0% found this document useful (0 votes)
212 views10 pages

Category Theory

Matematicas

Uploaded by

Isaac Salinas
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
212 views10 pages

Category Theory

Matematicas

Uploaded by

Isaac Salinas
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 10

Category theory

Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and


their relations that was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders
Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work
on algebraic topology. Nowadays, category theory is used in almost all
areas of mathematics, and in some areas of computer science. In
particular, many constructions of new mathematical objects from
previous ones, that appear similarly in several contexts are
conveniently expressed and unified in terms of categories. Examples
include quotient spaces, direct products, completion, and duality.

A category is formed by two sorts of objects: the objects of the


category, and the morphisms, which relate two objects called the Schematic representation of a
source and the target of the morphism. One often says that a morphism category with objects X, Y, Z and
is an arrow that maps its source to its target. Morphisms can be morphisms f, g, g ∘ f. (The
composed if the target of the first morphism equals the source of the category's three identity
second one, and morphism composition has similar properties as morphisms 1X, 1Y and 1Z , if
function composition (associativity and existence of identity explicitly represented, would
morphisms). Morphisms are often some sort of function, but this is not appear as three arrows, from the
always the case. For example, a monoid may be viewed as a category letters X, Y, and Z to themselves,
with a single object, whose morphisms are the elements of the monoid. respectively.)

The second fundamental concept of category is the concept of a


functor, which plays the role of a morphism between two categories and it maps objects of to
objects of and morphisms of to morphisms of in such a way that sources are mapped to sources
and targets are mapped to targets (or, in the case of a contravariant functor, sources are mapped to targets
and vice-versa). A third fundamental concept is a natural transformation that may be viewed as a morphism
of functors.

Contents
Categories, objects, and morphisms
Categories
Morphisms
Functors
Natural transformations
Other concepts
Universal constructions, limits, and colimits
Equivalent categories
Further concepts and results
Higher-dimensional categories
Historical notes
See also
Notes
References
Citations
Sources
Further reading
External links

Categories, objects, and morphisms

Categories

A category C consists of the following three mathematical entities:

A class ob(C), whose elements are called objects;


A class hom(C), whose elements are called morphisms or maps or arrows.
Each morphism f has a source object a and target object b.
The expression f : a → b, would be verbally stated as "f is a morphism from a to b".
The expression hom(a, b) – alternatively expressed as homC(a, b), mor(a, b), or C(a, b) –
denotes the hom-class of all morphisms from a to b.
A binary operation ∘, called composition of morphisms, such that
for any three objects a, b, and c, we have

∘ : hom(b, c) × hom(a, b) → hom(a, c).

The composition of f : a → b and g : b → c is written as g ∘ f or gf,[a] governed by two


axioms:

1. Associativity: If f : a → b, g : b → c, and h : c → d then

h ∘ (g ∘ f) = (h ∘ g) ∘ f

2. Identity: For every object x, there exists a morphism 1x  : x → x called the identity
morphism for x,
such that

for every morphism f : a → b, we have


1b ∘ f = f = f ∘ ida.[b]

From the axioms, it can be proved that there is exactly one identity morphism for
every object.
Some authors deviate from the definition just given, by identifying each object with
its identity morphism.

Morphisms

Relations among morphisms (such as fg = h) are often depicted using commutative diagrams, with "points"
(corners) representing objects and "arrows" representing morphisms.

Morphisms can have any of the following properties. A morphism f : a → b is a:


monomorphism (or monic) if f ∘ g1 = f ∘ g2 implies g1 = g2 for all morphisms g1, g2 : x → a.
epimorphism (or epic) if g1 ∘ f = g2 ∘ f implies g1 = g2 for all morphisms g1, g2 : b → x.
bimorphism if f is both epic and monic.
isomorphism if there exists a morphism g : b → a such that f ∘ g = 1b and g ∘ f = 1a.[c]
endomorphism if a = b. end(a) denotes the class of endomorphisms of a.
automorphism if f is both an endomorphism and an isomorphism. aut(a) denotes the class of
automorphisms of a.
retraction if a right inverse of f exists, i.e. if there exists a morphism g : b → a with f ∘ g = 1b.
section if a left inverse of f exists, i.e. if there exists a morphism g : b → a with g ∘ f = 1a.

Every retraction is an epimorphism, and every section is a monomorphism. Furthermore, the following
three statements are equivalent:

f is a monomorphism and a retraction;


f is an epimorphism and a section;
f is an isomorphism.

Functors
Functors are structure-preserving maps between categories. They can be thought of as morphisms in the
category of all (small) categories.

A (covariant) functor F from a category C to a category D, written F : C → D, consists of:

for each object x in C, an object F(x) in D; and


for each morphism f : x → y in C, a morphism F(f) : F(x) → F(y) in D,

such that the following two properties hold:

For every object x in C, F(1x ) = 1F(x);


For all morphisms f : x → y and g : y → z, F(g ∘ f) = F(g) ∘ F(f).

A contravariant functor F: C → D is like a covariant functor, except that it "turns morphisms around"
("reverses all the arrows"). More specifically, every morphism f  : x → y in C must be assigned to a
morphism F(f) : F(y) → F(x) in D. In other words, a contravariant functor acts as a covariant functor from
the opposite category Cop to D.

Natural transformations
A natural transformation is a relation between two functors. Functors often describe "natural
constructions" and natural transformations then describe "natural homomorphisms" between two such
constructions. Sometimes two quite different constructions yield "the same" result; this is expressed by a
natural isomorphism between the two functors.

If F and G are (covariant) functors between the categories C and D, then a natural transformation η from F
to G associates to every object X in C a morphism ηX : F(X) → G(X) in D such that for every morphism
f : X → Y in C, we have ηY ∘ F(f) = G(f) ∘ ηX; this means that the following diagram is commutative:
The two functors F and G are called naturally isomorphic if there exists a natural transformation from F to
G such that ηX is an isomorphism for every object X in C.

Other concepts

Universal constructions, limits, and colimits

Using the language of category theory, many areas of mathematical study can be categorized. Categories
include sets, groups and topologies.

Each category is distinguished by properties that all its objects have in common, such as the empty set or
the product of two topologies, yet in the definition of a category, objects are considered atomic, i.e., we do
not know whether an object A is a set, a topology, or any other abstract concept. Hence, the challenge is to
define special objects without referring to the internal structure of those objects. To define the empty set
without referring to elements, or the product topology without referring to open sets, one can characterize
these objects in terms of their relations to other objects, as given by the morphisms of the respective
categories. Thus, the task is to find universal properties that uniquely determine the objects of interest.

Numerous important constructions can be described in a purely categorical way if the category limit can be
developed and dualized to yield the notion of a colimit.

Equivalent categories

It is a natural question to ask: under which conditions can two categories be considered essentially the
same, in the sense that theorems about one category can readily be transformed into theorems about the
other category? The major tool one employs to describe such a situation is called equivalence of categories,
which is given by appropriate functors between two categories. Categorical equivalence has found
numerous applications in mathematics.

Further concepts and results

The definitions of categories and functors provide only the very basics of categorical algebra; additional
important topics are listed below. Although there are strong interrelations between all of these topics, the
given order can be considered as a guideline for further reading.

The functor category DC has as objects the functors from C to D and as morphisms the
natural transformations of such functors. The Yoneda lemma is one of the most famous basic
results of category theory; it describes representable functors in functor categories.
Duality: Every statement, theorem, or definition in category theory has a dual which is
essentially obtained by "reversing all the arrows". If one statement is true in a category C
then its dual is true in the dual category Cop. This duality, which is transparent at the level of
category theory, is often obscured in applications and can lead to surprising relationships.
Adjoint functors: A functor can be left (or right) adjoint to another functor that maps in the
opposite direction. Such a pair of adjoint functors typically arises from a construction defined
by a universal property; this can be seen as a more abstract and powerful view on universal
properties.

Higher-dimensional categories

Many of the above concepts, especially equivalence of categories, adjoint functor pairs, and functor
categories, can be situated into the context of higher-dimensional categories. Briefly, if we consider a
morphism between two objects as a "process taking us from one object to another", then higher-
dimensional categories allow us to profitably generalize this by considering "higher-dimensional
processes".

For example, a (strict) 2-category is a category together with "morphisms between morphisms", i.e.,
processes which allow us to transform one morphism into another. We can then "compose" these
"bimorphisms" both horizontally and vertically, and we require a 2-dimensional "exchange law" to hold,
relating the two composition laws. In this context, the standard example is Cat, the 2-category of all (small)
categories, and in this example, bimorphisms of morphisms are simply natural transformations of
morphisms in the usual sense. Another basic example is to consider a 2-category with a single object; these
are essentially monoidal categories. Bicategories are a weaker notion of 2-dimensional categories in which
the composition of morphisms is not strictly associative, but only associative "up to" an isomorphism.

This process can be extended for all natural numbers n, and these are called n-categories. There is even a
notion of ω-category corresponding to the ordinal number ω.

Higher-dimensional categories are part of the broader mathematical field of higher-dimensional algebra, a
concept introduced by Ronald Brown. For a conversational introduction to these ideas, see John Baez, 'A
Tale of n-categories' (1996). (http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/week73.html)

Historical notes

It should be observed first that the whole concept of a category is essentially an auxiliary one;
our basic concepts are essentially those of a functor and of a natural transformation [...]

— Eilenberg and Mac Lane (1945) [1]

Whilst specific examples of functors and natural transformations had been given by Samuel Eilenberg and
Saunders Mac Lane in a 1942 paper on group theory,[2] these concepts were introduced in a more general
sense, together with the additional notion of categories, in a 1945 paper by the same authors[1] (who
discussed applications of category theory to the field of algebraic topology).[3] Their work was an
important part of the transition from intuitive and geometric homology to homological algebra, Eilenberg
and Mac Lane later writing that their goal was to understand natural transformations, which first required
the definition of functors, then categories.

Stanislaw Ulam, and some writing on his behalf, have claimed that related ideas were current in the late
1930s in Poland. Eilenberg was Polish, and studied mathematics in Poland in the 1930s. Category theory is
also, in some sense, a continuation of the work of Emmy Noether (one of Mac Lane's teachers) in
formalizing abstract processes;[4] Noether realized that understanding a type of mathematical structure
requires understanding the processes that preserve that structure (homomorphisms). Eilenberg and Mac
Lane introduced categories for understanding and formalizing the processes (functors) that relate
topological structures to algebraic structures (topological invariants) that characterize them.

Category theory was originally introduced for the need of homological algebra, and widely extended for
the need of modern algebraic geometry (scheme theory). Category theory may be viewed as an extension
of universal algebra, as the latter studies algebraic structures, and the former applies to any kind of
mathematical structure and studies also the relationships between structures of different nature. For this
reason, it is used throughout mathematics. Applications to mathematical logic and semantics (categorical
abstract machine) came later.

Certain categories called topoi (singular topos) can even serve as an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a
foundation of mathematics. A topos can also be considered as a specific type of category with two
additional topos axioms. These foundational applications of category theory have been worked out in fair
detail as a basis for, and justification of, constructive mathematics. Topos theory is a form of abstract sheaf
theory, with geometric origins, and leads to ideas such as pointless topology.

Categorical logic is now a well-defined field based on type theory for intuitionistic logics, with applications
in functional programming and domain theory, where a cartesian closed category is taken as a non-syntactic
description of a lambda calculus. At the very least, category theoretic language clarifies what exactly these
related areas have in common (in some abstract sense).

Category theory has been applied in other fields as well. For example, John Baez has shown a link between
Feynman diagrams in physics and monoidal categories.[5] Another application of category theory, more
specifically: topos theory, has been made in mathematical music theory, see for example the book The
Topos of Music, Geometric Logic of Concepts, Theory, and Performance by Guerino Mazzola.

More recent efforts to introduce undergraduates to categories as a foundation for mathematics include those
of William Lawvere and Rosebrugh (2003) and Lawvere and Stephen Schanuel (1997) and Mirroslav
Yotov (2012).

See also
Mathematics
portal

Domain theory
Enriched category theory
Glossary of category theory
Group theory
Higher category theory
Higher-dimensional algebra
Important publications in category theory
Lambda calculus
Outline of category theory
Timeline of category theory and related mathematics

Notes
a. Some authors compose in the opposite order, writing fg or f ∘ g for g ∘ f. Computer scientists
using category theory very commonly write f ; g for g ∘ f
b. Instead of the notation 1x , the identity morphism for x may be denoted as idx .
c. Note that a morphism that is both epic and monic is not necessarily an isomorphism! An
elementary counterexample: in the category consisting of two objects A and B, the identity
morphisms, and a single morphism f from A to B, f is both epic and monic but is not an
isomorphism.

References

Citations
1. Eilenberg, Samuel; Mac Lane, Saunders (1945). "General theory of natural equivalences" (h
ttps://www.ams.org/journals/tran/1945-058-00/S0002-9947-1945-0013131-6/S0002-9947-19
45-0013131-6.pdf) (PDF). Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 58: 247.
doi:10.1090/S0002-9947-1945-0013131-6 (https://doi.org/10.1090%2FS0002-9947-1945-00
13131-6). ISSN 0002-9947 (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/0002-9947). Archived (https://ghos
tarchive.org/archive/20221010/https://www.ams.org/journals/tran/1945-058-00/S0002-9947-
1945-0013131-6/S0002-9947-1945-0013131-6.pdf) (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-10.
2. Eilenberg, S.; Mac Lane, S. (1942). "Group Extensions and Homology" (https://www.jstor.or
g/stable/1968966). Annals of Mathematics. 43 (4): 757–831. doi:10.2307/1968966 (https://do
i.org/10.2307%2F1968966). ISSN 0003-486X (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/0003-486X).
JSTOR 1968966 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/1968966) – via JSTOR.
3. Marquis, Jean-Pierre (2019). "Category Theory" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/category-t
heory/). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Department of Philosophy, Stanford
University. Retrieved 26 September 2022.
4. Reck, Erich (2020). The Prehistory of Mathematical Structuralism (1st ed.). Oxford University
Press. pp. 215–219. ISBN 9780190641221.
5. Baez, J.C.; Stay, M. (2009). "Physics, topology, logic and computation: A Rosetta stone".
New Structures for Physics. Lecture Notes in Physics. Vol. 813. pp. 95–172.
arXiv:0903.0340 (https://arxiv.org/abs/0903.0340). doi:10.1007/978-3-642-12821-9_2 (http
s://doi.org/10.1007%2F978-3-642-12821-9_2). ISBN 978-3-642-12820-2.
S2CID 115169297 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:115169297).

Sources
Adámek, Jiří; Herrlich, Horst; Strecker, George E. (2004). Abstract and Concrete Categories
(http://katmat.math.uni-bremen.de/acc/acc.htm). Heldermann Verlag Berlin.
Barr, Michael; Wells, Charles (2012) [1995], Category Theory for Computing Science (http://
www.tac.mta.ca/tac/reprints/articles/22/tr22abs.html), Reprints in Theory and Applications of
Categories, vol. 22 (3rd ed.).
Barr, Michael; Wells, Charles (2005), Toposes, Triples and Theories (http://www.tac.mta.ca/t
ac/reprints/articles/12/tr12abs.html), Reprints in Theory and Applications of Categories,
vol. 12, MR 2178101 (https://mathscinet.ams.org/mathscinet-getitem?mr=2178101).
Borceux, Francis (1994). Handbook of categorical algebra (https://books.google.com/books?
id=YfzImoopB-IC&q=%22Handbook+of+categorical+algebra%22&pg=PP1). Encyclopedia
of Mathematics and its Applications. Cambridge University Press. pp. 50–52.
ISBN 9780521441780.
Freyd, Peter J. (2003) [1964]. Abelian Categories (http://www.tac.mta.ca/tac/reprints/articles/
3/tr3abs.html). Reprints in Theory and Applications of Categories. Vol. 3.
Freyd, Peter J.; Scedrov, Andre (1990). Categories, allegories (https://books.google.com/boo
ks?id=fCSJRegkKdoC). North Holland Mathematical Library. Vol. 39. North Holland.
ISBN 978-0-08-088701-2.
Goldblatt, Robert (2006) [1979]. Topoi: The Categorial Analysis of Logic (https://books.googl
e.com/books?id=AwLc-12-7LMC). Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics.
Vol. 94. Dover. ISBN 978-0-486-45026-1.
Herrlich, Horst; Strecker, George E. (2007). Category Theory (3rd ed.). Heldermann Verlag
Berlin. ISBN 978-3-88538-001-6..
Kashiwara, Masaki; Schapira, Pierre (2006). Categories and Sheaves (https://books.google.
com/books?id=K-SjOw_2gXwC). Grundlehren der Mathematischen Wissenschaften.
Vol. 332. Springer. ISBN 978-3-540-27949-5.
Lawvere, F. William; Rosebrugh, Robert (2003). Sets for Mathematics (https://archive.org/det
ails/setsformathemati0000lawv). Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-01060-3.
Lawvere, F. William; Schanuel, Stephen Hoel (2009) [1997]. Conceptual Mathematics: A
First Introduction to Categories (https://archive.org/details/conceptualmathem00lawv)
(2nd ed.). Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-89485-2.
Leinster, Tom (2004). Higher Operads, Higher Categories (https://web.archive.org/web/2003
1025120434/http://www.maths.gla.ac.uk/~tl/book.html). Higher Operads. London Math.
Society Lecture Note Series. Vol. 298. Cambridge University Press. p. 448.
Bibcode:2004hohc.book.....L (https://ui.adsabs.harvard.edu/abs/2004hohc.book.....L).
ISBN 978-0-521-53215-0. Archived from the original (http://www.maths.gla.ac.uk/~tl/book.ht
ml) on 2003-10-25. Retrieved 2006-04-03.
Leinster, Tom (2014). Basic Category Theory (https://books.google.com/books?id=Q3vsAwA
AQBAJ). Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics. Vol. 143. Cambridge University
Press. arXiv:1612.09375 (https://arxiv.org/abs/1612.09375). ISBN 9781107044241.
Lurie, Jacob (2009). Higher Topos Theory. Annals of Mathematics Studies. Vol. 170.
Princeton University Press. arXiv:math.CT/0608040 (https://arxiv.org/abs/math.CT/0608040).
ISBN 978-0-691-14049-0. MR 2522659 (https://mathscinet.ams.org/mathscinet-getitem?mr=
2522659).
Mac Lane, Saunders (1998). Categories for the Working Mathematician. Graduate Texts in
Mathematics. Vol. 5 (2nd ed.). Springer-Verlag. ISBN 978-0-387-98403-2. MR 1712872 (http
s://mathscinet.ams.org/mathscinet-getitem?mr=1712872).
Mac Lane, Saunders; Birkhoff, Garrett (1999) [1967]. Algebra (2nd ed.). Chelsea. ISBN 978-
0-8218-1646-2.
Martini, A.; Ehrig, H.; Nunes, D. (1996). "Elements of basic category theory" (http://citeseer.is
t.psu.edu/martini96element.html). Technical Report. 96 (5).
May, Peter (1999). A Concise Course in Algebraic Topology. University of Chicago Press.
ISBN 978-0-226-51183-2.
Mazzola, Guerino (2002). The Topos of Music, Geometric Logic of Concepts, Theory, and
Performance. Birkhäuser. ISBN 978-3-7643-5731-3.
Pedicchio, Maria Cristina; Tholen, Walter, eds. (2004). Categorical foundations. Special
topics in order, topology, algebra, and sheaf theory. Encyclopedia of Mathematics and Its
Applications. Vol. 97. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-83414-8.
Zbl 1034.18001 (https://zbmath.org/?format=complete&q=an:1034.18001).
Pierce, Benjamin C. (1991). Basic Category Theory for Computer Scientists (https://books.g
oogle.com/books?id=ezdeaHfpYPwC). MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-66071-6.
Schalk, A.; Simmons, H. (2005). An introduction to Category Theory in four easy movements
(https://web.archive.org/web/20170321152109/http://www.cs.man.ac.uk/~hsimmons/BOOK
S/CatTheory.pdf) (PDF). Archived from the original (http://www.cs.man.ac.uk/~hsimmons/BO
OKS/CatTheory.pdf) (PDF) on 2017-03-21. Retrieved 2007-12-03. Notes for a course offered
as part of the MSc. in Mathematical Logic, Manchester University.
Simpson, Carlos (2010). Homotopy theory of higher categories (https://archive.org/details/ar
xiv-1001.4071). arXiv:1001.4071 (https://arxiv.org/abs/1001.4071).
Bibcode:2010arXiv1001.4071S (https://ui.adsabs.harvard.edu/abs/2010arXiv1001.4071S).,
draft of a book.
Taylor, Paul (1999). Practical Foundations of Mathematics (https://books.google.com/books?
id=iSCqyNgzamcC). Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics. Vol. 59. Cambridge
University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-63107-5.
Turi, Daniele (1996–2001). "Category Theory Lecture Notes" (http://www.dcs.ed.ac.uk/home/
dt/CT/categories.pdf) (PDF). Retrieved 11 December 2009. Based on Mac Lane 1998.

Further reading
Marquis, Jean-Pierre (2008). From a Geometrical Point of View: A Study of the History and
Philosophy of Category Theory. Springer. ISBN 978-1-4020-9384-5.

External links
Theory and Application of Categories (http://www.tac.mta.ca/tac/), an electronic journal of
category theory, full text, free, since 1995.
nLab (http://ncatlab.org/nlab), a wiki project on mathematics, physics and philosophy with
emphasis on the n-categorical point of view.
The n-Category Café (https://golem.ph.utexas.edu/category/), essentially a colloquium on
topics in category theory.
Category Theory (http://www.logicmatters.net/categories/), a web page of links to lecture
notes and freely available books on category theory.
Hillman, Chris (2001), A Categorical Primer, CiteSeerX 10.1.1.24.3264 (https://citeseerx.ist.p
su.edu/viewdoc/summary?doi=10.1.1.24.3264), a formal introduction to category theory.
Adamek, J.; Herrlich, H.; Stecker, G. "Abstract and Concrete Categories-The Joy of Cats" (htt
p://katmat.math.uni-bremen.de/acc/acc.pdf) (PDF). Archived (https://web.archive.org/web/20
060610174819/http://katmat.math.uni-bremen.de/acc/acc.pdf) (PDF) from the original on
2006-06-10.
"Category Theory" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/category-theory/) entry by Jean-Pierre
Marquis in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, with an extensive bibliography.
List of academic conferences on category theory (http://www.mta.ca/~cat-dist/)
Baez, John (1996). "The Tale of n-categories" (http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/week73.html).
— An informal introduction to higher order categories.
WildCats (http://wildcatsformma.wordpress.com) is a category theory package for
Mathematica. Manipulation and visualization of objects, morphisms, categories, functors,
natural transformations, universal properties.
The catsters's channel (https://www.youtube.com/user/TheCatsters) on YouTube, a channel
about category theory.
Category theory (https://planetmath.org/9categorytheory) at PlanetMath..
Video archive (http://categorieslogicphysics.wikidot.com/events) of recorded talks relevant to
categories, logic and the foundations of physics.
Interactive Web page (https://web.archive.org/web/20080916162345/http://www.j-paine.org/c
gi-bin/webcats/webcats.php) which generates examples of categorical constructions in the
category of finite sets.
Category Theory for the Sciences (https://web.archive.org/web/20150109111227/http://categ
ory-theory.mitpress.mit.edu/index.html), an instruction on category theory as a tool
throughout the sciences.
Category Theory for Programmers (https://bartoszmilewski.com/2014/10/28/category-theory-f
or-programmers-the-preface/) A book in blog form explaining category theory for computer
programmers.
Introduction to category theory. (http://math.mit.edu/~dspivak/teaching/sp18/7Sketches.pdf)

Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Category_theory&oldid=1127456471"

This page was last edited on 14 December 2022, at 20:38 (UTC).

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 3.0; additional terms may apply. By
using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the
Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.

You might also like