Some Basic Concepts of Figurational Sociology

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 27

Dunning, Eric, and Jason Hughes. "Some Basic Concepts of Figurational Sociology.

" Norbert
Elias and Modern Sociology: Knowledge, Interdependence, Power, Process. London:
Bloomsbury Academic, 2013. 50–75. Bloomsbury Collections. Web. 31 Mar. 2021. <http://
dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781780933405.ch-002>.

Downloaded from Bloomsbury Collections, www.bloomsburycollections.com, 31 March 2021,


04:45 UTC.

Copyright © Eric Dunning and Jason Hughes 2013. You may share this work for non-commercial
purposes only, provided you give attribution to the copyright holder and the publisher.
2
Some Basic Concepts of
Figurational Sociology

E lias never considered his position to be ‘unique’. He did, however, consider it


to be distinctive. Indeed, he fought against a series of dominant intellectual
currents to champion what was sometimes seen to be an outmoded approach
by his contemporaries. It was one of Elias’s hopes that, in the course of time,
the central tenets of his work would come to be accepted simply as core parts
of sociology. He was anticipating in this connection – and sought to contribute
to – an end to the ‘paradigm wars’ that we have described in earlier sections, or
at least a transformation of them in a more constructive direction.
The main distinctive features of figurational sociology are its emphasis
on processes and relations. However, it is radically processual and radically
relational in character; that is, it is processual and relational at its roots or core.
The stress of Elias’s sociology is centrally upon the explanatory importance of
time. It correspondingly emphasises the importance of long-term as opposed to
short-term processes, although Elias did not neglect the latter.
When he was President of the American Sociological Association in
the 1960s, the late George Homans devoted a Presidential Address to the
theme of ‘bringing the people back in’ (Homans 1961). He was advocating
a sociology that would be less statistical/mathematical than what was then
becoming dominant in the United States, a sociology in which it is never
forgotten that it is people who act, occupy statuses, perform roles and form
social structures. Like Homans, Elias, too, sought to lay the foundations for
a ‘scientific’ sociology that did not simply involve the emulation of the more
successful natural sciences but which was attuned, on the one hand, to those
properties of the subject that it shares with other sciences; and on the other,
to the balance of similarities and differences between humans, their societies
and the rest of the known or empirically experienced world. It is an approach
in which far greater stress is placed on what human beings are and how they
came to be as they are than has conventionally been the case with sociology
at least since the end of the Second World War. Dunning vividly remembers
how, as a student, he was expected by Elias to have some understanding
of human anatomy and physiology, and of biological evolution as well as
human history and social development. Further to this, in his sociology, Elias
eschewed the use of the more popular mechanical and organic analogies for
the purpose of sociological concept-formation and stressed, instead, models

50
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 51

taken from social life itself, for example, dances, games and the personal
pronouns.
At the core of Elias’s work is a stress on the observable fact that, like the
universe at large, each human individual is a process: that is, we are born,
mature and die – a set of facts which sound banal until it is remembered that
the sociology of birth, death, and dying are marginal specialisms in our subject.
Elias wrote of Humana Conditio, ‘the human condition’ (Elias 1985), in this
connection. Our difficulties in coming to grips with the processual character of
everything, he said, are compounded by our fears and hesitations regarding our
mortality. Sociologists, he argued, need to develop a vocabulary which avoids
the tendency to reduce processes to steady states (Zustandsreduktion). Such a
tendency is characteristic of Western languages. As he expressed it:

Our languages are constructed in such a way that we can often only express
constant movement or constant change in ways which imply that it has the
character of an isolated object at rest, and then, almost as an afterthought, adding
a verb which expresses the fact that the thing with this character is now changing.
For example, standing by a river we see the perpetual flowing of the water. But to
grasp it conceptually, and to communicate it to others, we do not think and say,
‘look at the perpetual flowing of the water’; we say, ‘look how fast the river is
flowing’. We say, ‘The wind is blowing’, as if the wind were actually a thing at rest
which, at a given point in time, begins to move and blow. We speak as if the wind
were separate from its blowing, as if a wind could exist which did not blow. …
This reduction of processes to static conditions, we shall call ‘process-reduction’
for short … (Elias 2012b: 106–107).

It was in order to capture this idea of process that Elias insisted that the
conventional sociological vocabulary which involves talking, for example, of
‘social structure and social change’, a formulation which implies that non-
changing social structures could exist, should be abandoned and, even though
they often sound ugly in English, replaced by process terms such as ‘socialisation’,
‘civilisation’, ‘industrialisation’, ‘urbanisation’, ‘democratisation’, ‘courtisation’,
and ‘sportisation’.
According to Elias, humans are also bound to others by fluid ties of
interdependence which are a biosocial and not simply a social or learned fact
of life. That is, we have a partly inborn, partly socially instilled tendency to
seek the company of others, for example for sexual purposes, but also as an
enjoyable ‘end-in-itself’. Sociability is also important for human survival. The
babyhood and infancy of humans last a relatively long time, and babies and
infants cannot survive on their own. They have to bond with others and others
with them. As Winnicott, the psychoanalyst famously put it: ‘There is no such
thing as a baby, there is a baby and someone’ (Winnicott 1965). Humans also
have a mobile facial musculature, a biological fact which is a precondition
for smiling, another crucial inborn feature at the emotional level of human
bonding.33 It plays an important part in the bonding of parents and their
52 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY

newborn babies. Laughter is another uniquely human feature which can play an
important bonding role. Although most people tend to take it for granted, there
is an occupational group in modern societies – comedians – who specialise in
making other people laugh, and there is now a substantial body of sociological
research on this profession and on comedy itself (see, for example, the work
of Lockyer and Pickering (2006); and Kuipers (2006)). And, of course, just as,
among adolescents and adults, smiling can be used to deceive people, so laughter
can be used to ridicule other individuals and groups. Both are sometimes used
in ‘legal’ and ‘illegal’ murders. Examples include public executions of the kind
that used to be common in European and other countries.

Human figurations

Another way of expressing the radical interdependence of humans would be


to say that we form dynamic ‘figurations’ with one another. Elias developed
the concept of ‘figuration’ as an alternative to, but by no means the equivalent
of, terms such as structure, society, and system. The notion is centrally
related to a homines aperti view of humans – that human beings can only
be properly understood as pluralities, and not as isolated individual ‘actors’
who variously ‘interact’ with other ‘individuals’, ‘groups’, ‘organisations’, or
‘social institutions’. Elias argued that homo clausus formulations – which
stem from an understanding of humans as ‘closed off’ ‘essences of uniqueness’
that ‘stand in relation to’ ‘society’ – can be understood as not simply in
themselves conceptually problematic, but as reflective of a particular moulding
of human psychic structures that emerges in tandem with particular social
processes, notably those to which he referred as ‘civilising processes’. Elias’s
aim in coining the term figuration, and in his work more generally, was to
counter what has become to people in societies such as ours a socially intuitive
reification: that we are individuals closed off from one another and from other
‘social formations’. Moreover, Elias’s term at its core is intended as a counter
to the notion that ‘social agencies’, ‘institutions’, and ‘society’ are entities that
exist somehow separately from the people who comprise them. That is, the
concept of figurations is predicated upon an understanding of the fundamental
interdependence of human beings, first in their biology, and then through
their socially developed reciprocal needs (Elias 2012a: 525). Such human
interdependencies comprise the nexuses of figurations: shifting networks of
people with fluctuating, asymmetrical power balances. Sociologically, the
concept directs attention towards shifting patterns, regularities, directions of
change, tendencies and counter-tendencies, in webs of human relationships that
are always changing over time. To think of the concept in relation to a more
conventional sociological lexicon, the term invokes ‘the individual’, ‘agency’,
‘society’, ‘social change’, ‘power’, and ‘structure’ simultaneously, but purposely
without being reducible to any of these components. Again, effectively built-in
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 53

to the concept of figurations is the core idea that notions such as ‘the individual’
as an isolated abstraction, or ‘agency’ as some-thing that is ‘held’ or ‘exercised’
by ‘the individual’ or ‘the state’ are in themselves misleading terms which, to
varying degrees, involve forms of conceptual reductionism and reification.
A guiding analogy for the concept of figurations is that of dance. Viewing
dancers on a dance-floor as a mobile figuration of interdependent people is
useful because it refers to ‘real-life’ social processes, and not abstract (and
highly problematic) comparisons with, for instance, biological organisms or
synthetic mechanisms. However, equally, in invoking dance as an analogy, Elias
also wanted us, by extension, to envisage families, cities, nation states, and even
feudal, capitalist, and communist societies, all as figurations, but with differing
degrees of length and complexity. We can think of recognisable patterns emerging
from such shifting figurations, just as we might, for example, be able to discern
the ‘tango’, or the ‘waltz’, or simply ‘dance in general’ as distinct, say, from
‘walking’. However, Elias argues, it is important not to conceive of ‘dance’ as a
structure or ‘thing’ which is somehow ‘outside’ of ‘the individual’ (2012a: 525).
While different people can dance the same dance figuration, there is no dance
as such without dancers. Dance figurations, like any social figuration, are to a
degree independent of the specific individuals forming them at any particular
time, but are not independent of individuals as such. Neither, Elias proposed,
are dances, or by extension figurations, mere abstracted mental constructions
produced from the observation of individuals considered in isolation from one
another. While figurations can persist even after the individuals who comprised
them at one time died and became replaced, they only exist through the on-
going participation of constituent members.
The analogy of dance, and indeed the concept of ‘figurations’, may appear
simple at first sight, perhaps common-sensical, but the insights they yield are
of great conceptual significance. In this concept – which, we shall show, must
be understood in relation to the others he offers – Elias provides a means of
circumventing, not so much resolving, the ‘agency-structure dilemma’. The
dilemma centres on the difficulties attendant upon developing formulations of
the relationship between individuals and the societies they form which avoid
the trap of ‘reductionism’ to ‘individuals’ and ‘agency’ on the one hand, and the
‘reification’ of ‘society’ and ‘structure’, on the other, whilst simultaneously doing
justice to both ‘the individual’ and ‘the social’ sides of the equation. Sociologists
have been embroiled in the agency-structure/individual-society conundrum
since the inception of their subject when it separated from philosophy in the
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. Another name for the conundrum/dilemma
is the ‘nominalism’ versus ‘realism’ controversy (Popper 1957). Emile Durkheim
(1895) who saw sociology as the study of ‘social facts’ was a sociological realist
who in some formulations came close to reifying social phenomena by playing
down, perhaps even failing to see, that they are simultaneously individual. Max
Weber who saw sociology as the study of ‘social action’ was a sociological
nominalist because he denied the reality to which sociological constructs such
54 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY

as ‘state’ and ‘society’ correspond and refer (Gerth and Mills 1970). For Weber,
they are ultimately nothing more than names.
It is important to recognise that Elias only came to develop his concepts,
theories and methods gradually over time. They did not flow automatically or
quickly from his pen. In his 1921 essay, ‘On Seeing in Nature’, for example, in
which he discussed the balance of similarities and differences between ‘the arts’
and ‘the sciences’, he used the term ‘laws’ to express the discoveries unearthed
by practitioners of the latter. Somewhat later, in his plan for his later abandoned
Habilitationsschrift (post-doctoral thesis) which was to have been supervised
by Alfred Weber (Collected Works (2006a), Vol. 1: 111–122) and likewise in
his 1929 essay on ‘The Sociology of German Anti-Semitism’ (2006a: 78–80), he
made explanatory use of the metaphor of ‘constellations’ to express the idea of
structure but later abandoned it on account of its astronomical connotations.
It was only when working in the 1960s on a joint article with Eric Dunning,
‘Dynamics of Sport Groups with Special Reference to Football’ (Elias and
Dunning 1966), that Elias came to prefer the concept of ‘configurations’ because
of its combination of structural and processual connotations.34
It soon became clear, however, that Elias had a considerably more complex
set of concepts forming in his mind. He used the concept of ‘law-like regularities’
as explanatory of the relatively simple, recurring properties of the phenomenal
universe such as light and gravity with which physicists and chemists have been
centrally concerned. However, he did not think of them as necessarily universal
and eternal as philosophers such as Popper seem to have done. Moreover, he
spoke of the configurational dynamics of emergent organic structures such as
DNA where the helix has to be double in order to result in genetic inheritance.
‘Figurational dynamics’ was the term he reserved for the highly complex and
dynamic structures and processes that human societies involve, and that are
the objects/subjects of sociological research. Elias expressed this latter point
as follows:

It is important … to distinguish clearly the integration and organisation of


sub-units in formations such as a cell or an organism from the integration and
organisation of human beings in society. For this reason I have introduced the
concept of the figuration of human beings, to designate the unique mode of
organisation and integration of human individuals in societies. In this way, a
clear distinction can be drawn between the configuration of large models in a cell
and the manifold figurations of human beings that we call groups or societies.
But what is paramount for me here are the differences in the things themselves.
For these, conceptual symbols which are as reality-congruent as possible must be
found. (Elias 2009c: 199, n12)

Earlier, Elias had sought to represent diagrammatically what he called ‘some


of the stages of integration’ in the following way.
Figure 2.1 shows in diagrammatic form how Elias sought to develop a
conceptual vocabulary which was attuned to the considerably higher levels of
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 55

Most highly differentiated and integrated organisms


(human) with multi-level neural centralisation, uniquely
high learning capacity, with inter-generational knowledge
transmission, with a biological potential for forming permanent
social units which, however, have no biologically predetermined
structure, are, therefore, not species specific and can change in
accordance with learning processes and other external or
internal levers of change.

from these

More highly differentiated and integrated organisms with


multi-level neural centralisation, higher though still very
limited learning capacity, forming transient or permanent
social units with species specific structure.

from these

More differentiated and more closely integrated organisms


with one or two levels of neural centralisation and some
learning capacity forming loosely integrated mostly
impermanent social units with species-specific structure.

from these

Multi-cellular organisms loosely integrated without or with


rudimentary neural or hormone centralisation, no or little
learning capacity, no or loosely integrated social units.

from unicellar organisms

unicellar organisms

from large molecules

large molecules

from small molecules

small molecules

from atoms

atoms

from sub-atomic particles


Figure 2.1 Some of the stages of integration as they can be presented today
56 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY

complexity pertaining to human societies: in his terms – the levels of integration


involved within the sphere of human figurations. We have already touched upon
some of the important ways in which Elias’s concept of figurations, in turn,
also needs to be understood in tandem with the concepts of interdependence,
homines aperti and homo clausus. It is thus pertinent now to explore these
concepts in more depth for it is precisely this de-centring and re-orientation of
the human self-image that is fundamental to Elias’s sociological approach, and
which marks his distinctive break from a pervasive current of post-Renaissance/
Enlightenment thinking. To commence this undertaking, it is necessary once
again first to return to the inter-related dilemma of structure versus agency.

Homo clausus and homines aperti:


Between the Scylla and Charybdis

In an interview with a journalist from Woman’s Own magazine in 1987, former


British Prime Minister, Margaret Thatcher, (in)famously said: ‘There is no such
thing as society… there are individual men and women and there are families’.
The phrase later became celebrated as something of a neo-liberal mantra.
Of course, the statement is entirely and inherently nonsensical. To use the
term ‘families’ is already to posit the existence of an entity which is supra-
individual. That is, implicit in what Mrs Thatcher said is the idea that a society
consists of families and is, hence, more than the sum of its individual members.
Her mentor in this mistaken way of thinking seems to have been the late
Sir Keith Joseph – one of the home secretaries during her reign – and he, in
his turn, seems to have got his understanding from reading the philosophers
Hayek (1944) and Popper (1957), both of them advocates of varieties of
sociological nominalism. Among other things, what this example shows is that
the agency-structure/individual-society conundrum is not just a dry-as-dust
academic issue but one with political implications.
In contrast to sociological nominalism, many, if not most of whose advocates
come from the political right, the advocates of sociological realism tend,
though again not always, to come from the political left. That is because, while
people on the right are liable to advocate varieties of relatively unregulated
entrepreneurship, rugged individualism, and unfettered markets, people on the
left are more likely to champion government responsibility, state-intervention,
and control, expressed through ideas such as ‘no man is an island’ and ‘we
are all responsible for one another’. An exception in this regard is provided
by German National Socialism (‘Nazism’) with its extreme, völkisch racism,
its idea of society (‘the nation’, ‘the people’ (das Volk)) as an entity which is
somehow ‘superorganic’, and its stress on the subordination of individuals to
‘the state’.
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 57

Much more typical of sociological realism is the ‘structural Marxism’ of


Louis Althusser, a variant of Marxism from which ‘the human being as a
creative person is almost entirely absent …’ (Layder 1994: 41). People are
seen from this standpoint as mere ‘carriers’ (Träger) of beliefs and structures
which serve to support the status quo and bolster the power of the ruling class.
It is a position which contrasts markedly with Marx’s own, as can be seen
from his famous statement that: ‘Men make their own history, but they do not
make it just as they please; they do not make it under circumstances chosen
by themselves, but under circumstances directly found, given and transmitted
from the past’ (Marx in Marx and Engels 1942, vol. 2: 315). As we shall show,
the balance between voluntarism and determinism expressed in this passage is
close to Elias’s position.
According to Elias, it is one of the chief tasks of sociologists to steer the
sociological ship between the ‘Scylla’ of reification and determinism on the
one hand, and the ‘Charybdis’ of individualistic reductionism and voluntarism
on the other. What this means is that he urged them to use a combination of
theory-based reasoning and empirical observation in which neither is allowed
to become dominant. The idea is to build-up a picture of humans and their
social worlds which is as congruent as possible with how individuals and
their societies ‘really’ are. In short, based on his own researches, Elias was
recommending a conceptualisation in which societies are neither conceived as
wholly determining ‘things’ (reification), nor reduced to unstructured congeries
of freely-choosing individuals (reductionism, individualism, voluntarism).
Elias expressed his view of the ‘individual–society’ problem thus:

Our conventional tools for thinking and speaking are to a considerable degree
constructed as if everything external to the single person were an object, moreover
an object usually in a state of rest. Concepts like ‘family’ or ‘school’ plainly refer to
networks of people. But the conventional way in which we form our … concepts
makes it appear as if the groupings formed by humans were pieces of matter –
objects of the same kind as rocks, trees or houses. This reifying character of the
conventional means of speaking and thinking about groups of interdependent
people – groups to which one perhaps belongs oneself – appears not least in the
concept of society and the way in which one thinks about it. One says that ‘society’
is the ‘object’ which sociologists research. But this reifying mode of expression
contributes not a little to the difficulties encountered in understanding what
sociology is all about. (Elias 1970: 9–10. Authors’ translation from the German)

Conventional modes of thinking and speaking, especially in the relatively


‘civilised’ urban-industrial societies of the modern era, says Elias, encourage
the impression that ‘society’ is made up of ‘structures’ that are external to
individuals, and that individuals are at one and the same time surrounded by
‘society’ yet separated from ‘it’ by an invisible wall. This common-sense model
which dominates people’s experience of their relationship to ‘society’ today is,
according to Elias, ‘naïvely egocentric’. Such a model is illustrated in Figure 2.2.
58 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY

State

Industry

School

Family

SOCIETY ME
Ego

Figure 2.2 Basic pattern of the egocentric view of society

Figure 2.2 depicts what Elias called the homo clausus image of humans and
their societies. In it, people experience themselves as isolated individuals (‘egos’)
or ‘I’s who are walled off from others, separated from them as if by an invisible
barrier, while at the same time experiencing the institutions that they form such
as families, schools, economies, and states and which are nothing more than
differently organised groups of individuals, as ‘objects’ or ‘compelling forces’
that are more, as it is sometimes metaphysically put, than ‘the sum of their
individual parts’. A more appropriate image, said Elias, is provided by Figure 2.3.
This depicts a figuration of homines aperti, ‘open people’ who, ‘through their
basic dispositions and inclinations, are directed towards and linked with each
other in the most diverse ways’ (Elias 1978: 14–15). According to Elias ‘people
make up webs of interdependence or figurations of many kinds … They are
characterised by power balances of many sorts …’ (2012b: 10).
The first thing worthy of note in this connection is that Elias’s understanding
of the concept of interdependence is not the same as Durkheim’s in
The Division of Labour (1964). The French classical sociologist distinguished
between ‘bonds of similitude’ based on likeness and ‘bonds of interdependence’
based on the division of labour. But, for Elias, ‘bonds of similitude’ involve
forms of interdependence, too, for example, the bonds between husbands and
wives, parents and children, and many more. That is, interdependence is far
from being simply an ‘economic’ phenomenon. Dunning vividly remembers
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 59

Individual
(‘Ego’, ‘I’)

Symbol for a more


or less unstable
balance of power

Open (unattached)
valencies

Figure 2.3 A figuration of interdependent individuals

driving Elias from Leicester to London along the M1 motorway in the 1960s
and asking: ‘Norbert, this is a form of interdependence in your understanding
of the term, isn’t it? All of us drivers are dependent on the others observing the
rules of the road and not losing self-control. It’s surely a kind of life and death
interdependence’. Elias replied: ‘Yes it is, Eric my dear. In fact, in The Civilising
Process, you will remember, I contrast a medieval road where the main danger
was from wild animals or deliberate attack from other humans and a modern
road where the principal danger is that of other people losing their self-control’
(see Elias 2012a: 406–7).
American sociologist Thomas J. Scheff has written on this issue as follows:
In What is Sociology? (1978; 2012b) and Involvement and Detachment (1987a;
2007a), Elias implicitly uses interdependence to contrast it with two different types
of relationship: ‘independence’, or a relationship characterized by detachment and
‘dependence’, a relationship so over-involved as to be suffocating to one or both
parties. This more specific use of interdependence is also implied in his discussion
of the ‘I-we’ balance in the preface to Involvement and Detachment (1987a;
2007a). In this passage a balanced I-we relationship would seem to correspond to
interdependence. A relationship that did not involve a balance between the ‘I’ and
the ‘we’ would not be interdependent; if one or both parties maintained an ‘I-self’,
the relationship would be one of independence; if one or both parties maintained
a ‘we-self’, the relationship would be one of dependence … [Elias] is not
always consistent in his usage of the term ‘interdependence’, however. Although
I have not found the reference, I have been told that Elias has written that war
between two nations can involve interdependence (personal communication from
Jon Fletcher)… (Scheff in Salumets 2001: 103)

Scheff is a prominent advocate of Elias’s work, and one of the few American
scholars to have engaged with his ideas in a sustained manner. However, his
60 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY

exposition of Elias above serves to highlight some of the principal sources of


his misunderstanding of Elias’s concept of interdependence. It is first important
to note that, pace Scheff, Elias thought and wrote in terms of continua and
balances or scales, not separate and discrete types of relationships. For
Elias, as we saw earlier, humans are always and everywhere involved from
birth to death in bonds of interdependence. Even though the bonds may
vary, involvement in them – even of supposedly marginal exceptions such as
hermits – is a constant. In fact, the isolation of hermits is illusory. Even they
forage for food in neighbouring human settlements and are sometimes supported
by them. They also tend to be affectively bonded to the people with whom they
were once close. Seen in these terms, ‘independence’ and ‘dependence’ are not
discrete types of relationships but positions towards polar ends of a continuum
or scale. Furthermore, in Elias’s usage, the term ‘balance’ has been shorn of all
harmonistic value-conceptions. Scheff’s misconstrual of the latter is perhaps
given clearest expression in what he writes about interdependence and war
(see, once again, the quotation above in which he refers to the work of
Jonathan Fletcher). The passage Fletcher was referring to is in What Is
Sociology? where Elias wrote:
Fierce antagonists … perform a function for each other, because the
interdependence of human beings due to their hostility is no less a functional
relationship than that due to their position as friends, allies, and specialists
bonded to each other through the division of labour. Their function for each
other is in the last resort based on the compulsion they exert over each other by
reason of their interdependence. (Elias 2012b: 72)

Part of the source of Scheff’s and others’ misunderstanding of Elias on this


issue appears, once again, to relate to Elias’s terminology. The term ‘function’
has, particularly in relation to its use within major strands of American
functionalism, long had ‘consensus’ connotations. However, as can be clearly
observed in the passage above, Elias’s usage of the term expressly avoided any
such connotations, and indeed, was used in this instance to refer specifically to
conflict-driven relationships. Indeed, such uses of the concept form part of Elias’s
attempt to rescue it in a way which was common to Weimar Germany sociologists
such as Mannheim (we shall return to this theme shortly). Furthermore,
Scheff’s exposition also betrays another principal source of misunderstanding
of the concept of ‘interdependence’, namely, the idea that the concept refers
solely or mainly to the ‘division of labour’. This, as we have said, is a common
misconception.
There is a tendency in complex ‘modern’ societies, the ‘urban-industrial-
nation-states’ which came to dominate the world in the eighteenth, nineteenth,
and twentieth centuries, to think of ‘the economy’ as the central determining
‘factor’ in social life. Although it finds its clearest expression in some of the
key variants of Marxism, such a tendency is by no means solely restricted to
Marxist thinking. This is not the place for a full-scale investigation into why
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 61

‘economistic’ thinking has become prominent – a process which also finds


clear expression in the taken-for-granted assumption that ‘economics’ is the
leading, most necessary social science. It must be enough in the present context
simply to suggest that what one might call the ‘economisation of thinking’
is probably connected, at least in part, with what Elias called ‘functional
democratisation’, a process generated, as we shall see in Chapter 3, by the
growing ‘pressures from below’ which ruling groups experience as societies
develop beyond a given level of structural complexity. Such pressures are
reinforced by the egalitarian ideologies which develop in these contexts and
which involve the emergence and articulation of ideas such as ‘the people’,
‘the commonwealth’ and ‘the economy’; the last term derived from oikos,
the Greek for ‘household’. In the dynastic states which preceded the nation
states of modern Europe, ‘the economy’ was, in effect, coterminous with the
household of the monarch. ‘The economy’, however, is best conceptualised,
not as some separate ‘part’ of social life but, in complex ‘modern’ societies
as people working – a term which covers manufacturing, trading, organising,
administering, teaching, maintaining, cleaning and entertaining, and so
forth – in order to earn money. This is reinforced, according to Elias, by the
growing ‘monetarisation’ of social relations and the fact that the industrial,
commercial, and governing bourgeoisie are ‘the first working ruling class’ in
history. Earlier rulers had been warriors, priests, landowners, courtiers or
members of a leisured elite.
It is the hegemony of ‘economic reductionism’ or ‘economistic thinking’
that lies at the heart of confusing the concept of division of labour with that
of bonds of interdependence. The latter concept, as we have said, applies to
the compulsions which make enemies in a war interdependent, as well as
people driving on a motorway. It also applies to the compulsions operative
on parents and children, masters and slaves, employers and employed,
doctors and patients, rulers and ruled. Elias drew attention, in addition,
to the impersonal bonds which form in conjunction with the emergence
of larger social units and in which people become emotionally bound
together through the medium of such symbols as coats of arms, flags and
national anthems. ‘What’, he asked, ‘are the common features of the various
figurations which at different stages of development have bound individuals
to them by this type of predominating emotional bond?’ (Elias 2012b: 133).
Earlier, he had posed the question: ‘… why do emotional bonds to state-
societies – which nowadays are nation-states – take priority over bonds to
other figurations?’ (2012b: 133). In other words, why are people expected
to sacrifice their lives at the behest of the rulers of their nation-states? Why,
in so many cases, do they do so willingly? Why do they die defending their
flags? Why have some people, for example, Josef and Magda Goebbels in
Germany in 1945, sacrificed themselves and their children for the abstract
ideal of their beleaguered and defeated Volk and its equally beleaguered
62 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY

and defeated Führer? Why did people in the past sacrifice themselves for
their tribe or their religion, and why are some members of militant religious
groups today willing to sacrifice themselves for their beliefs? Elias began to
answer these questions as follows:

First of all, these units all seem to have exercised comparatively strict control over
the use of physical violence in relationships between their members. At the same
time, they have allowed, and often encouraged, their members to use physical
violence against non-members. To date, sociology has lacked any clear conception
of the common features of this type of solidaristic grouping at different levels of
social development. Its function is obvious: it knits people together for common
purposes – the common defence of their lives, the survival of their group in the
face of attacks by other groups and, for a variety of reasons, attacks in common on
other groups. Thus the primary function of such an alliance is either physically to
wipe out other people or to protect its own members from being physically wiped
out. Since the potential of such units for attack is inseparable from their potential
for defence, they may be called ‘attack-and-defence units’ or ‘survival units’.
At the present stage of social development, they take the form of nation-states.
In the future they may be amalgamations of several former nation states. In the
past they were represented by city-states or the inhabitants of a stronghold. Size
and structure vary: the function remains the same. At every stage of development,
wherever people have been bound and integrated into units for attack and defence,
this bond has been stressed above all others. This survival function, involving the
use of physical force against others, creates interdependence of a particular kind.
It plays a part in the figurations people form, perhaps no greater but also no more
negligible than ‘occupational’ bonds. Although it cannot be reduced to ‘economic’
functions, neither is it separable from them. (Elias 2012b: 133–4)

According to Elias, the division of humanity into ‘survival units’


(see Kaspersen and Gabriel (2008)) will probably last until we have become
effectively integrated into one such unit: humankind as a whole. It is entirely
possible, of course, that such a stage will never be reached or that, after being
once formed, such a unit could disintegrate. It is also worth noting, once
again, that whilst in general agreeing with and, indeed, taking part in the
attacks on functionalism in the 1960s and 1970s, Elias insisted on retaining a
concept of functions rather than altogether abandoning it. In his case, unlike
that of Parsons, it was a non-harmonistic concept, closely tied up with Elias’s
concept of power and equally attuned to harmony and disharmony, order and
disorder, integration and disintegration, unity and conflict. In short, for Elias,
‘function’ was a technical and empirically attuned concept that did not contain
an axiomatic presupposition of any particular type of figurational dynamic,
whether harmonious or otherwise. The same can be said for Elias’s concept of
‘social order’. According to Elias:

The distinction between ‘order’ and ‘disorder’, so significant for the people
involved, is sociologically speaking without significance. Among men, as in
nature, no absolute chaos is possible … [T]he word ‘order’ is not being used
[here] in the sense in which it is used when people speak of ‘law and order’ or, in
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 63

adjectival form, of an ‘orderly’ as opposed to a ‘disorderly’ person. One is talking


about an order in the same sense that one talks of a natural order, in which decay
and destruction as structured processes have their place alongside growth and
synthesis, death and disintegration alongside birth and integration. For the people
involved, these manifestations seem, with good cause, to be contradictory and
irreconcilable. As objects of study, they are indivisible and of equal importance.
(Elias 2012b: 70–71)

According to Elias, furthermore, power is a central aspect of all forms of ‘social


order’, a ‘social universal’, independently, firstly, of whether it is recognised as
such by the people involved, and secondly, of whether these people experience
it as ‘good’ or ‘bad’. Thus, once again, Elias’s concept of power is fundamentally
inter-related with his other key conceptual innovations, in particular, as we have
shown, with the concepts of interdependence and figurations. It is also closely
related to, and finds clear expression within, Elias’s theorisation of ‘established-
outsider’ figurations. It is to this topic we shall now turn as part of our more
general exposition of Elias’s conceptualisation of power.

Established-outsider figurations and Elias’s theory of power

In a study that he carried out in the late 1950s and early 1960s with John
Scotson entitled The Established and the Outsiders (1994 (1965)), Elias
centrally examined a figuration formed by two working class groups in
‘Winston Parva’, his pseudonym for a suburb of Leicester, a medium-sized
city in the English East Midlands. One of these groups, ‘the established’, was
clearly dominant. The other, ‘the outsiders’, was clearly subordinate. According
to Elias and Scotson, these groups were identical in terms of the conventional
indices of social stratification – wealth, income, occupations, education,
status/prestige – differing only in the fact that members of the ‘established’
group and their families had lived in the community for several generations,
whilst the ‘outsiders’ and their families were relative newcomers. Yet a whole
constellation of symptoms usually associated with class exploitation and
social oppression was detectable in the relations between them. This led Elias
and Scotson to ask: ‘What … induced the people who formed the first of the
two groups to set themselves up … as higher and better …? What resources
of power enabled them to assert their superiority and to cast a slur on the
others as (people) of a lesser breed?’ (Elias and Scotson 2008: 3–4). Elias
found in ‘Winston Parva’ conflict-ridden figurational dynamics of the sort that
would normally be encountered between groups that differed along national,
ethnic, or class lines. What was particularly interesting about the case of this
suburb, however, was that the ‘full armoury of group superiority and group
contempt’ (Elias and Scotson 1994: xvii) was mobilised not in relation to
obvious physical, cultural, or linguistic differences, but solely with regard to
differences between residents in terms of how long they had lived within the
64 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY

neighbourhood, how ‘established’ they were within the community. Simply the
length of association, Elias and Scotson wrote, was, in and of itself, sufficient
to generate ‘the degree of group cohesion, the collective identification, the
commonality of norms, which are apt to induce the gratifying euphoria that
goes with the consciousness of belonging to a group of higher value and with
the complementary contempt for other groups’ (Elias and Scotson 2008: 4).
For Elias, Winston Parva presented an empirical crucible in which to develop
a series of more general observations about power. It is evident in the passage
that follows that Elias was, at least in part, developing these observations in
response to long dominant conventional Marxist and Weberian formulations
of power. He wrote:

[O]ne could see here the limitations of any theory which explains power
differentials only in terms of a monopolistic possession of non-human objects
such as weapons or means of production and disregards the figurational aspects
of power differentials due purely to differences in the degree of organisation of
the human beings concerned … [T]he latter, especially differences in the degree
of internal cohesion and communal control, can play a decisive part in the
greater power ratio of one group in relation to that of another … [In the small
community of Winston Parva], the power-superiority of the old-established group
was to a large extent of this type. It was based on the high degree of cohesion of
families who had known each other for two or three generations, in contrast to
the newcomers who were strangers in relation not only to the old residents but
also to each other. It was thanks to their greater potential for cohesion and its
activation by social control that the old residents were able to reserve offices in
their local organisations … for people of their own kind and firmly to exclude
from them people who lived in the other part [the ‘outsiders’] and who, as a
group, lacked cohesion … Exclusion and stigmatisation of the outsiders by the
established group, thus were two powerful weapons used by the latter to maintain
their identity, to assert their superiority, keeping the others firmly in their place.
(Elias and Scotson 2008: 4)

The power of the ‘established’ group in Winston Parva thus depended,


according to Elias, on the fact that the ‘oldness’, that is, the length of time of
their association, had enabled them to develop greater cohesion relative to
the ‘outsiders’, many of whom started as strangers to each other, and this, in
turn, enabled them to monopolise official positions in local associations. Such
greater cohesion of ‘established’ relative to ‘outsider’ groups, Elias suggested, is
a common, ‘purely figurational’ aspect of dominance-subordination relations,
that is, of figurations in which some are dominant and others subordinate. The
criticism implied here of the Marxian and similar approaches was later taken
up by Elias explicitly. He recognised the sociological value of what he called
Marx’s ‘great discovery’, namely the idea that ownership and control of the
means of production constitute the key determinants of class relations, but
was critical of what he regarded as the tendency in some sociological circles –
it was probably at its strongest in the 1960s and 1970s – ‘to see in it the end
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 65

of the road of discovery about human societies’. ‘One might rather’, he added,
‘regard it as one manifestation of a beginning’ (Elias and Scotson 2008: 18).
In other words, Elias considered Marx to have developed an important and
significant insight in uncovering a fundamental inter-relationship between the
asymmetrical distribution of the means of production and a correspondingly
uneven distribution of the means of satisfying human material needs
(Elias and Scotson 2008: 18). However, Elias considered this to be only
partially correct since Marx presented the struggle over ‘economic’ goals as the
‘root source’ of conflict between dominant and subordinate groups such that,
‘to this day the pursuit of “economic” goals, elastic and ambiguous as this use
of the term “economic” is, appears to many people as the “real”, the basic goal
of human groups by comparison with which others appear to be less “real”,
whatever that may mean’ (Elias and Scotson 2008: 18).
Elias would not have sought to deny that Marx’s theory of class formation
deals with the generation of a particular form of social cohesion, namely that
involved in the transformation of disunited ‘classes in themselves’ (Klassen
an sich) into united ‘classes for themselves’ (Klassen für sich) (Bendix 1953:
30). What he would have denied is that such processes are to be universally
understood solely intra-societally and in relation to modes of production.
‘Economic’ forms are socially structured and socially structuring but, Elias
contended, they are not alone in that respect: other aspects of figurations which,
especially in an age of increasing and increasingly rapid globalisation, have
to be understood inter-societally and not simply intra-societally such as state-
formation which is influenced, among other things, by war, the length and density
of interdependency chains which have long since been spreading beyond national
borders, and the relative cohesion of and balance of power between groups, all
of which are equally structured and structuring and no less ‘real’. Under specific
circumstances, these other aspects enjoy degrees of autonomy in relation to and
even dominance over modes of production. That is, in this as in other aspects
of his work, Elias rejected the notion of universal ‘law-like’ relations between
supposedly constituent social ‘parts’ such as ‘the economy’, ‘the state’ and ‘civil
society’ (Elias 2009: 66–84). Consistent with this, he suggested that the degree
to which ‘economic’ conflicts are paramount in a society is partly a function of
the balance of power between its constituent groups. He wrote:

The supremacy of the economic aspects of established-outsider relationships is


most pronounced where the balance of power between the contenders is most
uneven … The less that is the case, the more recognisable become other, non-
economic aspects of the tensions and conflicts. Where outsider groups have to live at
a subsistence level, the size of their earnings outweighs all their other requirements
in importance. The higher they rise above the subsistence level, the more does even
their income … serve as a means of satisfying human requirements other than that
of stilling their most elementary animalistic or ‘material’ needs and the more keenly
are groups in that situation liable to feel the … inferiority of power and status from
66 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY

which they suffer. And it is in that situation that the struggle between established
and outsiders gradually ceases to be, on the part of the latter, simply a struggle for
stilling their hunger, for the means of physical survival, and becomes a struggle
for satisfying other human requirements as well. (Elias and Scotson 2008: 17–18)

According to Elias, in other words, the phase of development of the shifting


balance of power between established and outsider groups plays a key part
in shaping the aims and demands of the outsiders and in the responses of the
established to them. This insight has more fundamental implications for Elias’s
discussion of power per se.
According to Max Weber, the ‘classical’ sociologist who devoted most time
to articulating what is meant sociologically by the concept of ‘power’, ‘we
understand by “power” the chance of a man or a number of men to realise their
own will in a communal action even against the resistance of others’ (Weber
1946: 180). Elsewhere, he offered the following variation: ‘power means any
chance within a social relationship to realise one’s own will, even in the face
of resistance, regardless of the basis on which this chance rests’ (Weber 1972:
28; our translation from the original German). It was this idea of the relational
character of power that was seized upon by Elias. Thus he wrote of ‘power-
balances’ or ‘power-ratios’ and suggested that:

From the day of its birth, a baby has power over its parents, not just the parents
over the baby. At least the baby has power over them as long as they attach …
value to it. If not, it loses its power … Equally bi-polar is the balance between
a slave and his [sic] master. The master has power over his slave, but the slave
also has power over his master, in proportion to his function for his master – his
master’s dependence on him. In relationships between parents and infants, masters
and slaves, power chances are distributed very unevenly. But whether the …
differentials are large or small, balances of power are always present wherever there
is functional interdependence between people … Power is not an amulet possessed
by one person and not by another; it is a structural characteristic of a relationship –
of all human relationships. (Elias 2012b: 69–70)

Elias went on to tie the concept of power more explicitly to that of


interdependence. A solution to the problems of power more adequate than
those on offer in sociology so far, he suggested:

depends on power being understood unequivocally as a structural characteristic


of a relationship … We depend on others; others depend on us. In so far as we
are more dependent on others than they are on us, more reliant on others than
they are on us, they have power over us, whether we have become dependent
on them by their use of naked force, or by our need to be loved, our need for
money, healing, status, a career or simply for excitement. (Elias 2012b: 88. Our
translation from the German)

It is noteworthy that Elias wrote this in the late 1960s for publication in
a German book which appeared in 1970, for the seemingly straightforward
diagnosis that he offers is arguably sociologically profound. What Elias was
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 67

suggesting is twofold: (i) that power is ‘polymorphous’, that is, many-sided


and inherent in all human relationships; and (ii) that the key to understanding
power lies in the interdependency of people. The examples Elias gives in the
passages we have quoted all refer to ‘bi-polar’ or ‘two-person’ relationships but
he was clear that power balances in the wider society and in the relationships
between societies are always multipolar; that is, they involve large, complex
and dynamic figurations of interdependent individuals and groups.
Elias’s theory of what he called ‘functional democratisation’ is inherent in his
concept of power as deriving mainly from interdependence. He contended that
the social transformation usually referred to by terms denoting specific aspects
such as ‘industrialisation’, ‘economic growth’, ‘urbanisation’, ‘bureaucratisation’
and many others, in fact involves a transformation of the total social structure
(Elias 2012: 59ff). And, he suggested, one of the most significant aspects of
such a total social transformation consists in the emergence of larger, more
differentiated, and denser ‘chains of interdependence’ (Elias 2012a; 2012b).
Concomitantly with this, according to Elias, there occurs a change in the
direction of generally decreasing power differentials within and among groups,
more specifically an equalising change to some degree in the balance of power
between rulers and ruled, social classes, men and women, parents and children,
and the generations more generally (Elias 2012b: 63ff). At the most general level,
Elias maintained, such a process of ‘functional democratisation’ occurs when
increasing specialisation takes place. That is the case because the performers
of specialised roles gain from their specialisations chances of exerting varying
degrees of reciprocal influence and control, for example, by withdrawing their
services or, in the case of the purchasers of these services, refusing to pay for
them. The power chances of specialised groups are further enhanced if they
manage to organise since they then become able by collective action to disrupt
the wider chains of interdependence on which a modern society depends. It is
in ways such as these, according to Elias, that increasing division of labour and
the emergence of larger chains of interdependence lead over time to greater,
more even forms of reciprocal dependency and, hence, to patterns of multi-polar
influence and control within and among groups. It is important, however, to
stress that we have said here ‘more even forms of reciprocal dependency’, not
‘even’ forms. The comparative is significant. Elias’s hypothesis is about processes
of equalisation which can be demonstrated empirically to have occurred but is
not intended to deny the vast inequalities which remain in Western societies and
the world at large, and which have increased in certain respects in recent years.
It is noteworthy that our discussion above of Elias on power commenced in
relation to an exposition of some of his other key ideas, and continued via an
empirical analysis of established–outsider relationships, before moving on to a
consideration of some of the long-term social processes involved in ‘functional
democratisation’. We stress this because it serves once more to demonstrate, firstly,
the theoretical–empirical character of Elias’s approach, secondly, the fundamental
68 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY

‘interdependence’ of Elias’s key concepts, and thirdly, the primacy of process in


his sociological models. In the next part of this chapter, we shall explore more
centrally the underpinning diachronic orientation of Elias’s approach, with a
specific discussion of his work on time, and a more general examination of some
of his observations regarding the relations between history and sociology.

Time and history in the work of Elias

Of all the major sociologists of the twentieth century, especially its second
half, Elias was the one who argued most consistently in favour of an ‘historical
approach’. (The reasons why we have put ‘historical’ in inverted commas will
become clearer as our exposition of Elias unfolds.) In order fully to grasp what
he wrote on the subject of the sociology-history interface and the need for a
process-orientated view to be dominant in both subjects, it is necessary to have
an understanding of at least the basic elements of what he wrote on the subject
of time. The principal contribution that Elias had to offer in this regard is
best illustrated by comparing what he wrote with the views on this subject of
Anthony Giddens. According to Giddens in The Constitution of Society:

As the finitude of Dasein and as ‘the infinity of the emergence of being from
nothingness,’ time is perhaps the most enigmatic feature of human experience.
Not for nothing [sic] was that philosopher who has attempted to grapple in the
most fundamental way with the problem, Heidegger, compelled to use terminology
of the most daunting obscurity. But time, or the constitution of experience in
time-space, is also a banal and evident feature of … day-to-day life. It is in some part
the lack of ‘fit’ between our unproblematic coping with the continuity of conduct
across time-space, and its ineffable character when confronted philosophically,
that is the very essence of the puzzling nature of time. (Giddens 1984: 34–5)

Dasein is the German for ‘being’ or ‘existence’ and, following his interpretation
of Heidegger, Giddens is suggesting here that ‘time’ is unproblematic as a
‘common sense’, routine feature of daily life but massively problematic when
viewed philosophically because, in the latter context, we are unable to escape
‘ultimate’ issues of a kind that we humans can only ‘resolve’ inadequately
through the use of patently metaphysical ideas such as ‘absolute beginnings’,
‘ultimate origins’, ‘uncaused’ ‘first’ and ‘final causes’, and ‘being emerging from
nothingness’. Elias never pretended he had got anywhere near to solving the
‘mysteries’ of existence. As he expressed it in a poem in Luciad, the Leicester
student magazine in 1962, ‘There are no mysteries/only a lot I don’t know’.
He also claimed in conversations to have gone further than philosophers
such as Heidegger and philosophically-minded sociologists such as Giddens
regarding the understanding of time. More particularly, from Elias’s standpoint
both sides of the equation as formulated by Giddens are problematic. That is,
while ‘time’ may be a ‘banal and evident feature of human day-to-day life’ in
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 69

the modern world where we have inherited a workable calendar and efficient
devices such as clocks and watches for measuring what we call ‘time’, this has
not always been the case. According to Elias: ‘One forgets that for thousands
of years the calendars people used ran into trouble again and again; they had
to be reformed and improved until one … reached the near perfection the
European calendar has attained since the last calendar reform’ (Elias 2007b:
156–7). Indeed, so far from being ‘banal and evident’ is this taken-for-granted
feature of human life that there have been times when people were opposed to
calendar reforms because they believed they would shorten their lives!
The other side of what Giddens wrote is problematic because he does
not appear to have considered the possibility that the ‘daunting obscurity’
of Heidegger’s terminology may have been connected, not so much with the
properties of ‘time’ as with the fact that Heidegger approached the problem
in a purely rational and quasi-theological manner. More particularly, while
the problems associated with ‘time’ remain complex if approached in a more
theoretico-empirical manner, they are not necessarily ‘daunting’ and ‘obscure’.
At the most basic level, they are relatively straightforward. That is, ‘time’ is
a concept which, in Elias’s sociological terms, refers to a symbolic ‘means of
orientation’ through which humans coordinate their lives – ‘I’ll meet you in the
pub at 6.15’; ‘the plane leaves Heathrow Airport at 18.30’; – and communicate
their understanding of natural and sociohistorical processes of various kinds –
‘light travels at 186,000 miles per second’; ‘the Nazi dictatorship came to an
end in 1945’. The reality of ‘time’ is as a social, collectively produced symbol in
a world where only natural processes and events, including processes and events
at the human-social level, occur; where, we might say, only events and processes
of various kinds are ‘real’. That, at least, was Elias’s view. He expressed it thus:

Linguistic habits … constantly reinforce the myth of time as something which in


some sense exists and as such can be determined or measured even if it cannot
be perceived by the senses. On this peculiar mode of existence of time one can
philosophise tirelessly, as has indeed been done over the centuries. One can
entertain oneself and others with speculation on the secret of time as a master of
mystery, although there is no mystery. It was Einstein who finally set the seal on
the discovery that time was a form of relationship and not, as Newton believed,
an objective flow, a part of creation like rivers and mountains which, although
invisible, was like them independent of the people who do the timing. But even
Einstein did not probe deeply enough. He too did not entirely escape the pressure
of word-fetishism and in his own way gave sustenance to the myth of reified time,
for example, by maintaining that under certain circumstances time could contract
or expand. (Elias 2007b: 36–37)

So, processes and events, not symbols, are the only substantives, and ‘time’
is a humanly constructed symbol, not a process like a flowing river or an event
like a flood. Furthermore, ‘every change in “space” is a change in “time”;
[and] every change in “time” [is] a change in “space”’ (Elias 2007b: 82).
70 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY

Part of the reason why is that the earth is constantly moving round the sun
and the sun is part of a galaxy, ‘the Milky Way’, that, with the exception
of local galaxies such as Andromeda which are moving towards us, is
moving away at speed from the billions of other galaxies which constitute
the currently known universe. We propose not to elaborate on the concepts
of ‘space’ and ‘time’ any further here, except to add that, just as people
today are the inheritors of more reality-congruent time symbols and
more accurate time meters such as atomic clocks and the quartz watches
that we in the more ‘advanced’ societies carry round on our wrists, so, too,
are we the inheritors of a fund of more reality-congruent knowledge about
‘space’, especially the ‘local space’, namely the earth and the solar system,
which we inhabit. That is, we have not only more effective calendars and
chronometers – time-measuring devices – but also more detailed and reliable
maps and devices such as compasses, radar, satellites and global positioning
systems (‘sat navs’) for accurately measuring relative positions in ‘space-
time’. Our technologically buttressed abilities in these regards are crucial to
the operation of the networks of global and local interdependence which
characterise the present-day world.
The principal relevance for sociology of these issues is that the subject ought
to be centrally concerned with the study of social events and processes in space
and time. This means that the conventional view according to which sociology
and history are separate subjects, one concerned with ‘the present’, the other
with ‘the past’, is arbitrary and wrong. All studies are necessarily studies of ‘the
past’. A moment’s reflection will show how this is so. Human societies exist in
space-time, and time, as the old personifying adage has it, ‘never stands still’.
To express it non-metaphysically, human individuals, their societies, the earth,
our solar system, the Milky Way and the universe are processes, constantly
moving, constantly changing. This means that what we call the ‘present’ is a
constantly shifting reference point in the ceaseless flow of physical, biological,
social and individual processes and events. What was ‘the present’ on all these
levels when we started writing this chapter had already become part of the
past when we completed it. In a word, ‘the present’ is an ambiguous concept
with multiple levels of meaning and it has to be read as having an historical
connotation. It follows that, if it were to be accepted that sociology is the study
of ‘the present’, some more or less arbitrary judgement about the relatively
recent past would have to be made. One would have to decide whether the term
‘past’ refers to, say, the 1990s, the 2000s, or the 2010s, to the years since the
1960s, or to those since the end of the Second World War. However, whatever
decision was made, any such studies would necessarily involve attempts to
come to terms with aspects of ‘the past’. In short, it would inevitably lead one
to become involved in a kind of ‘historical’ study. Elias commented upon this
fundamental relationship between sociology and history in some detail as we
shall now discuss.
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 71

History and sociology

One of Elias’s lengthiest statements on the relationship between history and


sociology is contained in the Introduction to his book, The Court Society
(Elias 2006b (1969)). He began with a critical examination of the popular
belief, expounded most systematically by the philosopher Karl Popper in his
book, The Poverty of Historicism (1957), that history and historical sociology
cannot possibly be ‘scientific’ because of the uniqueness and unrepeatability
of historical events. It was Popper’s contention that a ‘science’ is only possible
with recurring events and phenomena because only then can you test and
formulate testable ‘laws’. Elias took issue with this popular view, suggesting
that uniqueness and unrepeatability are not inherent in history as an ‘object’,
that is, inherent in its ‘nature’ independently of the values and interests of
people like Popper who make claims of this kind. On the contrary, such claims
reflect the values of people in highly differentiated urban-industrial societies in
which individual uniqueness is prized. Elias’s case against Popper and others
who propound similar views was complex. He began to unravel the complexity
by suggesting that:

unrepeatable and unique phenomena are by no means confined to the sequences


of events that historians take as the object of their studies. Such phenomena exist
everywhere. Not only is each human being, each human feeling, each action and
each experience of a person unique, but each bat and bacillus. Every extinct
animal species is unique. The saurians [that is, the dinosaurs] will not return. In
the same sense, Homo sapiens, the human species as a whole, is unique. And the
same can be said of each speck of dust, of our sun, the Milky Way and of every
other formation: they come, they go and when they have gone they do not return.
(Elias 2006b: 10)

These observations, said Elias, suggest that there are ‘different degrees of
uniqueness and unrepeatability, and what is unique and unrepeatable on one
level can be seen on another as repetition, a return of the never-changing’. Take,
for example, the often claimed uniqueness of individual human beings – one of
the reasons advanced for the impossibility of a ‘scientific’ history or a ‘scientific’
sociology. According to Elias, it provides a good example of a phenomenon
that involves uniqueness on one level and repeatability on another. That is so,
Elias said, because ‘individual human beings are themselves repetitions of an
unchanging form, and what differs between people now appears as a variation
of the ever-recurring basic pattern’ (Elias 2006b: 10).
This observation allows Elias to question how ‘object adequate’ or ‘reality
congruent’ – in more popular terms, how ‘accurate’ – is the argument that
history consists of a unique sequence of unrepeatable events. Is it, he asked,
a product of unprejudiced critical analysis or the result of an ideological
manipulation in which the practitioners of history in highly differentiated and
individualised societies project their specific social conditioning and short-lived
72 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY

values onto their ‘object of study, the historical process itself’? This question,
said Elias, cannot be answered in simple ‘yes/no’, terms; nor can it be reduced
to a simple formula. Elias stressed the need to define clearly both the differences
and the relationships between ‘biological evolution’, ‘social development’ and
‘history’. The failure to do this up to now, said Elias, has acted as a blockage
to knowledge.
Elias also contended that the biological constitution of social insects
such as ants and bees is both relatively fixed and determines their social
organisation. The evolution of Homo sapiens has led our species, too, to have
a relatively fixed biological constitution. However, it is one which makes
individual members of the species dependent on experience and learning.
Humans have to learn in order to be able to function and it is this which
makes it possible for human societies to have a history and to develop, that is
to undergo changes of structure or form. According to Elias, however, while
the biological evolution of Homo sapiens cannot be reversed – though the
species could, of course, become extinct and, when our sun ‘dies’, probably
will unless we have managed by then to transfer to a new habitable planet
in a new sun system – their social development is reversible. As Elias put it:

Change in human figurations is … closely bound up with the possibility of


transmitting experiences gathered in one generation to subsequent generations
as acquired social knowledge. This continuous social accumulation of knowledge
plays a part in the changing of human society. But the continuity of the collection
and transmission of knowledge can be broken. The increase in knowledge does
not bring about a genetic change in the human race. Socially accumulated
experiences can be lost. (2006b: 13)

The terms ‘biological evolution’, ‘social development’ and ‘history’ denote


layered yet separate sequences embracing the whole of humankind and they
occur at different rates. In the long process of biological evolution, the species
Homo sapiens emerged for the first time as a distinct species some 50,000 years
ago. Its social development, though fast by comparison with the rate at which
significant biological evolution generally takes place, was, at first, comparatively
slow, speeding up following the agricultural and urban ‘revolutions’ and
becoming even quicker following the ‘scientific revolution’ of the seventeenth
century and the ‘industrial revolution’ of the eighteenth. Nevertheless, though
fast by comparison with biological evolution, social developments are often so
slow by comparison with an individual life-time that people do not recognise
them as occurring at all. In Elias’s words:

Measured by the length and rate of change of an individual human life, social
developments often take place so slowly that they seem to stand still. It is
possible that the … figurations formed by people change so little for a number
of generations that they are regarded by those involved as immutable … Thus,
for a long period in the development of European society, people are embraced
over and over … by the figuration ‘knight-page-priest-bondsman’. Today, and
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 73

for a number of generations past in the developed industrial societies, people


are repeatedly found in relationships such as ‘worker-employee-manager’ or
‘higher-middle-lower official’. The functional interdependence of these and all
other divisions in a particular society entails … a certain exclusivity. Knight and
bondsman would scarcely fit into an industrial configuration. (2006b: 13)

Each human individual, said Elias, though a variation on the relatively


unchanging pattern of the species as a whole, is ‘unique’ and ‘unrepeatable’ and,
in the course of his/her life-time undergoes rapid change. Nevertheless, these
unique, unrepeatable and rapidly changing individuals form relatively persisting
figurations with one another which are ‘just as real as the individual people
forming them’. This is rarely recognised by the institutionalised establishment
of historians, argued Elias, and it perpetuates both the inherent individualism
of their approach and their feelings of superiority relative to newcomers such as
sociologists. This leads to a terrible waste of human effort in the sense that each
generation feels an urge to rewrite history in the sense of historians continually
revisiting the same topics and events, bringing with them new values, new
axes to grind, new sensibilities and new biases but little sense of the need for
incremental knowledge.

Elias as a radical sociologist

We commenced this chapter by arguing that Elias’s sociological approach was


radically processual and radically relational. However, that Elias’s sociological
insights might be considered ‘radical’ requires some qualification. As a means
of concluding and distilling some of the key arguments of this chapter, we shall
thus elaborate in more detail what we mean in this respect.
Johan Goudsblom of the University of Amsterdam has likened Elias to
Charles Darwin (1977), the principal progenitor of the theory of biological
evolution via ‘natural selection’. An additional parallel – with Copernicus, the
sixteenth century Polish astronomer – may also be pertinent. This is because
Elias arguably succeeded not just in recognising that members of the species
Homo sapiens are a kind of animals which evolved biologically to bond closely
with each other, to be dependent on languages and the intergenerational
transmission of acquired funds of knowledge, but also, as we have endeavoured
to show in this chapter, in developing a conceptual repertoire attuned to
this fundamental insight. Kilminster (2007: 154–5) elaborates on an idea of
Freud’s in this connection by referring to Elias’s work as having delivered the
fourth, sociological ‘blow to human narcissism’; the first three having been
delivered, respectively, by Copernicus, Darwin, and Freud. In his seminal
essay, ‘Resistances to Psychoanalysis’ (Freud 1925: 273), Freud had pointed
to: Copernicus as having delivered the first, that is, the cosmological blow to
human self-love by discovering that the earth revolves around the sun rather
74 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY

than vice versa; Darwin as having delivered the second, that is, the biological
blow, by discovering such basic facts about humans as that they had evolved
out of earlier species of hominids; and the third, psychological blow that was
delivered by Freud himself with regard to his highly influential and important
thesis regarding the human repression of libidinal impulses.
In a manner that parallels Copernicus with respect to our solar system and
astronomy, Elias pointed the way towards a sociology in which a resolution by
means of theory-guided empirical research and research-based theorising could
take the place of merely thinking about such age-old philosophical/sociological
issues as the agency-structure dilemma (nominalism versus realism), the nature/
society dichotomy, the nature versus nurture problem, body-mind dualism,
materialism versus idealism, and many more. Elias’s conceptual reorientation –
aspects of which we have begun to explore in this chapter – has arguably laid the
foundations for a ‘post-philosophical’ (Kilminster 2007) model for approaching
such problems.
As was typical of Elias, he viewed his own contribution to sociology in terms
of evolutionary scale processes of human development. In his text The Symbol
Theory, Elias wrote of humans as having become equipped via evolution to
undergo a process of ‘symbol emancipation’, that is, a potentially liberating
increase in power and control made possible by language and knowledge-
stocks in four main areas: (i) over their wider environment; (ii) relative to
other animals, of humans developing from a ‘hunted’ into a ‘hunting’ species
(Goudsblom 1994); (iii) over themselves as individuals; and (iv) over themselves
as groups. A related notion is what Elias (1978: 156–7) called ‘the triad of basic
controls’, that is, the control of self, society, and nature. Symbol emancipation,
Elias suggested, must have involved simultaneous and interacting processes
of biological evolution and social development, each mutually dependent on
and not reducible to the other. Such processes are still far from being fully
understood and the difficulty of understanding them is inhibited by a tendency
to distinguish, as we have seen, between, for example, ‘nature’ and ‘society’, as
if ‘societies’ could exist somewhere other than in ‘nature’. The institutionally
reinforced distinction between the ‘social sciences’ and the ‘natural sciences’
contributes further to the inhibition. In Elias’s words:

Most of [the social sciences], history and sociology among them, are concerned
with aspects of human life which are uniquely human, which in other words
are, or are due to, evolutionary innovations. They distinguish humanity from
other species. As a rule, however, these human sciences … do not ask how these
uniquely human properties are connected with those which humans share with
other species, such as birth and death … [N]o attempts are made … to discover
the hinge connecting nature with … ‘non-nature’. Thus sociologists may see the
body as a topic of interest. But the prevailing routines … make it easy to treat
the body as a topic of sociological research set apart from other topics, perhaps
as the subject-matter of a specialism. There does not seem any need to explore
the links connecting aspects of humans conceived as body, with other aspects
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 75

perhaps conceived as disembodied. On a larger scale, too, human sciences of


this type tacitly work with the image of a split world. The division of sciences
into natural sciences and others not concerned with nature reveals itself as a
symbolic manifestation of an ontological belief – of the belief in a factually
existing division of the world … The question as to which unique biological
characteristics of human beings make history possible has hardly been a talking
point among historians. Nor have the distinguishing characteristics and the
relationship of biological evolution and social development been a frequent
point of discussion among sociologists. The term evolution is at present used
indiscriminately with reference to both. How culture, rationality, knowledge,
conscience and other similar aspects of human beings fit into the well-established
theory of an evolutionary descent of humans is anybody’s guess… (Elias 2009b:
141–58)

Just as Copernicus rejected the old geocentric or earth-centred picture of


our local solar system and replaced it with a heliocentric or sun-centred view,
so, to continue with Freud’s model, Elias can be seen as having established
crucial preconditions for the establishment of sociology as a human science
(Menschenwissenschaft) by correcting the homo clausus or ‘closed person’
view of humans and replacing it with an orientation towards homines aperti,
pluralities of ‘open people’. Each of these reorientations involved a process
of decentring: in the case of Copernicus, a decentring from humanity’s
primary anthropocentrism, that is their view of Homo sapiens and the
earth as the centre of everything. In the case of Elias, a decentring from the
Enlightenment/Judaeo-Christian view of humans as ‘rational’ beings created
by an anthropomorphic conception, ‘God’, who stands ‘above’ and in some
ways ‘outside nature’. Further to this, humans are seen according to this view
as apart from and above other animals, and as separated and alone in relation
to each other.
In the next chapter, we shall develop this argument further through an
exploration of how Elias attempted to add to a reorientation of sociology
through what he regarded as his most important contribution to the subject,
his theory of ‘civilising processes’.

You might also like