Some Basic Concepts of Figurational Sociology
Some Basic Concepts of Figurational Sociology
Some Basic Concepts of Figurational Sociology
" Norbert
Elias and Modern Sociology: Knowledge, Interdependence, Power, Process. London:
Bloomsbury Academic, 2013. 50–75. Bloomsbury Collections. Web. 31 Mar. 2021. <http://
dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781780933405.ch-002>.
Copyright © Eric Dunning and Jason Hughes 2013. You may share this work for non-commercial
purposes only, provided you give attribution to the copyright holder and the publisher.
2
Some Basic Concepts of
Figurational Sociology
50
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 51
taken from social life itself, for example, dances, games and the personal
pronouns.
At the core of Elias’s work is a stress on the observable fact that, like the
universe at large, each human individual is a process: that is, we are born,
mature and die – a set of facts which sound banal until it is remembered that
the sociology of birth, death, and dying are marginal specialisms in our subject.
Elias wrote of Humana Conditio, ‘the human condition’ (Elias 1985), in this
connection. Our difficulties in coming to grips with the processual character of
everything, he said, are compounded by our fears and hesitations regarding our
mortality. Sociologists, he argued, need to develop a vocabulary which avoids
the tendency to reduce processes to steady states (Zustandsreduktion). Such a
tendency is characteristic of Western languages. As he expressed it:
Our languages are constructed in such a way that we can often only express
constant movement or constant change in ways which imply that it has the
character of an isolated object at rest, and then, almost as an afterthought, adding
a verb which expresses the fact that the thing with this character is now changing.
For example, standing by a river we see the perpetual flowing of the water. But to
grasp it conceptually, and to communicate it to others, we do not think and say,
‘look at the perpetual flowing of the water’; we say, ‘look how fast the river is
flowing’. We say, ‘The wind is blowing’, as if the wind were actually a thing at rest
which, at a given point in time, begins to move and blow. We speak as if the wind
were separate from its blowing, as if a wind could exist which did not blow. …
This reduction of processes to static conditions, we shall call ‘process-reduction’
for short … (Elias 2012b: 106–107).
It was in order to capture this idea of process that Elias insisted that the
conventional sociological vocabulary which involves talking, for example, of
‘social structure and social change’, a formulation which implies that non-
changing social structures could exist, should be abandoned and, even though
they often sound ugly in English, replaced by process terms such as ‘socialisation’,
‘civilisation’, ‘industrialisation’, ‘urbanisation’, ‘democratisation’, ‘courtisation’,
and ‘sportisation’.
According to Elias, humans are also bound to others by fluid ties of
interdependence which are a biosocial and not simply a social or learned fact
of life. That is, we have a partly inborn, partly socially instilled tendency to
seek the company of others, for example for sexual purposes, but also as an
enjoyable ‘end-in-itself’. Sociability is also important for human survival. The
babyhood and infancy of humans last a relatively long time, and babies and
infants cannot survive on their own. They have to bond with others and others
with them. As Winnicott, the psychoanalyst famously put it: ‘There is no such
thing as a baby, there is a baby and someone’ (Winnicott 1965). Humans also
have a mobile facial musculature, a biological fact which is a precondition
for smiling, another crucial inborn feature at the emotional level of human
bonding.33 It plays an important part in the bonding of parents and their
52 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY
newborn babies. Laughter is another uniquely human feature which can play an
important bonding role. Although most people tend to take it for granted, there
is an occupational group in modern societies – comedians – who specialise in
making other people laugh, and there is now a substantial body of sociological
research on this profession and on comedy itself (see, for example, the work
of Lockyer and Pickering (2006); and Kuipers (2006)). And, of course, just as,
among adolescents and adults, smiling can be used to deceive people, so laughter
can be used to ridicule other individuals and groups. Both are sometimes used
in ‘legal’ and ‘illegal’ murders. Examples include public executions of the kind
that used to be common in European and other countries.
Human figurations
to the concept of figurations is the core idea that notions such as ‘the individual’
as an isolated abstraction, or ‘agency’ as some-thing that is ‘held’ or ‘exercised’
by ‘the individual’ or ‘the state’ are in themselves misleading terms which, to
varying degrees, involve forms of conceptual reductionism and reification.
A guiding analogy for the concept of figurations is that of dance. Viewing
dancers on a dance-floor as a mobile figuration of interdependent people is
useful because it refers to ‘real-life’ social processes, and not abstract (and
highly problematic) comparisons with, for instance, biological organisms or
synthetic mechanisms. However, equally, in invoking dance as an analogy, Elias
also wanted us, by extension, to envisage families, cities, nation states, and even
feudal, capitalist, and communist societies, all as figurations, but with differing
degrees of length and complexity. We can think of recognisable patterns emerging
from such shifting figurations, just as we might, for example, be able to discern
the ‘tango’, or the ‘waltz’, or simply ‘dance in general’ as distinct, say, from
‘walking’. However, Elias argues, it is important not to conceive of ‘dance’ as a
structure or ‘thing’ which is somehow ‘outside’ of ‘the individual’ (2012a: 525).
While different people can dance the same dance figuration, there is no dance
as such without dancers. Dance figurations, like any social figuration, are to a
degree independent of the specific individuals forming them at any particular
time, but are not independent of individuals as such. Neither, Elias proposed,
are dances, or by extension figurations, mere abstracted mental constructions
produced from the observation of individuals considered in isolation from one
another. While figurations can persist even after the individuals who comprised
them at one time died and became replaced, they only exist through the on-
going participation of constituent members.
The analogy of dance, and indeed the concept of ‘figurations’, may appear
simple at first sight, perhaps common-sensical, but the insights they yield are
of great conceptual significance. In this concept – which, we shall show, must
be understood in relation to the others he offers – Elias provides a means of
circumventing, not so much resolving, the ‘agency-structure dilemma’. The
dilemma centres on the difficulties attendant upon developing formulations of
the relationship between individuals and the societies they form which avoid
the trap of ‘reductionism’ to ‘individuals’ and ‘agency’ on the one hand, and the
‘reification’ of ‘society’ and ‘structure’, on the other, whilst simultaneously doing
justice to both ‘the individual’ and ‘the social’ sides of the equation. Sociologists
have been embroiled in the agency-structure/individual-society conundrum
since the inception of their subject when it separated from philosophy in the
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. Another name for the conundrum/dilemma
is the ‘nominalism’ versus ‘realism’ controversy (Popper 1957). Emile Durkheim
(1895) who saw sociology as the study of ‘social facts’ was a sociological realist
who in some formulations came close to reifying social phenomena by playing
down, perhaps even failing to see, that they are simultaneously individual. Max
Weber who saw sociology as the study of ‘social action’ was a sociological
nominalist because he denied the reality to which sociological constructs such
54 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY
as ‘state’ and ‘society’ correspond and refer (Gerth and Mills 1970). For Weber,
they are ultimately nothing more than names.
It is important to recognise that Elias only came to develop his concepts,
theories and methods gradually over time. They did not flow automatically or
quickly from his pen. In his 1921 essay, ‘On Seeing in Nature’, for example, in
which he discussed the balance of similarities and differences between ‘the arts’
and ‘the sciences’, he used the term ‘laws’ to express the discoveries unearthed
by practitioners of the latter. Somewhat later, in his plan for his later abandoned
Habilitationsschrift (post-doctoral thesis) which was to have been supervised
by Alfred Weber (Collected Works (2006a), Vol. 1: 111–122) and likewise in
his 1929 essay on ‘The Sociology of German Anti-Semitism’ (2006a: 78–80), he
made explanatory use of the metaphor of ‘constellations’ to express the idea of
structure but later abandoned it on account of its astronomical connotations.
It was only when working in the 1960s on a joint article with Eric Dunning,
‘Dynamics of Sport Groups with Special Reference to Football’ (Elias and
Dunning 1966), that Elias came to prefer the concept of ‘configurations’ because
of its combination of structural and processual connotations.34
It soon became clear, however, that Elias had a considerably more complex
set of concepts forming in his mind. He used the concept of ‘law-like regularities’
as explanatory of the relatively simple, recurring properties of the phenomenal
universe such as light and gravity with which physicists and chemists have been
centrally concerned. However, he did not think of them as necessarily universal
and eternal as philosophers such as Popper seem to have done. Moreover, he
spoke of the configurational dynamics of emergent organic structures such as
DNA where the helix has to be double in order to result in genetic inheritance.
‘Figurational dynamics’ was the term he reserved for the highly complex and
dynamic structures and processes that human societies involve, and that are
the objects/subjects of sociological research. Elias expressed this latter point
as follows:
from these
from these
from these
unicellar organisms
large molecules
small molecules
from atoms
atoms
Our conventional tools for thinking and speaking are to a considerable degree
constructed as if everything external to the single person were an object, moreover
an object usually in a state of rest. Concepts like ‘family’ or ‘school’ plainly refer to
networks of people. But the conventional way in which we form our … concepts
makes it appear as if the groupings formed by humans were pieces of matter –
objects of the same kind as rocks, trees or houses. This reifying character of the
conventional means of speaking and thinking about groups of interdependent
people – groups to which one perhaps belongs oneself – appears not least in the
concept of society and the way in which one thinks about it. One says that ‘society’
is the ‘object’ which sociologists research. But this reifying mode of expression
contributes not a little to the difficulties encountered in understanding what
sociology is all about. (Elias 1970: 9–10. Authors’ translation from the German)
State
Industry
School
Family
SOCIETY ME
Ego
Figure 2.2 depicts what Elias called the homo clausus image of humans and
their societies. In it, people experience themselves as isolated individuals (‘egos’)
or ‘I’s who are walled off from others, separated from them as if by an invisible
barrier, while at the same time experiencing the institutions that they form such
as families, schools, economies, and states and which are nothing more than
differently organised groups of individuals, as ‘objects’ or ‘compelling forces’
that are more, as it is sometimes metaphysically put, than ‘the sum of their
individual parts’. A more appropriate image, said Elias, is provided by Figure 2.3.
This depicts a figuration of homines aperti, ‘open people’ who, ‘through their
basic dispositions and inclinations, are directed towards and linked with each
other in the most diverse ways’ (Elias 1978: 14–15). According to Elias ‘people
make up webs of interdependence or figurations of many kinds … They are
characterised by power balances of many sorts …’ (2012b: 10).
The first thing worthy of note in this connection is that Elias’s understanding
of the concept of interdependence is not the same as Durkheim’s in
The Division of Labour (1964). The French classical sociologist distinguished
between ‘bonds of similitude’ based on likeness and ‘bonds of interdependence’
based on the division of labour. But, for Elias, ‘bonds of similitude’ involve
forms of interdependence, too, for example, the bonds between husbands and
wives, parents and children, and many more. That is, interdependence is far
from being simply an ‘economic’ phenomenon. Dunning vividly remembers
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 59
Individual
(‘Ego’, ‘I’)
Open (unattached)
valencies
driving Elias from Leicester to London along the M1 motorway in the 1960s
and asking: ‘Norbert, this is a form of interdependence in your understanding
of the term, isn’t it? All of us drivers are dependent on the others observing the
rules of the road and not losing self-control. It’s surely a kind of life and death
interdependence’. Elias replied: ‘Yes it is, Eric my dear. In fact, in The Civilising
Process, you will remember, I contrast a medieval road where the main danger
was from wild animals or deliberate attack from other humans and a modern
road where the principal danger is that of other people losing their self-control’
(see Elias 2012a: 406–7).
American sociologist Thomas J. Scheff has written on this issue as follows:
In What is Sociology? (1978; 2012b) and Involvement and Detachment (1987a;
2007a), Elias implicitly uses interdependence to contrast it with two different types
of relationship: ‘independence’, or a relationship characterized by detachment and
‘dependence’, a relationship so over-involved as to be suffocating to one or both
parties. This more specific use of interdependence is also implied in his discussion
of the ‘I-we’ balance in the preface to Involvement and Detachment (1987a;
2007a). In this passage a balanced I-we relationship would seem to correspond to
interdependence. A relationship that did not involve a balance between the ‘I’ and
the ‘we’ would not be interdependent; if one or both parties maintained an ‘I-self’,
the relationship would be one of independence; if one or both parties maintained
a ‘we-self’, the relationship would be one of dependence … [Elias] is not
always consistent in his usage of the term ‘interdependence’, however. Although
I have not found the reference, I have been told that Elias has written that war
between two nations can involve interdependence (personal communication from
Jon Fletcher)… (Scheff in Salumets 2001: 103)
Scheff is a prominent advocate of Elias’s work, and one of the few American
scholars to have engaged with his ideas in a sustained manner. However, his
60 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY
and defeated Führer? Why did people in the past sacrifice themselves for
their tribe or their religion, and why are some members of militant religious
groups today willing to sacrifice themselves for their beliefs? Elias began to
answer these questions as follows:
First of all, these units all seem to have exercised comparatively strict control over
the use of physical violence in relationships between their members. At the same
time, they have allowed, and often encouraged, their members to use physical
violence against non-members. To date, sociology has lacked any clear conception
of the common features of this type of solidaristic grouping at different levels of
social development. Its function is obvious: it knits people together for common
purposes – the common defence of their lives, the survival of their group in the
face of attacks by other groups and, for a variety of reasons, attacks in common on
other groups. Thus the primary function of such an alliance is either physically to
wipe out other people or to protect its own members from being physically wiped
out. Since the potential of such units for attack is inseparable from their potential
for defence, they may be called ‘attack-and-defence units’ or ‘survival units’.
At the present stage of social development, they take the form of nation-states.
In the future they may be amalgamations of several former nation states. In the
past they were represented by city-states or the inhabitants of a stronghold. Size
and structure vary: the function remains the same. At every stage of development,
wherever people have been bound and integrated into units for attack and defence,
this bond has been stressed above all others. This survival function, involving the
use of physical force against others, creates interdependence of a particular kind.
It plays a part in the figurations people form, perhaps no greater but also no more
negligible than ‘occupational’ bonds. Although it cannot be reduced to ‘economic’
functions, neither is it separable from them. (Elias 2012b: 133–4)
The distinction between ‘order’ and ‘disorder’, so significant for the people
involved, is sociologically speaking without significance. Among men, as in
nature, no absolute chaos is possible … [T]he word ‘order’ is not being used
[here] in the sense in which it is used when people speak of ‘law and order’ or, in
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 63
In a study that he carried out in the late 1950s and early 1960s with John
Scotson entitled The Established and the Outsiders (1994 (1965)), Elias
centrally examined a figuration formed by two working class groups in
‘Winston Parva’, his pseudonym for a suburb of Leicester, a medium-sized
city in the English East Midlands. One of these groups, ‘the established’, was
clearly dominant. The other, ‘the outsiders’, was clearly subordinate. According
to Elias and Scotson, these groups were identical in terms of the conventional
indices of social stratification – wealth, income, occupations, education,
status/prestige – differing only in the fact that members of the ‘established’
group and their families had lived in the community for several generations,
whilst the ‘outsiders’ and their families were relative newcomers. Yet a whole
constellation of symptoms usually associated with class exploitation and
social oppression was detectable in the relations between them. This led Elias
and Scotson to ask: ‘What … induced the people who formed the first of the
two groups to set themselves up … as higher and better …? What resources
of power enabled them to assert their superiority and to cast a slur on the
others as (people) of a lesser breed?’ (Elias and Scotson 2008: 3–4). Elias
found in ‘Winston Parva’ conflict-ridden figurational dynamics of the sort that
would normally be encountered between groups that differed along national,
ethnic, or class lines. What was particularly interesting about the case of this
suburb, however, was that the ‘full armoury of group superiority and group
contempt’ (Elias and Scotson 1994: xvii) was mobilised not in relation to
obvious physical, cultural, or linguistic differences, but solely with regard to
differences between residents in terms of how long they had lived within the
64 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY
neighbourhood, how ‘established’ they were within the community. Simply the
length of association, Elias and Scotson wrote, was, in and of itself, sufficient
to generate ‘the degree of group cohesion, the collective identification, the
commonality of norms, which are apt to induce the gratifying euphoria that
goes with the consciousness of belonging to a group of higher value and with
the complementary contempt for other groups’ (Elias and Scotson 2008: 4).
For Elias, Winston Parva presented an empirical crucible in which to develop
a series of more general observations about power. It is evident in the passage
that follows that Elias was, at least in part, developing these observations in
response to long dominant conventional Marxist and Weberian formulations
of power. He wrote:
[O]ne could see here the limitations of any theory which explains power
differentials only in terms of a monopolistic possession of non-human objects
such as weapons or means of production and disregards the figurational aspects
of power differentials due purely to differences in the degree of organisation of
the human beings concerned … [T]he latter, especially differences in the degree
of internal cohesion and communal control, can play a decisive part in the
greater power ratio of one group in relation to that of another … [In the small
community of Winston Parva], the power-superiority of the old-established group
was to a large extent of this type. It was based on the high degree of cohesion of
families who had known each other for two or three generations, in contrast to
the newcomers who were strangers in relation not only to the old residents but
also to each other. It was thanks to their greater potential for cohesion and its
activation by social control that the old residents were able to reserve offices in
their local organisations … for people of their own kind and firmly to exclude
from them people who lived in the other part [the ‘outsiders’] and who, as a
group, lacked cohesion … Exclusion and stigmatisation of the outsiders by the
established group, thus were two powerful weapons used by the latter to maintain
their identity, to assert their superiority, keeping the others firmly in their place.
(Elias and Scotson 2008: 4)
of the road of discovery about human societies’. ‘One might rather’, he added,
‘regard it as one manifestation of a beginning’ (Elias and Scotson 2008: 18).
In other words, Elias considered Marx to have developed an important and
significant insight in uncovering a fundamental inter-relationship between the
asymmetrical distribution of the means of production and a correspondingly
uneven distribution of the means of satisfying human material needs
(Elias and Scotson 2008: 18). However, Elias considered this to be only
partially correct since Marx presented the struggle over ‘economic’ goals as the
‘root source’ of conflict between dominant and subordinate groups such that,
‘to this day the pursuit of “economic” goals, elastic and ambiguous as this use
of the term “economic” is, appears to many people as the “real”, the basic goal
of human groups by comparison with which others appear to be less “real”,
whatever that may mean’ (Elias and Scotson 2008: 18).
Elias would not have sought to deny that Marx’s theory of class formation
deals with the generation of a particular form of social cohesion, namely that
involved in the transformation of disunited ‘classes in themselves’ (Klassen
an sich) into united ‘classes for themselves’ (Klassen für sich) (Bendix 1953:
30). What he would have denied is that such processes are to be universally
understood solely intra-societally and in relation to modes of production.
‘Economic’ forms are socially structured and socially structuring but, Elias
contended, they are not alone in that respect: other aspects of figurations which,
especially in an age of increasing and increasingly rapid globalisation, have
to be understood inter-societally and not simply intra-societally such as state-
formation which is influenced, among other things, by war, the length and density
of interdependency chains which have long since been spreading beyond national
borders, and the relative cohesion of and balance of power between groups, all
of which are equally structured and structuring and no less ‘real’. Under specific
circumstances, these other aspects enjoy degrees of autonomy in relation to and
even dominance over modes of production. That is, in this as in other aspects
of his work, Elias rejected the notion of universal ‘law-like’ relations between
supposedly constituent social ‘parts’ such as ‘the economy’, ‘the state’ and ‘civil
society’ (Elias 2009: 66–84). Consistent with this, he suggested that the degree
to which ‘economic’ conflicts are paramount in a society is partly a function of
the balance of power between its constituent groups. He wrote:
which they suffer. And it is in that situation that the struggle between established
and outsiders gradually ceases to be, on the part of the latter, simply a struggle for
stilling their hunger, for the means of physical survival, and becomes a struggle
for satisfying other human requirements as well. (Elias and Scotson 2008: 17–18)
From the day of its birth, a baby has power over its parents, not just the parents
over the baby. At least the baby has power over them as long as they attach …
value to it. If not, it loses its power … Equally bi-polar is the balance between
a slave and his [sic] master. The master has power over his slave, but the slave
also has power over his master, in proportion to his function for his master – his
master’s dependence on him. In relationships between parents and infants, masters
and slaves, power chances are distributed very unevenly. But whether the …
differentials are large or small, balances of power are always present wherever there
is functional interdependence between people … Power is not an amulet possessed
by one person and not by another; it is a structural characteristic of a relationship –
of all human relationships. (Elias 2012b: 69–70)
It is noteworthy that Elias wrote this in the late 1960s for publication in
a German book which appeared in 1970, for the seemingly straightforward
diagnosis that he offers is arguably sociologically profound. What Elias was
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 67
Of all the major sociologists of the twentieth century, especially its second
half, Elias was the one who argued most consistently in favour of an ‘historical
approach’. (The reasons why we have put ‘historical’ in inverted commas will
become clearer as our exposition of Elias unfolds.) In order fully to grasp what
he wrote on the subject of the sociology-history interface and the need for a
process-orientated view to be dominant in both subjects, it is necessary to have
an understanding of at least the basic elements of what he wrote on the subject
of time. The principal contribution that Elias had to offer in this regard is
best illustrated by comparing what he wrote with the views on this subject of
Anthony Giddens. According to Giddens in The Constitution of Society:
As the finitude of Dasein and as ‘the infinity of the emergence of being from
nothingness,’ time is perhaps the most enigmatic feature of human experience.
Not for nothing [sic] was that philosopher who has attempted to grapple in the
most fundamental way with the problem, Heidegger, compelled to use terminology
of the most daunting obscurity. But time, or the constitution of experience in
time-space, is also a banal and evident feature of … day-to-day life. It is in some part
the lack of ‘fit’ between our unproblematic coping with the continuity of conduct
across time-space, and its ineffable character when confronted philosophically,
that is the very essence of the puzzling nature of time. (Giddens 1984: 34–5)
Dasein is the German for ‘being’ or ‘existence’ and, following his interpretation
of Heidegger, Giddens is suggesting here that ‘time’ is unproblematic as a
‘common sense’, routine feature of daily life but massively problematic when
viewed philosophically because, in the latter context, we are unable to escape
‘ultimate’ issues of a kind that we humans can only ‘resolve’ inadequately
through the use of patently metaphysical ideas such as ‘absolute beginnings’,
‘ultimate origins’, ‘uncaused’ ‘first’ and ‘final causes’, and ‘being emerging from
nothingness’. Elias never pretended he had got anywhere near to solving the
‘mysteries’ of existence. As he expressed it in a poem in Luciad, the Leicester
student magazine in 1962, ‘There are no mysteries/only a lot I don’t know’.
He also claimed in conversations to have gone further than philosophers
such as Heidegger and philosophically-minded sociologists such as Giddens
regarding the understanding of time. More particularly, from Elias’s standpoint
both sides of the equation as formulated by Giddens are problematic. That is,
while ‘time’ may be a ‘banal and evident feature of human day-to-day life’ in
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 69
the modern world where we have inherited a workable calendar and efficient
devices such as clocks and watches for measuring what we call ‘time’, this has
not always been the case. According to Elias: ‘One forgets that for thousands
of years the calendars people used ran into trouble again and again; they had
to be reformed and improved until one … reached the near perfection the
European calendar has attained since the last calendar reform’ (Elias 2007b:
156–7). Indeed, so far from being ‘banal and evident’ is this taken-for-granted
feature of human life that there have been times when people were opposed to
calendar reforms because they believed they would shorten their lives!
The other side of what Giddens wrote is problematic because he does
not appear to have considered the possibility that the ‘daunting obscurity’
of Heidegger’s terminology may have been connected, not so much with the
properties of ‘time’ as with the fact that Heidegger approached the problem
in a purely rational and quasi-theological manner. More particularly, while
the problems associated with ‘time’ remain complex if approached in a more
theoretico-empirical manner, they are not necessarily ‘daunting’ and ‘obscure’.
At the most basic level, they are relatively straightforward. That is, ‘time’ is
a concept which, in Elias’s sociological terms, refers to a symbolic ‘means of
orientation’ through which humans coordinate their lives – ‘I’ll meet you in the
pub at 6.15’; ‘the plane leaves Heathrow Airport at 18.30’; – and communicate
their understanding of natural and sociohistorical processes of various kinds –
‘light travels at 186,000 miles per second’; ‘the Nazi dictatorship came to an
end in 1945’. The reality of ‘time’ is as a social, collectively produced symbol in
a world where only natural processes and events, including processes and events
at the human-social level, occur; where, we might say, only events and processes
of various kinds are ‘real’. That, at least, was Elias’s view. He expressed it thus:
So, processes and events, not symbols, are the only substantives, and ‘time’
is a humanly constructed symbol, not a process like a flowing river or an event
like a flood. Furthermore, ‘every change in “space” is a change in “time”;
[and] every change in “time” [is] a change in “space”’ (Elias 2007b: 82).
70 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY
Part of the reason why is that the earth is constantly moving round the sun
and the sun is part of a galaxy, ‘the Milky Way’, that, with the exception
of local galaxies such as Andromeda which are moving towards us, is
moving away at speed from the billions of other galaxies which constitute
the currently known universe. We propose not to elaborate on the concepts
of ‘space’ and ‘time’ any further here, except to add that, just as people
today are the inheritors of more reality-congruent time symbols and
more accurate time meters such as atomic clocks and the quartz watches
that we in the more ‘advanced’ societies carry round on our wrists, so, too,
are we the inheritors of a fund of more reality-congruent knowledge about
‘space’, especially the ‘local space’, namely the earth and the solar system,
which we inhabit. That is, we have not only more effective calendars and
chronometers – time-measuring devices – but also more detailed and reliable
maps and devices such as compasses, radar, satellites and global positioning
systems (‘sat navs’) for accurately measuring relative positions in ‘space-
time’. Our technologically buttressed abilities in these regards are crucial to
the operation of the networks of global and local interdependence which
characterise the present-day world.
The principal relevance for sociology of these issues is that the subject ought
to be centrally concerned with the study of social events and processes in space
and time. This means that the conventional view according to which sociology
and history are separate subjects, one concerned with ‘the present’, the other
with ‘the past’, is arbitrary and wrong. All studies are necessarily studies of ‘the
past’. A moment’s reflection will show how this is so. Human societies exist in
space-time, and time, as the old personifying adage has it, ‘never stands still’.
To express it non-metaphysically, human individuals, their societies, the earth,
our solar system, the Milky Way and the universe are processes, constantly
moving, constantly changing. This means that what we call the ‘present’ is a
constantly shifting reference point in the ceaseless flow of physical, biological,
social and individual processes and events. What was ‘the present’ on all these
levels when we started writing this chapter had already become part of the
past when we completed it. In a word, ‘the present’ is an ambiguous concept
with multiple levels of meaning and it has to be read as having an historical
connotation. It follows that, if it were to be accepted that sociology is the study
of ‘the present’, some more or less arbitrary judgement about the relatively
recent past would have to be made. One would have to decide whether the term
‘past’ refers to, say, the 1990s, the 2000s, or the 2010s, to the years since the
1960s, or to those since the end of the Second World War. However, whatever
decision was made, any such studies would necessarily involve attempts to
come to terms with aspects of ‘the past’. In short, it would inevitably lead one
to become involved in a kind of ‘historical’ study. Elias commented upon this
fundamental relationship between sociology and history in some detail as we
shall now discuss.
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 71
These observations, said Elias, suggest that there are ‘different degrees of
uniqueness and unrepeatability, and what is unique and unrepeatable on one
level can be seen on another as repetition, a return of the never-changing’. Take,
for example, the often claimed uniqueness of individual human beings – one of
the reasons advanced for the impossibility of a ‘scientific’ history or a ‘scientific’
sociology. According to Elias, it provides a good example of a phenomenon
that involves uniqueness on one level and repeatability on another. That is so,
Elias said, because ‘individual human beings are themselves repetitions of an
unchanging form, and what differs between people now appears as a variation
of the ever-recurring basic pattern’ (Elias 2006b: 10).
This observation allows Elias to question how ‘object adequate’ or ‘reality
congruent’ – in more popular terms, how ‘accurate’ – is the argument that
history consists of a unique sequence of unrepeatable events. Is it, he asked,
a product of unprejudiced critical analysis or the result of an ideological
manipulation in which the practitioners of history in highly differentiated and
individualised societies project their specific social conditioning and short-lived
72 NORBERT ELIAS AND MODERN SOCIOLOGY
values onto their ‘object of study, the historical process itself’? This question,
said Elias, cannot be answered in simple ‘yes/no’, terms; nor can it be reduced
to a simple formula. Elias stressed the need to define clearly both the differences
and the relationships between ‘biological evolution’, ‘social development’ and
‘history’. The failure to do this up to now, said Elias, has acted as a blockage
to knowledge.
Elias also contended that the biological constitution of social insects
such as ants and bees is both relatively fixed and determines their social
organisation. The evolution of Homo sapiens has led our species, too, to have
a relatively fixed biological constitution. However, it is one which makes
individual members of the species dependent on experience and learning.
Humans have to learn in order to be able to function and it is this which
makes it possible for human societies to have a history and to develop, that is
to undergo changes of structure or form. According to Elias, however, while
the biological evolution of Homo sapiens cannot be reversed – though the
species could, of course, become extinct and, when our sun ‘dies’, probably
will unless we have managed by then to transfer to a new habitable planet
in a new sun system – their social development is reversible. As Elias put it:
Measured by the length and rate of change of an individual human life, social
developments often take place so slowly that they seem to stand still. It is
possible that the … figurations formed by people change so little for a number
of generations that they are regarded by those involved as immutable … Thus,
for a long period in the development of European society, people are embraced
over and over … by the figuration ‘knight-page-priest-bondsman’. Today, and
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 73
than vice versa; Darwin as having delivered the second, that is, the biological
blow, by discovering such basic facts about humans as that they had evolved
out of earlier species of hominids; and the third, psychological blow that was
delivered by Freud himself with regard to his highly influential and important
thesis regarding the human repression of libidinal impulses.
In a manner that parallels Copernicus with respect to our solar system and
astronomy, Elias pointed the way towards a sociology in which a resolution by
means of theory-guided empirical research and research-based theorising could
take the place of merely thinking about such age-old philosophical/sociological
issues as the agency-structure dilemma (nominalism versus realism), the nature/
society dichotomy, the nature versus nurture problem, body-mind dualism,
materialism versus idealism, and many more. Elias’s conceptual reorientation –
aspects of which we have begun to explore in this chapter – has arguably laid the
foundations for a ‘post-philosophical’ (Kilminster 2007) model for approaching
such problems.
As was typical of Elias, he viewed his own contribution to sociology in terms
of evolutionary scale processes of human development. In his text The Symbol
Theory, Elias wrote of humans as having become equipped via evolution to
undergo a process of ‘symbol emancipation’, that is, a potentially liberating
increase in power and control made possible by language and knowledge-
stocks in four main areas: (i) over their wider environment; (ii) relative to
other animals, of humans developing from a ‘hunted’ into a ‘hunting’ species
(Goudsblom 1994); (iii) over themselves as individuals; and (iv) over themselves
as groups. A related notion is what Elias (1978: 156–7) called ‘the triad of basic
controls’, that is, the control of self, society, and nature. Symbol emancipation,
Elias suggested, must have involved simultaneous and interacting processes
of biological evolution and social development, each mutually dependent on
and not reducible to the other. Such processes are still far from being fully
understood and the difficulty of understanding them is inhibited by a tendency
to distinguish, as we have seen, between, for example, ‘nature’ and ‘society’, as
if ‘societies’ could exist somewhere other than in ‘nature’. The institutionally
reinforced distinction between the ‘social sciences’ and the ‘natural sciences’
contributes further to the inhibition. In Elias’s words:
Most of [the social sciences], history and sociology among them, are concerned
with aspects of human life which are uniquely human, which in other words
are, or are due to, evolutionary innovations. They distinguish humanity from
other species. As a rule, however, these human sciences … do not ask how these
uniquely human properties are connected with those which humans share with
other species, such as birth and death … [N]o attempts are made … to discover
the hinge connecting nature with … ‘non-nature’. Thus sociologists may see the
body as a topic of interest. But the prevailing routines … make it easy to treat
the body as a topic of sociological research set apart from other topics, perhaps
as the subject-matter of a specialism. There does not seem any need to explore
the links connecting aspects of humans conceived as body, with other aspects
SOME BASIC CONCEPTS OF FIGURATIONAL SOCIOLOGY 75