Jurnal Ks
Jurnal Ks
Jurnal Ks
During the past decade we have witnessed renewed interest in the study and analysis
of both social policy and social structure. Journalists, administrators, politicians,
welfare personnel and social scientists have extensively been engaged in the interpre-
tation and assessment of the impact of social policy on social structure and vice versa.
Downloaded by The University of British Columbia Library At 20:37 30 January 2016 (PT)
It would appear that the return of liberal governments in the United States, the
United Kingdom and Australia had much to do with this time-honoured revival. In
the United States this activity can be largely attributed to the promise of the "Great
Society" - an attempt by the Johnson administration (1963-1968) to eliminate pov-
erty, create employment, improve medical care and education and revitalise cities
and rural areas. In the United Kingdom the Labour Governments of Wilson (1964-
1970; 1974-1976) and Callaghan (1976-1979) held out similar promises for a more
equitable society. Predictably the literature on social policy and social structure
increased accordingly.
16
The implicit identification of social policy with welfare politics may not have
been intended by the architects of the new Fabian Society. Nevertheless most
Australian theoretical treatises and research publications quite explicitly equate
social policy with a truncated notion of welfare politics and oftentimes narrow the
broad field of social policy to the small albeit important topics of wealth and income
redistribution. In so doing they largely emulate their British and American
colleagues who were equally explicit in limiting the study of social policy to the
examination of distributive justice. Thus T.H. Marshall (1965), the doyen of British
social policy spokesmen, defines social policy as the "policy of governments with
regard to action having a direct impact on the welfare of citizens, by providing them
Downloaded by The University of British Columbia Library At 20:37 30 January 2016 (PT)
with services or income. The central core consists, therefore, of social insurance,
public (or national) assistance, the health and welfare services, and housing policy"
(p.7). Martin Rein (1970), the American doppelgaenger of T.H. Marshall, views
social policy analysis in a similar vein when he reduces social policy to the planning
for social externalities, and the equitable distribution of social benefits, especially
social services. Graycar (1977), on the other hand, offers a more encompassing
definition of social policy when he first defines it as the result "of a desire to pursue
social justice, to achieve equality, to effect redistribution or to ensure the efficient
functioning of society" (p.3 - emphasis added). In his more recent work, however, he
too suggests that social policy is mainly to be equated with welfare politics (1978,
1979). More to the point yet: a national conference on social policy in the 1980's
(Canberra, 1982) almost exclusively featured speakers who took it for granted that
social policy is to be equated with welfare distribution and administration.
Despite our assertion of a temporal and conceptual affinity between the notions
of social policy and social structure a search of the literature reveals a peculiar
hiatus between these two concepts. The gap is two-fold: first, definitions of social
policy typically do not make explicit reference to social structure; second, computer
searches of Books in Print, Sociological Absracts and Psychological Information
Databases produced 1,245 entries on social policy, 4,300 entries on social structure,
and a grand total of 26 entries where both concepts were indexed together. Yet
publications on social policy and social structure wax and wane together as Figure 1
demonstrates.
Figure 1 presents the bi-ennial count of entries of social policy and social structure
as a percentage of all entries in Sociological Abstracts from 1964 to 1981. Two
features stand out: the seventies are characterised by a continuous increase in the
relative importance of studies in social policy and social structure as publication
material. In addition, the two are highly correlated over time (Pearson's r = +.73).
How can these divergent observations be reconciled? Two explanations come to
mind: first, there is little agreement concerning the definitions of both social policy
and social structure among the many writers on these topics. Second, the concept of
social policy has disproportionately often been limited to the study of a truncated
notion of the social welfare system. Consequently it appeared irrelevant to many
aspects of social and societal structure. As a result, the concepts of social policy and
social structure are only rarely linked explicitly in most publications (hence the few
entries which index both). However, the two concepts are intrinsically ordained
toward each other. This may account for the simultaneous growth and decline of
publications in both areas. At this point we are not prepared to offer an
17
Downloaded by The University of British Columbia Library At 20:37 30 January 2016 (PT)
18
interpretation of the most recent decrease in publishing activity although it could be
suggested that it mirrors the disenchantment of social engineers because of the
economic crisis and the victory of conservative governments in Australia, the United
Kingdom and the United States.
The purpose of this article is to broaden and specify the concepts of social policy
and social structure. This is attempted by providing definitions of social policy and
social structure and highlighting how these two concepts are interrelated. The
emphasis rests on the specification and elaboration of the component parts of these
two crucial concepts.
Downloaded by The University of British Columbia Library At 20:37 30 January 2016 (PT)
In our view, limiting social policy to welfare is extremely unfortunate and totally
unacceptable. It is unfortunate in as much as it deprives the study of social policy of
the broader context of social justice and societal interaction. By restricting social
policy to welfare administration one perpetuates the practice of excluding public
subsidies to the middle class and the rich from discussions of the social welfare
system. For instance, social policy analysis restricted to welfare administration
would typically fail to consider such issues as free tertiary education for the middle
class and rich in Australia. University fees were abolished in 1974 in an attempt to
enable the poor and underprivileged to attend tertiary studies. Little has been
accomplished except that the poor now finance the education of the well-to-do.
(See Anderson and Vervoorn (1983).) It is apposite to note that the university
graduate commands an above average salary after four years (each of 30 weeks) of
study which is not only tuition-free but also subsidised for everyday living expenses.
This subsidy amounts to about 3,000 per annum. A similar situation prevails
concerning the construction of superhighways through most American cities for the
convenience of the relatively well-to-do suburbanite irrespective of the cost to the
dwellers in the inner city. The inner city predictably turned into slum, partly
because of a federal policy not to grant any housing assistance for these less
desirable living quarters. The reduced scope of social policy as the distribution of
welfare benefits in the traditional sense not only dismisses justice as the relevant
criterion but also fails to consider many of the less obvious welfare payments to
privileged classes.
For these reasons we prefer to view the study of social policy as the critical
examination of the planning and implementation of social justice. By social justice
we refer to the moral imperative that equals be treated equally and unequals
according to their relevant inequalities. Social justice thus implies equitable rather
19
than equal treatment. It also puts the onus of proof for justifying differential
treatment on whoever wants to make distinctions. This line of reasoning stems
directly from Plato's Republic and Aristotle's Nichomachean Ethics.
competing teams be reshuffled to ensure that a "fair" play will result. Thus the
concept of "fairness" in sports - "that's not fair," "that's not cricket," "fair go ya
mug" - does not refer to the redistribution of basic team assets but rather to equal
treatment of all players according to the rules of the game. It is noteworthy that in
sports, rules precede fairness; similarly, in social policy, rights precede justice - at
least according to Thomas Aquinas (Summa Contra Gentes, 2,28). In addition fair
rules vary from one sport to the next. Should one expect rules of fairness and equity
to vary from one policy area to the next? Still, when does inequality become
inequitable? We suggest that inequality is inequitable in terms of social policy
formulation whenever the following two conditions apply:
-it is believed that something can be done about this perceived inequality.
Without the potential for improvement, social policy efforts remain doomed to
failure. This implicitly challenges the profoundly held article of faith in social
administration, namely, that all social problems are amenable to solution, or at
least to amelioration (Pinker, 1982).
Given that equity and justice have different denotations in different policy areas,
it is helpful to differentiate among three types of social policy as Thomas Aquinas
does in his discussion of justice (Summa Theologiae, II, II). Aquinas notes two
essential characteristics of justice. First, justice always deals with a relationship
between at least two actors and, second, the distinguishing mark of justice is that
some debt is to be paid. The nature of the debt to be paid varies depending on the
actors engaged in the relationship under discussion. On this basis Aquinas suggests
three types of social justice as diagrammed in Figure 2.
20
Downloaded by The University of British Columbia Library At 20:37 30 January 2016 (PT)
21
The complementarity of distributive and restributive justice is acknowledged by
contemporary writers as well. Rawls (1972) in his A Theory of Justice develops two
principals of justice. His first principle links restributive (legal) justice with civil
liberty when it stipulates that "each person is to have an equal right to the most
extensive total system of equal basic liberties comparable with a similar system for
all" (p.302). Basic liberties refer to freedom of thought and conscience as well as
liberty of speech and assembly. The second principle asserts "that social and
economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both: (a) to the greatest
benefit of the least advantaged, consistent with the just savings principle, and (b)
attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of
Downloaded by The University of British Columbia Library At 20:37 30 January 2016 (PT)
opportunity" (p.302). In the second principle one may note an overlap between
distributive justice and social security. Brennan's (1983) incisive comment on
Rawls' two principles further links social security and distributive justice when he
offers a first preliminary principle: "Each person is to have the right to necessaries
of life, including food, shelter, and other things required for survival, and the right
to security so those necessaries may be retained and used" (p.203). Brennan's
second preliminary principle connects restributive justice with civil liberty when it
states that "every person is to have the right to live under a just (or nearly just)
constitution. If such a constitution is to endure, it must be assured of a background
of relative stability and of substantial compliance by all citizens with their natural
duties and political and moral obligations" (203).
Still the concept of equity has come under fierce attack particularly by the radical
left because equity implies that - depending on the policy area - equitable treatment
may not be equal and vice versa. Stilwell (1980) in a rhetorical outburst dismisses
the notion of equity as part of the lexicon of "snake oil merchants who try to justify
the cutbacks in social welfare and the widening of recession." Our understanding of
social welfare suggests that concern for equity rather than equality permits
extensive and effective redress of social injustice. For instance, the argument for
progressive taxation where the individual capacity to pay is taken as a ground for
discrimination presupposes a decision in favour of equity rather than equality. Lest
there be a misunderstanding, equity subsumes and treats as a special case the
22
concern for equality. This is already implied by our definition of justice. It also may
explain why a good deal of the traditional equality literature effectively amounts to
a proposition for equitable rather than equal treatment.
different groups and individuals among them" (1952, p.39). Pinker (1982) is
equally adamant when he observes that "radical change in social policy does not
abolish the criteria by which we allocate welfare goods and services; it simply
changes them." He is yet more challenging when he suggests that "social workers
today may identify themselves with the minority of deprived citizens who are
victims of change in the mixed capitalist society, but if processes of radical change
eventually give rise to a more egalitarian society, they are likely to find themselves
ministering to the needs of a dispossessed and alienated bourgeoisie" (p. 13).
Clearly poverty is not overcome by abolishing wealth. Finally, affirmative action
programmes typically rest on the concept of equity rather than equality. There
would be no room for reverse or positive discrimination (most welfare program-
mes) if treatment were to be based on equality rather than equity.
The concepts of social justice and equity point to the need for the study of social
change and invite a broader definition of social policy. Peter Townsend's (1975)
definition of social policy is sufficiently broad and specific for our purpose. He
defines social policy as those mechanisms and processes "whereby societies
prevent, postpone, introduce and manage changes in structure" (p.2). This
definition is broad enough to permit the study and examination of all three sides of
the justice triangle. Still we wish to extend this definition by substituting "social
systems" for "societies" in order to include both social organisations and entire
societies in our analysis. In so doing we do not subscribe to the distinction between
social and societal policy. Ferge (1978) defines social policy as "handling essentially
central redistribution" and societal policy as "aiming deliberately at the trans-
formation of structural social relations in accordance with socialist aims" (p.82).
We imply that any redistribution results in a realignment of social structure and vice
versa.
Our notion of social policy is not limited to the traditional concerns of welfare
politics (health, education, housing and income maintenance). It also includes the
frequently neglected areas of civil liberty (freedom of thought, conscience, speech
and assembly as well as the right to privacy, property and protection). Further
social control, that is, problems of system boundary permeability (migration and
international trade policies) and system regulation (e.g. civil duties, control of
substance use, gambling and fair trade practices) are core areas of social policy.
Our intention is not to deal with any of these social policy areas in detail but rather
to broaden our definition of social policy and to alert the reader to the fact that
modification of any policy issue is likely to have implications for other policy areas.
23
Our definition of social policy also implies that social policy may be based on
social action or inaction, that is, changes in structure may be brought about by
commission as well as omission. Laissez faire is therefore not viewed as the absence
of policy (as the literal meaning suggests) but rather as the endorsement of a
specific policy model. Similarly, mechanisms which hinder rather than help
structural change are core elements in the study of social policy. As the proposed
definition leaves empirically and ideologically problematic the desirability of
structural change, it permits detached examination of the startling situation which
frequently results when social policy cross-cuts ideology. Ideology, of course,
results whenever we mistakenly take our preference for a given theory as the final
Downloaded by The University of British Columbia Library At 20:37 30 January 2016 (PT)
truth. Despite all our commitments to the creation of a more equitable and just
world our theories should be treated as conjectures and our methods of scientific
enquiry should consist of ingenious and severe attempts to refute them (Popper,
1981, pp.80-81). As a result it is "vitally important for the subject of social policy
and administration to remain answerable to the academic community, notwith-
standing its association with politics and policy-making" (Pinker, 1982, p.8).
24
from the Latin struere meaning "to heap up," "to build." Thus "something" is used
as building blocks to produce a "structure". What are these building blocks? The
authors diverge. The first group treats as structural building blocks the relative
frequencies in each of several categories of certain variables of interest. Thus
demographers speak of the occupational structure of a society and refer to the
proportion of the labour force found in various occupational slots, e.g.,
professionals, graziers, clerical, operatives, etc. Population pyramids - often
referred to as graphic displays of population structures - rest on a similar notion of
categorical frequencies of the age and sex distributions. Usually little effort is made
to show how these categories relate to each other and how these relationships affect
Downloaded by The University of British Columbia Library At 20:37 30 January 2016 (PT)
social interaction.
A fourth kind of building block for structural analysis combines the building
blocks of the second and third approaches and focuses on relationships of social
actors. Social structure is thus defined as a pervasive pattern or network of
relationships among social positions. This is the definition of social structure most
suitable for the study of social policy. The proposed definition emphasises both the
social and concrete dimensions of the concept "structure". Concreteness is assured
because the focus is on actual relationships rather than on subjective meaning
elements; and the social aspect is preserved because the concern is with positions
rather than with incumbents of positions or individual elements. The distinction
between positions and incumbents is important in this context because a given
incumbent may occupy several positions, that is, play various roles. Our definition
of social structure has been suggested by Laumann and Pappi (1976) who
specifically identify the unit of structural analysis as the relationship between any
pair of actors. The concept of social actor leaves as empirically problematic the
level of analysis and suggests that individuals, groups, organisations and societies
25
may be used as the end points (or nodes) of a specific relationship. Given our notion
that social policy result from commission or omission it is evident that the absence of a
relationship between two actors is as important as its presence.
26
teacher interaction is very much subject to situational definition by different action
systems. More than that, Parsons observes that the role expectations of two actors
may not be symmetrical. Thus the patient may expect his physician to provide
emotional nurturance while the professional orientation of the physician suggests
emotional detachment. Parsons' concern then is to provide normative templates of
abstractly defined social relationships which permit the researcher to compare them
against the observed reality and to specify the degree to which the latter
approximates the former. The nomenclature of the pattern variables implies
dichotomies. However there is no apparent reason why the pattern variables could
not be measured in a more refined fashion, particularly since the underlying
Downloaded by The University of British Columbia Library At 20:37 30 January 2016 (PT)
27
the notion of "burden of proof in clarifying conflict situations about role
obligations: if two actors cannot agree whether a given function is normatively
included in the role definition, the relationship is said to be specific if the actor
requesting the service must prove its legitimacy within the role expectation; it is
said to be diffuse if the actor refusing the service is expected to justify such a
refusal. For example, it is perfectly appropriate for a parent to inquire from a
teenage daughter as to her whereabouts this morning at 3 a.m. The same inquiry
from the milkman would presumably be judged inappropriate. Refusal of the
requested information in the former instance would have to be justified by the
daughter (diffuse relationsip) whereas in the latter situation any claim to an answer
Downloaded by The University of British Columbia Library At 20:37 30 January 2016 (PT)
The remaining two pattern variables deal with ways judged appropriate for
treating role actors. The first focuses on the universalism-particularism distinction.
It can perhaps be conceptualised by asking how appropriate it is to substitute one
social actor for another. Thus the question is whether an actor is to be judged in
terms of some universal standard or in terms of some particular frame of reference
in which ego is personally involved. For instance, bank tellers, taxi drivers and
lecturers are supposed to be chosen in terms of some universally agreed-upon
standard rather than in terms of personal consideration such as whether a given
actor happens to be a cousin, neighbour or personal acquaintance. Thus criteria
employed for the selection of such personnel permit one to determine the degree to
which a relationship is universalistic. Inasmuch as the occupancy of a given position
by a specific incumbent results in a role transformation, the role may be judged
particularistic. Alternatively, one might enquire of participants in the system
whether or not different incumbents of a specific position (e.g., teacher, student,
business partner) are treated alike. To the extent that identical behaviours of all
incumbents are reported by all (or the majority of) participants, the role may be
deemed universal. Specifically one may want to gauge the degree of particularism
by computing a weighted average of how much relationship-specific criteria are
applied in the selection or treatment of social actors. Clearly, if nepotism instead of
competence is the decisive criterion for treating social actors in normatively
universal relationships, systematic deviance results. Social policy based on equality
largely favours the universalistically defined social relationships whereas the equity
28
argument presupposes a particularistic definition of the relationship as it permits
the differential treatment of actors on situation-specific criteria. However it should
be noted that this very distinction depends on the definition of system boundaries:
particularism tends to give way to universalism as the system grows.
physical attractiveness, age, sex and racial origin prevail in the selection and
treatment of social actors a relationship is termed quality-oriented; conversely, if
effort, performance and excellence are prime considerations, the relationship is
said to be achievement-oriented. Thus the person prepared to scold a coed is
quality-oriented if he addresses his insults to the lady while the person who directs
his comments mainly to the student is performance-oriented. In evaluating a
specific relationship one might draw up a list of suitable statements, perhaps of a
Likert-type, and compute an overall agreement score to compare actual rela-
tionships with each other or against a normatively defined situation. Titmuss (1974)
recognises the quality-performance distinction when he adds to his residual and
institutional redistribution models of social policy a third model: the industrial
achievement-performance model. He does not have much to say about this model,
because its assumed ideology of laissez faire is discussed in the context of the
residual model. Traditional welfare politics have little use for the industrial
achievement-performance model. This model holds that social needs should be met
on the basis of merit, work performance and productivity. In social policy analysis,
however, it is of considerable importance, particularly in the debate of civil liberty
(private entrepreneurship) versus social security (shared social responsibility).
Universalism Bureaucracy
Specificity
Particularism
Universalism
Diffuseness
Particularism Parenthood
29
Given the above contingency table, the researcher may want to enter into the
resulting cells normatively defined or actually observed scores computed on the
basis of the above suggested methods for the description, analysis and comparison
of any two relationships. Of particular interest may be difference scores between
normatively defined and actually observed relationships in order to ascertain the
amount of deviance present in the system. These scores might then be used both to
measure strain perceived by social actors and to estimate the potential for
systematic change.
How can one justify this relaxation of Mitchell's definition if one wants to infer
the presence of links between nodes that are comprised of complex entities such as
political parties or ethnic groups? Laumann and Pappi (1976) suggest an appealing
solution to this problem. They propose that one may "consider the 'relationship'
between the two nodes consisting of complex entities as being indicated by the
differential likelihood that their constituent elements have the relationship in
question with one another" (p.19). For instance, Social Democrats may more
readily support Labour rather than Liberal party causes. Given such a tendency
one may suggest that the party of Social Democrats is closer to the Labour party
than to the Liberal party. Given this relaxation of the network notion, all sorts of
social relationships may justifiably be subjected to network analysis and become
part of a structural analysis in an effort to shed additional light on social policy
issues.
Lest our definition of structure be dismissed as too static and hence irrelevant for
the study of social policy, three postulates of structural analysis must be identified
(see Laumann and Pappi, 1976, p.7-8):
31
Downloaded by The University of British Columbia Library At 20:37 30 January 2016 (PT)
Despite this seemlingly clear-cut definition of social indicators the vagueness and
elusiveness of the concept remain whenever they are used in actual research. The
major problem with social indicators derives from their very nature: they are
measures and surrogates (see Carley. 1981). As such they are affected by
32
measurement error and suffer from the less than perfect overlap with the reality
which they are to indicate. Even in situations where a strong correlation obtains
between the phenomenon (indicator) and the noumenon (the underlying reality of
interest), problems of both reliability and validity reign supreme. A relevant
example is provided by the legal presumption that blood alcohol concentration in
excess of .05 percent constitutes dangerous driving and the current debate of the
usefulness of random breathalyser tests for accident prevention. Incidentally, this
very debate neatly illustrates the precarious balance between providing social
security without unduly restricting civil liberty.
Downloaded by The University of British Columbia Library At 20:37 30 January 2016 (PT)
33
It would be futile to arbitrate between these two competing interpretations of
social indicators. Any indicator which can mean opposite things either is not an
indicator of an empirical referent or has arbitrarily been loaded with ideological
meaning elements foreign to it. It is at this point that social indicators become social
vindicators. We are not implying that data speak for themselves or even have an
objective existence of their own; rather data are information anchored in a
theoretical frame of reference. Thus the major problem with social indicators is not
the empirical observation but rather its interpretation. This points to two important
qualifications.
Downloaded by The University of British Columbia Library At 20:37 30 January 2016 (PT)
This article has attempted to identify the difference between traditional social
policy concepts and social policy as a modifier of social structure. It was noted that
a large number of writers have equated social policy with welfare politics. It was
also alleged that in doing so emphasis came to be placed on equal rather than
equitable treatment. To overcome this unduly narrow conceptualisation of social
policy it was argued that social policy should be predicated on the concepts of
equity and social justice. On this basis social policy was defined as those
mechanisms and processes whereby systems prevent, postpone, introduce and
manage structural change. This definition of social policy led to a definition of
structural change and its major components. The article concluded with some
observations about the usefulness and limitations of social indicators as a means of
examining social policy.
35
References
Alford, R.R. "Ideological filters and bureaucratic responses in interpreting research: Com-
munity planning and poverty." In Demerath, et al (Eds.), Social policy and
sociology. New York: Academic Press, 1975.
Anderson, D.S., and "Access to privilege: Patterns of participation in Australian post-secondary
Vervoom, A.E. education." Canberra: Australian National University, 1983.
Andrews, F.M., and "Measures of self-reported well-being: Their affective, cognitive, and other com-
McKcnnell, A.C. ponents." SocialIndicatorsResearch, 1980,8, 127-155.
Armstrong, A.F. "An introduction to social indicators." Proceedings of the National Social Indi-
cators Conference. Melbourne: Bureau of Statistics, 1981.
Atkinson, T. "The stability and validity of quality of life measures." Social Indicators Re-
search, 1982,10,113-132.
Downloaded by The University of British Columbia Library At 20:37 30 January 2016 (PT)
Campbell, A., The quality of American life: Perceptions, evaluations, and satisfactions. New
Converse, P., and York: Russell Sage, 1976.
Rodgers, W.
Brennan, F. Too much order with loo little law. Brisbane: University of Queensland Press,
19S3.
Carley, M. Social measurements and social indicators: Issues of policy and theory. London:
George Allen & Unwin, 1981.
Coutu, W. Emergent human nature, a symbolicfield interpretation. New York: A.A. Knopf,
1949.
Duncan, O.D. Toward social reporting: Nat steps. New York: Russell Sage Foundation, 1969.
Ferge, Z. "Hungary". In S.B. Kamerman & A.J. Kahn (Eds.), Family policy: Government
and families in fourteen countries. New York: Columbia University Press. 1978.
Frankel, M.R. Inference from survey samples. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan, 1971.
Freeman, H.E., and "Social indicators." In J.B. Turner et al (Eds.), Encyclopaedia of Social Work
Sheldon, E.B. (17th ed.). Washington: National Association of Social Workers, 1977, 2, 1350-
1354.
Gillin, J.P. The ways of man. New York: D. Appleton-Century Co., 1948.
Goodman, L.A. Analyzing qualitative/categorical data. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Abt Books,
1978.
Graycar, A. Social policy: An Australian introduction. Sydney: Macmillan, 1977.
Graycar, A. (Ed.) Perspectives in Australian social policy. Sydney: Macmillan, 1978.
Graycar, A. Welfare politics in Australia: A Study in policy analysis. Sydney: Macmillan, 1979.
Greenberg, J., and Equity and justice in social behaviour. New York: Academic Press, 1982.
Cohen, R.L.
Grichting, W.L. "Controlling alcohol abuse in Australia: From treatment to prevention." British
Journal of Addiction, 1983, 78, 37-50.
Heady, B., "Quality of life studies and the development of positive welfare programs." In J.
Holmstrom, E., and Dixon & D.L. Jayasuriya (Eds.), Social policy in the 1980s. Canberra: Canberra
Wearing, A. College of Advanced Education, 1983.
Kutz, T.J. "Quality of life, an objective and subjective variable analysis." Regional Studies,
1978, 12, 409-117.
Laumann, E.O., and Networks of collective action. New York: Academic Press, 1976.
Pappi. F.U.
Marshall, T.H. Social policy. London: Hutchinson, 1965.
Mitchell, J.D. (Ed.) Social networks in urban situations. Manchester, England: Manchester
University Press, 1969.
Nadel, S.F. The theory ofsocial structure. London: Cohen & West, 1957.
Parsons, T. The structure ofsocial action. New York: McGraw Hill, 1937.
Parsons, T. "A revised analytical approach to the theory of social stratification." In R.
Bendix & S.M. Lipset (Eds.), Class, status, and power: A reader in stratification.
New York: Free Press, 1953.
Peacock, A. The welfare society. London: Liberal Publication Department, 1960.
Pfeffer, J. Power in organisations. Marshfield, Massachusetts: Pitman, 1981.
Pinker, R. Theory, ideology and social policy. Sydney: Social Welfare Research Centre,
University of New South Wales, Report No. 26, 1982.
Popper, K.R. Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981.
Priorities Review Staff Interim report on goals and strategies. Canberra: AGPS, 1973. Parliamentary
Paper No. 26 of 1973.
Rawls, J. A theory ofjustice. London: Oxford University Press, 1972.
Rein, M. Social policy:Issuesof choice and change. New York: Random House, 1970.
Rolfe, B. In F.K.H. Maher, W. Waller, & D.P. Derham, Cases and materials on the legal
process (2nd ed.). Melbourne: Law Book Co.. 1971.
36
Schneider, M. "The quality of life in large American cities: Objective and subjective social
indicators." Social Indicators Research, 1975, I, 495-509.
Sim, R.A. Government grants to voluntary organisation. Ottowa: Voluntary Action Com-
mittee of the Canadian Association of Adult Education through the Citizenship
Branch of the Department of Secretary of State, undated.
SthVell, F.J.B. Equality. In P. Weller and J. North (Eds.), Labor: Directions for the Eighties.
Sydney: Novak, 19S0.
Tawney, R.H. Equality (revised edition). London: Allen & Unvwin, 1952.
Thomas Aquinas Summa Theologiae, London: Blackfriars in conjunction with Eyre and Spot-
tiswoode, 1964-1976.
Titmuss, R.M. Social policy: An introduction. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1974.
Townsend, P. Sociology and social policy. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1975.
Downloaded by The University of British Columbia Library At 20:37 30 January 2016 (PT)
37