Thomas Aquinas On Slavery
Thomas Aquinas On Slavery
Thomas Aquinas On Slavery
Ralph Neill
April 4, 2011
1
Introduction
The purpose of this essay is to clarify Thomas’s position on slavery with particular
focus on his texts themselves rather than on secondary literature. But in order to best
understand Thomas’s views on slavery, it is beneficial to understand Aristotle’s views
because he provides some historical and intellectual context in which to place Thomas.
Other than a few passages in The Athenian Constitution, all of Aristotle’s significant
writings on slavery appear in the Politics and the Nichomachean Ethics, and the majority
of Aristotle’s statements on slavery can be found in the Politics. We know that Thomas
was very well acquainted with Aristotle’s views on slavery in both of these works
because he wrote commentaries on them. Although Thomas’s commentary on the
Politics is incomplete and ends with chapter six of book three, Aristotle’s comments on
slavery are concentrated in books one and three of the Politics. Given Aristotle’s
profound influence on Thomas, throughout this essay I will generally begin with passages
from Aristotle and then provide the essence of Thomas’s thoughts on the sentiments
expressed in those passages. Most of Thomas’s views are not directly expressed in his
commentaries on the Politics and the Ethics; in fact, it is often difficult to divine exactly
what Thomas thinks about Aristotle because his commentaries are designed more for the
clear elaboration of Aristotle’s position than for a critical assessment of Aristotle per se.
However, Thomas discusses slavery in several passages in his Summa Theologiae, and I
have attempted to relate these passages to passages in Aristotle’s writings that have
similar themes.
In order to provide a complete and yet coherent picture of Thomas’s views on slavery,
I have structured my essay in the following way. First I discuss the nature of slavery and
the relation between master and slave. Next I distinguish between natural and
conventional slavery. I then discuss the theory and characteristics of natural slavery
followed by a discussion of conventional slavery. Following this I discuss economic
slavery or indentured servitude as a form of conventional slavery tolerated by Thomas. I
then discuss comments made by Thomas regarding the treatment of slaves. I conclude
my essay with a summary of Thomas’s position on slavery.
2
and the slave” (1252b1). Thomas agrees that the status of women is much higher than
the status of slaves. In the Summa Theologiae he writes:
A wife, though she is something belonging to the husband, since she stands
related to him as to her own body, as the Apostle declares (Eph. 5:28), is
nevertheless more distinct from her husband, than a son from his father or a slave
from his master: for she is received into a kind of social life, that of matrimony,
wherefore according to the Philosopher (Ethics V.6) there is more scope for
justice between husband and wife than between father and son, or master and
slave” (II-II, q.57, a.5, co.).
Also in the Summa Theologiae where Thomas discusses the creation of woman from the
rib of man, he writes: “Nor was it right for her to be subject to man’s contempt as his
slave, and so she was not made from his feet” (I, q.92, a.3, co.). In other words, slaves
are an object of contempt and rank below women in the hierarchy of the household.
Having established the uniquely low status of slaves in Aristotle’s hierarchy in the
household, Aristotle then provides a number of characteristics of slaves. First of all he
says that a slave is a piece of property which belongs to the household (1256a1). While
discussing the concept of justice in the Summa Theologiae, Thomas discusses the
ownership of slaves as follows: “Now that which is ordered to a man is said to be his
own. Thus the master owns the slave, and not conversely, for that is free which is its own
cause” (I, q.21, a.1, arg.3). Given that a slave is a piece of property, Aristotle then
becomes more specific as to the kind of property. In particular, a slave is an instrument
or tool to be used by the household. However, the slave is “an instrument which takes
precedence of all other instruments” (1253b34). Thomas explains that what Aristotle
means by “taking precedence” is that slaves use and move the other non-living
instruments and tools found in the household (Commentary 1.2.7). Aristotle then makes
a distinction between the activity of a household slave, which is action, and the activity of
a manual labourer, which is production. He states that the activity of household life is
higher than mere production of goods because the latter is subordinate to the former.
Aristotle therefore implies that the activity of a household slave is somewhat more
elevated than the activity of hired manual workers, for example leather workers, who
produce goods that are used to support the activity of the household. Thomas then takes
4
these various passages from the Politics, synthesizes them, and forms a typically
Aristotelian definition of the species “slave” comprised of a genus and a collection of
differences. Thomas defines a slave in the following way:
We posit instrument as the genus and add five specific differences. By the fact
that we call the instrument living, we distinguish it from inanimate instruments.
By the fact that we call the instrument useful for activity, we distinguish it from a
craftsman’s assistant, who is a living instrument of production. By the fact that
we say that the instrument belongs to another, we distinguish a slave from a free
person, who sometimes serves in a household freely or for pay, not as property.
By the fact that we call the instrument separate, we distinguish it from a part like
the hand, which belongs to something else but is not separate. And by the fact
that we call the instrument a human being, we distinguish it from irrational
animals, which are separate property (1.2.11).
The preceding serves as a general definition of a slave, but in theory there are two types
of slaves differentiated by both Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas. In the Politics Aristotle
writes: “The words slavery and slave are used in two senses. There is a slave or slavery
by law as well as by nature. The law of which I speak is a sort of convention – the law
by which whatever is taken in war is supposed to belong to the victors” (1255a4-7).
There is a greater element of force involved when it comes to slavery by law, and there is
no common interest between a master and a conventional slave: all the benefits of the
relationship accrue to the master. The attitude of Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas towards
slavery by law is complicated, and I will discuss it in more depth later in the essay.
However, both Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas recognize the legitimacy of slavery by
nature, and in this restricted sense of slavery one can fairly say that Thomas “supported”
slavery.
When it comes to natural slavery, there is a common interest between a master and his
slave. In his Commentary on the Politics, Thomas writes:
It is advantageous for slaves and masters, fit to be such by nature, that one be the
master, and the other the slave. And so there can be friendship between them,
since the association of both in what is advantageous for each is the essence of
friendship (1.4.11).
5
The key feature of natural slavery is that the natural slave benefits from the relationship.
In the Summa Theologiae, Thomas makes use of Aristotle’s distinction of two kinds of
servitude or two kinds of subjection when he discusses the relationship between men and
women:
Subjection is twofold. One is servile, by virtue of which a superior makes use of
a subject for his own benefit, and this kind of subjection began after sin. There is
another kind of subjection, which is called economic or civil, whereby the
superior makes use of his subjects for their own benefit and good; and this kind of
subjection existed even before sin (I, q.92, a.1, arg.2).
The first “servile” kind of subjection corresponds to slavery by law. The superior is the
one who benefits from the relationship. On the other hand, the second or “economic”
kind of subjection corresponds to slavery by nature; the subjects are governed for their
own benefit. Justifying the lordship of Adam over Eve, Thomas goes on to say: “For
good order would have been wanting in the human family if some were not governed by
others wiser than themselves” (I, q.92, a.1, arg.2). Therefore everyone benefits from the
natural form of subjection or slavery. Thomas makes similar comments when he
discusses the rights of nations:
Considered absolutely, the fact that this particular man should be a slave rather
than another man, is based, not on natural reason, but on some resultant utility, in
that it is useful to this man to be ruled by a wiser man, and to the latter to be
helped by the former, as the Philosopher states (Politics I.2) (II-II, q.57, a.3,
arg.2).
The key words are “utility” and “useful.” Thomas explicitly supports natural slavery in
the Summa Theologiae where he discusses natural law and whether it can be changed.
An objection is raised that the possession of all things in common and uniform freedom
are part of the natural law, so it could not be possible for slavery to be natural. Thomas
answers that one way in which natural law may be changed is by adding to it for the
greater good: “nothing hinders the natural law from being changed, since many things for
the benefit of human life have been added over and above the natural law, both by the
Divine law and by human laws” (II-I, q.94, a.5, co.). He then replies to the objection by
claiming:
6
‘the possession of all things in common, and uniform freedom’ are said to be of
the natural law, because, that is, the distinction of possessions and slavery were
not brought in by nature, but devised by human reason for the benefit of human
life. Accordingly the law of nature was not changed in this respect, except by
addition” (II-I, q.94, a5, arg.3).
Thomas is clear that natural slavery is “for the benefit of human life;” one therefore
cannot claim that Thomas was against all forms of slavery. But in order to understand
how a slave can benefit from slavery, we first need to understand what Aristotle and
Thomas meant by a natural slave.
Natural Slavery
On the first page of the Politics, Aristotle writes:
There must be a union of natural ruler and subject, that both may be preserved.
For he who can foresee with his mind is by nature intended to be lord and master,
and he who can work with his body is a subject, and by nature a slave; hence
master and slave have the same interest (1252a32-5).
There are two points that are noteworthy. The first is that there is an analogy between a
good ruler of free people and a slave master: both are concerned with not only their own
benefit but the benefit of those over whom they have dominion. The second noteworthy
point is that the defining difference between a master and a natural slave is that the
master “can foresee with his mind;” in other words, the master is more intelligent than the
natural slave. Aristotle writes that a slave by nature is someone who “participates in
rational principle enough to apprehend, but not to have, such a principle” (1254b21-2).
Thomas elaborates: “one who is a slave by nature, because he lacks sufficient reason,
cannot help us in deliberation or any work of reason. Nevertheless, a slave, because he
has reason, can serve in physical tasks in more ways than an irrational animal can”
(Commentary 1.3.11). Therefore, natural slaves do have some reason, but their reason is
limited. This lack of sufficient reason is something congenital: “From the hour of their
birth, some are marked out for subjection, others for rule” (1254a23).
Thomas in his Commentary on the Politics explains that some form of natural slavery
is necessary for the survival of the natural slave: “nor would those who abound in
7
physical powers be able to be preserved unless the practical wisdom of another were to
rule over them” (Commentary 1.1.7). The natural slave benefits from his master in the
same way that a tame animal benefits from human ownership “since the animals in many
cases then obtain physical safety that they could not obtain by themselves. For example,
this is evident when human beings provide them with abundant food and medical help”
(Commentary 1.3.7). Thomas points out that “performing manual tasks is the best work
that they can do, since they can execute the latter but not the works of reason”
(Commentary 1.3.10). Both Aristotle and Thomas therefore definitely approve of natural
slavery on the basis of intelligence because it is mutually beneficial. Aristotle
summarizes his position with the following comment: “It is clear, then, that some men are
by nature free, and others slaves, and that for these latter slavery is both expedient and
right” (1255a2-3). Thomas summarizes his position with the following:
Therefore, all human beings who differ from others as much as the soul does from
the body, and as human beings do from irrational animals, are, because of the
eminence of reason in them and the deficiency in others, by nature masters of the
others. In this regard, Solomon also says in Proverbs 11:29: ‘The stupid will
serve the wise.’ (Commentary 1.3.10).
This is one of the few scriptural references quoted by Thomas in his Commentary on the
Politics; this suggests that Thomas strongly believes in the merit of Aristotle’s argument
regarding natural slaves.
Given the legitimacy of natural slavery, an obvious next question is: how do we
identify whether someone ought to be a natural slave? There certainly were no
intelligence tests in the days of Aristotle or Thomas. Instead both Aristotle and Thomas
seem to point to barbarians or foreigners as potential sources for natural slaves. When
Aristotle describes the farmer or husbandmen class of people in Book VII of his Politics,
he writes: “The very best thing of all would be that the husbandmen should be slaves
taken from among men who are not all of the same race…. The next best thing would be
that they should be perioeci4 of foreign race, and of a like inferior nature” (1330a25-31).
Aristotle therefore implies that foreigners are inferior to Greeks. Earlier in the Politics he
4
Perioeci, or περί οικοι in Greek, comes from περί (around) and οικοι (those who dwell) and refers to
free people dwelling around Sparta but who were not citizens.
8
notes: “Hellenes do not like to call Hellenes slaves, but confine the term to barbarians”
(1255a29). In commenting on this passage, Thomas makes a distinction between
absolute foreigners and relative foreigners. A relative foreigner is someone who speaks a
different language but is rational and literate in that language. Although Thomas’s
Commentary did not go as far as Book VII of the Politics, had he done so he would likely
have mentioned the following passage from Aristotle as an example of relative
foreigners: “the natives of Asia are intelligent and inventive, but they are wanting in
spirit” (1327b27). By contrast, absolute foreigners “do not establish laws, or [they]
establish unreasonable laws… [and] have no literary practices” (Commentary 1.1.9).
They lack reason and “seem absolutely foreign to the human race” (1.1.9). Thomas
opines that “they lack reason either because they happen to live in a climate so
intemperate that it causes most of them to be dim-witted, or because there is an evil
custom in certain lands whereby human beings are rendered irrational and brutish, as it
were” (1.1.9). Thomas then makes a generalization regarding the suitability of certain
people to be natural slaves – a generalization that Aristotle himself does not directly
make: “most [absolute] foreigners are physically strong and mentally weak” (1.1.10).
Aristotle does, however, imply that certain foreigners are more suitable as natural slaves:
“Those who live in a cold climate and in Europe are full of spirit, but wanting in
intelligence and skill” (1327b23-4). In On Kingship, Thomas quotes a passage from
Vegetius’ De Re Militari that echoes these sentiments: “As Vegetius tells us ‘… Northern
tribes, far removed from the burning rays of the sun, are more dull-witted indeed’”
(II.V.126). Thomas does not contradict this opinion; in fact, he uses it to support his
arguments. Clearly Thomas believes in some form of slavery based on intelligence and,
at least indirectly, based on race.
Other than low intelligence, it is reasonable to ask what sorts of qualities a natural
slave has or ought to have. Aristotle writes:
A question may indeed be raised, whether there is any excellence at all in a slave
beyond and higher than merely instrumental and ministerial qualities – whether he
can have the virtues of temperance, courage, justice, and the like; or whether
slaves possess only bodily and ministerial qualities (1259b21-5).
9
Aristotle answers this question by stating that both free men and slaves “must have a
share of virtue, but varying according to their various natures” (1260a4-5). He goes on to
say that “although the parts of the soul are present in [the free man and the slave], they
are present in different degrees” (1260a11). He concludes by stating: “We determined
that a slave is useful for the wants of life, and therefore he will obviously require only so
much virtue as will prevent him from failing in his duty through cowardice or lack of
self-control” (1260a34-6). Therefore slaves must have some virtues, and it is the
responsibility of the master to help the slave acquire his small amount of virtue. Aristotle
writes:
It is manifest, then, that the master ought to be the source of such excellence in
the slave, and not a mere possessor of the art of mastership which trains the slave
in his duties. Wherefore they are mistaken who forbid us to converse with slaves
and say that we should employ command only5, for slaves stand even more in
need of admonition than children (1260b4-7).
Thomas agrees that slaves must be allowed to develop some amount of virtue. In the
Summa Theologiae he writes: “Prudence is not the virtue of a slave as slave nor of a
subject as subject. Since however every man for as much as he is rational, has a share in
ruling according to the judgment of reason, he is proportionately competent to have
prudence” (II-II, q.47, a.12, co.). Responding to one of the objections, Thomas writes:
“A slave is not capable of taking counsel, in so far as he is a slave (for thus he is the
instrument of his master), but he does take counsel in so far as he is a rational animal”
(II-II, q.47, a.12, arg.2). In other words, to the extent that slaves have reason, however
limited, they ought to be given counsel in order that they may develop virtues such as
prudence and that they may develop them to whatever level they are mentally able to
attain.
Slavery by Law, or Conventional Slavery
Having established Thomas’s views on natural slavery, we are in a position to try to
clarify his views on slavery by law, or conventional slavery. In his article “Aquinas’
Doctrine of Slavery in Relation to Thomistic Teaching on Natural Law,” Oscar J. Brown
5
In this passage Aristotle is responding to Plato’s The Laws, in which the Athenian stranger says that one
ought to address slaves with a simple command. The Laws 777e.
10
admits that with respect to slavery by convention: “there is quite a considerable quarrel
among commentators – concerning both the doctrine of Aristotle himself and also,
especially, Aquinas’ exegesis of Aristotelian teaching on the subject” (Brown 173).
Rather than examining the various positions of commentators, I will focus on the texts of
Aristotle and Thomas themselves.
Having outlined his position on natural slavery in the Politics, Aristotle writes:
“Others affirm that the rule of a master over slaves is contrary to nature, and that the
distinction between slave and free man exists by law only, and not by nature; and being
an interference with nature is therefore unjust” (1253b20-2). He admits that those who
hold this opposite opinion from his “have in a certain way right on their side” (1255a4).
He then cites the convention that the victors of a war may take the vanquished as slaves.
He points out that some people identify justice with goodwill and “detest the notion that,
because one man has the power of doing violence and is superior in brute strength,
another shall be his slave and subject” (1255a9-10). He points out that other people
identify justice with the “mere rule of the stronger” and believe that “superior power is
only found where there is superior excellence of some kind” (1255a14). Brown claims
that Aristotle’s position is difficult to determine “due to its almost inextricable
entanglement with the two extreme positions he wants to reject” (Brown 173). Although
I agree that, in general, Aristotle’s position on conventional slavery is difficult to
determine, in this passage I believe that Aristotle greatly favours the former position.
Aristotle does not identify justice with the “mere rule” of the stronger, and Aristotle
believes that it is insufficient for the victor to simply have “superior excellence of some
kind”. Aristotle raises the question: “what if the cause of the war be unjust?” and
answers it: “no one would ever say that he is a slave who is unworthy to be a slave. Were
this the case, men of the highest rank would be slaves and the children of slaves if they or
their parents chance to have been taken captive and sold” (1255a25-8). When Aristotle
says that those who oppose slavery “have in a certain way right on their side,” he is
referring precisely to those cases of conventional slavery where someone who is not a
natural slave is enslaved. He also writes that “there is great evil” when a legislator trains
his citizens to conquer their neighbours, and he writes: “neither should men study war
11
with a view to the enslavement of those who do not deserve to be enslaved” (1333b38-
40).
However, Aristotle goes on to write that men “should seek to be masters only over
those who deserve to be slaves” (1334a3). Here he does not define who exactly deserves
to be enslaved. One might try to argue charitably that he is referring strictly to natural
slaves. But if that is the case then it is difficult to explain what Aristotle means when he
says that if good citizens learn the crafts of their inferiors and habitually practise them,
“there will cease to be a distinction between master and slave” (1277b6). We have
already established that natural slaves differ from their masters in that their intellects are
significantly less developed. There should never be a problem distinguishing master
from natural slave. Furthermore, Aristotle’s position on conventional slavery is made
more complicated by comments such as the following: “But the art of acquiring slaves, I
mean of justly acquiring them, differs both from the art of the master and the art of the
slave, being a species of hunting or war. Enough of the distinction between master and
slave” (1255b38-40). He tries to suggest that slaves can be acquired justly by “hunting”
them or through acts of war. But notice that he ends the discussion without elaborating
further on how this hunting of slaves can be defended as being just. I suspect that
Aristotle knew that his position was murky and indefensible.
But even more damaging to Aristotle’s position is the following comment: “I will
hereafter explain what is the proper treatment of slaves, and why it is expedient that
liberty should be always held out to them as the reward of their services” (1330a34).
Now if the only people deserving to be slaves are natural slaves, then their intellect is
limited. If their intellect is limited, then they were enslaved in the first place for their
own good. Why would one need to hold out the promise of freedom to a slave who is
benefiting from his enslavement? Aristotle does not answer this question. He therefore
seems to support some kind of conventional slavery.
In contrast to Aristotle, I believe that Thomas is more consistently opposed to
conventional slavery except when it is economically necessary6. In a number of places in
the Summa Theologiae Thomas writes that “mastership has a twofold meaning” (I, q.96,
a.4, co.). The first is the master who has a conventional slave by law; the master has use
6
I explain economic slavery, or indentured servitude, later in the essay.
12
of the slave and benefits from the slave. The second master is analogous to a governor
ruling over free men, or, alternatively, the second master is analogous to certain angels
ruling over other angels in a heavenly hierarchy such as archangels ruling over angels.
This kind of mastership corresponds to natural slavery. Thomas notes that: “in the state
of innocence man could have been a master of men, not in the former but in the latter
sense” (I, q.96, a.4, co.). In other words, conventional slavery is part of a sinful world.
Thomas then makes his position more explicit: “It is a grievous matter to anyone to yield
to another what ought to be one’s own, therefore such dominion implies of necessity a
pain inflicted on the subject” (I, q.96, a.4, co.). Thomas makes similar negative
statements about slavery in his work entitled The Religious State, the Episcopate, and the
Priestly Office. He writes: “Nothing is so repugnant to human nature as slavery; and,
therefore, there is no greater sacrifice (except that of life), which one man can make for
another, than to give himself up to bondage for the sake of that other” (Chapter 10, p45).
He goes on to say:
The state of slavery does in some sort resemble death, and is therefore called civil
death. For life is chiefly manifested in ability to move; he that cannot move save
by the agency of others, may be accounted dead. Now, a slave has no power over
himself, but is governed by the will of his master; and therefore this condition of
bondage may be compared to death. Hence a man, who, for the love of another,
delivers himself to bondage, practises the same perfection of charity, as he who
exposes himself to death. Nay, we may say that he does more; for slavery is more
abhorrent to our nature than is death. (Chapter 14, p79).
In the preceding passage, slavery is likened to a state even worse than death. This
position of Thomas is antithetical to conventional slavery.
There is a passage from the Summa Theologiae that is sometimes taken out of context
that seems to imply that Thomas believes that conventional slavery is justified as a form
of punishment. Thomas writes: “Since slavery was imposed in punishment of sin, it
follows that by slavery man forfeits something which otherwise would belong to him,
namely the free disposal of his person, for a slave, as regards what he is, belongs to his
master” (II-II, q.189, a.6, arg.2). In this passage Thomas is commenting on a passage
13
from the Old Testament of the Bible7. He uses the past tense “was imposed.” He does
not mean to imply that slavery is still imposed on a given race of men as a punishment for
their collective sins.
7
“Cursed be Canaan! The lowest of slaves will he be to his brothers” (Genesis 9:25). New International
Version.
14
8
Likely by Fra Rainaldo da Piperno. I assume, however, that the sentiments expressed in the Supplement
reflect Thomas’s views.
15
I answer that, by receiving Orders a man pledges himself to the Divine offices.
And since no man can give what is not his, a slave who has not the disposal of
himself, cannot be raised to Orders. If, however, he be raised, he receives the
Order, because freedom is not required for the validity of the sacrament, although
it is requisite for its lawfulness, since it hinders not the power, but the act only.
The same reason applies to all who are under an obligation to others, such as
those who are in debt and like persons (Th. Suppl. q.39, a.3, co.).
However, if a slave is ordained with the knowledge of his master, he is automatically
freed:
If he be ordained, his master knowing and not dissenting, by this very fact he
becomes a freedman. But if his master be in ignorance, the bishop and he who
presented him are bound to pay the master double the slave's value, if they knew
him to be a slave. Otherwise if the slave has possessions of his own, he is bound
to buy his freedom, else he would have to return to the bondage of his master,
notwithstanding the impossibility of his exercising his Order (Th. Suppl., q.39,
a.3, arg.5).
Thomas is clear that the debt must be voluntarily forgiven by the master, or else the debt
must be paid. In either case, the implication is that the slave is an economic slave or an
indentured servant.
Conclusion
Thomas’s position on slavery can be summarized as follows. Following Aristotle,
Thomas believes that some people are, through an intellectual limitation often influenced
by race, natural slaves because it is in their own best interest. These slaves are not to be
abused but can be physically punished for their own instruction. They should be trained
in virtue by their masters to whatever level they are able to attain. They can marry and
even, in some circumstances, be ordained as priests. In contrast to Aristotle, Thomas is
more consistently opposed to conventional slavery. In general he finds this form of
slavery abhorrent. One exception is that Thomas tolerates economic slavery or
indentured servitude: a debt must either be paid off or else explicitly forgiven by the
creditor.
16
Before criticizing Thomas’s position on slavery, one must first consider that the word
slavery in English is a politically-charged word that is almost always associated with the
inexcusable, financially-motivated African slave trade of the fifteenth to nineteenth
centuries. Thomas would have considered this type of slavery to be “abhorrent to our
nature.” One could not consider this a form of natural slavery because the forcible
removal of Africans from their homelands, and their transportation to plantations in
South America and the southern United States, was clearly not for their benefit. And the
fact that they had no debt to repay also rules out the economic form of conventional
slavery.
But given the limited knowledge of foreigners and the different economic system of
the thirteenth century, Thomas’s position on slavery is rational and consistent.
17
Bibliography
Aquinas, Thomas. The Religious State, the Episcopate, and the Priestly Office. Trans.
Aristotle. The Politics. Trans. Benjamin Jowett. Mineola, NY: Dover, 2000.
(1979): 173-181.