolutionary extremes. It
was his defense of Darwinism against neo-Darwinians, who pushed Darwin's theory
of natural selection too far by claiming that it alone accounted for all evolutionary
change, and the anti-Darwinists, who were equally extreme in attacking and dismiss
ing Darwin's theory of natural selection. Far from merely claiming that Darwinism
stood "seriously discredited in the biological world," Kellogg argued, "no replacing
hypothesis or theory of species-forming has been offered by the opponents of selec
tion which has met with any general or even considerable acceptance by naturalists."
Darwinism, Kellogg concluded, was far from its deathbed (Kellogg, 1907, p. 5).
Darwinism To-Day heralded the primacy of Darwinian natural selection, it explored
the details of alternative and additive theories of evolution and?most significantly?it
presented some of the shortcomings of early twentieth-century evolutionary theory
that Kellogg believed his colleagues needed to address as they continued to move
their discipline forward. Hardly a cry from the dark age of evolutionary thought, the
book celebrated the progress made in the field and presented a plan for even more
fruitful work. Nowhere else is this view as clearly demonstrated as it was in Stephen
Jay Gould's magnum opus, The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. In his work, Gould
described how he valued Kellogg's interpretation of the relationship of Darwinian
natural selection to competing and complementary theories of evolution. Kellogg's
argument, he explained, "correctly represents, in my view, the relationship of modern
hierarchical selection theory to classical Darwinism and to the Modern Synthesis as
well." Gould (2002) intentionally used the same framework that Kellogg did in Dar
winism To-Day. He also attacked cynicism about the state of Darwin a century after
Kellogg, explaining, "the demise of Darwinism has been trumpeted more often than
the guard changes at Buckingham Palace, notwithstanding the evident fact that both
seem to stand firm as venerable British institutions." We should no more consider
Darwin eclipsed in the minds of Kellogg and his colleagues than we would among
biologists today (Gould, 2002, pp. 216-217, 353, 383, 489, 506-507, 585, 589).
evolution by natural selection is fundamentally different than what was done in Dar
win's day. Likewise, the modern evolutionary synthesis represents something both
cognitively and, as Cain and Smocovitis have argued, disciplinarily different. It is not,
however, appropriate to adopt a term popularized by the succeeding generation of
historical actors. Doing so allows historical actors to write their own histories, some
thing no academic historical discipline sanctions.
The era of the so-called eclipse of Darwinism was, in fact, a dynamic and exciting
time in the history of evolutionary biology, far from being the dark age. American
biologists who worked in the late nineteenth and early twentieth century laid the
very foundation for synthesis authors, and powerfully impacted their education and
early careers. Take, for example, Sewall Wright. In his biography of Wright, Provine
explained that Kellogg's Darwinism To-Day made the "greatest impression" of all
the books on evolution that Wright read as a young professional, and Provine called
the book "even at this writing one of the two best accounts of the various compet
ing theories of evolution and heredity that abounded in the late nineteenth century."
Later in the biography, he stated that Darwinism To-Day "was assigned reading for
almost every college-level course dealing with evolutionary biology in the decade after
its publication" (Provine, 1986, pp. 24-25, 228).
Perhaps nowhere are the enthusiasm, energy and potential of early twentieth
century evolutionary biology as clearly evident as in the final chapter of Kellogg's
Darwinism To-Day. In contrast to the "intemperate and indecent" claims that occa
sionally came from European neo-Darwinists and anti-Darwinists, Kellogg offered
an optimistic call to evolutionary biologists. Asserting that "we are ignorant; terribly,
immensely ignorant," and he argued that the task before evolutionary biologists was
to learn "to observe, to experiment, to tabulate, to induce, to deduce" (Kellogg,
1907, pp. 6, 387). "Biology," he concluded, "was never a clearer or more inviting
field for fascinating, joyful, hopeful work." These are hardly the words of a man work
ing in the dark age of evolution biology.
By lifting the veil of the eclipse by recognizing the confining and distorting impact
of the phrase "eclipse of Darwin," we can reveal all sorts of valuable historical, his
toriographical, and scientific issues. If Kellogg was a Darwinian during the era of the
supposed eclipse, what other Darwinians are out there? David Starr Jordan, C. Hart
Merriam, and William Keith Brooks, all noted early twentieth-century Darwinists,
have seen some work. Who else considered themselves Darwinians, regardless of cur
rent historians' claims that "there weren't any," and how did they define Darwinism?
We need to make a close examination of other early twentieth-century American biol
ogists to see what they meant when they talked about Darwinism. Among the people
who have not yet seen enough study are Charles Davenport, Leon Cole, Maurice Big
elow, Frank Lillie, and dozens of other early twentieth-century biologists. Analyzing
them we may well find, as I suspect, that throughout the era of the supposed eclipse
of Darwinism, Darwin's methods and claims thrived in work done on eugenics and
nature study and in certain locations, like the newly formed experimental stations on
both coasts and in breeding farms around the country.
A more accurate and complete picture of evolutionary biology in early twentieth
century America may also provide valuable information about later developments in
evolutionary biology. The modern evolutionary synthesis certainly appears to have been
a departure from previous work, both in terms of some of the technical components
Conclusion
I would like to offer a potential replacement for the metaphor of the eclipse; in
of calling the period from 1880 to about 1940 the eclipse, I encourage you to use
term "interphase," which was suggested to me by Paul Farber and is borrowed f
cell biology.
Through the mid-1960s, the interphase was a time in cellular division when
researchers believed that very little was happening. For example, Alfred Elliott and
Charles Ray, Jr., in their 1967 textbook Biology, explained, "The so-called 'resting'
phase or interphase is a state when there is little or no apparent activity in the nucleus"
(Elliott & Ray, 1965). Shortly thereafter, biologists came to understand the inter
phase as not a time of rest, but rather as a period in cell division when a great deal
of vital activity is taking place, activity that is necessary for later developments. In his
1980 textbook Biological Science, William Keeton explained, "The nondividing cell
is said to be in the interphase state. In past years, such a cell was commonly called a
resting cell, but this terminology has been abandoned as grossly inappropriate. The
interphase cell is definitely not resting; it is carrying out all the innumerable activities
of a living, functioning cell" (Keeton, 1980, p. 560).
Those familiar with cell biology and with the history of cell biology will recognize
that the term interphase works on two levels as a replacement for the phrase "eclipse
of Darwinism." As with the interphase, we once imagined that the era of the so-called
eclipse of Darwin was a time when little productive work took place, a time when a
generation of biologists made little or no progress. It was, in reality, a time of tremen
dous activity, all of which was vital to later developments that took place in evolutionary
biology.
Like cell biologists' previous notions of the interphase, I recommend we abandon
the metaphor of eclipse as grossly inappropriate. It is a vestigial structure of the mod
ern evolutionary synthesis, and the historians who unquestionably adopted the term
from their historical subjects have not yet adequately challenged their subjects' depic
tions of the research that preceded them. The term is a lingering relic that is no longer
necessary and ultimately harmful to our ability accurately to depict twentieth-century
evolutionary biology, so we should replace it and generate a more accurate assessment
of the innumerable activities of the living, functioning careers of those who worked
in the era before the synthesis. We need a new term and a new conception of the
work done in evolutionary biology between 1880 and 1940, one that analyzes early
twentieth-century evolutionary biology on its own terms, not merely in the context
of what followed it.
Acknowledgments
The author wishes to thank Joe Cain, Michael Ruse, Paul Farber, Chris Young, and
especially John P. Jackson, Jr., for their encouragement and suggestions.
Notes
1. For the purposes of this chapter, I will assume that the phrases "eclipse of Darwi
"eclipse of Darwinism" are synonymous. There is, however, an argument to be ma
"eclipse of Darwin" refers to the rejection of Darwin's use of inductive methodolog
"eclipse of Darwinism" describes the rejection of natural selection as the principle
changing agent.
2. Ruse (1996). When I asked him why he did not include in his book any American evo
ary biologists who worked during the era of the eclipse, Ruse said, "I did not writ
them, because there weren't any."
3. For an excellent discussion of the propagandist^ origins and uses of the term "Dar
see Russell (1991). My analysis of the phrase "eclipse of Darwinism" was powerfully
enced by Russell's arguments. For him, as for me, the derogatory nature of phrases and
like "eclipse of Darwinism" and "Dark Ages" is deeply problematic. We both are tr
resurrect the status of the eras we study by attacking problematic labels attached to th
4. Bowler (1983, p. 5) incorrectly assumed Huxley originated the phrase "eclipse of D
ism," presumably because the first time the term appeared in print was in Huxley
Smocovitis (1999; 2005) made the same claim.
5. David Starr Jordan, "The Ways of Organic Evolution," Unpublished manuscript, Dav
Jordan Papers, Stanford University Libraries Archives. The manuscript, titled "The
Organic Evolution," was discovered among Jordan's papers at Stanford University's
and reassembled by Jane Maienschein and David Magnus. It was to have been Jordan's last
statement on the subject of evolution, written ca. 1925.
6. Among the definitions of eclipse offered by the Oxford English Dictionary is its use in the
astronomical sense: "An interception or obscuration of the light of the sun, moon, or other
luminous body, by the intervention of some other body, either between it and the eye, or
between the luminous body and that illuminated by it; as of the moon, by passing through
the earth's shadow; of the sun, by the moon coming between it and the observer; or of a satel
lite, by entering the shadow of its primary"; as well as figuratively: "Obscuration, obscurity;
dimness; loss of brilliance or splendour." When used as an astronomical term, as it was by
Huxley, the term necessitates the eventual return of the luminous body Jordan used the term
"eclipse" in the figurative sense, which does not necessitate the eventual return to splendor of
the eclipsed object; in this case, Darwinism.
7. Smocovitis (1996, pp. 117-122). Quotes are from Kellogg (1907, pp. 1-2).
8. The notion of a "historiographical blunder," as I use it here, is borrowed from Jackson
(2000), who traced the history of arguments made against the social scientists testifying in the
Brown v. Board case and argued that later critiques of their work are based on a fundamental
misunderstanding of the earlier social scientists' claims. By ignoring the context of the original
claims, Jackson asserted that historians were making "one of the worst historiographical blun
ders one can malee" by "pointing to scientific errors of the past using present-day scientific
knowledge" (Jackson, 2000, p. 47).
9. For a broader study of Kellogg, see Largent (2000a; 2000b).
10. Vernon Lyman Kellogg personal communication to David Starr Jordan, September 18,
1893, David Starr Jordan Papers, Stanford University Library Archives. Also Kellogg (1894;
1898).
11. Vernon Lyman Kellogg personal communication to David Starr Jordan, March 5, 1905,
David Starr Jordan Papers, Stanford University Library Archives. Vernon Lyman Kellogg
personal communication to David Starr Jordan, March 9, 1905, David Starr Jordan Papers,
Stanford University Library Archives.
12. Kellogg (1907, pp. 130, 122-132, 374). Vernon Lyman Kellogg personal communication
to David Starr Jordan, December 20, 1905, David Starr Jordan Papers, Stanford University
Library Archives.
13. Kellogg (1907, pp. 4-7, 375). Vernon Lyman Kellogg personal communication to David
Starr Jordan, November 13, 1904, David Starr Jordan Papers, Stanford University Library
Archives.
14. Not surprisingly, Huxley's chapter "The eclipse of Darwinism" (1942, p. 22) began in pre
cisely the same manner.
15. Kellogg (1907, pp. 1, 5-6). Kellogg cited Dennert (1903, p. 4), but also see Dennert (1904)
and Wolff (1898, p. 54).
16. Vernon Lyman Kellogg to David Starr Jordan, November 7, 1904, David Starr Jordan
Papers, Stanford University Library Archives. Vernon Lyman Kellogg to David Starr Jordan,
December 12, 1905, David Starr Jordan Papers, Stanford University Library Archives. Ver
non Lyman Kellogg to Luther Burbank, January 16, 1906, Luther Burbank Papers, Library
of Congress.
17. Vernon Lyman Kellogg to David Starr Jordan, December 12, 1905, David Starr Jordan
Papers, Stanford University Library Archives. Kellogg (1907, pp. 376, 379, 383). Also see
Desmond and Moore (1994, p. 547) and Jenkin (1867).
18. Also, see Jordan (1907). The passage Lutz quoted is from Kellogg (1907, p. 374).
19. The principal argument regarding the problematic nature of the term "social Darwinism"
was offered by Bannister (1979). Both Kellogg and Jordan helped popularize the term as an
attack on German militarists. See, for example, Kellogg (1918) and Jordan (1918).
References
Anonymous. (1908). [Review of the book Darwinism To-Day]. The Annals of the American
Academy, 32, 182-183.
Bannister, R. C. (1979). Social Darwinism: Science and myth in Anglo-American social thought
Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Bowler, P. (1983). The eclipse of Darwinism: Anti-Darwinian evolution theories in the decades
around 1900. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Cravens, H. (1978). The triumph of evolution: The heredity-environment controversy, 1900
1941. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Crook, P. (1994). Darwinism, war and history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Degler, C. (1991). In search of human nature: The decline and revival of Darwinism in Ameri
can social thought. New York: Oxford University Press.
Dennert, E. (1903). Vom sterbelager des Darwinismus. Stuttgart: Richard Miihlmann's
Verlag.
Dennert, E. (1995). At the Deathbed of Darwinism. (E. V. O'Harra & J. H. Peschges, Trans.).
In Numbers, Ronald (Ed.), Anti-evolutionism before World War I, volume I, creationism
in twentieth-century America: A ten-volume anthology of documents, 1903-1961 (Vol. 1,
pp. 177-321). New York: Garland. (Reprinted from At the Deathbed of Darwinism, by
Eberhard Dennert, 1904, Burlington: German Literary Board).
Desmond, A., & Moore, J. (1994). Darwin: The life of a tormented evolutionist. New York: W.
W. Norton.
Elliott, A., & Ray, C, Jr. (1965). Biology. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Farber, P. (2000). Finding order in nature: The naturalist tradition from Linnaeus to E. O.
Wilson. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Glick, T. (Ed.). (1974). The comparative reception of Darwinism. Chicago: University of Chi
cago Press.
Gould, S. J. (2002). The structure of evolutionary theory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Grabiner, J., 8c Miller, P. (1974). Effects of the Scopes trial. Science, 185, 832-837.
Huxley, J. (1942). Evolution: The modern synthesis. New York: Harper.
Jackson, J., Jr. (2000). The triumph of the segregationists? A historical inquiry into psychology
and the Brown litigation. History of Psychology, 3, 239-261.
Jenkin, F. (1867). The origin of species. North British Review, 46, 277-318.
Jordan, D. S. (1907). The present status of Darwinism. The Dial, 43, 161-163.
Jordan, D. S. (1916). Plea for old-fashioned natural history. Bulletin of the Scripps Institution
for Biological Research, 1, 2-5.
Jordan, D. S. (1918). Social Darwinism. Public, 1918, 400-401.
Keeton, W. T. (1980). Biological science (3rd ed.). New York: W. W. Norton.
Kellogg, V. L. (1894, January 4). On a student's first day. Kansas University Courier.
Kellogg, V. L. (1898). Rudolf Leuckart. Psyche, 8, 214-215.
Kellogg, V. L. (1907). Darwinism to-day: A discussion of present-day scientific criticism of the
Darwinian selection theory, together with a brief account of the principal other proposed
auxiliary and alternative theories of species-forming. New York: Henry Holt.
Kellogg, V. L. (1909). The upholding of Darwin: Poulton and Plate on evolution. The Ameri
can Naturalist, 43, 317-320.