What (Good) Is Historical Epistemology
What (Good) Is Historical Epistemology
What (Good) Is Historical Epistemology
Editors' Introduction
Author(s): Uljana Feest and Thomas Sturm
Source: Erkenntnis (1975-) , November 2011, Vol. 75, No. 3, WHAT (GOOD) IS
HISTORICAL EPISTEMOLOGY? (November 2011), pp. 285-302
Published by: Springer
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Erkenntnis
(1975-)
Received: 27 September 201 1 / Accepted: 27 September 201 1 / Published online: 25 October 201 1
© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 201 1
1 Introduction
Uljana Feest and Thomas Sturm have contributed equally to this article.
U. Feest (El)
Institut für Philosophie, Literatur-, Wissenschafts- und Technikgeschichte, Technische Universität
Berlin, Straße des 17. Juni 135, 10623 Berlin, Germany
e-mail: [email protected]
T. Sturm
Departament de Filosofia, Universität Autónoma de Barcelona, Edifici В, 08193 Bellaterra,
Barcelona, Spain
e-mail: [email protected]
Springer
belief, justification, ob
from the notorious arm
possess some kind of
advocates of the claim
social, historical, mate
of this context. In th
naturalized, evolutiona
family of approaches i
approaches just mentio
by historians of scienc
1987; Kmita 1988; Tiles
in any of the leadin
Encyclopedia of Philoso
article in major com
However, we think tha
one, and that it deserv
are therefore grateful
publication.
The question posed in the title of this essay might suggest that our aim is, first, to
explain what historical epistemology really is, and then to evaluate its advantages
and drawbacks vis-à-vis traditional analyses of knowledge. This is not our objective,
however. Right from the outset we wish to emphasize that there are - sometimes
strikingly - different versions of historical epistemology, and that we do not intend
to declare which one is the right kind. Our primary interest here is to compare the
aims and methods of existing versions of historical epistemology with those of
related traditions, projects, and approaches in philosophy. Simply put, advocates of
historical epistemology frequently describe their approach as challenging standard
notions of epistemology (including its history) and the philosophy of science. For
that reason alone the idea needs philosophical scrutiny.
Our assertion that historical epistemology is a concept currently often invoked
by historians of science, but largely ignored by philosophers, needs to be qualified.
A little bit of history will help here (and elsewhere in this introduction). The
concept was chosen to express the guiding idea of the kind of research pursued at
the Max Planck Institute for the History of Science in Berlin (MPIWG) when it
was founded in 1994. To a large extent, this was a contributing cause of the
current popularity of the label among historians. But there was a philosophical
motivation behind this choice as well, which persists until today. A philosopher,
Lorenz Krüger (1932-1994), was chosen to become one of the founding directors,
and it was only his premature death that prevented this appointment. In his own
prior work, he had not only attempted to build bridges between history and
philosophy of science, but to strengthen the ties between history of science and
history of philosophy as well (e.g. Krüger 1973, 1982, 1987; Krüger et al. 1987a,
b; and the essays collected in Krüger 2005). 'Historical epistemology' was
employed as a useful term for expressing these different combinations (cp.
Zwijtink 1995, p. 23), and it became a guiding concept of the new institute (Renn
Springer
Springer
2 Historical Epistem
1 . Histories of episte
2. Histories of episte
3. Dynamics of long-t
Ô Springer
Springer
religion; Kleeberg an
observation (Daston 200
program - that fund
historical change - giv
of identity of a particu
that it has a history? S
down the path of rel
questions can be answ
adopted in historical i
what does it mean to s
rise to historical accou
The first two question
provide an argument
(objectivity, probabilit
change in some respects
the other hand, if Dast
conditions of the identi
certainly be open. Taki
Kusch's contribution t
up to the relativism th
and Galison have tried
identical to relativizing
and Galison 2007, p. 3
offers what can be con
charge. He does so by
objectivity, according
while being in continui
question can neverthel
What about the third q
study of epistemic con
Jutta Schickore addres
practices for understan
and explanation - and
"historical epistemolo
systematic contribution
ambition that Thomas
inherent problems of t
historical epistemology
epistemic concepts. The
of empirical knowledg
between perception and
pursued by philosophic
than a history of pra
reconstruction of the
thereby enable us to ev
past arguments may ha
Springer
Springer
â Springer
Springer
Ö Springer
â Springer
With this overview in mind, we can now return to our guiding questions: What kind
of enterprise is historical epistemology? And what, if anything, might more
mainstream approaches to epistemology or the philosophy of science learn from it?
It should by now be abundantly clear that "historical epistemology" denotes no
one approach to history of science and its epistemological dimensions. This has led
one recent critic to denounce the label as just that, a label, suggesting neither a
coherent movement, nor a real contribution to epistemology (Gingras 2010).
According to Gingras, of the three more recent projects that have adopted the name
"historical epistemology," only one (that of Hans-Jörg Rheinberger) reflects on the
genealogy of this name and self-consciously situates his approach within the
philosophical tradition within which the expression was coined. To Gingras, this
suggests that Daston and Renn are not practicing epistemology at all, whereas
Rheinberger works in a tradition that has effectively redefined what epistemology is,
thereby making his work of limited use to mainstream epistemology. Gingras
correctly points out that there was some disagreement about whether the resulting
project in the study of knowledge was to be called 'historical epistemology' or
'epistemological history' (of science). Canguilhem himself seems to have preferred
the latter, and in that sense his (and Rheinbergers) approach could be read as
primarily addressing questions in the history - rather than epistemology - of
science. At this point, it is illuminating to note that Rheinberger (2010, p. 3f.)
claims that there were two converging tendencies throughout the twentieth century:
a "historicization of the philosophy of science", and an "epistemologization of the
history of science", and that both can be "combined under the concept of historical
epistemology" - which he himself favors. In this way, Rheinberger emphasizes the
philosophical ambitions of his research.
But Gingras's assertion is not quite accurate for another reason. Wartofsky
(1979a, p. 121) referred back to the French backgrounds, but he also compared his
conception to Piaget's "genetic epistemology" (Wartofsky 1983a) and Quine's call
for an "epistemology naturalized" (Wartofsky 1987). Renn (1996, p. 242) explicitly
refers to Wartofsky, albeit without adopting the latter's conception. Hacking and
Daston, in turn, do not refer to Wartofsky, but share some of his ideas: the Kantian
goal of explaining concepts of knowledge or science, and the emphasis upon
practices in explaining the emergence and development of these concepts. If
Ö Springer
Ô Springer
point is independent of
whether epistemologic
in passing that early m
mutually informed one
the history of science m
conceived by him. How
made by historical epis
can and should replace
Kitcher's arguments f
epistemology are closer
explicitly calls for an i
epistemology of mathe
history of mathemat
mathematics as descrip
Kitcher's more general
neglect its own history
of tradition." Accordi
individualist conceptio
problems are. By contra
we should use history t
the history of science
material in support of
naturalism." Kitcher's
assumption that practic
this in the realm of stu
Mary Tiles, finally, de
debates. In this, she foc
As she lays out, Bruno
French historical epist
Pierre Bourdieu. Latour
far enough in rejecting
and nature, a separatio
critique is unwarranted,
readings of what this "
Latour' s project of ana
conceptualize seemingl
terminology and back
analytical philosophers,
are quite similar to rec
distinction between ep
We are aware that this special issue offers only a glimpse of the kinds of questions
raised by the approaches subsumed under the label "historical epistemology." In
Springer
â Springer
References
Andersen, H., Barker, P., & Chen, X. (2006). The cognitive structure of scientific revolutions. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Burian, R. M. (1977). More than a marriage of convenience: On the inextricability of the history and
philosophy of science. Philosophy of Science, 44 , 1-42.
Canguilhem, G. (2006). Wissenschaft, Technik, Leben: Beiträge zur historischen Epistemologie, Transi,
by R. Voullié et al., with an afterword by H. Schmidgen. (Berlin: Merve).
Chimisso, C. (2003). The tribunal of philosophy and its norms: History and philosophy in Georges
Canguilhem's historical epistemology. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and
Biomedical Sciences, 34 , 297-327.
Damerow, P. (2006). The material culture of calculation: A theoretical framework for a historical
epistemology of the concept of number. In U. Geliert & E. Jabloňka (Eds.), Mathematisation and
demathematisation: Social, philosophical and educational ramifications (pp. 19-56). Rotterdam:
Sense Pubi.
Daston, L. (1988). Classical probability in the enlightenment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Daston, L. (1994). Historical epistemology. In J. Chandler, A. I. Davidson, & H. Harootunian (Eds.),
Questions of evidence (pp. 282-289). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Daston, L. (Ed.). (2000). Biographies of scientific objects. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Daston, L. (2007). The history of emergences, /sis, 98 , 801-808.
Daston, L. (2008). On scientific observation. Isis, 99, 97-1 10.
Daston, L., & Galison, P. (2007). Objectivity. New York: Zone Books.
Daston, L., & Limbeck, E. (Eds.). (201 1). Histories of scientific observation. Chicago: Chicago University
Press.
Davidson, A. I. (2002). The emergence of sexuality: Historical epistemology and the formation of
concepts. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Ô Springer
â Springer
ö Springer