Citizenship and Identity - Engin Isin and Patricia K Wood
Citizenship and Identity - Engin Isin and Patricia K Wood
Citizenship and Identity - Engin Isin and Patricia K Wood
1-2
In some ways a direct challenge to the liberal democratic institutions that sustained it, cultural politics
has emerged in the past 20 years as a force for the recognition of both identity and difference.
“Venturing beyond the liberal and communitarian views that lament the decline of the public sphere
and active citizenship, cultural politics forced a relentless pluralization of taste, identity, politics and
being in the world and opened up new and vital spaces for politics (C. Connolly, 1993; W.E. Connolly,
1995). Lacking – indeed shunning – a center or party, the cultural politics of recognition sometimes
culminated in progressive politics of inclusion and sometimes in regressive politics of exclusion. But,
overall, its diversity, plurality, nomadism and culturaism surprised and confused those both on the left
and the right (Foweraker and Landman, 1997).”
2
Amongst advocates of cultural politics, however, there is disagreement as to the extent of the
redistributive and equalizing potential of cultural politics. “To put it simply, the political question (or
perhaps anxiety) of our times is whether cultural politics can form an effective resistance ot injustice,
inequality domination and oppression engendered by advanced capitalism and institutionalized by
neoliberalism… To some, cultural politics is too fragmented, incoherent and ‘merely cultural’ – that is,
too far removed from the economic realm – to mount such resistance… To others, the fragmentation,
incoherence and symbolism of cultural politics are precisely its political strengths. They believe that
groups suffer injustices and inequalities on the basis of unequal and unfair distribution not only of
economic capital but also of symbolic, social and cultural capital.”
“This book addresses citizenship and identity as two different windows on the same questions: what
conceptual tools are available to define a deep concept of citizenship that can recognize group rights;
and what happens when we take group-differentiated or multilayered citizenship seriously under
advanced capitalism?”
3
It is a commonplace view that citizenship and identity are incompatible and incommensurable
attachments, and thus are irreconcilable political forces. This arises from a specific conception of each:
“citizenship as universal and identity as particular”. The fear is that there is a parochial quality to identity
that negates the possibilities of an inclusive and responsive notion of citizenship, which is typically seen
as more abstract (See Friedman 1989; Littleton 1996; Morely and Robins 1995; Heater 1990).
4
“This book takes a different tack. We approach the relationship between citizenship and identity from a
perspective that sees modern citizenship not only as a legal and political membership in a nation-state
but also as an articulating principle for the recognition of group rights…Rather than regarding citizenship
and identity as antinomic principles, we recognize the rise of new identities and claims for group rights
as a challenge to the modern interpretation of universal citizenship, which is itself a form of group
identity.”
“Citizenship can be described as both a set of practices (cultural, symbolic and economic) and a bundle
of rights and duties (civil, political and social) that define an individual’s membership in a polity. It is
important to recognize both aspects of citizenship – as practice and as status – while also recognizing
that without the latter modern individuals cannot hold civil, political and social rights. In the same vein
many rights often first arise as practices and then become embodied in law as status – while also
recognizing that without the latter modern individuals cannot hold civil, political and social rights.
Citizenship is therefore neither a purely sociological concept nor purely a legal concept but a relationship
between the two… While, then, citizenship can be defined as a legal and political status, from a
sociological point of view, it can be defined as competent membership in a polity, thus emphasizing the
constitutive aspect of citizenship (Turner, 1994b).”
4-5
Since the late eighteenth century, the nation state has become the predominant polity the world over –
and while its composition of rights and practices may vary, as an institution it is near ubiquitous.
5
“It is very important to recognize that the status and practice of citizenship emerged in specific places in
response to specific struggles and conflicts. It is a contested and contingent field that allowed for the
mediation of conflict, redistribution of wealth and recognition of various individual and group rights
throughout history. The fact that it eventually became universal should be interpreted not as ‘natural’
but rather as contingent and political.”
6
Though citizenship has a long history of contestation and transformation – so that assuming a
fundamental historical continuity in the substance of rights and practices is problematic – these
transformations are especially tied to periods of social transformation or upheaval. Thus today, the
sense of a fundamentally changed world signaled by the idea of post-modernism (though the substance
of this change, be it of disembedding or fragmentation, is widely contested) has led to a linked re-
interrogation and contestation over ideas of citizenship.
8
There is a notable gap between the philosophical doctrine of liberalism and the actual legal and political
practice in modern democracies (Frazer and Lacey 1993; Oldfield 1990). Indeed, the literature on
governmentality interprets liberalism in the real world as a practice articulated through various
technologies of government – whose net result does not quite resemble liberalism as conceived and
engaged with philosophically (Barry, Osborne and Rose 1996; Burchell Gordon and Miller 1991).
10
While liberalism, communitarianism and civic republicanism “struggle for a new conception of
citizenship that resolves the tension between universalism and particularism, there is also an ostensibly
radical view of democracy that sees such a tension as constitutive of the democratic process. Among
these commentators Mouffe (1993) has been prominent. She argues that a radical democratic
conception of citizenship ‘can only be adequately formulated within a problematic that conceives of the
social agent not as a unitary subject but as the articulation of an ensemble of subject positions,
constructed within specific discourses and always precariously and temporarily sutured at the
intersection of those subject positions’. She advocates developing a non-essentialist conception of the
subject and regarding identity as identification with groups rather than as essential properties of the
subject (Mouffe, 1993: 71; 1996).” In Mouffe’s conception, then, political community must be focused
on justice, equality and community in a way which is responsive to emergent political demands.
“According to Mouffe, ‘The question at stake is to make our belonging to different communities of
values, language, culture and others compatible with our common belonging to a political community
whose rules we have to accept’ (1995: 34).”
“Mouffe contends that exclusive concern with individual rights cannot provide guidance for the exercise
of those rights. In other words, ‘The limitation of democracy to a mere set of neutral procedure, the
transformation of citizens into political consumers, and the liberal insistence on a supposed ‘neutrality’
of the state have emptied politics of all its substance. It is reduced to economic and stripped of all its
ethical components’ (Mouffe 1996: 22).”
11
Viewing identity as multiply constituted “Mouffe rightly does not see group rights in conflict with
citizenship. Rather, radical democratic citizens depend on a collective form of identification among the
democratic demands found in a variety of movements: women, workers, black, gay and ecological as
well as other oppositional movements. Her conception of citizenship aims to construct a ‘we’, a chain of
equivalence among various demands to articulate them through the principle of democratic equivalence
without eliminating difference (Mouffe 1995: 38).”
Thus, drawing on Oakeshott’s (1975) distinction between univesitas and societas, she argues that we can
conceive of polities as held together by common purpose, or by common interest – and advocates for
the former. Common purpose allows for a singular social teleology, while common interest recognizes
and works with different purposive associations, while constituting a broader polity in terms of their
intersecting interests and implications.
12
Based on this, Mouffe advocates for a polity that values conflict and antagonism. “In this view,
individuals would not be construed as peacefully pushing their interests, but would be engaging each
other over the meaning and definition of their common interests. The object of politics would be the
association itself. There will never be a homogenous unity in such an association since there will always
be a need for a constitutive other (1992: 235)
Thus, in Mouffe’s conception, citizenship is neither simply one identity amongst many (as in liberalism)
nor a predominant set of rules (as within communitarianism), but “‘an articulating principle that affects
the different subject positions of the social agent.. while allowing for a plurality of specific allegiences
and for the respect of individual liberty.’ (1992: 235).”
“We part with Mouffe, however, because she ultimately conflates citizenship and identity. While she
aims to develop a conception of radical citizenship that is not unitary, she eventually succumbs to a
conception where citizenship becomes a master political identity.”
13
“This conflation between citizenship and identity takes Mouffe back to the ‘political liberalism’ of Rawls
(1996), where a sharp distinction is drawn between citizenship as political identity and other identities
attachments and loyalties.” In casting the salience of group identities – themselves formed through the
historical inculcation of particular dispositions - as difference to be effaced in light of an overarching
citizenship, Mouffe is ultimately unable to treat identity and difference as a resource.
14
While the question of identity is not new, Bauman (1996) rightly argues that it is distinctive in the
modern era. There are three factors here: firstly in that debates over the distribution of wealth and
power have been complicated by struggles over the specific exclusion and possibilities for inclusion of
different identity groups; secondly that everyday life has become increasingly aestheticized, with
consumption becoming an important constitutive aspect of identity formation; and third that the shift to
a post-industrial economy has meant that he production of images, sounds, experiences and knowledge
has gained primacy over the production of material commodities.”
14-15
If the first wave of identity politics focused on identifying identities constructed as categories of
disadvantage so as to dismantle this socially-constructed disadvantage, the second wave became about
positively recognizing the differences between groups and society as a whole. However, a third wave
can be identified which articulates a set of strategies which simultaneously aims to affirm identities and
to transcend them (Lister 1997a; Voet 1998; hall and Du Gay 1996; Rajchman 1995).
16
For Hall (1996) who puts the emphasis on the processual nature of identity, “Individual and group
‘identities about questions of using the resources of history, language and culture in the process of
ecoming rather than being: not ‘who we are’ or ‘where we came from’, so much as what we might
become, how we have been represented and how that bears on how we might represent ourselves’ (4).
This is neither an active nor a passive conception of identity. To Hall, ‘Identities are… points of
temporary attachment to the subject positions which discursive practices construct for us’ (5-6).”
16-17
“While Hall has been crucial in developing non-essentialist views of identity, his view of multiple subjects
and the construction of identity leave open the gap in understanding why groups feel so strongly about
their identities and invoke essentialist notions in their struggle for recognition. As Calhoun (1994a: 14-
16) argued, such social construtivism can become exclusionary when every effort of group identification
is criticized for essentialism.”
17-18
To address some of the limitations in essentialist and constructivist approaches to identity, four key
concepts presented here: the concept of difference describes the constitutive relationship of negativity
that subordinate groups have to super-ordinated groups, rendering dominant identities inherently
unstable as they must necessarily incorporate their negation if they are to define themselves; the
concept of fragmentation sees lived identity as a fragmentary and often contradictory unity; the concept
of hybridity captures border existences, or subaltern identities, existing or moving between two
competing identities; and finally the concept of diaspora which is closely related to the idea of border-
crossing, but with a more cross-time inflection.
19
“While it is important to recognize that identification is not a simple process, it is also important that
‘identity formation’ through which individuals incorporate certain characteristics and values is a process
involving relatively durable attachments, obligations and promises. Thus, it is inadequate to focus on
one aspect (fluidity and multiplicity) of identity at the expense of the other (solidity and relative
permanence).”
“Many scholars argue for a concept of citizenship broader than an juridical and legal status but these
arguments do not change the basic fact that ultimately citizenship allows or disallows civil, political and
social rights and obligations in a polity. Such arguments for active citizenship or deep citizenship are
concerned with deepening the scope of citizenship but they nevertheless presuppose that the status of
citizenship already exists.”
Usefully, “Identity is a concept that presupposes a dialogical recognition of the other; it is a relational
concept. But it is also a concept that presupposes identification in the sense that individuals recognize
attributes or properties in each other that are constructed as identical, or at least similar. These
properties, then, are used as an index of individual position and disposition. Identity is therefore not so
much of uniqueness or distinction as of resemblance and repetition (Jenkins, 1996). By contrast, an
individual is a distinct assemblage of identities. Thus, individuality should be kept distinct from identity.”
20
Against those who charge that the particularism of identity politics cuts against a vital universalism
within citizenship, an important first step is the recognition that despite claims to universalism,
citizenship has never been expanded to all members of any polity – and for those to whom it is
extended, it is often articulated in stratified ways. The fact is that by defining a specific set of rights and
duties, citizenship cannot ever be wholly inclusive. A principle of recognizing group difference is a way
to perpetually mitigate against the closures of citizenship, by empowering groups to mobilize and come
together in blocks to struggle for rights. Such a value of ongoing conflict (or agonism) emerges from
formulations of post-modern or radical democracy (W.E. Connolly, 1988, 1991; Hatab, 1995; Mouffe,
1992c, 1993; Trend, 1996).
21
The formulation of citizenship ultimately developed here is “a richer and multilayered conception of
citizenship understood as an ensemble of different forms of belonging rather than a universal or unitary
conception”.
22
Various modes of radical democratic citizenship are expounded here, including “the political, civil, social,
economic, diasporic, cultural, sexual and ecological.”
“Being a radical citizen cannot merely be associated with being a member of the nation state and
nationality as master identity. Rather, the identity of a postmodern citizen is an ensemble of these
different forms of citizenship understood as competent membership in various value-spheres or fields
such as the sexual or ecological.”