Sellars 1969
Sellars 1969
Sellars 1969
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
International Phenomenological Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.
http://www.jstor.org
LANGUAGE AS THOUGHTAND AS COMMUNICATION
WILFRID
SELLARS
506
LANGUAGE ANDAS COMMUNICATION
AS THOUGHT 507
tions are intrinsically interesting and relevant to the general topic of this
paper, I shall not discuss them. For however the domain of norms and
standardsis to be stratifiedand botanized,the term 'rule' has acquired
over the years a technicaland genericsense in which it appliesto general
statementsconcerningthat which ought or ought not to be done or to
be the case, or to be permissibleor not permissible-. distinctionswhich
can be put in many differentways.
For our purposes,then, a rule is roughly a general 'ought' statement.
Such statementshave been traditionallydivided into hypotheticaland
categorical'oughts,'or, as it has often misleadinglybeen put, 'impera-
tives.' The distinctionbetween hypotheticaland categoricaloughts is an
importantone, though I believe that they are far more intimatelyrelated
than is ordinarilytaken to be the case.'
Hypotheticaloughts have the form "if one wants X, one ought to
do Y." They transpose a relation of implication between a state of
affairs X and a doing of Y into an implicationappropriateto practical
reasoning.In spite of their crucial importanceto a theory of normative
discourse,I shall have nothing to say about them, save by implication.
As far as anything I have so far said is concerned, a categorical
ought is simply one that is not, in the familiarKantian sense, a hypo-
thetical ought. I shall continue my division informallyby calling atten-
tion to the most familiar variety of general categorical oughts, those,
namely, of the form
If one is in C, one ought to do A.
Notice that althoughthis propositionis conditionalin form, it is not,
in the Kantiansense, a hypotheticalought; and it is as contrastedwith
the latter that, even though it is conditional,it is called categorical.By
applicationand the use of modus ponens one can derive conclusionsof
the form
S ought to do A
which not only are not hypotheticaloughts,but are categorical(non-iffy)
statements. Notice, by contrast, that from "If one wants X, one ought
to do A," togetherwith "S wants X" it is not correctto infer "S ought
to do A."
The importantfeature,for our purposes,of generalcategoricaloughts
of the above form is that for actual existenceto conformto these oughts
is a matter of the agents to which they apply doing A when they are
actually in the specified circumstanceC; and this, in turn, a matter of
1 For an exploration of this and related issues, see my Science and Metaphysics
(London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1968), Chapter VI (especially sections
XIV-XVII).
508 PHILOSOPHY
ANDPHENOMENOLOGICAL
RESEARCH
their setting about doing A when they believe that the circumstances
are C.
It follows that the 'subjects'to which these rules apply must have the
concepts of doing A and being in C. They must have, to use a current
tum of phrase, the appropriate'recognitionalcapacities.'Furthermore,
for the rule itself to play a role in bringing about the conformityof
'is' to 'ought,'the agentsin questionmust conceive of actions A as what
ought to be done in circumstancesC. This requiresthat they have the
concept of what it is for an action to be called for by a certain kind
of circumstance.
II
III
IV
say 'this is red.' In other words, they must alreadyhave the conceptual
frameworkof what it is to do somethingin a circumstance.
The distinctionbetweensaying and uttering,or being disposedto utter,
is diagnosticof the differencebetween the 'ought-to-do'and the 'ought-
to-be.' It might be objected that to use languagemeaningfullyis to say
ratherthan merely utter. But to merely utter is to parrot, and we need
a conceptwhich mediatesbetweenmerely utteringand saying.
Notice that the ought-to-dowhich correspondsto the above ought-
to-be, namely
One ought to bring it about (ceteris paribus)that people respond
to red objects in sunlight by uttering or being disposed to utter
'this is red.'
presupposesthat its agent subjectshave a conceptualframeworkwhich
includes the concepts of a red object, or sunlight, of uttering 'this is,
red,' of what it is to do or bring about something,and of what it is for
an action to be called for by a circumstance.
On the other hand, this ought-to-do does not presuppose that the
subjectsin which the dispositionto utter 'this is red' in the presenceof
red objectsin sunlightis to be broughtabout have any of these concepts.
But what of the objectionthat the subject-mattersubjectsof the ought-
to-be coincide with the agent subjectsof the ought-to-doand hence that
they too must have the concepts in question? The answer should be
obvious; the members of a linguistic community are first language
learnersand only potentially'people,'but subsequentlylanguageteachers,
possessed of the rich conceptualframeworkthis implies. They start out
by being the subject-mattersubjects of the ought-to-be'sand graduate
to the status of agent subjectsof the ought-to-do's.Linguisticought-to-
be's are translatedinto uniformitiesby training. As Wittgensteinhas
stressed, it is the linguistic community as 'a self-perpetuatingwhole
which is the minimumunit in terms of which conceptual activity can
be understood.
Furthermorethere are radicallydifferentkinds of linguisticought-to-
be's: not only word-objectought-to-be's(or, as I have called them else-
where, language entry transitions)4, but also the ought-to-be'sformu-
lated by formationand transformationrules.
4 "Some Reflections on Language Games," Philosophy of Science, Vol. 21, No. 3,
1954 (Reprinted as Chapter 11 in Science, Perception and Reality). It is important
to note that a full discussion would refer to may-be's (or permitteds) as well as
ought-to-be's - otherwise the concept of 'free' as opposed to 'tied' (stimulus bound)
linguistic activity, essential to any account of the functioning of a conceptual sys-
tem, would be left out of the picture.
LANGUAGEAS THOUGHTAND AS COMMUNICATION 513
VI
VII
But before I develop this point let me returnto the formulawe were
consideringbefore this digressionon the orientationtoward contexts of
communicationof the categoriesin terms of which common sense, lin-
guistics,and many philosophiesof languageapproachlinguisticbehavior.
The formulawas
x is a primaryexpressionof Jones' belief that-p
- x is a primarymanifestationof his settled dispositionto think
that-p (i.e. is a thinkingthat-p).
The implicationsof the term 'manifestation'(and, for that matter, of
'expression')led us in the directionof a logical behaviorismaccording
to which the relevant sense of 'thinking that-p' is 'thinking-out-loud
that-p.' Thus reinterpreted,the formula becomes
x is a primaryexpressionof Jones' belief that-p
x is a primary manifestationof Jones' settled disposition to
think-out-loudthat-p (i.e., is a thinkingout-loud that-p).
It will be rememberedthat the point of this behavioristicmove was
to assimilate the sense in which an episode is a primary expression
(implyingovertness)of a belief to the sense in which an episode of, for
example,a piece of litmus paper turningred is a manifestation(implying
overtness)of its dispositionto turn red.
It should be noted in passing that in the case of the litmus paper we
seem requiredto expand the characterizationof the dispositioninto
dispositionto turn red, if put in acid.
This generatesthe suspicionthat if we are to continuewith our strategy,
we must similarlyexpand our analysisof 'Jones believes that-p'into
Jones has a settled dispositionto think-out-loudthat-p, if.
If what?There many pitfalls here, though we can, perhaps,cover them
up temporarilywith somethinglike 'if the questionwhether-parises.'To
do so, however, would immediatelyconfront us with a more serious
LANGUAGE AS THOUGHT AND AS COMMUNICATION 519
VIII
On the other hand, if, however?we are to continuewith our original
strategy,we must resolutelyput aside the temptationto draw the kind
of distinctionbetween thoughtand its expressionwhich this formulation
implies, and continue with the intriguingidea that an uttering of 'p'
which is a primaryexpressionof a belief that-p is not merely an expres-
sion of a thinkingthat-p, but is itself a thinking,i.e., a thinking-out-loud
that-p.
Yet the preceding remarks do remind us that we must take into
account the fact that there is a sense of 'express'in which we can be
said to express our thoughts by using language for this purpose. Thus,
we express our thought that-p by saying 'p.' Can we sophisticate our
logical behaviorismto do justice to this fact?
Let us take a closer look at the words 'thought'and 'express.'First
the latter: it will be noticed that the referenceto observabilityimplied
by the term 'manifestation'in the context 'manifestationof the disposi-
tion to think that-p' was absorbed by the behavioristinto the phrase
which describesthe disposition. Thus, 'manifestationof the disposition
to think that-p,' became, in effect 'actualizationof the disposition to
think-out-loudthat-p.'
Thus the behaviorist'sformulabecomes, in effect,
x is a primaryexpressionof Jones' belief that-p
x is a manifestationof Jones' settled dispositionto think that-p
- x is an actualizationof Jones' settled dispositionto think-out-
loud that-p (i.e., x is a thinking-out-loudthat-p).
is
It only too clear that by pushingthis analysis of the context 'expres-
sion of belief' in this directionthe behavioristhas lost contact with the
idea that people express their beliefs by using language.The point can
be put simply - indeed bluntly - by saying that the concept of the
actualizationof a dispositionis not, as such, the concept of an action,
whereas expressingtheir beliefs is somethingpeople do.
520 RESEARCH
PHILOSOPHYAND PHENOMENOLOGICAL
The statement
Jones, by saying 'p', expressed his belief that-p
requires an interpretation of saying p as an action which is undertaken
by Jones in order to express (to someone) his belief that-p. If we suspect
that Jones is lying, we could equally describe him as saying "p", but
we would then go on to say something like
Jones, by saying 'p', pretended to believe that-p.
In neither case could Jones' saying 'p' be construed as a case of
thinking (even 'out loud') that-p. Thus were Jones speaking truthfully,
the thinking immediately involved, if any, would be of the sort described
by such formulas as
Jones thought that saying '...' would express his belief that-p
Jones intended to express his belief that-p by saying ...
or, in the case of lying
Jones intended to pretend to believe that-p by saying ....
Thus, granted the validity of the concept of thinking-out-loud, the
thinking-out-loud which, were it to occur, would be immediately in-
volved in the situation formulated by
Jones, by uttering '...,' expressed his belief that-p
would be not
Jones thought-out-loud that-p
but rather
Jones thought-out-loud that saying '...' would express his belief
that-p
or, where Jones is lying,
Jones thought-out-loud that he would pretend to believe that-p by
saying ....
Needless to say, the latter thinking-out-loud would be self-frustrating in
the presence of the audience he intends to deceive.
Ix
for want of a better term, the 'causal'sense. Both, as we shall see, are
to be distinguishedfrom a third sense illustratedby the context
Jones' utteranceof 'p' expressedthe thoughtthat-p
where the phrase 'the thought that-p' stands for an abstract entity, a
thoughtin Frege's sense (i.e., in one sense of this term, a 'proposition').
I shall call this the logical (or semantical)sense of 'express.'
Although my ultimateaim is to show how a logical behavioristmight
draw these distinctions,my initial move will be to discuss them in more
traditionalterms. I shall, therefore,constructa regimented(I dare not
say idealized) model accordingto which, in the course of learning to
speak a language,a child acquires the capacity to be in mental states
which are counterparts, in a sense to be analyzed, of the utterances
which come to belong to his repertoryof linguistic behavior.The idea
can be blocked out in two steps:
(a) A mental episode which is a thinking that-p is correlated,in
a certain linguistic community,with a piece of linguistic be-
havior which stands for (expressesin the logical or semantical
sense) the thought (proposition)that-p
(b) In the initial stages of the child's mastery of the language,
wheneverit has a thoughtthat-p, this thought is manifestedin
a purelyinvoluntaryway by the correspondingverbal behavior.
As our model for understandingthe sense in which the uttering of
'p' is the involuntarymanifestationof a thinkingthat-p, let us take the
instinctive connection between a pain and a piece of unlearnedpain
behavior.The fact that a connectionbetween states A and B of a child
is, in some sense, learned rather than instinctive,acquiredrather than
part of its initial equipment,by no means entails that either A or B is
under the child's voluntarycontrol. Not all learningto, do somethingin
a broad sense of 'do' consists in the addition of new behaviorsto the
stock of things that are under one's voluntarycontrol.
The key featureof our model is that the acquiredconnectionbetween
the mental act and the verbal behavior is not to be construedon the
action model of 'using the behavior to express one's thought.' Thus,
verbal behavioris not in our child's voluntarycontrol in that, although,
once the languageis learned,a necessaryand sufficientconditionof the
child saying 'p' is that it thinks that-p, the saying is the involuntary
manifestationof the thinking.
Notice that the model allows the child a rich vocabulary,including
the languageof intention and resolve as well as the languagein which
matters-of-factare stated. It also allows that the child learns to verbalize
522 RESEARCH
ANDPHENOMENOLOGICAL
PHILOSOPHY
X
We are now in a position to weaken our model and still make our
point. We need not suppose that the child remains a chatterbox.We
can suppose it to acquire the ability to keep its thoughts to itself in
the sense that it can effectivelytell itself to keep quiet, without ceasing
to think. We can grant that to this limited extent its verbal behavior
becomes under its voluntary control. When it is thinking without
speaking,we shall say that it is in a keeping-its-thoughts-to-itself frame
of mind. When not in this frame of mind, it thinks out loud. 8 Thus,
'Thinkingout loud' remainsthe primaryform in which thinkingoccurs.
The child'skeepingits thoughtsto itself can be comparedto the opening
of a general switch which breaks (or, to mix metaphors)short circuits
the initial acquiredconnectionbetweenthoughtsand verbalbehavior.
At this stage, the child has no conception of locutionary acts (e.g.
predicting,telling) as verbal behaviorwhich can be engaged in whether
or not one is thinkingthe correspondingthoughts.It has no concept of
saying "p" without thinkingthat-p.
On the other hand, it is perfectly capable of having concepts of
actions involvingthinkingout loud. Thus, wonderingout loud about the
weather; "I shall wonder out loud about the likelihood of rain." It is
importantto see that this by no means entails that there is such a thing
as an action of thinkingout loud that-p.Even in our more sophisticated
frameworkthere is no such thing as an action of thinkingthat-p, though
there is the action of deliberating(i.e., deliberatingout loud) what to
do. By granting,as we must, that it can conceive of actions consisting
of thinkings out loud, we admit a further sense in which its verbal
behavior (as thinkingsout loud) would be under its voluntarycontrol.
The child's verbal behaviorwould express its thoughts,but, to put it
paradoxically,the child could not express them.
Notice, also, that althoughits linguisticbehaviorwould be meaningful,
and we could say of each of its utteranceswhat, specificallyit meant, e.g.
Jones' utterancemeant 'it is raining,'
It would, on our assumptions,be incorrectto say, for example
Jones, by uttering '...' meant (to convey) ..
8 The concept of 'thinking out loud' appropriate to this model should not be
For the latter supposes that Jones has the concept of an action of
uttering '....' as a piece of linguistic behavior which could exist in-
dependentlyof its being the "spontaneousverbal expression" of the
correspondingmental act. There being no such action as bringingabout
a specific mental act, there could be no such thing as bringingabout a
thinkingout loud for the purposeof conveyinga thought.
In other words, just as our regimentingfiction enables us to draw a
distinctionbetween a sense in which a mode of verbal behavior can
express thoughtswithout being used to express them, so it enables us
to distinguishbetween the context
utterance of E (in L) means ---
and the sense of 'means,'closely related to 'intends,'which involves the
context
Jones, by uttering E, means (to convey) ...
The familiarsaw that words have meaningonly because people mean
things by them is harmlessif it tells us that words have no meaningin
abstractionfrom their involvementin the verbal behavior of language
users. It is downrightmistaken if it tells us that for an expressionto
have a certainsense or referenceis for it to be used by people to convey
the correspondingthought. Rather, we should say, it is because the
expressionhas a certainmeaningthat it can be effectivelyused to convey
the correspondingthought.
XI
Let us now return to the initial accounts we gave of belief and its
expression.The first thing to note is that if we were to reformulatethem
in termsof our model we would get somethinglike the followingschema
Jones believes that-p - Jones has a settled disposition to think
that-p, if the question occurs to him
whether-p,and, indeed, to think out loud
that-p, unless he is in a keeping-his-
thoughts-to-himselfframe of mind.9
We also get the followingformulaewith respectto 'expressionof belief':
x is a primaryactualizationof Jones'belief that-p-- x is a thinking
that-p (and, indeed, a thinkingout loud
that-p unless he is in a keeping-his-
thoughts-tohimself frame of mind.)
' The 'if the question occurs to him whether-p' condition can be taken to cover
all cases in which, where the alternatives 'p' and 'not p' are relevant to his course
of thought, he thinks that-p, even if the question whether-p is not actually raised.
524 PHILOSOPHY RESEARCH
ANDPHENOMENOLOGICAL
XII
But what will our logical behavioristsay to all this? Clearlyhe will be
unhappyabout our uncriticalacceptanceof mental acts as covert inner
episodes. What moves might he make? He may well accept our initial
formula
Jones believes that-p Jones has a settled disposition to think
that-p.
But he will emphasizethe 'settled,'which we have not yet done, and will
call attentionto the fact that it presumablycontrastswith something.It
is not obviouswhat the contrastingadjectiveshouldbe, but it, too, should
apply to dispositions.Let us, he suggests, try 'proximate,'drawingon
the contrastbetween 'settled'and 'nearthe surface.'Another appropriate
contrastwould be providedby 'short term.'
Objects, as is well known, can have causal propertieswhich are not
so to speak, immediatelyavailable. Thus iron attractsfilings, if it has
been treated in a certain way. A proximatedispositioncan roughly be
characterizedas one which is immediatelyavailable.
Our logical behaviorist,consequently,suggeststhat
Jones believes that-p = Jones has the settled dispositionto have
short term, proximate dispositions to
think-out-loud that-p, if the question
whether-parises, and he is in a thinking-
out-loud frame of mind.
In other words, our logical behavioristconstruesthe contrastbetween
fleeting thought episodes and settled beliefs as falling within the broad
categoryof dispositions,and hence construesthe 'covertness'of thoughts
as simply a special case of the covertnessof dispositions.Flammability,
he remindsus, is not a covert flame.
Many featuresof our previousdiscussioncan be fitted into this frame-
work, once its distinctivecharacteris understood.Thus, the behaviorist
substitutesfor the previous account of the child's candid and spontane-
ous verbalbehavioras the expression(in the 'causal'sense) of classically
conceivedepisodesof thought, an account accordingto which a
thinking-out-loudthat-p
is simply an 'actualization'of a
LANGUAGE
AS THOUGHT
ANDAS COMMUNICATION 525
XIII
UNIVERSITYOF PITTSBURGH.
knowing as contrasted with the order of being. As an analogy, notice that con-
cepts pertaining to things as perceived by the senses are prior in the order of
knowing to concepts of micro-physicalparticles, whereas, (for the Scientific Realist)
micro-physical particles are prior in the order of being to objects as perceived by
the senses.