Ethics-Reviewer (1)
Ethics-Reviewer (1)
Ethics-Reviewer (1)
Critical Morality
When we talk about morality in this course, we will
be referring to moral standards that are not rooted in
widespread endorsement, but rather are independent of
conventional morality and can be used to critically
evaluate its merits.
It’s possible, of course, that conventional morality is
all there is. But this would be a very surprising discovery.
Most of us assume, as I will do, that the popularity of a
moral view is not a guarantee of its truth. We could be
wrong on this point, but until we have a chance to consider
the matter in detail, I think it best to assume that
conventional morality can sometimes be mistaken. If so,
then there may be some independent, critical morality that
(1) does not have its origin in social agreements;
(2) is untainted by mistaken beliefs, irrationality, or popular
prejudices; and
(3) can serve as the true standard for determining when
conventional morality has got it right and when it has fallen
into error.
That is the morality whose nature we are going to
explore in this course.
Moral Reasoning
When we feel strongly about an issue, it is tempting
to assume that we just know what the truth is, without
even having to consider arguments on the other side.
Unfortunately, however, we cannot rely on our feelings, no
matter how powerful they may be. Our feelings may be
irrational; they may be nothing but the by-products of
prejudice, selfishness, or cultural conditioning.
Thus, if we want to discover the truth, we must let
our feelings be guided as much as possible by reason.
This is the essence of morality. The morally right thing to
do is always the thing best supported by the arguments.
Of course, not every reason that may be advanced is a
good reason. There are bad arguments as well as good
ones, and much of the skill of moral thinking consists in
discerning the difference.
The first thing is to get one’s facts straight. The facts
exist independently of our wishes, and responsible moral
thinking begins when we try to see things as they are.
Next, we can bring moral principles into play. In our
three examples, a number of principles were involved: that
we should not “use” people; that we should not kill one
person to save another; that we should do what will benefit
the people affected by our actions; that every life is
sacred; and that it is wrong to discriminate against the
handicapped. Most moral arguments consist of principles
being applied to particular cases, and so we must ask
whether the principles are justified and whether they are
being applied correctly.
The role application of routine methods is never a
satisfactory substitute for critical thinking, in any area.
Morality is no exception.