Hobbes and The Legitimacy of Law
Hobbes and The Legitimacy of Law
Hobbes and The Legitimacy of Law
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Law and
Philosophy
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
DAVID DYZENHAUS
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
462 DAVID DYZENHAUS
2 Both of these theses are articulated in H.L.A. Hart, "Positivism and the
Separation of Law and Morals," reprinted in his Essays in Jurisprudence and
Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), pp. 49-87 and in Hart, The Concept
of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961). In a posthumously published "Post-
cript" to the second edition of the latter work, Hart qualified the second thesis
by joining the "incorporationist" camp within legal positivism; see Concept of
Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), pp. 250-254. I will not go into this issue
here but I explore it in detail in "Positivism's Stagnant Research Programme",
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 20 (2000), pp. 703-722.
3 See Hart, "Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals," pp. 58-60 and
The Concept of Law, chap. 6.
4 As I will indicate later, Hobbes's closest ally in contemporary debates is Lon
L. Fuller. See Fuller, The Morality of Law (New Haven: Yale University Press, rev.
edn., 1969). Fuller, however, adopted the Hobbist reading of Hobbes sketched
below - see Lon L. Fuller, The Law in Quest of Itself (Boston: Beacon Press,
1966), pp. 19-30, although he did note (at pp. 22-23) that Hobbes's principles of
natural reason complicate the reading. In earlier work, I accepted Fuller's Hobbist
reading - see David Dyzenhaus, Hard Cases in Wicked Legal Systems: South
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 463
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
464 DAVID DYZENHAUS
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 465
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
466 DAVID DYZENHAUS
And first it is manifest, that Law in generall, is not Counsell, but Comm
Command of any man to any man; but only of him, whose command is
to one formerly obliged to obey him. And as for Civill Law, it addeth
name of the person Commanding, which is Persona Civitatis, the Pers
Common-wealth.9
COMMAND is, where a man saith, Doe this, or Doe not this, without expecting
other reason than the Will of him that sayes it. From this it followeth manifestly,
that he that Commandeth, pretendeth thereby his own benefit: For the reason of
his Command is his own Will onely, and the proper object of every mans Will, is
some Good to himselfe.10
I will leave until later Hobbes's rather odd claim that the
commander has only his own benefit in mind, noting only
neglected movement in his definition of command from the id
of a natural commander in chapter 25 to the idea of the artific
legislator or sovereign in his chapter 26 definition of civil law. F
I want to get clear the puzzle about how to place Hobbes.
Hobbes seems part of the natural law tradition because he den
the Separation Thesis; there can, according to him, be no confl
between positive law and morality or natural law. But he also see
to subscribe to the Identification Thesis, which says that all law
positive law. Moreover, it can be argued that if Hobbes's position
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 467
12 The most sophisticated attempt so far to put Hobbes back in the natur
tradition is to be found in Mark C. Murphy, "Was Hobbes a Legal Positivi
Ethics 105 (1995), pp. 846-873. On my account, Murphy's attempt fails, fi
because he accepts the terms set by the contemporary debate and second, b
he, like almost all other participants in the discussion about how to place H
discusses the relationship between the laws of nature and positive law wit
giving any real attention to Hobbes's catalogue of natural law.
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
468 DAVID DYZENHAUS
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 469
a third, to punish the second; and so continually without end, to the Confusion,
and Dissolution of the Common-wealth". Leviathan, chap. 29 [169], p. 367. For
the label "regress argument", see Jean Hampton, Hobbes and the Social Contract
Tradition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), pp. 97 ff.
14 Hence, Hobbes's curious position on punishment, in which punishment is an
act of public authority, but which the sovereign exercises as a kind of residue of
the right of nature - Leviathan, chap. 28 [161-162], pp. 353-354.
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
470 DAVID DYZENHAUS
II
Scholarly neglect of the laws of nature has effects well beyond lack
of attention to the issue of degrees of indeterminacy. It has meant
15 "It is true that they that have Soveraigne power, may commit Iniquity; but
not Injustice, or Injury in the proper signification"; Leviathan, chap. 18 [90], p.
232. "Now the Intention of the Legislator is alwayes supposed to be Equity: For it
were a great contumely for a judge to think otherwise of the Soveraigne. He ought
therefore, if the Word of the Law doe not fully authorise a reasonable Sentence,
to supply it with the Law of Nature ..."; Leviathan, chap. 26 [145], p. 326. "For
in this consisteth Equity; to which, as being a Precept of the Law of Nature, a
Soveraign is as much subject, as any of the meanest of his people"; Leviathan,
chap 30 [180], p. 385.
16 Leviathan, chap. 28 [162], p. 354; and for the law, see chap. 15 [76], p. 210.
Hobbes makes the connection plain in his fifth inference in chap. 28 [162], p. 355.
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 471
that the different functions Hobbes might have had in mind for th
laws of nature have hardly been discussed.
I have already suggested that laws 1, 2 and 3 are fundamental.
Law 1 enjoins us to seek peace as long as there is hope of attaining
it.17 Law 2 tells us "That a man be willing, when others are so too, a
farre-forth, as for Peace, and defence of himselfe, to lay down thi
right to all things; and be contented with so much liberty agains
other men, as he would allow other men against himselfe."18 Law 3
says simply that "men performe their Covenants made" and Hobbe
tells us that in this law of nature is to be found the "Fountain and
Originall of JUSTICE" since the definition of injustice is "the not
Performance of Covenant".19
Once he has set out law 3, Hobbes immediately draws our atten-
tion to the fact that the pervasive fear of the state of nature renders
any covenant therein invalid, so that for justice and injustice to come
into being, it must be the case that there already exists a sovereign
coercive power which can guarantee performance. Here we get the
problem that exit from the state of nature by mutual covenant seems
impossible, which then seems to make superfluous Hobbes's discus-
sion in chapter 18 of sovereignty by institution. And the conundrum
Hobbes raises here is only made worse by the fact that for him
sovereignty by institution - by covenant - is at least as important
a mode of establishing sovereignty as sovereignty by acquisition -
where you assent to the authority of a sovereign who has captured
you.20
17 Hobbes adds that when one cannot obtain peace, one may "seek, and use, all
helps, and advantages of Warre"; Leviathan, chap. 14 [65], p. 190.
18 Leviathan, chap. 14 [64-65], p. 190.
19 Leviathan, chap. 15 [71], pp. 201-202.
20 Indeed, one could argue, though I will not do so here, that for Hobbes
sovereignty by institution is paradigmatic for understanding the problems in
constructing civil society while sovereignty by acquisition is deviant. Not only
does he deal with sovereignty by institution first, but his initial contrast between
the two makes it clear that sovereignty by institution coheres with his idea that
obligations are generally incurred through an unforced covenant, while sover-
eignty by acquisition is forced; Leviathan, chap. 17 [88], p. 228. The latter of
course raises no problem about an impossible transition from a state of nature
since it involves giving one's consent to an already existing sovereign. But it is
at first sight problematic because of the dubious legitimacy of a situation where
your consent is given to a foreign sovereign who has you by the throat. Hobbes is
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
472 DAVID DYZENHAUS
clear that in both cases fear is the ground of assent to sovereign authority - fear
of others in the state of nature in the case of institution, and fear of the existing
sovereign in the case of acquisition. Leviathan, chap. 20 [102], p. 252. And he
expressly argues that duress in and of itself did not invalidate a covenant. But
he is still concerned about the issue of legitimacy, since he returns to it in the
"Review and Conclusion" to Leviathan, [390], p. 719. (He had though, it must be
pointed out, personal reasons for emphasizing the basis for his own allegiance to
a political regime he had opposed.)
21 Hobbes, De Cive, in Bernard Gert (ed.), Man and Citizen (Indianapolis:
Hackett Publishing Company, 1991), chap. 3, paragraph 27, p. 149. All references
to De Cive will be to this edition.
22 Leviathan, chap. 15 [75], p. 209.
23 Leviathan, chap. 15 [76], pp. 209-210.
24 Leviathan, chap. 15 [76-77], pp. 210-212.
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 473
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
474 DAVID DYZENHAUS
Note that the distinction between the third and the second
is not very sharp. Law 15 is in the third group because the
for it is closely tied to the reason for submission of contr
to arbitration. But it could be in the second group as a requi
of the "readiness of mind" of subjects who understand their
tions to natural law, just as the acknowledgment of the ob
to submit one's controversies to arbitration is also part and
of that same readiness of mind. Moreover, laws in groups t
three are united by the fact that their observance is clearly
in order to sustain civil society, even if the groups have di
functions.
Nor is the distinction between the first and second grou
sharp, since, while it is the sovereign's task to give content to t
two laws of nature, he must give content in such a way that he
it possible for subjects to maintain their readiness to obey.31 It
insignificant that when Hobbes tells us that the "Lawes of
are Immutable and Eternall", it is laws in the second group t
with law 3 that he specifically names, saying that their violatio
never be made lawfull. For it can never be that Warre shall p
life, and Peace destroy it."32 For here Hobbes is telling us
sovereign's command that any one of these laws be violated
be equivalent to a positive law which commanded subjects t
conflict rather than peace. Indeed, it seems clear that Hobbes
that these laws cannot be commanded - are beyond authority
the same reason that it is superfluous for the sovereign to co
his subjects to obey his positive laws: "For except subject
before obliged to obedience, that is to say, not to rebel, all la
no force. Now the obligation which obligeth to what we were
obliged to, is superfluous."33
31 This creates yet another link between Hobbes and Fuller, if one und
Fuller's legal theory in the way proposed by Daniel Brudney, "Two
Law and Morality", Ethics 103 (1993), pp. 280-301. Only somewhat iron
Brudney's contrast class for subjects with the right psychology is the
sian creatures, concerned solely for survival depicted by [H.L.A.] Hart
discussion of what he calls 'the minimum content of natural law'" ...; p
32 Leviathan, chap. 15 [79], p. 215.
33 De Cive, chap. 14, paragraph 21, p. 287. And see Leviathan, c
[163], p. 356 and chap. 30 [175-176], p. 377. I say in some sense not
to command, because it is clear that the sovereign can outlaw classes of
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 475
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
476 DAVID DYZENHAUS
as submission to lawful execution. See Leviathan, chap. 21, [112], pp. 269-270,
though in "A Review, and Conclusion", Hobbes adds a further law to his laws of
nature "to protect in Warre, the Authority, by which he is himself protected in tim
of Peace"; [390], pp. 718-719.
37 Daniel Brudney provided me with a useful list of situations to test my argu-
ment, including: (a) regardless of his intent, the sovereign fails to bring peace; (b
regardless of his intent, the tendency of the soverein's actions will not - in the not
too distant future - bring peace; (c) the sovereign declares his intent not to bring
peace, but circumstances are such that peace obtains - the sovereign is wicked but
ineffective. Without going into detail, I suggest that the distinction (one which
Brudney also pointed out) between the ways in which the laws of nature are
empirically constitutive of sovereign authority and conceptually constitutive, is
helpful here precisely because it shows how in practice the two are linked.
With (a) and (b), if the sovereign does intend to bring peace, but his law
contradict his intentions, then authority is in fact undermined. And at a certain
point in this process, conceptual or normative issues about authority will perforc
arise because the factual is connected to the normative. For example, consider the
issue about whether judges should be entitled to scrutinise the reasonableness of
the executive's judgment that circumstances are such that declaration of a state
of emergency is warranted. (For an instructive decision during the apartheid er
in South Africa, see Friedman J.'s judgment for a full bench of the Natal court in
Tsenoli v. State President, discussed and overruled in State President v. Tsenoli
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 477
1986 (4) SA 1150 (A). For discussion, see Etienne Mureinik, "Security and Integ-
rity, Acta Juridica (1987), pp. 197-219, and David Dyzenhaus, Hard Cases in
Wicked Legal Systems: South African Law in the Perspective of Legal Philosophy,
p. 167. In South Africa's post-apartheid Constitution, the courts are now given
explicit authority to test this issue.)
Conversely, in regard to (c), laws which explicitly contradict the duty to seek
peace will always be suspect in part because one can never predict that stability
will not be undermined by a public declaration of this sort. Consider, for example,
what the public would make in the United Kingdom of the enactment of the Group
Areas Act, discussed in the text below, even if one would have predicted that
such a statute could never be enforced in the United Kingdom. Put differently,
the prediction depends also on the judgment that no Parliament would ever enact
such a statute. The other part of the response to (c) is, of course, that efficacy is a
precondition for the existence of legal order, but not for the validity of particular
laws.
38 Murphy argues that such a command would be valid; see Murphy, "Was
Hobbes a Legal Positivist?", p. 857.
39 Suppose, however, that the sovereign wishes mediators to be killed because
that will cause conflicts in other parts of the world to persist which will then ensure
his ability to withstand attack from without, thus making peace within more
secure. This problem is one about tensions between Hobbes's theory of inter-
national relations, which holds that such relations are like the relations between
individuals in the state of nature, and his account of domestic order. I will not go
into this issue here.
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
478 DAVID DYZENHAUS
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 479
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
480 DAVID DYZENHAUS
III
The Lawes of Nature oblige in foro interno; that is to say, they bind to a desire
they should take place; but in foro externo; that is, to the putting them in act,
not alwayes. For he that should be modest, and tractable, and performe all he
promises, in such time, and place, where no man els should do so, should but
make himselfe a prey to others, and procure his own certain ruine, contrary to the
ground of all Lawes of Nature, which tend to Natures preservation. And again, he
that having sufficient Security, that others shall observe the same Lawes towards
him, observes them not himselfe, seeketh not Peace, but War; & consequently the
destruction of his Nature by Violence.44
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 481
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
482 DAVID DYZENHAUS
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 483
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
484 DAVID DYZENHAUS
these constraints at their most minimal are much thicker than the
constraints of manner and form which Hart had in mind.
As we have seen, Hobbes in contrast to contemporary positivists
supposes there is one substantive constraint on the sovereign. By
definition, civil law is law which the subject has a prior obligation
to obey, and so, if the basis for that obligation is missing, then the
sovereign's commands are suspect.
Now there are two interpretations about how to cash out this
constraint. The first is that the constraint is illusory, since whatever
the sovereign commands must be taken as conforming to the natural
law. The second is that the constraint does have cash value. For
natural law interpretations of Hobbes the cash value of the constraint
is the subject's right to resist the sovereign in particular circum-
stances, while in contemporary debates it is more or less assumed
that it is judges who are the guardians of constraints on sovereign
authority.
I mentioned above reasons for doubting the natural law inter-
pretation of that constraint. Another way of putting those reasons
is to say that it is a mistake to think that a substantive constraint
in order to be a genuine constraint has to cash out in something
substantive. In other words, a constraint that starts in something
substantive might turn out to be formal in nature but still genuinely
constraining.
Recall my claim that for Hobbes it has to be the case that a
sovereign who issues a command which expressly contradicts the
purpose of law 1 would have issued a command that is on its face
suspect. I also suggested that the same might be true of commands
which expressly violate the purpose of any of the laws of nature, of
commands which require actions in violation of the content of the
person or body who has power to initiate repeal of a law is only bound by that
law in that he or it chooses not to repeal it. "The Soveraign of a Common-wealth,
be it an Assembly, or one Man, is not Subject to the Civill Lawes. For having
power to make, and repeale Lawes, he may when he pleaseth, free himselfe from
that subjection, by repealing those Lawes that trouble him, and making of new;
and consequently he was free before. For he is free, that can be free when he
will ..."; Leviathan, chap 26. [137-138], p. 313. Compare the passage which
contains the "regress" argument: Leviathan, chap. 29 [169], p. 367. Note that
Hobbes does permit the subject to challenge the sovereign in court for violating
the law - Leviathan, chap. 21 [113], pp. 271-272.
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 485
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
486 DAVID DYZENHAUS
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 487
For it is not the Letter, but the Intendment, or Meaning; that is to say, the authe
tique Interpretation of the Law (which is in the sense of the Legislators), in whi
the nature of the Law consisteth; And therefore the Intepretation of all Law
dependeth on the Authority Soveraign; and the Interpreters can be none but those
which the Soveraign (to whom only the Subject oweth obedience), shall appoint
For else, by the craft of an Interpreter, the Law may be made to beare a sense
contrary to that of the Soveraign; by which means the Interpreter becomes th
Legislator;
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
488 DAVID DYZENHAUS
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 489
The Group Areas Act represents a colossal social experiment and a long te
policy. It necessarily involves the movement out of Group Areas of numb
people throughout the country. Parliament must have envisaged that comp
shifts of persons occupying certain areas would inevitably cause disruption
within the foreseeable future, substantial inequalities. Whether all this will
to be for the common weal of all the inhabitants is not for the Court to d
... The question before this Court is the purely legal one whether this
of legislation impliedly authorises, towards the attainment of its goal, the
immediate and foreseeable discriminatory results complained of in this c
my view, for the reason which I have given, it manifestly does.71
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
490 DAVID DYZENHAUS
73 My claim in the text is not in tension with the fact that Henochs
rely on the common law of judicial review. It is quite significant, in m
that Hobbes - the great opponent of the common law tradition - in gi
catalogue of the values of legality also put forward some of the centra
of that tradition, most notably, the principles of natural justice and of
tional boundaries which are the mainstays of the common law of judicia
(See on related issues, Richard Tuck, Natural Rights Theories: Their
and Development (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), p. 13
cising J.G.A. Pocock, The Ancient Constitution and the Feudal Law: A S
of English Historical Thought in the Seventeenth Century: A Reissue w
Retrospect (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987).) But in con
those principles to bringing substantive judgments made elswhere into th
perspicuity, Hobbes kept judges away from the usurpation of the legisla
which comes about when the common law is conceived as a law which first and
foremost protects a catalogue of substantive rights. It may even be that Hobbes can
support a limited doctrine of constitutional adjudication, that is one which regards
constitutional review as legitimate as long as it confines itself to judgments about
proportionality of means adopted to implement legitimate objectives, where what
is a legitimate objective is decided - with few exceptions - legislatively.
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 491
IV
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
492 DAVID DYZENHAUS
I have already noted that Hobbes reserves to the subject the right to
believe that the sovereign is wrong on matters of faith, although the
subject must submit his private reason to the public by confining his
belief to his heart.81 And I suggested that Hobbes must think that
the same is true of a subject's sense that a particular positive law is
a mistake, that is, the subject must subordinate his private reason to
the reason of the sovereign.
The passage just quoted might seem to conflict with this sugges-
tion, since it says that the subject must take the law as a public
the "Lawes of Nature which he is bound to obey"; Leviathan, chap 28 [167-168],
pp. 362-363. Hobbes does in this passage say that the sovereign's obligation to
obey arises because he should fear God. But he offers first another reason, which
seems clearly in itself sufficient: "But because he is mortall, and subject to decay,
as all other Earthly creatures are; ..."; ibid.
78 Hobbes, De Cive, chap. 8, p. 205, para. 1.
79 It is the case that Hobbes, at the time of writing Leviathan was not in point
of fact concerned with creating order out of nothing but with a problem of "trans-
itional justice" - the creation of order during an interregnum when there exists
some basis for stability.
80 Leviathan, chap. 29 [168-169], p. 366.
81 Leviathan, chap. 38 [238], p. 478.
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 493
No man is bound by the words themselves, either to kill himselfe, or any oth
man; And consequently, that the Obligation a man may sometimes have, upon t
Command of the Soveraign to execute any dangerous, or dishonourable Offic
dependeth not on the Words of our Submission; but on the Intention; which is
be understood by the End thereof. When therefore our refusall to obey, frustra
the End for which the Soveraignty was ordained; then there is no Liberty to refu
otherwise there is.83
82 Leviathan, chap. 30 [177], p. 379. John Austin, in my view the true found
of contemporary legal positivism, thought that Hobbes's optimism had been
proved wrong - see Austin, Lectures on Jurisprudence, 2 vols., London, John
Murray, 5th edn. 1885, vol. i, 134.
83 Leviathan, chap. 21 [112], p. 269.
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
494 DAVID DYZENHAUS
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 495
87 Hobbes, Leviathan, chap. 14 [69-70], p. 199, and the text to note 83 above.
88 Leviathan, chap. 13 [62], p. 186.
89 See Edward G. Andrew, "Hobbes on Conscience within the Law and
Without", Canadian Journal of Political Science 32 (1999), pp. 203-225.
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
496 DAVID DYZENHAUS
90 David Gauthier, "Public Reason", Social Philosophy 19-42 (1995), pp. 36-
37; and see Leviathan, chap. 15 [72-73], pp. 203-204.
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOBBES AND THE LEGITIMACY OF LAW 497
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
498 DAVID DYZENHAUS
University of Toronto
Faculty of Law
78 Queen's Park
M5S 2C5
Toronto, Canada
E-mail: [email protected]
Hobbes into Locke, which is against the grain of much else in Leviathan. But
on my account the constraints on the sovereign are not the "kick the bastards
out" constraints which Locke envisages, but the constraints that necessarily attend
the exercise of power through law. It is these constraints that explain why there
is a mutual, ongoing relationship between protection and obedience in civil
society, and not the complete subjection to power which the Hobbist interpretation
requires.
94 Hart, "Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals", p. 59
95 One might naturally raise a challenge here which if successful undermines
the argument of the whole essay - that the constraints I identify do not amount
to a morality. But that challenge assumes a particular conception of morality, for
example, a liberal list of individual rights and liberties. Although I will not defend
this claim here, Hobbes's conception of morality seems much closer to what we
might think of as a democratic conception of morality in the standard debates
between liberals and democrats.
This content downloaded from 27.34.16.214 on Wed, 14 Nov 2018 04:24:10 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms