The Sacred Quality of The Political Hobb
The Sacred Quality of The Political Hobb
The Sacred Quality of The Political Hobb
By Tracy B. Strong*
To read Carl Schmitt in the context of Paul and Hobbes is, among other
things, to raise the question of the relation of significant elements of the
Western tradition to the thought and political choices of Carl Schmitt. If
Schmitt joined the NSDAP by mistake – not clear what it was, thinking it
merely a more effective form of German nationalism – then it is hard to
account for his remaining in the Party and his silence about it after the
defeat. If he joined it by accident – thinking that this happened to be the
best path to his advancement and for his career, then his thought will at
most be only contingently relation to National Socialism. This we can re
ject: too many people have seen links for us, again in the face of Schmitt’s
postwar silence, for us simply to excuse or overlook.3
We are left with the fact that reading Schmitt in the context of thinkers
such as Hobbes and St. Paul raises that there are many paths to take from
within what are apparently our best traditions.
remains night. If you wish to inquire, then come again and inquire.” (Isaiah, xxi,
11–12).
3 See Volker Neumann, “Carl Schmitt: Introduction,” in: Arthur Jacobson / Bern
hard Schlink (eds.), Weimar: A Jurisprudence of Crisis, University of California
Press, 2000, p. 282. On the distinction of “mistake” and “accident” and the moral
difference it makes, see J. L. Austin, “A Plea for Excuses,” in his Philosophical
Papers, Oxford, Clarendon, 1963.
4 See e. g. Gustavo Gutiérrez, A Theology of Liberation: History, Politics, Salva
tion, Revised edition: Orbis books. New York, 1988.
5 See Walter Rauschenbusch, Christianity and the Social Crisis, New York, Mac
Millan, 1908, chapter Seven (“What To Do”).
6 Heinrich Meier has argued that Schmitt has a theological politics and contrasts
Schmitt to Leo Strauss’ philosophical politics. (Heinrich Meier, The Lesson of Carl
Schmitt: Four Chapters on the Distinction between Political Theology and Political
Philosophy, trans. Marcus Brainard, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998. I
think rather that Schmitt has a political theology, that is that the way in which he
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 3
The political realm – and thus the reality of the human – was, for Schmitt,
in danger of disappearing. In modern times he saw it being replaced by two
realms. One realm was the supposedly neutral space of scientific technique, in
which rational and logical conclusions – neutral with regard to human beings
– were attainable. “Heute ist nichts moderner als der Kampf gegen das Poli-
tische. … Es soll nur das organisatorish-technische und Ökonomisch-soziolo-
gische Aufgaben, aber keine politischen probleme mehr geben.11” In 1929,
Schmitt will lecture on Barcelona on this topic as “Das Zeitalter der Neutral-
isierungen und Entpolitisierungen”12 The decline or disappearance of the po
litical is itself always for Schmitt a “political matter,” as he makes clear in the
preface to the second edition of PT. If, however, the political is in danger of
disappearing as a human form of life, this can only be because sovereignty as
Schmitt understands it is increasingly not a constituent part of our present
world. Thus in his 1938 book on Hobbes, he will write “die Mechanisierung
der Staatsvorstellung hat die Mechanisierung des anthropologischen Bildes
vom Menschen vollendet.”13 Schmitt, with explicit reference to Max Weber,
sees danger in the increasing sense of the State as “ein grosser Betrieb.”
(PT 69 / 65) Increasingly this plant “läuft jetzt von selbst [und] dadurch geht
das dezisionistische und personalistische Element des bisherigen Sou-
veränitätsbegriffes verloren.”14 (PT 52 / 48) Schmitt sees it as his role to re
cover that element for the contemporary period.
The Barcelona lecture was published in 1930 and was added to the 1932
edition of The Concept of the Political: Schmitt thought of it as part of his
general argument in that book. As the political is for Schmitt the realm of
that which is truly human,15 his distress is that the West is loosing touch
with that which gives life human meaning. As he develops his argument in
this article, the contemporary West stands at the end of a series of “central
11 Carl Schmitt, Politische Theologie, Berlin. Duncker & Humblot, [1022] 2004,
p. 68. Henceforth “PT xx” in the text. English edition as Political Theology, trans.
George Schwab with a Foreword by Tracy B. Strong, Chicago, University of Chi
cago Press, 2005. Page numbers in text as PT xx (German) / yy (English): “Today
nothing is more modern than the onslaught against the political … There must be
no longer be political problems, only organizationaltechnical and economicsocio
logical ones.” (English PT 65).
12 BPZN 79–95.
13 Carl Schmitt, Der Leviathan in der Staatslehre des Thomas Hobbes: Sinn und
Feldschlag eines politischen Symbols, Stuttgart, KlettCotta, 1995, p. 60 “… the
mechanization of the conception of the State has ended by bringing about the
mechanization of the anthropological understanding of human beings.”
14 “A huge industrial plant” … “runs on its own … [and] the decisionistic and
personalistic element in the concept of sovereignty is lost.”
15 See Strauss, “Notes on Carl Schmitt,” par. 1, in: Carl Schmitt, The Concept of
the Political, Chicago, 1995, p. 83. See footnote 7 above.
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 5
16 “If a sphere of thought becomes central, then the problems of other spheres
are solved in terms of the central sphere – they are considered secondary problems
whose solution follows as a matter of course only if the problems of the central
sphere are solved.”
17 This periodisation can be also be found in shorter form in the 1934 preface to
Politische Theologie, pp. 1–2. The stages are well discussed in Henning Ottmann,
“Das Zeitalter der Neutralisierungen und EntTotalisierungen: Carl Schmitts Theorie
der Neuzeit,” in: Reinhard Mehring (ed.), Carl Schmitt. Der Begriff des Politischen.
Ein Kooperativer Kommentar, Akademie Verlag. Berlin, 2003, pp. 156–169. See the
more extensive discussion in my foreword to Political Theology.
18 A contemporary edition is Julien Benda, Le trahison des clercs, Les cahiers
rouges. Grasset, 2003.
19 Jacob Taubes, The Political Theology of Paul, Stanford, Stanford UP, 2004),
writes that “He [Schmitt] is a clerk, and he understands his task not to be to estab
lish the law but to interpret the law.” (p. 103).
6 Tracy B. Strong
The central quality of all transformations that have led to our present
stage – “technicity” – is the “striving for a neutral sphere.” For Europe, the
attraction of a neutral sphere is that is seemed to provide a solution to the
conflicts that had grown up out of quarrels over theology. It transformed the
concepts elaborated “in vielen Jahrhunderten theologischen Denkens” into
what are for Schmitt “jetzt … Privatsachen.” (BPZN 89)20 However, each
stage of neutralization became, in Schmitt’s analysis, merely the next arena
of struggle. Thus what someone like John Rawls sees as one of the most
important achievements of the West – religious toleration – is for Schmitt
merely the prelude to another form of conflict.
The central question now therefore is what conflicts will arise when the
central sphere is technicity, which, “eben weil sie jemand dient, ist … nicht
neutral.” (BPZN 90)21 Here Schmitt finds himself in opposition to thinkers
like Weber, Troeltsch and Rathenau, whom he reads as in despair before the
“Entzauberung der Welt”. If one follows them, Schmitt says, one will de
spair, for the world will appear only as what Weber called a “stahlhartes
Gehäuse” with no way out, not even a look.22 This leads to quietism or
despair, the most important danger now confronting Europe. This danger
arises because it is Russia (i. e. the USSR) who has understood and seized
technicity and made it its own in the new arena of conflict. Only in Russia
does one now find a sense of a new “strong politics.”
Schmitt writes somewhat chillingly in Der Begriff des Politischen that
“[d]adurch, dass ein Volk nicht mehr die Kraft oder den Willen hat, sich in
der Sphäre des Politischen zuhalten, verschwindet das Politische nicht aus
der Welt. Es verschwindet nur ein schwaches Volk.”23 He thus closes his
Barcelona article with a truncated citation from Vergil’s “Fourth Eclogue”:
Ab integro nascitur ordo. The full line is “Magnus ab integro seclorum
nascitur ordo” which translates as “a great order of the ages is born from
the renewal.” Schmitt’s abbreviated line means “an order is born from the
renewal.”24 The eloquent two closing paragraphs of Schmitt’s article are in
effect a call for the West to be equal to the need for this renewed conflict
and to oppose the forces of Communism. (Here Schmitt shares concerns
with Heidegger). And this is at the core of his claim that ours is an age of
“neutralisation and depoliticization”: whereas previous eras still had leaders
and decisionmakers, the era of technology and technological progress is
different in that increasingly it has no need of actual individual persons.25
What is wrong with technicity? The danger and problem with technicity
is that it claims to have personneutral ways of solving disputes. The “or
ganisationtechnical” method is characterised by three epistemological pre
suppositions. The first is that one can make a clearcut conceptual separation
between facts and values and that, in consequence, values were subjective,
not of the world, and could be kept apart from ones analysis of social real
ity. This was not a denial that values were “important” but it was a denial
that values were objects of knowledge.26
A second claim was parent to the first. It was a claim that propositions
about the world could and should be made to speak for themselves – thus
that propositions about the world should have a validity independent of he
or she who advanced them. One could and should clearly separate the
speaker from the spoken, for if one did one’s work right not just empirical
claims about the world but concepts themselves would stand independently
of the speaker. In its simplest form, the claim was that a statement like
“mass equals force times acceleration” was true independently of who said
it and of when and where it was said.
The third claim derived from the first two. It held that certain forms of
discourse (claims to knowledge) were responsible and responsive to the
real world in ways that other forms (one might think of them as emotive,
or expressive) were not.27 In the first but not the second, the expectation
was that the world would correct mistakes is an erroneous analysis.
prophecy of the coming of Christ. The last entry in Schmitt’s Glossarium (published
in 1991) reads: “Mit jedem neugeborenen Kind wird eine neue Welt geboren.” He
goes on to hope that the child will be an “Aggressor.”
25 This periodisation can be found explicitly in the Barcelona address and is
implicit in the first several pages of chapter three of PT; it is made explicit in
shorter form in the 1934 preface to PT, pp. 1–2. The stages are well discussed in
Henning Ottmann, “Das Zeitalter der Neutralisierungen und EntTotalisierungen: Carl
Schmitts Theorie der Neuzeit”, in: Reinhard Mehring (ed.), Carl Schmitt. Der
Begriff des Politischen. Ein Kooperativer Kommentar, Akademie Verlag. Berlin,
2003, pp. 156–169.
26 See James Conant, “Must We Show What We Cannot Say,” in: Paul Guyer /
Hilary Putnam (eds.), The Senses of Stanley Cavell, esp. p. 252–253.
27 See the discussion in Stanley Cavell, Themes Out of School, Chicago, 1984,
36.
8 Tracy B. Strong
Along with science, and perversely companion to it, Schmitt saw the
arising of a second realm, the realm of aesthetic subjectivity. The transition
to the Technizität sphere is made possible, Schmitt argues by an “Ästheti-
sierung aller geistigen Gebiete [aestheticization of all sectors of the spirit].”
(BPZN 83) This is the epistemological basis for his critique of liberalism
as a clasa discutora, unable to come to any decision on anything because
all decisions appear the same. If the scientific realm held out a method for
resolving some disputes, the aestheticization of the rest of the world – of
that portion not amenable to scientific resolution – subjectivized it and held
that was no way to resolve those disputes if they could not be resolved by
science.
Thus liberal scienticism and romanticism come together – two sides of
the same modern coin. From this we get his lapidary sentence from The
Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy: If a liberal is asked “Christ or Barra
bas, he responds with a proposal to adjourn or appoint a committee of
investigation.”28
Responding to the double bind of modern society, Schmitt argues that in
such a context the recovery of the political realm must of necessity come
from outside the liberalromantic world, that is, it cannot be justified in
terms of the categories of that world. It must come, as Herbert Marcuse
argued, from a state whose only “justification is its existence”29 – or rather
its practice. Justification must be ontological rather than epistemological.
But how can something come to have the quality of being convincingly
present to us, such that it serves as an authority? I believe the model for
Schmitt’s approach to these questions has its origin in Kant’s Kritik der
30 “Genius” is one of the topoi of nineteenth century thought. See the account in
Jochen Schmidt, Die Geschichte des GenieGedankens in der deutschen Literatur,
Philosophie und Politik, 1750–1945. 2 volumes, Darmstadt, 1985, which covers
thinkers from Klopstock and Lessing, through Kant to Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and
the twentieth century, albeit not always unconventionally. On Kant see also Giorgio
Tonelli, “Kant’s Early Theory of Genius (1770–1779): Part I,” in: Journal of the
History of Philosophy, v. IV (1966): 10931 and “Part II,” in: ibid., v. V, pp. 209–24.
Thanks to Jackob Pyetranker for calling these articles to my attention.
31 See for instance, F. Nietzsche, Die Fröhliche Wissenschaft, # 105. I am in
debted here to several conversations with Professor Alexander Rehding of the Har
vard Music Department.
32 I. Kant, Kritik der Urteilskraft [henceforth KU] § 45, Akademie edition: 5.306.
33 As Dieter Henrich, Aesthetic Judgment and the Moral Image of the World,
Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA, 1992, writes: “We must … wonder how
understanding, in its lawfulness, can enter a situation that cannot be elucidated by
reference to the constitutive usage of the categories and that precludes general con
cepts.” (p. 47).
34 KU § 6 (5.211).
10 Tracy B. Strong
“Genie ist das Talent (Naturgabe), welches der Kunst die Regel giebt.”35
The genius has the complete freedom of incomprehensibility. “Der Urheber
eines Products, welches er seinem Genie verdankt, selbst nicht weiß, wie
sich in ihm die Ideen dazu herbei finden, auch es nicht in seiner Gewalt
hat, dergleichen nach Belieben oder planmäßig auszudenken und anderen
in solchen Vorschrifte.”36 This is originality, which means for Kant that
what the genius accomplishes cannot be confined to, nor explained by, any
systematic understanding or procedure. In the Anthropology, Kant is clear
that the word applies only to an “artist” and only to the artist who does
something original. Later in that book he can write that “Das Genie glänzt
daher als augenblickliche, mit Intervallen sich zeigende und wieder ver-
schwindende Erscheinung nicht mit einem willkürlich angezündeten und
eine beliebige Zeit fortbrennenden Licht, sondern wie sprühende Funken,
welche eine glückliche Anwandelung des Geistes aus der productiven Ein-
bildungskraft auslockt.”37 Here it is worth noting that even Newton does not
count as a genius for what he did could be set out for all to understand and
thus could in principle have been discovered by others.38
It seems to me clear from this that the actual operation of genius remains
a bit of a mystery for Kant. Thus he must ascribe it to a “happy seizure of
the spirit.” This mysterious quality is all the more important in that Kant
thinks that a work of art (of true art) has the quality of providing grounds
for others to judge and of at the same time providing the structure – as we
might call it – for their mutual comprehensibility. Kant will say that “Die
Einbildungskraft (als produktives Erkenntnisvermögen) ist nämlich sehr
mächtig in Schaffung gleichsam einer andern Natur, aus dem Stoffe, den ihr
die wirkliche gibt”39 Thus Novalis will in the last decade of the XVIIIth
KU § 46 ff (5.307ff).
35
KU § 46 (5. 308) “He does not know himself how the ideas for [the beautiful
36
work of art] come to him, and also does not have it in his power to think up such
things at will or according to plan, and to communicate to others precepts that
would put them in apposition to produce similar products.”
37 Anthropologie (5.318n) “Genius … glitters like a momentary phenomenon
which appears and disappears at intervals, and vanishes again. It is not a light that
can be kindled at will and kept burning for a period of one’s choosing, but it is
rather like a spark scattering flash which a happy seizure of the spirit entices from
the productive imagination.”
38 KU § 47 (5.309).
39 Ibid § 49 (5.314). “the imagination (as a productive cognitive faculty) is,
namely, very powerful in creating, as it were, another nature, out of the material
which the real one gives to it.”
I suspect that it is in response to this that Nietzsche can write in “Vom Nutzen
und Nachteil der Historie für das Leben” (HL 3 WKG III1 p. 261): “Denn da wir
nun einmal die Resultate früherer Geschlechter sind, sind wir auch die Resultate
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 11
The frontispiece to the Leviathan is justly famous and has recently been
subject to an important commentary by Horst Bredekamp.42 Let us note
some additional qualities of the engraving:
− The giant who appears on the horizon has the quality of always being in
view. When one comes out for ones newspaper in the morning, the Le
viathan is there, just as it was when you went to bed.
− The body of the giant is composed of individually distinguishable beings
all of who face towards the giant; like a theater audience they have an
intransitive relationship to that which they behold. You see their backs
just as one does when seated in the theater. (Their orientation is, inciden
tally, a change, requested by Hobbes, from an earlier version where the
artist drew them facing outwards).
− Under the picture is a double escutcheon (Schild); the banner uniting
them proclaims this to be a book about a “Commonwealth Ecclesiastical
and Civil.” The important word there is the “and” which joins the instru
ments of civil power on the left to the ecclesiastical ones on the right.
Thus Rousseau in the Contrat Social (iv, 8) writes that Hobbes “[d]e tous
les Auteurs Chrétiens … est le seul qui ait bien vû le mal et le remède,
qui ait osé proposer de réunir les deux têtes de l’aigle, et de tout ram-
ener à l’unité politique, sans laquelle jamais Etat ni Gouvernement ne
sera bien constitué, qui a su réunir les deux têtes de l’aigle.”43
− Over everything there is a citation from Scripture, the book of Job (Hiob):
“Non est potestas super terram quae comparetur. (Auf Erden ist nicht
seines gleichen).” The verse continues to say that the Leviathan is “with
out fear.”
The passage from Hiob comes at the end of a sequence that begins in
book 38 with a comparison of God to a geometer or an architect.
[1] Und der HERR antwortete Hiob aus dem Wettersturm und sprach:
[2] Wer ist’s, der den Ratschluß verdunkelt mit Worten ohne Verstand?
[3] Gürte deine Lenden wie ein Mann! Ich will dich fragen, lehre mich an
[4] Wo warst du, als ich die Erde gründete? Sage mir’s, wenn du so klug bist!
[5] Weißt du, wer ihr das Maß gesetzt hat oder wer über sie die Richtschnur
gezogen hat?
[6] Worauf sind ihre Pfeiler eingesenkt, oder wer hat ihren Eckstein gelegt,
[7] als mich die Morgensterne miteinander lobten und jauchzten alle Gottessöhne?44
I do not think it an accident that Hobbes places Scripture over everything.
The particular citation is a citation that describes what would be an absolute
and unquestionable authority, as least on this earth. (It is thus significant
that Hobbes was a Christian mortalist, i.e that he believed that the soul died
with the body and would be reborn together only at the Last Judgment. If
there were an independently existing soul the thisearth focus would be
called into question – cf Lev. 38, 44).
Put these points about the frontispiece together and we find that the Com
monwealth requires (1) a single, absolute power in and as which we all
exist; (2) that the Sovereign has no fear (of death, especially45); and (3) that
the existence of the commonwealth is brought about by art – poiesis.
The need for this single absolute power derives from the fact that Hobbes
knows there to be two kinds of knowledge. The first is natural or mathe
matical and as he says in the dedication to Humane Nature is “free from
controversy.” (English Works 4.xiii). The second kind of knowledge of
which Leviathan is possibly a first exemplar is also knowledge, but knowl
edge in which profit and pleasure intervene. About such knowledge there
44 1. Then the Lord answered Job out of the whirlwind, and said,
2. Who is this that darkeneth counsel by words without knowledge?
3. Gird up now thy loins like a man; for I will demand of thee, and answer thou
me.
4. Where wast thou when I laid the foundations of the earth? declare, if thou hast
understanding.
5. Who hath laid the measures thereof, if thou knowest? or who hath stretched the
line upon it?
6. Whereupon are the foundations thereof fastened? or who laid the corner stone
thereof;
7. When the morning stars sang together, and all the sons of God shouted for joy?
45 It is worth noting that Hobbes spent a lot of time convincing people that they
were in fact afraid of violent death, something that the history of the preceding
quartercentury called into serious question.
14 Tracy B. Strong
46 See Ted H. Miller, “The Uniqueness of Leviathan,” in: T. Sorrell (ed.), Levia
than After 350 Years, Cambridge UP, 2001, as well as Douglas M. Jesseph, Squar
ing the Circle: The War Between Hobbes and Wallis, Chicago. University of Chi
cago Press, 2000.
47 T. Hobbes, “Six Lessons for the Professors of Mathematics,” English Works,
Molesworth Edition, volume 7: 184.
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 15
It is a question much disputed between the divers sects of Christian religion, from
whence the Scriptures derive their authority; which question is also propounded
sometimes in other terms, as, how we know them to be the word of God, or, why
we believe them to be so: and the difficulty of resolving it, ariseth chiefly from
the improperness of the words wherein the question itself is couched. For it is
believed on all hands, that the first and original author of them is God; and
consequently the question disputed, is not that. Again, it is manifest, that none can
know they are God’s word, (though all true Christians believe it,) but those to
whom God himself hath revealed it supernaturally; and therefore the question is
not rightly moved, of our knowledge of it. Lastly, when the question is pro
pounded of our belief; because some are moved to believe for one, and others for
other reasons, there can be rendered no one general answer for them all. The
question truly stated is, by what authority they are made law.
From what and how is the commonwealth made? Hobbes criticizes the
Descartes’ development (in the “Second Meditation”) of the cogito from the
act of thinking to a “spirit, a soul, an understanding, a reason.” Hobbes is
perfectly happy to say that he is a thing that thinks (that is a body) but he
resists Descartes’ move to selfconsciousness by arguing that Descartes
would thereby commit himself to an endless regress.50 Hobbes must refer
the act of thinking to a corporeal, material, thisworldly being. He makes
these moves as early as 1640 in De Corpore but they are central to his
notion of sovereignty as an artificial soul, existing only when the Leviathan
is animated by living persons.
We find that this Leviathan is brought into existence in a manner analo
gous to God’s creation of the world. This is poiesis.
“For by art is created that great Leviathan called a Commonwealth, or State, (in
Latin Civitas) which is but an artificial man; though of greater stature and strength
than the natural, for whose protection and defense it was intended;” (L.
Introduction).51
What makes this art possible? In the “Introduction,” Hobbes gives us the
means:
[T]here is a saying much usurped of late, that wisdom is acquired, not by reading
of books, but of men. Consequently whereunto, those persons, that for the most
part can give no other proof of being wise, take great delight to show what they
think they have read in men, by uncharitable censures of one another behind their
backs. But there is another saying not of late understood, by which they might
learn truly to read one another, if they would take the pains; and that is, nosce
teipsum, read thyself: which was not meant, as it is now used, to countenance,
either the barbarous state of men in power, towards their inferiors; or to encourage
men of low degree, to a saucy behaviour towards their betters; but to teach us,
that for the similitude of the thoughts and passions of one man, to the thoughts
and passions of another, whosoever looketh into himself, and considereth what he
doth, when he does think, opine, reason, hope, fear, &c. and upon what grounds;
he shall thereby read and know, what are the thoughts and passions of all other
men upon the like occasions.52
The art of bringing the Leviathan into existence is based on reading
oneself; indeed, the most stunning part of this declaration of intention is
Hobbes’ translation of nosce teipsum. It clearly means “know thyself” yet
Hobbes gives it immediately and pointedly as “read thyself.”53 Such reading
he goes on to say will cause the characters to become legible. When we
have read we will have read what is in the heart of each of us. We will
have read ourselves as we construct of artificial man who is the Sovereign
and the commonwealth.
How can this happen that I find a text I myself, that I know that I am a
text? How then can I know that you have found the same text and thus that
we have found each other as we found ourselves, that this text is the au
thoritative base of our commonality? It is not easy: in the “Appendix” to
the Latin edition of Leviathan, Hobbes writes:
“Natural law is eternal, divine and inscribed only in human hearts. But there are
very few men who know who to examine their own heart and read what is writ
ten there? Thus it is from written laws that men know what they must do or
avoid.”54
Hobbes understands his book as that which he has read in his and thus
in our heart: most of us cannot so read. What is in my heart is what is in
yours and Hobbes has made us a present of it and made us present to it by
his book. What if he is wrong? Here his position is like that of Luther on
conscience: if we can convince him that he is wrong, he will change his
52 Hobbes may have in mind the poem “Nosce Te Ipsum” by Sir John Davies
(English lawyer, Speaker of the Irish Parliament, and Lord Chief Justice who lived
from 1569 to 1626). See Ted H. Miller, “The Uniqueness of Leviathan,” in: T. Sor
rell (ed.), Leviathan After 350 Years, Cambridge. Cambridge UP, p. 97
53 For a more extensive discussion see my “How to Write Scripture: Words, Au
thority and Politics in Thomas Hobbes,” Critical Inquiry 1993 (20:1) pp. 128–159
and “When Is a Text Not a Pretext? A Rejoinder to Victoria Silver,” pp. 172–178 in
the same issue. See also Gary Shapiro, “Reading and Writing in the Text of Hobbes’
Leviathan,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 18 [April, 1980], 147–157.
54 See Thomas Hobbes, Léviathan (ed. F. Tricaud) Paris, Siley, 1988, p. 700.
I note that Davies’s poem contains the lines:
We interpret lawes, which other men haue made,
But reade not those which in our hearts are writ.
18 Tracy B. Strong
mind.55 (As we known, Hobbes was somewhat hard to convince that he was
wrong as he produced over ten proofs for the squaring of the circle).
What however is inscribed as the Leviathan? It is words that are in our
(each of us) heart. At the beginning of the gospel of John we find that “Im
Anfang war das Wort … Und das Wort ward Fleisch und wohnte unter uns.”
Christ is thus an incarnation of the word. The Leviathan is also a making
flesh – more precisely a making of artificial flesh, at once God, Man, mon
ster, and machine – of the words that are in our heart. Hobbes was worried
that he might be thought to be making a mere automaton – only a machine
– and he explicitly places the Leviathan on a higher level than a mere au
tomaton. (“Art goes yet further [then automata], imitating that rational and
most excellent work of nature, man”). The creature that is made is in fact
the civilphilosophical equivalent of Christ in that he / she / it is a “mortal
god” and a man.
Thus I do not think that Hobbes is best understood as being about “agree
ment,” as is often argued. Hobbes wants his readers to acknowledge – the
covenant is the acknowledgement – that the conditions laid out by him in
Leviathan are in fact in each of us, and that as they are mine so also are
they yours. That we resist them is the secular equivalent of original sin and
the source for our legitimation of a power over us. The move may appear
secular but it has a sacral structure.
What this means is that for Hobbes the Leviathan is the incarnation of
the words in our hearts – and what is in our hearts is material that we find
hard to read and to acknowledge. The Leviathan is an incarnation (albeit
poietic) of words that are in each of us but which will ordinarily only be
recognised when it is made visible such that we can read it in the laws and
words of the Sovereign. (Thus Hobbes wanted the Leviathan to be taught
in the universities, much as Scripture was taught in church. Leviathan is, to
draw upon Wittgenstein, intended as the “grammar” of the political). What
is attained with the Leviathan is our recognition of our commonalty with
all those others who have given themselves the common text of each. The
Sovereign is us, is what is in each of our hearts, something that Hobbes has
read even if we have not been able to. (Hobbes is then not so much the
author of the Leviathan as its transcriber).
5. This produces what Hobbes calls a “real unity,” what is called homothu-
madon (“with a common thumos”), a doctrine associated with the corpus
mysticum doctrine of the Church by Roman Catholicism and taken over
by Hobbes for the commonwealth;56
6. Finally if the Leviathan is a “mortal god” then it is the Christ – at least
in the matters with which civil philosophy is concerned.
What Hobbes has done is to combine a tradition of covenanting that
derives from Protestantism with the Catholic tradition of the corpus mysti-
cum. In this way an act of will produces an unquestionable and authoritative
unity.57 The reason that the sovereign cannot be questioned is that the sov
ereign is my incarnation of myself, of a self that I most often wish to avoid.
I am the author of the acts of the Sovereign and they are thus my acts. For
Hobbes humans become human, or realise their humanity, accede to some
thing more than what Giorgio Agamben calls “bare life” only when they
submit themselves to an authority that they have themselves authorized. The
state is a consequence to the convenant and is a katechon in that it holds
back the civil war which threatens constantly.58
a) Christianity on Earth
56 See e. g. Acts 1.14; 2.46; Romans 15.6. See James Edwards, “Unity Not of
Our Making,” Christianity Today, Aug 6, 2001 (Vol. 45, No. 10) pp. 48–50. See also
Vatican II, Dogmatic Constitution on the Church, 11: “Strengthened in holy Com
munion by the body of Christ, [the faithful] manifest in a concrete way the unity of
the people of God that this sacrament aptly signifies and wondrously causes”. It may
also be the case as Bredekamp argues, that Hobbes draws on the tradition of the
Gnostic corpus hermeticum. But although that tradition did indeed have many rep
resentations of bodies making up a body, it is also the case that such detailed rep
resentations were common at the time.
57 As Jacques Maritain was to put it: “Either sovereignty means nothing, or it
means supreme power separate and transcendent – not at the peak but above the
peak – and ruling the entire body politic from above. That is why this power is
absolute (absolute, that is nonbound, separate) and consequently unlimited.” (Mar-
itain, Man and the State, 47).
58 Wolfgang Palaver, “Hobbes and the katechon” theol.uibk.ac.at / cover / conta
gion / contagion02_Palaver.pdf.
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 21
a true and unfeigned Christian [ie one who truly proclaims Jesus to be the
Christ] is not liable to excommunication: nor he also that is a professed
Christian, till his hypocrisy appear in his manners, that is, till his behaviour
be contrary to the law of his sovereign, which is the rule of manners, and
which Christ and his apostles have commanded us to be subject to. For the
Church cannot judge of manners but by external actions, which actions can
never be unlawful, but when they are against the law of the commonwealth.”
It turns out in Lev. 43 that the proclamation of Jesus as the Christ entails
obedience to the laws of the sovereign even if that sovereign be “an infi
del.” So Jesus as the Messiah entails the reestablishment of the earthly
kingdom and thus sovereignty. As Hobbes says in Lev. 41:
If then Christ whilst he was on earth, had no kingdom in this world, to what end
was his first coming? It was to restore unto God, by a new covenant, the king
dom, which being his by the old covenant, had been cut off by the rebellion of
the Israelites in the election of Saul. Which to do, he was to preach unto them,
that he was the Messiah, that is, the king promised to them by the prophets …
Schmitt picks up on this and in the Glossarium (23.5.49) draws a severe
conclusion:
Der wichtigste Satz des Thomas Hobbes bleibt:
“Jesus is the Christ”. Die Kraft eines solchen Satzes wirkt auch dann, wenn er in
Begriffssystem des gedanklichen Aufbaus an den Rand, ja scheinbar dogar ausser
halb des Begiffkreises geschoben wird. Diese Abschiebun ist ein des Verkultung
Christi analoger Vergang, wie ihn der Grossinquistitor Dostojewskis vornimmt.
Hobbes spricht aus und begründet wissenschaftlich, was Dostojewskis Grossin
quisitor tut: die Wirkung Christi im sozialen und politischen Bereich unschädlich
machen; das Christentum entanarchisieren, im aber im Hintergrunde eine gewisse
legitierende Wirkund zo belassen und jedenfalls nicht darauf zu verzichten. Ein
kluger Tatiker verzichtet auf michts, es sei denn restlos unverwetbar. Soweit war
es mit dem Christentunm noch nicht. Wir können fragen: wer ist dem Grossin
quisitor Dostokewskis näher: die romishce Kirche oder der Souverän des thomas
Hobbes? … Nenne mir Deinen Feind, und ich sage Dir, wer du bist. Hobbes und
die römische Kirche: der Feind ist unsere eigene Frage als Gestalt.59
Name your enemy and I will tell you who you are. Hobbes and the Roman Church:
the enemy is our characteristic question as form.”
60 Carl Schmitt, Der Angriff, 1 September 1936, quoted from Gopal Balakrishnan,
The Enemy: An Intellectual Portrait of Carl Schmitt, Verso, 2000, p. 203.
61 The katechon reappears in the thought of Dietrich Bonhoeffer but not as a
being exempt from sin as he tends to in Schmitt’s work. See the discussion in
Wolfgang Palaver, “Collective Security. Opportunities and Problems from the Per
spective of Catholic Social Teaching,” in: Peace in Europe – Peace in the World:
Reconciliation, Creation and International Institutions. Ed. by Iustitia et Pax – Öster
reichische Kommission, Iustitia et Pax Dokumentation 4, Wien: SüdwindVerlag,
2003, 86–102.
62 I am helped in part of this by the work of Wolfgang Palaver cited in note 55.
See the citation from Tertullian below, footnote 137.
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 23
towards anarchy and chaos until the Second Coming. If Jesus as God will
be absent until He returns, we need all the more a Jesus of this earth – a
Sovereign – until then. Jesus as God plays no real role in Hobbes’ vision
of politics (as long as people do not act contrary to the commands of the
mortal God they can think privately what they want). Like the Grand In
quisitor, Hobbes’ secularization of theology keeps the anarchic truth of the
God Jesus away from this world. I note that Nietzsche had the same insight
in his pun on “Christ und Anarchist.”63
When Christ comes in Ivan’s story in The Brothers Karamazov, it is not
the end of the world: He has merely come back, for a visit as it were. It is
this that the Grand Inquisitor sees as dangerous.64 Jesus thus plays no real
role in Hobbes’ vision of politics (as long as people do not overtly blas
pheme the can believe what they want). What is important here is that
Hobbes (and Schmitt) are extremely anxious about the role of Christ as
Redeemer. Any political theology must therefore legitimate only the role of
Christ as Messiah.65
What does it mean to find oneself on the side of the Grand Inquisitor? It
is to claim that the political Right has gotten the problem of modern politics
correct, even if what it has sometimes proposed to do about it (as with
Maistre, Bonald and Cortes) has not always been on target or on the only
target. But with this, what now? One can only note in this day an age that
the United States today has on its books a sufficient number of emergency
powers, established sine die, to allow the executive free hand at the rule of
many aspects of my country. The present US administration has ruled that
A second issue with the opening sentence comes from the understanding
of Ausnahmezustand. What the first question might seem to reinforce (the
absolute and dictatorial and unlimited quality of the decision), this second
concern might seem to mitigate. It is the case that Schmitt sometimes uses
more general words when speaking of this question, including “state of
exception (Ausnahmefall),” crisis or state of urgency (Notstand), and even
more generally “emergency, state of need (Notfall).”72 The idea of a “Aus-
nahmefall,” however, has more of a legal connotation: it is more confined
than an “exception.” Thus the same issue is raised as with the “über”: can
the understanding of what counts as an “exception” be defined in legal
terms, or is it more of what one might think of as an open field?73
Note here that he is not talking simply about dictatorship. In Die Dik-
tatur, published one year before PT, Schmitt differentiates between “com
missarial dictatorship” –he cites Lincoln in the Civil war as an example
– and “sovereign dictatorship.” The former defends the existing constitu
tion and the latter seeks to create the conditions for a new one, given the
collapse of the oldone might think to some degree of DeGaulle in 1958.
Die Dikatur is a theory of dictatorship; PT, however, is a theory of sov
ereignty and an attempt to locate the state of emergency in a theory of
sovereignty. More importantly, PT in effect discusses that which for
Schmitt lies under the various kinds of dictatorship and makes both of
them possible74
I again do not think this linguistic glide on Schmitt’s part to be acciden
tal. Rather than seeking to determine what precisely an “Ausnahmezustand”
(or an “Notfall” or a “Notstand”, etc.) is, the problem should be looked at
from the other direction. It is importantly the case for Schmitt that no pre
existing set of rules can be laid down that will tell anyone if this situation
“is” in actual reality an “exception.” It is of the essence of Schmitt’s con
ception of the state that there can be no preset rulefixed definition of
Schlegel, idem.
72
One should note here that this question bedevils all situations in which consti
73
tutions provide for an exception. For a brief history of XIXth and XXieth century
constitutional provisions for exception, including the French 1814 Constitution,
World War One in France and Switzerland, the 1920 Emergency Powers Act in
England, Lincoln at the beginning of the Civil War [noted by Schmitt, in: Die
Diktatur, Munich, Duncker & Humblot, 1921, p. 136], the United States under
Wilson during World War One, Article 16 of the French Fifth Republic, etc. … See
Giorgio Agamben, State of Exception, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 2005,
pp. 11–26.
74 I thus resist John McCormick’s conclusion that PT “repudiates much of what
is of value in the book published before it” in his “Dilemmas of Dictatorship,” in:
Dyzenhaus (1998), p. 241.
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 27
sovereignty.75 Why not? What is clear here is that the notion of sover
eignty contains, as Schmitt tells us, his general theory of the state. (PT 13 / 5)
The nature of the sovereign, he remarks in the preface to the second edition
(1933) is the making of “eine echte Entscheidung [genuine decision].”
(PT 8 / 3) Thus it is not simply the making of a decision, but of a “genuine”
decision that is central. The obvious question is what makes a decision
“genuine” and not simply an emanation of a “degenerierter Dezionismus
[degenerate decisionism].” Schmitt is never “simply” a decisionist, if by
that one means simply that choice is necessary and any choice is better than
none.76
What constitutes a “genuine decision” is a complex matter in Schmitt. To
understand his position one must realize why politics (or here, “the politi
cal”) is not the same for Schmitt as “the state,”77 even if the most usual
framework for the concretization of politics in modern times has been the
state.78 In PT II (1969) taking up the themes of PT, Schmitt writes “Man
kann das Politische heute nicht mehr vom Staate her definieren, sondern
das, was man heute noch Staat nennen kann, muss umgekehrt vom Poli-
tischen her bestimmt und begriffen werden.”79 Underlying the state is a
community of people – necessarily not universal – a “we” that, as it defines
itself necessarily in opposition to that which it is not, it presupposes and is
75 Thus the exception is part of the “order” even if that order is not precisely
juridical. Schmitt engaged in an exchange about this with Walter Benjamin over
violence. See Benjamin, “Towards a Critique of Violence,” in: Walter Benjamin,
Selected Writings, volume I, Cambridge. Harvard University Press, 1996. See the
discussion in Agamben, op. cit., 52–64.
76 I note here that there seem to be strong elements of Schmitt quietly present in
much of Henry Kissinger’s analyses of international politics. See for instance his
“The Necessity for Choice”, New York, Harper, 1961.
77 This is a theme from Schmitt’s earliest work, including his Habilitationsschrift,
Der Wert des Staates und die Bedeutung des Einzelnen, Hellerau, 1917. See Rein-
hard Mehring, Carl Schmitt. Zur Einführung, Hamburg, Junius, 2001, pp. 19–21.
78 Cf Max Weber’s definition of the state: “Heute dagegen werden wir sagen
müssen: Staat ist diejenige menschliche Gemeinschaft, welche innerhalb eines bes
timmten Gebietes – dies: das ‘Gebiet’ gehört zum Merkmal – das Monopol legi
timer physischer Gewaltsamkeit für sich (mit Erfolg) beansprucht.” (Max Weber,
Politik als Beruf, Politische Schriften, 397. See also Max Weber, The Vocation Lec
tures, David Owen / Tracy B. Strong (eds.) p. xlix. If is important that this is the
definition to which the “nowadays” compels us and that Weber here flies directly in
the face of those (like the Georgkreis and others) who placed emphasis on the “na
tion,” on “blood and soil.” See below.
79 Carl Schmitt, Politische Theologie, II, Duncker & Humblot, 1969, 1996, p. 21:
“[T]oday one can no longer define politics in terms of the State; on the contrary
what we can still call the State today must inversely be defined and understood from
the political.”
28 Tracy B. Strong
80 One finds the influence of Schmitt for instance thus in what might appeared
to be a far removed locus, e. g. Bertram de Jouvenel, The Pure Theory of Politics,
New Haven, Yale University Press, 1964.
81 This is confirmed explicitly in a letter from Leo Strauss to Schmitt, September
4, 1932. It is printed in Heinrich Meier, Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss: The Hidden
Dialogue, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1995, p. 124. Meier’s book is an
insightful analysis of the difference between political theology and political philoso
phy – between Schmitt and Strauss. For an attempt at a critique of Meier’s complex
political rapprochement of Strauss and Schmitt, see Robert Howse, “The Use and
Abuse of Leo Strauss in the Schmitt Revival on the German Right – The Case of
Heinrich Meier,“ (forthcoming) a draft of which is available on line at http: / /
faculty.law.umich.edu / rhowse / Drafts_and_Publications / Meierbookrev.pdf.
82 Translations are mine as Schmitt quotes in Latin and Greek. Schmitt will on
the next page read “Love thine enemy” as referring to inimicus, which it is in
Latin although in Greek it is exthros.
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 29
the publication of PT had published Das Problem der Souveränität und die
Theorie des Völkerrechts,83 in which he set out the foundations for what he
would later call a “pure theory of law,” a theory of law from which all
subjective elements would be eliminated.84 Kelsen sought, in other words,
a theory of law that would be universally valid for all times and all situa
tions.85 It is worth noting here that this quarrel is analogous to the quarrel
between Heidegger and Carnap, between thought with its feet in the earth
and what one might call “freischwebende Gedanken.”
Against this Schmitt insists that “alles Recht ist Situationsrecht [all law
is situational law].” (PT 19 / 13) What he means by this is that in actual
lived human fact it will always be the case that precisely at unpredictable
times that “In der Ausnahme durchbricht die Kraft des wirklichen Lebens
die Krusste einer in Wiederholung erstarrten Mechanik [the power of real
life breaks through the crust of a mechanism that has become stiff by rep
etition].” (PT 21 / 15) Schmitt, in other words, requires that his understand
ing of law and politics respond to what he takes to be the fact of the ulti
mately unruly and unruled quality of human life. And if life can never be
reduced or adequately understood by a set of rules, no matter how complex,
then this means that in the end rule is of men and not of law, or rather that
the rule of men must always existentially underlie the rule of law. For
Schmitt, to pretend that one can have an ultimate “rule of law” is to set
oneself up to be overtaken by events at some unpredictable but necessarily
occurring time and it is to lose the human element in and of our world.86
This is a powerful and important theme in Schmitt. It is not a claim that
law is not centrally important to human affairs but that in the end human
affairs rest upon humans and cannot ever be independent of them. In his
83 Hans Kelsen, Das Problem der Souveränität und die Theorie des Völkerrechts,
Tübingen, Mohr, 1920. (The Problem of Sovereignty and the Theory of Interna
tional Law). See the articles on Kelsen, in “European Journal of International Law,”
IX. 2 (1998), especially that by Danilo Zolo.
84 A volume of articles comparing Schmitt and Kelsen has appeared: Dan Din-
er / Michael Stolleis (eds.) Hans Kelsen and Carl Schmitt: A Juxtaposition, Schriften
reihen des Instituts für deutsche Geschichte, University of Tel Aviv, 1999.
85 After 1933 Schmitt was apparently instrumental in the removal of Kelsen from
the Law Faculty of the University of Köln. See David Dyzenhaus, Legality and
Legitimacy: Carl Schmitt, Hans Kelsen and Hermann Heller, Oxford: Clarendon,
1997, p. 84.
86 One might in fact see much of the philosophical debates in the 1920’s and
1930’s as between those who sought to develop understandings that were independ
ent of time and place and those who argued that all understanding needed to be
grounded in concrete historical actuality. One might see Max Weber as the pro
genitor of both approaches. See the exceptional book by Michael Friedmann, A
Parting of the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger, Chicago. Open Court, 2000.
30 Tracy B. Strong
discussion of Locke, for instance, he criticizes Locke for saying that while
the “law gives authority,” he (Locke) “sieht nicht, dass das Getzetz nicht
sagt, wem es Authorität gibt. Es kann doch nicht jeder. …” (PT 38 / 32).87
Schmitt contrasts this to Hobbes’s discussion (and in doing so brings out
qualities often overlooked in discussions of Hobbes). As noted, he cites
Leviathan, chapter 26 to the effect that sovereign power and not truth makes
laws.88 And he then drives the point home by citing Hobbes to the effect
that “For Subjection, Command, Right and Power are accidents not of Pow
ers but of Persons.”89 “Persons,” for Hobbes, are beings constituted or au
thorized to play a certain role or part.90
Schmitt’s insistence on the necessarily and irreducibly human quality of
political and legal actions is key. Those who would elaborate a set of rules by
which decisions can be made take the politics out of human life: Schmitt is
concerned to keep them in human life. (It is for reasons like this some object
to John Rawls’ A Theory of Justice and even more to his Political Liberalism
fpr what appears to them as Rawls’ overly legalistic reliance on courts.91) Hu
87 “Did not recognize that the law does not designate to whom it gives authority.
It cannot be just anybody …” One might have thought here that Schmitt would have
referred to Locke’s discussion of the prerogative. Thus in the Second Treatise on
Government, paragraph 156, Locke writes: “What then could be done in this case
to prevent the community from being exposed some time or other to eminent haz
ard, on one side or the other, by fixed intervals and periods, set to the meeting and
acting of the legislative; but to entrust it to the prudence of some, who being present,
and acquainted with the state of public affairs, might make use of this prerogative
for the public good?” and in para 160: “This power to act according to discretion,
for the public good, without the prescription of the law, and sometimes even against
it, is that which is called prerogative.” Paragraphs 160–168 form a section entitled
“Of Prerogative”. There is a lot of secondary literature on this. See e. g. Clement
Fatovic, “Constitutionalism And Contingency: Locke’s Theory Of Prerogative,” His
tory of Political Thought, 2004, vol. 25, no. 2, pp. 276–297 as well as the discussion
of prerogative, in: J. Dunn, The political thought of John Locke: an historical ac
count of the argument of the ‘Two Treatises of Government’, London, Cambridge
U.P., 1969. See the short discussion in McCormick, op. cit. 237–238.
88 Schmitt quotes the Latin Leviathan, probably because the formulation is more
succinct: “auctoritas, non veritas fecit legem.” The corresponding passage in English
is: “… though it be evident truth, is not therefore presently law; but because in all
commonwealths in the world, it is part of the civil law: For though it be naturally
reasonable; yet it is by the sovereign power that it is law …”
89 Leviathan, chapter 42. The context is the relation of civil to ecclesiastical au
thority.
90 See my “Seeing the Sovereign: Theatricality and Representation in Hobbes,”
in: Stephen Schneck (ed.), Letting Be. Fred Dallmayr’s Cosmopolitan Vision, Notre
Dame, University of Notre Dame Press, 2006.
91 See e. g. Sheldon S. Wolin, “Review of Rawls, ‘Political Liberalism’,” in:
Political Theory XXIV.1 (February, 1996).
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 31
man society can thus never be made to rest on the determination and applica
tion of rules to individual situations. Decisions and judgments would always
be necessary. In this Schmitt can be thought to be an initiator (albeit not rec
ognized or known to be such) of contemporary developments such as both
Critical Legal Studies on the left and the Law and Economics movement on
the right.
Thus for Schmitt, the state is not cofounded with the legal order, and in
exceptional situations the juristic order that prevails is “keine Rechtsord-
nung [not of the ordinary kind]”92 (PT 18 / 12) and “normativ betrachtet [ist]
aus einem Nichts geboren.” (PT 38 / 31) The point therefore of this notion
of sovereignty ultimately unconstrained by formal rules is “Recht zu schaffen
[create a juridical order]” under conditions that threaten anarchy.93 Only
when freed from normative ties is the authority absolute. This is why this
is a political theology – God is neither good nor evil in Himself and his
authority is not ethical. The sovereign must decide both that a situation is
exceptional and what to do about the exception in order to be able to create
or recover a judicial order when the existing one is threatened by chaos.
Ethics and the juridical order are grounded in das Nichts. And it was from
das Nichts that God created the world.
The necessarily extraordinary quality of sovereignty is made clear in the
analogy he uses to explain his point. He writes: “Der Ausnahmezustand ist
wie das Wunder für die Theologie. [The exception in jurisprudence is
analogous to the miracle in theology.]” (PT 43 / 36) What does it mean to
refer the “exception” to a “miracle?” Clearly, this has to do with “political
theology.” To move towards an answer one should look first at the author
who remained Schmitt’s touchstone. In the third book of Leviathan, Hobbes
first identifies a miracle as an occurrence when “the thing is strange, and
the natural cause difficult to imagine” and then goes on to define it as “a
work of God, (besides his operation by the way of nature, ordained in the
creation,) done, for the making manifest to his elect, the mission of an
extraordinary minister for their salvation.”94 Hobbes’ definition is apposite
to Schmitt, as for him the “exception” is the occasion for and of the revela-
tion of the true nature of sovereignty. Thus the sovereign does not for
Schmitt only define the “exception” – he is also revealed by and in it,
which is why Schmitt must refer to a “genuine” decision.
What would be wrong with at least trying to rest human affairs on the
rule of law?
Schmitt finds two major problems. The first comes from the epistemo
logical relationship between the exception and the norm. Sovereignty is
what Schmitt calls a “Grenzbegriff,” a limiting or border concept.95 It thus
looks in two directions, marking the line between that which is subject to
law – where sovereignty reigns – and that which is not – potentially the
space of the exception. (PT 13) To look only to the rule of law will be to
misunderstand the nature and place of sovereignty. For Schmitt we only
understand the nature of the juridical order by understanding sovereignty,
that is, understanding that which opens on to the province of the excep
tion.96 This is because, he asserts, “die Ausnahme ist interessanter als der
Normalfall [the exception is more interesting than the rule].” (PT 21 / 15) As
with the citation from Kierkegaard that Schmitt uses to support this claim
argues, this is not because one cannot think about the rule or the “general,”
but because one does not notice anything in the general worth thinking
about and thus our thought in this realm would be “nicht einmal mit Lei-
denschaft [in no case with passion].” (PT idem) The point here, I believe,
is that the exception engages the human being in the way that the normal
routine does not.
Secondly, it is important to realize that one can only have an exception
if one has a rule. Therefore the designation of something as an exception is
in fact an assertion of the nature and quality of rule. If, as director of the
program I say “I am going to make an exception in your case and let you
go on the exchange program to Germany despite the fact that you did not
have the required grades,” I am affirming both the rule and the fact that the
rule is a human creation and hence does not control us automatically. I am
also making a judgment that in this case, at this time, the good of all con
cerned, indicates the need for this exception (and thus that I am not taking
a bribe). There can thus be no exceptions without there also being a rule.
What though am I affirming in affirming the human quality of the rule?
The claim about the exception and thus the grounding of rules on human
actions is part of what Schmitt sees as the need to defend the political. As
noted earlier, when Max Weber described the workings of bureaucracy he
asserted that in no case are bureaucratic (rationalized, rationallegal) rela
95 Thus the exception is both part of and not part of the juridical order. See the
useful discussion in Agamben, op. cit., 24–26.
96 See the striking and informative discussion in William Scheuerman, Between
the Norm and the Exception: The Frankfurt School and the Rule of Law, Cam
bridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1994. pp. 330 and passim.
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 33
97 Max Weber, Economy and Society, Berkeley and Los Angeles, University of
California Press, 1967, p. 975.
98 This periodisation can be found explicitly in the Barcelona address and is
implicit in the first several pages of chapter three of PT; it is made explicit in
shorter form in the 1934 preface to PT, pp. 1–2. The stages are well discussed in
Henning Ottmann, “Das Zeitalter der Neutralisierungen und EntTotalisierungen: Carl
Schmitts Theorie der Neuzeit,” in: Reinhard Mehring (ed.), Carl Schmitt. Der
Begriff des Politischen. Ein Kooperativer Kommentar, Akademie Verlag, Berlin,
2003, pp. 156–169.
99 “The central concepts of modern state theory are all secularized theological
concepts.” (PT 36) “As translator, George Schwab was faced with the difficult task
of rendering ‘prägnanten’ – it means ‘concise, succinct’ which is only partly caught
by Schwab’s ‘significant’.” I have gone (with thanks for a consultation to William
Arctander O’Brien) for what I believe to be the meaning rather than for a literal
equivalent.
34 Tracy B. Strong
earlier and are unable to resist the dynamics of technology. The conse
quence of Schmitt’s notion of secularisation is to try and restore to the
concepts of sovereignty and political authority in a secular age the qualities
that they had earlier.
The modern age is importantly one in which an analogue for transcendent
authority must be sought for “bei der Masse der Gebildeten alle Vorstel-
lungen von Trancendenz untergehen [all conceptions of transcendence will
no longer be credible to most educated people].” (PT 54 / 50) Any theory of
decisionism must therefore rest on immanent criteria. This is the essence of
what Schmitt considers the political matter: to find the secular analogue to
the sacred. Such was the achievement of Hobbes, who, by creating an arti
ficial yet transcendent sovereign, provided the model for the solution to the
problem of modernity as Schmitt posed it.
These thoughts help explain the last chapter of PT. There Schmitt argues
that Maistre, Bonald and Cortes exaggerate evil. They exaggerate evil in
that they fail to see that the humans striving for power not only renders
people capable of great evil but also makes possible the domination of a
certain class of leaders. There is nothing necessarily wrong with domination
for Schmitt. Thus while the decision will emanate from nothingness (das
Nichts) it must always be sanctioned by “die Willen des Volkes – the will
of the people.” (PT 69 / 66) Thus one might say that Schmitt is not a
counterrevolutionary in a reactionary sort of way. He accepts that legiti
macy in this age must be in some sense democratic – it certainly cannot be
monarchical. Thus although it is clear that he thinks that Maistre, Bonald
and Cortes got the problem right, their solutions (monarchy for the French
men and dictatorship for the Spaniard) are unacceptable. As he notes on the
last page of PT: “[J]ener gegenrevolutionären Staatsphilosophen … steigern
das moment der Dezision so stark dass es schiesslich den Gedanken der
Legitimität, von dem sie ausgegangen sind, aufhebt. … Das ist aber we-
sentlich Diktatur, nicht Legitimität. [Those counterrevolutionary philosophers
of the state … heightened the moment of the decision to such an extent that
the notion of legitimacy, their starting point, was dissolved … This [deci
sionism] is however essentially dictatorship, not legitimacy.” (PT 69 / 65–66)
While Schmitt has sympathies for these theorists over and against the
bourgeois liberal thinkers that Cortes and he had stigmatised as a “clasa
discutidora” (PT 66), the point of the analysis of the centrality of the excep
tion for sovereignty is precisely to restore, in a democratic age, the element
of transcendence that had been there in the XVIth and even the XVIIth
centuries – Hobbes, Schmitt believes, understood the problem exactly: he
dealt with the problem of transcendence in an age when theological con
flicts had made any claim to transcendence apparently inherently question
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 35
able. Recall that for Hobbes the sovereign was each of us and that the
sovereign’s authority was established by a creative covenant that placed
what was written in hearts (the same in each heart) beyond question – it
was an absolute authority, like that of Scripture for Protestants.
Failing such an accomplishment, the triumph of nonpolitical, nonhuman
Technizität – of liberalism and the aestheticization of human judgment –
will be inevitable. There is thus in Schmitt a challenge to those who would
argue that politics in a democratic age can rest on (rational) discussion.100
Such a claim is for him the privilege, as we saw, of the bourgeois “discuss
ing classes.”
Political concepts are secularized theological concepts. The task for poli
tics in the present is to find an immanence that does for politics what
transcendence had done in the past. For Schmitt, the secularization of theo
logical concepts in the realm of sovereignty is to be understood as corre
sponding to the greatest progress in human rationality, progress that has
occurred in and because of the State. This is “the distinction between enemy
and criminal and from that the only possible foundation for a theory of
State neutrality at the time of wars between other states.”101 Secularisation,
in other words, has made it possible for conflict to occur between enemies
and not between the legal and the criminal.102 Schmitt is claiming here that
the modern state based politics is in fact potentially more moderate than a
situation in which the opposition is between state and nonstate, i. e. crimi
nal. As humanity can have no enemies (barring an invasion form another
planet), the idea of a “crime against humanity” is tellingly problematic in
that it would involve a change from “friendenemy” to “humancriminal.”
And then anything goes.
What is consequent to this understanding of secularisation?103 Three ele
ments are involved. First of all, is his understanding of power. Political
power is to be understood on the model of God’s creation – which is how
Hobbes had understood it. Power is to make something from that which is
not something and thus to be above or not subject to laiddown laws. This
understanding of power clearly draws upon medieval theology but it is the
point of Schmitt’s last chapter in PT to show that it is basically a modern
100 See the discussion in Chantal Mouffe, “Carl Schmitt and the Paradoxes of
Liberal Democracy,” in: Dyzenhaus (1998), 165–168.
101 Schmitt, The Crisis of Liberal Democracy, p. 86.
102 Schmitt will towards the end of his life write on “Die Theorie des Partisans”
in an insightful analysis of the transformations in warfare in the postcolonial period.
103 I am conscious in the next three paragraphs of the general influence of
Etienne Balibar, “Introduction” to Carl Schmitt, Le Leviathan dans la doctrine de
l’état de Thomas Hobbes, Paris, Seuil, 2002.
36 Tracy B. Strong
104 Carl Schmitt, Hüter der Verfassung, Tübingen. Mohr, 1931, p. 159. See the
discussion of this passage in Caldwell, op.cit., 115
105 All this, one should note, is quite consonant with a reading of Hobbes. See
my “How to Write Scripture: Words and Authority,” in: Thomas Hobbes, Critical
Inquiry, Autumn, 1993, and Carl Schmitt, Der Leviathan in der Staatslehre des Tho
mas Hobbes. Sinn und Feldschlag eines Symbols, Cotta’sche Buchhandlung, Stutt
gart, 1993 (1938).
106 Jacob Taubes, The Political Theology of Paul, Stanford, 2004, p. 102.
107 See the discussion in Hermann Meier, Carl Schmitt, Leo Strauss and “The
Concept of the Political,” Chicago. University of Chicago Press, 2003, p. 77.
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 37
him there was, in the Germany of that time, with its common language and
customs, no real basis for different systems of law.108 For Savigny, the
sovereign or legislator was the expresser of the Volksbewusstsein.109 Schmitt,
as we have seen, gives this part of Savigny’s thought very strong emphasis.
And in the present age, if we think in terms of ‘national interest” we are
thinking in terms that are Schmittian.
Schmitt’s original understanding of the Volk in his 1928 Verfassungs-
lehre, conceived of the Volk as that which was represented in the Sovereign
in the State.110 It is precisely in being represented that that which had not
had form (the mass of people) acquires what Schmitt calls Existenz. While
the notion of a people carries here some of the sense that the Greeks had
of the polis as the attunement of a group of people to a land, Schmitt tends
after 1933, especially in Staat Bewegung, Volk (1934), to give a much more
racial meaning, a meaning that is embodied in the idea of Führung and thus
the Führer.111 It is important to note that Hobbes has no need of the concept
of Volkbewusstsein and is thus close to the earlier Schmitt but not the latter:
there is a territorial notion of the state but not an ideological or racial one.
In this Hobbes is oddly closer to Max Weber than is Schmitt. When Weber
proclaimed in Political as a Vocation that: “Heute dagegen werden wir
sagen müssen: Staat ist diejenige menschliche Gemeinschaft, welche inner-
halb eines bestimmten Gebietes – dies: das ‘Gebiet’ gehört zum Merkmal
– das Monopol legitimer physischer Gewaltsamkeit für sich (mit Erfolg)
beansprucht”112 he was insisting against people like Stefan George (and the
later Schmitt) that the state was not to be understood as geistlich.
Taken together these elements in Schmitt’s thought casts light on what
we can surmise was the attraction of National Socialism. Schmitt came, as
did Heidegger, from a rural, Catholic, petitbourgeois upbringing. He de
scribes his childhood, adolescence and youth – the latter lasting for him
until the end of World War I during which he served as an officer and at
108 See the discussion of von Savigny, in: Carl Schmitt, Der Nomos der Erde.
109 This may make the question of Schmitt’s antiSemitic writings more complex.
One might speak of antiJudaism, meaning by that that Schmitt saw in German
Judaism the kind of pluralism that he found incompatible with the commonalty of
the Volk that he saw as essential to the political. In practice, however, certainly in
the Third Reich, one could not be opposed to Judaism without being opposed to
Jews …
110 Carl Schmitt, Verfassungslehre, Berlin, Duncker & Humblot, 1965 [1928],
p. 207. See the interesting discussion in Bernhard Radloff, “Heidegger and Carl
Schmitt: The historicity of the Political (part two).”
111 As Rudolf Hess proclaimed at Nuremberg: “Hitler ist Deutschland.”
112 Max Weber, “Politik als Beruf,” Politische Schriften, Tübingen, Mohr, 1968,
p. 397.
38 Tracy B. Strong
the end of which he was thirty years old – as periods of getting rid of
various influences: his Catholicism is “entortet [displaced]” and “enttotal-
isiert [detotalised]”; greater Prussianness is “enthegelianisiert [deHege
lised]”. Likewise during his “manhood,” Weimar Germany is “entpreusst
[dePrussified].”113 While Catholicism was always to remain important to
Schmitt, it is important to see in this self description the portrait of a person
whose ties to his various traditions are negative and are not replaced by a
liberal faith in the future or in progress.114 One has to read therefore his
attacks on liberalism in conjunction with the accumulation of “ent” verbs.115
What remains when one has lost most of that one was?
What then was the source of his attraction to Hitler? It was pretty
clearly not an admiration of the particular qualities that the man had: even
if one discounts the occasion, the disdain he expresses during his interroga
tion at Nuremberg is palpable.116 One might rather say that Hitler appeared
to him something like the entity God had sent to perform a miracle – as in
the citation from Hobbes above – and the miracle was the recovery of a
thisworld transcendence to sovereignty and thus the human realm of the
political. From this understanding, the person Hitler was nothing important
and Schmitt’s relation to it could only be the relation one has to a miracle:
acceptance or rejection.
This is all the more likely as very rapidly Hitler seemed to many to be
have like as a true statesman in times of exception, legally elected but / or / and
capable of making the hard, extralegal decisions that were necessary. When
Hitler and Goering ordered on June 30–July 1 and 2 the execution of all of
the leadership of the SA, within two days almost all the press was con
gratulating them on having saved the country from civil war. Hindenburg
sent (or was led to send) a telegram of thanks to the new Chancellor. Sch
mitt published on August 1, 1934 a newspaper article entitled “Der Führer
schutzt das Recht [The Führer protects the legal order]” defending Hitler’s
actions.117 Thus it is the reality of taking power and manifesting sover
eignty in the use of power that attracted Schmitt: his understanding of law
required that he support Hitler. It was not a question of succumbing to the
charisma of a prophet, true or false.
Schmitt thus, in his 1938 book on Hobbes, attacks Hobbes for allow
privacy of belief. This destroys, he says, the Leviathan from inside. The
privacy of belief in the end, Schmitt argues, will put an end to the katechon.
Hobbes’ sovereign, while of the same structure as Schmitt’s, is much more
restrained: as noted above there is no potential Volksgeist waiting to be
awakened.118 And perhaps this is the reason that Schmitt will think Toc
queville to be the most important contemporary historian. Tocqueville un
derstood the irresistibility of the democratic spirit of equality. For Schmitt,
as for Max Weber, there are only the words of Jesaja that stand as an epi
graph to this article.
117 The matter is a bit more complex. Ellen Kennedy, mainly on Schmitt’s testi
mony, argues that he was forced to do so. Schmitt was identified with some ele
ments of the SA and there is some evidence that he was specifically exempted from
the purge by Goering. In a somewhat selfpitying and selfaggrandizing poem he
wrote for his sixtieth birthday, Gesang des Sechzigjährigen, he notes that he has
been “three times in the belly of the fish.” The first is 1934; the second, the attacks
on him in 1936 in the Gestapo organ “Das schwarze Korps” (a moment he identifies
to his interrogator in Nuremberg as when he “foreswore the devil”) and the last his
interrogation after the war when he appears to believe that he might be hung. See
Schmitt, Glossarium entry for 12.1.48.
118 See George Kateb, “Hobbes and the Irrationality of Politics,” Political Theory,
17, 3 (August, 1989), pp. 355–391.
40 Tracy B. Strong
maine”). Sieyes has recourse to the pouvoir constituant and de Sade calls
upon “Mother Nature.” Bataille associates sovereignty with killing. Writing
around the same time as Schmitt, Freud suggests that even the most egali
tarian social arrangements cannot function without some implicit or ex
plicit invocation of an exceptional figure: In Totem and Taboo he invokes
a primal figure; in Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego this be
comes the leader; in Moses and Monotheism, the nation of Israel is found
ed by a nonHebrew.119
Political theology is thus concerned not only with the appeal to a source
of legitimation figured as “beyond” the law, but with the fact that the Law
has the quality of seeking to annihilate or displace the lawless authority of
the law’s “beyond.” What Schmitt shows in his critique of “normative” law
is that there is necessarily a “gap” in the law such that it is in its nature
incapable of addressing such lawless – anomic – situations as revolution or
a general strike. It is the case that a spontaneous arising can, as Hannah
Arendt argues, give rise momentarily to what Aristide Zolberg has called a
“moment of madness” in which “the people” appear to take power and from
which there arise various egalitarian groups (the soviets, councils etc).120
But such moments are fleeting and unless a sovereign acts to close this gap
in the law by preserving its “spirit” against its “letter,” suspending the con
stitution to maintain the order of law (or the existence of the state as such)
nothing will be achieved.
It is thus the case that the archetype of the strategy of the exception is
Paul’s account of Christ as the “fulfillment of the law,” the living logos who
consigns the “old” written law to obsolescence, and who actualizes in his
person the transcendent Kingdom of God. Calvin, in the Institutes, rails
against those who would live by the Law and insists that with God we live
in love. Both Schmitt and Hobbes take up the terms of Paul’s or Calvin’s
polemic against the Mosaic law. It is thus the case that, as Hobbes himself
remarks, that Jesus is the Christ is the foundation of all of Paul’s thought:
“Besides, this article, that Jesus is the Christ, is so fundamental, that all the
rest are by St. Paul … said to be built upon it.” (De Cive 18.9)
Paul, a Jew, found himself in struggle with not only the disciples who
saw Jewishness a prerequisite to Christianity – who thus wanted to limit the
119 I am indebted here to some conversations with Professor Jason Frank of Cor
nell University. On Freud see my Psychoanalysis as a Vocation: Freud, “Politics and
the Heroic,” Political Theory (February, 1984).
120 Aristide Zolberg, “Moments of Madness,” Theory and Society (1972), esp.
p. 172. See also Sidney Tarrow, “Cycles of Collective Action: Between Moments of
Madness and the Repertoire of Contention,” Social Science History, Vol. 17, No. 2
(Summer, 1993), pp. 281–307.
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 41
121 Pliny the Younger, Epistles 10.34.1: Sed meminerimus provinciam istam et
praecipue eas civitates eius modi factionibus esse vexatas. Quodcumque nomen ex
quacumque causa dederimus iis, qui in idem contracti fuerint, hetaeriae eaeque brevi
fient.
122 Pliny, op cit, 10.9394: non ad turbas et ad illicitos coetus, sed ad sustinen
dam tenuiorum inopiam utuntur. In ceteris civitatibus, quae nostro iure obstrictae
sunt, res huius modi prohibenda est.
123 Thus Paul’s founds the Christian Church. Cf Wittgenstein’s remark in “Cul
ture and Value”, p. 35: “The spring that flows quietly & clearly in the Gospels
seems to foam in Paul’s Epistles.”
42 Tracy B. Strong
sind: so auch Christus. … Ihr aber seid der Leib Christi und jeder von
euch ein Glied.) Paul’s description of the church would, if sketched, look
very similar to the portrait of the Leviathan that opens Hobbes’ book. But
this vision of the Church is universalistic for there is no principled reason
why a given member cannot be of the body. It is thus a threat to the
Empire and its claim to be the creator of pax. The Roman word pax tends
to refer to a state of affairs achieved and preserved by arms. It is thus
political and consists in separating the Roman Empire off from those who
are not so pacified. However, in the wellknown passage from the Letter
to the Galatians, Paul allows no finality in differentiation. (Gal 3.23: Hier
ist nicht Jude noch Grieche, hier ist nicht Sklave noch Freier, hier ist
nicht Mann noch Frau; denn ihr seid allesamt einer in Christus Jesus.)124
For Paul, it is precisely the resurrected Christ, the occurrence of something
from beyond the realm of possibility which is affects everyone, regardless
of their sex, race, ethnicity and so forth, a Lacanian Real that annihilates
the normal, that engenders a new universality. As Nietzsche writes: “Pau-
lus wusste nichts Besseres seinem Erlöser nachzusagen, als dass er den
Zugang zur Unsterblichkeit für Jedermann eröffnet habe. …”125 Paul is
responding to the promise that he sees instantiated in Jesus’ resurrection,
an Event the Truth of which can in no ways be proven but can only be
believed. Just as the Real cannot be represented, language itself, Paul as
serts, would diminish the promise of the resurrection (I Corinthians 1.17).
It is not surprising that the Athenian philosophers refer to Paul as a sper-
mologos – a babbler – Acts 17.18.
Were the Church to remain a subdivision sect of the Jews, it would not
be a threat – the Jews were wellknown to the Romans as an odd people,
but one that generally kept to itself. Thus the Church as Paul envisages it
is thus an epistemological threat to the Roman Empire, but one to which
the Romans will respond politically (by persecuting them – the grounds are
laid out in the correspondence between Pliny and Trajanus discussed above).
All relations and authority is now to be mediated by and in Christ: to be a
disciple of Christ one must hate one’s family and even one’s own life (Lu
kas 14.26). Christ and the Church function as what Schmitt called a Grenz-
begriff. Jesus says in Matthew 5.17: “Ihr sollt nicht meinen, daß ich ge-
kommen bin, das Gesetz oder die Propheten aufzulösen; ich bin nicht ge-
kommen aufzulösen, sondern zu erfüllen.”126 For Paul, Christ reasserts the
124 It is to this dismemberment that Nietzsche points in the “Von der Erlösung”
chapter in Zarathustra II.
125 Nietzsche, Morgenröte, # 72.
126 “Think not that I am come to destroy the law, or the prophets: I am not come
to destroy, but to fulfill.”
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 43
Law precisely and only by going beyond it. Thus Romans 13:10: “die Liebe
[ist] des Gesetzes Erfüllung (Love is the fulfillment of the Law).”
While a number of passages oppose love and the gospel to the Law (e. g.
John 1.17; II Cor 3.611: Denn der Buchstabe tötet, aber der Geist macht
lebendig),127 overwhelmingly the texts place the law and love into a com
plex relationship. What seems to me clear in Paul is what Zlavoj Zizek
points out: “the very act of fulfilling the Law undermines its direct
authority.”128 This was also Nietzsche’s position, as he writes in Jenseits
von Gut und Böse (Sprüche und Zwischenspiele 164) “Jesus sagte zu seinen
Juden: ‘das Gesetz war für Knechte – liebt Gott, wie ich ihn liebe, als sein
Sohn! Was geht uns Söhne Gottes die Moral an!’ [Jesus said to his Jews:
‘The law was for servants – love God as I love him, as his Son! What is
morality to us sons of God!’]” While the love of God fulfills the law it is
by definition not covered by the law. Thus being a Christian means always
living a Grenzbegriff – living as both exception and law. It is thus inherent
in the structure of a Church that it both invokes and resists the realm that
is beyond the Law. When Paul says “So ist nun die Liebe des Gesetzes
Erfüllung,” he is saying that inherent in the foundation of a Church is the
opening to that which is beyond the law. The Church is the fulfillment of
the Law but that fulfillment is always from beyond the Law.
How did Paul bring his vision about? In the epistles that we are rela
tively sure Paul wrote, he always begins them by instantiating his authority.
Paul had not been a disciple; he had never known Christ. Indeed, his early
career was spent in the persecution of those who followed Christ. It was on
the road to Damascus that he becomes who and what is is. [Cf. I Cor 15.10:
“Aber durch Gottes Gnade bin ich, was ich bin.”] We find a clue in the
very first line of the letter to the Romans. Luther renders this as: “Paulus,
ein Knecht Christi Jesu, berufen zum Apostel, ausgesondert, zu predigen
das Evangelium Gottes.”129 The Greek, however, gives us: “Paulos doulos
Christou Iesou, kletos apostolosaforismenos eis euangelion Theou.” The key
is doulos – slave130. Paul, a Jew, a Roman, describes himself here by ap
127 The relation of love and law is a matter of considerable dispute in Christian
theology. Some separate the two radically, others refer to a “law of love” which is
the same as a “law of grace.”
128 Zlavoj Zizek, The Ticklish Subject, Verso, London, 2000, p. 115. My para
graph here is indebted to pp. 113–116 of this book.
129 “Paul, a servant of Jesus Christ, called to be an apostle, separated unto the
gospel of God.” Of the seven epistles reliably attributed to Paul, he invokes his
authority as doulos in three (Romans, Philippians and Philemon) and as apostolos
(I and II Corinthians, Galatians, and I Thessalonians) in the others.
130 Greek distinguished between a slave proper (doulos) and a slave taken in war
(andrapodon).
44 Tracy B. Strong
propriating a term for precisely those who are at the bottom of the Roman
world – slave. And this designation is used as the source of his authority.
Why should being a doulos be a claim to authority? Jacob Taubes, in:
“Die politische Theologie des Paulus” argues that the true founder of Chris
tianity was Paul and not Christ.131 In this he picks up on Nietzsche, who in
Morgen 68 sees Paul as “the First Christian.” Paul overcomes the law pre
cisely because he comes to revalue what it meant to die on the cross. In
stead of being shameful, that death is the prerequisite to living outside the
law, thus to living beyond sin. Nietzsche will analyze this more generally
in Jenseits and Zur Genealogie: slave morality consists in taking that which
had designated the base and shameful and turning it into an instrument of
power. Paul thus sought nothing less than to recast the entire Roman system
by taking what Romans had despised and rendering it the most worthy of
admiration. Slavery to the law is replaced by the transcendent slavery –
doulos – to Christ. We find in Romans 8: 2–4:
[2] Denn das Gesetz des Geistes, der lebendig macht in Christus Jesus, hat dich
frei gemacht von dem Gesetz der Sünde und des Todes.
[3] Denn was dem Gesetz unmöglich war, weil es durch das Fleisch geschwächt
war, das tat Gott: er sandte seinen Sohn in der Gestalt des sündigen Fleisches und
um der Sünde willen und verdammte die Sünde im Fleisch,
[4] damit die Gerechtigkeit, vom Gesetz gefordert, in uns erfüllt würde, die wir
nun nicht nach dem Fleisch leben, sondern nach dem Geist.132
This slavery is the authority by which he sets out the promise of the
resurrection. It is precisely because he is a slave that he has authority as
being called, as apostolos. The incarnation is of little importance to Paul
(and likewise to Hobbes).
Life after death – the resurrection – is the promise that the Law is unable
to accomplish. And this inability shows the limits of the Law and why Love
is the fulfillment of the law. And the question then becomes what are we
to be until we pass beyond death. What is required is the Church, the as
sembly of those who are all similarly summoned by this call. Paul’s vision
of the Church is remarkably like that we find in Hobbes. Each individual
is individual and yet part of the whole. One soon finds similar sentiments
in those who follow Paul. Tertullian, in his Book of Apology Against the
Heathen will write: “We are a body formed by our joint cognizance of
Religion, by the unity of discipline, by the bond of hope. We come to
gether in a meeting and a congregation as before God, as though we would
in one body sue Him by our prayers. This violence is pleasing unto God.
131 Jacob Taubes, The Political Theology of Paul, Stanford, 1997, p. 41.
132 See also I Corinthians 6. 15–17; I Corinthians 10. 15–17; I Corinthians 12.
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 45
We pray also for Emperors, for their ministers and the powers, for the
condition of the world, for the quiet of all things, for the delaying of the
end.”133 Tertullian sees the Church as had Paul, and as will Schmitt, as a
katechon, that delays the eschaton.
Such is the Church for Paul: how is it legitimated and against what is it
defined? For Schmitt, Paul defines the Church against its enemies, which
Schmitt understands as the Jews. The enemy is something “existentially
other and alien” As I noted, he remarks that “Feind ist hostis nicht inimicus
im weiteren Sinne; polémios, nicht echthrós.” (BP 29 / 28) TO understand
this the key passage is again from Romans: “Im Blick auf das Evangelium
sind sie zwar Feinde um euretwillen; aber im Blick auf die Erwählung sind
sie Geliebte um der Väter willen.”134 The Latin Vulgate is “secundum evan-
gelium quidem inimici propter vos secundum electionem autem carissimi
propter patres;” The Greek is “Kata men to euangelion echthroi di humas,
kata deten eklogen agapetoi dia tous pateras.”
For Schmitt it is important that the Church be the “friend” and that it
have an enemy, here the Jews who insisted on circumcision as a prerequi
site for becoming Christian and hence denied the universalism that Paul was
seeking. Schmitt sees the enemy as hostes and polémios. In this passage,
however, Paul (and his Latin translator) refers to them as inimici and ech-
throi. Thus in Schmitt’s nomenclature Paul’s understanding of the relation
of the Church to the Jews is not what Schmitt wishes it to be. The key here
is how the “enemy” is defined. For Schmitt, inimicus and echthros are en
emies in a private sense (we are thus enjoined to love them by Jesus).
Hostes and polémios are enemies in a public sense: they are our enemies
and, remarks Schmitt, we are never enjoined to love them, to welcome the
Saracens’ capture of Jerusalem, for instance. In Schmitt, the enemy (here
the Jews) of the Church is defined politically – and thus we get an insight
into Schmitt’s antiSemitism or rather his antiJudaism.
However, Paul, in this passage, does not define the Christian relation to
the Jews politically but rather defines it theologically. While it is clear that
concerning the Gospel the Jews (that is those who hold Judaism to be a
prerequisite for Christianity) are enemies, it is also clear that they are be
loved of God. In my analysis, which leans heavily on Karl Barth and par
ticularly on Jacob Taubes, one is to love ones enemy because since God has
revealed himself as the Other in the enemy, by loving the enemy we bring
133 Tertullian, Book of Apology Against the Heathen, Oxford, Parker, 1842, sec
tion xxxix, page 80.
134 Romans 11.28: As concerning the gospel, indeed, they are enemies for your
sake: but as regards the election, they are beloved of the Father.
46 Tracy B. Strong
V. Concluding Remarks
What might one say at the end? The friendenemy definition of politics
that underpins Schmitt’s analysis has the advantage of keeping combatants
from seeing their enemy as criminal. He writes in “Der Begriff des Poli
tischen”: “Die Menschheit also solche kann kein Krieg führen, denn sie
had keinen Feind, wingstens nicht auf diesem Planeten. Der Begriff der
Meschheit schliesst den Begriff des Feindes aus, wiel auf der Feind nicht
aufhört, Mensch zu sein und darin keine spezifische Unterscheidung liegt.
…“ (BP 54–55 / 54) Should however a conflict occur where one group con
ceives of itself as fighting for humanity, then its opponents will be under
stood as criminals and a danger to “humanity.” At the end of his book he
tells us: “Der Gegner heisst nicht mehr Feind, aber dafür wird er als
Friedensbrecher und Friedensstörer hors-la-loi und hors l’humanité ge-
setzt. …” (BP 77 / 79) Schmitt wrote these words in apparent response to
the “war to end all wars” as conceived by Woodrow Wilson. They antici
pate however the accusation of “crimes against humanity” that has become
increasingly standard fare since the trials at Nuremberg. The grounds for
this universalism, however, are laid in the Pauline universalism, the uni
versalism that claims to affect everyone in the same way. If the political
requires friends, enemies and conflict, then in the end Jesus’ life under
135 In Matthew 5.4445 Jesus orders that one love one’s enemies:
[44] Ich aber sage euch: Liebt eure Feinde und bittet für die, die euch verfolgen,
[45] damit ihr Kinder seid eures Vaters im Himmel. Denn er läßt seine Sonne auf
gehen über Böse und Gute und läßt regnen über Gerechte und Ungerechte.
136 This raises another large question. For an initial entry to it, see Tristan Storme,
Carl Schmitt et le marcionisme, Paris. Editions du Cerf, 2008.
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 47
137 John Rawls, “Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical,” Collected Pa
pers, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 2001, p. 395. This matter is more
complex however. One should reflect carefully on the difference and similarity of
the usage by each of “the political.” For both it can take place in a realm that is not
Law governed – for Schmitt in the state of exception and for Rawls in the original
position. See Miguel Vatter, “The Idea of Public Reason and the Reason of State:
Schmitt and Rawls on the Political,” Political Theory (April 2008) 239–271.
138 See Harold Relyea, “Terrorist Attacks and National Emergencies Act Declara
tions,” for the Congressional Research Service, Library of Congress (RS21017)
January 7, 2005.
48 Tracy B. Strong
139 Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer, Stanford, Stanford University Press, 1998;
State of Exception, Stanford, Stanford University Press, 2005.
140 I am again indebted here to conversations with Professor Jason Frank of Cor
nell University.
141 See here, J. L. Nancy, “La Comparution / Compearance,” (trans. Tracy B.
Strong) Political Theory (November 1991).
Reflections on Hobbes, Schmitt and Saint Paul 49
nese Cultural Revolution that “latrines are political” as we are the watch
word of the “Sixties” that “the personal is political.”
Lastly, as noted briefly above, the modern world has produced a whole
new kind of people: these may come from what we call “failed states”; or
they may be asylum seekers from culturally oppressive regimes; they may
be “illegal aliens” in search of employment that cannot be found “at home”;
they may be prisoners at Guantanamo. None of this is easily covered by
Schmitt’s analysis and is to some degree covered over by the idea of po
litical theology.
On the other hand, Schmitt will avoid the path that we find in someone
like Bataille, where the exercise of sovereignty becomes only a recovery of
the nonrulebound, the immediate and the noninstrumental. Bataille calls
this the “animality that we perceive in sovereignty” and he is in favor of it.
He writes that “… we may call sovereign the enjoyment of possibilities that
utility doesn’t justify (utility being that whose end is productive activity).
Life beyond utility is the domain of sovereignty. … What is sovereign in
fact is to enjoy the present time without having to anything else in view but
this present time.”142
On this score it is interesting and important to note something to which
Heinrich Meier has already called attention: Schmitt’s distaste for Nietzsche.
In the Glossarium he scorns the idea of eternal return as in fact making
impossible the idea of the katechon. He writes on 26 / 9 / 49 (s. 272) that “if
there was an end it would be here so there is nothing to wait for.” He also,
interestingly, sees Nietzsche as the forerunner not only of fascism but also
of bolshevism, relating him to Trotsky (Glossarium 13.6.48 (s. 163). What
Schmitt dislikes in Nietzsche, I think, is later found in Bataille: a distrust
of the will and a valuing of what he calls necessity. Thus, drawing an
analogy between sovereignphilosophers and artists, he will say of them that
“gerade dann, wo sie Nichts mehr ‘willkürlich’ und Alles nothwendig
machen, ihr Gefühl von Freiheit, Feinheit, Vollmacht, von schöpferischem
Setzen, Verfügen, Gestalten auf seine Höhe kommt, – kurz, dass Noth-
wendigkeit und ‘Freiheit des Willens’ dann bei ihnen Eins sind.”143
Lastly, there may be something too strong in Schmitt’s reduction of law
to normativity and thus his rejection of it as destructive of sovereignty. For
Benjamin, the written law of both the Greeks and the Hebrews was a de
fence against the “tyranny of mythic states.” In the Seventh Seminaire,
142 Georges Bataille, The Accursed Share, MIT Press. Cambridge, MA, 1993,
volume 3 (“Sovereignty”), chapter one.
143 F. Nietzsche, Jenseits von Gut und Böse, # 213. In the next paragraph I again
owe a debt to Professor Jason Frank.
50 Tracy B. Strong
Jacques Lacan argues that the Ten Commandments are “nothing other than
the laws of speech,” and that speech is the “distance between the subject
and das Ding.” Thus written law is not so much a punishment for offense
as a way of erecting a barrier against das Ding – that is, against that which
is a cathexis of the death drive and all that represents it: God, the mother
of the incest prohibition, the neighbor, etc. If these thoughts are on the right
track, then law is not only concerned with norms and procedures and petri
fied regularities – what Badiou dismisses as the logic of “particularism.”
The realm of law is also the realm of speech and the symbolic and the way
in which humans inscribe a barrier against the tyranny of absolute power
that the law may also want to claim. Such would be to reclaim Paul from
Schmitt and join him to Hobbes.