Playing Dice With The Universe 20221212
Playing Dice With The Universe 20221212
Playing Dice With The Universe 20221212
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
SF-TH Inc is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Science Fiction
Studies
Amy Ransom
Meillassoux digs deeper and finds three types of extro-science worlds, two of
which he subsequently disqualifies. True XSF must construct a world in which
“irregularity is sufficient to abolish science, but not consciousness” (36);
random events would occur with a certain amount of frequency, so that “no
eventual sphere would be preserved from a-causal disorder,” but “daily life
could always build on stabilities that are certainly very relative, but still
sufficiently powerful to allow a conscious existence” (36). Finally, genuine
XSF fulfills two requirements: “within it events take place that no real or
imaginary ‘logic’ can explain; … [and] the question of science is present in the
tale, albeit in a negative mode”: it presents “a world in which science
suddenly becomes … impossible” (44) or was never present at all.
Meillassoux then offers three partial examples from the Anglo-American
canon, and claims to have identified one bona fide XFS novel, French sf
writer René Barjavel’s Ravage (1943). The first three, Philip K. Dick’s Ubik
(1969), Douglas Adams’s Hitchhiker’s Guide to the Galaxy (1979), and Robert
Charles Wilson’s Darwinia (1998), are all “novels that take place within an
uncertain reality, in which the real would go to pieces, progressively ceasing
to be familiar” (48). Unfortunately, though, these novels eventually either
explain their unstable phenomena or, in the case of Hitchhiker’s Guide,
“produce a form of nonsense, verging on the pure joke” (47; emphasis in
original). Only in Barjavel’s Ravage (translated by Damon Knight as Ashes,
Ashes in 1967) does he find a work that so completely “grafts itself on a SF
context that it contaminates with a logic foreign to it” (49-50). According to
Meillassoux, Barjavel denies any restoration of order or logical explanation so
“that the inhabitants of this world have all their time taken up by the vagaries
of an environment that has become unpredictable and unrecognizable” (52-53).
René Barjavel (1911-1985) is one of France’s most respected sf writers,
but his works are also found in mainstream literary imprints. Wikipedia credits
him with being one of the first writers to invoke the grandfather paradox in
time travel, with Le Voyageur imprudent (1944; trans. as Future Times Three
by Margaret Sansone Scouten in 1958). La Nuit des temps (1968; trans. as The
Ice People by C.L. Markham in 1971) is considered an incontournable
[unavoidable; a must-read] classic of French sf. He is a logical choice of
author for Meillassoux as his works, in particular La Faim du tigre [The
Hunger of the Tiger, 1966], question the existence of God. The goal of
Meillassoux’s philosophy is precisely to recover his discipline’s capacity for
speculative thinking in the absence of metaphysics and theism (see Watkin).
One must understand this aspect of Barjavel’s ideology to accept Meillassoux’s
categorization of Ravage as XSF; without this knowledge, aspects of the text
suggest that divine intervention might explain the breakdown of natural laws
that it posits.
Ravage at first appears to be a typical French anticipation [novel of the
future] extrapolating technological developments and their impact on everyday
life in the year 2052. The tale is told with humor and/or a critical bent that
makes its future Paris something of a dystopia, and when that society suddenly
breaks down—the book was written during the Nazi Occupation, as was Albert
a formerly maintained law of physics, the world goes on; life becomes
increasingly contingent, however, and a good portion of the novel narrates the
protagonist’s struggle to survive with a small group of followers. It eventually
concludes with their installation on a farm (a fortunate throwback still in
existence thanks to stubborn peasants’ refusal to embrace modernity) and the
constitution of a new, peaceful, agrarian society with an oral tradition of its
origin and a new religion. All seems to be for the best in the best of possible
worlds—until, one day, a curious boy constructs a machine.…
Meillassoux senses the critical potential that such fiction holds for
speculative thought, and I cannot help but be swept away by his rhetoric. Yet
some unresolved issues plague the text. First, Meillassoux waffles in his
terminology, referring variously to extro-science fiction as a “genre within the
genre” (4), but later arguing that it “can become a full-fledged genre” of its
own (56). This may be simply splitting hairs. Of more substantial difficulty
is Meillassoux’s lack of engagement with other theories of sf. My impression
is that his differentiation of what we might call “classic” sf from “extro-sf”
may not be a completely original insight, although his manner of arriving at
it is. I would welcome a deeper interrogation of this short book in relation to
existing genre theory. Finally, his understanding of the term “science” is an
uncomplicated one, taking for granted that all science is Western-style science,
thus leaving him open to critiques from alternative perspectives. I would like
to see how XSF might be related to indigenous futurism, postcolonial sf, and
other forms of speculative fiction outside the Anglo-American canon.
Meillassoux’s example of Barjavel’s Ravage does suggest the potential
application of the term XSF to any number of Western texts today, beginning
with certain zombie-apocalypse narratives, from Colson Whitehead’s Zone One
(2011) to the recent French series (not really about zombies per se) Les
Revenants [The Returned, 2012-2015]. The latter presents a world in which
the dead return for no apparent reason, and why these dead in particular is
never fully explained (although this may be due to the pressures to wrap up
a series before it has run its course in its creators’ minds). Indeed, in most
zombie texts, although a pseudo-scientific explanation may be given (an
epidemic), no current laws of physics or biology can explain the walking
dead, nor are any new ones rationally extrapolated. But are we then in the
realm of true extro-science fiction, or merely poorly conceived sf, or perhaps
the supernatural fantastic?
Which brings us back to Meillassoux’s interest in metaphysics. With its
intriguing title and cover illustration (a manipulated image of stars scintillating
in what appears to be deep space), After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity
of Contingency may at first glance appear to be more directly related to the
problems of space and time at the core of science fiction than it actually is.
Although its conclusions do have significant bearing on our field, and one of
its particular goals is to legitimate the scientific study of the distant past and
far future, Meillassoux’s most serious book may prove a bit much for the non-
philosopher. Meillassoux himself admits that “[p]hilosophy is the invention of
strange forms of argumentation, necessarily bordering on sophistry, which
remains its dark structural double” (76). This book is a proof in point.
Whereas his goal is to refute Kant’s and Hume’s positions on the necessity of
the laws of nature, concluding instead that the only absolute necessity is
contingency, the path he takes to get there—admittedly, in keeping with his
profession as a philosopher and a teacher at one of France’s most prestigious
universities, the École Normale Supérieure—is a series of seemingly
convoluted arguments, as well as refutations of potential objections to those
arguments, deeply rooted in the philosophical tradition. Although I frequently
felt in above my head, I will attempt to summarize here the main points of
relevance to the study of sf.
Chapters 1, “Ancestrality,” and 2, “Metaphysics, Fideism, Speculation,”
introduce two key concepts in Meillassoux’s overall project: ancestrality and
correlationism (see Harman). Correlationism is Meillassoux’s term for the type
of philosophy in effect since Kant and codified by twentieth-century
phenomenologists—that, in the absence of an absolute necessity (God),
knowledge cannot be absolute but must be based on human observation. All
knowledge (and thus reality) is based on the co-relation between human
observer and observed; this philosophical position introduces a form of anti-
realist relativism that ultimately denies the independent existence of the
universe outside of human intelligence/reason. The problem for science is that
we now have scientifically observed and/or extrapolated phenomena that
predate and outdistance actual human perception. Ancestrality refers to
scientific facts that pose a problem for correlationist thought—for example,
archeological knowledge of the earth’s development before the evolution of
human intelligence or astronomical data about the distant past taken from stars
hundreds of thousands of light years away from earth. Meillassoux’s goal is
to resolve this conundrum, effectively rejecting correlationism as a tenable
epistemology; he has to justify “the possibility of thinking what there is when
there is no thought” (36).
Traveling through Descartes’s cogito ergo sum (from the 1637 Discourse
on Method), which was put into the service of metaphysics by also being used
to prove the existence of God (fideism), moving on to Kant’s Critique of Pure
Reason (1781), which allows the refutation of Descartes and becomes the basis
of contemporary correlationism, Meillassoux argues that in order to escape the
traps of both the necessity of God and correlationism, “we must uncover an
absolute necessity that does not reinstate any form of absolutely necessary
entity” (34; emphasis in original). Since it seems generally agreed that neither
God nor any other ultimate cause for the universe exists to explain why things
are the way they are, we must find some other type of final cause, or perhaps
not even a cause per se.
In chapter 3, “The Principle of Factiality,” Meillassoux takes on Kant and
Hegel, borrowing the Heideggerian term “facticity” (see Harman 21-22), and
works toward “demonstrating the thesis which states that the thing-in-itself
actually exists, and there is a realm of the in-itself” (71)—that is, that the real
does exist independently of human perceptions of it, thus refuting the
correlationist position. Through facticity, he arrives at an absolute, “the one
that would allow mathematical science to describe the in-itself” (64): Chaos.
Along the way, Meillassoux acknowledges the skeptic’s questions, such as
“How could such a disaster provide the foundation for scientific knowledge?
How could Chaos possibly legitimate knowledge of the ancestral?” (65) He
asserts that only “an extreme form of Chaos, a hyper-chaos, for which nothing
is or would seem to be impossible, not even the unthinkable” (64) offers
philosophy “an omnipotence equal to that of the Cartesian God, and capable
of anything, even the inconceivable” (64; emphasis in original). This hyper-
chaos is “Contingency [that] expresses the fact that physical laws remain
indifferent as to whether an event occurs or not—they allow an entity to
emerge, to subsist, or to perish” (39; emphasis in original). This, and this
alone, of all natural laws is necessary; thus, contingency is the absolute
necessity. He then develops another apparently original concept, mentioned in
the chapter’s title: “factuality,” that “exerts the actual contingency of the laws
of nature” (83; see Harman 30).
Chapter 4, “Hume’s problem,” refers not just to the fact that Meillassoux
“has a problem” with Hume’s philosophy, but also to the “familiar
philosophical problem” of cause and effect, predictability, and returning again
to the necessity of natural laws governing the universe (85-86). Essentially,
Hume argues that, since we can predict the workings of the universe via
science and can repeat experiments to verify results, we have predictability,
which means there must be natural laws organizing the universe. Here is
where After Finitude is most closely linked to Science Fiction and Extro-
Science Fiction, because once Meillassoux demolishes Hume he opens the way
for XSF and restores to philosophy a speculative power that it had
relinquished to science. He asserts that: “Hume’s problem raises the question
of whether … physics as such … will continue to be possible in the future.…
[C]an we demonstrate that the experimental science which is possible today
will still be possible tomorrow?” (86; emphasis in original). Concluding that
we cannot, he confronts his imaginary objectors, at the same time describing
before the fact the task of XSF narratives. His argument posits, first, that, if
we accept that there is no reason for things to be the way they are (there is no
absolute necessity, either God or natural laws), then we must embrace
unreason (82-83). But if we do admit that “not only things but also physical
laws are really contingent, … we would have to admit that these laws could
actually change at any moment for no reason whatsoever” (83; emphasis in
original). Such a world, “a world without physical necessity[,] would be riven
at each instant and in each of its points by an immense multiplicity of
disconnected possibilities” (84); this possibility very clearly points to
imaginary worlds found in a wide array of texts that we now label sf but may
now want to reconsider as XSF. A further passage, in which Meillassoux
answers his objectors, bears citing because of its literary applications:
Those of us who endorse this claim [that natural laws are contingent] would
have to spend our time fearing that familiar objects could at any moment
behave in the most unexpected ways, congratulating ourselves every evening
on having made it through the day without a hitch…. Such a conception of
not play dice with the universe” (although this may be a merely personal
connection; it seems unlikely that Einstein spent his free time reading French
symbolist poetry). Of course, Einstein was not reaffirming Divine Providence
but rather addressing the strangeness of quantum mechanics and attempting to
refute Heisenberg’s Uncertainty Principle (see Dickerson). The cat in the
metaphorical box, in Schrödinger’s telling, is both alive and dead at the same
time. This is precisely the position taken by the protagonist of Mallarmé’s
poem, a figure for the poet himself. In Meillassoux’s account, Mallarmé
achieves the perfect ambiguity, a moment of hesitation frozen forever in the
poem’s telling (a technique that could be linked to the Todorovian fantastic),
in which the ship’s captain has either thrown or not thrown the dice as his ship
(in another clear homage to Poe) descends into the maelstrom. Meillassoux’s
fascination with this poem and his desire to crack its code derives as well from
his own search to find an absolute necessity in the absence of God.
To return to the question asked in the introduction of this review-essay: by
reducing the necessity for natural laws to the single law of contingency, has
Meillassoux rendered the scientific project to discover such laws useless? I
hope it has been clear that, instead, his philosophical project actually seeks to
rescue science by removing the barrier that contemporary philosophy has
placed on scientific knowledge by limiting it to the scope of human reason.
More important for Meillassoux, though, is his call to philosophy to once
again engage in speculative theorization, a function it lost when it abandoned
metaphysics as a valid pursuit. Most importantly for us, his work invites the
question: has science fiction (with or without its corollary of extro-science
fiction) been performing all along the speculative work that philosophy has for
so long abjured?
WORKS CITED
Barjavel, René. Ashes, Ashes. 1943 (as Ravage). Trans. Damon Knight. New York:
Doubleday, 1967.
Dickerson, Kelly. “One of Einstein’s Most Famous Quotes Is Often Completely
Misinterpreted.” Tech Insider. 19 Nov. 2015. Online.
Harman, Graham. Quentin Meillassoux: Philosophy in the Making. Edinburgh:
Edinburgh UP, 2011.
“René Barjavel.” Wikipedia: The Free Encyclopedia. Online.
Watkin, Christopher. “Beyond A/theism? Quentin Meillassoux.” Difficult Atheism:
Post-Theological Thinking in Alain Badiou, Jean-Luc Nancy and Quentin
Meillassoux. Edinburgh: Edinburgh UP, 2011. 132-67.