(Foundations of Human Interaction) Douglas W. Maynard, John Heritage - The Ethnomethodology Program - Legacies and Prospects-Oxford University Press (2022)
(Foundations of Human Interaction) Douglas W. Maynard, John Heritage - The Ethnomethodology Program - Legacies and Prospects-Oxford University Press (2022)
(Foundations of Human Interaction) Douglas W. Maynard, John Heritage - The Ethnomethodology Program - Legacies and Prospects-Oxford University Press (2022)
F O U N DAT IO N S O F H UM A N I N T E R AC T IO N
General Editor: N.J. Enfield, Max Planck Institute for Psycholinguistics,
Radboud University, Nijmegen, and the University of Sydney
This series promotes new interdisciplinary research on the elements of human sociality,
in particular as they relate to the activity and experience of communicative interaction
and human relationships. Books in this series explore the foundations of human
interaction from a wide range of perspectives, using multiple theoretical and
methodological tools. A premise of the series is that a proper understanding of
human sociality is only possible if we take a truly interdisciplinary approach.
Relationship Thinking
N.J. Enfield
Talking About Troubles in Conversation
Gail Jefferson
Edited by Paul Drew, John Heritage, Gene Lerner, and Anita Pomerantz
The Instruction of Imagination
Daniel Dor
How Traditions Live and Die
Olivier Morin
The Origins of Fairness
Nicolas Baumard
Requesting Responsibility
Jörg Zinken
Accountability in Social Interaction
Jeffrey Robinson
Intercorporeality
Edited by Christian Meyer, Jürgen Streeck, J. Scott Jordan
Repairing the Broken Surface of Talk
Gail Jefferson
Edited by Jörg Bergmann and Paul Drew
The Normative Animal?
Neil Roughley and Kurt Bayertz
When Conversation Lapses
Elliott M. Hoey
Communicating & Relating
Robert B. Arundale
Asking and Telling in Conversation
Anita Pomerantz
Face-to-Face Dialogue
Janet Beavin Bavelas
The Book of Answers
Tanya Stivers
The Ethnomethodology
Program
Legacies and Prospects
Edited by
D OU G L A S W. M AY NA R D
J O H N H E R I TAG E
1
3
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers
the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education
by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University
Press in the UK and certain other countries.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780190854409.001.0001
1 3 5 7 9 8 6 4 2
Paperback printed by Marquis, Canada
Hardback printed by Bridgeport National Bindery, Inc., United States of America
Contents
Acknowledgments vii
List of Contributors ix
PA RT I : A N T E C E D E N T S A N D T H E O RY
PA RT I I : E M P I R IC A L I M PAC T
PA RT I I I : G R OW T H P O I N T S
Notes 477
Name Index 495
Subject Index 503
Acknowledgments
This book emerged as a result of a gathering at the University of California, Los Angeles
(UCLA) to celebrate Harold Garfinkel’s life and work, and to take stock of his research
endeavors, their influence, and their contemporary development. We are grateful to the
organizers of this meeting, including Emanuel Schegloff and Stefan Timmermans, for
assembling a group of scholars who have been influenced by Garfinkel and his ethno-
methodological inquiries, and to UCLA and the Department of Sociology for facilitating
and hosting the meeting.
The present volume arose from our collective belief that the meeting contained too
much of value to be consigned to the vagaries of collective memory, and that instead
it could form a nucleus for a wider and more integrated consideration of Garfinkel’s
initiatives and their consequences. We are grateful to Meredith Keffer, Acquisitions
Editor and Macey Fairchild, Project Editor, at Oxford University Press, and Preetham Raj,
Project Manager, at Newgen Knowledge Works, for expertly shepherding the manuscript
through the production process. Keith Cox handled the responsibilities of assembling
the chapters and graphics for submission to Oxford University Press, and Lucas Wiscons
facilitated the enhancement of graphic images for several of the chapters. We also thank
Keith Cox and Lucas Wiscons for their prompt and skillful assembly of the subject and
name indexes.
Contributors
Steven E. Clayman
Department of Sociology, University of California, Los Angeles, CA, USA
Harold Garfinkel
Formerly Department of Sociology, University of California, Los Angeles, CA, USA
Charles Goodwin
Formerly Professor of Communication, University of California, Los Angeles, CA, USA
Christian Greiffenhagen
Department of Sociology, The Chinese University of Hong Kong, Hong Kong, China
Christian Heath
Professor of Work and Organisation, King’s College, London, England
John Heritage
Department of Sociology, University of California, Los Angeles, CA, USA
Nikki Jones
Department of African American Studies, University of California, Berkeley, CA, USA
Lillian Jungleib
Department of Sociology, University of California, Santa Barbara, CA, USA
Eric Livingston
Faculty of Medicine and Health; School of Psychology, University of New England,
Armidale, Australia
Paul Luff
Professor in Organisations and Technology, King’s College, London, England
Michael E. Lynch
Department of Science & Technology Studies, Cornell University, Ithaca, NY, USA
Michael Mair
University of Liverpool, Liverpool, England
Douglas W. Maynard
Department of Sociology, University of Wisconsin, Madison, WI. USA
Lorenza Mondada
Professor for French and General Linguistics, University of Basel, Basel, Switzerland
x Contributors
Geoffrey Raymond
Department of Sociology, University of California, Santa Barbara, CA, USA
Kristen Schilt
Department of Sociology, University of Chicago, Chicago, IL, USA
Wes W. Sharrock
Department of Sociology, University of Manchester, Manchester, England
Philippe Sormani
Senior FNS Researcher, University of Lausanne, Lausanne, Switzerland
Iddo Tavory
Department of Sociology, New York University, New York, NY, USA
Jason J. Turowetz
Garfinkel Archive, Newburyport, MA, USA; University of Siegen, Siegen, GE
Darin Weinberg
Department of Sociology, University of Cambridge, Cambridge, England
Don Zimmerman
Department of Sociology, University of California, Santa Barbara, CA, USA
1
Ethnomethodology’s Legacies
and Prospects
John Heritage and Douglas W. Maynard
The first development was, of course, the one pioneered by Parsons himself
(1951). The second, with its focus on the structuring of experience as the foun-
dation of social organization, would occupy Garfinkel over the next 50 years and
beyond. It would lead to a variety of quasi-experimental “breaching” studies,
to explorations of the ineluctable contextuality of human reasoning, action,
and language use, to a re-specification of the role of norms in social action, to
studies of the embodied management of courses of action ranging from the most
mundane of everyday activities to fundamental scientific experiments, and to
investigations of singular events such as moments of scientific discovery. In the
process, Garfinkel engaged with topics in social science—the theory of action,
2 The Ethnomethodology Program
Garfinkel’s Development
Harold Garfinkel was born in 1917 into a large Jewish community in Newark,
New Jersey. The initial plan was for him to join the small furniture business
owned by his father, and to this end he enrolled at the University of Newark (now
part of Rutgers University) for training in business and accounting. During
this period, Garfinkel developed a strong interest in sociology and, having
graduated in 1939, proceeded to become a graduate student in the Sociology
Department at the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill (Garfinkel
2002a; Rawls 2002 and Chapter 3 in this volume). The graduate students he
joined at North Carolina had Weberian interests, drawing on Znaniecki’s work
on Social Actions (1936), and Parsons’s The Structure of Social Action (1937).
From the philosophy department, Garfinkel was exposed to phenomenological
texts, including those by Husserl (Garfinkel 2002b). The sociology department
was headed by the redoubtable Howard Odum, a scholar and administrator of
immense energy, the founder of the journal Social Forces, and a past president
of the American Sociological Association (1930). Odum was strongly committed
to the study of African American culture in the South, and to racial progress
(Vance and Jocher 1955), and this interest was shared by Garfinkel, whose two
earliest publications addressed issues of racism and racial injustice (Rawls,
Chapter 3 in this volume).
Ethnomethodology’s Legacies and Prospects 3
attention to and respect for the overarching demands of justice (Garfinkel 1949).
However, for the B-B cases, although degrees of guilt also emerged, they were not
constructed within an overall orientation to justice as a fundamental or sacred
goal. Neither did motives, circumstances, and identities, if known or understood
at all, carry much weight. The stance of the court in dealing with B-B defendants
was pragmatic, rather than principled. Whereas numbers of B-B cases with first-
degree indictments were reduced to second degree or less, the B-B cases did not
“earn” or deserve such outcomes. Manslaughter was determined to be the most
fitting description of the crime, because it disdainfully allowed “that homicide
was committed, but that the homicide involved Negroes” (Garfinkel 1949).
Taken together, the “Color Trouble” and homicide studies focused on so-
cial justice issues while embodying an analytic framework that centered
on presuppositions involved in the construal of actors and actions in social
encounters. Garfinkel would continue this approach in his preliminary PhD
studies on racial and other minorities at Harvard (Rawls and Turowetz 2019a;
Turowetz and Rawls 2020), in an essay on degradation ceremonies (Garfinkel
1956), and most tellingly in his analysis of Agnes, a transsexual who provided
him with an occasion for a radical rethinking of gender (Garfinkel 1967b; Schilt,
Chapter 8 in this volume). In addition, Garfinkel’s investigation of race-differen-
tial patterns of homicide convictions foreshadowed the critique of excessive reli-
ance on official statistics that emerged in the 1960s. The study presciently took up
a phenomenological critique of the statistical positivism that was then advancing
to ascendency in postwar American sociology (Calhoun 2008; Rawls 2018).
Harvard
The integration of a set of common value patterns with the internalized need-
disposition structure of the constituent personalities is the core phenomenon
of the dynamics of social systems. That the stability of any social system except
the most evanescent interaction process is dependent on a degree of such in-
tegration may be said to be the fundamental dynamic theorem of sociology.
(1951:42)
social situations and the continually dynamic contexts of interaction, the ways
in which norms might be appropriately applied to such contexts, and communi-
cation about all of these were all questions about social order that were ontolog-
ically prior to the Hobbesian motivational concerns, which indeed presupposed
all of them. Answering Georg Simmel’s (1910) famous question “How is society
possible?” could not truly be achieved without addressing them.
The intellectual dialogue with Parsons continued into the 1960s in lectures,
meetings, and successive revisions of the Parsons Primer (Garfinkel [1962] 2019;
Rawls and Turowetz 2019a). Rather as Schütz ([1932] 1967) undertook to re-
construct the methodological foundations of Max Weber’s social theory in terms
of meaning construction, Garfinkel’s dissertation attempted the same task for
Parsonian social systems theory. The plausibility of the undertaking rested on
their common commitment to the theoretical centrality of social interaction.
However, Parsons, whose work focused on the motivation of action and the
Hobbesian problem of order, was content with top-down generalizations about
normative values. Garfinkel’s focus from the North Carolina days, by contrast,
was on social experience, and the knitting of that experience through the process
of interaction into constructed and reconstructed orders of meaning that can en-
dure across time and place.
Garfinkel’s (1952) dissertation elaborated a comparison of the handling of
“pre-theoretical” problems by Parsons and Schütz (abridged as Chapter 2 of
this volume), exploring the epistemological and methodological implications of
the notion that the human world is constructed within social interaction, and
only there. The thesis itself was “concerned with the conditions under which a
person makes continuous sense of the world around him” (Garfinkel 1952:1).
The procedure he used to address this question involved the manipulation of
“incongruous” understandings of events by experimental subjects. The results
of the study are briefly reported in Garfinkel (1967e:58–67). Having worked as
an experimenter on the “Information Apperception Test” at Harvard (Rawls,
Chapter 3 in this volume), Garfinkel was experienced in working with incon-
gruity scenarios. It was a technique that he would also continue to exploit in the
ensuing decade at UCLA.
Garfinkel’s primary theoretical resource, both in the dissertation and sub-
sequently, was Alfred Schütz. Arriving in New York in 1940 as a refugee from
Hitler’s Germany, Schütz devoted himself to theoretical research that stressed the
social constitution of experience and knowledge. Drawing on Husserl, Schütz
argued that human experience is constituted within pragmatic presuppositions
that he termed the “epoché of the natural attitude.” Within this attitude of eve-
ryday life, persons assume that the world will be the same today as it was yes-
terday, and that ordinary practices of living will work in the same ways and with
Ethnomethodology’s Legacies and Prospects 7
the same effects as they have done previously. The knowledge that actors draw
upon, Schütz averred, is socially presupposed, approximate, and held in typified
forms that are adaptable, and adapted, to circumstances. Significantly, there is
little convergence between this type of recipe knowledge and the rationality of
scientific knowledge. Indeed, Schütz held that the scientific attitude and the nat-
ural attitude are distinct from one another, and the knowledge stemming from
them is not easily compatible. A person may be “rational” in the common-sense
world, but this rationality is pragmatic and not to be confused with scientific ra-
tionality (Garfinkel 1967f; Schütz 1962).
In the context of social interaction, Schütz argued that despite the fact that
actors’ orientations to the world are unavoidably perspectival, they will none-
theless continue to assume what he termed the “general thesis of reciprocal
perspectives” (Schütz 1962:12; Garfinkel 1967e:55–57). The maintenance of this
assumption, Schütz argued, involves no “guarantees”: instead, it depends solely
and entirely on the efforts of the actors themselves. Many of Garfinkel’s early ex-
perimental procedures, or what he called “demonstrations,” were designed to
undermine these reciprocities, and to reveal the associated collapse of intersub-
jectivity that resulted. The demonstrations showed that the management of the
reciprocities is deeply embedded in the moral order, and that they are funda-
mental features of the “trust” conditions (Garfinkel 1963) on which all human
intersubjectivity is fundamentally based. Trust, in Garfinkel’s rendering, consists
in an actor’s assuming the general thesis, assuming that others adhere to it as
well, and assuming that others take for granted the actor’s own adherence to the
thesis.
. . . like “fact” and “fancy” and “opinion” and “my opinion” and “your opinion”
and “what we’re entitled to say” and “what the evidence shows” and “what can
be demonstrated” and “what actually was said” as compared with “what only
you think he said” or “what he seemed to have said.” You have these notions
of evidence and demonstration and of matters of relevance, of true and false,
of public and private, of methodic procedure, and the rest. At the same time
8 The Ethnomethodology Program
the whole thing was handled by all those concerned as part of the same set-
ting in which they were used by the members, by these jurors, to get the
work of deliberations done. That work for them was deadly serious. (Hill and
Crittenden 1968:7; reprinted in Garfinkel 1974:16)
The methods of reasoning that Garfinkel encountered in the jury project could
not remotely be handled through the Parsonian tenets of social action. Instead,
Garfinkel advocated a form of analysis—ethnomethodology—to investigate
“people’s methods” (Lynch 2007) for jointly determining, in the case of jurors,
facts, evidence, etc., in ways that were publicly accountable. In other contexts,
the methods of reasoning would be different. The term “ethnomethodology” was
intended as a cognate of extant anthropological terms such as “ethnobotany” or
“ethnomedicine,” that focused on the knowledge practices deployed in distinc-
tive sociocultural contexts.
In the process of developing ethnomethodology, Garfinkel initiated huge the-
oretical innovations: that rules and norms could neither determine nor explain
behavior without reference to the details of their situated application; that there
are no guarantees of mutual understandings among persons, nor could such
understandings be achieved except through the practices of situated interac-
tion; and that social reasoning is multitudinous and cannot be reduced to logical
structures. Above all, and notwithstanding his advertised interest in sense-
making, Garfinkel insisted on an anti-cognitivist approach to the topic. Social
sense-making cannot conceivably be reduced to psychological processes, and
shared understanding cannot be understood as the projection of cognitive prop-
erties. Ethnomethodology would focus on the “witnessable order” (Livingston
2008). And it would address the shared social methods that social actors together
use to perceive, recognize, and act upon everyday circumstances, and to do so
in a common, socially shared fashion that is itself recognizable and accountable.
The breaching demonstrations included the use of everyday games that are easily
disrupted by departures from basic rules. In a celebrated study, Garfinkel (1963)
engineered disruption using a simple field of action—the game of tic-tac-toe.
Garfinkel observed, in parallel with John Rawls (1955), that the game and its as-
sociated field of events are constituted by a set of “basic rules.” These include that
the players take alternate turns; that moves have to be made within the confines
of a single cell; that moves, once made, cannot be changed; and that the object of
the game is to get “three in a row,” which constitutes a victory ending the game.
These rules define the constituent events making up tic-tac-toe. To become con-
stitutive, these rules have to be oriented as framing a set of actions that players
cannot choose to depart from, and that they expect to be binding on other
player(s), and expect that other(s) expect the same of them (Garfinkel 1963:190).
Garfinkel underscores that these constitutive rules are used to define the game
itself. Thus, changes in the basic rules will change the game. The rules will also
define the meanings of actions within the game:
The basic rules provide a behavior’s sense as an action. They are the terms
in which a player decides whether or not he has correctly identified “What
happened.” “Subjective meaning” is “attached” to a behavior in terms of these
rules. (Garfinkel 1963:195)
As will be clear, the basic rules are central to participants’ reasoning about any
“state of play” in the game: for example, a person who sees “two crosses in a row”
should, using what may be termed “tic-tac-toe reasoning,” use their turn to block
the winning third move (cf. Heritage 1998:178–79).
Given their constitution, games are easily disrupted by departures from
basic rules. Garfinkel engineered disruptions by having experimenters (UCLA
undergraduates) invite subjects to make the first move in a game of tic-tac-toe,
then erasing their mark and placing it elsewhere, while avoiding any indication
that something unusual was being done. In over 250 trials (Garfinkel 1963:200–
206), almost all subjects displayed a disturbed reaction to the behavior and 75%
objected strongly to it. However, a small minority, who responded by recipro-
cating the experimenter’s moves, were comparatively serene, having effectively
elected to play a new game. Thus adjusting (or not) to what were treated as con-
stitutive rules of the game with their associated interpretive frameworks had a
major effect on the actions and the sentiments of the participants.
In a series of related procedures aimed at disrupting everyday activities,
experimenters insisted that subjects clarify the meaning of simple remarks. As
is well known, subjects again reacted with bewilderment and anger. Garfinkel
Ethnomethodology’s Legacies and Prospects 11
When the work with games was begun, we took for granted that the
omnirelevance of normative regulation was peculiar to games. . . . When, how-
ever, incongruity-inducing procedures were applied in “real life” situations, it
was unnerving to find the seeming endless variety of events that lent themselves
to the production of really nasty surprises. These events ranged from those that,
according to sociological commonsense, were “critical,” like standing very, very
close to a person while otherwise maintaining an innocuous conversation, to
others that according to sociological commonsense were “trivial,” like saying
“hello” at the termination of a conversation. . . . It was conjectured therefore that
all actions as perceived events may have a constitutive structure, and that per-
haps it is the threat to the normative order of events as such that is the critical
variable in evoking indignation. . . . (Garfinkel 1963:198)
structure, and indeed language use itself, are dependent on their usage and
application. But “stability” is itself a gloss for a large variety of environing
circumstances and considerations. As Raymond et al. (Chapter 6 in this volume)
note, police use of a sidewalk ordinance “for another first time” involves such
matters as when and where they enforce it, the methods they use in doing so,
the various ways in which officers and residents alike are treated as accountable
to the ordinance, who apologizes to whom, and so on. The ordinance therefore
becomes incarnate in how the participants cast the specific particulars of those
scenes as documents of an underlying pattern described in the text of the ordi-
nance, the exceptions it provides for, and the sedimented patterns of enforce-
ment that have preceded the current encounter. The profound embeddedness of
rule application in a complex mesh of ecological circumstances (Goodwin 2000
and Chapter 7 in this volume; Mondada, Chapter 11 in this volume) and the ways
in which these applications are made observable and accountable should be the
true object of normative analysis.
Language Use
The situated characteristics of normative rules also apply to the primary me-
dium of social understanding and communication—language use. The term “in-
dexical” was originally used by linguists to refer to terms whose reference and
meaning unavoidably shift with context: these include pronouns, deictic terms
like “here” and “there,” and time formulations such as “today,” “tomorrow,” etc.
Thus, the expression “I’ll be here tomorrow” cannot be understood without
knowing who the speaker is, where s/he is located, and what day it is, and whether
the expression is a threat, a promise, or some other kind of action.
As was the case for the “documentary method,” Garfinkel massively expands
the meaning of the term “indexical expression” to embrace every use of language.
Because it is based on typification, language is open and elastic in terms of its
fit to real-world circumstances (Schütz 1962; Heritage 1984, 1987) and requires
contextual elaboration to achieve sense and reference. Language usage is also un-
avoidably a part of action-in-context and it therefore involves participants’ rec-
ognition of how it is being used and for what purpose. Garfinkel summarized
these features, in parallel with his account of the documentary method, as the
indexical properties of natural language, and summarized them in the observa-
tion that
In the 1950s and 1960s, at the dawn of the cybernetic age, the fundamental hope
and expectation was that finite sets of rules could generate all the meanings that
human beings can extract from sentences. This was also the underlying com-
mitment of the “normative paradigm” (Wilson 1970), with its objective of a de-
terministic science of rule-governed behavior. This hope was frustrated during
later decades and, with it, the sociological expectation that a “common cul-
ture” of uninterpreted rule-based symbols could credibly be said to undergird
intersubjectivity and shared understandings in the social world. Though, as
Watson (2008) has commented, quantitative researchers, like the logicians be-
fore them, were aware of the flexibilities of language in use and the difficulties
of establishing equivalences across settings (Blalock 1982; cf. Cicourel 1964),
Garfinkel’s observations accurately anticipated the problems and contradictions
to which this program was heir. Yet if the meaning of rules, norms, and linguistic
signs is assured by nothing other than “stability in usage,” the way is open for the
normative, conceptual, and linguistic plasticity and flexibility that will be both
the condition and consequence of social change. Indeed, dynamism in usage
generates a continuous potential for change, regardless of whether change is
actualized or not (Heritage 2010).
Accountability
his research was based are merely the aggregate of these very judgments. It was
with the advent of Garfinkel’s work that the constitutive investigative judgments
in the formation of the suicide statistics would take hold as sociological topics.
How are the ordinary judgments of officials to be related to the suicide rates?
In his discussion of the work of coroners and their field investigators,
Garfinkel observes that they begin
. . . with a death that the coroner finds equivocal as to mode of death. That
death they use as a precedent with which various ways of living in society
that could have terminated with that death are searched out and read “in
the remains”; in the scraps of this and that like the body and its trappings,
medicine bottles, notes, bits and pieces of clothing, and other memora-
bilia—stuff that can be photographed, collected, and packaged. Other “re-
mains” are collected too: rumors, passing remarks, and stories—materials in
the “repertoires” of whosoever might be consulted via the common work of
conversations. (1967g:17)
Douglas (1967), drawing on Garfinkel’s work, was the first to argue that some
of the patterns in the suicide statistics—for example, the lower level of suicide
among Catholics compared with Protestants that was relied upon in Durkheim’s
([1897] 1951) classic study—might be a product of the activities of various in-
terested parties in a position to influence rate-producing agencies in predomi-
nantly Catholic and Protestant jurisdictions. This was confirmed by Day (1987)
in a later study of suicide rates in Protestant and Catholic regions of Switzerland,
Austria, and the Netherlands during the late nineteenth century. Day (1987:459)
showed that, by comparison with Protestant areas, Catholic jurisdictions had
elevated levels of deaths classified as “accidental” and theorized that classifying
deaths in this way likely provided a method of avoiding the deep religious, moral,
and social stigma arising from suicide verdicts.
Atkinson’s (1978) research additionally showed that coroners and their field
investigators distinguish between equivocal modes of death, such as falling,
drowning, etc., and unequivocal ones, such as hanging or gunshot wounds.
Equivocal deaths allow more leeway for judgments of accidental death or “open”
verdicts, which will not be recorded as suicides. These judgments are integrated
with findings about the victim’s background and social circumstances—religion,
bereavement, financial pressure, severe illness, depression, etc.—to yield a con-
clusion which is held with varying degrees of doubt or uncertainty. Many dif-
ferent participants—the deceased, the deceased’s family, official investigators,
and recording officials—can all contribute to the final judgment. For example,
investigating officers develop “hunches” about cases based on knowledge of the
mode of death, the circumstances, and the state of mind and motivations of the
16 The Ethnomethodology Program
deceased (Atkinson 1978). However, both family members and, before their
death, suicidal persons themselves can conceal or mask, or alternatively accen-
tuate, motivations and evidences that could lead to a suicide verdict and, in turn,
investigating officers may be oriented to those possibilities. At the end of the day,
the suicide statistics record the outcomes of a tangle of actions accomplished by
all the relevant actors, who are themselves reflexively oriented to normative con-
siderations, and to prospective and retrospective practical reasoning about the
“remains” of the case.
The notion that sociological phenomena and findings can be profitably
connected to the constitutive sociological work done “in the streets” is also to be
found in Cicourel’s (1968) landmark study of juvenile justice, Wieder’s (1974) in-
vestigation of the operation of the “convict code” in a halfway house for paroled
narcotics addicts, and Dorothy Smith’s (1978) analysis of how mental illness
is portrayed through descriptions of departures from normality. Perhaps the
single most influential of these studies is Garfinkel’s path-breaking analysis of
“Agnes,” an intersexed person who presented at UCLA in 1958 in search of sur-
gery (Garfinkel 1967b; see Schilt, Chapter 8 in this volume).
Collectively, these studies underline the hopeless inadequacy of attempts to
explain human actions in terms of adherence to rules. For just as Durkheim
in the Division of Labor argued that contract alone cannot explain the
arrangements of modern societies because contract is undergirded by what he
termed the non-contractual elements of contract, so Garfinkel shows that the
operation of norms, indeed of the very institution of gender, is undergirded
by an indefinitely large array of socially organized practices of reasoning and
action (Heritage 1984:180–98). Accounting practices that are sustained by
use and reuse, together with many that are “protected from induction” (Sacks
1992a:394) and indefeasible (Pollner 1974a, 1975), are the resources which
persons can and must deploy, regardless of personal interests. These studies
point to the role of accounting practices, not only in explanation and justifi-
cation, but most fundamentally in the constitution of social events and their
everyday apprehension and recognition.
Garfinkel’s theoretical and empirical orientations related to the documen-
tary method of interpretation, the trust conditions providing a moral founda-
tion to the sense of normative orientations in everyday life, the indexical use
of language, and accountability in practical actions such as “counting” suicides
or assembling other official statistics, have provided an inexhaustible baseline
of topics for inquiry, carried forward both broadly and deeply into a pano-
rama of social life domains and activities (Vom Lehn 2013:Chapter 9). We call
these inquiries “ethnomethodology’s legacies,” and we review them in five di-
verse but overlapping collections: (I) language use and social interaction; (II)
ethnographic inquiry and legal environments; (III) science, technology, and
Ethnomethodology’s Legacies and Prospects 17
workplace studies; (IV) statistics, surveys, and social problems; and (V) studies
of being and doing: gender, race, and other identities. That ethnomethodology’s
legacies are vast is indicated by these diverse collections, but this also creates se-
vere challenges to any kind of comprehensive overview. Although we review and
cite a very large number of studies, we necessarily have been incomplete in our
references. Those studies we do cite should be taken as pointers toward further
aspects of the literature comprising ethnomethodology’s legacies.
Conversation Analysis
CA began from the premise that these methods were real, researchable, and
trans-situational in application. As Sacks put it in one of his lectures:
For example, while any in situ deployment of a practice (e.g., initiating re-
pair on another speaker’s talk) may have many differing consequences for the
parties’ understandings and repercussions for subsequent action, other-initi-
ated repair is nevertheless a general practice (or set of practices) that can be
robustly described and repeatedly and reliably identified in other contexts.
Accordingly, Sacks also readily embraced Schegloff ’s mid-1960s introduction
of the use of collections of cases, and this usage has remained standard prac-
tice in CA ever since.
CA studies conceive context in “local” terms. In the first instance, taking turns
in interaction is a highly situated activity, requiring, on a recipient’s part, atten-
tion to a current speaker’s turn to identify its completion, and to determine who
has rights to speak next (Sacks, Schegloff, and Jefferson 1974). Moreover, each
turn is both “context-shaped and context-renewing” (Heritage 1984:242), and
analysis involves, as Schegloff (1992:1320) observes, both “position and compo-
sition.” A turn of talk implements a social action that initially displays a grasp of
what was just said (Schegloff 1992), at the same time as it sets the context for a
next action which will also require a similar display (Sacks and Schegloff 1973).
The “context of action” is thus for CA a highly dynamic entity, and one which is
even more intricate once the visual and embodied contexts of action are taken
Ethnomethodology’s Legacies and Prospects 19
into account (Streeck, Goodwin, and LeBaron 2011; Goodwin, Chapter 7 in this
volume; Mondada, Chapter 11 in this volume).
The predominantly, indeed overwhelmingly, local nature of interaction has an
important methodological payoff: the so-called next turn proof procedure. Given
that each next turn displays an understanding of the turn before, a speaker of the
current turn can inspect that next turn to see how their own turn was understood,
and so can the external “overhearing” researcher—the conversation analyst. The
analyst, at least partially, can characterize the action-import of a speaker’s turn
by delineating aspects of the recipient’s response.2 That is, each next turn will
be understood as “fitted” to the prior and to be “recipient designed” to display
an orientation to the characteristics of its producer and its context (Sacks et al.
1974:727). Hence, for any given turn, albeit subject to some limitations (Goodwin
and Goodwin 1987; Heritage and Atkinson 1984; Schegloff 1996), mutual
understandings of local context will be on display for analytic treatment.
In the past 50 years, CA has grown enormously and has expanded in ap-
plication to many different languages (Clift 2016; Sidnell and Stivers 2013).
Increasingly, its findings appear to be robust across a range of unrelated lan-
guages (Enfield et al. 2019; Kendrick et al. 2020; Stivers et al. 2009) and have
even been applied to ancient texts (Boas 2017). In the course of its expansion,
accumulating research about interactional practices is finding that they cluster
around the management of fundamental aspects of social life: turn taking (Sacks
et al. 1974); the sequencing of action (Schegloff 2007c); the repair of production
and reception problems (Schegloff, Jefferson, and Sacks 1977); affiliation and
social solidarity; reference; epistemics and deontics; among others (Sidnell and
Stivers 2013). Finally, applications in medicine (Heritage and Maynard 2006),
mass media (Clayman and Heritage 2002), sociolegal contexts (Atkinson and
Drew 1979; Maynard 1984), education (Seedhouse 2011), people-processing
institutions (Heritage and Clayman 2010; Zimmerman 1992), survey research
(Maynard et al. 2002) and collaborative workplaces of various kinds have pro-
liferated very widely.3 CA has also expanded to include analysis of a wide range
of body behaviors and configurations, now effectively its own subfield of “multi-
modal analysis” (Streeck et al. 2011).
CA has become a vast field of study with numerous applications and enor-
mous influence. Within sociology, it has thoroughly rejuvenated the study of so-
cial action in the tradition of Weber, Mead, Parsons, and Goffman, adding rigor
and precision to research that previously traded in broad generalities and glosses.
Its specificity has led to an expanding intersection with linguistics, including the
development of a subfield—interactional linguistics (Clift 2016; Couper-Kuhlen
and Selting 2018)—and infusing the study of language with insights from the
study of action and vice versa.
20 The Ethnomethodology Program
CA is not the only domain of study that Sacks initiated. A second domain—mem-
bership categorization analysis (MCA)—also has a robust intellectual presence.
Many of Sacks’s observations targeted common-sense knowledge of the social
world that is embedded in categorical terms and is deployed in locally managed
sequences of interaction. From early in his career, Sacks’s goal was to create a
formal apparatus for the description of this knowledge. As developed in his dis-
sertation and later, its fundamental concept is the notion of membership cate-
gorization devices (MCDs). These comprise a set of categories and some rules of
application. Categories, Sacks observed, are organized in collections that “go to-
gether” within a given culture: [male/female], [Catholic, Protestant, Jew, Muslim,
etc.], [quarterback, forward, wide receiver, etc.]. As Schegloff (2007a) notes:
. . . some of them go together with alternative sets of other categories (e.g., “pro-
fessor” goes with student, administrator, staff, etc., as “campus” categories on
the one hand, and with plumber, doctor, secretary, undertaker as occupational
categories on the other). (In “The Baby Cried” paper,4 “baby” belongs to several
such alternative collections.) (2007a:467)
Sacks (1972a) described some MCDs as “Pn-adequate,” meaning that the cate-
gories within them can define any member of a population. Age (young, old) and
sex (male, female), per Sacks (1972a:33) are Pn-adequate category collections
(although the sex MCD would now have additional categories, and in some cases
would no longer be regarded as Pn-adequate), while the collection of categories
making up a football team are not. Membership categories have several impor-
tant properties:
1) They are inferentially rich. As Schegloff (2007a:469) states the point, “They
are the store house and the filing system for the common-sense knowledge
that ordinary people—that means ALL people in their capacity as ordinary
people—have about what people are like, how they behave etc.”
2) Much of this richness arises from their association with category-bound
activities: these are activities or conduct generally taken to be typical or
characteristic of category incumbents. Sacks illustrated this with a con-
versation in which a thrice-married male caller to a suicide prevention
center who had worked in the hair and fashion industry was asked about
sexual problems. His response: “You probably suspect, as far as the hair
stylist and, uh one way or the other, they’re straight or homosexual, some-
thing like that” directly connects the question to his previous occupation
(Sacks 1992a:46).
Ethnomethodology’s Legacies and Prospects 21
3) Sacks also observed that membership categories are protected against in-
duction: incompatibilities between category membership, behavior, and
other attributes are treated as “exceptions.” Thus, as Sacks notes, “[T]here
are, for example, ‘Mommy’s cars’ and ‘Kids’ cars.’ And again, the phenom-
enon of ‘Mommy’s cars’ is protected against induction. It isn’t the case that
if you think that a Pontiac station wagon is a Mommy’s car, then if you
see a kid driving one you say, ‘I guess I’m wrong.’ You see ‘a kid driving a
Mommy’s car.’ ” (Sacks 1992a:394)
Sacks identified a range of rules associated with the use of MCDs. The economy
rule indicates that a single category term from any MCD can do adequate ref-
erence. The consistency rule provides that when one category is deployed to
refer to or identify a person in a scene, then others in the scene may be identi-
fied by reference to the same or other categories from the given collection. Thus,
a person introduced as “a physicist” may prompt a recipient to self-identify as
“a biochemist”—both categories being drawn from the collection “occupations.”
Finally, in his famous paper on children’s stories, Sacks (1972b) argued that these
rules have corollary maxims for recipients. A hearer’s maxim provides that if you
are presented with an action that is tied to some category from a collection, you
“hear it that way” (Sacks 1972b:334). A viewer’s maxim provides that if you see
“a category-bound activity being done, then, if one can see it being done by a
member of a category to which the activity is bound, then: See it that way” (Sacks
1972b:338).
A significant strand of MCA research focuses on identity (Antaki and
Widdicombe 1998; Fitzgerald and Housley 2015), and “the ways that per-
sons make who they are (or what they are doing) visible and recognizable to
others . . . as that kind of person or of doing that kind of action” (Wieder and
Pratt 1990:46), whether it is standing in line (cf. Garfinkel 2002:215– 16;
Garfinkel and Livingston 2003), being a member of some specialized com-
munity of practice (Kitzinger and Mandelbaum 2013), using questions to po-
sition an interview subject’s views as “marginal” or “extreme” (Clayman 2017),
manifesting orientations to heterosexuality (Kitzinger 2005), or (as in the Agnes
study), doing “being a woman.” Other studies work on the relationship between
actions and identity that are managed through deontic and epistemic claims that
are conveyed through action and turn design (Lindström and Weatherall 2015).
Some—perhaps a large majority—of the practices involved exist outside of con-
scious deployment, as in Raymond and Heritage’s (2006) study of the interac-
tional maintenance of the status of grandmother. Finally, this domain is part of
the stock in trade of studies of institutions, where the burden of demonstration
is considerably more straightforward (Boden and Zimmerman 1991; Drew and
Heritage 1992; Heritage and Clayman 2010).
22 The Ethnomethodology Program
A second strand of MCA research addresses how social actors deploy de-
scriptive categories as a part of the formation of specific social actions. As
Edwards (1998:15) notes, this was central to some of Sacks’s most evocative
early papers—for example, his analysis of how a group of teenagers used the
term “hot- rodder”— a category that they “owned” and administered— to
maintain a discursive space separate from adult control. An early study along
these lines was Drew’s (1978) examination of how place names (such as “Divis
Street”) were deployed to build accusations of police conduct in the Northern
Ireland “troubles.” Stokoe (2009) and Stokoe and Edwards (2009) have inves-
tigated couples counseling and related environments in which the categoriza-
tion of circumstances and identities is central. Kameo and Whalen (2015) show
how call-takers at a center for police and fire dispatch deploy a variety of MCDs
to describe those who are the subjects of emergency inquiries or requests: race,
gender, age, height, weight, and clothing type. These categories derive from the
forms that call-takers use and transform a caller’s original narrative not only
into an actionable document for police or fire personnel but also become part
of an official incident report.
In an influential paper, Watson (1997; see also Housley and Fitzgerald
2015) called for a convergence in the deployment of sequential and categorial
approaches to interactional data. This convergence has become progressively actu-
alized in the CA and MCA literature on gender and interaction (Speer and Stokoe
2011b; Stokoe 2012), as well as other categories (Kitzinger and Mandelbaum 2013;
Raymond and Heritage 2006; Rossi and Stivers 2021; Turowetz and Maynard
2015; Watson 1978). We illustrate this using a recent paper by Raymond (2019)
that observes the use of category accounts to address circumstances of perceived
incongruity, indexed by questioning or other signs of puzzlement:
Wkend_Dinner_08:30
1 Ann: So y’know we all met up at Betty Smith’s [apartment first,
2 Jen: [Right,
3 Jen: Uh huh,
4 (.)
5 Ann: An-which is so: disgusting,
6 Jen: Wh-Betty’s is?
7 Ann: W’l y’know she was the only gir:l out of four brothers.
8 Jen: Oh.=I: see::.
9 Ann: Yeah so anyway we started there, b’t then we went to . . .
After Ann describes Betty Smith’s apartment as ‘so: disgusting’ (line 5), Jenny
shows puzzlement (line 6), whereupon Ann alludes to category-bound activities
Ethnomethodology’s Legacies and Prospects 23
Discursive Psychology
Emerging from discursive approaches in the sociology of science (Latour and
Woolgar 1979; Mulkay and Gilbert 1984), proponents of discursive psychology
(DP) began from the observation that many of the basic concepts of social
psychology— perception, cognition, representation, memory, etc.— are also
deployed in ordinary interactions (Edwards 1997; Edwards and Potter 1992;
Potter and Wetherell 1987). Taking an “action-oriented” understanding of lan-
guage as its point of departure, scholars such as Antaki (1994), Billig (1987),
Edwards (1997), Edwards and Potter (1992), and Potter (1996) have questioned
the cognitivist presuppositions predominant in current social psychology.
Although Coulter (1999) has questioned how thorough or cogent its anti-cog-
nitivism is, at least from a kind of Wittgensteinian and ethnomethodological
point of view, DP, instead of engaging experimental manipulation of social situ-
ations,5 investigates how, and to what effect, cognitive concepts are used in eve-
ryday contexts. There are strong resonances here with a neo-Wittgensteinian
and anti-cognitivist treatment of mental predicates (Coulter 1983, 1989), as in
the analysis of conversational uses of “remembering” and its attributes (Edwards
and Middleton 1986; Middleton and Edwards 1990), and their manipulation in
official discourse (Edwards and Potter 1992; Locke and Edwards 2003; Lynch
and Bogen 1996). Similarly, although not in the DP tradition as such, Goodwin
(1987) has studied the use of “forgetfulness” as an interactive resource in the
context of ordinary conversation. DP has also been used in the analysis of ra-
cial categorization (Wetherell and Potter 1993), where there are also significant
convergences with more analytically oriented conversation research.
The most sustained investigations in the MCA tradition are those that address
gender and race. Both categories are what Sacks called “Pn[population]-ad-
equate,” as they are potentially omnirelevant in social life. MCA research into
these and other categories has insisted on their situated deployment, and contex-
tually specified significance.
With both Garfinkel’s famous “Agnes” study and the massively influential
“Doing Gender” statement of West and Zimmerman (1987) as important back-
ground, Speer and Stokoe’s (2011a) introduction to their book on Gender and
Conversation (2011b) takes issue with “essentialist” approaches to gender and
talk, which have unsuccessfully posited linguistic productions—classically, tag
questions (Lakoff 1975), but also interruptions, per the CA-related research
of West and Zimmerman (1983)—as being driven by the gender categories to
which participants belong. It also critiques (a) “constructionist” versions that
Ethnomethodology’s Legacies and Prospects 25
remain top down in the sense of suggesting how participants in interaction “do”
femininities and masculinities, and (b) feminist CA (Kitzinger 2000) for the pos-
sibility that prioritizing gender in the analysis of talk may “re-essentialize” the
identity, overlooking more basic “identity” practices related to person reference
and other mechanisms in talk.
Each of the chapters in the Speer and Stokoe (2011b) volume, although
sharing these critiques, have different starting points. Drawing on Schegloff ’s
(1991) notions about doing technical analysis of talk-in-interaction, and only
tracing the relevance of MCDs according to participants’ orientations and the
“procedural consequentiality” of categories,6 the book has four parts: (I) gender,
person reference, and self-categorization (as related to interactional goals and
contexts for their achievement, for example); (II) gender, repair, and recipient
design (the use of repair mechanisms to reformulate gender references involving
third parties); (III) gender and action formation (related to complimenting,
assessing, telling jokes, affiliating, and others); and (IV) gender and membership
categorization practices (especially in interactions among children as they play,
argue, insult one another, and so forth). More recent work relevant to gender, in-
teraction, and categorization includes Raymond’s (2019) previously noted anal-
ysis of “category accounts” and how, in explaining what a participant (through a
repair initiation) takes to be a troublesome utterance, speakers may resolve the
difficulty by using a normatively based gender formulation. Thereby, paradoxi-
cally, they reconstitute common-sense stereotypes in situations where reported
behavior is treated (in the conversation) as anomalous.
Whereas studies of gender in conversation analysis have proliferated, that is
less the case when it comes to race. Although race also may be “Pn-adequate”
in the sense that it could be applied to any member (Sacks 1972a:32–33), it may
not have the ubiquitous visibility nor potential consequentiality (for example, in
same-race interactions) as does gender. At the same time, it is clear that CA and
MCA studies involving race are presently emergent (Rawls and Duck 2020).
Whitehead, drawing from the literature on MCDs, has a series of studies re-
lated to race and racial categorization. One paper (Whitehead 2009) explores
participants’ use of racial referencing to describe or explain actions of people.
When speakers perform such an action, it raises the possibility that they will be
understood or seen to be doing this action because of their own race. Accordingly,
to avoid being categorized when they categorize others, speakers deploy several
conversational practices that show an orientation to race as a normative. envi-
ronment for social action. In another paper, Whitehead (2015) draws on the re-
search in CA concerned with preference structure to illuminate how the hearer
of a racial stereotype can show resistance by way of deploying silence and other
forms of delay that give a speaker the chance to back down. However, when the
speaker does not do so, the hearer may engage what are otherwise dispreferred
26 The Ethnomethodology Program
turn formats to confront the speaker. In a third paper, Whitehead (2018) pursues
the matter of racial common sense and stereotyping, critiquing a predominant
mode of analyzing stereotypes, which is cognitive. The paper shows how analysis,
rather than being about what people think, can examine what they do through
modes of interaction, whether it is to sanction or to align with a racialized trajec-
tory in the talk. There are still further papers, including one in which Whitehead
(2020) suggests the possibility of bringing an analytic lens to implicitness in the
invocation of racial categories in interaction.
The data for Whitehead’s studies derive from two sets. One is a racial sensi-
tivity training session or workshop involving participants from a “White Group”
and from a “People of Color Group.” The other data are recorded interactions
from call-in shows on three South African radio stations. Accordingly, the data
for Whitehead’s studies are drawn from specialized environments rather than
more everyday or “ordinary” contexts, but it is important to recognize that
it is exceedingly difficult to collect more “naturally occurring” interactions
in which racialized utterances are present. Nevertheless, it is possible to draw
from “opportunistic” or “institutional” third-party video data venues in which
the interactions feature racial conflict (Jones and Raymond 2012; Whitehead,
Bowman, and Raymond 2018), as a paper by Rawls, Duck, and Turowetz (2018)
demonstrates.
Across the domains of CA and MCA, there is a manifest relationship to the
“linguistic turn” in philosophy, when scholars began exploring language as a
mode of life, a way of being, or, to paraphrase the philosopher John Austin, a
realm in which people “do things with words.” As scholars interested in practices
of language use, analysts of conversation and of membership categories propose
that speech is neither an appendage to, nor an epiphenomenon of, human con-
duct. It is not simply a repository of meaning that can be tapped as a resource for
the investigation of sociology’s substantive problems. Language use and social
interaction are themselves the substance; they are the site where people produce
elementary forms of social organization that are irreducible to terms other than
those of intrinsic composition.
interactionism,” the term that Blumer (1969) coined to capture the tradition set
in motion by George Herbert Mead and Charles Cooley. By the 1960s, fieldwork
in this tradition had a strong presence in the sociological world, especially as
represented by the “Chicago School” (Abbott 1999; Becker 1999; Fine 1995),
which was self-consciously aligned against such figures as Robert Merton and
Paul Lazarsfeld at Columbia, and Talcott Parsons and Samuel Stouffer at Harvard
(Abbott 1999:9–10,78).
Accordingly, it would seem that those aspects of the Chicago School embodied
in the theoretical concerns of Blumer (1969), and in the real-worldly observa-
tional and interpretive traditions of the Everett Hughes–Howard Becker7 or
Lloyd Warner–Erving Goffman linkages (cf. Abbott 1999) would provide a com-
patible field of inquiry for ethnographic ethnomethodologists. Consider Pollner
and Emerson’s (2007) opening paragraph in a chapter on “Ethnomethodology
and Ethnography”:
The overlap of genealogies, concerns and prefixes might lead one to expect a
cordial relationship between ethnomethodology (EM) and ethnography (EG).
Both perspectives are informed by the interpretive tradition, concerned with
the lifeworld, respect the point of view of the social actor (hence “ethno-”), and
typically eschew quantitative and theoretical approaches. From a distance—the
heights of, say, macro-or historical sociology—the family resemblances must
seem striking. Despite the similarities, however, the relationship has not been
congenial. (2007:118)
. . . members’ accounts, of every sort, in all their logical modes, with all their
uses, and for every method for their assembly are constitutive features of the
settings they make observable. (1967g:8)
Ethnomethodology’s Legacies and Prospects 31
The excavation of sociological resources, including those utilized in the best eth-
nographic research of the time, as exemplified in the work of Erving Goffman
or other Chicago School ethnographers, requires a kind of gestalt switch on the
part of the investigator. To capture “members’ accounts”—such as their orien-
tation to bureaucratic rules or their recitations of a code of conduct—as a fea-
ture that is inside rather than somehow acting as a cultural or cognitive matter
outside of, but guiding human conduct, requires an analytic shift in which rules
or codes are embedded in a social scene rather than serving as its backdrop.
More current studies in an ethnographic vein but with an ethnomethodolog-
ical rather than Chicago School sensibility can be found in Liberman’s (2013)
investigations of crossing the street, following “sketched” maps, participating
in board games, managing intercultural conversations, coffee tasting, and others.
For other studies that combine ethnography and CA, see Maynard (1984) and
Maynard and Turowetz (2022).
In sum, the distinctive feature of ethnomethodological ethnography has been
its radical excavation—unearthing material, interactional practices that are oth-
erwise abstracted, made transcendental, and obscured through the launching of
theories, methods, and concepts into the rarefied atmosphere of sociological dis-
course. Even when the celestial bodies of rules and norms in the atmosphere of
sociological discourse (as collected in the amorphous concept of “culture,” for
example) are said to come from direct social experience, as rendered from obser-
vation and interview or other techniques of the interpretive paradigm and eth-
nography, excavation is needed to prioritize the realm of actual activity, rather
than activity generalized, conceptualized, operationalized, measured, corre-
lated with other abstractions, and the rest. Actual practices are the participant-
produced, immensely variegated, deeply detailed, real and actual contours of
socially organized actions-in-interaction. The attractiveness of such autochtho-
nous inquiry, originating Garfinkel’s work, has drawn practitioners to investi-
gate a number of social arenas with ethnomethodology’s tools and orientations,
whether ethnographically or by way of CA and MCD analyses. These arenas in-
clude legal environments, scientific investigations, and studies of work.
their everyday practices for articulating the official line in relation to a case
at hand. As Garfinkel (1967c:110) noted, “a person is 95 per cent juror before
he comes near the court.” This is because they cannot “know beforehand the
conditions under which they will elect any one of a set of alternative courses of
action” (Garfinkel 1967c:113). Instead, their decisions emerge in and through the
endemic way that decision-making is done in real time, as information emerges
and therefore as actors developmentally discover the “nature” of the situation in
which they find themselves. This is why, as noted earlier, jurors can be seen to de-
fine their decisions retrospectively. The beforehand means by which they achieve
some outcome are the “ethnomethods” of the situation.
In no small part, the jury study was an argument against game theory in eco-
nomics, including its preoccupation with decision-making under risk according
to expected utilities of possible outcomes and associated preferences. Once
Garfinkel excavated such decision-making from the realm of hypostasized cog-
nitive states, inferences, or, in slightly more current terms, “heuristics,” it opened
the door for a wide variety of studies regarding law and its operation in actual
action, rather than according to how behavior accords with “law on the books”
and how actors may comport themselves in relation to such law and the utilities
of conforming or not. Classic in this regard are Bittner’s studies of peacekeeping
on skid row (Bittner 1967b) and of apprehending mentally ill individuals
(Bittner 1967a). In both studies, Bittner shows that “keeping peace” and making
apprehensions occur not in accord with any strict interpretation of law—in-
deed, there is great reluctance to rely on legal stipulations. Rather, police make
judgments about when to use the law in conjunction with other practices that
keep locales peaceful, organized, and orderly. Officers of the law seek detailed
knowledge about people and areas under their jurisdiction that allows them
to assess risk for the area, rather than culpability as such. So, the task involves
common sense, is practical, and situated. As Bittner (1967a:291; cf. Meehan
2018, our emphasis) observes, “. . . it is possible that an officer who merely com-
plies with the law may nevertheless be found to be an incompetent practitioner
of his craft.”
A wide variety of studies embracing legal, law enforcement, and forensic
contexts flowed from these early investigations. Concerned with the enforce-
ment of a “Civil Sidewalk Ordinance” in “Garden City,” Chapter 6 by Raymond
et al. in this volume is directly in this line of research. An extensive number of
journal publications include further studies of policing (Meehan 1986, 1987),
courtroom processes (Drew 1992; Komter 1994; Liberman 1981; Seuren 2019),
congressional hearings (Lynch and Bogen 1996; Molotch and Boden 1985), 911
emergency dispatch systems (Bittner 1967b), the jury room (Manzo 1995, 1996;
Maynard and Manzo 1993; Pomerantz and Sanders 2013), and consultations and
Ethnomethodology’s Legacies and Prospects 33
Overall, the Lynch et al. study of DNA fingerprinting, as it traces how controver-
sies over DNA profiling have come to a kind of closure regarding its validity in
both law and science, forms a bridge between ethnomethodological studies of legal
environments and those related to laboratory science and workplaces. Indeed,
Lynch (Chapter 4 this volume) situates ethnomethodological science studies in
Garfinkel’s larger “studies of work” program, describing the compatibility of ethno-
methodological science and technology investigations with the “strong program”
emerging from the Science Studies Unit at the University of Edinburgh in the
1970s, which proposed the relevance of sociological studies taking on the actual
content of the natural sciences and not just constructs such as norms, incentives,
and networking relationships surrounding laboratory and related investigations.
Also compatible with the strong program were ethnographies of scientific work
(cf. Knorr-Cetina 1983; Latour and Woolgar 1979; Traweek 1988). However, these
latter works were more along the lines of social constructionist approaches in sci-
ence studies, as analytically they also incorporated social and political structures
beyond the lab itself as driving forces for science (cf. Button and Sharrock 1993;
Lynch 1993:Chapters 2–3; Lynch, Chapter 4 in this volume).
Ethnomethodological studies of science had a different target: “the effort
to observe, describe, and explain ‘actual’ scientific practice in situ . . .” (Lynch
1993:113). Garfinkel’s harnessing of the documentary method of interpretation
and the critique regarding the essential incompleteness of language, rules, in-
struction manuals, and other human artifacts formed the background for the
study of interpretive elaboration in concrete contexts. The recognition of this in-
completeness and need for understanding detailed forms of competence may go
back to Garfinkel’s work with the US Air Force in the 1940s (Garfinkel [1962]
2019; Rawls and Lynch 2019; see later discussion in this chapter). However,
Garfinkel eventually drew on Husserl’s (1970) discussion of the mathematiza-
tion of the natural world initiated by Galileo. As Lynch notes, Husserl viewed
Galileo’s findings:
Rather than seeing the specificities of the lived world as in need of analytic
reworking—into generalizations, abstractions, formalizations and the like—
that then order and explain the concreteness, ethnomethodological studies
take as their topic just how, specifically, the work of ordering (including but not
limited to its technologies of analysis) gets done. (2011:23)
Remarkably, at the Xerox Palo Alto Research Center (Xerox PARC, now known
only as PARC), Suchman in 1979, with colleagues such as Jeanette Blomberg
(1987) and Julian Orr (1996), pioneered such studies within a group that has
had additions and departures (including Suchman’s) over the years, but which
remains intact with different personnel today. Orr (2006:1807), in particular,
cites his indebtedness to Bittner’s (1965) “seminal piece” on organizations, and
developed the notion of “improvisation” among technicians, customers, and
machines. Improvisation, paradoxically, makes possible the implementation of
otherwise choreographed action sequences in teleservice centers, such as those
concerned with providing aid to users who are experiencing on-site difficulties
with a company’s machines—e.g., printers and copiers (Whalen and Vinkhuyzen
2000; Whalen, Whalen, and Henderson 2002).
Themes in workplace studies, which include attention to a variety of computer-
based systems, have ramified into computer- supported cooperative work
(CSCW), human computer interaction (HCI), and other studies of technology
and how it is embedded in work settings and in the practical actions of users and
consumers alike (Button 1993). Studies of work include Button and Sharrock’s
(1996, 1998) investigations of software engineering, design options in the print
industry (Button and Sharrock 1997), and human-computer interaction (Button
and Sharrock 2009). Whalen et al. (2004:208) innovatively analyze what they call
“workscapes”—how interaction in “the work of the world . . . entails engagement
with the material features of settings; with technologies, artifacts, the physical
configuration of buildings or other social spaces, and the like.” A potentially al-
lied subfield is that concerned with “distributed cognition,” and the ways in which
“thinking” is not an individual activity so much as it involves interrelationships
38 The Ethnomethodology Program
Building on Garfinkel’s basic inquiry into the assembly of social scientific data
are other recent studies of statistical and survey methodologies, and also qualita-
tive methodologies (Greiffenhagen, Mair, and Sharrock 2012). In Chapter 13 of
this volume, Mair, Sharrock, and Greiffenhagen examine the situated practices
related to “doing research with numbers,” and elsewhere have published a
“working bibliography” (Mair, Greiffenhagen, and Sharrock 2013) of social
studies of social science, while Maynard and Schaeffer (2000, 2002), drawing
heavily on the survey methodological literature, extant social studies of science
and technology (STS), ethnomethodology and CA, extended studies of (nat-
ural) science to elaborate social studies of social scientific knowledge (SSSK),
and “standardization in interaction.” Addressing a different vein of classic so-
cial science methodology is Livingston and Heritage’s Chapter 14 in this volume
on the phenomenon of praxeological reasoning, collaboratively undertaken in
situations of investigative uncertainty. In this case, the ties to Garfinkel’s (1967d)
jury study develop another facet of scientific reasoning, which is how the matter
of accountability for “findings” of any kind depend as much on the ways that
participants hold one another accountable in their public forms of reasoning as
they do on any purported relationship between “what actually happened” and
their determinations of fact.
The early work of Garfinkel (1967d) on research procedures in the social sci-
ences stimulated a long but different tradition concerned with social problems
and deviance. That early work was sifted through Cicourel’s (1964) Method
and Measurement and especially his investigation of juvenile justice (1968),
which shows how common-sense concepts regarding “wrongdoing,” typ-
ical perpetrators and their backgrounds, the meaning of legal statutes, and
other embedded facets of law enforcement work generate objective-seeming
distributions of crime. The theme of this book—its examination of the in
situ, socially organized ways of counting offenses, rather than just their dis-
tribution according to conventional categorizations—echoed the collabora-
tive Cicourel and Kitsuse (1963) approach that mapped the routes by which
educational professionals define, classify, and funnel high school students to
college vs. non-college careers. Rather than taking distributions at face value,
the approach is to decompose “student types” and rates into the common-
sense constructs by which personnel interpret and categorize incidents and
behaviors involving students along different lines and for subsequent educa-
tional careers.
Ethnomethodology’s Legacies and Prospects 43
This racial or ethnic dimension to Garfinkel’s work has yet to be fully appre-
ciated and may eventually occasion a better sociological understanding of
marginal identities of various kinds and their dynamics for lived experience.
There may be opportunities for exposing the ways in which these identities as
co-productions can inhibit the marginalized participants from achieving ordi-
nary goals. Or, at least, ethnomethodological studies can highlight how reaching
such achievement depends on managing not only the practices for, but also ex-
traordinary forms of anxiety attendant to, performing “membership” of various
kinds in light of their taken-for-granted features. As with his study of transsexu-
alism, wherein the appreciation of gender accomplishment has been exposed at
an unprecedented level of embodied, interactional detail, so too other identities
may come under the ethnomethodological gaze for their aspects as fraught and
contingent achievements.
to undermine the prevailing sociological view that rules, norms, or values could
provide a determinate basis for social organization, let alone for the scientific
predictability of social action. For all of them involve usage in context and, with
it, practical and overwhelmingly tacit interpretation. The import of this was ex-
traordinarily wide-ranging. Everything requires contextualization for its import
to be understood—from single words, sentences, conversations, and documents
such as prescriptions, instruction and repair manuals, and rulebooks, to norms,
laws, and values.
The move was repeated in Garfinkel’s equally expanded use of the term “index-
ical” and its corollary “reflexivity” to register the context-dependent nature of all
observation and understanding in the social world. And the notion was further
exploited in the idea of “Lebenswelt pairs,” comprising a “gapped” relationship be-
tween a set of instructions and the practical actions and know-how required to
implement them. (Ala Garfinkel (2002:Chapter 6), a simple exemplification of this
gap will be encountered by anyone who tries to build an item of furniture from the
instructions in an IKEA pack.) Very large bodies of ethnomethodological work in
the studies of deviance and policing, the operations of the law, sciences, workplace
studies, and human-computer interaction are founded on these basic ideas.
Third, while the contextual determination of intersubjective understanding
is a complex and multifaceted process, the sequential organization of action has
offered massive leverage, both in Garfinkel’s own endeavors and even more so in
CA. With this insight, the study of social action has been renewed and revivified. It
is now recognized that in the context of interaction, sequence is the fundamental
key both to the achievement of intersubjectivity and to the recognition by the
parties that it has been achieved (Heritage 1984:254–60; Maynard and Clayman
1991:399; Schegloff 1992). It would be no exaggeration to observe that the over-
whelming majority of CA research, now running to some 8,000+publications, is
built on the armature of sequence and sequential analysis. This orientation has
also begun to significantly influence psychology, linguistics, and, in particular, the
new subfield of interactional linguistics (Couper-Kuhlen and Selting 2018).
Fourth, the functioning of these bodies of practices is underwritten by
what Garfinkel terms “trust”: the mutual and presupposed commitment of the
members of society to the fact that meaning can and will be managed through
the contextual operations that are perforce performed on talk and action. In
his dissertation, Garfinkel argued that this commitment to sense-making is the
fundamental characteristic of the social order, and one which is much deeper
in its implications than the more familiar conflict question promulgated by
Hobbes. Garfinkel also showed how profoundly moral this commitment is, that
it is threaded through the entire set of processes through which actions and
circumstances are rendered as accountable, and that it is this accountability that
persons use and rely upon in every moment of their waking lives.
50 The Ethnomethodology Program
These are grand themes of immense scope and power. They penetrate every
crevice of social life, and they drive empirical contributions that are corre-
spondingly diverse: ethnographies of normal and normative environments,
social problems, deviance, disability, science and technology, workplace
investigations, the methodologies involved in more standard research—
coding, survey research, statistical interpretations—and the ways that gender,
race, and other categories of identity attain their objectivity. We cannot predict
what further investigations may still emerge, reveal, or how. Just like the vir-
tual explosion of gender studies, basic ethnomethodological research in other
domains may set in motion or underwrite, in the social sciences, large-scale,
even explosive, developments that are not yet in view.
Such claims are possible because that there simply is no time out from the
common-sense reasoning and practices thereof that ethnomethodology brings
to light and shows to be fundamental to enacting social actions in every domain
of human life. Indeed, that professional social science might be more interested
in ethnomethodology than it has been is something that Garfinkel felt and con-
veyed in different ways. In Chapter 5 of this volume, for example, he suggests
that from the standpoint of the profession, the organization of ordinary activi-
ties—their ethnomethods and practices—are seen as trivial phenomena. When
compared to the enormous significance that we accord to the compelling issues
in contemporary society, whether they include inequality, oppression, economic
conditions, family structure, bureaucracies, disease, and the like, it would seem
that the organization of everyday activities is of miniscule importance.
However, Garfinkel wanted to reverse that attitude—to reclaim for the disci-
pline the magnitude of ethnomethodological studies—and he does so by pro-
posing what he called a “figure of speech,” a kind of metaphor, where “the missing
what” of detailed, embodied social accomplishment dwarfs the typical concerns
most central to sociology (Garfinkel’s emphasis):
With respect to the circumference of the earth, Mt. Everest has the prominence,
importance and relevance of a pockmark on a billiard ball. The missing what
that ethnomethodologists have been at the work of discovering is available to
lay and professional versions of organization as the earth stands to the presence
of Mt. Everest. Orderings of ordinary activities are unimaginably extensive phe-
nomena; they are essentially other than we do imagine or could ever imagine
them to be, and they await discovery. (Garfinkel, Chapter 5 in this volume, p. 155)
everyday life, are massive in terms of their presence for the produced structures
that inhabit these spheres. Moreover, they affect what our enterprises generate
as “data”—ordinary and institutional information and outcomes. The immense
presence of orderly, common-sense actions also means that there is an infinite
variety of practices—“more than we can ever imagine, more than we ever would
have imagined” (Garfinkel, Chapter 5 in this volume, p. 157)—whose presence
for our everyday, every night, ordinary, occupational, workaday, identity-re-
lated, playful, and other social worlds have yet to be fully investigated and un-
derstood. There is a huge amount of “unfinished business” that Garfinkel has
bequeathed to the social and linguistic sciences, just as there are many legacies
already in place.
Acknowledgments
We would like to thank Steve Clayman, Rod Watson, and Jack Whalen for their
comments on an earlier draft of this chapter.
References
Abbott, Andrew. 1999. Department and Discipline: Chicago Sociology at One Hundred.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Anderson, Elijah. 2015. “The White Space.” Sociology of Race and Ethnicity 1(1):10–21.
doi: 10.1177/2332649214561306.
Antaki, Charles. 1994. Explaining and Arguing: The Social Organization of Accounts.
Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.
Antaki, Charles, and Sue Widdicombe, eds. 1998. Identities in Talk. Thousand Oaks,
CA: SAGE.
Atkinson, J. Maxwell. 1978. Discovering Suicide: Studies in the Social Organization of
Sudden Death. London: Macmillan Press.
Atkinson, J. Maxwell, and Paul Drew. 1979. Order in Court: The Organization of Verbal
Interaction in Judicial Settings. London: Macmillan.
Barnes, Rebecca. 2007. “Formulations and the Facilitation of Common Agreement in
Meetings Talk.” Text & Talk 27(3):273–96. doi: 10.1515/text.2007.011.
Becker, Howard S. 1963. Outsiders. New York: Free Press.
Becker, Howard S. 1999. “The Chicago School, So-Called.” Qualitative Sociology 22(1):3–
12. doi: 10.1023/a:1022107414846.
Berger, Peter L., and Thomas Luckmann. 1967. The Social Construction of Reality: A
Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. New York: Anchor Books.
Bergmann, Jörg R. 1998. “Introduction: Morality in Discourse.” Research on Language
and Social Interaction 31(3–4):279–94.
Billig, Michael. 1987. Arguing and Thinking: A Rhetorical Approach to Social Psychology.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bittner, Egon. 1965. “The Concept of Organization.” Social Research 32(3):239–55.
52 The Ethnomethodology Program
Dupret, Baudoin, Michael Lynch, and Tim Berard, eds. 2015. Law at Work: Studies in
Legal Ethnomethods. New York: Oxford University Press.
Durkheim, Émile. [1897] 1951. Suicide: A Study in Sociology. Glencoe, IL: Free Press.
Edwards, Derek. 1997. Discourse and Cognition. London: SAGE.
Edwards, Derek. 1998. “The Relevant Thing about Her: Social Identity Categories in Use.”
Pp. 15–33 in Identities in Talk, edited by C. Antaki and S. Widdicombe. Thousand
Oaks, CA: SAGE.
Edwards, Derek, and David Middleton. 1986. “Joint Remembering: Constructing an
Account of Shared Experience through Conversational Discourse.” Discourse Processes
9(4):423–59. doi: 10.1080/01638538609544651.
Edwards, Derek, and Jonathan Potter. 1992. Discursive Psychology. Thousand Oaks,
CA: SAGE.
Emerson, Robert M. 2015. Everyday Troubles: The Micro-Politics of Interpersonal Conflict.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Emirbayer, Mustafa, and Douglas W. Maynard. 2011. “Pragmatism and Ethnomethodology.”
Qualitative Sociology 34(1):221–61. doi: 10.1007/s11133-010-9183-8.
Emirbayer, Mustafa, and Ann Mische. 1998. “What Is Agency?” American Journal of
Sociology 103(4):962–1023. doi: 10.1086/231294.
Enfield, N. J., Tanya Stivers, Penelope Brown, Christina Englert, Katariina Harjunpää,
Makoto Hayashi, Trine Heinemann, Gertie Hoymann, Tiina Keisanen, Mirka
Rauniomaa, Chase Wesley Raymond, Federico Rossano, Kyung- Eun Yoon, Inge
Zwitserlood, and Stephen C. Levinson. 2019. “Polar Answers.” Journal of Linguistics
55(2):277–304. doi: 10/ghk6bn.
Evaldsson, Ann-Carita. 2014. “Doing Being Boys with ADHD: Category Memberships
and Differences in SEN Classroom Practices.” Emotional and Behavioural Difficulties
19(3):266–83. doi: 10.1080/13632752.2014.883783.
Fasulo, Alessandra, and Chiara M. Monzoni. 2009. “Assessing Mutable Objects: A
Multimodal Analysis.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 42(4):362–76.
doi: 10.1080/08351810903296481.
Fenstermaker, Sarah. 2016. “The Turn from ‘What’ to ‘How’: Garfinkel’s Reach Beyond
Description.” Symbolic Interaction 39(2):295–305. doi: 10.1002/symb.222.
Fine, Gary Alan. 1995. “The Development of a Postwar American Sociology.” Pp. 1–16 in
A Second Chicago School? The Development of a Postwar American Sociology, edited by
A. D. Abbott and J. R. Gusfield. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Fitzgerald, Richard, and William Housley. 2015. Advances in Membership Categorisation
Analysis. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.
Ford, Cecilia E. 2008. Women Speaking Up: Getting and Using Turns in Workplace Meetings.
New York: Palgrave.
Garcia, Angela Cora. 2012. “Medical Problems Where Talk Is the Problem: Current
Trends in Conversation Analytic Research on Aphasia, Autism Spectrum Disorder,
Intellectual Disability, and Alzheimer’s.” Sociology Compass 6(4):351–64. doi: 10.1111/
j.1751-9020.2011.00452.x.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1941. “Color Trouble.” Pp. 97–119 in The Best Short Stories, edited by
E. J. O’Brien. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1949. “Research Note on Inter-and Intraracial Homicides.” Social
Forces 27(4):369–81. doi: 10/ctczzb.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1952. “The Perception of the Other: A Study in Social Order.” PhD
thesis, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA.
Ethnomethodology’s Legacies and Prospects 55
Heritage, John, and Douglas W. Maynard. 2006. “Problems and Prospects in the Study
of Physician-Patient Interaction: 30 Years of Research.” Annual Review of Sociology
32(1):351–74. doi: 10.1146/annurev.soc.32.082905.093959.
Higginbotham, David Jeffery, and Christopher R. Engelke. 2013. “A Primer for Doing
Talk-in-Interaction Research in Augmentative and Alternative Communication.”
Augmentative and Alternative Communication 29:3– 19. doi: 10.3109/07434618.
2013.767556.
Hilbert, Richard A. 1981. “Toward an Improved Understanding of ‘Role.’” Theory and
Society 10:207–26. doi: 10.1007/bf00139892.
Hill, Richard J., and Kathleen S. Crittenden, eds. 1968. Proceedings of the Purdue
Symposium on Ethnomethodology. Lafayette, IN: Purdue Research Foundation.
Housley, William, and Richard Fitzgerald. 2015. “Introduction to Membership
Categorisation Analysis.” Pp. 1–22 in Advances in Membership Categorisation Analysis,
edited by R. Fitzgerald and W. Housley. London: SAGE.
Husserl, Edmund. 1970. The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental
Phenomenology: An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy. Evanston, IL:
Northwestern University Press.
Hutchins, Edwin. 1995. Cognition in the Wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Jayyusi, Lena. 1984. Categorization and the Moral Order. London: Routledge.
Jayyusi, Lena. 1991. “Cummunicative Praxis as a Moral Order.” Pp. 227– 51 in
Ethnomethodology and the Human Sciences, edited by G. Button. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Jones, Nikki. 2009. Between Good and Ghetto: African American Girls and Inner-City
Violence. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
Jones, Nikki. 2018. The Chosen Ones: Black Men and the Politics of Redemption. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
Jones, Nikki, and Geoffrey Raymond. 2012. “‘The Camera Rolls’: Using Third-Party
Video in Field Research.” The ANNALS of the American Academy of Political and Social
Science 642(1):109–23. doi: 10/f32pbh.
Kameo, Nahoko, and Jack Whalen. 2015. “Organizing Documents: Standard Forms,
Person Production and Organizational Action.” Qualitative Sociology 38(2):205–29.
doi: 10.1007/s11133-015-9302-7.
Kashimura, Shiro. 2015. “Hearing Clients’ Talk as Lawyers’ Work: The Case of Public Legal
Consultation Conference.” Pp. 87–113 in Law at Work: Studies in Legal Ethnomethods,
edited by M. L. Baudouin Dupret and T. Berard. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Katz, Jack. 1999. How Emotions Work. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Katz, Jack. 2015. “Foreword.” Pp. ix–xiii in Everyday Troubles: The Micro-Politics of
Interpersonal Conflict, edited by R. M. Emerson. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Kendrick, Kobin H., Penelope Brown, Mark Dingemanse, Simeon Floyd, Sonja Gipper,
Kaoru Hayano, Elliott Hoey, Gertie Hoymann, Elizabeth Manrique, Giovanni Rossi,
and Stephen C. Levinson. 2020. “Sequence Organization: A Universal Infrastructure for
Social Action.” Journal of Pragmatics 168:119–38. doi: 10.1016/j.pragma.2020.06.009.
Kessler, Suzanne J. 1998. Lessons from the Intersexed. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers
University Press.
Kessler, Suzanne, and Wendy McKenna. 1978. Gender: An Ethnomethodological Approach.
New York: Wiley.
Kitzinger, Celia. 2000. “Doing Feminist Conversation Analysis.” Feminism & Psychology
10(2):163–93. doi: 10/ch8g26.
58 The Ethnomethodology Program
Lynch, Michael. 1988. “The Externalized Retina: Selection and Mathematization in the
Visual Documentation of Objects in the Life Sciences.” Human Studies 11(2–3):201–34.
doi: 10/cps9k5.
Lynch, Michael. 1991. “Method: Measurement—Ordinary and Scientific Measurement as
Ethnomethodological Phenomena.” Pp. 77–108 in Ethnomethodology and the Human
Sciences, edited by G. Button. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Lynch, Michael. 1993. Scientific Practice and Ordinary Action: Ethnomethodology and
Social Studies of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lynch, Michael. 2007. “The Origins of Ethnomethodology.” Pp. 485–515 in Philosophy of
Anthropology and Sociology, edited by S. Turner and M. Risjord. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Lynch, Michael, and David Bogen. 1996. The Spectacle of History: Speech, Text, and
Memory at the Iran-Contra Hearings. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Lynch, Michael, Simon A. Cole, Ruth McNally, and Kathleen Jordan. 2008. Truth
Machine: The Contentious History of DNA Fingerprinting. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Lynch, Michael E. 1982. “Closure and Disclosure in Pre-Trial Argument.” Human Studies
5(1):285–318. doi: 10.1007/bf02127682.
Lynch, Michael E., Eric Livingston, and Harold Garfinkel. 1983. “Temporal Order in
Laboratory Work.” Pp. 205–38 in Science Observed: Perspectives on the Social Study of
Science, edited by K. Knorr-Cetina and M. Mulkay. London: Sage.
Lynch, Michael, and Steve Woolgar, eds. 1990. Representation in Scientific Practice.
Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
Macbeth, Douglas. 1992. “Classroom ‘Floors’: Material Organizations as a Course of
Affairs.” Qualitative Sociology 15(2):123–50. doi: 10.1007/bf00989491.
Mair, Michael, Alexandra Barlow, Susan E. Woods, Ciara Kierans, Beth Milton, and
Lorna Porcellato. 2006. “Lies, Damned Lies and Statistics? Reliability and Personal
Accounts of Smoking among Young People.” Social Science & Medicine 62(4):1009–21.
doi: 10.1016/j.socscimed.2005.07.002.
Mair, Michael, Christian Greiffenhagen, and W. W. Sharrock. 2013. “Social Studies of
Social Science: A Working Bibliography.” in NCRM Working Paper online https://epri
nts.ncrm.ac.uk/id/eprint/3219/.
Mannheim, K. 1952. “On the Interpretation of ‘Weltanschauung.’” Pp. 33– 83 in
Essays on the Sociology of Knowledge by Karl Mannheim, edited by P. Kecskemeti.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Manning, Peter K. 1970. “Talking and Becoming: A View of Organizational Socialization.”
Pp. 239–56 in Understanding Everyday Life: Toward the Reconstruction of Sociological
Knowledge, edited by J. D. Douglas. Chicago: Aldine.
Manzo, John. 1995. “‘You Wouldn’t Take a Seven-Year-Old and Ask Him All These
Questions’: Jurors’ Use of Practical Reasoning in Supporting Their Arguments.” Law
and Social Inquiry 19:601–26.
Manzo, John F. 1996. “Taking Turns and Taking Sides: Opening Scenes from Two Jury
Deliberations.” Social Psychology Quarterly 59(2):107–25. doi: 10.2307/2787046.
Maynard, Douglas W. 1982. “Aspects of Sequential Organization in Plea Bargaining
Discourse.” Human Studies 5(4):319–44. doi: 10.1007/BF02127683.
Maynard, Douglas W. 1984. Inside Plea Bargaining: The Language of Negotiation.
New York: Plenum.
Maynard, Douglas W. 1991. “Goffman, Garfinkel, and Games.” Sociological Theory
9(2):277–79. doi: 10.2307/202090.
60 The Ethnomethodology Program
Maynard, Douglas W. 2003. Bad News, Good News: Conversational Order in Everyday Talk
and Clinical Settings. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Maynard, Douglas W. 2012. “An Intellectual Remembrance of Harold Garfinkel: Imagining
the Unimaginable, and the Concept of the ‘Surveyable Society.’” Human Studies
35(2):209–21. doi: 10.1007/s10746-012-9226-0.
Maynard, Douglas W., and Steven E. Clayman. 2003. “Ethnomethodology and
Conversation Analysis.” Pp. 173–202 in The Handbook of Symbolic Interactionism, ed-
ited by L. T. Reynolds and N. J. Herman-Kinney. Walnut Creek, CA: Altamira Press.
Maynard, Douglas W., Hanneke Houtkoop-Steenstra, Nora Cate Schaeffer and Hans van
der Zouwen, eds. 2002. Standardization and Tacit Knowledge: Interaction and Practice
in the Survey Interview. New York: John Wiley.
Maynard, Douglas W., and John F. Manzo. 1993. “On the Sociology of Justice: Theoretical
Notes from an Actual Jury Deliberation.” Sociological Theory 11(2):171–93. doi: 10.2307/
202141.
Maynard, Douglas W., and Nora Cate Schaeffer. 2000. “Toward a Sociology of Social
Scientific Knowledge: Survey Research and Ethnomethodology’s Asymmetric
Alternates.” Social Studies of Science 30(3):323–70. doi: 10.1177/030631200030003001.
Maynard, Douglas W., and Nora Cate Schaeffer. 2002. “Standardization and Its
Discontents.” Pp. 3– 46 in Standardization and Tacit Knowledge: Interaction and
Practice in the Survey Interview, edited by D.W. Maynard, H. Houtkoop-Steenstra, N.
C. Schaeffer, and H. Zouwen. New York: Wiley Interscience.
Maynard, Douglas W., and David Schelly. 2017. “Tunnel Vision in a Murder
Case: Telephone Interaction between Police Detectives and the Prime Suspect.”
Discourse Studies 19(2):169–95. doi: 10.1177/1461445617691703.
Maynard, Douglas W., and Jason Turowetz. 2022. Autistic Intelligence: Interaction,
Individuality, and the Challenges of Diagnosis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Meehan, Albert J. 1986. “Record-Keeping Practices in the Policing of Juveniles.” Journal of
Contemporary Ethnography 15(1):70–102. doi: 10.1177/0098303986015001003.
Meehan, Albert J. 1987. “Assessing the ‘Police- Worthiness’ of Citizen’s Complaints
to the Police: Police Accountability and the Negotiation of ‘Facts.’” Pp. 116–40 in
The Interactional Order: New Directions in the Study of Social Order, edited by T. W.
Anderson, A. J. Meehan, and A. W. Rawls. New York: Irvington.
Meehan, Albert J. 2018. “Egon Bittner and the Language Practices of the Police.”
Ethnographic Studies 15:159–88. doi: 10/ggxnkw.
Mehan, Hugh, and Houston Wood. 1976. “De-Secting Ethnomethodology.” American
Sociologist 11:13–21.
Middleton, David, and Derek Edwards. 1990. Collective Remembering. Thousand Oaks,
CA: SAGE.
Mishler, Elliot G. 1986. Research Interviewing: Context and Narrative. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Molotch, Harvey L., and Deirdre Boden. 1985. “Talking Social Structure: Discourse,
Domination and the Watergate Hearings.” American Sociological Review 50(3):273–88.
doi: 10.2307/2095539.
Mondada, Lorenza. 2014. “Requesting Immediate Action in the Surgical Operating
Room.” Pp. 271–304 in Requests in Interaction, edited by E. Couper-Kuhlen and P.
Drew. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Ethnomethodology’s Legacies and Prospects 61
Mondada, Lorenza. 2016. “Challenges of Multimodality: Language and the Body in Social
Interaction.” Journal of Sociolinguistics 20(3):336–66. doi: 10/f87f6j.
Moore, Robert J., and Raphael Arar. 2019. Conversational UX Design: A Practitioner’s
Guide to the Natural Conversation Framework. New York: ACM Books.
Mori, Junko. 2003. “The Construction of Interculturality: A Study of Initial Encounters
between Japanese and American Students.” Research on Language and Social Interaction
36(2):143–84. doi: 10.1207/s15327973rlsi3602_3.
Mulkay, Michael, and G. Nigel Gilbert. 1982. “Accounting for Error.” Sociology 16:165–83.
doi: 10.1177/0038038582016002001.
Mulkay, Michael, and G. Nigel Gilbert. 1984. Opening Pandora’s Box: A Sociological
Analysis of Scientists’ Discourse. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Nishizaka, Aug. 1995. “The Interactive Constitution of Interculturality: How to Be a
Japanese with Words.” Human Studies 18(2–3):301–26. doi: 10.1007/bf01323214.
Nishizaka, Aug. 2011. “Touch without Vision: Referential Practice in a Non-Technological
Environment.” Journal of Pragmatics 43(2):504–20. doi: 10/dhcp9g.
Nishizaka, Aug. 2014. “Instructed Perception in Prenatal Ultrasound Examinations.”
Discourse Studies 16(2):217–46. doi: 10/f5wwdt.
Orr, Julian. 1996. Talking about Machines: An Ethnography of a Modern Job. Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press.
Orr, Julian E. 2006. “Ten Years of Talking about Machines.” Organization Studies
27(12):1805–20. doi: 10.1177/0170840606071933.
Palmer, Richard E. 1969. Hermeneutics. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
Parsons, Talcott. 1937. The Structure of Social Action: A Study in Social Theory with Special
Reference to a Group of Recent European Writers. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Parsons, Talcott. 1951. The Social System. New York: Free Press.
Parsons, Talcott. 1952. “The Superego and the Theory of Social Systems.” Psychiatry
15(1):15–25. doi: 10.1080/00332747.1952.11022854.
Parsons, Talcott. 1970. “On Building Social System Theory: A Personal History.” Daedalus
99(4):826–81.
Parsons, Talcott, and Edward Shils, eds. 1951. Toward a General Theory of Action.
Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
Pollner, Melvin. 1974a. “Mundane Reasoning.” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 4(1):35–54.
doi: 10.1177/004839317400400103.
Pollner, Melvin. 1974b. “Sociological and Common Sense Models of the Labelling
Process.” Pp. 27–40 in Ethnomethodology, edited by R. Turner. Harmondsworth,
England: Penguin.
Pollner, Melvin. 1975. “‘The Very Coinage of Your Brain’: The Anatomy of Reality
Disjunctures.” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 5(3):411–30. doi: 10/bm9xdq.
Pollner, Melvin, and Robert M. Emerson. 2007. “Ethnomethodology and Ethnography.”
Pp. 118–35 in Handbook of Ethnography, edited by P. Atkinson, S. Delamont, A. Coffey,
J. Lofland, and L. Lofland. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.
Pollner, Melvin, and Lynn McDonald- Wikler. 1985. “The Social Construction of
Unreality: A Case Study of a Family’s Attribution of Competence to a Severely Retarded
Child.” Family Process 24:241–54. doi: 10.1111/j.1545-5300.1985.00241.x.
Pomerantz, Anita. 1978. “Attributions of Responsibility: Blamings.” Sociology
12:115–21.
62 The Ethnomethodology Program
Pomerantz, Anita, and Robert E. Sanders. 2013. “Conflict in the Jury Room: Averting
Acrimony and Engendering It.” Journal of Language Aggression and Conflict
1(2):141–64. doi: 10.1075/jlac.1.2.01pom.
Potter, Jonathan. 1996. Representing Reality: Discourse, Rhetoric and Social Construction.
London: SAGE.
Potter, Jonathan, and Derek Edwards. 2003. “Rethinking Cognition: On Coulter on
Discourse and Mind.” Human Studies 26(2):165–81. doi: 10.1023/A:1024008104438.
Potter, Jonathan, and Margaret Wetherell. 1987. Discourse and Social Psychology: Beyond
Attitudes and Behaviour. London: SAGE.
Rawls, Anne Warfield. 2002. “Editor’s Introduction.” Pp. 1–64 in Ethnomethodology’s
Program: Working Out Durkheim’s Aphorism, edited by H. Garfinkel. Lanham,
MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Rawls, Anne Warfield. 2018. “The Wartime Narrative in US Sociology, 1940–1947:
Stigmatizing Qualitative Sociology in the Name of ‘Science.’” European Journal of Social
Theory 21(4):526–46. doi: 10.1177/1368431018754499.
Rawls, Anne W., and Waverly Duck. 2020. Tacit Racism. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Rawls, Anne W., Waverly Duck, and Jason Turowetz. 2018. “Problems Establishing
Identity/Residency in a City Neighborhood during a Black/White Police‐Citizen
Encounter: Reprising Du Bois’ Conception of Submission as ‘Submissive Civility.’” City
and Community 17(4):1015–50. doi: 10.1111/cico.12345.
Rawls, Anne Warfield, and Michael Lynch. 2019. “Harold Garfinkel’s History of Gulfport
Field 1942, Part II, The Aircraft Mechanics School: Mocking-up and Making-Do in the
Midst of Wartime Urgency.” Pp. i–xlviii in The History of Gulfport Field 1942, edited by
T. Thielmann. Media of Cooperation.
Rawls, Anne Warfield, and Jason Turowetz. 2019a. “‘Discovering Culture’ in
Interaction: Solving Problems in Cultural Sociology by Recovering the Interactional
Side of Parsons’ Conception of Culture.” American Journal of Cultural Sociology
9(293–320). doi: 10.1057/s41290-019-00079-6.
Rawls, Anne Warfield, and Jason Turowetz. 2019b. “Introduction to Parsons’ Primer.” Pp.
1–108 in Harold Garfinkel: Parsons’ Primer, Beiträge zur Praxeologie /Contributions to
Praxeology, edited by A. W. Rawls. Stuttgart: J. B. Metzler.
Rawls, John. 1955. “Two Concepts of Rules.” The Philosophical Review 64(1):3–32.
doi: 10.2307/2182230.
Raymond, Chase Wesley. 2019. “Category Accounts: Identity and Normativity in
Sequences of Action.” Language in Society 48(4):585–606. doi: 10/ggxpfh.
Raymond, Geoffrey, and John Heritage. 2006. “The Epistemics of Social Relations: Owning
Grandchildren.” Language in Society 35(5):677–705. doi: 10/b7nzx4.
Robillard, Albert B. 1999. Meaning of a Disability: The Lived Experience of Paralysis.
Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Rossi, Giovanni, and Tanya Stivers. 2021. “Category-Sensitive Actions in Interaction.”
Social Psychology Quarterly 84(1):49–74. doi: 10.1177.
Sacks, Harvey. 1972a. “An Initial Investigation of the Usability of Conversational Materials
for Doing Sociology.” Pp. 31–74 in Studies in Social Interaction, edited by D. N. Sudnow.
New York: Free Press.
Ethnomethodology’s Legacies and Prospects 63
Sacks, Harvey. 1972b. “On the Analyzability of Stories by Children.” Pp. 325–45 in
Directions in Sociolinguistics: The Ethnography of Communication, edited by J. J.
Gumperz and D. Hymes. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
Sacks, Harvey. 1984. “Notes on Methodology.” Pp. 2– 27 in Structures of Social
Action: Studies in Conversation Analysis, edited by J. M. Atkinson and J. Heritage.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sacks, Harvey. 1992a. Lectures on Conversation. Vol. 1, edited by G. Jefferson. Oxford;
Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.
Sacks, Harvey. 1992b. Lectures on Conversation. Vol. 2, edited by G. Jefferson. Oxford;
Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.
Sacks, Harvey, and Emanuel A. Schegloff. 1973. “Opening up Closings.” Semiotica
8(4):289–327. doi: 10.1515/semi.1973.8.4.289.
Sacks, Harvey, Emanuel A. Schegloff, and Gail Jefferson. 1974. “A Simplest Systematics
for the Organization of Turn-Taking for Conversation.” Language 50(4):696–735.
doi: 10.2307/412243.
Saloman, Gavriel, ed. 1996. Distributed Cognitions: Psychological and Educational
Considerations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Schaeffer, Nora Cate. 1991. “Conversation with a Purpose—or Conversation? Interaction
in the Standardized Survey.” Pp. 367–91 in Measurement Errors in Surveys, edited by P.
P. Biemer, R. M. Groves, L. E. Lyberg, N. A. Mathiowetz, and S. Sudman. New York: John
Wiley & Sons.
Schaeffer, Nora Cate, and Douglas W. Maynard. 1996. “From Paradigm to Prototype
and Back Again: Interactive Aspects of Cognitive Processing in Standardized Survey
Interviews.” Pp. 65–88 in Answering Questions: Methodology for Determining Cognitive
and Communicative Processes in Survey Research, edited by N. Schwarz and S. Sudman.
San Francisco: Jossey Bass.
Schaeffer, Nora Cate, and Douglas W. Maynard. 2009. “The Contemporary Standardized
Survey Interview.” Pp. 31-57 in Envisioning the Survey Interview of the Future, edited
by F. G. Conrad and M. F. Schober. New York: Wiley.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1991. “Reflections on Talk and Social Structure.” Pp. 44–70 in Talk
and Social Structure: Studies in Ethnomethodology and Conversation Analysis, edited by
D. Boden and D. H. Zimmerman. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1992. “Repair after Next Turn: The Last Structurally Provided Place
for the Defense of Intersubjectivity in Conversation.” American Journal of Sociology
95(5):1295–1345. doi: 10.1086/229903.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1996. “Confirming Allusions: Toward an Empirical Account of
Action.” American Journal of Sociology 102(1):161–216. doi: 10.1086/230911.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 2002. “Survey Interviews as Talk-in-Interaction.” Pp. 151–57 in
Standardization and Tacit Knowledge: Interaction and Practice in the Survey Interview,
edited by N. C. S. Douglas, W. Maynard Hanneke Houtkoop-Steenstra, and J. van der
Zouwen. New York: Wiley.
Schegloff, E. A. 2006. “Interaction: The Infrastructure for Social Institutions, the Natural
Ecological Niche for Language and the Arena in Which Culture Is Enacted.” Pp. 70–96
in The Roots of Human Sociality: Culture, Cognition and Interaction, edited by N. J.
Enfield and S. C. Levinson. New York: Berg.
64 The Ethnomethodology Program
Kyung-Eun Yoon, and Stephen C. Levinson. 2009. “Universals and Cultural Variation
in Turn-Taking in Conversation.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences
106(26):10587–92. doi: 10/cdfkps.
Stivers, Tanya, Lorenza Mondada, and Jakob Steensig, eds. 2011. The Morality of
Knowledge in Conversation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Stokoe, Elizabeth. 2009. “Doing Actions with Identity Categories: Complaints and
Denials in Neighbor Disputes.” Text & Talk 29(1):75–97. doi: 10.1515/text.2009.004.
Stokoe, Elizabeth. 2012. “Moving Forward with Membership Categorization
Analysis: Methods for Systematic Analysis.” Discourse Studies 14(3):277–303.
doi: 10.1177/1461445612441534.
Stokoe, Elizabeth, and Derek Edwards. 2009. “Accomplishing Social Action with Identity
Categories: Mediating and Policing Neighbour Disputes.” Pp. 95–115 in Theorizing
Identities and Social Action, edited by M. Wetherell. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Streeck, Jürgen, Charles Goodwin, and Curtis LeBaron, eds. 2011. Embodied
Interaction: Language and Body in the Material World. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Suchman, Lucy A. 1987. Plans and Situated Actions: The Problem of Human Machine
Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Suchman, Lucy. 2007. Human–Machine Reconfigurations: Plans and Situated Actions.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Suchman, Lucy. 2011. “Work Practice and Technology: A Retrospective.” Pp. 21–33 in
Making Work Visible: Ethnographically Grounded Case Studies of Work Practice, edited
by M. H. Szymanski and J. Whalen. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Suchman, Lucy, and Brigitte Jordan. 1990. “Interactional Troubles in Face- to-
Face
Survey Interviews.” Journal of the American Statistical Association 85(409):232–41.
doi: 10.1080/01621459.1990.10475331.
Sudnow, David. 1965. “Normal Crimes: Sociological Features of a Penal Code in a Public
Defender’s Office.” Social Problems 12(3):255–76. doi: 10.2307/798932.
Sudnow, David. 1978. Ways of the Hand: The Organization of Improvised Conduct.
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Svennevig, Jan. 2008. “Exploring Leadership Conversations.” Management Communication
Quarterly 21(4):529–36. doi: 10/drqv99.
Svennevig, Jan. 2012. “Interaction in Workplace Meetings.” Discourse Studies 14(1):3–10.
doi: 10/ggxn54.
Sykes, Gresham M., and David Matza. 1957. “Techniques of Neutralization: A Theory of
Delinquency.” American Sociological Review 22(6):664–70. doi: 10.2307/2089195.
Szymanski, Margaret H., and Jack Whalen, eds. 2011. Making Work Visible: Ethnographically
Grounded Case Studies of Work Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Travers, Max, and John F. Manzo, eds. 1997. Law in Action: Ethnomethodological and
Conversation Analytic Approaches to Law. Brookfield, VT: Ashgate.
Traweek, Sharon. 1988. Beamtimes and Lifetimes: The World of High Energy Physics.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Turowetz, Jason, and Douglas W. Maynard. 2010. “Morality in the Social Interactional
and Discursive World of Everyday Life.” Pp. 503–26 in Handbook of the Sociology of
Morality, edited by S. Hitlin and S. Vaisey. New York: Springer.
Turowetz, Jason, and Douglas Maynard. 2015. “Category Attribution as a Device for
Diagnosis: Fitting Children to the Autism Spectrum.” Sociology of Health & Illness
38:357–83. doi: 10.1111/1467-9566.12382.
66 The Ethnomethodology Program
Whalen, Marilyn R., and Jack Whalen. 2004. “Studying Workscapes as a Natural
Observational Discipline.” Pp. 208– 29 in Discourse and Technology: Multimodal
Discourse Analysis, Georgetown University Round Table on Languages and Linguistics,
edited by P. LeVine and R. Scoloon. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
Whitehead, Kevin A. 2009. “‘Categorizing the Categorizer’: The Management of Racial
Common Sense in Interaction.” Social Psychology Quarterly 72(4):325–42. doi: 10.1177/
019027250907200406.
Whitehead, Kevin A. 2015. “Everyday Antiracism in Action: Preference Organization
in Responses to Racism.” Journal of Language and Social Psychology 34(4):374–89.
doi: 10.1177/0261927x15586433.
Whitehead, Kevin A. 2018. “Managing the Moral Accountability of Stereotyping.” Journal
of Language and Social Psychology 37(3):288–309. doi: 10.1177/0261927X17723679.
Whitehead, Kevin A. 2020. “The Problem of Context in the Analysis of Social
Action: The Case of Implicit Whiteness in Post-Apartheid South Africa:” Social
Psychology Quarterly 83(3):294–313. doi: 10/ghj8bw.
Whitehead, Kevin A., Brett Bowman, and Geoffrey Raymond. 2018. “‘Risk Factors’
in Action: The Situated Constitution of ‘Risk’ in Violent Interactions.” Psychology of
Violence 8(3):329–38. doi: 10.1037/vio0000182.
Wieder, D. Lawrence. 1974. Language and Social Reality: The Case of Telling the Convict
Code. The Hague: Mouton.
Wieder, D. Lawrence, and Steven Pratt. 1990. “On Being a Recognizable Indian among
Indians.” Pp. 45–64 in Cultural Communication and Intercultural Contact, edited by D.
Carbaugh. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Wieder, D. Lawrence, Don H. Zimmerman, and Geoffrey Raymond. 2010. “UCLA: Then
and Now.” Pp. 127–58 in The Social History of Language and Social Interaction Research,
edited by W. Leeds-Hurwitz. Cresskill, NJ: Humana Press.
Wilkinson, Ray, John Rae, and Gitte Rasmussen, eds. 2020. Atypical Interaction: Impacts
of Communicative Impairments within Everyday Talk. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Wilson, Thomas P. 1970. “Conceptions of Interaction and Forms of Sociological
Explanation.” American Sociological Review 35(4):697–710. doi: 10.2307/2093945.
Woolgar, Steve, and Dorothy Pawluch. 1985. “Ontological Gerrymandering: The
Anatomy of Social Problems Explanations.” Social Problems 32(1):214–27.
Zimmerman, Don H. 1970. “The Practicalities of Rule Use.” Pp. 221–38 in Understanding
Everyday Life, edited by J. Douglas. Chicago: Aldine.
Zimmerman, Don H. 1976. “A Reply to Professor Coser.” American Sociologist 11:4–13.
Zimmerman, Don H. 1992. “The Interactional Organization of Calls for Emergency.” Pp.
418–69 in Talk at Work: Interaction in Institutional Settings, edited by P. Drew and J.
Heritage. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zimmerman, Don H., and Melvin Pollner. 1970. “The Everyday World as a Phenomenon.”
Pp. 80–104 in Understanding Everyday Life: Toward the Reconstruction of Sociological
Knowledge, edited by J. D. Douglas. Chicago: Aldine.
Zimmerman, Don H., and D. Lawrence Wieder. 1970. “Ethnomethodology and the Problem
of Order: Comment on Denzin.” Pp. 285–95 in Understanding Everyday Life: Towards a
Reconstruction of Sociological Knowledge, edited by J. D. Douglas. Chicago: Aldine.
Znaniecki, Florian. 1936. Social Actions. Farrar & Rinehart.
PART I
ANT E C E DE N T S A N D T H E ORY
2
A Comparison of Decisions Made on Four
“Pre-Theoretical” Problems by Talcott
Parsons and Alfred Schütz
Harold Garfinkel
Describing another man’s “theory of objects” is the same as describing the other
man acting as an epistemologist. I conceive the epistemologist as the man who,
once having acknowledged the temporality of sensory evidences, has gone on
to ask how he is to account for the fact of reliable knowledge in the face of the
fact that the world is not always what it appears to be. Parsons and Schütz, as
epistemologists, frame the question differently. In the Kantian tradition, Parsons
asks: How can we believe our eyes? Schütz, in the Husserlian tradition, asks in-
stead: How do we believe our eyes? The difference in accent is a considerable one.
The Kantian question looks for the criteria of the validity of knowledge to primal,
invariant categories and thereby effects the notion of Being. The Husserlian
question proposes knowledge itself as the “yardstick for Being” by making of this
72 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
notion, Being, merely a name that designates “an infinite series of operations to
be effectuated” by an experiencer.2
Whether he likes it or not, the investigator who seeks a theory of human con-
duct will have to make use of such terms as “real object” and “knowledge of the
objective world.” The sociologist not only is without a hiding place in the matter
but his task is compounded in its nastiness since as a routine part of his theo-
rizing he must attempt to make theories about other persons’ theories, a task that
involves him in almost every statement with the question of the meaning of the
claim to objective knowledge. The decision therefore is not one that he does in
fact pass off as the proper concern of philosophers even though he may claim to
be doing otherwise.
The nature of the decision that Parsons employs to allow him this claim, and
the one that is the most prevalent in the social sciences today is known as the
“correspondence theory”3 of reality. After describing it, I shall compare it with
Schütz’s decision which might be called the “congruence theory”4 of reality.
A person is said to entertain a correspondence theory of reality if it can be
shown that the person’s theorizing about the world employs the view that there
is a difference between the perceived object of the “outer world” and the concrete
object (exemplified in the metaphorical admonition that the cake of the universe
may be cut in diverse ways, or that the objects of the outer world are indubitably
out there but they may be variously invested with meaning). The concreteness
of the object in this view is a property of the object; such concreteness being in-
dependent of the various modes of attending of an experiencer. That an object
is a real object means in this view that the possibility of apprehending it is not
dependent upon the many possible ways in which it may be apprehended. It is in
this sense “actual.” This view marks off what it refers to as the fullness of the con-
crete object from the selective, schematic-like emphasis that it receives through
a conceptual representation. If the user of this theory places no limit upon the
perceiver’s conceptual inventiveness, the statement follows that one can never
exhaust the number of factual statements that can be made about the object.
The correspondence theory holds further that the function of any schema
of categories is to render some sort of approximation of what is actually out
there. The view is that through successive states of improvement, the logico-
empirical methods, based as they are on universal and unchanging primary
categories of apprehension, gives to the properly qualified observer a view of
the world of real objects that is independent of the historical conditions of the
observer’s circumstances as far as the accuracy of reproduction of actual things
is concerned.
An analytical model is then judged not only with reference to its utility within
the purposes of the observer, but also with reference to the extent to which it
renders an accurate reproduction of the reality that is out there. However, it
FOUR PRE-THEORETICAL DECISIONS 73
should be noted that this test of accuracy does not consist of a comparison of
what the observer says is out there with what is really out there as it is determined
by criteria independent of those employed by the observer (a position that would
make the tester akin to an interpreter of God’s secret intent) but rather, accuracy
is an automatic result of acting with proper regard for the canons of logico-em-
pirical inquiry.
That the objects that are reproduced correspond in their logical character to
the logical design of the real world is taken as a miracle of a sort, and like all
miracles is unproblematical with regard to how it is possible. Hence, the lack of
concern with the nonetheless legitimate question that arises within this view as
to whether the world could go contrary to the laws of logic and if so under what
conditions? The answer, at the limits of the conversation, goes to the effect that
it could but so far it has not, the “reason” being that the basic rules, based as they
are on the primary categories, are not subject for their validity to the fluctuations
of circumstance. A statement that is true for one place and time is universally
true if it is to begin with the product of the proper procedures.
The correspondence theory makes a separation between the real world and
the subjective interpretation of the real world. The separation is such that there
are on the one hand the concrete objects in all their fullness and on the other
hand the conceptual representations of these objects. Such representations in
abstracting as they do certain features from the concrete object present the sci-
entist with a faded reproduction. The objects that an actor treats, whether he be
layman or scientist, are those concrete objects though he treats them in terms of
their features that are of interest to him. The things about them that interest him
and their reality as objects have nothing to do with each other, nor does the fact
that he has an interest in them necessarily guarantee the objective character of
the objects.
The leading premise of the “congruence” theory of reality is that the perceived
object of the “outer world” is the concrete object, and that the two terms, “per-
ceived object” and “concrete object,” are synonymous and interchangeable terms.
Rather than there being a world of concrete objects which a theory cuts this
way and that, the view holds that the cake is constituted in the very act of cut-
ting. No cutting, no cake, there being no reality out there that is approximated
since the world in this view is just as it appears. To use a phrase common to the
conversations of phenomenologists, “There is nothing behind it.” In this view,
the way in which something is of interest to a witness is all of the way in which
that thing is real. Rather than the actuality of the object being defined by the fact
of sensory evidences, actuality means only “not supposedly.” Nor, in this view,
does concreteness depend upon the variety of sensory presentations. The view
holds by contrast with the correspondence theory that sensory evidences are the
conditions but not the contents of perceptions, while only insofar as there is a
74 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
standard found in a non-perceptual order that remains invariant under the var-
ious sensory aspects is concreteness possible. The concreteness of the object in
this view is found in the object constituted as a unity of meanings and only as a
unity of meanings. Only insofar as sensory signals are experienced as signifying
something other than themselves do they function as specifications of an object.
An actual object is any unified set of experiences regardless of whether they be
ideally or sensorily founded. The fullness of the concrete object is not marked
off in this view from the schematic emphasis of a conceptual representation of
the object. Rather the object is conceived as never appearing except through
its schema. The schema of specifications is precisely the object itself. Hence, the
statement under the correspondence theory that a conceptual scheme can never
exhaust the number of factual statements that can be made about the concrete
object reads according to the congruence theory that only in God’s eye are all
possible specifications of an object simultaneously relevant, and that where this
is the case the all-seeing God for knowing all knows nothing.
Compared again to the view that a function of any conceptual scheme is to
render some sort of approximation of what is really out there, the congruence
theory holds that however the experiencer experiences something out there, is
out there in the way he experiences it. For example, the doubt that he experiences
about what he heard is along with the other specifications of what he heard a
specification of what he heard as something doubted. As an object, the thing
heard stands before him complete with its doubted character.
Whereas in the correspondence theory one may ask the question of what is
the objective world and what is objective knowledge, one can only ask under the
premises of the congruence theory, what are the varieties of objective worlds and
what are the varieties of objective knowledge. Here the talk is of a pluralism of
worlds; of “multiple realities.” Within this view there are many objective worlds;
as many objective worlds as there are variations in the attitudes that constitute
them. In fact, in this view, the only worlds are objective worlds. The alternative
to a world that is not objective, is a world that is meaningless, that is, experi-
enced as the “mere actuality of sensory stimuli.”5 In the congruence theory the
term “subjective” means the inability of an experiencer to actualize an object, i.e.,
to intend a meaning. A world experienced subjectively is experienced without
sense; it is experienced as William James’s “bloomin’, buzzing confusion.” In a
word then, the congruence theory puts both actor and observer into a setting as
the organizers of that setting and keeps them there.
But the ways in which these objects are constituted, the rules that govern the
tests that the experiencer uses of whether he has seen correctly, the tests that
he considers legitimate ones for the accuracy of his judgments, the conditions
under which he can experience a discrepancy between expectations and events,
the consequences of such surprises, the socially legitimate methods for resolving
FOUR PRE-THEORETICAL DECISIONS 75
such discrepancies, the rules that govern his judgmental behavior, the devices by
which he establishes and maintains the relevance of events for each other—all
these show different characteristics as one compares worlds and the modes of
attending them that are particular to each of these worlds. Hence they show not
only between themselves but between them and the world of the sociological
attitude different effects for the constitution of objects and objective knowledge.
The “congruence” view holds that it is a consequence of acting according to the
rules of logico-empirical method that statements cannot be tested by consulting
the meanings of empirical constructs but must be tested by subjecting them to
a course of experience with a Nature that the user conceives of as blind to the
meanings of his statements. A theory constructed within such a view is regarded
as organizing the possibilities of the observer’s experience to present him with
one out of a boundless class of possible objective worlds. Hence determinism
is not an ontological characteristic of a set of actual events but is a property of
the theory that presents a set of events as relevant to each other. In the corre-
spondence theory an empirical law is a reflection of nature’s uniformities. In
the congruence theory an empirical law is a statement of the uniformities of the
observer’s experiences. In the correspondence theory, a theory is conceived of as
asymptotic to the correspondence theory’s concrete world. As Norbert Wiener
puts it, the best model of a cat is the cat itself. To say of such a theory that it
is a first order approximation means that it is a preliminary fitting to a system
of actual events. In the congruence theory, to say that a theory is a first order
approximation means that a set of events has been fitted to an initial formula-
tion of their relatedness. The correspondence view conceives the “fitting” to be a
matching operation between a theoretical and an actual system. The congruence
view conceives the “fitting” to be a constitutive operation in which the objective
character of events and the significations that lend to experiences their character
as actual events is given to an observer through the operations of his theory.
According to the congruence theory, a theory serves the function of orga-
nizing the possibilities of experience to present the experiencer with one out of
many possible objective worlds. Where the action is guided by rules of logico-
empirical method, the objective world is peculiar in that it stands only as long as
the experiences that it hypothesizes can be repeatedly confirmed by any person
regardless of social affiliation who does what the statements say he should do.
Such a world is certainly at variance with the world of objectivities of everyday
life. According to the congruence view, the business of “sciencing” a problem
is not seen as it is in the correspondence view as a procedure by which reality
is successively approximated. Rather, it is seen as a procedure of successively
transforming, or better successively reconstituting a world, any world, in accord-
ance with the particular rules of the scientific attitude and the procedure of the
scientific method.
76 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
To understand Parsons’s decision with regard to the logical status and uses of
empirical ideal types it is helpful to recall that within the correspondence theory
a difference is predicated between the perception of the object and the concrete
object. The provision for the separation between subject and object (with the
relationship between them being represented by the subject’s object oriented
actions) provides a single function that empirical constructs can serve in the
“economy” of activity. For the actor, such empirical constructions serve only a
mapping function and in this sense the actor’s empirical categorizations are rele-
vant to the actor’s purposes as well as his scientifically assessed probable success
in accomplishing these purposes. Affective and valuative colorings reflect non-
empirical aspects of these constructs. The use of rationality as a methodological
principle in evaluating the reality oriented notions of the actor is clearly implied.
The congruence theory by contrast provides for the empirical character of the
construct only by the test that the actor attaches specifications of a standard time
and place to the possibilities of experience that the construct orders. That the
construct may embody affective coloring is taken as a possible characteristic par-
ticularly for the constructs of the attitudes of daily life where hopes and fears
are inextricable parts of the colorings of the actor’s situation. Hence the witches
that materialize in graveyards every midnight on every October 30 are empirical
constructs of precisely the same logical order as the construction “my desk that
will be in the corner of my office when I go there later this afternoon.” There may
be a difference in the way in which the frame of restricted possibilities that each
proposes is tested but this difference in procedures does not impugn the empir-
ical character of the construction itself. The congruence theory thereby makes
investigatively problematical what the correspondence theory settles by assump-
tion; namely, the properties of rationality in the social world. Further, evaluating
the reality oriented notions of the actor requires, if one adheres to the rules of
the congruence theory, that one assess these actions relative to the peculiarities
of the structure of relevances as they make up the meaningful structure of a so-
cial world.
Notice has already been taken that a separation is intended and maintained
in the correspondence theory between the empirical construction and the ob-
ject it designates. In its abstracting function, the empirical construct stands to
the object as that abstracted set of specifications of the concrete object relevant
to the actor’s interests. The empirical construct in this important sense of its log-
ical status is not constitutive of the object. Rather, the correspondence theory
holds that the empirical construct tells only what there is about the concrete ob-
ject as it stands independently of the construction that is of interest. Insofar as
the attendant theory is worked out in formal fashion those constructs provide a
FOUR PRE-THEORETICAL DECISIONS 77
something actual to which the actor attaches meanings. It is actual through the
meanings that together are constitutive of the object. The object is a meaningful
one in the moment of recognition, that is, in the moment of the actor’s treatment
of a set of specifications as related to each other. Hence, subject and object are si-
multaneously constituted as a unified field. The actor is not conceived by Schütz
to be related to the object by his actions. Rather, the system of specifications as an
object and the system of objects stand in relationships to each other. The actor’s
actions become for the observer a set of operators whereby these relationships
are maintained and altered.
There is another point of contrast. In Parsons’s usage, the empirical construct
stands to the object as a set of specifications abstracted from the concrete object
in accordance with the actor’s interests. Schütz’s usage provides that the object
is itself constituted according to the actor’s interests, with nothing left over. The
object in fact is real in precisely the sense of the way it stands as a schema of in-
terest relevant specifications. There is therefore a problem involved for Schütz in
describing the object that is not a problem for Parsons. This problem is that of
describing the structural organization of the object, i.e., its organizational prop-
erties as a unity of meanings. This concern is the heart of Schütz’s insistence on
the importance and the lack of sufficient work on the problem of relevance while
for Parsons this problem has been decided through the pattern variable scheme.
A classification of objects for Schütz would have to wait upon a phenomenolog-
ical description of the formal properties of these relevance structures. And before
even this can be successfully undertaken, much more needs to be known than
is currently available about the ways in which “consistency” both appears and
is achieved within the various modes of attending to various worlds. Parsons’s
classification of objects short circuits this area of problems by starting with the
very kind of classification that Schütz would arrive at as an end product of his
researches.
The empirical construct for Schütz does not have the sense of a faded repro-
duction of the actual object. Rather, any schema of specifications is constitutive
of an object that is distinct from others and is experientially irreducible. Schütz
would ask the question of the conditions of the actor’s make-up under which the
object shows, as an organized set of specifications, the property of a closed set
or an open set or a set that permits the relevance of all possible specifications.
There is for Schütz as there is not for Parsons the relevance of time as a phase
so to speak of each specification’s meaning so that the structure of the object
is depicted as a reticulated set of temporally qualified specifications within the
stream of experience. For Schütz the object experienced as a unity of meaning is
a unity, a web of temporalized specifications. The thing perceived would be for
Schütz not a schema of perceptual events but a schema of temporally related per-
ceptual events (or better, temporally qualified events).
FOUR PRE-THEORETICAL DECISIONS 79
Any such set of specifications may be the constitutive specifications of the ob-
ject, but there is no sense here of the construct as an abstract portrait that stands
in approximation to the concrete object. Hence it is only with reference to the time
schemas of the actor’s actions that the object is real and concrete. Hence at any par-
ticular moment in standard time for Schütz the concrete object is never more
than what the actor knows or expects of it through the treatment that the actor
gives or gets, has given or expects to give or get from it. Rather than depending
then on its ontological characteristics to provide for the fact that the actor may
learn something new, Schütz would point to the nature of the construction and
the rules governing the test of the actor’s preconceptions as well as the procedures
for administering and evaluating the tests of the actor’s own preconceptions to
allow for the possibility that he might learn something new.
It is in this respect that language is problematical for Schütz. Rather than lan-
guage being epiphenomenal with reference to the experienceable possibilities,
and rather than language being problematical only in the various ways it may
prepare an actual object for the actor’s treatment, it is inseparable from the phe-
nomenon of a unity of specifications. It does not consist in the initial instance
in a grammar and a set of signs, but rather consists of the logics and the objec-
tive designata—the things meant by the signs and the objects that expressions
express, that meanings mean or point to as standards found in a non-percep-
tual order whereby an interpersonally constituted world of objects is achieved.
That language may show the above nominalistic properties is not a philosophical
point of beginning for Schütz as it is for Parsons, but needs accounting for in
terms of the conditions of experience under which the relationship of the sign
to the thing it refers to shows such an amazing characteristic, amazing because it
is precisely a feature of the familiar language of daily life that one cannot play in
such fast and loose manner with language.
Finally, the empirical ideal type as the arbitrarily constructed standard of com-
parison with actual events—the merely empirically possible object which the fall
of events can neither confirm nor deny—the mere guide for the researcher in
ordering the actual observations, is for Schütz nothing else than the constructed
object that an actor, any actor orients as an object, but viewed by the observer as
a constructed object rather than as it appears to the natural attitude as the thing
actually out there.
This problem involves a decision whereby the attitude is designated within the
rules of which the observer invokes a guarantee as to the reproducible character
of the observed data.
80 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Much talk has recently been going the rounds of social scientists about phe-
nomenology. In a prevailing accent of this conversation something referred to
as phenomenology, depicted as a new philosophy of social scientific method, is
proposed as a touchstone by which one may get away from theoretical super-
fluities to the world of actual appearance. What is not seen, by and large, is that
the term “phenomenology” refers only to the rules that will be found operating
in any perspective—scientific, religious, aesthetic, practical, etc.—whereby cer-
tain areas of experience are made non-relevant to the problem in hand, while
with reference to others a “position is taken.” They are accorded the accent of
affirmation, of just so. Every philosophy, every theory, every attitude toward the
world has its relevant phenomenology, or better, its relevant phenomenological
attitude and method if one uses the term phenomenology as MacLeod suggests.
Every perspective includes its rules on which the irreducible character of data-
experiences is based. Every perspective provides the rules whereby the differ-
ence is made between that which appears in its theoretic sense and that which
appears in its sense of a datum, whether it be the theoretic or data sense of the
“outer world” or the world of “inner experience.” This holds for the businessman
as well as the infant; the scientist as well as the theologian. One may see this if the
terms “scientist” and “practical man” are used to designate ways of attending to
the world rather than as designations of actual persons.
There are many phenomenologies to choose from. Or better, there are
many phenomenological attitudes to choose from. There are also two leading
contenders: (1) the so-called “neo-Kantian” phenomenology which is preva-
lent in social science today, and with this or that shading is found in the work of
Cassirer, Lewin, Freud, Mead, Weber. We are interested in the fact that it is also
found in the work of Parsons. (2) The Husserlian phenomenology is represented
in the work of Schütz.
The question that the choice between them decides may be asked as follows: If
one allows the possibility that the world has a perspectival appearance to the
actor—and both Parsons and Schütz are insistent on this—then in achieving
a description of the world “from the point of view of the actor” how can the
describer guarantee the anonymity of his description, i.e., how can he guarantee
that his description will vary independently with the occasions of his own
social life.
For both Parsons and Schütz the situation of action is constituted simultane-
ously with the defining specifications of the actor. Both stress the importance
of perspectival appearance. In achieving a description of the actor’s world,
Parsons’s phenomenology requires that the observer suspend judgment on eve-
rything but the possibility of a community between the actor and the observer.
This possibility stands without question under the assumption of the invariant
primal categories of understanding. Thus, the truth is in all of us if we act in
FOUR PRE-THEORETICAL DECISIONS 81
The problem that Schütz addresses instead is simple but potent: granted a
world that actor and observer may know together, with whatever colorings of
doubt, hesitancy, certainty, typicality, uniqueness, publicity, privacy, orderliness,
confusion, determinateness or indeterminateness, repetition or singularity, and
with whatever accents of immanence or transcendence to thought—granted
all this. What are the conditions by way of the properties of the structuring of
experiences and only of the structuring of experience under which an experi-
encer experiences an order that shows these faces? Granted that there is know-
ledge that shows the peculiar and in many ways the historically recent property
of being invariant with reference to the social status of the knower—knowledge
that is simultaneously “anonymous and communal” (to borrow a phrase from
Thomas Mann)—what is there property-wise in the structures of the attitudes
that are constitutive of such an order of experience under which the experienced
world shows such intriguing features? For Schütz such a question cannot as a
matter of rule be answered by invoking philosophical doctrine. It requires in the
very way in which it is posed that one seek an answer by addressing the nature of
experience itself.
To adopt such a view cuts one off from the use of the rational man as a de-
vice for assessing the factual, hypothetical, theoretical, mythical, or whatever
character of the knowledge that the experiencer has about the world. Rather,
the make-up of the rational man even as a mere construction—and it seems that
if one follows Schütz this is the best one can ever hope for as far as the use of
the rational man in the investigator’s tasks is concerned—must be drawn from
the investigations of how men, isolated and yet simultaneously in an odd com-
munion, go about the business of constructing, testing, maintaining, altering,
validating, questioning, defining an order together.
An important consequence of using Parsons’s phenomenological attitude as
compared with Schütz’s can be shown by comparing the status of factual know-
ledge and ignorance under the two attitudes.
If we examine the actor’s definition of the situation as it is known under the
neo-Kantian phenomenological attitude, the observer finds the actor’s informa-
tion as something in the world only after he has discounted the actor’s situation of
action in light of the observer’s wider knowledge and wiser procedures of infor-
mation gathering and interpretation. If one actor sends a message to another, the
amount of factual information that the receiver gets from the message is limited,
by the observer as a matter of methodological principle, by the extent to which
the receiver operates upon the message according to the canons of rationality.
Everything he receives and makes sense of outside of this is in such an observer’s
view error or myth. Thus despite the protestations of the actor that the Jews really
have control of the country as is evidenced in the newspaper reports of the current
tax scandals he is met by the observer with a quiet, “Tush, I know better.”
FOUR PRE-THEORETICAL DECISIONS 83
If matters did not go beyond the fact that the one maintained that the Jews
were taking over while the other wagged his finger at him, there would be no case
for comparison of any theoretical or practical importance. But the case is other-
wise. The observer not only wags his finger, but he maintains as well that unless
the actor changes his ways, that is, unless the actor revises his portrait to accord
with the factual state of affairs as it is presented by the observer, the actor stands
a good chance of failing to realize his projects. In fact, it is only by a random con-
catenation of events that he could under such circumstances realize his project,
and if he does, he will have been right but will adduce the wrong reasons. In the
final analysis, he will not have accumulated a body of empirically useful infor-
mation and will not know how to bring about the effect that for one reason or
another he seeks. In effect, discrepancies from the logico-empirical procedures
reduce the instrumental efficacy of his knowledge. Or, following Hobbes, you
can’t be rational and lose.
An important consequence of this view for structural-functional theory is that
in finding a place for the functions of ignorance in a social arrangement, a theorist
so oriented would provide the following: Not only what a man knows but what he
does not know has to be accounted for in rendering logically complete description
of the factors that condition the occurrence of a set of events of conduct. In short,
logical completeness requires that ignorance be accorded motivational status.
By contrast there is Schütz’s insistence that the actor as well as the observer
are always left with the actual light that they have; they never have more nor less
and that they act always and only on the basis of what they know. The impor-
tant thing, for Schütz, and the thing that stands for him without a standard with
which to judge ironically is that the actor keeps going. But how? Parsons would
find the answer in a community of myth or the various structural arrangements
and operations, e.g., the allocating of authority and responsibility whereby the
members knowingly or not protect each other from the actual consequences of
their errors. Schütz would seek the answer in the properties of the constructs of
everyday life, the nature of the structure of relevances, the logics of everyday life,
the interpersonally entertained and validated canons for achieving a definition
of a situation and an assessment of outcomes whereby a situation is experienced
by the actor as determinate in its meanings and certain as far as needed informa-
tion is concerned even though a strict rational assessment of the situation would
make a determinate solution impossible. Thus, for Schütz, the huge problemat-
ical thing is the nature of the actor’s factual knowledge. For him the nature of the
actor’s factual knowledge and ignorance as well as the fact that it shows in some
matter of degree instrumental adequacy must somehow be accounted for within
the character of the actor’s experiences and only here, and with reference to the
relationship between the structural characteristics of his factual knowledge and
the continuity of his activity.
84 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
For Schütz, unlike Parsons, the notion of the rationality of the action
designates nothing else than the properties of the actor’s model, the opera-
tions of judgment, choice, assessment of outcomes, and so on that he does in
fact employ. Should the actor deliberate, or should he erect a plan of decisions
whereby he sets up prior to the occurrence the alternative he will choose should
he be faced with them, then the term rationality may be used to designate just
this: that he acts deliberately and with a preconceived strategy. The effect of
such a view is to reduce the term “rationality” to the status of a mere sign for
the actions or cluster of actions that the observer must now seek to correlate
empirically with the various orders of consequences of these actions that the
observer may be interested in.
By comparison with Parsons, Schütz does not treat the subjective categories as
intervening variables. Rather, the sociologist’s enterprise involves him according
to one postulate of his method at every moment of his theorizing with the use of
subjective categories. Schütz, in fact, deplores the use of the term “subjective cat-
egories” as misleading since it is frequently used to make a difference somehow
between the world portrayed according to objective categories and the world
portrayed according to subjective categories as if the “two worlds” were different
from each other.
With due regard for the fact that the observer’s model of the actor, according
to Schütz, includes the actor’s model of the world as the observer constructs the
actor’s model, one can say that the observer’s model of the actor is all of what is
meant by Schütz by the subjective categories. There is no problem of finding out
what is really going on under the other man’s skull. Even the finest devices that
would translate brain waves into the content of the stream of experience would
not do away with the necessity of this postulate of “subjective” interpretation.
The only data that the observer has access to is behavioral data, the signs that
the other person generates, while the schema of the actor that the observer
uses serves as nothing else than a set of rules whereby behavioral categories are
transformed into the categories of action.
The subjective categories for Schütz therefore refer to the fact that the observer
constructs an analytical dummy called an actor with typified ways of experien-
cing a typified order of objects, and that he interprets the bodily movements
and sounds of the empirical other person according to the rules provided in the
constructed actor in his constructed situation.
With this much comparison, the way is open to show how these decisions even-
tuate in different conceptions of the problem of order.6 The problem of order is
conceived to consist of the observer’s tasks of specifying the factors that are con-
ditional of permanence and change. Parsons and Schütz are alike in their con-
cern for achieving something more than a vocabulary that permits a set of static
state descriptions. Each seeks to handle the problem of permanence and change
by invoking a set of terms that permit statements describing the “path” of the
alterations of a state. But the different decisions lend different phrasings to the
question and thus the visions of the correct solution differ.
It is possible, of course, to construct many theories within any set of decisions.
In discussing consequences for a theory of order one cannot therefore point
directly to the theoretical constructions that are implied by the decisions. One
86 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
can however ask for the kinds of questions that these decisions raise as one goes
about constructing a theory and thereby understand the consequences in the
sense that the decisions about the theory of order are confined by the framework
of rules of proper procedure laid down in the way the problems discussed above
were settled. This is the procedure we shall use.
We consider Parsons first, holding in mind that he seeks, as does Schütz, a
theory that provides more than a set of momentary state descriptions. What
problems does he have to settle and what solution does he choose for settling
them? This is the question.
The correspondence theory with its separation of subject and object and its
provision for a guaranteed communal world between actors poses the problem
of whether situational and actor changes are to be conceived of as varying inde-
pendently of each other. The actor invests his situation of objects with meaning
and is allowed to treat the situation of objects in terms of their attached meanings,
so the problem is made nasty because one must necessarily distinguish between
a representation of the situation as it appears from “within” and the situation as it
appears from “without.” Given this distinction as it is drawn up under Parsons’s
decisions one has to decide then how to handle a system of actors in a situation
of action depicted from the standpoint of the observer and without reducing the
actor’s view to the status of a mere epiphenomenon on the one hand, or, on the
other hand, allowing the actor’s view and thereby allowing the individual as a
source of change in the system with the risk of indeterminism or risk the gain of
a determinism at the cost of turning the system into a table of organization that
operates as a set of impersonal forces that shove the individuals around here and
there, while taking it as a matter of factual interest that he is correctly aware or
not of what is happening to him.
Here the assumption of communality, the nature of the concrete and actual
object, and the decision to allow the observer a guaranteed factually anonymous
picture if he acts rationally permits a solution at one point at least. The situation
from within and the situation from without are the same when the actor is ra-
tionally oriented to the logico-empirical realities of his situation. But there is a
troublesome residue. There remains the case where the actor’s system of empir-
ical constructions may be factually at fault though despite this the actor seems
nevertheless to thrive and even shows considerable reluctance to follow attempts
made to enlighten him even when it appears that his rational self-interest is not
served by his remaining “in error.” This question that arises directly from the na-
ture of the decisions requires solution. We shall see in a moment how it is solved.
Let’s first consider some further problems faced by the theorist.
Provision is made in Parsons’s theory of action for the inherent purposiveness
of action. It involves by definition an orientation to a future state of affairs by an
actor driven by the quest for satisfactions, his drives showing again by definition
FOUR PRE-THEORETICAL DECISIONS 87
some degree of normative control. This raises the question of how to handle the
social structuring of need dispositions, action orientations, and situations of
objects, for the looming fact is that of social routinization—the “ruttedness” of
the activities of men in social groupings. Or to put it flatly, the phenomena of
orderliness.
Finally—though finally only in the sense that this is the last point we shall be
concerned with—the decision to require two Egos orienting an order in which
each finds the other and that stands with some “necessary minimum” of con-
sensus with regard to standards of preference, traditions, empirical mappings,
time perspectives, ultimate and short term interests and so on permits the notion
of state of the patterned interactions that define a system at a moment of clock
time, though this moment is a fat moment, that is, an interval treated as a point.
A succession of such fat moments produces the notion of temporal sequence. But
for playing in such fast and loose fashion with the relevance of time in the defini-
tion of action the fat moment squeezes out the temporal meaning of duration, so
that one must look elsewhere than to the analysis of time to answer the question
that remains: where to look for the factors that are conditional of the regularities
of temporal succession?
The problems so presented and taken together permit of more than one joint
solution. One could, for example, concretize the system, give it a set of purposes
of its own, subordinate the actor to the teleology of the system and the pro-
ject would be launched. It is not enough to say that this solution is little better
than a political doctrine, for there is much work going on today particularly in
the area of “organizational behavior” that works with exactly this kind of ra-
tionale for the questions that are asked by the users. It is not difficult to under-
stand since common sense finds nothing out of the ordinary in the notion of an
organization’s goals or purposes.
For Parsons the solution is sought in the metaphor of systemic equilibrium
in the face of environmental alterations, where the notion of system and envi-
ronment or setting are terms that are always relative to each other in a “little sys-
tems have littler systems to bite ’em” kind of way. That system beyond which are
the settings of the barren time and physical conditions is the society. The system
of action is conceived to be systematically related to a structurally relevant set-
ting in the sense that certain of its operations known as boundary operations
serve to maintain those characteristics of the activity that remain relatively in-
variant with reference to structurally relevant alterations in the setting. That is
to say, these operations maintain the distinctiveness of the system relative to its
setting. The system is conceived to be dissolvable in the sense that the character-
istics of the activities can become indistinguishable from the structured envi-
ronment. Not only are the activities such as to show this boundary maintaining
property but they show as well the property in the conditions of their occurrence
88 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Harold Garfinkel, a Jewish minority who was personally familiar with discrim-
ination and deeply committed to questions of racism and inequality, began
exposing the tacit interactional practices of racism as a graduate student at the
University of North Carolina in 1939, producing the first research on how tacit
presuppositions, labels, and accounts can become institutionalized such that
ordinary activities will, as a matter of course, categorize and disenfranchise,
without conscious intent. Taking the position that the rules and norms framing
the interactional work of communicating and presenting Self are usually taken
for granted and therefore both invisible and unconscious, Garfinkel argued that
these processes are essential to understanding society, but were being ignored by
sociology.1 Garfinkel proposed that examining the interactional work of mar-
ginal and disenfranchised persons (Black, Jewish, Transgender, mentally ill,
etc.), who have what W. E. B. Du Bois (1903) called a “double consciousness”
about the discrimination they face that heightens their awareness of interac-
tional work, can reveal not only the inequality they face, but also the underlying
moral requirements for successful interaction that they are denied.
Garfinkel’s work on Race, Gender, and other forms of inequality continued
to develop in the 1940s through his research for the Army during World War
II (in a psychiatric hospital) and after he arrived at Harvard in 1946. By 1947
he was documenting a need for reciprocity and mutual commitment to what he
called the “Trust Conditions” underlying interaction, showing that persons in
asymmetrical social positions (whose category/label is assigned without their
consent) have extra difficulty achieving mutual intelligibility with Others in in-
teraction (Garfinkel 1947, 1952a, 1952b, 1956, 1963, 2019, [1962] 2019). He was
the first to study how people are disenfranchised during interaction by asym-
metry in the assignment of the categories Negro/White (Garfinkel 1940, 1942);
Negro/Jew/Red/Criminal (Garfinkel 2012:20); in the assignment of labels
Sick soldier/Cured soldier (Garfinkel 1948b, 2006:154–62); through inequality
GARFINKEL: RACISM, INEQUALITY, AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 91
situated interactions, rather than assuming they exist as epistemic objects inde-
pendently of interaction, which they can therefore mediate. Instead, Garfinkel
proposed the constitutive expectancies of interaction as the mediating force.
For Garfinkel (1948b:98), all signs in a modern society, even the more durable
symbols he referred to in (1948c) and (1948a) as “signposts,” acquire meaning
as the immediate result of a course of interaction. Insisting that studies of in-
teraction should focus on the back-and-forth exchange of the visible/hear-
able actions that comprise interaction, turn by turn, sequence by sequence,
Garfinkel, from the beginning, treated every creation of a social fact as a situ-
ated accomplishment (Garfinkel 1940, 1946, 1947, 1948a, 1948c). Whether the
moral conditions for this mutual creation are being met is also a situated matter
that varies across situations: Every instance of inequality interferes with sense-
making turn by turn.
When Garfinkel began working with Harvey Sacks, their joint discovery in
1962 of how detailed the order properties of interaction actually are, and the
degree to which they can be specified, enhanced their ability to demonstrate
this. To the extent that it is the tacit taken-for-granted character of constitutive
practices that hides and enables inequality, Garfinkel’s lifelong quest to docu-
ment the taken-for-granted in empirical detail is particularly important, laying
the groundwork for contemporary studies of how Race, Gender, and other
potentially stigmatized categories are actualized through taken- for-
granted
practices in situated interaction of all kinds.
Garfinkel’s approach to “systems of interaction” or interaction orders, and
morality as mutually constitutive, is one of the most important theoretical
innovations of the twentieth century. Various misunderstandings, plus the fact
that his position challenges conventional thinking, have made the argument dif-
ficult to understand. But the point is in essence quite simple: in homogeneous
contexts, persons attempting to communicate can assume a great deal of shared
meaning, in the form of signs, symbols, beliefs, and folkways. In diverse modern
contexts, however, this is no longer possible; the beliefs, situations, and values
are too varied. Thus, sociological approaches that do not distinguish the cooper-
ative making of meaning in diverse modern contexts, from meaning-making in
contexts grounded on practices that Garfinkel (1952b, 1967b) called tribal, fail to
capture the essential requirements for mutual intelligibility and social order in
modernity. These requirements, Garfinkel argues, involve cooperation and reci-
procity in the use of tacit “constitutive” practices that are not defined by folkways.
Achieving meaning always requires the cooperative use of shared practices (or
ethno-methods). But, in diverse modern contexts, constitutive practices must
be independent from social structure, uniquely tied not only to their situated
contexts of use, but also to their social and technical purposes, and they must be
attended equally by all participants, or they will not work.
GARFINKEL: RACISM, INEQUALITY, AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 93
When Garfinkel arrived at North Carolina in August 1939, having spent the
summer at a Quaker work camp in Georgia building an earth dam,5 the Sociology
Department, chaired by Odum, was already known as a center for “modeling,” an
abstract logical and quantitative approach. But, social theory at North Carolina
was taught under Odum (who collected Black folk narratives), with an emphasis
on the Action Theory of Florian Znaniecki and W. I. Thomas. The perspective of
the actor and the interest in interaction inspired by Znaniecki, Thomas, Cooley,
and Mead were serious issues, as was the Chicago School’s focus on ethnographic
94 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
field studies. Postwar “scientific” sociology, with its emphasis on aggregation and
generalization and its insistence that “real” science was neutral on questions of
justice, did not yet dominate the department.
Odum and Guy Johnson, another of Garfinkel’s mentors at North Carolina,
were committed to documenting the folkways and mores of the American South,
with an emphasis on racial issues and folkways in the Black community. They
encouraged Garfinkel to pursue field research documenting racial “accounting
practices” in 10 county courtrooms, with a focus on how Race impacted
decisions in murder trials. Odum and Johnson were well-known proponents
of an approach to civil rights that challenged the White Southern status quo.
Unfortunately, their challenge was limited by their theoretical commitment to
a need for stable folkways. Unlike Durkheim, who had argued that constitutive
practices could replace folkways, Odum and Johnson’s belief that stable folkways
are necessary to maintain social order meant they were not prepared to abandon
White Southern folkways, even though they disagreed with them. The slow
change in Race relations they advocated was criticized by civil rights activists and
White Southerners alike (Gilmore 2008:226–30). As a consequence, Odum went
from being an influential president of the American Sociological Association
(ASA) in 1930 to relative obscurity before his death in 1954. Unfortunately,
Garfinkel’s association with them may have obscured the radical character of his
approach to Race inequality.
The sociology Garfinkel found at North Carolina was multifaceted and uncon-
ventional. For instance, his insight that “accounts” reveal tacit aspects of social
order came from Kenneth Burke, a literary theorist whose work he encountered
there, not C. Wright Mills (1940) (who would, however, be a mentor of Sacks at
Columbia). Garfinkel’s grasp of the implications of “incongruity” for the coordi-
nation of action was inspired by Burke, Aron Gurwitsch, and Gestalt psychology.
Incongruity means that what one sees, hears, touches, tastes, etc., cannot be
made to match up with what was expected: it is incongruous and cannot be made
sense of. From Odum (1937, 1947) Garfinkel would have inherited the idea that
forms of practice (“technicways”), such as ways of lining/queuing up, or scien-
tific techniques not constrained by folkways, could develop suddenly, and could
resist and neutralize folk inequalities. The idea was in some respects similar to
Durkheim’s (1893) argument that constitutive practices of science can work in-
dependently of tradition. Odum (1943) noted that technical ways of lining up at
the post office in the segregated South that ignored Race and took everyone in
turn had developed in everyday interaction in spite of their conflict with folk-
ways. The big difference is that Durkheim’s constitutive practices require a moral
foundation very like Garfinkel’s Trust Conditions, whereas Odum, who located
morality exclusively in folkways, thought that technicways were morally neutral
and hence could be manipulated for evil purposes.
GARFINKEL: RACISM, INEQUALITY, AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 95
North Carolina, where he was a graduate student. The bus stopped in Petersburg,
Virginia, on May 23, 1940 (Easter weekend). Many Black passengers left the bus,
leaving two Black passengers sitting in the middle seats, one of whom was, unbe-
knownst to Garfinkel, Pauli Murray, a famous Transgender civil rights activist.
Because of Murray’s presence, the incident became famous, has a presence in the
history of civil rights, and generated comparisons of Murray’s own account of the
incident with Garfinkel’s.6
The driver explained that he could not load new passengers and continue the
journey until the two Black passengers moved to the back of the bus: the Jim
Crow practice at the time. One of the two was dressed as a woman, the other as a
boy. They refused to move all the way back and pointed out to the driver that the
seat behind them was over the wheel and very uncomfortable, and that the one
behind that one was broken. They offered to move into the broken seat if he could
fix it. But they refused to sit over the wheel. The bus driver initially accepted the
compromise as preserving the appearance of Jim Crow rule, and said he would
try to fix the seat—which he did. The bus remained in Petersburg for two hours
as the incident unfolded.
The article reporting Garfinkel’s observations first appeared in the journal
Opportunity (published by the Urban League) within days of the incident in May
1940, and was then reprinted as if it were fiction in Best Short Stories of 1941 (and
again in Primer for White Folks, 1945). The 22-year-old Garfinkel did not write it
as fiction. While the analysis employs literary devices (representing the thoughts
of participants) that Garfinkel did not use in his later work, these devices are
used in this detailed ethnographic analysis to portray tacit presuppositions about
Race and inequality that he observed at work in the interaction. It is an inter-
esting early approach to making the tacit visible.
Garfinkel opened the article with the observation that the racial troubles he
observed were related to the institutional obligations of bus company workers,
“accounts” the company will accept for failures like lateness, “accident cards”
that need to be filled out to bolster such accounts, and how these clash with the
requirements for making sense in the interaction. If the company did not ac-
cept those accounts, the bus driver could still be a racist, but would have trouble
acting on his racism without getting fired. This pointed Garfinkel toward the
importance of institutional accounting practices. As Garfinkel (1940) set up the
problem in his first line:
“Denial of ‘the rights and privileges of a free citizenry’ ” Garfinkel (1940:97) notes,
“can be accounted for as the cause of ‘unavoidable delays’ between Washington
and Durham.” The institutionally accepted account protects the driver’s job while
he enacts racism. A two hour delay that occurs at the bus driver’s insistence, is
accountable to the company as an “unavoidable delay” caused by “color trouble.”
Historians and civil rights activists have treated this now famous incident nar-
rowly in terms of civil rights issues. Their analysis has been critical of Garfinkel
for taking a conventional White perspective and missing the revolutionary char-
acter of the incident. But his analysis was not at all conventional. One reason for
their criticism is that the points being made by a sociologist and those made by
civil rights activists are quite different. For the civil rights activists the problem
is treated as a relatively straightforward question of “strategy.” For Garfinkel,
by contrast, there are many hidden social undercurrents that need to be con-
sidered. In other words, the situation is much more complicated than the civil
rights activists have seen. Garfinkel’s account supports some of the claims the
civil rights activists want to make. But he makes an even stronger case than the
civil rights activists do about how the racism involved actually works in the inter-
action, which has important implications for taking action on civil rights that the
civil rights activists missed.
The article as originally published in Opportunity was a detailed report on
and analysis of the incident Garfinkel had witnessed, with dates, times, and bus
routes supplied. It was not presented as fiction. It is also notable that Garfinkel
was concerned enough about what he had witnessed to get the article written and
published within days of its occurrence.
Most importantly, there is independent verification of the accuracy of
Garfinkel’s account. A comparison by Rosalind Rosenberg (2017), while critical
of Garfinkel, reveals only minor differences between the accounts by Murray and
Garfinkel: on the question of whether “accident cards” were given only to White
passengers, and whether the bus driver was “enraged” at the end. Both can be
explained by the different locations of Garfinkel and Murray in the bus (Garfinkel
at the front with the “White” passengers and Murray more than halfway back), as
Rosenberg herself notes.
In other words, the “facts” reported by the two accounts are remarkably sim-
ilar. It is what they make of the incident that differs. Garfinkel’s sociological focus
on tacit presuppositions and taken-for-granted interactional processes makes
for differences between his analysis and that of the historians and activists. When
the two Black passengers refuse to move to the back of the bus, for instance,
Garfinkel (1940:100) observes that everyone was initially “rendered actionless”
by the “denial of the commonplace.” Whereas the activists focused on analyzing
the “strategies” used by the activists, Garfinkel focused on how those “strate-
gies” impacted the taken-for-granted character of the interaction and its tacit
98 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
does not understand how things work in Virginia that creates the possibility of
compromise, not the Gandhi strategy. However, before too long, the bus com-
pany will intrude into the situation via the driver’s obligation to be on time and
his available institutional account for lateness, that he had “color trouble” with
the bus—which undercuts the reciprocity (Trust Conditions) the activists were
relying on—and gives the driver a way out when his tacit presuppositions are fi-
nally openly breached.
Ultimately, in Garfinkel’s view, this happens because competing tacit
understandings of the terms “gentleman” and “lady” and their racial implications
in 1940 Virginia make it inevitable that a request (from Murray’s Black female
companion to the White bus driver) for an apology with a reference to herself
as a “lady” will result in arrest: a Black woman is excluded by asymmetrical cat-
egory assignment from being a “lady.” She went too far and the driver suddenly
sees that he has no “choice.”
Some commentators have argued that Garfinkel’s racial status explains the
differences between the accounts. This is unfortunate because it obscures the so-
ciological implications of his analysis. Rosenberg (2017:6), for instance, suggests
that Garfinkel may have been unable “to see anything wrong with the bus driver’s
giving accident cards [only] to whites,” because he was White. Garfinkel saw
a great deal wrong with the whole process, including the “accident cards.” It is
important to remember that he was a young Jewish minority traveling in the
American South at a time when being Jewish in the United States meant living in
stigmatized Jewish enclaves, and suffering from the social exclusion, dispropor-
tionate police surveillance, job exclusion, and the criminal careers that follow.
While Garfinkel is now usually considered “White,” he was often treated
as non-White, particularly in the South, where he lived from 1939 to 1946.7
According to Arlene Garfinkel (married 1943), when traveling they needed to
check ahead with hotels and restaurants to see if Jews were accepted. Many did
not accommodate Jewish travelers. Garfinkel’s life experience in the 1940s was
not that of a White man.8 He would certainly have considered it wrong that only
Whites received “accident” cards. But, for him, that inequality would not have
stood out from the rest: everything about the asymmetrical relations on the bus was
wrong and ultimately nonsense. The fact is that Garfinkel saw a lot more racism
on the bus than the activists did. His sociological position was that making sense
in interaction demands equality and reciprocity, which as a minority he knew he
was often denied. His account focuses on the bus driver’s ability to deny interac-
tional reciprocity; and the ability of Whites to frame, label, and categorize Black
passengers without their consent (an issue that he would take up again in his
analysis of American attitudes toward Russia in 1947).
In contrast to Murray, Garfinkel portrays White passengers as prepared to be
entertained by the spectacle of Black passengers being “put in their place.” This
100 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
two-hour interlude on the bus—which for Murray and her companion is a par-
tial success because they engaged the driver and police in “rights talk” for two
hours—in Garfinkel’s account—is anticipated as a boundary reinforcing enter-
tainment by White passengers—a ritualized display to reinforce for “insiders,”
Black and White—the unequal (asymmetrical) relationship in which they stand.
The police officer who came onto the bus to explain things to the two Black
passengers complained to the driver: “Why didn’t you tell me?” (Garfinkel
1940:103), which Garfinkel takes to mean that the officer was complaining that
the driver had not told him he was going to be dealing with Black people who
don’t know the rules and thus will not help him by publicly embracing their un-
equal status. This was the problem with “the boy”—he made sense—and that
sense made a “nonsense” of any attempt at a ritualized degradation ceremony.9
The expectation of the driver and other riders on the bus was that the interaction
would proceed in asymmetrical terms.
According to Garfinkel (1940:107), Murray’s companion was violating
a taboo and “saying things too bluntly.” The activists seem to chalk this up to
Garfinkel’s “White” identity. But it is actually a penetrating analysis of the tacit
presuppositions of White racism. In the context of Jim Crow in 1940s Virginia,
there were things that could not be said—but she was saying them. “Besides,” he
says, for White passengers “there was still a point of pride. Rights or no rights,
logic or no logic, she was still a Negro and had talked too damn loud” (Garfinkel
1940:105). Talk about Race, he says, has a taboo status, and assumptions about
Race are expected to remain tacit: you “mention them to your priest . . . but never
never shout” (Garfinkel 1940:107). Murray’s companion was openly challenging
the whole Southern status quo: something the White passengers, driver and po-
lice officer, needed to remain tacit because they have no good way of dealing with
it openly.
When the driver hands out accident cards for his report to the bus company
(to account for the “unavoidable delay”), Garfinkel (1940:108) portrays him as
“flustered.” Garfinkel continues: “He was an hour late, had been ill-advised, his
job might well be in the balance.” He portrays the passengers as discussing what
to write: “What did you write?” “What did you write?” “There really was no acci-
dent. How can you answer it?” “Look, look, he wrote ‘nonsense’ on his.”
At the end, Garfinkel (1940:113) describes the driver as enraged. Just as it
seemed he had a compromise worked out, Murray’s (1940:113) companion
requested an apology: “You’re a gentleman, and I’m a lady . . . and therefore . . . ,
I think that as a gentleman to a lady you owe me an apology.” Garfinkel’s “literary”
portrayal of the reaction to this is, “Good God in His everlasting mercy, did she
realize what she was doing?” He describes the driver: “Transfixed, the driver
stared down at her.” “This,” Garfinkel (1940:114) says, “was the opening, here
was something to understand; the fog had finally dissipated and the barriers
GARFINKEL: RACISM, INEQUALITY, AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 101
The buzzer sounded and the bus slowed to a crunchy stop in order to discharge
three Negro passengers. Hunched over in anticipation of the low doorway,
the first one tapped the driver on the shoulder and waved his hand in friendly
greeting as he clattered out. “Thankya, boss.” The second did the same. The
third said nothing. His hand on the door lever, the driver called after them.
“Boy she sure didn’t come from Virginia, did she?”
“Ah shood say not,” the answer drifted down the length of the bus as the
group moved off.
He leaned toward the door, addressing the darkness. “Ain’t you boys glad you
live in Virginia?”
Again the answer, “You shoor said it, boss.”
There was no echo to the driver’s thin laughter.
(Garfinkel 1940:118–19)
This banter restores the appearance that all passengers are working with the same
set of tacit expectations. But it also underscores the divide between Black and
White passengers, and the need of White Southerners for cooperation from Black
102 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Garfinkel’s second major work, his MA thesis of 1942 on “Inter-Racial and Intra-
Racial Homicide,” an abridged version of which was published in Social Forces
in 1949, focused on how courtroom outcomes that appeared statistically to
be “fair” were actually based on racialized accounts that were produced in the
courtroom as part of the trial. At a time when the discipline was advocating a
turn toward statistics, Garfinkel was demonstrating the pitfalls of a statistical ap-
proach, particularly in getting at issues of racial discrimination. The assumption
that research based on statistics is objective is naively wrong when the numbers
in question refer to things like trial outcomes that were produced using institu-
tional accounting processes that treated Race and racialized narrative accounts
as a taken-for-granted aspect of the legal decision-making process.
Working with the guidance and encouragement of Odum and Johnson,
Garfinkel undertook an ambitious thesis project that required him to do exten-
sive field research in 10 North Carolina county courthouses. His analysis focused
on narrative accounts about Race offered in court by persons involved officially
in the cases of the accused (including judges, prosecutors, defense attorneys, and
witnesses). These accounts he recorded by hand. Garfinkel found that accounts
produced for the court, which were highly racialized, played a significant role in
determining the outcome of cases. The puzzle was that when looked at statisti-
cally, the distribution of punishments by Race looked “fair.” Garfinkel realized
that the results of two contrasting sets of institutional accounts had the effect of
GARFINKEL: RACISM, INEQUALITY, AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 103
neutralizing each other so that statistically it looked as if Race were not playing an
important role in the determination of cases when in fact it was often playing the
determining role. Garfinkel realized that something like this could be happening
in any social institution to produce a false appearance of fairness or equity.
The way it worked was simple. Accounts were offered in court regarding the
moral character of both the offender and the victim: character assessments. These
accounts of moral order were framed in terms of shared cultural assumptions
about Race. In other words, Black and White men were not expected to be-
have the same way, and judgments of character reflected these not so tacit
presuppositions. Good White men contributed to the community. Good Black
men knew their place. Racialized judgments of “good” and “bad” character thus
became part of the court process. Simply put, Garfinkel found that “good” White
men were rewarded (with lenient sentences or dismissal) for killing “bad” Black
men. Similarly, “good” Black men could be rewarded for killing “bad” Black men
and “doing the community a favor.” Statistically (holding constant other factors)
White and Black men in these two cases had a similar statistical probability of
getting lenient sentences. In cross-Race Black/White homicides, White men
were rewarded for homicide, while Black men were penalized. But because most
homicide occurs within Race, these made up a very small percentage of the cases.
The more lenient sentences for White men killing Black men and Black men
killing bad Black men, Garfinkel found, canceled each other out and obscured the
racial bias. Not only was the fact that Black men were always penalized for killing
White men while White men were rewarded for killing Black men obscured, but
the fact that the decisions were based on racist narratives remained hidden. The
numbers were telling a big fat lie.
That the entire process was racialized was obscured by the statistical anal-
ysis, because the results canceled each other out. As a consequence, a situation
that in the courtroom was openly discussed in racialized terms appeared sta-
tistically to be the result of a just and fair legal process. It is a huge and contin-
uing social problem that social actions that are explicitly motivated by Race and
tacit assumptions about Race can look fair in the aggregate. It is also the case
that particular actions with no racial motivation can nevertheless have racist
outcomes if they reproduce racialized inequality, which is what the term “insti-
tutional racism” refers to.11
It is remarkable that given such a clear demonstration of how racism can be
rendered invisible by statistical accounts, it has become an accepted legal crite-
rion today in the United States that claims of Race and Gender discrimination
must be accompanied by statistical proof that an institution has a “pattern” of
bias. As Garfinkel demonstrated in 1942, this is often impossible—even in the
most explicit cases of institutional racism—because statistics (which measure
the outcomes of institutionally acceptable accounts—not events in the world)
104 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
can obscure the discriminatory practices in question such that outcomes appear
legally and morally fair when they are not.
For instance, in contemporary American society, most people believe that
there is a high Black crime rate and accept that as a justification for the high rate
of surveillance and arrest in Black communities. But the high Black crime rate
that justifies this differential treatment is nothing more than an “institutional ac-
count” produced by high rates of surveillance and arrest. The actual “real” world
incidence of crimes of various kinds has been shown by study after study to be
equally distributed across racial groups. In fact, if anything, White rates of actual
crime are higher due to a combination of greater opportunity and lack of negative
consequences. Furthermore, studies have shown that institutional workers un-
derstand how this works and can routinely manage institutional accounts such
that a statistical analysis will demonstrate compliance with various egalitarian
institutional and societal objectives, even when the actions in question violate
those objectives, and the outcomes reproduce racial inequality and exclusion.
Garfinkel’s early demonstration of this problem deserves more attention.
When he arrived at Harvard after the war in the summer of 1946, Garfinkel grav-
itated toward scholars (notably Parsons, Bruner, and Robert Bales) who focused
on the importance of democracy, the social and psychological dynamics of ine-
quality, and the effects of differential position on the ability to share objects and
meaning in modern societies. He was also surrounded by scholars who threw
themselves eagerly into the new idea that statistical analysis was the key to scien-
tific objectivity. But he continued to fight against this trend. It was Garfinkel’s ex-
perience that minorities and marginal persons like himself, the Black passengers
on the bus in Virginia, and the Black men he had observed in North Carolina
courtrooms experienced higher levels of incongruity and inequality than others.
He knew from his MA thesis research that statistics could hide this inequality,
and he now saw that sociology as a discipline was moving toward a naive em-
brace of statistics that would make the situation worse.
There were some categories of people, Garfinkel said, who experienced so
much incongruity that they were in themselves “natural experiments.” He in-
cluded Transsexuals and schizophrenics in this category, along with minorities
and sick soldiers, and began to center an approach to sociological theory and re-
search on this proposal. Whereas in the face of a challenge to their expectations he
found that White Americans were able to continue for some time trying to repair
and make sense of interaction, there were categories of persons who experienced
GARFINKEL: RACISM, INEQUALITY, AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 105
so much incongruity that they would switch interpretive frameworks at the first
indication of trouble. His first several PhD proposals (1948a, 1948c) focused
on this idea explicitly with regard to Jewish identity. In setting up the argu-
ment, Garfinkel was drawn to the narrative psychology of Bruner (with whom
Garfinkel worked in 1946–1947), which was inspired by Bruner’s experience
with the Office of Strategic Services (OSS) interviewing French townspeople in
1944 about collaboration with the Nazis, the Gestalt psychology of Gurwitsch
(with whom he met regularly in Cambridge), and the work of theorists of per-
ception (including Adelbert Ames, Kurt Lewin, and Egon Brunswik).
With Parsons as his mentor/advisor, Garfinkel took up the challenge of giving
interactional incongruity a theoretical foundation in sociology. In three papers
written in 1946–1947, his first year as a PhD student, Garfinkel sketched out his
position, including the beginnings of what would become his famous Trust ar-
gument. In 1947 he also wrote a long dissertation proposal which was published
in 2006 as Seeing Sociologically (Garfinkel 2006). In addition, he wrote a series of
dissertation proposals in 1948 titled “The Jew as a Social Object” (Turowetz and
Rawls 2021). The four papers and manuscripts from 1946–1947, the dissertation
proposals from 1948, along with five others (from 1946–1947), were the foun-
dation for his dissertation,12 The first of the four papers, “Some Reflections on
Action Theory and the Theory of Social Systems” (Garfinkel 1946), written for
a course, reformulated Parsons’s Social Action Theory. The second and third pa-
pers “Notes on the Information Apperception Test” (Garfinkel 1947) and “The
Red as an Ideal Object” (Garfinkel 2012) were based on research Garfinkel did
in the spring of 1947 at the Harvard social research laboratory, with Bruner,
Brewster Smith, and a large research team. The dissertation proposal from 1947,
referred to as the 1948 manuscript (Garfinkel [1948] 2006), attempted to pull
everything together. Garfinkel not only fine-tuned his understanding of ac-
counts, labels, categories, and Trust Conditions during this period, it was also his
first encounter with using transcribed audio data to study interaction, a method
he would use for his own dissertation. When he published a version of his MA
thesis in 1949, Garfinkel used the categories and symbolic typologies he had
worked out in “The Red” to frame the analysis.
While Garfinkel agreed with Parsons that sociology needed a theory of ac-
tion, he argued that it should focus on what happens between people/actors in
interaction; what was missing from sociology, he said, was an understanding of
how social objects, categories, labels, etc., are constituted in the back-and-forth
of interaction, and how much that process relies on equality. Without such a
theory, he argued, social research was coming to be more and more naively based
on untested assumptions that embed inequality. Since the details of interac-
tional reciprocities are constitutive of meaning, his new approach would require
researchers to observe, record and analyze interactional details in situ—rather
106 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Garfinkel wrote “Some Reflections on Action Theory and the Theory of Social
Systems” for a seminar he took at Harvard in the summer or fall of 1946 in which
Parsons participated. The paper argued that a workable theory of action needs a
theory of the object. Even taking into account Garfinkel’s relative maturity at the
time (he was 29), the manuscript is remarkable. In 17 single spaced pages, he laid
out a comprehensive appraisal of social action theory and the changes it needed,
which he would follow throughout his career.
The main problem, in Garfinkel’s view, was that Parsons’s action theory had
no theory of the object. Additionally, Garfinkel argued, while Parsons had rec-
ognized that interaction is of central importance, he had not focused on actual
interaction, but on the actor’s point of view. Garfinkel exposed the assumptions
and concerns that contributed to these shortcomings, with the objective of
respecifying social action theory around a new theory of the object. On the other
hand, he argued that Parsons’s functionalism could not be fixed. It suffered from
a circularity which required that it be eliminated entirely.
His critique of Parsons is penetrating. While Garfinkel credited Parsons with
a radical departure from conventional empiricism, he argued that in retaining
a realist correspondence theory of reality, and invariant categories, Parsons
had not been radical enough, inadvertently building on unexamined assump
tions. Thus, Parsons retained what Garfinkel called “ethnocentrism” (cultural
assumptions) when he meant to focus objectively on the empirical dimension
of social interaction.
Garfinkel specified two things a theory of action must do, and he explained
how all existing theories fail to do these two things: first, a theory of social ac-
tion must explain how social objects are created and sustained; and, second, it
must take the problem of how incongruities are handled into account to explain
the possibility of sustained coherences in social contexts not characterized by
what Garfinkel called “tribal” consensus. By “social objects,” Garfinkel meant
everything that is given meaning in interaction; including identity (role), words,
GARFINKEL: RACISM, INEQUALITY, AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 107
symbols, rationality, information, and “things” like tables, chairs, smokes (as op-
posed to cigarettes), etc.
behind it. For Garfinkel the test is not about Russia or things Russian. The im-
plied question, Garfinkel says (1947:2), is “whether and how the types of objects
seen, their relationships to each other, and the kinds of reactions of the Subject to
them will vary” according to aspects of the test itself.
As in his earlier research, Garfinkel maintained that what was being taken for
granted obscured the social processes involved such that researchers focused
on the wrong things: overlooking deep questions of sense-making that were in-
volved in the test situation itself.
Garfinkel’s approach to the tacit issues embedded in the research design was
so sophisticated that the others could not see his point. This is evident in Smith’s
comments on his manuscript. One of Garfinkel’s points, that “anything can mean
anything,” such that particular meanings must be settled sequentially, and not on
the basis of imported understandings, Smith dismissed with the comment “Can
anything mean anything? Is not the meaning an essential part of the experience?”
Of course it is. But Garfinkel’s point is that certainty of meaning is achieved through
the coherence of the test-taking experience itself. Smith was taking meaning for
granted. Garfinkel argued, by contrast, that coherent meaning is a cooperative
achievement. Meaning can change. The feedback loop is at work. Something that
meant one thing can suddenly mean something else in the next turn. So, yes, any-
thing can mean anything and therefore that it means something particular calls for
explanation. It is the cooperative use of constitutive practices that allows fragile
indexical meanings to achieve certainty. This is why reciprocity is necessary: the
central premise of ethnomethodology, as Garfinkel would later develop it.
In an article developed from the IAT experience, titled “The Red as an Ideal
Object,” completed in late spring of 1947 (Garfinkel 2012), Garfinkel refers re-
peatedly to difficulties faced by persons who are asymmetrically assigned cat-
egories he refers to as “Jews,” “Negroes,” “Reds,” and “Criminals,” expecting
the performance of Self to be more difficult, the Trust Conditions less likely to
be met, and the consequences of failed reciprocity more serious for persons
assigned these labels (an argument he went on to elaborate in his dissertation).
Garfinkel’s point is that while all four categories constitute marginal statuses,
the social practices by which marginality is accomplished are different in each
case. The relationship of each category to the institutionalized norms of the com-
munity is also different. This in turn results in a different positioning of possibili-
ties vis-à-vis the majority for each labeled minority.
Conclusion
Amidst the turbulent 1960s, when issues of social justice again came to the fore-
front, Garfinkel was often portrayed as advocating moral neutrality and then
110 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
criticized for being indifferent to moral issues. This is ironic, since his entire po-
sition rests on a moral foundation of implicit social contact. However, Garfinkel’s
studies of how minorities and marginal persons are differentially impacted by
asymmetrical categories, labels, and accounting practices illuminated more than
inequality. These interactional processes and their constitutive organization hold
the key to explaining the possibility of coherent democratic public life. They
also show how fragile it is. This should give studies of how people enact Race
and Gender inequality a special position in contemporary sociology. They are
not only studies of inequality—they are evidence of an important but missing
theoretical point: the fragile social objects of modernity, as Garfinkel (and
Durkheim) argued, require a degree of reciprocity and cooperation that is not re-
quired by the durable symbols of the tribe. A mutual commitment to reciprocity
conditions—Trust Conditions—defines this morality and must be present for in-
teraction to work. In contexts of inequality, the frames, accounts, and labeling
practices of folkways and formal institutions resist the required reciprocity, cre-
ating an asymmetry that interferes with sense-making.
Garfinkel’s discovery that reciprocity and equality are requirements for
making coherent sense and Self in diverse modern contexts explains how an in-
quiry that began with a focus on Race and Inequality became a comprehensive
theoretical/research approach to modernity in all of its aspects, including science
and technology and human machine communication. In making this argument,
Garfinkel was building on the work of his mentors: Parsons, his PhD advisor,
had advocated studying culture as an independent domain of interaction in-its-
course (Parsons 1950); Burke had proposed a “Grammar of Motives”; Odum
(1937) had proposed “technicways” as a new type of social practice that made
rapid social change possible when folkways resist change; Bruner had given him
the idea of “cognitive style”; and Schütz had pioneered an approach to the study
of embodied courses of action. Building on their insights, Garfinkel went fur-
ther: his ethno-methods comprising a morally grounded “way” of cooperatively
making modern social facts that is independent of broader social structures.
In his presidential address to the ASA in 1949, while Garfinkel was working
on his dissertation with him, Parsons (1950) argued that culture should be
studied as an independent domain. This is exactly what Garfinkel did. In a 1961–
1962 draft of Studies in Ethnomethodology, Garfinkel titled his first chapter “The
Discovery of Culture.” The relationship with Parsons was profound. But, by the
time Studies was published, sociology had taken a conservative turn, and Parsons
was no longer at the helm. Odum died in 1954, leaving the idea of technicways
to languish (Vance 1972), and Schütz died in 1959. The eclectic studies of the
prewar period were shortly to be thoroughly replaced by statistical analysis fo-
cused on “objective” and “value-free” variables (Rawls 2018).
While his friends Jerome Bruner and Herbert Simon (a friend from Princeton,
1952), who shared his theoretical concerns, went on to hugely influence their
GARFINKEL: RACISM, INEQUALITY, AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 111
References
Bruner, Jerome. 1990. Acts of Meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Coser, Lewis A. 1975. “Two Methods in Search of a Substance.” American Sociological
Review 40(1):691–700. doi: 10.2307/2094174.
Du Bois, W. E. B. 1903. The Souls of Black Folk: Essays and Sketches. Chicago: A. C. McClurg.
112 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Durkheim, Emile. 1893. De la division du travail social [The division of social labor].
Alcan: Paris.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1940. “Color Trouble.” Opportunity, May (reprinted 1941. Pp. 97–119
in The Best Short Stories, edited by E. J. O’Brien. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, and again in
Primer for White Folks, 1945).
Garfinkel, Harold. 1942. “Inter-Racial and Intra-Racial Homicide in Ten Counties in North
Carolina, 1930–1940.” Master’s thesis, University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1946. “Some Reflections on Action Theory and the Theory of Social
Systems.” Garfinkel Archive.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1947. “Notes on the Information Apperception Test.” Garfinkel Archive.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1948a. “A Further Note on the Prospectus for an Exploratory Study of
Communication and the Maintenance of Understanding in Selected Types of Dyadic
Relationship with Particular Reference to the Jew as an Object of Social Treatment.”
Garfinkel Archive.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1948b. “Prospectus for an Exploratory Study of Communicative Effort
and the Modes of Understanding in Selected Types of Dyadic Relations.” Garfinkel Archive.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1948c. “The Jew as an Intended Object in Selected Types of Dyadic
Relationship.” Garfinkel Archive.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1949. “Research Note on Inter-and Intra-Racial Homicides.” Social
Forces 27(4):369–81. doi: 10/ctczzb.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1952a. “Anxiety and the Social Perception of the Pre-Medical Candidate.”
Presented at the annual meetings of the American Sociological Association. Atlantic City
NJ: September.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1952b. “The Perception of the Other: A Study in Social Order.” PhD
dissertation, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1956. “Conditions of Successful Degradation Ceremonies.” American
Journal of Sociology 61(5):420–24. doi: 10/b7gcn5.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1963. “A Conception of, and Experiments with, ‘Trust’ as a Condition of
Stable Concerted Actions.” Pp. 187–238 in Motivation and Social Interaction: Cognitive
Determinants, edited by O. J. Harvey. New York: Ronald Press.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1967a. “Passing and the Managed Achievement of Sex Status in an
Intersexed Person.” Pp. 116–85 in his Studies in Ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice Hall.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1967b. Studies in Ethnomethodology. Cambridge, UK: Polity.
Garfinkel, Harold. [1948] 2006. Seeing Sociologically: The Routine Grounds of Social Action.
Boulder, CO: Paradigm.
Garfinkel, Harold. 2012. “The ‘Red’ as an Ideal Object.” Etnografia: E Ricerca Qualitativa
1(1):19–34.
Garfinkel, Harold. [1962] 2019. Harold Garfinkel: Parsons’ Primer. Edited by A. W. Rawls.
Stuttgart: Springer Nature.
Garfinkel, Harold. 2019. “Notes on Language Games as a Source of Methods for Studying
the Formal Properties of Linguistic Events.” European Journal of Social Theory
22(2):148–74. doi: 10.1177/1368431018824733.
Garfinkel, Harold. [1943] 2019. The History of Gulfport Field 1942. Edited by T. Thielmann.
Siegen, Germany: University of Siegen.
Gilmore, Glenda E. 2008. Defying Dixie: The Radical Roots of Civil Rights 1919–1950.
New York: W. W. Norton.
GARFINKEL: RACISM, INEQUALITY, AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 113
Heims, S. J. 1991. The Cybernetics Group 1946–1953: Constructing a Social Science for
Postwar America. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Lundberg, George. 1944. “Sociologists and the Peace.” American Sociological Review
9(1):1–13. doi: 10.2307/2086017.
Madge, John. 1962. The Origins of Scientific Sociology. New York: Free Press.
Meehan, Albert J. 1987. “Assessing the ‘Police-Worthiness’ of Citizen’s Complaints to
the Police: Police Accountability and the Negotiation of ‘Facts.’” Pp. 116–40 in The
Interactional Order: New Directions in the Study of Social Order, edited by D. Helm,
T. W. Anderson, A. J. Meehan, and A. W. Rawls. New York: Irvington.
Odum, Howard W. 1937. “Notes on the Technicways in Contemporary Society.” American
Sociological Review 2:336–46. doi: 10.2307/2084865.
Odum, Howard W. 1943. Race and Rumors of Race: The American South in the Early
Forties. Baltimore, MD: John’s Hopkins University Press.
Odum, Howard W. 1947. “Folkways and Technicways.” In Folk, Region, and Society: Selected
Papers of Howard W. Odum. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.
Parsons, Talcott. 1950. “The Prospects of Sociological Theory.” American Sociological
Review 15:3–16. doi: 10.2307/2086393.
Parsons, Talcott. 1951. The Social System. New York: Free Press.
Rawls, Anne. 2004. Durkheim’s Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rawls, Anne Warfield. 2018. “The Wartime Narrative in US Sociology, 1940–
1947: Stigmatizing Qualitative Sociology in the Name of ‘Science.’” European Journal of
Social Theory 21(4):526–46. doi: 10.1177/1368431018754499.
Rawls, Anne Warfield, and Jason Turowetz. 2019. “Introduction.” In pp. 1–108 in Harold
Garfinkel: Parsons’ Primer. Stuttgart: Springer.
Rawls, Anne Warfield, and Jason Turowetz. 2021. “‘Discovering Culture’ in Interaction:
Solving Problems in Cultural Sociology by Recovering the Interactional Side of
Parsons’ Conception of Culture.” American Journal of Cultural Sociology. 9:293–320.
doi: 10.1057/s41290-019-00079-6.
Rosenberg, Rosalind. 2017. Jane Crow: The Life of Pauli Murray. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Simon, Herbert. 1997. An Empirically Based Microeconomics. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Smith, Brewster, Jerome Bruner, and Robert White. 1956. Opinions and Personality.
New York: Wiley & Sons.
Sudnow, David. 1965. “Normal Crimes: Sociological Features of the Penal Code in a
Public Defender Office.” Social Problems 12:255–76.
Turowetz, Jason, and Anne Rawls. 2021. “The Development of Garfinkel’s ‘Trust’
Argument from 1947 to 1967: Demonstrating How Inequality Disrupts Sense and
Self-Making.” Journal of Classical Sociology (21)1:3–37.
Vance, R. B. 1972. “Howard Odum’s Technicways: A Neglected Lead in American
Sociology.” Social Forces 50:456–61. doi: 10.2307/2576788.
Wieder, D. Lawrence. 1974. Language and Social Reality: The Case of Telling the Convict
Code. The Hague: Mouton.
Wieder, Lawrence D. 1974. “Telling the Code.” Pp. 144–72 in Ethnomethodology, edited by
R. Turner. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1953. Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.
4
Garfinkel’s Studies of Work
Michael E. Lynch
Introduction
Work as a Topic
When Garfinkel’s announced the studies of work program in the early 1970s,
he certainly knew that he and other ethnomethodologists had been studying
work all along. Many of the earliest ethnomethodological studies focused on
the work of professional staff, clients, and subjects at hospitals and clinics,
suicide prevention centers, law courts, prisons, and many other bureaucratic
and occupational settings (Heritage 1984:294). A not-insignificant amount of
attention also had been given to the quotidian work of doing professional so-
ciology, such as in Garfinkel’s (1967:19ff.) discussions of researchers’ efforts
to implement a coding scheme for analyzing clinic records. However, when
announcing the studies of work program in the 1970s, he proposed a radically
different approach to occupations, professions, arts, sciences, and everyday
life than could be found in previous sociological (including ethnomethodo-
logical) studies.2
The radical difference had to do with an explicit recognition that many con-
temporary activities not only deploy distinctive methods, they also explicate
their own methodologies: canonical procedures, organizational standards, and
constituent practices. Sociology’s epistemic and literary resources often pale by
comparison to the extensive bodies of writing and practical instruction avail-
able in other fields. So, for example, the literatures in sociology of science, art,
medicine, and law are dwarfed by the popular, academic, and didactic accounts
written by practitioners. Even many recreational and “do-it-yourself ” pursuits
are supported by large literatures and online resources. In addition to exemplary
stories, “how to” manuals, recipe books, and the like, such literatures also include
practitioners’ “philosophical” reflections and methodological debates. Garfinkel
also noted that the literary and oral traditions in many fields include endogenous
sociologies or anthropologies of the relevant organized activities, and he refused
to grant professional sociologists or anthropologists (ethnomethodologists in-
cluded) with a special epistemic authority or reflexive capacity with which to su-
persede such “lay sociologies” with professional versions.
Faced with such a rich and intricate tapestry of practices, Garfinkel saw no
prospect for developing a stable and elaborate body of concepts, theories, and
methods that would encompass practical actions of all kinds. Consequently,
he did not propose that ethnomethodology would become a general science of
practical actions because, most obviously in the natural sciences but certainly in
other fields as well, the territory already was occupied by legitimate claimants.
Instead, he suggested that ethnomethodology would be paired, and even hybrid-
ized, with an open-ended variety of other sciences and arts of practical action
integral to particular fields (Garfinkel 2022:28).
116 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
The explicit aim of the studies of work program was to investigate the “whatness”
of organized activities. By “whatness,” Garfinkel meant the distinctive embodied
practices, and uses of instruments, texts, and other equipment, that constitute the
work itself. Initially, he used the term quiddity to dignify “whatness” with a der-
ivation from the Medieval Latin term quidditas, often translated as the “nature”
or “essence” of a phenomenon (Garfinkel, Lynch, and Livingston 1981:133). He
later adopted a more obscure term from Medieval scholastic philosophy, haec-
ceity: “thisness” or “just thisness” (Garfinkel 2002:99n., 249). He preferred that
term, because it allowed him to avoid any suggestion of essentialism, and more
sharply to highlight the singular performance of practical actions. He argued
that the very production of music by musicians, discoveries by scientists, and
aggregate traffic patterns by drivers is missed by social science studies that take
for granted the identity and detailed practices of an occupation, profession, or
other organized activity, while focusing on social, cultural, political, economic,
and psychological aspects of the work.
When introducing the studies of work program, Garfinkel credited Harvey
Sacks with identifying a “missing what” in social studies of practical activities: a
massive domain of social phenomena that, virtually without exception, sociolog-
ical and administrative studies rely upon, make use of, and yet ignore:
While praising Sudnow’s effort to engage with and describe the work (or, rather,
the improvisational play) of professional jazz musicians, he noted that Sudnow’s
study initially was limited to an examination of “ethnographic materials,” and
later to “single person improvisational jazz- piano playing and improvised
touch typing,” instead of explicating the relevant ensemble practices (Garfinkel
1986:vii; alluding to Sudnow 1978, 1980, 2001).
Garfinkel proposed that the “missing what” is made up of distinctive organ-
izations of competent practice that make up the performance of particular arts,
sciences, and technical professions, as well as more ubiquitous activities in a
given society. In his view, the “missing what” is nothing other than the practices
themselves, as coordinated embodied performances, identical with, carried out
through, and constitutive of socially organized activities.
One might wonder how Garfinkel could imagine that previous sociological
and organizational studies could possibly have missed something so obvious,
given the substantial number of available studies of occupations, professions, or-
ganizations, and everyday life activities. During the heyday of the Chicago School
of sociology, dozens of students turned out descriptive case studies on all kinds
of elite and humble professions and occupations, as well as on vagrant and “de-
viant” activities not listed in the Dictionary of Occupational Titles. Using partic-
ipant observation methods, such studies portrayed daily conduct in institutions
such as hospitals, prisons, and asylums; and they attempted to convey the points
of view of different participants in those institutions. In order to distinguish the
program he was initiating from previous ethnographies, Garfinkel occasion-
ally used the expression “the Howard Becker phenomenon.”4 In an unpublished
manuscript, Garfinkel credited Sudnow with having come up with the phrase:
To take Becker’s studies for example we learn that there are jazz musicians,
where they work, who they work with, what they earn, how they get their jobs,
or what the audience will request of them. But . . . a curiosity of the reportage,
Sudnow points out is that Becker’s articles speak of musicians’ work and do so
by omitting entirely and exactly the practices that for those engaged in them
makes of what they are doing . . . : making music. . . . In that musicians are to-
gether in that place for the so-and-what they are doing, Becker’s account takes
on its character as the thing it can be about. But it can be about that in a sin-
gular way. Sudnow points out that even though it was written by a jazz musi-
cian, it is an appreciation of the work of jazz musicians. (Garfinkel n.d.; quoted
in Tolmie, Benford, and Rouncefield 2013:228, ellipses and emphasis in Tolmie
et al. quotation)
Garfinkel made clear that Becker and other professional sociologists do not
“miss” the “what” of the specific practices they describe through an oversight or
118 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
lapse. Instead, they miss it as a consequence of the very coherence and integrity
of their discipline. Sociologists have their own hard-won professional interests,
methods, and interpretive schemes with which to study practices in other fields.
Commitment to the discipline also sets up critical, competitive, or adversarial
relations with formal and informal accounts given by professionals in fields such
as psychiatry, criminal justice, and school administration. A sociologist’s per-
sonal background in the relevant profession can provide an initial basis for un-
derstanding and contesting official practitioner versions, but the professional
literature, concepts, and theories in sociology usually provide the basis for an-
alytic and critical commentary. In contrast, Garfinkel suspended, and even ac-
tively eschewed, the authoritative use of disciplinary theory and methodology as
a basis for knowing other and better than what qualified practitioners say about
the organization of their activities.
Garfinkel’s indifference toward professional social science concepts and
methods was more than a rhetorical exercise in “anti-professionalism” (Fish
1989:215ff.). It was instead an effort to come to grips with how lay and profes-
sional activities of all kinds constitute particular social orders. Philosophers
of social science such as Alfred Schütz (1962) and Peter Winch (1958:89)
had previously argued that social studies take up concepts and pragmatic
understandings that are available to members of the societies they study and
translate them into second-order constructs. These constructs then provide
professional social scientists with methodological resources for distinguishing
native common-sense beliefs from the analytical knowledge particular to
the sociological discipline. When discussing sociological and psychological
conceptualizations of, for example, “rationality” and “motives,” Schutz and
Winch questioned the independence of such second-order constructs from
ordinary (first-order) uses of those terms to explain, praise, or condemn con-
duct. In line with their arguments, Garfinkel eschewed giving priority to social
science concepts and methods, and instead proposed to examine how vernac-
ular usage and routine practices are methodically produced and ordered in
their own right. In the case of the “vernacular of the laboratory” (Senior 1958),
and practices in specialized fields of all kinds, Garfinkel suggested that such
ordinary practices constitute specific social arrangements, and display spe-
cialized understandings of those arrangements. In other words, he suggested
that technical methods particular to science, music, etc., are themselves so-
cial activities, and further that technically specific understandings of those
practical activities are distinctive sociologies (Garfinkel et al. 1988; Garfinkel
2022). This proposal seemed to disrupt the contemporary division of intel-
lectual and methodological labor between sociology and other academic and
non-academic practices, and it also appeared to forgo the hard-won, and still
fragile, autonomy of the sociological discipline. As we shall see, the disruption
Garfinkel’s Studies of Work 119
was a deliberate effort to create the space for a radically different sociological
initiative.
with colonial legacies. For the most part, there was little interest in delving more
deeply into the “mess” of laboratory practice, though numerous ethnographic
studies of science, technology, and medical practices have been undertaken in
the following decades.8
At this point, the apparent commensurability of laboratory ethnographies
with ethnomethodological studies of scientific work begins to break down.
A major sticking point is that Bloor, Collins, and others associated with the so-
ciology of scientific knowledge give credence to disciplinary sociology as a per-
spective and body of methods and concepts for discerning the central role of “the
social” in the sciences. Given their indifference toward disciplinary sociology as
a privileged vantage point, ethnomethodological studies of natural science are
reluctant to grant that sociological concepts, theories, and methods constitute
an adequate basis for investigating the nature and contents of the various nat-
ural sciences. For Garfinkel, each natural science is a distinctive science of prac-
tical actions—that is, of the practical actions particular to that science. This can
be understood to mean that practical actions and practical reasoning in the sci-
ences, no less than on city streets and in government offices, constitute relevant
social orders distinctively and irreducibly (Garfinkel et al. 1988; Garfinkel 2022).
Accordingly, an array of stable “social” variables does not exert influence on “sci-
ence,” as though from outside; instead, scientific practice is in its own right a dis-
tinctive site, and source, of social order.
Bruno Latour and Michel Callon took this point to heart when they developed
actor-network theory (Callon and Latour 1981; Latour 1987, 2005).9 However,
they eventually transformed the proposal that science and society are insepa-
rable in practice into an ontological postulate: a “second axis of symmetry” to
supplement Bloor’s first axis of symmetry between “true” and “false” belief. Like
the first axis, with its impartiality toward the validity or invalidity of a given be-
lief, the second axis was indifferent to conventional distinctions between human
and nonhuman entities, actions, causes, and influences; treating all identi-
ties and differences among society, politics, and nature as co-determined (co-
constructed, co-produced) nodes of action inscribed in and through continually
and unexpectedly shifting historical networks.
Ethnomethodologists did not follow actor-network theory’s incursions into
ever-expansive, heterogeneous networks of co-construction. Instead, Garfinkel
and his students pressed more intensively to examine and demonstrate the prac-
tical details that constituted technical work. The unique adequacy requirement
acted both as a constraint upon and an expression of that difference. It also
encouraged ethnomethodologists to take up a different mode of investigation
to that of ethnography—the method with which they were, and often still are,
closely identified.
122 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Studies of the sciences and professions have been the most visible product
of the studies of work program. However, while promoting that program,
Garfinkel (2002:257) also continued his ongoing studies of what he called “nat-
urally organized ordinary activities.” Such activities include commonplace
embodied activities, such as driving in traffic and producing order of service in
queues (e.g., Garfinkel and Livingston 2003), which are “naturally organized”
in the sense that they are produced by participants in the particular activity;
participants whose routine actions reflexively (though not necessarily “self-re-
flectively”) compose and react to the contingencies of a developing aggregate
order. Garfinkel did not draw a sharp distinction between ordinary activities
and the specialized work of laboratories, courtrooms, or mathematics lectures,
though it might seem that ethnomethodologists and conversation analysts
would have no need to worry about the unique adequacy requirement when
they study such routines as crossing the street at a busy intersection, forming
a service line at a ticket booth, or conversing over the phone. However, there is
a way in which that requirement still applies to studies of such commonplace
activities.
Despite the fact that no specialized training or credential is needed to witness
and perform ordinary actions, there still remains the problem of how to charac-
terize what participants in singular occasions of an activity are doing then and
there. Livingston (2008:246) provides a concise definition of this “characteriza-
tion problem” as “the attempt to characterize an activity, in its identifying lived
detail, as the recognizable work of its production.” He contrasts such an attempt
to the prerogatives of what he calls a “sociology of the hidden order”: an inter-
pretive program that falls back on general disciplinary knowledge (concepts,
Garfinkel’s Studies of Work 125
Instructed Actions
authoritatively about practices in a specialized domain: the key issue is that such
mastery is a condition for recognizing and exhibiting the competent production
of “social things.” Moreover, these “things” and the methodic practices that pro-
duce them are the very phenomena that are of central interest to classical soci-
ology, and yet paradoxically they are not accessible to sociology’s methods unless
and until those methods are supplemented, or even replaced, by other methods
that are integral to the practices studied. Except in the case of a reflexive investi-
gation of sociology’s standard methods, training in sociology could not possibly
prepare a student to investigate the routine production of other fields of practice
that also involve extensive training.
Garfinkel identified his conception of ethnomethodological “things” with
Durkheim’s injunction to consider social facts as things (Garfinkel 2002; Rawls
2002), but unlike Durkheim, he broadened his conception to include not
only collective social phenomena such as queues, traffic jams, and multiparty
conversations, but also the things that are central to other fields, such as legal
arguments, mathematical proofs, experimental practices, astrophysical discov-
eries, software programs, and so on. Above all, he did not follow Durkheim’s
(1982:63) effort to build a discipline with a specialized methodology that would
surpass lay “prenotions” with scientific knowledge.
The implications for ethnomethodology of Garfinkel’s stance toward
Durkheim’s Rules are not entirely clear (Lynch 2009, 2015). As Hutchinson,
Read, and Sharrock (2008:109) observe, “[t]here are at least two conflicting
ways in which ethnomethodologists can think of their inquiries,” both of which
are suggested, and to an extent exemplified, in Garfinkel’s (2002) treatment of
Durkheim. One is as the legitimate heir to Durkheim’s program, which is to
“think of ethnomethodology as a first step in the direction of a genuine social sci-
ence, [but] one which differentiates itself from sociology at large . . . in being the
only branch of sociology that addresses itself directly to actual and observable
occurrences in and of the social order” (Hutchinson et al. 2008:109). This would
be an alternative to existing sociology in the sense that it would get closer to the
“data” of actual social life than is possible through surveys, models, and other
formal-analytical methods. The other, which is much more in line my own un-
derstanding of Garfinkel’s program, is not to view ethnomethodology as a more
rigorous empirical sociology, but to view it as an alternate form of investigation
that shadows formal analysis wherever it is found, both within and beyond the
academy (see Button, Lynch, and Sharrock In press).
Formal analysis, in Garfinkel’s (2002) terms, includes but is not limited to
the various theories, methods, and analytic practices in sociology, all of which
attempt to develop robust generalizations about the organization and struc-
ture of social actions. It also includes more workaday phenomena such as plans
and rules, navigation maps and route directions, classroom pedagogies, and
Garfinkel’s Studies of Work 129
phenomenological term for “life-world” (Husserl 1970): the lived-in world sen-
sually revealed and explored through embodied actions. The “pair” is made
up of a here-and-now activity together with an account that either (or both) is
deployed for guidance or produced as a “rendering” of that activity. There are
endless examples: a recipe and an attempt to enact it in a specific instance; a map
and a journey that attempts to follow it; a course of keyboard writing complete
with false starts and erasures, resulting in a written text as its residue; a conver-
sation and an audio or video recording of that conversation; a recording and a
transcript of it; a meeting and minutes of the meeting. It should be added that the
Lebenswelt covers both the here-and-now “experience” and any formal instruc-
tion or subsequent rendering of the action that is featured in a singular instance
of the action.
The second strange phrase—asymmetric alternates—is a claim about the re-
lationship between formal accounts and the lived practices of composing and
using them. As an illustration, consider the relationship between a sketch map
(or even a GPS) and the lived-work of following it from a point of origin to a
point of destination (Singh et al. 2019; Brown and Laurier 2012; Liberman 2013;
Psathas 1986). The map may be an indispensable guide for the journey, but it
cannot possibly anticipate or notate the contingencies that arise in the course
of reading it, getting lost, finding one’s way back “on” to the map, and so on. The
asymmetry has to do with how the map’s formal features provide a reduced and
rather inflexible account of the journey, whereas the journey subsumes the map
within a vast surplus of circumstantial, and largely gratuitous, detail. In the case
of a meeting and the recorded minutes, the vast amount of activity at the meeting
that is not recorded in the minutes cannot be recovered from the record, but the
record can be read in light of the meeting by those who attended it.
This simple pairing resonates with well-known organizational gaps: the gap
between formal accounts of methods and the performance of experiments; the
gap between managerial accounts and shop-floor practices; the gap between the
design of “intelligent” tools and the practices of using them; the gap between
law school curricula and the work of trying a case in court. Lucy Suchman’s
(1987) Plans and Situated Actions effectively developed the instructed action
paradigm into an entire research program at Xerox Palo Alto Research Center
(PARC), which has taken hold in other corporate research centers, and in the
academic field of communication and information science. Suchman’s project
had both critical-theoretical and practical-empirical aspects. The criticism
Garfinkel’s Studies of Work 131
took aim at the privileging of abstract plans, not only in the management of
organizational affairs but also throughout cognitive science, for operational-
izing practical action and practical reasoning. The practical aspect made up
a research program for conducting detailed ethnographic and conversation
analytic research at the site of work activities. Workplace and work practice
studies, as they came to be called, described practical and interactional con-
tingencies that elude formal design and management. Such research contrib-
uted to—indeed, it helped form—the field of computer-supported cooperative
work (CSCW), in which practitioners collaborate with ethnographers to inves-
tigate practical actions and interactions among designers at work, and among
users and various computational devices in different organizational and prac-
tical environments.
When focused on sociological methods and other formal analytical programs,
Garfinkel’s alternate can seem to take on a distinctively subversive character.
However, Garfinkel denies being critical of social science methods, because
the ad hoc performance of such methods is far from unusual as an instance of
instructed actions, and the analytical stance he takes toward the gap between
social science methods and practices is no different from the one he takes to-
ward the (often aggravating) difference between, for example, the instructions
for assembling a bicycle rack and an arduous and clumsy effort to mount the
rack on the back of a particular automobile. However, a sense of criticism arises
from an incongruity between the situated performance of research and the wide-
spread presumption in the social sciences that rigorous procedures should ad-
here strictly to methodological protocols.16
connections), and their research remains situated, however uneasily, within ac-
ademic sociology.
Perhaps the most robust environment for hybrid studies has been in the field
of CSCW, a field that was given a major boost by the reception to Suchman’s and
others’ ethnographic studies at Xerox PARC and at other private-sector research
centers where ethnographers, often in collaboration with programmers and
other technically proficient staff, examined technology design and use. Unlike
academic sociology, in which such a close attention to detailed technical practice
is often dismissed as too “micro” to be of interest, in such environments a deep
understanding of praxiological organization is a crucial part of the productive
enterprise. The place of ethnomethodology in CSCW and related fields is not
assured, however, as it vies with other social science programs to sustain its dis-
tinctive initiatives, and workplace studies often take a more eclectic form than
Garfinkel was willing to countenance (see Button et al. 2015 for a critical provo-
cation on this point).
At present, Garfinkel’s design for studies of work remains only partly fulfilled,
and ethnomethodology and conversation analysis for the most part have de-
veloped, and continue to develop, in a way that he critically and ambivalently
contrasted with the program he envisaged (see Button, Lynch, and Sharrock In
press: Chapter 7). He was all too aware of this prospect, and attributed it to the
professional academic circumstances under which he and his students oper-
ated. So, for example, he noted that his “dissatisfactions” with analytical eth-
nographies of science were the flip side of their “virtues”; their virtues being
that they tie “into, while developing further, current science studies of experi-
mental practices” in the field of science and technology studies (Garfinkel et al.
1988:118n10; Garfinkel 2022:83n10). The same can be said of studies that tie
into, and contribute to, literatures in fields such as communication and infor-
mation studies, criminology and legal studies, medical sociology, and so on.
Nevertheless, while his initiatives have not been fully developed, they are fre-
quently invoked, partly taken up, and to an extent exemplified by work in an
array of fields within and beyond sociology.
Garfinkel’s proposal for studies of work expresses a radical insight that the
professional social sciences are constitutionally inclined to reject, but which is
likely to haunt their disciplinary programs for years to come. The insight is that
the methodic production and analysis of sociology’s substance, as a practical
matter, is everybody’s business. Accordingly, the work of elucidating this me-
thodic production is not done by following any of the established social science
methods, whether qualitative or quantitative. Understanding this point can lead
one to appreciate both the radical novelty of Garfinkel’s program and its failure
to catch on in any particular social science discipline, except in an occasional and
fugitive way.
Garfinkel’s Studies of Work 133
References
Alac, Morana. 2011. Handling Digital Brains: A Laboratory Study of Multimodal Semiotic
Interaction in the Age of Computers. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Arminen, Ilkka. 2008. “Scientific and ‘Radical’ Ethnomethodology: From Incompatible
Paradigms to Ethnomethodological Sociology.” Philosophy of the Social Sciences
38(2):167–91. doi: 10.1177/0048393108315508.
Becker, Howard. 1951. “The Professional Dance Musician and His Audience.” American
Journal of Sociology 57(2):136–44. doi: 10.1086/220913.
Bjelic, Dusan I. 1996. “Lebenswelt Structures of Galilean Physics: The Case of Galileo’s
Pendulum.” Human Studies 19(4):409–32. doi: 10.1007/BF00188851.
Bjelic, Dusan. 2003. Galileo’s Pendulum. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Bjelic, Dusan, and Michael Lynch. 1992. “The Work of a Scientific Demonstration:
Respecifying Newton’s and Goethe’s Theories of Prismatic Color.” Pp. 52–78 in Text
in Context: Contributions to Ethnomethodology, edited by G. Watson and R. M. Seiler.
London: SAGE.
Bloor, David. 1976. Knowledge and Social Imagery. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Boden, Deirdre, and Donald H. Zimmerman, eds. 1991. Talk and Social Structure: Studies in
Ethnomethodology and Conversation Analysis. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Brown, Barry, and Eric Laurier. 2012. “The Normal-Natural Troubles of Driving with
GPS.” Pp. 1621–30 in Proceedings of the SIGCHI Conference on Human Factors in
Computing Systems. ACM Association for Computing Machinery, Austin, Texas, USA,
5–10 May.
Burns, Stacy. 2001. “‘Think Your Darkest Thoughts and Blacken Them’: Judicial Mediation
of Large Money Damage Disputes.” Human Studies 24(3):227– 49. doi: 10.1023/
a:1017563922116.
Button, Graham, Andy Crabtree, Mark Rouncefield, and Peter Tolmie. 2015.
Deconstructing Ethnography: Towards a Social Methodology for Ubiquitous Computing
and Interactive Systems Design. London: Springer.
Button, Graham, Michael Lynch, and Wes Sharrock. In press. On Formal Structures of
Practical Action: Ethnomethodology, Conversation Analysis, and Constructive Analysis.
London and New York: Routledge.
Button, Graham, and Wes Sharrock. 1993. “A Disagreement over Agreement and
Consensus in Constructionist Sociology.” Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour
23(1):1–25. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-5914.1993.tb00228.x.
Callon, Michel, and Bruno Latour. 1981. “Unscrewing the Big Leviathan: How Actors
Macro-Structure Reality and How Sociologists Help Them to Do So.” Pp. 277–303
in Advances in Social Theory and Methodology: Toward an Integration of Micro-and
Macro-Sociologies, edited by K. Knorr-Cetina and A. Cicourel. London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul.
Collins, H. M. 1985. Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice.
London: SAGE.
Coulter, Jeff. 1989. Mind in Action. Cambridge: Polity.
Crabtree, Andrew, Tom Rodden, Peter Tolmie, and Graham Button. 2009. “Ethnography
Considered Harmful.” Pp. 879–88 in Proceedings of the SIGCHI Conference on Human
Factors in Computing Systems. Boston, MA: ACM.
Doing, Park. 2008. “Give Me a Laboratory and I Will Raise a Discipline: The Past, Present,
and Future Politics of Laboratory Studies in STS.” Pp. 279–318 in The Handbook of
134 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Heritage, John. 1984. Garfinkel and Ethnomethodology. Cambridge; New York: Polity Press.
Heritage, John, and Steven Clayman. 2010. Talk in Action: Interactions, Identities, and
Institutions. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
Hill, Richard J., and Kathleen S. Crittenden, eds. 1968. Proceedings of the Purdue
Symposium on Ethnomethodology. Lafayette, IN: Purdue Research Foundation.
Husserl, Edmund. 1970. The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental
Phenomenology: An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy. Evanston, IL:
Northwestern University Press.
Hutchinson, Phil, Rupert Read, and Wes Sharrock. 2008. There Is No Such Thing as a Social
Science. Burlington, VT: Ashgate.
Knorr-Cetina, Karin. 1981. The Manufacture of Knowledge. Oxford: Pergamon.
Knorr-C etina, Karin. 1983. “The Ethnographic Study of Scientific Work: Towards a
Constructivist Sociology of Science.” Pp. 115–40 in Science Observed: Perspectives
on the Social Study of Science, edited by K. Knorr-Cetina and M. Mulkay. London:
Sage.
Koschmann, Timothy, Curtis LeBaron, Charles Goodwin, and Paul Feltovich. 2011.
“‘Can You See the Cystic Artery Yet?’ A Simple Matter of Trust.” Journal of Pragmatics
43(2):521–41. doi: 10.1016/j.pragma.2009.09.009.
Latour, Bruno. 1987. Science in Action: How to Follow Scientists and Engineers through
Society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Latour, Bruno. 2005. Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network Theory.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Latour, Bruno, and Steve Woolgar. 1979. Laboratory Life: The Social Construction of
Scientific Facts. London: Sage.
Liberman, Kenneth. 2013. More Studies in Ethnomethodology. Albany: State University of
New York Press.
Livingston, Eric. 1986. The Ethnomethodological Foundations of Mathematics.
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Livingston, Eric. 1995. “The Idiosyncratic Specificity of the Methods of Physical
Experimentation.” The Australian New Zealand Journal of Sociology 31:1–22.
doi: 10.1177/144078339503100302.
Livingston, Eric. 2006. “The Context of Proving.” Social Studies of Science 36(1):39–68.
doi: 10.1177/0306312705053055.
Livingston, Eric. 2008. Ethnographies of Reason. London: Routledge.
Lynch, Michael. 1985. Art and Artifact in Laboratory Science. London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul.
Lynch, Michael. 1991. “Laboratory Space and the Technological Complex: An Investigation
of Topical Contextures.” Science in Context 4(1):51–78. doi: 10.1017/s0269889700000156.
Lynch, Michael. 1993. Scientific Practice and Ordinary Action: Ethnomethodology and
Social Studies of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lynch, Michael. 2009. “Working Out What Garfinkel Could Possibly Be Doing with
‘Durkheim’s Aphorism.’” Pp. 101–18 in Sociological Objects: Reconfigurations of Social
Theory, edited by G. Cooper, A. King, and R. Rettie. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Lynch, Michael. 2015. “Garfinkel’s Legacy: Bastards All the Way Down.” Contemporary
Sociology 44(5):604–15. doi: 10.1177/0094306115599356a.
Lynch, Michael. 2019. “Garfinkel, Sacks, and Formal Structures: Collaborative Origins,
Divergences and the Vexed Unity of Ethnomethodology and Conversation Analysis.”
Human Studies 42(2):183–98.
136 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Lynch, Michael and Oskar Lindwall (eds.). Forthcoming. Studies of Instructed Actions.
New York and London: Routledge.
Macbeth, Douglas. 1991. “Teacher Authority as Practical Action.” Linguistics and
Education 3(4):281–313. doi: 10.1016/0898-5898(91)90012-8.
Macbeth, Douglas. 2012. “Some Notes on the Play of Basketball in Its Circumstantial
Detail, and an Introduction to Their Occasion.” Human Studies 35(2):193–208.
doi: 10.1007/s10746-012-9235-z.
Mannheim, Karl. 1936. Ideology and Utopia. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Maynard, Douglas, and Nora Cate Schaeffer. 2000. “Toward a Sociology of Social Scientific
Knowledge: Survey Research and Ethnomethodology’s Asymmetric Alternates.” Social
Studies of Science 30(3):323–70. doi: 10.1177/030631200030003001.
Merton, Robert K. 1973. The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Mondada, Lorenza. 2003. “Working with Video: How Surgeons Produce Video Records
of Their Actions.” Visual Studies 18(1):59–73. doi: 10.1080/1472586032000100083.
Ogien, Albert, Michel Fornel, and Louis Quéré, eds. 2001. L’ethnomethodologie: Une
sociologie radicale. Paris: La Découverte.
Polanyi, Michael. [1966] 2009. The Tacit Dimension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Pollner, Melvin. 2012. “Reflections on Garfinkel and Ethnomethodology’s Program.” The
American Sociologist 43(1):36–54. doi: 10.1007/s12108-011-9146-x.
Psathas, George. 1986. “Some Sequential Structures in Direction-Giving.” Human Studies
9(2–3):231–46. doi: 10.1007/bf00148129.
Rawls, Anne. 2002. “Editor’s Introduction.” Pp. 1–64 in Ethnomethodology’s Program:
Working Out Durkheim’s Aphorism, by Harold Garfinkel, edited by A. Rawls. Lanham,
MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Rouncefield, M., and P. Tolmie, eds. 2011. Ethnomethodology at Work. Farnham, UK:
Ashgate.
Ryle, Gilbert. 1946. “Knowing How and Knowing That: The Presidential Address.”
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 46(1):1–16. doi: 10.1093/aristotelian/46.1.1.
Ryle, Gilbert. 1971. “The Thinking of Thoughts: What Is ‘Le Penseur’ Doing?” Pp. 480–96
in Ryle, Collected Papers. Vol. 2. London: Hutchinson.
Sacks, Harvey. 1984. “Notes on Methodology.” Pp. 2– 27 in Structures of Social
Action: Studies in Conversation Analysis, edited by J. M. Atkinson and J. Heritage.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1997. “Whose Text? Whose Context?” Discourse & Society
8(2):165–87. doi: 10.1177/0957926597008002002.
Schegloff, E. A. 2005. “On Integrity in Inquiry . . . of the Investigated, Not the Investigator.”
Discourse Studies 7(4–5):455–80. doi: 10/ds2cd6.
Schütz, Alfred. 1951. “Making Music Together: A Study in Social Relationship.” Social
Research 18:76–97.
Schütz, Alfred. 1962. “Concept and Theory Formation in the Social Sciences.” Pp. 48–66
in A. Schütz, Collected Papers. Vol. 1. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Schütz, Alfred. 1970. Reflections on the Problem of Relevance. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Senior, James K. 1958. “The Vernacular of the Laboratory.” Philosophy of Science
25(2):163–68. doi: 10.1086/287595.
Singh, Ranjit, Chris Hesselbein, Jessica Price, and Michael Lynch. 2019. “Getting
‘There’ from the Ever-Changing ‘Here’: Following Digital Directions.” Pp. 280–99
Garfinkel’s Studies of Work 137
in digitalSTS: A Field Guide for Science & Technology Studies, edited by J. Vertesi
and D. Ribes. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Sormani, Philippe. 2015. Respecifying Lab Ethnography: Experimental Physics in
Ethnomethodological Perspective. Farnham, UK: Ashgate.
Suchman, Lucy A. 1987. Plans and Situated Actions: The Problem of Human Machine
Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Suchman, Lucy, and Brigitte Jordan. 1990. “Interactional Troubles in Face-to-Face Survey
Interviews.” Journal of the American Statistical Association 85:232–41.
Sudnow, David. 1978. Ways of the Hand: The Organization of Improvised Conduct.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Sudnow, David. 1980. Talk’s Body: A Meditation between Two Keyboards. London;
New York: Penguin.
Sudnow, David. 2001. Ways of the Hand: A Rewritten Account. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Tolmie, Peter, Steve Benford, and Mark Rouncefield. 2013. “Playing in Irish Music
Sessions.” Pp. 227–56 in Ethnomethodology at Play, edited by P. Tolmie and M.
Rouncefield. Farnham, UK: Ashgate.
Tolmie, Peter, and Mark Rouncefield, eds. 2013. Ethnomethodology at Play. Farnham,
UK: Ashgate.
Traweek, Sharon. 1988. Beamtimes and Lifetimes: The World of High Energy Physics.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Weeks, Peter. 1996. “A Rehearsal of a Beethoven Passage: An Analysis of Correction
Talk.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 29:247– 90. doi: 10.1207/
s15327973rlsi2903_3.
Wilson, Thomas P. 2012. “Classical Ethnomethodology, the Radical Program, and
Conversation Analysis.” Pp. 207–38 in Interaction and Everyday Life: Phenomenological
and Ethnomethodological Essays in Honor of George Psathas, edited by H. Nasu and F. C.
Waksler. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
Winch, Peter. 1958. The Idea of a Social Science and Its Relation to Philosophy.
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1958. Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.
PART II
E MPIR IC A L IM PAC T
5
Sources of Issues and Ways of Working
An Introduction to the Study of Naturally Organized
Ordinary Activities*
Harold Garfinkel
*For an explanation about the origins of this chapter, see the Editors’ Note at the end of this chapter, pp. 159–60.
142 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
The steps of the argument are these. I want first to introduce to you the
“Missing Interactional What” of organizational objects. In order to justify the
claim of ethnomethodology’s discovery of naturally organized ordinary activi-
ties and to produce the claim to specifications, I shall need to demonstrate that
the Interactional What is essentially missing from lay and professional organiza-
tional studies and to provide for the Missing What as a technical phenomenon.
These are the technical aims of the paper’s arguments.
With the phenomena having been provisionally identified, three sources of
studies of that Missing What will be described: (l) the Missing What as it is avail-
able in “case materials” and ethnographic reportage; (2) the Missing What via
the analysis of Organizational Items; and (3) the Missing What in that it consists
of the practical objectivity and practical visibility of several systems of naturally
organized phenomena. Each source in ways particular to it, in its singular ways,
provides for issues of structures of social activities. However, the seriousness and
consequentiality of the claimed discovery turn on (3); and with it the strange,
discoverable, unsuspected and consequential thing structure is in practical
actions. These topics will be followed with (4) a summary.
Last January Harvey Sacks and I spent the day discussing an outlined manual
of studies that I asked him to criticize. He discussed at length a curiosity in the
history of work in the social sciences. He spoke of the absence of interactional
studies in professional studies of organization. His question was simple: How
could it be that bureaucracies, for example, would have been studied to such
depth of effort, care, and money and nevertheless that thing would have been
missed that ethnomethodologists are addressed to and are picking up endlessly
and on every side, to the point that whatever else might happen to our enterprise
it looks like we couldn’t be wrong on having picked up the presence in the world
of those interactional events. Sacks has this way of indicating the formidable
presence of interaction. He is doing this to indicate the massive endless business
of looking, nodding, shaking and the rest of it that makes itself present to anal-
ysis and demands our interest. Speaking past the suggestion with its use, several
observations make specific what Sacks is talking about.
just-
what of ordinary activities remains, for all practical purposes,
ignored, unknown, unsuspected, and unmissed as technical phenomena.
(iii) Taken together, (i) and (ii) compose a technical phenomenon. It is a
discoverable phenomenon—a discoverable phenomenon and not im-
aginable. It has been discovered in various activities and is being dis-
covered. It is consequential. And it is criterial. The phenomenon is
this: the essential, acknowledged, used, ignored relevance to the collab-
orated production of the structures of commonplace activities of the
circumstantial, embodied, interactional, just-so and-just-what of those
ordinary activities. That is what I take to be, at least if I need to put it
into a few slogans, we will call that the Missing What. Caution: That
statement is about the Missing What, about the Missing What in the
same way that an extensive list of studies exists, none of it reporting
(describing) the structures of practical action but composed instead
of studies about ethnomethodology, or studies about conversational
analysis. It is loose preparatory talk designed to convey transient
convictions of coherence and comprehensiveness but to be abandoned
at the first whiff of the world.
One further remark. The Missing What is not such as to make ordinary activi-
ties concrete. That is a prevailing notion. Instead, it consists of unavoidably jury
deliberations, of unavoidably searching for lost keys, of unavoidably improvised
jazz, or eligibility interviews, or kung-fu instruction, or Kpelle secrecy.
The interactional what of conversation’s activities is for the local production
cohort of conversationalists hopelessly “sensible,” unavoidably and without
remedy understood. The missing what provides, too, an unavoidable, irreme-
diable relevance to the local production cohort’s arts and sciences of practical
action, even while it remains ignored by these arts and sciences, unknown, and
unmissed as technical phenomena.
This Missing What can be provisionally identified with some “case materials,”
concluding with observations about ethnography: 1. Dave Sudnow’s observations
re: Howard Becker’s articles on jazz musicians; 2. The strange and recurrent prac-
tical fault of manuals of instruction that they omit exactly and delicately what
the novice most needs to know; 3. Traffic engineers’ analysis of context-specific
features of traffic streams; 4. Ethnographic reportage.
144 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Dave Sudnow, a jazz musician, on the basis of his studies of improvised jazz,1
called to my attention what he called the Howard Becker phenomena in the
sociological study of jazz.2 Becker’s studies he says can be read to learn about
jazz musicians, where they work, who they work with, what they earn, or how
they get their “gigs”; in the place where they are playing that there is an au-
dience, what the audience will request of them, and so on. But, says Sudnow,
nowhere in the articles can it be read, and no interrogation of the articles will
supply that in just those places, just those persons, with just who is there, and
at just that time, under the circumstances at hand, must in and as local work
make music together. Sudnow points to a curiosity of the reportage: The ar-
ticles omit entirely and exactly what the parties are doing that makes of what
they are doing for each other recognizably the just this, just so and just what
is going on, making music of a certain sort, and not in any which way, but in
the certain local, witnessed ways of musicians’ practices. That is omitted. It
cannot be recovered from the account. Instead the article provides the work
of the jazz musicians as something describable, but describable after, or in the
way, it has been disengaged from the occasion in which that work is done, and
is no longer referable to that work or needs to be or can be answerable to that
work to find its sense particularly.
The account construes that work according to an analytical contention of
that work as an occupation: where they play, whom they play with, what they
play, who is in the audience, how much they will get paid for it, how they ar-
range for jobs, and so on—all these gathered, written, understood, occupation-
ally relevant matters would be provided for. Throughout the text and wherever
occupationally relevant matters are provided for there, then just there in the
text at exactly and in just that place will be an omission. And because the omis-
sion is stable for those places it is a standing omission. The standing omis-
sion has to do with what those musicians in each other’s company in the place
where they are playing music together are doing to make of what they are
doing witnessably jazz music. The absence of descriptive/instructive literature
on musicians’ praxis is a complete absence, and is generalizable. A descrip-
tive/instructive literature can’t be found for occupational practices of any sort.
Instead in endless discussions and descriptions, work is handled in familiar
vernacular terms, arranged with the use of descriptive devices of the dictionary
of occupational titles. They provide a resemblance, a simulacrum of the situ-
ated organization of activities. They render accountable effective practices in a
sense of structure.
Sources of Issues and Ways of Working 145
2. Manuals
Traffic engineers have collections of policies and methods with which to specify
definitive structures of apparently ordinary activities of traffic streams. Their
studies are preoccupied with these events as self-producing, self-explicating phe-
nomena. By structures they understand activities, circumstances, movements,
reasoning, etc., in that according to drivers methods, (a) they exhibit the prop-
erties of uniformity, reproducibility, repetitiveness, standardization, typicality,
stability, direction, relevance, and so on; (b) these properties are independent of
local production cohorts of drivers; (c) local production cohort independence
is a phenomenon for drivers’ (members’) recognition; and (d) the phenomena
(a), (b) and (c) are every local production cohort’s practical, circumstantial
accomplishment.
Several years ago I began to study context-specific features of traffic streams
because of the promising and deep problems they pose. One of these: instead of
models for events of traffic streams being devices for analyzing these phenomena,
the models owe their cogency, consistency, perspicuity, and every other beautiful
logical property to the matters of that and how they are constituent parts of the
phenomena they analyze. We began to collect and analyze videotaped photo-
graphic materials of traffic stream events from the point of view of the driving.
These materials were examined for the purpose of deciding and documenting
the feasibility and consequences of formulating, with their use, an alternative
policy to the policies of constructive analysis that prevail when context-specific
events of traffic streams are analyzed by traffic engineers.
We thought of the problems to be solved as follows. When prevailing policies
are used to describe and explain traffic streams the task is done by formulating
driver-witnessable activities as ideal accounts of “actual activities like these.”
Customarily a mathematical analysis of the ideal is carried out to provide prop-
erties of the ideal. These are then assigned to the actual driving practices. That
is, it is implicitly assumed that these mathematically derived properties are ex-
istent in the actual driving practices and recommendations for the alterations of
driving environment, and driving practices are imagined and justified in terms
of these ideal properties.
Almost all traffic researchers analyze context-specific properties in this way.
Well known successes accompany that policy. Well known, but little understood
embarrassments accompany it, too. Several may be mentioned.
We found that a basic problem confronts traffic research. That problem is to de-
scribe (a) the flow and (b) how the flow “got that way.” Describing the flow is
accomplishable with the aid of various kinds of recording devices that are usually
placed outside the flow. Describing how the flow got that way has not yet been
satisfactorily accomplished. It is the hope of most traffic engineers that (b) is re-
coverable from (a). Thus they invent models that answer (b) and reproduce (a).
However, the problem immediately arises that there are many models that an-
swer (b) and reproduce (a) which are incompatible with each other. Thus, having
the property of “answering (b) reproducing (a)” is not sufficient to guarantee that
a model explains how the flow “got that way.”
We propose to analyze the flow from inside the flow, and in doing so to answer
(b). From our answer of (b) we will then recover (a). Since our answer of (b) will
actually be generated from the flow—as opposed to being invented to answer
(b)—we feel confident that the properties that we describe will actually exist in
the flow, i.e., that they are findable. However, we are presented with the task of
recovering the properties of the flow as an entity from observations made by a
part of the flow. To carry out this analysis it is required that we describe the phe-
nomena of local production cohorts and their properties.4
148 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
situations to persuade people to the view that this kind of work is worth some-
thing; that it has a currency. It is possible to hear in it that it deals with recogniz-
able persons in real affairs. For teaching I can recommend them. They are easy
stuff. Particularly where novices are concerned they permit you to start with fa-
miliar territory and to move around in it.
There are also grounds for dissatisfaction. The practices of practical action and
practical reasoning—reported as the work of coders, of juror’s deliberations, the
investigations of suicidal deaths at the Suicide Prevention Center—are “naturally
available”: they are recognized by members; they are recognized by members
to be unavoidable; members recognize them as well to be unavoidable, and
members recognize them as storyable practices—practices that are available to
them for the telling. They are available through and by reason of the mastery of
natural language, which is to say, they are ethnographically available. Finally, the
natural availability is itself a phenomenon for members. The availability of that
recognition together with the willingness and the ability to use the recognition
for further inquiries turns on the mastery of a certain practiced way of speaking
among us. I am not talking only of professional shoptalk. Then telling these prop-
erties elicit certifying remarks like, “Yeah, I know what you are talking about.
I have seen that. It happened to a cousin of mine that. . . .” And all the rest of this
stuff that composes the recognition as a usable thing.
Although ethnography can deal with the missing what, it does so in the pe-
culiar fashion in which persons, who know what the ethnographer is talking
about, can hear him talking about just that, and can talk about the matter in a
similar manner. Talking-amongst-us is the heart of it. When the talking gets
done, whether it is done in the writing, the teaching, or the storytelling, it doesn’t
provide for the kind of “technical instruments” that are prevalent or make up
the art of talk. Instead, it uses naturally the arts of talk, and lets it go for the time
being what that instrument might consist of until the issue “matures.” Where
the arts of writing, of being able to write in formatted fashion from beginning
to end, displaying a step-wise, developing course via appropriate connectives,
via thus-es, and-it-followed-thens, narrative markers and the rest—these can be
used to make cogent, clear, credible, deliverable, plausible, questionable, all the
beautiful things that need to be claimed on behalf of the thing talked about, even
that one is speaking in a referentially appropriate way (which is itself an enor-
mous achievement). All that can be done between us. Parties to that enterprise,
like professional sociologists, end up reading the stuff on documentary method
as if it was interpreted to catch as a way of working the word of street interviews
and survey procedures. Persons who had any experience with that work would
say things like, “that sounds pretty good,” “it sounds right,” “in my own case it
happened that. . . .” You get into exchanges of experience like that; of “trading up’ ”
recognized topics to establish the facts of life.
150 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
These are grounds for dissatisfaction where issues of the circumstantial rel-
evance of structure, the circumstantial production—the embodied produc-
tion of structure of service lines are contingent achievements, problematic to
queues, or to the embodied production of the structures of turn taking, or to
the use of manuals, manuals, maps, etc.5—assure that the studies of structure
are defeated if the missing what is grounded in ethnography. Studies of the
missing what grounded in ethnography are essentially unable to encounter ad-
dress, formulate, or settle issues of structure. Where issues of the situated and
circumstantial production of structures are of interest, in that and in the ways
ethnomethodologically speaking that their circumstantial production is prob-
lematic, the study of structure is defeated when the missing what is grounded in
ethnographic reportage. Characteristically attempts to provide the missing what
via ethnographic reportage occur in the work of novices, in the work of persons
who are self-taught in ethnomethodology, in the work of those who seek to do
ethnomethodological studies of the structures of practical reasoning and prac-
tical action but avoid each in its own ways, or remain indifferent to the work
of conversational analysis, gives causes for complaint or dissatisfaction where
ethnomethodologists’ studies of structure are of interest.
Not all the work of ethnomethodologists, however, is of that sort.
A contrasting treatment of the missing what consists of a compendium of
(singular or particular) closely analyzed organizational objects. The work of
Sacks and Schegloff and their coworkers on the events of conversation provide
an immense corpus of such object events. But there is the work of others too.
Cicourel’s6 studies of lay and professional practices in assembling and analyzing
rates make up part of this compendium of organizational objects. Recently,
I have been examining “formatting” in queues,7 by which I mean that person[s]
in the way in which they are positioned with respect to a serving function can
display by their positioning the presence to persons in the queue of an order
of service that is itself available to queuers in all of the events, features that
the order of service can be said fairly to compose, but which requires for the
practical objectivity and visibility of its features one’s motivated, committed,
or interested presence to the same order of service as a member of the line.
The phenomena of formatting in queues include among the queue’s practical
objectivity and observability for queuers’ accountable features the presence
of reckoning procedures which are “parts” of the queue in the way that any
other features are parts of the queues, but are available to the members, for
which the line itself, in the kind of ordering activity it consists of, provides
for the full array of its members as worldly things in-of-and-as the system that
“incorporates” them, that “includes” them, or that “gathers” them. To explicate
those terms you are required to go into the queue to find how they are being
made out for the “accountable character” of its own activities and features.
Sources of Issues and Ways of Working 151
(1) Finding, collecting and analyzing organizational items, in, of, and as
various enterprises of ordinary activities. Greetings-in-of-and-as con-
versational activity is an organizational item. Story-telling, topicality, or
turn-taking in, of, and as conversational activity are other organizational
items, as are place in line, place holding, waiting, or place reckoning in, of,
and as queues.
(2) An enterprise’s Organizational Items are then gathered as an “Activity.”
The gathering is critical. I refer to gathering in the active way in which
an Item having been possibly discovered, immediately sets up the rele-
vance of it to Items to which it beckons and is beckoned for its relevancies
and “companionability.” That they are gathered into an Activity means
that they are increasingly justifiable as elucidations of their coherent or-
ganization, of their coherent course. It is not that conversation stands
independent of and indifferent to, and, as a rich resource is endlessly
available to inquiries that learn this and that about it so that an amount
of ignorance is transferred from one mound to the other. An ordering of
Organizational Items is itself unavoidably a discoverable matter. In its dis-
covery—in the developing discovery—it reveals the work which is hidden
in the character of the activities that originally beckoned the inquiry. So
the claim that one has provided for the turn-taking organization of con-
versational activity comes only after long and arduous investigation into
conversations’ Organizational Items, and not conversations generally
152 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
(l) With respect to issues (i.e., phenomena that call for further description/
instruction) of their objectivity and observability that are collected in and
posed by the properties of the social facticities, if there are things in the
world like greetings in conversation, then the matters that Sacks and com-
pany have been describing are greetings in conversation. The first thing
that we come upon is not a way to begin, but a way in which, as a worldly
beginning we find ourselves in the midst of and in easy and ordinary rec-
ognition of the worldly events: greetings. Not greetings as worldly events;
not greetings whose presence poses questions of their worldliness, but
worldly events, greetings—greetings in-of-and-as-the world. I don’t find
greetings in the world: I find greetings. Better: when I listen to the tape, I
hear the exchange of greetings.
154 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
For sociological inquiry and the problem of social order, for sociological in-
quiry, which is the problem of making researchable the real world of everyday
activities as occasioned structures, was to be realized by explicating Gestalt co-
herence as a practical achievement, i.e., as an organizational achievement. There
are a lot of claims on that score. I wouldn’t give a dime for the best of them. I’m
putting my bets elsewhere than with Sapir-Whorf linguistics, cognitive anthro-
pology, Cassirer’s phenomenology, Schütz’s “structures of relevance,” etc., etc. The
work of Sacks and Schegloff provides the strongest criticism of these treatments
by showing actual research consequences of using a corpus of materials to mo-
tivate these issues, as compared with principled treatments or uses of practical
metaphysical devices. The crux of their treatment is this: Their work provides an
unprincipled version of that coherence. Unless they can find the coherence arising
Sources of Issues and Ways of Working 155
(3) A third collection of properties are called “the structures.” That feature
of conversational activity for conversationalists the presence to them of
uniform standard, repetitive, typical, directedness, etc., which are inde-
pendent of the local production cohort independence, exhibit as well rec-
ognized local practical achievements. Traffic events are located by getting
to the places where driving is going on. When you get to the place where
driving is going on the driving is what Sacks would speak of as a “com-
petent system”; it is already available just-there to parties to drive and to
driving and in ways that are peculiar to driving it provides for drivers, just
as conversations provides singularly for conversationalists, and queues
for queuers. Whether we are dealing with driving as competent systems
or conversations as competent systems the idea is that these systems are
available for the practitioners. They are available—they are present to—
they are practically objective and observable for the practitioners who use
those systems.
(4) The social facts are with respect to their accountability indefinitely dense.
Which is to say, with respect to their ways of being made matters for
observations and report, with respect to their ways of being made matters
are seeable-s ayable; matters witnessable-for-telling-for-w hosoever-
has-cause-to-s ee-and-tell; matters witnessable-in-a-phrase-after-a-
long-prolix-story-about-it-able; matters witnessable-for-the-gist-of-a
grunt-like-“oh, that . . .”-able, and see who that is and not everybody is
privileged to the that. It is not that we are in the same world. It has nothing
to do with the same world. It has only to do with the world; it has to do
with worldly things.
Big point: if we are to be all that careful in the way we talk, then surely we
are not talking in an advisory way about how we could come into the presence
of those things because we come to them in a very peculiar fashion: Namely,
our methods will be uniquely adequate to the phenomena that they find. And
that is another property of the social facts: they are uniquely adequate to the
phenomena that they find. And in that way we encounter the awesome phe-
nomenon that not any name will do. In some cases not any name will do; and
in other cases we are into the full nominalistic thing. If we are finding nomi-
nalism then it has to be in-of-and-as features of organizational objects. When
they are found in that way they will be called natural names. That is a bit of
local usage. I’m telling you a property of natural names: namely, they are indef-
initely dense. There is no end to them. That is to begin with, that there is no end
156 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
to them. They have other properties too that we need to take note of as we come
to examine them further.
(5) Another property, a lovely big property: the recognition of the social facts
is done—more than done, the recognition entails—more than entails,
the recognition is fateful—it is inescapably ethnomethodologically a
recognition done via a vulgar competence. Done via a vulgar competence
means it is done without thought for credentials, or maybe not thought for
credentials, but without requirements of credentials. If there are thoughts
and requirements for credentials they occur in that the phenomenon is
present as a worldly thing in the first place. So that it is already available to
the vulgar competence and on those grounds can announce itself as ques-
tionable, even as questionable to the philosophies, to the major philoso-
phies, where, what the general structures of experience or activity might
be, in general are provided for in the vulgar competence of the presence in
the first place to a question, or of a question. Hume, even while he would
have brought the entirety of the presence of the ordinary world under
question, could wonder that he could do this but at the cost of forgetting
all of it once he closed the door to his study and left it behind for the day.
You can so imagine the world as to require it to answer to every claim that
it exercises for its existence. You can do that as long as you close the door
to the study to get it done. Big problem: that vulgar competence study of
structures of practical action. Vulgar competence comes up for thematic
treatment in all of our rival treatments of the “problem of structure.”
(6) The vernacular way to speak of the sensible presence of an organizational
object is provided for by that object as an observable in its own right. The
observable in its own right exhibits itself in and through an embodied
presence of an observable in its own right. The features of conversation
that wait for me to find them out, jump off the transcript; they jump out of
the text; they stand forth in the tape to be heard again when once I passed
them by, to be recalled over and over again, to be played and therein or
thereby to be available over and over without change. They stand, they
are available in that lovely, beautiful way that we call it: objectively. They
are available in their fashion as objects; there for the taking, announcing
themselves. They are available, according to the work of a “observances.”
Not as disengaged spectacle but as observances. Think of an observance
according to the precepts of ceremonial work. Or think of the events of
a game with rules like chess or poker and of your being in their presence
in the way a chess player whose play satisfied the precepts of chess as a
game with rules is “into chess” and thereby the game’s events are sensible,
factual, objective, available in-of-and-as the observances of the game. Be
Sources of Issues and Ways of Working 157
Summary
Over the years that it has been going on, we have come in the presence of the
missing what of organization. So far: (1) I have identified provisionally the
missing what; (2) I wrote of its availability via case studies as matters of ethno-
graphic reportage. It is available (3) also in the compendium of these organiza-
tional event as the properties of Organizational Items. And (4), I wrote about the
Missing What with respect to their objectivity and observability.
What is next? Next are the claims that naturally organized ordinary activities
are fundamental phenomena in ethnomethodologists’ studies.
(1) In that we or any others not only in the professions but wherever organ-
ized activity is provided for in things like bureaucracies, families, small
groups, gangs, role relationships and so on, endlessly, these lay and pro-
fessional provided-for organizations of ordinary activities are unim-
portant phenomena. When compared to the astronomical magnitude
of organization in everyday activities they are of miniscule importance.
Let me specify this claim with a figure of speech. With respect to the cir-
cumference of the earth Mount Everest has the prominence, importance
and relevance of a pock mark on a billiard ball. The missing what that
ethnomethodologists have been at the work of discovering is to available
lay and professional versions of organization in ordinary activities as the
earth stands to the presence of Mount Everest. Orderings of ordinary ac-
tivities are imaginably extensive phenomenon; they are essentially other
than we do or could ever imagine them to be; and they await discovery.
They are available only to the work of discovery. They are not available to
any and all of the beautiful devices that the arts and sciences of practical
action and practical discourse provide as work for uncovering or coming
upon these organizational phenomena. The claim is this: there is one hell
of a lot of it, more than we can ever imagine, more than we ever would
158 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
have imagined, where the more is such that we couldn’t have imagined it
without the work behind us.
(2) Lay and professional theories of organization essentially misconceive
the phenomena of organization. The world is filled with sociolog-
ical descriptions that analyze a phenomenon that they are witnessably
about, and do so in the ways that they are parts of the phenomena that
they analyze. That formula has frequently been invoked in order to bring
up the phenomena of reflexive accountability, and to urge it as the sine
qua non of ethnomethodology’s enterprises. But that reflexive account-
ability is a phenomenon for ethnomethodological study. It is surely not
the phenomenon; it is not criterial of ethnomethodology. The reflex-
ivity of a question consists of the way a question is part of the activity it
questions. And so on for the “reflexivity” of names, diagrams, slogans,
instructions, or maps. That proposal delivers no news and solves no
problems of structure. Its virtue is as a research precept it points to pe-
culiar things that descriptions, names or instructions can be when they
are parts of the setting as of which describe, name, or instruct. In this
sense that and how descriptions “do the work” of describing, questions
“the work” of questioning, doubts of doubting, and all the other things
that local practices are heard for, analyzed as structures of the settings
as of which they are naturally present. Indeed reflexivity is a minus-
cule phenomenon and does not rate a second glance compared with
the overlooked embodied presence of natural organization as man’s so-
cial state.
Sacks points out whoever would have thought that this was what sociologists
were getting into when as standing policy sociology proposed that man is a
social animal. We have hardly begun to know its technical import; though we
can by some present findings surmise how immensely extensive that may be.
Sacks’s claims that no matter to what depth of detail conversational events have
been examined the examination has yet to run out of conversational events
(Organizational Items). The attempt several years ago by Kroeber and Parsons
to set straight what the issues were vis-à-vis cultural and social systems can be
considered theoretic baby talk. I’m saying that flatly; I’m not saying maybe. To
say that they provided access to the study of phenomena of organization is only
to allow that that thing that they went to such care to provide for as a method
that would give sociologists principled access in collecting their thoughts about
organized activity missed essentially what the phenomenon was and thereby
missed essentially—by essentially I mean missed without the possibility of
repairing it in those terms and in doing it in that way—access to what organiza-
tion was in the world.
Sources of Issues and Ways of Working 159
In the original paper, the first paragraph of Chapter 5 herein begins immediately
after this paragraph. Courtesy of the Harold Garfinkel Archives.
References
Becker, Howard S. 1951. “The Professional Dance Musician and His Audience.” American
Journal of Sociology 57(2):136–44.
Cicourel, Aaron V. 1963. Method and Measurement in Sociology. New York: The Free Press.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1967. Studies in Ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1996. “Ethnomethodology’s Program.” Social Psychology Quarterly
59:5–21.
Garfinkel, Harold. 2002. Ethnomethodology’s Program. Lanham, MD: Rowman &
Littlefield.
Sources of Issues and Ways of Working 161
Garfinkel, Harold, and Eric Livingston. 2003. “Phenomenal Field Properties of Order in
Formatted Queues and Their Neglected Standing in the Current Situation of Inquiry.”
Visual Studies 18(1):21–28.
Garfinkel, Harold, and Harvey Sacks. 1970. “On Formal Structures of Practical Actions.”
Pp. 337–66 in Theoretical Sociology, edited by J. D. McKinney and E. A. Tiryakian.
New York: Appleton-Century Crofts.
Sacks, Harvey, Emanuel A. Schegloff, and Gail Jefferson. 1974. “A Simplest Systematics for
the Organization of Turn-Taking for Conversation.” Language 50:696–735.
Sudnow, D. 1978. Ways of the Hand. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
6
Rules and Policeable Matters
Enforcing the Civil Sidewalk Ordinance for
“Another First Time”
Geoffrey Raymond, Lillian Jungleib, Don Zimmerman, and Nikki Jones
In his dissertation and later writings, Garfinkel recognized that the norma-
tive paradigm’s view of rules misunderstands basic elements of social action and
massively constrains the scope of sociological inquiry. It may be useful to ex-
plicate two interrelated elements of the normative paradigm as a way to begin
to understand the focus of Garfinkel’s critique: The treatment of interaction as
essentially rule-governed and the assumption that “sociological explanations
should properly take the deductive form characteristic of the natural sciences”
(Wilson 1970:59). Ultimately, it was this latter commitment, influenced by
the logical empiricism of the Vienna school social theorists (e.g., Hempel and
Nagel), that drove mid-twentieth-century sociologists to embrace a range of
assumptions about rules that turned out to be problematic.
Proponents of the normative paradigm argued that patterns of social
actions, and the stability of the social system of which they are a part, can be
explained by the complementary relationship between “needs dispositions”
that actors develop via processes of socialization (Parsons and Shils 1951:115,
see also Homans 1958) and the sanctioned expectations associated with the in-
stitutionalized roles those actors may occupy in their interactions with others
(Merton 1968; Parsons 1937). In this approach, “actors acquire characteristic
purposes and motives, that is dispositions, by virtue of their differential loca-
tion in society, and . . . they act in accordance to organized structures of expec-
tations supported by sanctions” (Wilson 1970:64; see Parsons and Shils 1951).
Crucially, these dispositions and expectations are treated as governing or regu-
lating action insofar as the theory treats them as the link between actors’ situ-
ations and their actions in those situations.
These same elements are, in turn, crucial for the sort of deductive model of ex-
planation that Parsons and others, following the logical positivism of the Vienna
school, viewed as characteristic of science. The aim of a deductive explanation is
to demonstrate that observable facts can be logically deduced from theoretical
concepts and empirical indicators (Wilson 1970). In the normative paradigm’s
approach to explain the causes of social action, theoretical premises would con-
sist of the theory’s model of the actor (e.g., with socially derived motives and a
capacity for communication that arises out of a shared symbol system), and empir-
ical indicators would consist of the normative expectations embedded in the so-
cial system in which she encounters others. Garfinkel (1967) famously noted that
such a theory renders social actors “judgmental dopes” because norms push and
pull them through their encounters with others, but they never have to choose,
judge, or reason. Moreover, because the analyst recruits rules, norms, and values
primarily to explain departures from “rationality” (i.e., why actors choose goals
or means of achieving them that cost them in terms of efficiency), the focus of so-
cial inquiry is reduced to a “sociology of error” (Heritage 1984:41; see also Bloor
1973) in which analysts become preoccupied with the distance between ordinary
164 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
and scientific reasoning, and with explaining why, on occasion, people depart
from rules or fail to meet expectations (see Garfinkel, Chapter 2, pp.81–83).
Drawing on insights from Wittgenstein and Schutz, Garfinkel shows that a
range of the normative paradigm’s underlying assumptions about rules turn out
to be problematic and limiting (Heritage 1984:110–15; Wilson 1970). As we shall
see, although developed independently of Garfinkel and others, H. L. A. Hart’s
Finitist critique of rules as regulators of conduct arrives at some of the very same
conclusions. In the following paragraphs, we focus on two of these assumptions.
First, these approaches assume that the application and use of rules in actual
situations and settings are largely straightforward or unproblematic. For this to
be so, however, one must make two further assumptions: (i) that both the rule
itself and the conditions of its use can be sufficiently elaborated to account for
the entire range of circumstances in which it might be applied; and (ii) that each
person using the rule has an identical understanding of it, the conditions of its
use, and any circumstance in which it is actually applied (Wilson 1970). From
accounts of even the simplest unwritten norms and rules that govern mundane
or everyday conduct (such as greetings and their return; see Heritage 1984:110–
15) to the application of laws in liberal democracies, however, these assumptions
have proven to be problematic. In a most basic sense, rules cannot apply them-
selves. As H. L. A. Hart (1961) argued,
Particular fact situations do not await us already marked off from each other,
and labeled as instances of a general rule, the application of which is in ques-
tion; nor can the rule itself step forward to claim its own instances. As a conse-
quence, persons acting in concert with others must apply rules, and in doing so
they must draw on interpretive resources to make sense of their settings, situ-
ations and choices. (1961:126)
Garfinkel (1967:21) found that in applying rules, members draw on “such con-
siderations as ‘et cetera,’ ‘unless,’ ‘let it pass’ and ‘factum valet’ ” to manage the
fundamentally open range of circumstances that any rule must cover, and thus
the wide range of meanings that may be associated with their use in specific
circumstances.
The use of these practices can be illustrated using simple traffic laws, such as
the requirement that drivers stop at an intersection when a traffic light is red. If
we take for granted the cultural, technical, and historical specifity of this rule
(and the use of cars and stop-lights), we can note that the use, application, and
meaning of it appears to be strightforward. And to be sure, persons for the most
part stop at such lights. In the US context, however, drivers arriving at an inter-
section finding a yellow (or warning light) must make complex judgments about
whether to stop before the intersection or proceed through it (even if it may turn
Rules and Policeable Matters 165
red while they are still crossing it). Complicating matters still further, however,
the courts have ruled that drivers can proceed through an intersection against a
red light if they believe the light to be malfunctioning, or that their vehicle is too
light to trip the sensors that govern its operations. Even these simple exceptions
raise yet more problems: What sort of events must transpire to enable a stopped
driver to recognize a malfunctioning light? What are the methods for proceeding
through an intersection against the light? How might another driver or police of-
ficer recognize a driver’s beliefs about the traffic light? As these example suggest,
even the most basic rules must “cover an indefinite range of contingent, concrete
possibilities. The rules must, in short, be applied, and to specific configurations
of circumstances which may never be identical” (Heritage 1984:121). In this
way, any use of a rule casts an occasion as a further instance of a common cir-
cumstance, as “generic,” often giving rise to a sense of “this again” (another red
light), even as any specific application is unavoidably contingent, variable, and
context specific (see Maynard and Clayman 2018). Thus, Garfinkel’s pithy obser-
vation that rules “are always applied ‘for another first time’ ” (Heritage 1984:390)
reminds us that “features of social life can embody both distinctiveness and re-
currence,” and that both “are equally fair game for analytic explication” (Maynard
and Clayman 2018:134).
Second, these approaches assume that rules, norms, and laws hover above or
outside of settings, institutions, and actions, and thus that their actual use on
specific occasions is essentially uninteresting. In viewing rules in such an ideal-
ized way, analyses of the use and application of rules tend to lose just how those
using rules “render such idealizations relevant as prescriptions, justifications,
descriptions, or accounts of their activities” (Zimmerman 1970:223). Rather
than being viewed as above, or outside of institutions and situations, Garfinkel
argued that rules, norms, and laws “can be treated as topics and as features of
the very settings they are taken to organize” (Maynard and Clayman 1991:390).
Accordingly, Garfinkel’s re-specification highlights the embodied character of
rule use: rules are used by actual people, with agency, acting in the company of
other people, also with agency, managing situations whose salient features and
participants’ orientations to them have to be coordinated. Thus, those using rules
are agents in situations in which their actions have consequences that overflow
the literal sense of a rule, while they nevertheless remain accountable to it.
This approach is perhaps nowhere more masterfully demonstrated than in
Bittner’s analysis of the work-a-day world of policing (Bittner 1967b, 1967a;
see also Meehan 1989, 2006). His (Bittner 1967b) observations on the peace-
keeping practices used by police patrolling skid row open an especially vivid
window into the ways in which participants orient to, invoke, and use rules and
laws in their encounters. Officers’ efforts to manage the “virtually limitless” do-
main of their service activity results in an approach at odds with conventional
166 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
. . . it is the rare exception that the law is invoked merely because the
specifications of the law are met. That is, compliance with the law is merely the
outward appearance of an intervention that is actually based on altogether dif-
ferent considerations. Thus, it could be said that patrolmen do not really en-
force the law, even when they do invoke it, but merely use it as a resource to
solve certain pressing practical problems in keeping the peace. (1967b:710)
The CSO, which was adopted by voters in Golden City in November 2010, is
simple enough: it prohibits persons from sitting or lying on the sidewalk between
7 a.m. and 11 p.m., with certain exceptions.1 Drawing on a database of several
hundred hours of video and interviews collected in ride-alongs with the Golden
City Police Department, this chapter explicates how officers and residents use
and make sense of the law across a range of settings and activities and how they
manage what are formulated as sanctioned exceptions to it. The analysis we
develop depends on the data supplied by both the researcher’s presence (as an
ethnographic observer) across a range of settings and times where the law is en-
forced and the video recordings they made of those encounters. The first allows
the use of the law in practice to be witnessed across the contingencies of situ-
ations of its use, while the latter preserves the details of those encounters for re-
view and analysis.
The CSO is one of many quality-of-life laws adopted to help the city manage
nonviolent activities considered nuisances in public spaces. The Golden
City Police Department identifies 36 such laws, more than any other city in
California, intended to “protect the well-being of [non-homeless] residents”
and “preserve the quality of public spaces” (Budget and Legislative Analyst’s
Office 2016). These include regulations concerning sitting, sleeping, eating,
urinating/defecating, camping, panhandling, soliciting, drinking in public,
Rules and Policeable Matters 167
and so on. Because most of the behaviors they prohibit are not wrong in and
of themselves (they fall under the legal rubric mala prohibita, or “wrong as or
because prohibited”) and would not be illegal were they to occur on a person’s
private property (e.g., in contrast to mala in se crimes such as assault, theft,
rape, murder, etc.), quality-of-life laws disproportionately impact chronically
homeless citizens.2 Although communities ostensibly adopt such quality-of-life
laws to provide law enforcement officials the legal means to manage forms of
conduct that can lead to disputes and other forms of disorder, sociologists have
argued that they are perhaps better understood as emerging out of “society’s
perception of a continuing need to control some of its ‘suspicious’ or ‘undesir-
able’ members” (Chambliss 1964:75).
Quality-of-life laws, such as the CSO, emerged after the broad vagrancy laws
of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries were declared unconstitutional (in the
US Supreme Court decision Papachristou v. City of Jacksonville 405 US, 1972).
In this legal environment, cities responded to growing populations of home-
less persons in the 1980s by adopting more narrowly targeted laws that banned
specific behaviors in specific places, creating a network of laws that effectively
criminalize “life-sustaining behaviors” of the chronically homeless (Coalition on
Homelessness 2015). Such quality-of-life laws targeting the chronically homeless
citizens are on the rise across the country (National Law Center on Homelessness
and Poverty 2014).
In Golden City, the CSO emerged out of a successful campaign by business
owners in the Park neighborhood. Contending that the presence of chronically
homeless residents in the neighborhood was bad for business, shop owners
formed the Coalition for Safe Sidewalks (City Hall Fellows 2012) with the aim of
providing law enforcement officials additional tools to address problems they as-
sociated with chronic homelessness, including public safety concerns, discour-
aging tourism, and preventing potential customers from entering businesses.
Opponents argued that the law unjustly criminalizes homelessness and that ex-
isting laws already provided officers with resources for addressing any legitimate
safety concerns (City Hall Fellows 2012).
Officers enforcing the CSO refer to their encounters as “move-alongs” because
their basic aim is to move the subject from the current position or place. The
formal contents of CSO are straightforward and unambiguous: persons are pro-
hibited from sitting or lying on any public sidewalks between the hours of 7 a.m.
and 11 p.m., though persons can only be ticketed and fined for the offense after
they have been warned or informed of its provisions. The ordinance also includes
escalating penalties ranging from fines ($50–$100) up through a misdemeanor
offense with a penalty of 30 days in county jail if a person fails to comply with an
officer’s directives or is found sitting or lying on a public sidewalk for a second
time within 24 hours.3
168 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
We can render the gross outlines of the practicalities of rule use observable by
considering the hypothetical case of a “strict” or literal enforcement of the CSO.
Were officers to follow the letter of the law, they would be required to ticket, fine,
or arrest most of the homeless people they encounter on a daily basis, and would
spend virtually all of their time keeping these residents on their feet for 16 hours a
day—knowing that they will encounter the very same people and circumstances
the following day. To avoid the conflicts and endless entanglements that a strict
enforcement style would entail, officers and homeless residents have arrived at
a range of unwritten, tacit agreements regarding when, where, and how the or-
dinance will typically be enforced. In this respect, the patterns of enforcement
that have emerged over time reflect a set of tacit agreements between officers and
the chronically homeless population regarding which aspects of street life are,
and are not, “police-able” (Meehan 1989). These broad, unwritten agreements
enable its primary targets—the chronically homeless residents of the city4—to
anticipate how the ordinance will be enforced, and thus to conduct themselves in
accordance with its basic provisions most of the time. It is the participants’ use of
the rule in practice, fitted to the exigencies of actual scenes of social activity, that
we explicate in what follows.
In a most basic sense, officers invoke the ordinance and its exceptions as re-
sources for distinguishing police-able problems from other concerns, thereby
minimizing the degree to which they become enmeshed in the routine personal
and medical problems of the homeless residents they encounter, or entangled in
the provision of solutions to the large-scale, chronic social conditions that give
rise to their predicament in the first place. That is, officers invoke the ordinance
and its provisions to distinguish police-able circumstances from ones that they
deem beneath or beyond the scope of their authority. These considerations, and
analyses of the specific circumstances in which these practical determinations
are made, however, reveal a range of other phenomena tied to the characteristics
of the ordinance and aspects of the settings and persons it targets. In addition to
the specific sense that participants make of individual encounters, these include
the participants’ reflexive orientation to the distribution of knowledge they treat
as a condition of the ordinance’s use and links between an officer’s authority to
enforce the ordinance and tacit agreements regarding when, where, and how the
CSO is typically enforced.
doing so, we consider variations in the ways that officers and residents initiate
and conduct these encounters, focusing on two basic features: how subjects
are positioned as accountable for violating the CSO, and how officers raise or
probe how and what the subjects know about the CSO. In contrast to mala in
se offenses, officers cannot assume that residents are aware of mala prohibita
offenses such as the CSO because they apply to ordinary forms of conduct that
are legal in most other circumstances. Indeed, the text of the CSO stipulates
that persons cannot be cited for violating it until they have been warned of
its provisions (Golden City Municipal Code, Section 168 (d), p. 69). In addi-
tion, precisely because the CSO prohibits conduct that is not otherwise mor-
ally problematic, officers and residents may view aspects of its enforcement
as unjust or problematic even in circumstances where all agree that persons
are subject to its provisions. For example, in an interview, one officer explains
feeling “pulled in two different directions” by the need to respond to pressures
from some community members who “don’t like the way [chronic homeless-
ness] looks” and the desire to “uphold the rights of homeless citizens” (GCPD
PA 05172012 3 Interview1, Urban Camper Ethnographic Interview). In ana-
lyzing these encounters, then, we will track how officers and residents invoke
knowledge of the CSO and the ways in which participants use the occasions of
its enforcement to delineate the moral, legal, and personal dimensions of these
occasions.
We begin by considering a simple instance of enforcement in which both the
officers and the subject treat their shared background knowledge of the CSO as
a basis for making sense of the subject’s violation of it, and the ways that each is
accountable to the other for aspects of its enforcement. In Extract (1), two officers
walking through a park find a man lying down in a sleeping bag with his eyes
closed. Following an opening in which the officers identify themselves and ex-
change greetings with the subject, the latter anticipates the reason for the encounter
by explaining how they came to find him in his current position (lines 7, 9).
(1) GCPD_SleepingManinPark2_CE_06212012.mov
The subject’s preemptive explanation (in lines 7 and 9) reveal the cognitive and
moral dimensions of the ways participants use rules. In a most basic sense,
the subjects’ explanations anticipate that the officers have contacted him for
violating the CSO. In this respect, the subject’s knowledge of the rule, to-
gether with his reflexive awareness that he is currently violating it, provides a
basis for making sense of the officers’ presence and the project that prompted
them to initiate contact. But his claims also reveal his orientation to the moral
dimensions of violating a rule: he claims that this violation (and perhaps the
failure to take remedial action before the officers contacted him, see Extract
4) was an accident—an inadvertent, unintentional byproduct of falling asleep
(line 9; see cases 7, 8, 11, and 12 for cases in which the very same states of af-
fairs, lying down and even sleeping, are treated as unremarkable). After regis-
tering and appreciating the subject’s account (lines 10 and 11), FPO explicitly
invokes the CSO by inviting the subject to confirm that he “knows” about its
provisions (lines 13–14). This apparently simple utterance indexes a range of
contextual features of the encounter:
• Its design strongly presumes that subject knows about the law via the use of
a “you know” prefaced declarative with an appended tag question (Heritage
and Raymond 2012), providing a potential challenge to the subject’s ac-
counts (in lines 7 and 9) which treated sleeping, rather than lying down per
se, as accountable.
• The strength of the officer’s presumption takes into account the subject’s
preemptive account and the officer’s categorization of him as a chronically
homeless person; she goes on to offer a range of services that are available
to him as a homeless veteran. (See Extract 6 for a case involving a potentially
homeless subject that disclaims any knowledge of the CSO.)
Rules and Policeable Matters 171
quality-of-life laws use similar formulations to invoke the basis on which their
recipients do or should know about the law they are currently violating, as in the
following cases.
(2) GCPD_YouKnowYouCantBeSellinHere_MI_08122013.mov
1 MPO: > You know you can't be sellin here. We’ve had this
2 conversa:tion before
3 CF1: I kno:::w.
(3) GCPD_NoTrespassingSign_MI_08122013.mov
Evidently officers use such formulations to establish that their recipients should
or do already know that they are violating the law, as well as how they could or
do know, as a way of directing them to resolve the matter. That is, by recurrently
invoking a local basis for their inferences about what recipients’ could or should
know about the ordinances they are violating (i.e., they have told the person be-
fore in 2, or the subject could the read posted signage in 3), the officers tacitly ac-
knowledge that the possession of such knowledge is a contingent, rather than an
obligatory (and thus moral) matter, even as they hold the subject accountable for
knowing it. And yet in Extract 2 a different form of moral accountability can be
observed: The subject’s stretched “I know” (line 3) confirms the officer’s assertion
that he has already warned her (see Mikesell et al., 2017), thereby tacitly acknow-
ledging the personal nature of her transgression (i.e., the same officer has caught
her for a second time).
Of course, the very fact that the officers have contacted the subject to issue a
reminder suggests a kind of failing beyond the violation of the ordinance itself. As
these cases suggest, officers don’t always orient to violations of the CSO in moral
terms. And yet knowledge of a rule should enable persons to conduct themselves
in light of it—or at least anticipate how it may be enforced by others—thereby
potentially obviating the need for enforcement by others in most cases. Indeed,
many of the chronically homeless residents in Golden City avoid contact with
the police by avoiding times and locales where officers strictly enforce the CSO.
Because the subject in case 1 (as well as 7 and 8 in the following) are sleeping,
however, they fail to see the officers approach, and thus fail to take steps that
might preempt the need for contact. In other cases, however, conscious persons
who are aware of the ordinance, and how their current position will be viewed in
light of it, often seek to avoid direct contact with the police by sitting up, packing
Rules and Policeable Matters 173
(4) GCPD_StopandWatch_PA_05172012.mov
Where officers can count on subjects knowing a rule, they can use their presence
as a means of enforcing compliance with it. As this officer explains, establishing
a focused presence (i.e., by conveying that the officer’s presence anticipates pos-
sible engagement with a specific recipient or set of recipients) can be enough
to move a person out of the area. Such practices suggests that the modes of en-
gagement police developed for policing “skid row” (Bittner 1967b) have been
expanded to cover the chronically homeless wherever they may be found. As
Bittner (1967b:708) observed, officers patrolling skid row “. . . install themselves
in the center of people’s lives and let the consciousness of their presence play the
part of conscience.”
174 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
(5) GCPD_ManonSidewalk_PA_05172012
1 MPO: ((Bang))
2 MPO: Yo!
3 (1.5)
4 MPO: Hey!
5 (1.5)
6 MPO: Hello?
7 (1.5)
8 MPO: Hey.
9 (0.5)
10 MPO: (Coming up?)
11 (2.0)
12 MPO: Hey, You can’t sit on the sidewalk.
13 (1.5)
14 MPO: Talked about this yesterday
15 (0.5)
16 CM1: No.
17 MPO: Yeh. (0.3) I definitely did
18 ((Civ begins getting up))
After the officer’s initial attempts to initiate contact (lines 1 and 2) with the
subject sitting against the newsstand fail, the officer positions himself in front of
the subject and continues to pursue a response (lines 4, 6, 8 and 10). Although
the subject appears to be aware of the officer (e.g., beginning around line 5 he
looks up, and then to the researcher; see Figure 6.1), he does not respond or
show any other orientation to the potential basis for the officer’s presence. We
can note, then, the officer’s use of a complaint formulation (in line 12, “you can’t
X”; cf. Schegloff 2005) to enforce the CSO, which treats the subject’s position
Rules and Policeable Matters 175
Figure 6.1 Golden City Police Officer enforcing the CSO rouses a chronically
homeless resident; Extract (5), GCPD_ManonSidewalk_PA_05172012
176 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
groomed appearance and the absence of a bedroll suggest that he has a location
to sleep, shower, and store his belongings. As the officer takes note of him sit-
ting in a shopping area subject to police scrutiny, she uses a step-wise approach
to establishing contact that provides the subject several opportunities (lines
1–5) to preempt or avoid a full-blown encounter with her (e.g., by moving, as
in Extract 4). She initially stops a short distance from him and announces her
presence with a summons (line 1) when the subject does not notice her on his
own. Only after the subject fails to begin moving in the midst of a substantially
delayed exchange of greetings (lines 3 and 4) does the officer step closer and in-
itiate the more sustained encounter that follows with a request for identification
(lines 6).
(6) GCPD_SitandLieArrest_MI_08052013
1 FPO: Hello:,
2 (1.3)
3 CM1: Hi.
4 FPO: Hi,
5 (.)
6 FPO: Got your ID on you?
7 (0.3)
8 CM1: U::mm (0.3) °no.°
9 FPO: No, yih don’t,<you from the city?
10 (.)
11 CM1: Yeah.
12 FPO: You’re aware of the civil sidewalk ordinance?
13 (1.5)
14 CM1: No:.
15 FPO: They call it sit-lie. You heard’ve it,
16 (2.0)
17 CM1: U:mm
18 FPO: How long’ve you been in thuh city:
19 (1.4)
20 CM1: Several years.
21 FPO: Okay:uh ‘cause they uh approved that in uh two
22 thousand ten.
.
. ((four lines omitted regarding reason for recording))
.
27 CM1: uh:[mm
28 FPO: [°Okay.° So do you have your ID or not.
Rules and Policeable Matters 177
Here, instead of moving directly to enforcing the sleep/sit ordinance (as in cases
1, 4, and 5, and cases 7–12), the officer suspends that project while she seeks to
establish whether the subject is a local (lines 10–12) and begins to pursue what
he knows about the CSO. The declarative query she uses to initially probe the
matter (in lines 13) strongly presumes (Heritage and Raymond 2012) that (as a
local) he knows about the ordinance (lines 10–12). After he flatly disclaims any
such knowledge (line 15), the officer’s follow-up queries (in lines 16, 19, 22–23)
convey her skepticism regarding this claim, suggesting it is inconsistent with his
status as a long-term resident (see especially lines 19, 22–23).
Following a series of negatively framed declarative questions that convey the
officer’s continuing skepticism regarding the resident’s claims (lines 31, 33–34),
the civilian attempts to embody his lack of awareness of the CSO by positioning
himself as a willing recipient of the officer’s “expla[nation of] the law” (line 38).
In doing so, this resident displays at least an openness to hearing about the ordi-
nance, thereby avoiding the possible implication that his current violation of it is
willful or flagrant. In this respect, he adopts an approach that parallels what we
178 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
observed with the resident in Extract 1, though from the perspective of a person
who claims to be unaware of the law. Such a claim would be undercut if the res-
ident has already been warned, however, and this officer remains unmoved.
While she explains the law and mentions a flyer she can give him (lines 45–46),
she suspends the realization of this offer until after she confirms the he hasn’t
been informed of the CSO (lines 48–49). Thus, across this exchange, just what
the resident knows about the CSO comes to be contested by the participants, and
a further adjudication of the case is deferred until that matter is resolved.
Unlike every other move-along case in our database, this encounter results
in the citizen’s arrest when the officer’s effort to establish whether he has been
warned about the CSO reveals that he has a warrant for his arrest. Because run-
ning checks for warrants, or even requesting subjects’ names, are not routine
elements of most move-along encounters, this person’s troubles seem to arise out
of his failure to move when he first sees the officer, his subsequent insistence that
he is unaware of the CSO, and the apparent ambiguity of his status as a homeless
person. Had the officer categorized the subject as a chronically homeless person
from the outset (as in 1), she would likely have presumed he knew about the or-
dinance and adopted a different method of enforcement (as in cases 1 and 4).
Similarly, had the subject simply admitted that he knew of the CSO and walked
away, he very likely would have avoided arrest.
This case illustrates the complexity associated with enforcing even a simple
rule “for another first time.” Here the officer treats the subject’s lack of move-
ment once she established her presence as an indication that he may not be a
member of one or another of the intersecting categories presumed to possess a
working knowledge of patterns of enforcement in the city (chronically homeless,
residents of the city). In this respect, the officer’s enforcement of the sit/lie rule is
sensitive to her understanding of “what socially defined types of persons are le-
gitimately entitled to have what kinds of trouble” (Garfinkel 1967:156).
In the preceding cases (Extracts 1, and 4–6), officers enforcing the CSO ap-
proach and contact residents sleeping or sitting on the sidewalks of busy streets
in the middle of the day—that is, at places and times when the CSO and the range
of tacit agreements shape its enforcement converge in making that conduct
policeable. By virtue of its status as a mala prohibita offense, officers treat gross
or direct violations of the CSO as raising questions about what residents know
about it, revealing a way in which they treat knowledge about the ordinance as a
contingent, rather than strictly moral, matter. In this way, a feature of rules and
rule following that typically remains a presupposed feature of participants’ con-
duct—whether they know about a rule—comes to be topicalized as a method for
enforcing it (see also Weider 1974).
In addition, participants treat such (potential) violations as making relevant
remedial actions that position the subject as a potential offender. For example,
Rules and Policeable Matters 179
Officers contacting residents for mid-day violations of the CSO in locales sub-
ject to strict enforcement only account for a small subset of move-alongs in
our database. More common are contacts at what might be called the “bound-
aries” of the CSO, such as when enforcement begins in the morning or phases
out in the evening, or takes place on streets and neighborhoods subject to
less stringent enforcement. Residents and officers take a different approach to
these encounters, even though they also involve violations of the CSO. In these
cases, assumptions about what residents know, and the methods officers use to
manage compliance, reflect participants’ orientations to the ways that any ac-
tual occasion of enforcement aligns the tacit agreements that shape the CSO’s
routine enforcement.
We begin by documenting the reality of the tacit agreements that inform how
officers enforce the CSO, which are perhaps best exemplified by the “morning
wake-up call.” Although the law prohibits sitting or lying on the sidewalk be-
tween 7 a.m. and 11 p.m., and makes a second contact within 24 hours a ticket-
able offense, officers contacting homeless residents in the morning (after 7 a.m.
and before 12 p.m.) approach their encounters as a “wake-up call.” For example,
they rarely if ever give tickets (for an initial contact at such times), even though
they encounter the same residents daily (i.e., within a 24-hour time frame).
Instead, officers seek to rouse the sleeping men they encounter, as in the fol-
lowing extracts.
5 MPO: What?
6 CM1: I’m talkin’
7 MPO: Well you gotta get up now:. Co’mon man.
8 (0.3)
9 MPO: If you get up I can go.
10 (0.3)
.
. ((8 lines omitted re: CM1’s nephew))
.
18 MPO: Well this is uh: This is your wake up call.
19 CM1: a’right.
The treatment of these encounters as “routine” is reflected in the ways that the
basis for them remains tacit. The officer’s encouragements (“rise and shine”) and
admonitions (“let’s not get cozy”) index, and rely on, participants’ knowledge of
the CSO as the basis for the encounter’s projects without either party explicitly
topicalizing it (as in Extracts 1, 5, and 6). Moreover, even as officers seek to get
the residents up and moving, neither party orients to the homeless resident’s po-
sition and state (e.g., sleeping) as problematic (in contrast to cases 1, 5, and 6).
Similarly, in our data, officers also routinely walk past persons they find sleeping
on the sidewalk in the early evening, even though the ordinance officially remains
in effect until 11 p.m.
Officers’ enforcement of the CSO also varies by locale, even though the or-
dinance ostensibly applies to every sidewalk in the city. In cases where they en-
counter residents near an area where enforcement is typically relaxed, officers
may direct the residents to those places. For example, officers may direct persons
to adjacent neighborhoods, as in the following (lines 3–5).
Or officers may tell subjects to move from a main avenue to a less exposed place
on a side street, as in the following (line 4).
Evidently, if officers did not make some such accommodations for the ordinary
routines of daily life, they would either be forced to ticket most of the chronically
homeless persons they encountered every day, or they would be forced to ensure
that the chronically homeless persons they encounter remain on their feet for 16
hours a day. These tacit accommodations regarding when and where the ordi-
nance will be enforced allow officers to avoid becoming continuously entangled
in managing the problems of chronic homelessness, even as they work to miti-
gate many of the conflicts that gave rise to the CSO’s adoption.
Although the CSO ostensibly governs the conduct of residents that lie or
sit on the sidewalk, officers nevertheless also find themselves accountable to
it. The broad discretion officers have in deciding when, where, and how to
enforce the CSO is tempered by complaints that other (presumably housed)
residents may call in. Because these residents may not be aware of (or ac-
countable to) the tacit agreements that otherwise inform the CSO’s enforce-
ment, responding to such complaints may require that officers depart from
them. In our data, officers manage apparent departures from these informal
agreements by invoking the “calls” and “complaints” that have occasioned the
contact, thereby suggesting that they must be attended to lest they be viewed
as failing to do their job. Here, instead of invoking or probing what residents
know about the CSO, officers account for their actions by explaining the local
bases for their departures from the tacit agreements that otherwise inform
patterns of enforcement.
For example, in the following case an officer approaches a homeless man, lying
in a sleeping bag on the sidewalk of a side street at dusk. While the subject is tech-
nically in violation of the CSO, his selection of an out of the way place (with vir-
tually no pedestrians) in the evening would not ordinarily attract the attention
of officers. We can note then that the subject does not anticipate that the officer
will view his position and location as problematic (e.g., by moving or preemp-
tively apologizing, as in Extract 1). Instead, the officer announces that she is obli-
gated to enforce the CSO (indexed by “move you along”) because of a complaint
(lines 5–6).
182 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
1 FPO: Hi::.
2 CM1: Oh hey.
3 FPO: How are ya?
4 CM1: Oh pretty good. How are you doin’?
5 FPO: Good. I have to move you
6 alo[::ng<I got a complaint, ok?
7 CM1: [Ok
.
. ((7 lines omitted re: shelters))
.
15 FPO: Ok. Thank you. Take your time
16 getting ready. ((FPO turns, walks away))
Here, it is the officer who treats enforcement of the ordinance as the account-
able matter. We can note that the officer positions herself as a beneficiary of the
subject’s cooperation (Bergmann 1993; Clayman and Heritage 2014; Raymond
and Zimmerman 2016), and invokes the caller’s complaint, rather than the CSO
per se, as grounds for moving the subject.
Similarly, in the following, an officer approaching a man lying in the doorway
of a business at dusk treats his enforcement of the CSO as a complainable matter
(Schegloff 2005).
1 MPO: Hello::,
2 (.)
3 MPO: Sir. How you doing?
.
. ((6 lines omitted re: opening))
.
9 MPO: Wanna go to a shelter or anything like that?
10 CM1: Oh no, I’m okay.
11 MPO: Okay yea, unfortunately someone ca::lled.
12 CM1: Oh-ughh
13 MPO: Yeah, you know usually I wouldn’t-you know:
14 I hate to do it so.
15 CM1: Tha:ts oka::y. I’ll mo::ve.
16 MPO: Tha:nks ma:n,=I appreciate it.<I mean you understand, I
Rules and Policeable Matters 183
As in the prior case, the officer reports that “someone called” (line 11) and, by
way of a gratuity token, positions himself as a beneficiary of the subject’s cooper-
ation and understanding (line 23). In addition, he offers a remedy for his putative
offense (lines 23–24) and comments on the futility of enforcing the ordinance in
the current circumstances (lines 26–27).
Across Extracts 7–12, officers moving residents for violating the CSO don’t
ask or assert what they know about the CSO. Instead, they treat residents’ com-
pliance with the tacit agreements that inform the CSO’s routine enforcement
as evidence of their willingness to comply with it in principle, and thus their
familiarity with the ordinance itself. Moreover, in Extracts 11 and 12, officers
use various methods to display their commitment to the tacit agreements that
otherwise inform how the CSO is enforced, even as their current enforcement
of it departs from those agreements. For example, on finding the subject of
complaints sleeping on the sidewalk (during hours covered by the CSO), they
nevertheless treat those residents’ positions, knowledge of the CSO, and lack
of remedial action as unremarkable, and treat their own effort to enforce the
CSO as accountable and objectionable. Such cases reveal the ways in which the
participants’ understanding of the CSO, and officers’ authority to enforce it, is
linked to both the text of the law and the tacit understandings that inform its
routine invocation. Officers strongly assert their authority to enforce the CSO
in circumstances where these two matters align in locating a residents’ position
as problematic (as in cases 1, 4–10). By contrast, officers’ orientation to their di-
minished authority to enforce the CSO in circumstances that depart from these
tacit understandings (in Extracts 11–12) can be found in the accounts, apologies,
and remedial actions they produce in doing so, and in their positioning as bene-
ficiaries of the residents’ cooperation.
184 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Concluding Remarks
and what he is presumed to know about the ordinance. Similarly, officers and
residents flexibly adapt the practices they use to initiate encounters and invoke
the rule. For example, our analysis explicates the specificity achieved via any
number of variations: how officers approach subjects (waking them up, walking
directly up to the subject, using a step-wise approach, and so on) and how the
residents respond to the officers’ presence and approach (moving, apologizing,
remaining seated, etc.); how the rule is introduced and formulated (e.g., as a re-
minder, a complaint, as part of a query, and so on); how any specific occasion for
enforcement is positioned as consistent (or not) with the myriad tacit agreements
that inform its use or the exceptions it provides for; and how enforcement or
compliance may figure in the emerging relationship between the participants
(e.g., as a personal favor or offense), and so on. In this way, we have sought to
explicate how those using the CSO are agents in situations in which their actions
have consequences that overflow the literal sense of it as an ordinance, while
they nevertheless remain accountable to it. Indeed, in just the ways that these
scenes are fashioned as “another” violation of the same ordinance—the varied
and detailed practices required to constitute a unique moment as a violation of
the “same” ordinance—is itself a source of variation and complexity. That is, the
effort to produce “recurrence” is, itself, a source of “distinctiveness” (Maynard
and Clayman 2018). While this can be appreciated across any source of variation,
it is perhaps most vividly illustrated in cases where the participants’ use of the
rule invoked their ongoing relations, including how previous encounters shape
current ones. In the very ways that participants oriented to “another” violation
as entailing a personal (rather than simply legal) transgression, they invoke
both continuity in and change to aspects of their emerging relations. In sum, in
finding how participants apply rules “for another first time,” we can begin to ap-
preciate how any participants’ use of a rule illuminates the particulars of a scene
and much that extends before and beyond it.
References
Alexander, Jeffrey C. 1987. Twenty Lectures: Sociological Theory since World War II. New
York: Columbia University Press.
Bergmann, Jörg R. 1993. Discreet Indiscretions: The Social Organization of Gossip.
New York: Aldine De Gruyter.
Bittner, Egon. 1965. “The Concept of Organization.” Social Research 32(3):239–55.
Bittner, Egon. 1967a. “Police Discretion in Emergency Apprehension of Mentally Ill
Persons.” Social Problems 14(3):278–92.
Bittner, Egon. 1967b. “The Police on Skid-Row: A Study of Peace Keeping.” American
Sociological Review 32(5):699–715. doi: 10.2307/2092019.
Bloor, David. 1973. Wittgenstein and Mannheim on the Sociology of Mathematics.
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 4(2), 173–191.
186 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Camic, Charles. 1989. “Structure after 50 Years: The Anatomy of a Charter.” American
Journal of Sociology 95(1):38–107.
Chambliss, William J. 1964. “A Sociological Analysis of the Law of Vagrancy.” Social
Problems 12(1):67–77. doi: 10.2307/798699.
City and County of San Francisco Police Department. 2010. “Civil Sidewalks Ordinance.”
http://sanfranciscopolice.org/civil-sidewalks-ordinance.
City Hall Fellows. 2012. Implementation, Enforcement and Impact: San Francisco’s Sit/Lie
Ordinance One Year Later. https://sfbos.org/sites/default/files/FileCenter/Documents/
42452-CHF_SitLieReport_FINALwAppendices_7.2.12.pdf.
Clayman, Steven E., and John C. Heritage. 2014. “Benefactors and Beneficiaries: Benefactive
Status and Stance in the Management of Offers and Requests.” Pp. 55–86 in Studies
in Language and Social Interaction. Vol. 26, edited by P. Drew and E. Couper-Kuhlen.
Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Drew, Paul. 1992. “Contested Evidence in a Courtroom Cross-Examination: The Case of a
Trial for Rape.” Pp. 470–520 in Talk at Work: Social Interaction in Institutional Settings,
edited by P. Drew and J. Heritage. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ewick, Patricia, and Susan S. Silbey. 1998. The Common Place of Law: Stories from
Everyday Life. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1967. Studies in Ethnomethodology. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Hart, H. L. A. 1961. The Concept of Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Heritage, John. 1984. Garfinkel and Ethnomethodology. Cambridge; New York: Polity
Press.
Heritage, John, and Geoffrey Raymond. 2012. “Navigating Epistemic Landscapes:
Acquiescence, Agency and Resistance in Responses to Polar Questions.” Pp. 179–92 in
Questions: Formal, Functional and Interactional Perspectives, edited by J. P. De Ruiter.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Homans, George C. 1958. “Social Behavior as Exchange.” American Journal of Sociology
63(6):597–606. doi: 10.1086/222355.
Maynard, Douglas W., and Steven E. Clayman. 1991. “The Diversity of Ethnomethodology.”
Annual Review of Sociology 17(1):385–418. doi: 10.1146/annurev.so.17.080191.002125.
Maynard, Douglas W., and Steven E. Clayman. 2018. “Mandarin Ethnomethodology or
Mutual Interchange?” Discourse Studies 20(1):120–41. doi: 10/gc92z8.
Meehan, Albert J. 1989. “Assessing the ‘Police-Worthiness’ of Citizen’s Complaints to the
Police: Accountability and the Negotiation of ‘Facts.’” Pp. 116–40 in The Interactional
Order: New Directions in the Study of Social Order, edited by David T. Helm.
New York: Irvington.
Meehan, Albert J. 2006. “Using Talk to Study the Policing of Gangs and Its Recordwork.”
Pp. 190–210 in Talk and Interaction in Social Research Methods, edited by G. R. Paul
Drew and D. Weinberg. London: Sage.
Merton, Robert K. 1938. “Social Structure and Anomie.” American Sociological Review
3(5):672–82. doi: 10.2307/2084686.
Merton, Robert King. 1968. Social Theory and Social Structure. New York: Free Press.
Mikesell, Lisa, Galina B. Bolden, Jenny Mandelbaum, Jeffrey D. Robinson, Tanya
Romaniuk, Alexa Bolaños-Carpio, Darcey Searles, Wan Wei, Stephen M. DiDomenico,
and Beth Angell. 2017. “At the Intersection of Epistemics and Action: Responding
with I Know.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 50(3):268–85. doi: 10.1080/
08351813.2017.1340711.
Rules and Policeable Matters 187
National Law Center on Homelessness and Poverty. 2014. No Safe Place: The
Criminalization of Homelessness in U.S. Cities. https://www.hivlawandpolicy.org/sites/
default/files/No_Safe_Place.pdf.
Parsons, Talcott. 1937. The Structure of Social Action: A Study in Social Theory with Special
Reference to a Group of Recent European Writers. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Parsons, Talcott, and Edward Shils, eds. 1951. Toward a General Theory of Action.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Raymond, G., and D. H. Zimmerman. 2016. “Closing Matters: Alignment and
Misalignment in Sequence and Call Closings in Institutional Interaction.” Discourse
Studies 18(6):716–36. doi: 10/ggxmsd.
Sacks, Harvey. 1992. Lectures on Conversation. Vols. 1 and 2, edited by G. Jefferson.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 2005. “On Complainability.” Social Problems 52(4):449–76. doi: 10/
bjsf2x.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 2007. “Categories in Action: Person-Reference and Membership
Categorization.” Discourse Studies 9(4):433–61. doi: 10.1177/1461445607079162.
Weider, D. Lawrence. 1974. “Telling the Code.” Pp. 144–72 in Ethnomethodology, edited
by R. Turner. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin.
Wilson, Thomas P. 1970. “Normative and Interpretive Paradigms in Sociology.” Pp. 57–70
in Understanding Everyday Life: Towards a Reconstruction of Sociological Knowledge,
edited by J. D. Douglas. Chicago: Aldine.
Wrong, Dennis H. 1961. “The Oversocialized Conception of Man in Modern Sociology.”
American Sociological Review 26(2):183–93. doi: 10/cbs2vv.
Zimmerman, Don H. 1970. “The Practicalities of Rule Use.” Pp. 221–38 in Understanding
Everyday Life: Towards a Reconstruction of Sociological Knowledge, edited by J. D.
Douglas. Chicago: Aldine.
7
The Cooperative, Transformative
Organization of Human Action
and Knowledge
Charles Goodwin
Action is central to both human language and human sociality (Enfield and
Levinson 2006; Levinson 2012; Sacks, Schegloff, and Jefferson 1974). Within
face-to-face interaction, the intrinsic dialogic organization of language (Linell
2009) is constituted as an emerging, multiparty process as participants assemble
action and units by operating on a range of different kinds of semiotic materials
that each is producing with an orientation toward the other (Goodwin 1979,
1980, 2000; Iwasaki 2011; Kaukomaa, Peräkylä, and Ruusuvuori 2013). This
chapter will investigate how actions are built by performing systematic opera-
tions on a public substrate which provides many different kinds of resources that
can be reused, decomposed, and transformed. Insofar as such processes preserve
with modification structures provided by the environments that constitute the
point of departure for new action, this process is accumulative, something that
is central to the distinctive organization of human culture and society. Through
such accumulation, highly varied settings, cultures, and distinctive ways of
knowing and operating upon the world are created and lodged endogenously
within particular communities. Members of such communities thus face, as part
of the intrinsic organization of action itself, the task of building new members
who can be trusted to see, understand, and act upon the world in relevant ways.
Actors can build new action by selectively reusing resources provided by a prior
action. Figure 7.1 provides an example.1 Chopper, in line 2, uses Tony’s own
words against him by employing “make me” to embed Tony’s challenge within a
new counter-challenge of his own.
HUMAN ACTION AND KNOWLEDGE 189
Figure 7.1 Building new action by decomposing and reusing materials created by
earlier actors.
(a) 7 Chuck:
8 Chil: Ni nan o.
9 Chuck: Di ya want·
10 Chuck: Want me ta get some. (.) No.
11 Chil: Ni nuh
12 (0.9)
13 Chuck: Do you want me ta take that away.
Laminated Action
Stance: Prosody
Target: Lexico-Semantic Structure
14 Chil: No No.
17 Chil: No no.
18 (0.6)
Chil’s semantics are rich because of the way his talk is built by performing structure-
preserving transformative operations on a substrate created by others.
For clarity it is useful to be more explicit about why I am choosing to use the
term substrate to describe the local public configuration of action (such as Tony’s
utterance in line 1 of Figure 7.1) that is operated on (frequently through pro-
cesses of decomposition, reuse, and indexical incorporation) to build a next
192 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
other subsequent meaning and action that emerge coherently from what has just
gone before, and which provides the materials for the construction of what will
happen next.
Chil’s talk in Figure 7.2 contains not only lexical items but also rich, highly varied
prosody. In Goodwin (2000) I argued that human beings build action by gath-
ering together different kinds of signs, each organized within a distinctive me-
dium that is crucial to its organization. Thus the semiotic structure provided by
a hopscotch grid makes relevant action possible only when it is inscribed on a
medium that allows actual bodies with weight to jump through it. Each of these
contextures of specific forms of semiosis (lexical structure, prosody, visible
embodied displays, etc.) organized within a particular medium can be called a
semiotic field, and the set of semiotic fields that participants demonstrably attend
to in order to build the action of the moment can be called a contextual configura-
tion. This productive heterogeneity, the ability to construct action through the si-
multaneous use of different kinds of materials, sits at the heart of human action.
For conciseness and clarity in this chapter I have focused on Chil’s simulta-
neous use of the lexical items No No, and prosody in Figure 7.2, but a range of
other semiotic fields, including gesture and bodily orientation, are also crucial
to the organization of the actions he builds there (Goodwin 2010a, 2011). The
term lamination will be used to describe a set of different semiotic fields organ-
ized as layers of diverse resources. Though there are limitations to lamination as
metaphor, I am choosing to use it for several reasons. First, I find that the visual
metaphor offered by the notion of lamination—a set of layers organized with ref-
erence to each other—provides a simple and vivid way to look clearly at how a
variety of semiotic fields with quite different properties work cooperatively with
each other simultaneously to build evanescent actions that might endure for only
a few seconds, but which have rich, analytically interesting complex internal
structure (see Figure 7.2). Using the notion of lamination to organize the display
of data, as most of the figures in this chapter do, allows us to move beyond a mere
record of the words spoken to try to find what Wittgenstein (1958:§122) termed
“a perspicuous representation [which] produces just that understanding which
consists in ‘seeing connexions.’ ” Thus it allows us to see substrates in a simulta-
neous as well as a sequential fashion, and to look clearly at how specific semiotic
fields contribute to the differential meaning-making practices that work together
to build particular actions.
Second, in classes at the University of Pennsylvania when I was a graduate
student, Erving Goffman, then in the process of developing his deconstruction
194 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Speaker &
Compositional Structure
(b) 1 Chuck: Was he a radiologist?
of Chil’s
2 (0.3)
Utterance/Action
3 Pat: Mm hm.
Distributed Across
4 (0.3)
Two Participants
5 Chuck: Em hm.
6 (0.5)
7 Pat: He was chief of radiology at
8 Colum bia Presbyterian Medical Center
10 Chuck: uh huh
Chil’s Gaze
11 Chil: [Di dih duh Treats Chuck,
12 Chuck: uh huh. Not Pat, as
13 (0.4) His Addressee
14 Chuck: Wow. Assumes
15 (0.3) Position
16 Chuck: (wum) K– K+ K+ of Speaker
Unknowing Knowing
Recipient Speakers
Figure 7.3 Chil builds an action by attaching his prosody to rich language structure
created by someone else
to obtain separate pitch tracks to display the different prosody of each speaker.
Indeed, their co-occurring action in overlap is precisely the phenomenon now
being pointed to analytically.
Chil does not simply affiliate to what Pat is saying, but adds a new evalua-
tion to the news she reports, transforming Pat’s report of an occupation into a
formulation of his friend as someone who occupied a special, exalted position.
Some demonstration that the participants themselves in fact treat what Chil is
doing as such an assessment is provided by Chuck’s “Wow.” in line 14. Further
support for the assessable status of what Chil is doing is provided by the subse-
quent development of the sequence. This reformulation of what Pat was saying
constitutes the point of departure for a new, independent telling by Chil (not to
be examined here).
196 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
With his prosody Chil says something that Pat does not, while using the con-
tent of her talk to do this. He thus acts as an independent speaker in his own
right, rather than as someone who is merely affiliating with what Pat is doing.
Chil’s ability to transform Pat’s action by replacing her prosody with some-
thing different demonstrates how action is constituted through the dynamic
interplay and mutual elaboration of different semiotic fields. The words used
to state a proposition in Chil’s and Pat’s utterances are quite literally identical,
since they are produced by Pat alone. However, Chil and Pat each construct a
subtly different action by using prosody to laminate a unique stance display on
this common linguistic structure. Chil builds his action by using rich prosody to
perform simultaneous, transformative operations on the substrate provided by
Pat. Indeed, though most analysis of how action can be built and understanding
is displayed within talk-in-interaction has focused on its sequential organiza-
tion, for example how the understanding of an utterance is revealed through a
subsequent response to it,5 the simultaneous, concurrent organization of ac-
tion is equally important. By providing different kinds of semiotic materials, ac-
tors in structurally different positions (e.g., speaker and hearer, storyteller and
principal character, etc.) can contribute in consequential ways to the organiza-
tion of a single action (Goodwin 1980, 1984; C. Goodwin and Goodwin 1987;
Iwasaki 2011).
This has a number of theoretical consequences. For Chil, but I would argue
for speakers in general, both the utterance and the speaker have a distributed ex-
istence. A crucial component of the talk that is central for proper understanding
of Chil’s utterances has been constructed by someone else, his interlocutor. His
action is intrinsically cooperative (different participants produce the varied
materials required for the actions he builds here) and deeply social in that he
builds meaning through systematic operations on language structure provided
by others. Using the distinctions provided by Goffman’s (1979) deconstruction
of the speaker, Chil acts as the principal, the party responsible for stating partic-
ular propositions and constructing specific forms of action. However, the author
of much of what he says, that is, the party who constructs the linguistic sign com-
plex required to explicitly state the proposition required for the intelligibility of
Chil’s action, is someone else. Indeed, it would be literally impossible for Chil
to construct by himself the sign complexes he needs to state the propositions
found in his utterances here. What happens here provides a vivid example of
the argument made by Bakhtin (1981:293–94) that the word in language is half
someone else’s. It becomes “one’s own” only when the speaker populates it with
his own intention, his own accent, when he appropriates the word, adapting it to
his own semantic and expressive intention. Prior to this moment of appropria-
tion, the word does not exist in a neutral and impersonal language (it is not, after
all, out of the dictionary that the speaker gets his words!), but rather it exists in
HUMAN ACTION AND KNOWLEDGE 197
other people’s mouths, in other people’s concrete context, serving other people’s
intentions: it is from there that one must take the word, and make it one’s own.
It might be argued that what Chil does here is special and idiosyncratic, a cre-
ative but unusual adaptation to his inability to produce linguistic structure of his
own. However, fully fluent speakers in mundane conversation also build action
by decomposing the layers of semiotic fields that others use to build utterances.
Goodwin and Goodwin (1992) describe a video-recorded interaction in which
a speaker telling a story used elaborate paired hand gestures to depict a set of
steps. A recipient then repeated these same gestures but attached them to new
words, the children’s song “Little Bunny Fou Fou,” while soliciting appreciation
of his heckling parody from another recipient. More generally, phenomena such
as next-turn repair initiation (Schegloff, Jefferson, and Sacks 1977) and aggra-
vated correction (Goodwin 1983) are frequently constructed by repeating part
of what was said by the prior speaker in the last turn, while replacing the original
prosody with a contour that displays doubt or opposition. Participants them-
selves thus not only treat utterances as complex structures assembled through
the dynamic interplay of different layers of diverse semiotic phenomena (talk,
prosody, gesture, etc.), but are able to decompose those structures and reuse
parts of them, while changing how what has been appropriated is to be under-
stood by embedding it within a new contextual configuration (Goodwin 2000).
Chil’s status as a speaker is revealed as well through the way in which he
organizes his body. Rather than positioning himself as simply a recipient to what
Pat is saying, he begins the utterance by raising his eyebrows toward Chuck while
endorsing for him what Pat is saying. He then looks briefly toward Pat in the
midst of his talk, but returns his gaze to Chuck well before his emphatic “Yea:h”
that ends the turn (see the image in Figure 7.3). The action he is performing by
using his body to address Chuck in this way is telling someone about the status of
his friend as news, an action that would be inappropriate to a knowing recipient
such as Pat (who is in fact providing the words necessary to describe the position
he occupied), but is appropriate to an unknowing recipient.
In the simplest terms, Chil builds an utterance with novel, complex lexicon
and syntax by attaching a prosodic contour, with a new display of stance and
evaluation, to talk being spoken and constructed by another.6 Here we find a de-
construction of the speaker (Goffman 1979) which distributes the activities that
constitute visibly doing being a speaker into multiple bodies, and streams of talk
being produced by separate actors, who are reflexively attending to each other
and using each other’s signs and actions as resources for the construction of their
own. Chil’s ability to act as a speaker here incorporates what Pat is saying as a cru-
cial component of his own action. Rather than a model of the speaker that takes
as its point of focus mental phenomena within the individual actor, here we find
speakership being constituted through the ability to participate in appropriate
198 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
The way in which human actions are composed of layers of distinctly different
kinds of semiotic materials provided Chil, faced with the limitations imposed by
his aphasia, with crucial resources. By operating on laminations, he was able to
construct combinatorial action of his own, and to incorporate crucial semiotic
materials found in other participants’ action, for example their rich language,
into new utterances of his own.
Environmentally coupled gestures (Goodwin 2007a) use pointing to tie lan-
guage to specific phenomena in the environment. Here again, action is built by
laminating layers of different kinds of semiotic resources together. Figure 7.4
provides a simplified diagram of how such actions are built by combining sepa-
rate semiotic fields, each of which makes a distinctly different contribution to the
HUMAN ACTION AND KNOWLEDGE 199
• Environmentally
Coupled Gesture
• Munsell
Chart
• Phenomena in
Domain of Security
Here Dirt to Be
Transformed into
Archaeological Data
Note how, in both of these examples, pointing gestures are tied to something
in the environment that is being carefully scrutinized by the participants.
In both examples in Figure 7.4, participants build action by laminating dif-
ferent kinds of meaning-making resources together. Complementary semi-
otic fields include (1) the mutual orientation of the participants’ bodies toward
both each other, and the materials they are working with, which creates a public
focus of attention and a locus for shared work; (2) language, including relevant
deictic terms, organized within sequences of action within human interaction;
(3) hands making environmentally coupled gestures (Goodwin 2007a); (4) con-
sequential phenomena in the surround that are being intensely scrutinized by
the participants as part of the work they are doing together. Here what is being
studied is dirt that is to be transformed into archaeological data.
The action on the right includes an additional semiotic field, the Munsell
chart, that is not found in the action on the left. In that each of these layers
constitutes a semiotic resource which is used by an actor to interpret another
semiotic resource, the insertion of a new layer is not merely additive, but rather
a transformative event that changes the organization of the entire configuration.
The contingent inclusion of a range of different semiotic fields, such as the addi-
tion of the Munsell chart to the formal arrangement found on the left, provides
an intrinsic source for variability, creativity, and intense local adaptation in the
organization of human action. Rather than being restricted to a fixed repertoire,
participants have the ability to incorporate quite diverse materials into the orga-
nization of the actions they are building together.
The Munsell chart itself is the accumulative product of a history of building
frameworks for knowing the world in action—relevant ways by linking diverse
materials with complementary properties into enduring configurations that
provide architectures for perception. Its structure includes the patches of color
which provide samples that can be pointed at and visually compared with the
dirt being classified, a grid that makes possible the identification of any par-
ticular patch as a set of standard coordinates, color names, and the distinctive
physical properties of its medium, paper, which permits holes to be cut to create
the architectures for perception used by the archaeologists to compare dirt to be
classified with color samples.
The way in which the work of our predecessors can be passed on to us in
forms that provide organization in fine detail for current work, such as using
the Munsell chart to classify the color of dirt, or a map to determine where in
the ocean samples are being taken by oceanographers (Goodwin 1995), or
the specification within a legal system of what can count as a crime (Goodwin
1994), shapes the epistemic activities being pursued by diverse communities in
very fine detail. Indeed, these accumulative practices make possible particular
HUMAN ACTION AND KNOWLEDGE 201
and labs, for example) reflexively tied to these actions. As argued by Wittgenstein
(1958:§23) there are
Human Tools
D
Stone
Leather
Thongs
Wooden
Handle
B
A
E
C
Human Utterance
14 Chil: No No.
utterances. The unique properties of each material make a separate and distinct
contribution to both the utterance and the action as a whole. What results is not a
single “thing” or indivisible, monolithic action, but rather changing contextures
of mutually elaborating phenomena organized as webs of relationships (Ingold
2007:75). Chil’s talk and human action in general are accumulative in that they
build from a substrate of prior resources, while constructing something new.
The tools being used by the animals in Figure 7.5 do not typically have this (ac)
cumulative combinatorial organization.10 However, as persuasively argued by
Reynolds (1993), human tools do. Though the sticks held by the animals operate
on something else in the environment (poking into trees to get tasty insects),
the tools themselves are not composed from separate parts (Goodwin 2010b).
They are not constructed as webs of interlocking resources which establish
relationships between different kinds of materials and participants. They do not
have an (ac)cumulative organization. D in Figure 7.5 is an ax constructed from
three separate materials: (1) a large stone, (2) pliable wood wrapped around the
stone to form a handle, and (3) leather thongs that tie the handle together tightly
to hold the stone. If the ax is disassembled, the ax itself cannot be found in any
single part in isolation. Without the web of relationships that link these separate
elements to each other to form a coherent whole, what one finds is simply a stone
or a strip of leather.
The formal properties of action and tool organization being noted here create
a space for systematic change within a framework that promotes the accumula-
tion of structure through time. For example, there are many different ways that
the head, the striking surface of the ax, might be attached to its handle: pliable
wood tightened with a leather thong as in Figure 7.5, cords alone tying the stone
to the handle, adhesives, etc. The task of joining the head to the handle creates a
problem space for experimentation through systematic variation. However, this
experimentation does not require that the complexity of the ax (or other action)
be focused on as a complex whole. Instead, the elements that are held constant,
the handle and the stone head for example, or alternatively the handle and the
haft if different kinds of hammers or blades are being experimented with, con-
stitute a matrix that can remain stable while variations in a single part are tested.
The formal arrangement of parts that constitute the tool or ax remains in place,
even as modification is occurring within that structure. Tools progressively dif-
ferentiate within the accumulative stability provided by a core feature of human
action, an organization that makes possible cooperative transformation zones.
The same is true for language structure. Through visible repair, a noun phrase
such as “my son” can be transformed into “my oldest son” and thus publicly
decomposed into differentiated sub-parts that permit optional insertion and de-
letion. These possibilities for decomposition and transformation are made vis-
ible to others with endogenous talk itself (Goodwin 2006).
206 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
In Figure 7.3, it was seen that Chil could build a single action by attaching
his prosody to rich lexico-syntactic structure constructed by another. More gen-
erally, utterances and turns at talk are built through the mutual cooperation of
speakers who provide talk and hearers who operate on that talk through visible,
embodied displays. Equivalently, when tools are built by combining different
kinds of parts, their collaborative social production by actors occupying alter-
native positions (designers in California and factory workers in China, for ex-
ample) becomes possible.
Though utterances and stone axes appear to be completely different kinds of
phenomena, and are indeed analyzed by entirely different disciplines within the
social sciences, as forms of human social action they have important patterns of
formal organization in common. Each is built by combining different kinds of
materials. This makes possible distinctive forms of collaborative social organi-
zation built through cooperative action as participants occupying structurally
different positions, such as speaker and hearer, or trading partners, contribute
different parts to the combinatorial arrangement required to build a single utter-
ance, turn at talk, tool, or object. These utterances and/or objects thus constitute
the nexus for extended, enduring webs of social relationships, and sites for accu-
mulative change.
archaeological data. It is also the site where participation in the activity helps
transform new students into skilled, competent archaeologists (Mogk and
Goodwin 2012) who have mastered the infrastructure of skilled practice, the
habitus (Bourdieu 1977), required to build the signature actions that constitute
the work of their community. Social learning, or more narrowly pedagogy, is as
unique a human adaptation as language and the use of compound tools (Csibra
and Gergely 2011). With very few, very limited exceptions, other animals do not
explicitly teach their young. However, human communities are faced with the
ongoing task of creating new competent members.
Ann Sue
archaeologist who is directing the field school. Sue uses her trowel to inscribe in
the dirt where she sees the shape she is trying to outline. Ann then uses her finger
to lightly draw a second line, just outside Sue’s, while saying, “I would’a put it a
ti::ny bit out there.” This calibration of the exact shape to be transferred to the
map is made possible because of the way in which Sue’s line makes public the pre-
cise way in which she sees the feature she is working with. Her public inscription
provides a substrate that Ann can operate on with her subsequent line, which is
organized not as a new completely different action, but instead as an interpretant
of Sue’s. This process not only calibrates the actions and objects the participants
are constructing: the line that accurately depicts the shape of the post mold. It
is also helps calibrate, in rather fine detail, the skill and professional vision that
must be mastered by a young archaeologist if others in her profession are to trust
the work she does.
As described in more detail in Goodwin (2010b), Figure 7.7 depicts in a simple
fashion some of what is created by building mundane, consequential action
within a local epistemic ecology. What emerges, through recursive processes of
mutual elaboration that link situated practice to many different kinds of semi-
otic phenomena, is the cooperative calibration of actors, practice, communities,
and the intelligibility of a world being scrutinized. This is made possible by the
way in which action is constructed through the entanglement of different kinds
of resources which allow differentially positioned actors to participate simulta-
neously in the construction and calibration of action. Epistemic ecologies not
‘That Disturbance’
Language
and Animate
Members’ Bodies
Its Work and Discourse
A Socially Organized, The Ability to see
Culturally Relevant Each Other’s Bodies
Sensorium in Just Those Ways
That Are Relevant to
the Accomplishment
of Collaborative Action
Figure 7.7 Building mundane, consequential action within a local epistemic ecology
HUMAN ACTION AND KNOWLEDGE 209
only organize ways of knowing that are consequential for the distinctive activi-
ties of a community, and records, such as maps, of how the world is known and
operated on in a relevant fashion by a particular community; they also provide,
within the midst of mundane action itself, the cooperative practices required to
instantiate the community’s epistemic ecology as situated practice within the
skilled competence of new members. Acquisition of the practices required to
construct a map simultaneously constructs the relevant cognitive architecture of
the archaeologists who use such maps to do their work.
Conclusion
Acknowledgments
References
Agha, Asif. 2007. Language and Social Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Bakhtin, Mikhail. 1981. The Dialogic Imagination: Four Essays. Edited by C. Emerson, M.
Holquist, and V. Liapunov. Austin: University of Texas Press.
Selting, Margret. 2010. “Prosody in Interaction: State of the Art.” Pp. 3–40 in Prosody in
Interaction, edited by D. Barth-Weingarten, E. Reber, and M. Selting. Amsterdam: John
Benjamins Publishing Company.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1977. Outline of a Theory of Practice. Richard Nice, Trans. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Brasier, Martin D., Richard Matthewman, Sean McMahon, and David Wacey. 2011.
“Pumice as a Remarkable Substrate for the Origin of Life.” Astrobiology 11(7):725–35.
doi: 10.1089/ast.2010.0546.
Csibra, Gergely, and György Gergely. 2011. “Natural Pedagogy as Evolutionary
Adaptation.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences
366(1567):1149–57. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2010.0319.
Du Bois, John W. 2014. “Towards a Dialogic Syntax.” Cognitive Linguistics 25(3):359–410.
doi: 10.1515/cog-2014-0024.
Enfield, N. J. 2009. The Anatomy of Meaning: Speech, Gesture, and Composite Utterances.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Enfield, N. J., and Stephen C. Levinson, eds. 2006. Roots of Human Sociality: Culture,
Cognition and Interaction. London: Routledge.
Fitch, W. Tecumseh. 2010. The Evolution of Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Goffman, E. 1979. “Footing.” Semiotica 25:1–29.
HUMAN ACTION AND KNOWLEDGE 211
Schegloff, Emanuel A., Gail Jefferson, and Harvey Sacks. 1977. “The Preference for Self-
Correction in the Organization of Repair in Conversation.” Language 53(2):361–82.
Streeck, Jürgen, Charles Goodwin, and Curtis LeBaron, eds. 2011. Embodied
Interaction: Language and Body in the Material World. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1958. Philosophical Investigations. 2nd ed. Edited by G. E. M.
Anscombe and R. Rhees. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
8
Sex and the Sociological Dope
Garfinkel’s Intervention into the Emerging
Disciplines of Sex/Gender
Kristen Schilt
Introduction
Harold Garfinkel’s case study of “Agnes,” a young woman assigned male at birth
who sought medical treatment at the University of California, Los Angeles
(UCLA), in the late 1950s, is widely characterized as the first sociological case
study of a person who might today identify as transgender (Connell 2009).
Published as the fifth chapter of his book Studies in Ethnomethodology (Garfinkel
1967), this case study is a departure from Garfinkel’s previous work in both
its ethnographic method and its topical focus. Though Garfinkel would pub-
lish no further work in this area, his theoretical insights about what he termed
“sex status” would come to anchor an ethnomethodological theory of gender
as a social, interactional production introduced by Suzanne Kessler and Wendy
McKenna (1978) and further developed by Candace West and Don Zimmerman
(1987).1 As theoretical paradigms about sex and gender developed and shifted
in the following decades, a continued interest in the significance of Agnes—first
as an illustration of a sociological concept, and later as a historical account of
a transitioning person navigating a regulatory medical institution—would gen-
erate myriad reinterpretations of Garfinkel’s analysis.2
While scholars have written both critically and appreciatively about the
meaning of Garfinkel’s case study of Agnes for psychoanalysis, queer theory,
feminist sociology, and transgender studies (see, e.g., Denzin 1990; Namaste
2000; Raby 2000; Rogers 1992; Spade 2006), there has been less scholarly atten-
tion to locating his theoretical insights from this work within the context of the
social sciences in the late 1950s and early 1960s (see Connell 2009; or Sassatelli
2007 for an exception). Drawing on published works and archival materials
from the Garfinkel Archives in Newburyport, Massachusetts,3 I situate this area
of his work within the then-dominant strands of sociological and psychoana-
lytic thinking about sex and gender. In particular, I focus on the distinctive so-
ciological—or, more precisely for the time period, ethnomethodological—lens
Sex and the Sociological Dope 215
through which Garfinkel interpreted Agnes’s life history. To highlight what I see
as his intervention into the emerging disciplines of sex and gender, I examine
Garfinkel’s writings alongside those of psychiatrist Robert J. Stoller, his collabo-
rator on Agnes’s case.
Stoller and Garfinkel coauthored two articles about Agnes’s case, and pro-
duced their own solo-authored analyses. Yet, as I argue in this chapter, they
approached this shared endeavor with different, and sometimes conflicting,
guiding theories and empirical questions. Stoller, widely considered a pioneer in
the study of psychological and biological “sex disorders” (Meyerowitz 2002), fo-
cused on the etiology, or why, of Agnes’s case. In contrast, Garfinkel was invested
in documenting the how of Agnes’s life—in particular, how she navigated her
everyday interactions as a woman without the biographical history and genital
configuration others assumed her to have on the basis of her appearance. Moving
the focus from etiology to interaction, he extrapolates from his interviews with
Agnes a general theoretical proposition that all people, even the “culturally de-
fined population of normally sexed persons” (Garfinkel 1960a:37), engage in
routine, interactional work to achieve their status as men or women on the basis
of appearance and behavior cues. This theoretical insight imagined sex status as a
contingent achievement accomplished in social interaction, rather than a static,
biological outcome derived from chromosomal and hormonal configurations—
the dominant understanding of sex status at the time. Though Garfinkel
(1960a:49) omitted some of his more cutting critiques of what he viewed as the
“impoverished” state of theorizing about sex status in the social sciences from his
later published work, his 1960 drafts that I examine here show a line of thinking
about sex and gender that would find echoes in 1980s post-structuralist theories
of gender performativity (see Moloney and Fenstermaker 2002; Sassatelli 2007).
And, while a radical idea for many sociologists at the time (see Sassatelli 2007),
his writings about sex status would come to inform the feminist theory of “doing
gender” (West and Zimmerman 1987), an explanatory framework for under-
standing the persistence of gender inequality that generated seismic shifts in so-
ciological thinking about sex and gender (Jurik and Siemsen 2009).
psychological gender identities and their primary and secondary sex character-
istics. At first glance, Agnes had all the typical indicators of such a condition. She
had been classified as male at birth on the basis of her external genital configu-
ration, and had been raised as a boy. Yet, by her own account, she had sponta-
neously begun to develop breasts at the age of 12. She reported that this breast
development further solidified her long-standing sense of herself as female. In
her late teenage years, she moved away from her hometown and started a new
life as a young woman in Los Angeles. Now 19, Agnes had sought out Stoller, the
West Coast expert on intersex conditions, on the advice of another physician. She
hoped to receive confirmation of an intersex condition and to be recommended
for vaginoplasty—a surgery that she felt would bring her genitals in line with her
gender identity (Garfinkel 1967). UCLA was one of the few US hospitals that
performed what was then a rare and widely disputed surgery (Meyerowitz 2002).
While Stoller had a great deal of experience with intersex conditions, he could
not provide a firm diagnosis for Agnes in their initial meetings. He found her
ability to live her life as a woman for the past two years notable, stating in his first
medical journal article about her case: “The most remarkable thing about the
patient’s appearance when she was first seen by us was that it was not possible
for any of the observers, including those who knew about her anatomic state,
to identify her as anything but a young woman” (Stoller, Garfinkel, and Rosen
1960:44). Indicating his assessment that her femininity did not come across as
a purposeful performance, he added: “there was nothing garish, outstanding, or
abnormally exhibitionist in her attire, nor was there any hint of poor taste or that
the patient was ill at ease in her clothes (as is so frequently seen with transvestites
and women with disturbances in sexual identification)” (Stoller et al. 1960:44).
Yet, while Agnes’s preliminary medical tests confirmed her breast development
and elevated estrogen levels, she had the chromosomal configuration and repro-
ductive system of a “normal” male. Without evidence for the typical indicators
of an intersex condition, Stoller’s team had to consider whether Agnes could be
taking an undisclosed source of external estrogen to simulate an intersex condi-
tion in order to access genital surgery—though they found it unlikely that she
could, at the age of 12, have had the knowledge about or the access to synthetic
estrogen (Stoller et al. 1960).
Establishing a firm etiology was crucial for Stoller’s research and for his treat-
ment recommendations. If Agnes had a verifiable intersex condition, and the
team determined that her internal sense of herself as a woman could not be
changed through therapy, she could be recommended for genital surgery as a cor-
rective intervention. However, if she were found to be taking an external source
of estrogen to induce breast development, she would be classified as having a
psychological “sex disorder,” such as what was then termed “transsexualism.”
In the late 1950s, the appropriate treatment for patients classified as transsexual
Sex and the Sociological Dope 217
noting this development and suggesting that he would write a follow-up article
that reanalyzed his case material in light of this new information. That he never
wrote such an article suggests that a follow-up ultimately was not necessary for
advancing his ethnomethodological project. While the empirical facts of Agnes’s
life had shifted with her disclosure—the source, or why, of her feminization was
external, not biological—the theoretical importance Garfinkel located in the how
of Agnes’s life, namely her ability to navigate everyday interactions as a woman
prior to her surgery, remained unchanged.
While Garfinkel’s approach to Agnes’s case conflicted at times with Stoller’s con-
cern with etiology and diagnostic criteria, it was in keeping with the central
tenets of an ethnomethodological approach to the social world laid out in the
first chapter of Studies in Ethnomethodology. As Garfinkel (1967:1) notes, such an
approach warrants close attention to “the activities whereby members produce
and manage settings of organized everyday affairs” and how they make them ac-
countable, or observable and reportable. In the majority of chapters in Studies,
Garfinkel (1967:1) makes his theoretical points by drawing on a wide variety of
empirical cases that bring the kind of attention “usually accorded to extraordi-
nary events” to “the most commonplace activities of daily life.” In 1967, Agnes’s
case appeared to some readers to be more in line with the extraordinary rather
than the mundane or everyday—a fact underscored in a particularly critical re-
view of Studies by prominent sociologist James Coleman that focused almost ex-
clusively on discrediting Garfinkel’s writings about Agnes (Sassatelli 2007). Yet,
for Garfinkel, the significance of Agnes’s case did not lie in her rare, and for some
readers, spectacular condition. Rather, his interest was in her perspective as a
“practical methodologist” (Garfinkel 1967) who could, by virtue of her life his-
tory, illuminate the everyday reality of sex status—a phenomenon understood by
scholars and laypersons to be among the most involuntary, the most mundane,
and the most natural facts of life.
Drawing on his interviews with Agnes, Garfinkel develops a set of taken-for-
granted or natural attitudes about sex and gender that operate at the level of the
commonsense and to which he argues that all members of society are account-
able—namely, that there are only two possible sex statuses, male or female, and
that assignment to one or the other of these statuses is natural, inevitable, and
invariant. He theorizes, in contrast, that much of what is taken to be a natural fact
about sex status is made possible in everyday practice because of an assumed,
interactional trust in facets of a shared reality, including the gender of any given
222 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
person. Supporting this point, he argues that Agnes’s feminine appearance and
behavior were sufficient criteria for her to achieve her desired gender identity as
a woman in most social interactions and settings because people had a shared
trust in a reality in which gendered appearance reflected the “biological facts” of
sex status. In 1960 drafts, he expands upon this idea, noting:
We have already seen that physical evidences are critical as socially employed
insignia. But like signs-in-a-language, these are insignia in an order of cultural
knowledge of sexuality. Culturally one can be counted a member of the popula-
tion of normally sexed persons with or without the actual possession of biolog-
ically appropriate organs. (Garfinkel 1960a:39–40)
He adds, “This is not to say that the organ is irrelevant, no more than the phys-
ical characteristics of an utterance are irrelevant to the recognition by a language
user of ‘the thing that the talker is talking about.’ But the utterance is to the word
as the biological penis is to the culturally ‘sexed person’ ” (Garfinkel 1960a:40).5
Within these passages, he begins to build a theory of sex status as an interactional
achievement.
Extrapolating from Agnes’s case, Garfinkel next considers what it would mean
to make sex status in general (e.g., not just for people with “sex disorders”) into
a sociological object of study. Within the social sciences in the early 1960s, such
an agenda would be radical. Sex role theory, the then-dominant paradigm in so-
ciology, took the structural functionalist idea that people learn and come to in-
habit socially mediated scripts, such as “the doctor” or “the housewife,” as the
starting point for making sense of gender difference.6 In this framework, most
sociologists imagined “male” and “female” to be invariant, ascribed statuses
that people were born into, while sex roles, such as “husband” or “mother,” were
achieved, or socially attained, statuses. Theoretical work on sex roles was heavily
influenced by psychological theories of child development that emphasized the
importance of the heterosexual, nuclear family for socializing boys and girls
into their appropriate and complementary sex roles, such as the “wife role” for
women or the “husband role” for men (see, e.g., Parsons 1942; see Connell 1987
for a critique of sex role theory). Sex status, in contrast, received little sociolog-
ical attention because it was viewed as natural rather than social.
The psychiatric work on “sex disorders” that Stoller and others were devel-
oping in the 1950s and 1960s had a great deal of overlap with sex role theory.
As a psychoanalyst, Stoller put an emphasis on family dynamics, particularly
the relationship between the mother and child, in creating what he classified as
psychological disorders of gender and sexual identity. From this disciplinary
perspective, only through studying the “dysfunctional” case could doctors deter-
mine how best to achieve “normal” development. In Sex & Gender, Stoller (1968)
Sex and the Sociological Dope 223
Conclusion
account of Agnes’s life than a traditional psychological case study of the time
period—perhaps accounting for why his chapter in Studies has generated a con-
tinued interest from scholars and laypersons that Stoller’s writings about her case
have not. These two aspects of his writings about Agnes—his theoretical insight
into sex status as an interactional achievement and his ethnographic description
of how Agnes navigated both her everyday life and the regulatory apparatus of
the UCLA medical establishment—would spark later generations of feminist
sociologists, queer theorists, and transgender studies scholars to develop his po-
litically neutral ideas into more socially informed theoretical frameworks aimed
at understanding and dismantling the social mechanisms that maintain gender
inequality and transgender discrimination.
Editor’s note: Kristen Schilt, the author of this chapter, is the co-director of the
2019 documentary short, “Framing Agnes,” with Chase Joynt, and the director
of research for a 2022 feature film of the same title. The documentary takes up
Schilt and Joynt’s archival research in Harold Garfinkel’s papers as a way into cur-
rent debates around transgender media representation and trans rights.
References
Anonymous. 1956. “SF-81 Letter.” Harold Garfinkel Archives. Newburyport, MA.
Burma, John, 1946. “The Measurement of Negro ‘Passing.’” American Journal of Sociology
52(1):18–22. https://doi.org/10.1086/219915.
Connell, Raewyn. 1987. Gender and Power. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Connell, Raewyn. 2009. “Accountable Conduct: ‘Doing Gender’ in Transsexual and
Political Retrospect.” Gender & Society 23(1):104–11. doi: 10.1177/0891243208327175.
Denzin, Norman. 1990. “Harold and Agnes: A Feminist Narrative Undoing.” Sociological
Theory 8(2):198–216. doi: 10.2307/202205.
Fuchs-Epstein, Cynthia. 1988. Deceptive Distinction: Sex, Gender and the Social Order.
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1960a. “Discussion.” Harold Garfinkel Archives. Newburyport, MA.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1960b. “‘Passing’ and the Managed Achievement of Sex Status in an
Intersexed Person.” Dated August. Harold Garfinkel Archives. Newburyport, MA.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1960c. “‘Passing’ and the Managed Achievement of Sex Status in an
Intersexed Person.” Dated October. Box 79. Robert J. Stoller Archive. University of
California at Los Angeles Special Collections. Los Angeles, CA.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1967. Studies in Ethnomethodology. Cambridge, UK: Polity.
Garfinkel, Harold. 2002. Ethnomethodology’s Program: Working Out Durkheim’s Aphorism.
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Goffman, Erving. 1963. Stigma: Notes on the Management of Spoiled Identity. New York:
Simon and Schuster.
Goldie, Terrie. 2014. The Man Who Invented Gender: Engaging the Ideas of John Money.
Vancouver, BC: University of British Columbia Press.
226 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Hobbs, Allyson. 2014. A Chosen Exile: A History of Racial Passing in American Life.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Jurik, Nancy, and Cynthia Siemsen. 2009. “Doing Gender as Canon or Agenda.” Gender &
Society 23(1):72–75.
Kessler, Suzanne, and Wendy McKenna. 1978. Gender: An Ethnomethodological Approach.
New York: Wiley.
Meyerowitz, Joanne. 2002. How Sex Changed: A History of Transsexualism in the United
States. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Moloney, Molly, and Sarah Fenstermaker. 2002. “Performance and Accomplishment.”
in Doing Gender, Doing Difference, edited by S. Fenstermaker and C. West.
New York: Routledge. 189–204
Namaste, Viviane. 2000. Invisible Lives: The Erasure of Transsexual and Transgendered
People. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Parsons, Talcott. 1942. “Age and Sex in the Social Structure of the United States.” American
Sociological Review 7(5):604–16.
Raby, Rebecca C. 2000. “Re-Configuring Agnes: The Telling of a Transsexual’s Story.”
Torquere 2(1):1–10.
Rogers, Mary. 1992. “They Were All Passing: Agnes, Garfinkel, and Company.” Gender &
Society 6(2):169–91. doi: 10.1177/089124392006002002.
Sassatelli, Roberta. 2007. “When Coleman Read Garfinkel . . . !” Sociologica 1(1):1–24.
doi: 10.2383/24200.
Schwabe, Arthur D., David H. Solomon, Robert J. Stoller, and John P. Burnham. 1962.
“Pubertal Feminization in a Genetic Male with Testicular Atrophy and Normal Urinary
Gonadotropin.” The Journal of Clinical Endocrinology & Metabolism 22(8):839–45.
doi: 10.1210/jcem-22-8-839.
Spade, Dean. 2006. “Mutilating Gender.” Pp. 315–34 in The Transgender Studies Reader,
edited by S. Stryker and S. Whittle. New York: Routledge.
Stoller, Robert J. 1968. Sex and Gender: The Development of Masculinity and Femininity.
New York: Science House.
Stoller, Robert J., Harold Garfinkel, and Alexander Rosen. 1960. “Passing and the
Maintenance of Sexual Identification in an Intersexed Patient.” Archives of General
Psychiatry 1(2):43–48.
West, Candace, and Don H. Zimmerman. 1987. “Doing Gender.” Gender & Society
1(2):125–51. doi: 10.1177/0891243287001002002.
9
Garfinkel, Social Problems, and Deviance
Reflections on the Values of Ethnomethodology
Darin Weinberg
Introduction
228 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
of sociology to not only lose the details but dramatically misconstrue the na-
ture of collective action (Garfinkel [1967] 1984). But he also insisted ethno-
methodology does not seek to formulate correctives (Garfinkel [1967] 1984:viii,
2002:121; Heritage 1984:140–41). I argue not that there is a contradiction in
Garfinkel’s simultaneously avowing these two positions, but that it presents a
perspicuous analogy for those interested in applying his insights to the study of
social problems and deviance. The sociology of social problems and deviance
has itself been fundamentally shaped by enduring debates between those who
seek to treat them as pernicious social facts that sociology might be enlisted to
remedy and those who seek to avoid correctives and to study “putative” social
problems and deviance more neutrally, exclusively as members’ achievements.
By examining the relation between Garfinkel’s two positions on the worldwide
social science movement, both in his own work and that of others influenced by
him, I argue we may forge a more nuanced orientation to social research as in-
trinsically socially engaged but nonetheless rigorously objective.
The chapter is divided into four sections. In the first I briefly review the histor-
ical development of social problems and deviance as a distinctive subdiscipline
of sociology. Since its inception, this subdiscipline has struggled with the ques-
tion of whether a genuine science of society is entitled to the moral preferences
seemingly required of campaigns for social reform. In this section I describe
these struggles and the ascendance of particular techniques for managing them
to positions of prominence in sociology. In the second section I discuss various
ways in which Garfinkel and other ethnomethodologists intervened in the study
of deviance and social problems. Emphasis is given not only to the transform-
ations these studies rendered to our understanding of the topics they consid-
ered, but also to the transformations they suggested with respect to the craft of
social research on these topics. Particular attention is given to the relationship
these studies suggest between dispassionate analysis and the orchestration of re-
form. In the third section I focus on Garfinkel’s enduring legacy. This section
is organized around what have become three major themes in ethnomethodo-
logical and ethnomethodologically inspired research on deviance and social
problems: (1) the topic/resource distinction, (2) membership categorization
analysis, and (3) the ethnomethology of mental disability. The final section
provides some concluding remarks.
Critics of the sociology of social problems and deviance have long been fond
of bemoaning the subfield’s analytic incoherence (cf. Best 2004; Spector and
Kitsuse [1977] 1987; Waller 1936). Such critiques have incited not only efforts
Garfinkel, Social Problems, and Deviance 229
to systematize this particular subfield but also efforts to systematize and thereby
legitimate sociology itself. Modern sociology, in the United States at least, arose
from nineteenth-century reform movements’ efforts to more effectively address
the social problems attendant to industrialization, urbanization, and moderni-
zation. By century’s end, these efforts had yielded an aggregate of investigations
conspicuously lacking in any unifying scientific framework. Would-be aca-
demic sociologists seized upon this disunity, professing a knowledge of the en-
during essence of social life to which they insisted the laity be held accountable.
No challenge was to become more definitive of sociology’s history than that of
reconciling its claims to a public warrant as socially useful with its claims to be
an integrated, holistic, and dispassionate science (Bannister 1987; Ross 1991;
Turner and Turner 1990).
Some have framed this tension as essentially one of transition. As soci-
ology moved into the academy, it gradually shed its commitments to reform
in favor of a value neutrality then seen as the hallmark of bona fide science.
Though there is certainly a kernel of truth to this framing, it risks overlooking
a crucial fact. Academic sociologists never actually forgot the importance of
highlighting sociology’s instrumental applications. Early analyses of social
problems in terms of social pathology and social disorganization were plainly
conceived as “value free” but nonetheless were cast as productive of clear-cut
recommendations for policy and social reform. By casting social problems as
symptomatic of structural disequilibrium, these studies sought to reconcile
scientific value neutrality with the idea that social problems are objectively
harmful and in need of remedies that sociology can provide technical assis-
tance in devising.
Of course, it wasn’t long before critics observed that the social pathologists
and social disorganization theorists had failed to transcend moral biases. Mills
(1943) famously characterized these biases in terms of the rural, Protestant,
and nativist predilections that many early theorists drew from their similar
social backgrounds. These biases were manifest, for example, in assumptions
that cities breed social problems due largely to their lack of the shared values
and informal cultural controls found in more “traditional” small towns. Such
biases resulted in both an underestimation of the problems caused by more
global variables like economic inequality and an overestimation of the problems
caused by what might now be called cosmopolitan culture. As funding from
private foundations and the federal government became more commonplace,
concerns about sociology’s biases focused less on its practitioners’ parochial
backgrounds and more on its co-optation by the American power elite (cf.
Lynd 1939).
But these concerns, incisive though they were, exerted minimal influence
during the middle decades of the twentieth century. Most sociologists proved
230 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
considerably more interested in fortifying their own scientific status and per-
ceived social utility than soul-searching interrogations of their complicity
with power. Combining attention to structures of opportunity, mainstream
American and alternative subcultures, sociologists sought to draw attention
away from the putatively intrinsic biological and psychological deficits of rule
breakers and toward the social structural and cultural determinants of their be-
havior. These foci were shared between devotees of the two approaches Matza
(1969) was eventually to characterize as correctional and appreciative. While
correctional research tended to focus on the social strains that fostered deviant
adaptations and the remedies that might curtail them, appreciative research
sought less to change them than to more fully grasp the understandings that
disparaged groups had of themselves. This dichotomy between correctional
and appreciative research has sometimes been equated with the more general
divide between structural functionalism and the research traditions associated
with the University of Chicago, but things were not actually quite so tidy.
Functionalists, including Robert Merton, Kingsley Davis, and Daniel Bell,
highlighted the latent functions of activities like political corruption, pros-
titution, and gambling, thereby distancing themselves from correctional
agendas. If these reviled activities increased the stability of social systems, per-
haps correction was unwarranted. Moreover, many of the best-known studies
combined attention to functionalist and Chicago traditions (cf. Cloward and
Ohlin 1960; Cohen 1955; Erikson 1962). Much more consequential than spe-
cific theoretical or methodological quarrels were the more general questions
of whether sociology is, can be, or ought to be nonpartisan. As noted earlier,
reformists were largely marginalized during the mid-twentieth century. Hence,
both correctional and appreciative approaches were preponderantly cast as
correctives to the normative biases of past generations. The correctional per-
spective was shrouded in the value neutral pretensions of social pathology and
social disorganization theory, while appreciative research was defended for its
dispassionate attention to the worldviews of deviants themselves. Regardless
of their theoretical or methodological predilections, most sociologists were
fundamentally concerned to transcend lay biases by treating the beliefs and
practices of both normals and deviants as topics of, rather than resources for, a
morally and intellectually detached science (cf. Becker 1963; Finestone 1957;
Merton 1957).
Despite their self- conscious posture of value neutrality, appreciative
researchers, more than their correctional colleagues, fostered a more anti-au-
thoritarian and critical sociology by effectively devaluing the received preoc-
cupation with personal deficits among people deemed troublesome (Merton
1938:672). Though appreciative research like Sutherland’s (1939) differential
association theory of crime, Lindesmith (1938) on opiate addiction, Becker
Garfinkel, Social Problems, and Deviance 231
Ethnomethodological Interventions
drew fairly stark contrasts between the natural attitude of everyday life and the
attitude of scientific theorizing, common-sense rationalities and the rationality
of the ideal scientist. And they often cast ethnomethodology as an enterprise de-
voted to developing the latter (cf. Cicourel 1964; Garfinkel 1960; Sacks 1963).
Indeed, the very point of highlighting the distinctiveness of common-sense ratio-
nalities from scientific rationality was to better equip sociologists to more rigor-
ously analyze and appreciate their objective characteristics as organizationally
distinct from, rather than merely deficient versions of, scientific rationality. This
was, for example, a main point to be drawn from Garfinkel’s ([1967] 1984) “Some
Rules of Correct Decisions That Jurors Respect,” and his and Bittner’s ([1967]
1984) “ ‘Good’ Organizational Reasons for ‘Bad’ Clinic Records.” It can be seen in
Cicourel’s ([1968] 1995) book on the social organization of juvenile justice and
Sudnow’s (1965) essay on normal crimes.
The fundamental objective shared by these studies was, then, neither to de-
fend nor critique the various agencies they described, but to explicate their
distinctive and eminently situated rationalities. Hence, for example, Bittner’s
(1967a, 1967b) studies of peacekeeping on skid row and police discretion in
the apprehension of mentally ill persons both sought to critically highlight
the distance between received theoretical preconceptions of the mandates and
jurisdictions of police work and the concrete practicalities to which it is actu-
ally accountable. While abstaining from the critique of members’ practices, this
research certainly presented correctives to widespread organizational tenden-
cies in professional sociology itself. Mainstream sociologists were routinely
held to have undervalued the rationality of members’ practices by overlooking
how they were finely honed to the priorities and exigencies specific to them. But
these efforts to reform mainstream sociology were not held to be value laden.
Instead, as good Schützians, early ethnomethodologists adhered to the premise
that scientific theorizing is a socially detached, disinterested, and value neu-
tral enterprise unsullied by the practical interests and concerns of members.
Science, then, including ethnomethodology, remained idealized as a set of
techniques for transcending mundane values and interests. I will have more to
say of this later, but suffice to say for now that their Schützian commitments in-
hibited early ethnomethodologists from fully appreciating that their critiques
of mainstream sociology manifestly exhibited mundane interests and values of
their own.
Moreover, these Schützian commitments served to facilitate a radical, indeed
categorical, distinction between the practical worlds and objectives of members,
on the one hand, and the purely scientific worlds and objectives of analysts, on
the other. This distinction was often articulated as an enjoinder to professional
sociologists that they avoid confusing the topics of their research with the re-
sources they deploy in its conduct (cf. Cicourel 1964; Sacks 1963). In one of the
234 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
more emphatic and articulate statements to this effect, Zimmerman and Pollner
(1970) wrote,
Zimmerman and Pollner here decisively divorce the lay understanding of the
social world as objectively given—that is, unified, stable, and independent of
people’s experiences of it—from a properly sociological understanding that duly
appreciates that the structures of the social world are collectively accomplished
in and through concerted practices. This position was also forcefully articulated
in Pollner’s (1978) famous critique of Howard Becker’s labeling theory. Pollner
took Becker to task for confusing sociological and common-sense orientations
to the labeling process. According to Pollner, common sense posits the objective
reality of deviance as independent of the societal reaction to it. By the common-
sense view, then, labels are distinct from the objective or real characteristics of
the people or behavior to which they are applied. In contrast, Becker’s sociolog-
ical orientation to labeling is ostensibly predicated on the culturally relativist po-
sition that different societies regard different sorts of things as deviant. Outside
the context of a particular society’s practices for sorting acts as normal or de-
viant, there simply are no resources available with which to determine whether
an act is deviant or not. Hence, societal reactions are not merely responsive to
deviance, they literally constitute deviance as such. The role of the sociologist,
then, cannot be to arbitrate whether labeling has been properly or improperly
accomplished. It can only be to analyze how members themselves orchestrate
such judgments.
However, as Pollner incisively observed, Becker slipped away from a thor-
oughly sociological orientation to deviance as invariably socially constituted
when he endorsed the ideas of secret deviance and false accusation. Insofar
as they posit an objective reality to deviance that can either go undetected
(secret deviance) or be wrongfully imputed (false accusation), both of these
ideas require the common-sense, and very unsociological, distinction be-
tween objective reality and the labeling activities of specific communities.1
Pollner called for a thorough divorce of the sociology of deviance from lay, or
common-sense, orientations to deviance such that the putative reality of de-
viance be construed exclusively as a topic of, rather than in any way a resource
for, social analysis.
Garfinkel, Social Problems, and Deviance 235
This was precisely the approach taken as well by Wieder ([1974] 1988) in his
classic study of the convict code, where he noted the widespread tendency of
sociologists and criminologists to utilize, in their own explanations of inmate
behavior, formulations of a “convict code” borrowed from those they studied.
However, in so doing, they invariably dislodged these formulations from the
situated conduct within which research subjects had originally invoked them.
These decontextualized formulations were then assembled into representations
of the convict code as a more or less fixed set of values that determined people’s
behaviors and beliefs. In contrast, Wieder highlighted how his own under-
standing of the convict code was as anything but a fixed set of norms. Instead,
he insisted his grasp of the code developed provisionally and piecemeal as he
encountered its invocation under diverse circumstances. And his capacity to in-
terpret any given utterance as an invocation of the code was elaborated as his
understanding of it was itself continuously elaborated. In the following example
from his fieldwork, a resident asked some assembled staff members in a voice
loud enough for anyone else around to hear, “Where can I find that meeting
where I can get an overnight pass?” Wieder ([1974] 1988) writes,
On the basis of what I had already learned, I understood him to be saying, “I’m
not going to that meeting because I’m interested in participating in the program
of halfway house. I’m going to that meeting just because I would like to collect
the reward of an overnight pass and for no other reason. I’m not a kiss-ass.” . . . In
this fashion, I employed my collection of “pieces” as a self-elaborating schema.
Each newly encountered “piece” of talk was simultaneously rendered sensible
by interpreting it in terms of the developing relevancies of the code and was, at
the same time, more evidence of the existence of that code. Furthermore, the
interpreted “piece” then functioned as part of the elaborated schema itself and
was used in the interpretation of still further “pieces” of talk. . . . In this sense,
it is much more appropriate to think of the code as a continuous, ongoing pro-
cess, rather than a set of stable elements of culture which endure through time.
([1974] 1988:185–86)
This recasts the convict code as what Zimmerman and Pollner (1970) called
an “occasioned corpus,” not a fixed set of explicit maxims but an endogenously
crafted “self-elaborating schema” that rendered the halfway house as what
Pollner (1979) has called a “self-explicating setting.” This formulation served
nicely to exhibit the extent to which the convict code was shot through with what
Garfinkel and Sacks (1970) called indexical expressions, or expressions that de-
rived their meaning and practical consequentiality from the specific situational
contingencies of their use. It also served to highlight how ethnomethodology
might seek to make norms or values “a pure topic, in contrast to a resource, of
236 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
how the recipient’s response might shape the formulation of trouble which
emerges from the interaction; how complainants seek to persuade recipients
of the validity of their accounts and hence of the justice of their complaints; and
how the extent of a recipient’s affiliation may have consequences for the organi-
zation of the activity of complaining. (Drew and Holt 1988:400)
including news interviews (cf. Clayman and Heritage 2002), news conferences
(cf. Clayman et al. 2007), and radio and television talk shows (cf. Hutchby
1996; Tolson 2001). Focusing on topics including their distinctive turn-taking
systems (cf. Greatbatch 1988), the achievement of epistemic neutrality (cf.
Clayman 1988) and/or authority (cf. Raymond 2000), and adversarialism (cf.
Clayman and Heritage 2002), this research demonstrates at an unprecedented
level of empirical depth just how public dialogue and debate are collectively
orchestrated.
Garfinkel’s Legacy
In this section I take up three themes that have emerged as focal ethnomethod-
ological concerns in the sub-discipline of social problems and deviance. These
themes—the topic/resource distinction, membership categorization analysis,
and the praxiology of mental disability—each serve to highlight not only the
contemporary vigor of ethnomethodologically informed research in this sub-
discipline, but also the contemporary state of play in debates surrounding the
values of ethnomethodology.
As was seen in the previous section, the admonition to avoid confusing the
topics of our research with the resources used in its accomplishment emerged
early in the history of ethnomethodology as an axiomatic precept. In its ear-
liest incarnations, this admonition was predicated on an explicit categorical
dichotomy between scientific and common-sense rationality and a strict adher-
ence to the view that the former must not be contaminated by the latter (cf.
Sacks 1963; Zimmerman and Pollner 1970). Whereas common sense was uni-
formly practical and driven by valued objectives, science was said to be uni-
formly theoretical, “value free,” and driven only by logic and observation. Sacks
(1963), among others, was acutely sensitive to the formidable problem posed
for sociology as a would-be bona fide science by the fact that it was steeped in
unexamined conceptual resources drawn from common sense, but he still felt
that this problem required solving. By the time he and Garfinkel had written
“On Formal Structures of Practical Action” (Garfinkel and Sacks 1970), his
views had decisively changed. In the first essay he dismissed “practical [theory]”
(Sacks 1963:16) as an inferior alternative to science, in the second he and
Garfinkel insisted that both lay and scientific sociology are irremediably prac-
tical (Garfinkel and Sacks 1970).
240 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Garfinkel and Sacks (1970) appear to resolutely disavow the notion that our
topics and conceptual resources might somehow be kept separate:
The fact that natural language serves persons doing sociology, laymen or
professionals, as circumstances, as topics, and as resources of their inquiries,
furnishes to the technology of their inquiries and to their practical sociological
reasoning its circumstances, its topics, and its resources. (1970:337)
Just as one cannot get out of language to talk about language . . . so one cannot
get out of the moral order in order to talk about the moral order. What does this
mean for the analyst? It means that she/he uses her/his moral membership, her/
his knowledge of the mundane organization of the practico-moral order as a
resource, even as she/he turns it into a topic.
Some statuses . . . override all other statuses and have a certain priority. Race
is one of these . . . the fact that one is a physician or middle class or female
will not protect one from being treated as a Negro first and any of these other
things second. The status of deviant (depending on the kind of deviance) is this
242 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
kind of master status. . . . One will be identified as a deviant first, before other
identifications are made. (1963:33)
While intuitively plausible, this argument was more often articulated as a the-
oretical declaration than an empirical demonstration. Moreover, despite occa-
sional qualifications, it was usually suggested that the master status possessed a
universal relevance and consequentiality regardless of practical context. As one
might imagine, this suggestion did not stand up to empirical test. Research has
repeatedly shown that even the most salient of our social identities are only epi-
sodically, rather than universally, implicated in the myriad ways we behave and
are treated by others (cf. Schegloff 1987). Becker’s argument also left undecidable
which status was operative when two or more presumably master statuses (e.g.,
race, gender, sexuality, convicted felon) were potentially relevant to one’s anal-
ysis. Membership categorization analysis is a branch of ethnomethodology that
has brought unprecedented levels of empirical rigor and nuance to our under-
standing of the relationships among identity ascription, behavior, and belief (cf.
Hester and Eglin 1997; Schegloff 2007a, 2007b).
Through membership categorization analysis, ethnomethodological students
of social problems and deviance have demonstrated that, as a practical matter,
ascriptions of deviance and normality are overwhelmingly tied to specific cat-
egories of social identity (cf. Hester 1992; Jayyusi 1984). With incumbencies
in certain membership categories come sets of normative expectations re-
garding likely and/or appropriate activities, characteristics, knowledge, rights
and obligations. What is held deviant or problematic for an adult, a woman, an
American, a Christian, or a homosexual may not be regarded so for a child, a
man, a German, a Muslim, or a heterosexual. However, in contrast to the idea of
master status, no assumption is made that such incumbency is necessarily rel-
evant or procedurally consequential to all activities in which members partici-
pate. Nor is the linkage of specific identities and attributes treated as a foregone
conclusion. Instead, on any given occasion the practical significance of catego-
rical identities, as well as their linkage to particular patterns of action or other
candidate predicates, is treated as a matter for empirical analysis.
Membership categorization analysis has been fruitfully applied in a range of
studies pertaining to deviance and social problems, including suicide prevention
(Sacks 1972), police interrogation (Watson 1990), putative sexual assault (Lee
1984), plea bargaining (Maynard 1984), misbehavior in schools (Hester 1992),
gang affiliation (Garot 2010), ascriptions of “hysteria” in 911 calls (Whalen
and Zimmerman 1998), the diagnosis of developmental disabilities (Gill and
Maynard 1995), and a host of others. In addition to showing just how social
identities actually work in practice, this line of research also highlights an im-
portant aspect of the place of values in both ethnomethodological and other
Garfinkel, Social Problems, and Deviance 243
During the 1960s and 1970s, one of the most prominent debates in the field of
social problems and deviance pitted labeling theorists of mental illness against
those who insisted mental illness is an objective disability. Whereas labeling
theorists emphasized the influences exerted on people’s identities, behavior, and
life chances by psychiatric diagnosis and mental institutionalization, objectivists
insisted that the most important independent variables were those related di-
rectly to people’s mental disabilities themselves. This debate presupposed a stark
dichotomy between labels and realities such that mental disability was construed
as either a discursive social construction or a bona fide independent reality.
Ethnomethodologists rejected this dichotomy. Early interventions often looked
at the kinds of evidence members marshalled to support or refute ascriptions of
mental disability (cf. Coulter 1975; Smith 1978). Such research moved beyond
questions of how mental disability is socially precipitated and/or interpreted to
questions of how it is interactionally constituted as such (Holstein 1993).
Departing from the reigning preoccupation of labeling theory with secondary
deviance and the adoption of deviant identities in favor of attending to the prac-
tical details of interaction itself, most ethnomethodological studies have empha-
sized members’ competences in either minimizing or otherwise managing the
troubles associated with putative mental problems. Thus, for example, Bittner
(1967a) looked at police practices of what he called “psychiatric first-aid,” Lynch
(1983) mapped various “accommodation practices,” Pollner and McDonald-
Wikler (1985) and Goode (1994) showed how family members find competence
in the practices of their mentally disabled children, Goodwin (1995) analyzed
244 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
empirically nuanced linkage of specific disabilities and the myriad types of social
assistance they might be held to warrant (Redley and Weinberg 2007). Though fo-
cused in the first instance on the detailed scientific analysis of members’ practices,
this type of research also promises insights of considerable value to those seeking
to empirically ground mental health policy and reform agendas.
Concluding Remarks
This value will likely be assessed differently in different contexts and perhaps
by different people in the same contexts. But in any case, ethnomethodological
studies will continue to show, through the meticulous analysis of locally con-
certed social interaction, just how.
References
Atkinson, J. Maxwell. 1978. Discovering Suicide: Studies in the Social Organization of
Sudden Death. London: Macmillan.
Atkinson, J. Maxwell. 1984. Our Masters’ Voices. London: Methuen.
Atkinson, J. Maxwell, and Paul Drew. 1979. Order in Court: The Organization of Verbal
Interaction in Judicial Settings. London: MacMillan.
Bannister, Robert C. 1987. Sociology and Scientism: The American Quest for Objectivity,
1880–1940. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.
Becker, Howard S. 1963. Outsiders. New York: Free Press.
Becker, Howard S. 1967. “Whose Side Are We On?” Social Problems 14(3):239–47.
doi: 10.2307/799147.
Berard, Tim J. 2005. “Evaluative Categories of Action and Identity in Non Evaluative
Human Studies Research: Examples from Ethnomethodology.” Qualitative Sociology
Review 1(1):5–30.
Best, Joel. 2004. Deviance. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Bittner, Egon. 1967a. “Police Discretion in Emergency Apprehension of Mentally Ill
Persons.” Social Problems 14(3):278–92. doi: 10.2307/799150.
Bittner, Egon. 1967b. “The Police on Skid-Row: A Study of Peace Keeping.” American
Sociological Review 32(5):699–715. doi: 10.2307/2092019.
Bogen, David, and Michael Lynch. 1993. “Do We Need a General Theory of Social
Problems?” Pp. 213–37 in Reconsidering Social Constructionism, edited by J. A. Holstein
and G. Miller. New York: Aldine de Gruyter.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1988. “Vive La Crise! For Heterodoxy in Social Science.” Theory and
Society 17(5):773–87. doi: 10.1007/bf00162619.
Burns, Stacy, and Mark Peyrot. 2003. “Tough Love: Nurturing and Coercing Responsibility
and Recovery in California Drug Courts.” Social Problems 50(3):416–38. doi: 10.1525/
sp.2003.50.3.416.
Cicourel, Aaron V. 1964. Method and Measurement in Sociology. New York: Free Press.
Cicourel, Aaron V. [1968] 1995. The Social Organisation of Juvenile Justice. New
Brunswick, NJ: Transaction.
Clayman, Steven E. 1988. “Displaying Neutrality in Television News Interviews.” Social
Problems 35(4):474–92. doi: 10.2307/800598.
Clayman, Steven E. 1993. “Booing: The Anatomy of a Disaffiliative Response.” American
Sociological Review 58(1):110–30. doi: 10/c7p9jg.
Clayman, Steven E., and John Heritage. 2002. “Questioning Presidents: Journalistic
Deference and Adversarialness in the Press Conferences of Eisenhower and Reagan.”
Journal of Communication 52(4):749–77. doi: 10/b9b9px.
Clayman, Steven E., John Heritage, Marc N. Elliott, and Laurie L. McDonald. 2007. “When
Does the Watchdog Bark? Conditions of Aggressive Questioning in Presidential News
Conferences.” American Sociological Review 72(1):23–41. doi: 10/dp8899.
Garfinkel, Social Problems, and Deviance 247
Cloward, Richard A., and Lloyd E. Ohlin. 1960. Delinquency and Opportunity. Glencoe,
IL: Free Press.
Cohen, Albert K. 1955. Delinquent Boys. New York: Free Press.
Coulter, Jeff. 1975. “Perceptual Accounts and Interpretive Asymmetries.” Sociology
9(3):385–96. doi: 10.1177/003803857500900301.
Crawley, Sara L. 2019. “Reality Disjunctures and Epistemological Encampment: Addressing
Relevance in Constructionist Perspectives on Social Problems.” The American
Sociologist 50(2):255–70. doi: 10.1007/s12108-018-9398-9.
Drew, Paul. 1998. “Complaints about Transgressions and Misconduct.” Research on
Language and Social Interaction 31(3–4):295–325. doi: 10/cjsp39.
Drew, Paul, and Elizabeth Holt. 1988. “Complainable Matters: The Use of Idiomatic
Expressions in Making Complaints.” Social Problems 35(4):398–417. doi: 10/ggxmm9.
Dupret, Baudouin. 2011. Adjudication in Action. Burlington, VT: Ashgate.
Durkheim, Émile. [1897] 1951. Suicide: A Study in Sociology. Glencoe, IL: Free Press.
Emerson, Robert M. 1969. Judging Delinquents. Chicago: Aldine.
Emerson, Robert M. 2015. Everyday Troubles: The Micro-Politics of Interpersonal Conflict.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Emerson, Robert M., and Sheldon L. Messinger. 1977. “The Micro-Politics of Trouble.”
Social Problems 25(2):121–34. doi: 10.2307/800289.
Erikson, Kai T. 1962. “Notes on the Sociology of Deviance.” Social Problems 9(4):307–14.
doi: 10.2307/798544.
Finestone, Harold. 1957. “Cats, Kicks, and Color.” Social Problems 5(1):3–13. doi:
10.2307/798943.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1960. “The Rational Properties of Scientific and Common Sense
Activities.” Behavioral Science 5(1):72–83. doi: 10.1002/bs.3830050106.
Garfinkel, Harold. [1967] 1984. Studies in Ethnomethodology. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Garfinkel, Harold. 2002. Ethnomethodology’s Program: Working Out Durkeim’s Aphorism.
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Garfinkel, Harold, and Harvey Sacks. 1970. “On Formal Structures of Practical Actions.”
Pp. 337–66 in Theoretical Sociology: Perspectives and Developments, edited by J. C.
McKinney and E. A. Tiryakian. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, Educational
Division.
Garfinkel, H., and D. L. Wieder. 1992. “Two Incommensurable, Asymmetrically Alternate
Technologies of Social Analysis.” Pp. 175–206 in Text in Context: Contributions to
Ethnomethodology, edited by G. Watson and R. M. Seiler. Newbury Park, CA: SAGE.
Garot, Robert. 2010. Who You Claim. New York: New York University Press.
Gill, Virginia Teas, and Douglas W. Maynard. 1995. “On ‘Labeling’ in Actual Interaction:
Delivering and Receiving Diagnoses of Developmental Disabilities.” Social Problems
42(1):11–37. doi: 10/gcm4v6.
Goffman, Erving. 1961. Asylums. Garden City, NY: Anchor.
Goffman, Erving. 1963. Stigma: Notes on the Management of Spoiled Identity. New York:
Simon and Schuster.
Goode, David. 1994. A World without Words: The Social Construction of Children Born
Deaf and Blind. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Goodwin, Charles. 1994. “Professional Vision.” American Anthropologist 96(3):606–33.
doi: 10.1525/aa.1994.96.3.02a00100.
Goodwin, Charles. 1995. “Co-Constructing Meaning in Conversations with an Aphasic
Man.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 28(3):233–60. doi: 10/d4zmxj.
248 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Goodwin, Charles, ed. 2003. Conversation and Brain Damage. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Gouldner, Alvin W. 1968. “The Sociologist as Partisan: Sociology and the Welfare State.”
The American Sociologist 3(2):103–16.
Gouldner, Alvin W. 1970. The Coming Crisis of Western Sociology. New York: Basic Books.
Greatbatch, David. 1988. “A Turn-Taking System for British News Interviews.” Language
in Society 17(3):401–30. doi: 10.1017/S0047404500012963.
Gubrium, Jaber F. 1992. Out of Control. London: Sage.
Heritage, John. 1984. Garfinkel and Ethnomethodology. New York: Polity Press.
Heritage, J., and D. Greatbatch. 1986. “Generating Applause: A Study of Rhetoric and
Response at Party Political Conferences.” American Journal of Sociology 92(1):110–57.
doi: 10.1086/228465.
Hester, Stephen. 1992. “Recognizing References to Deviance in Referral Talk.” Pp. 156–74
in Text in Context: Contributions to Ethnomethodology, edited by G. Watson and R. M.
Seiler. London: SAGE.
Hester, Stephen, and Peter Eglin. 1992. A Sociology of Crime. London: Routledge.
Hester, Stephen, and Peter Eglin, eds. 1997. Culture in Action: Studies in Membership
Categorization Analysis. Washington, DC: University Press of America.
Holstein, James A. 1993. Court-Ordered Insanity. New York: Aldine.
Holstein, James A., and Gale Miller, eds. 1993. Reconsidering Social Constructionism:
Debates in Social Problems Theory. New York: Aldine de Gruyter.
Hutchby, Ian. 1996. Confrontation Talk: Arguments, Asymmetries, and Power on Talk
Radio. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Ibarra, Peter R., and John I. Kitsuse. 1993. “Vernacular Constituents of Moral Discourse: An
Interactionist Proposal for the Study of Social Problems.” Pp. 25–58 in Reconsidering Social
Constructionism, edited by J. A. Holstein and G. Miller. New York: Aldine de Gruyter.
Jasanoff, Shiela. 2011. “The Practices of Objectivity in Regulatory Science.” Pp. 307–38
in Social Knowledge in the Making, edited by C. Camic, N. Gross, and M. Lamont.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Jayyusi, Lena. 1984. Categorization and the Moral Order. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Jayyusi, Lena. 1991. “Cummunicative Praxis as a Moral Order.” Pp. 227– 51 in
Ethnomethodology and the Human Sciences, edited by G. Button. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Kitsuse, John I. 1962. “Societal Reaction to Deviant Behavior: Problems of Theory and
Method.” Social Problems 9(3):247–56. doi: 10.2307/799235.
Kitsuse, John I., and Aaron V. Cicourel. 1963. “A Note on the Uses of Official Statistics.”
Social Problems 11(2):131–39. doi: 10.2307/799220.
Lee, John R. E. 1984. “Innocent Victims and Evil-Doers.” Women’s Studies International
Forum 7(1):69–83. doi: 10.1016/0277-5395(84)90086-4.
Lindesmith, Alfred R. 1938. “A Sociological Theory of Drug Addiction.” American Journal
of Sociology 43(4):593–613.
Longino, Helen E. 2002. The Fate of Knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Loseke, Donileen R. 1992. The Battered Woman and Shelters. Albany: State University of
New York Press.
Lynch, Michael. 1982. “Closure and Disclosure in Pre-Trial Argument.” Human Studies
5(1):285–318. doi: 10.1007/bf02127682.
Lynch, Michael. 1983. “Accommodation Practices: Vernacular Treatments of Madness.”
Social Problems 31(2):152–64. doi: 10/ggxnhj.
Garfinkel, Social Problems, and Deviance 249
Introduction
the latter to address what he considered to be lacunae in the action theory of the
former (see Garfinkel [1962] 2019; see also Heritage 1984). Sacks, by compar-
ison, while engaging and briefly collaborating with Garfinkel, neither addressed
Parsons nor drew particularly from the phenomenologists, and ultimately
diverged from Garfinkel’s approach in important ways. Erving Goffman’s work
was another source of inspiration, but Sacks was as selective in his engagement
with Goffman as he was with Garfinkel, synthesizing certain key ideas from both
figures with those of his collaborators Emanuel Schegloff and Gail Jefferson. The
conversation analytic discipline that emerged from this synthesis was geared
to advancing a simultaneously rigorous and thoroughly emic science of the
“witnessable order” (Livingston 2008) of human interaction.
This analogy, which Harold Garfinkel wrote in 1948, was directed toward the
social and linguistic sciences as then constituted in mid-twentieth century social
thought. A central assumption of that period was that everyday reasoning and so-
cial interaction are inherently disorderly (Garfinkel 1988; Sacks 1984). The social
sciences have attempted to use the hammer of social structures, invoking features
such as gender, race, and class as resources for explaining actual social conduct
(cf., Goffman 1964), but striking very few targets in the process. Linguistics, for
its part, whether in the work of Saussure, Bloomfield, or Chomsky, was premised
on the idea that spoken interaction is an impoverished and disorganized version
of linguistic competence, which may be discerned through grammatical analysis
centered largely on written texts (Harris 1981; Linell 2004). As Garfinkel, and
later Sacks, would see it, both disciplinary perspectives rely on relatively inert
tools—the structural “hammers” of their respective disciplines—that ultimately
occlude the processual realities of language, interaction, and social organization
as elements of lived experience.
Both Garfinkel and Sacks recognized this fundamental hammer and fly-swat-
ting problem, and the need for inquiries that are accountable to the indigenous
forms of organization that societal members themselves recognize and put into
254 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
practice, but their approaches were strikingly different. Briefly put, Garfinkel in-
itially used phenomenologically informed inquiries to gain access to the socially
organized world of everyday life, deploying incongruity experiments and further
forms of demonstration to expose otherwise-hidden methods of practical rea-
soning. Sacks, by contrast, was drawn to a more naturalistic style of inquiry and
a focus on non-contrived conduct in interaction, exploiting the affordances of
audio and video recordings to reveal the dynamics of action-production and rec-
ognition as it develops sequentially in real time.
In pursuing the analysis of everyday conduct, both Garfinkel and Sacks in ef-
fect put down the hammer, but the replacement tools they picked up were very
different and have yielded mutually sympathetic but ultimately divergent lines
of inquiry. To see how Garfinkel originated his own approach, we briefly review
a 1948 dissertation proposal, which adumbrated an initial interest in exploring
the domain of interaction. Although it represents a “road not taken” by Garfinkel
himself, it included an initial and highly prescient effort to grapple with the
context-dependency of meaning and action in everyday life. This theme would
later inform Studies in Ethnomethodology. Tellingly, it would also inform Sacks’s
treatment of the sequential organization of interaction.
The analogy about hammers and flies that we quoted earlier is from Seeing
Sociologically (Garfinkel [1948] 2006), a document originally designed as a
dissertation proposal. Although the dissertation project it foreshadowed was
never realized (it would be one proposal among several that Garfinkel assem-
bled), the document circulated in mimeograph form among graduate students at
Harvard and later among “several key thinkers,” including Erving Goffman (who
commented on it), Anselm Strauss, and Harvey Sacks (Rawls 2006:2).
Seeing Sociologically raises two original and fundamental problems bearing
on the intelligibility of social behavior, that would later gain increasing promi-
nence within ethnomethodology and allied approaches. One is the concision of
everyday speech, which always conveys more than what a dictionary provides.
As Garfinkel ([1948] 2006:105) put it, “One need only listen to what is actually
said between two close friends to realize that the heard speech conveys infinitely
more than Webster would have allowed.”
A second problem is related to what Garfinkel would later discuss under the
rubrics of the documentary method of interpretation (Garfinkel 1962) and in-
dexical expressions (Garfinkel 1967:4–7). He observes that, “. . . as far as the
problems of communication are concerned, any sign can signify anything in the
communicative universe. (Garfinkel [1948] 2006:106, italics in original). This
ETHNOMETHODOLOGY AND CONVERSATION ANALYSIS 255
observation is not to be confused with the claim that there is an arbitrary rela-
tion between sign and meaning. Rather it goes to the import of any utterance as
a communicative action that achieves its status as such through its relationship
with context. With these dual problems of meaning—the concision of speech
and its context dependency—Garfinkel ([1948] 2006:144–45) was staking out a
social territory consisting of “actual experiences,” and “working acts performed
with reference to another actor,” which he characterizes in an understated way as
“a field that is practically unexplored.”
Parsonian social theory had failed to take these fundamental matters
into account, instead developing an “action frame of reference” and stipu-
lating “meanings” by way of pattern variables designating internalized value
orientations to explain so- called unit acts (Heritage 1984:20). In Seeing
Sociologically, by contrast, Garfinkel sought to minimize theoretical imposi-
tion by coming to terms with the indigenously meaningful experience of human
action when sign-meanings require expansion and adjustment in context. The
ensuing discussion will bring us forward from 1948 to other work on the docu-
mentary method of interpretation and on indexical expressions.
Thus far we have identified two fundamental problems that Garfinkel targeted—
how “heard speech conveys infinitely more than Webster would have allowed”
(its concision, for short), and how “any sign can signify anything in the commu-
nicative universe” (its flexibility, due to context embeddedness). Now we con-
sider how he evinced an early concern with social interaction, only to abandon
this topic in favor of common-sense knowledge and methods of reasoning. This
shift in focus is what would come to distinguish ethnomethodology from the
emerging field of conversation analysis.
In his concern with direct experience, Garfinkel referred to and explicated the
notion of “communication.” He was at pains to avoid the term “interaction” be-
cause in the 1940s it was associated with the stimulus-response theories of B. F.
Skinner (Rawls 2006:25). We will, however, use the term “interaction” because
it posits the radical priority of the actor’s immediate relations with others (Rawls
2006:179) over the self as the locus of meaning and order. Garfinkel’s ([1948]
2006:181) characterization of interaction encompasses, first, the “products of
communication” or “signs,” which include “occurrences of his speaking” as well as
“his own gestures” as they occur “in the space and time of the outer world” within
the speaker’s “vivid presence.” Second, besides speaking, listening, and gesturing
and their temporal and spatial constitution, Garfinkel ([1948] 2006:182–83)
introduces the matter of “style” or the “manner of delivery,” the ways in which
256 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
things are said, including “tone, tics, posture, physical gesture, inflection” and “au-
ditory coordinates” such as “pitch, intensity, and loudness.”
It bears emphasis that Garfinkel was working at a time when there were few
sources other than the phenomenologists, and particularly Schütz (see Chapter 2,
this volume), who could offer any guidance for the analysis of actual lived experi-
ence in interaction, including signs and their manner of delivery. However, these
phenomenological guides mainly provided for what it is that needs to be studied
and understood sociologically: the actor’s lived experience as constituted in con-
crete real-time interaction with others. As for how to do this, Garfinkel’s own ap-
proach would come to involve experimental manipulations of “incongruities” to
see what their effects could tell us about the background expectancies involved in
the lived structures of everyday life. This turn toward the underlying assumptions
and presuppositions involved in the structuring of everyday experience found
Garfinkel proceeding along a different track than that which later emerged from
Sacks’s focus on the in-course organization of interaction as displayed in real
time. As explored in Garfinkel’s dissertation, and in later writings about incon-
gruities, the devices for resolving incongruity are methods that experimental
subjects deploy in response to disruptions produced by others. Thus, we learn
about how subjects display their common-sense assumptions in response to in-
teractional disruptions, but we learn less about how these assumptions are inter-
subjectively managed within the flow of undisrupted and hence routine courses
of interaction (Garfinkel [1948] 2006:207).
In effect, having uncovered the deficiencies of social theory in dealing with
everyday experience (see Chapter 2 in this volume), Garfinkel could only make
the organization of such experience visible by disabling it. “Procedurally,”
Garfinkel (1967:37) says, “it is my preference to start with familiar scenes and
ask what can be done to make trouble.” The result of this trouble-making strategy
was to provide for the visibility of a substrate of trust that lies in back of ordinary
social behavior (Garfinkel 1963) without exploring the intelligible structuring of
the behavior itself.
Papers from the late 1950s and early 1960s, later incorporated in Studies in
Ethnomethodology (1967), address both of these problems. Garfinkel succinctly
illustrated the problem of concision by way of a simple procedure in which he
asked students to write out an informal conversation of theirs on the left side of a
sheet of paper, and then to elaborate “what they were talking about” on the right
side (Garfinkel 1967:38–42). Participants had no trouble describing assumed
background knowledge on that right side and seeing that it was vastly more than
the (comparatively) meager amount of actual talk on the left side. However, they
began to find it irksome when Garfinkel persuaded them that their elaborations
themselves required further elaboration.
In the face of the participants’ inability to address utterance meaning
through literal or dictionary-defined description, Garfinkel (1959:57) turned
to Karl Mannheim’s (1952) notion of the “documentary method of interpre-
tation.” In everyday situations, routinely concise and at times telegraphic
utterances are understood in relation to a presumptively existing social con-
text. In Mannheim’s treatment, utterance and context elaborate one another
in a process in which the context contributes to an understanding of the ut-
terance, and in turn the utterance contributes to an understanding of the con-
text. There is therefore a reciprocal, mutually elaborative relationship between
utterance and context. In commenting on the “conversation clarification” pro-
cess, Garfinkel (1964:228–29) drew attention to “the role of time as it is consti-
tutive of ‘the matter talked about’ as a developing and developed event over the
course of action that produced it, as both the process and product were known
from within this development by both parties, each for himself as well as on
behalf of the other.” Indeed, regarding how one interlocutor waits for the other
to say something further to understand the significance of what had been said,
Garfinkel (1964:229) observes, “the sense of the expressions depended upon
where the expression occurred in serial order, the expressive character of the
terms that comprised it, and the importance to the conversationalists of the
events depicted.”
Garfinkel’s second problem—flexibility—is deeply related to the first, the
problem of concision. For if the meanings of words, sentences, and utterances
are expanded and specified by reference to context, then there may be no fea-
sible limit on the varying meanings that can be invested in expressions. A vivid
illustration is this utterance, produced in a telephone call in which the speaker
is reflecting on the losses stemming from a house fire: “I guess the hardest thing
is things that meant things. You know?” In this readily intelligible sentence, ev-
idently the word “thing” is invested with three quite distinct meanings. At the
level of action as well, utterances can be treated very differently depending on
whether the speaker is understood in context to be: “talking synonymously,
talking ironically, talking metaphorically, talking cryptically, talking narratively,
258 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
nuances without the theoretical baggage of logical empiricism. In this sense, Sacks
began his empirical researches from the point that Wittgenstein had reached after a
long struggle with a common adversary, the essentialist view of sign meanings that
was so deeply entrenched in philosophy and the social sciences.
In a later joint paper with Sacks, On Formal Structures of Practical Actions
(Garfinkel and Sacks 1970), Garfinkel once again raised indexical expressions as
problematic,2 commenting on the bulk of social scientific efforts to “remedy” in-
dexical expressions. He also noted that these attempts to substitute context-free
for context-bound expressions involved a process that his own investigations
demonstrated was doomed to futility. But these Sisyphean efforts need to be dis-
tinguished from how lay members orient to the inherent contextuality of lan-
guage and meaning. Accordingly, having noted how speech “contains more”
than its denotations, and may “signify anything” by way of indexical expressions,
Garfinkel remains preoccupied with the problematics of indexical expressions
for the social sciences, one that is less effective in raising empirical questions
about how participants adapt and use these inherent features of everyday lan-
guage use. Conversely, Sacks’s starting point is not with theoretically pre-identi-
fied problems, but with observations that directly illuminate naturally occurring
conduct in flight, revealing the indigenous uses to which indexical expressions
are put in everyday actions and activities.
In sum, Garfinkel’s treatment of the concision and flexibility of ordinary
speech arose from a critique of Parsonian theory’s failure to deal with funda-
mental aspects of social interchange, but his empirical research was inspired
by phenomenological writings that pointed toward a taken-for-granted do-
main of common-sense knowledge and forms of reasoning. The incongruity
demonstrations succeeded brilliantly in exposing the utterly foundational do-
main of indexical expressions and their reflexive relation to their circumstances
of use, making them available for analytic appreciation. These demonstrations
were less successful in showing how an empirical program might build a
systematic investigation of these phenomena. When Garfinkel refers to how
participants manage social settings by way of their “account-able” conduct, he
means that there are actual, real-time practices for both producing and rec-
ognizing the setting and its features. It has been Sacks and allied conversation
analysts, however, who have carried the investigation of such practices forward.
The line from Garfinkel to Sacks is best appreciated in conjunction with other lines
of inspiration and influence, and in light of Sacks’s own scholarly pursuits which
conditioned the kinds of resources to which he was exposed and what he made
ETHNOMETHODOLOGY AND CONVERSATION ANALYSIS 261
of them. Harold Garfinkel figures centrally in this process, together with Erving
Goffman, a second and relatively underappreciated contributor to the conversation
analytic lineage. Sacks drew from these and other sources, but what he took from
them is hardly more significant than what he left behind, and he also embraced
methodological innovations from his collaborators Emanuel Schegloff and Gail
Jefferson. The creative synthesis that emerged from all of this was heavily shaped by
Sacks’s own abiding interest in developing a thoroughly emic but rigorous science of
social action.
Law School
Sacks’s relevant academic background begins, not in sociology, but at Yale Law
School, where he received his LLB in 1959. A central component of legal training
involves applying general legal principles to specific cases, whether the principles
are formally codified in statutes or inferred from precedent. This form of legal
training, which interrogates the fit between abstract codes of conduct and concrete
events, may have predisposed Sacks toward a receptivity to Garfinkel’s exploration
of the common-sense reasoning required to implement social norms and rules of
conduct in everyday life. This association, although somewhat speculative, is rein-
forced by Schegloff ’s (1992a:xiii) firsthand account of a story told by Sacks about
a problem in case law—how low can an airplane fly before it becomes “unreason-
able” and vulnerable to property-owner lawsuits?—exemplifying the largely tacit
but nonetheless controlling power of ordinary common sense in professional legal
reasoning. Puzzles of this sort appear to have led Sacks away from the practice of
law and toward an interest in its sociological underpinnings.
Of potential relevance also is the fact that the case method approach to legal
training relies heavily on formal Socratic dialogue between professors and students.
This pedagogical approach, which emphasizes active problem-solving and public
accountability within an interrogative framework, emerged at Harvard Law School
in the late 1800s under the influence of the then-prevalent pragmatist theory of
learning, and quickly spread to become the dominant approach to legal training
(Garvin 2003). As we discuss later in the chapter, formal dialogue would become
a source of inspiration for Sacks as he began to focus on talk as a phenomenon and
speaking practices as constraints on conduct (Schegloff 1992a:xv–xvi).
Garfinkel
Sacks’s relationship to Harold Garfinkel dates to his later law school years,
when he was reconsidering a career in the law but had not yet made the leap
262 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Goffman
Just as Sacks drew selectively from Garfinkel, the same can be said of his rela-
tionship to Erving Goffman. The Goffman that would prove influential for
Sacks was not the analyst of total institutions and social stigma, ritual and cer-
emony, or even self-presentation, although this latter was closer to the mark; it
was rather the Goffman who pioneered the study of the interaction order as a
sociological specialization. This pithy term was coined by Goffman in his 1981
American Sociological Association (ASA) presidential address (published in
1983), substantially after Sacks’s own untimely death in 1975. The approach to
which it referred, however, was Goffman’s long-standing preoccupation from
his 1953 doctoral dissertation onward (Kendon 1990). Here we focus mainly
on Goffman’s programmatic statements and analyses (e.g., Goffman 1963, 1964,
1967), prior to and concurrent with Sacks’s early work.
As far back as his dissertation, Goffman proposed that the domain of in-
teraction between persons is a species of social organization comprising rules
governing various and sundry interactional occasions. Goffman worked to ab-
stract from otherwise diverse occasions “the orderliness that is common to all
of them, the orderliness that obtains by virtue of the fact that those present are
engaged in spoken communication” (Goffman’s 1953 dissertation, quoted in
Kendon 1990:39). This form of order underlies the more familiar institutional
and structural orders of society, but it is not merely a neutral medium in which
other structures operate and are reproduced (Goffman 1964); it is a partially au-
tonomous order with its own organizational integrity. Later, Goffman would de-
scribe this order as a social institution in its own right, and its norms as a system
of enabling conventions not unlike “the ground rules of a game, the provisions
of a traffic code, or the syntax of a language” (Goffman 1983:5). These abstract
ideas were fleshed out by Goffman’s observations of the specific norms and
conventions that distinguish unfocused from focused interaction, coordinate
entry into and exit from the latter, regulate attention and involvement, and other
elementary tasks intrinsic to the conduct of interaction per se.
Goffman maintained a thoroughly structural conception of the interaction
order, which he characterized with a transparent albeit tongue-in-cheek nod to
Durkheim as “a reality sui generis as He used to say” (Goffman 1964:134). He
later famously elaborated on this idea, portraying it as a level of social reality that
transcends the individual:
I assume that the proper study of interaction is not the individual and his psy-
chology, but rather the syntactical relations among the acts of different persons
mutually present to one another. . . . Not, then, men and their moments, but
rather moments and their men. (Goffman 1967:2)
264 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
There is a direct conceptual line from Goffman’s “moments and their men” to
Sacks’s conversational “machinery.”
At the methodological level, Goffman’s imprint is further apparent in the
naturalistic thrust of Sacks’s approach, which strongly emphasizes non-con-
trived data in conjunction with a specimen-collection approach to data gathering
(Maynard and Clayman 2018), a methodology common in geology, botany, and
zoology, as well as the then-emerging field of ethology, which had a direct in-
fluence both on Goffman and on the context analytic framework developed by
Fromm-Reichmann, Hockett, and Bateson, among others, at Palo Alto (Kendon
1990; Leeds-Hurwitz 1987; Scheflen 1966). Specimen-collecting involves the
compilation of numerous exhibits of a given phenomenon for systematic com-
parison and analysis in relation to the contexts in which they occur. The develop-
ment of collections, as a component of CA methodology, is a theme we take up
later in this chapter.
Notwithstanding these conceptual and methodological continuities, Sacks’s
engagement with Goffman was just as partial and selective as it was with
Garfinkel. There is no evident interest in asylums or other total institutions,
and only marginal interest in dramaturgy, self-presentation, or stigma manage-
ment. And while Sacks took up Goffman’s call for a sociology of the interaction
order, he was not particularly interested in those aspects that most preoccupied
Goffman, namely the intertwined phenomena of face, ritual, and ceremony. As
Schegloff (1988) has observed:
Goffman’s focus on patterns of talk and action was tied to ritual and face,
and resisted “secularization” to the syntax of action. . . . On this reading, the
ETHNOMETHODOLOGY AND CONVERSATION ANALYSIS 265
Sacks’s (1984) contrasting orientation toward the prospect of “order at all points”
yielded a far broader interest in the dynamics of action and sequence, and would
eventuate in the investigation of generic systems of practice that solve the most
fundamental problems that interactants face: how to manage the orderly transfer
of speakership, resolve problems of speaking, hearing, and understanding, and
so on (Heritage 2008; Schegloff 2006).
Sacks’s debt to both Garfinkel and Goffman is overtly acknowledged in an early
paper (Sacks 1972a), and the interweaving of threads from both mentors imparts
a highly distinctive cast to his work. This is nowhere more evident than in the si-
multaneous pursuit of, and indeed tension between, analytic specificity and gen-
erality. The Garfinkelian emphasis on the indexical properties of expressions and
a continued openness to the “something more” that each instance-in-context can
provide, sits alongside the Goffmanian pursuit of the structural “conversational
machinery” at the heart of the interaction order. How to combine and reconcile
these very different analytic sensibilities was by no means obvious at the outset
and would take time to develop.
If Goffman and Garfinkel guided Sacks toward the domain of the interaction
order and methods of reasoning operating within and upon it, the interest in
talk per se and recorded and transcribed talk in particular came from elsewhere.
For the affordances and rigors of such data, his mentors provided little if any
guidance. Goffman’s methods were predominantly ethnographic, although
supplemented with the data of etiquette manuals and mass media accounts.3
Garfinkel, for his part, conducted ethnographic interviews for the Agnes study
(1967:Chapter 5) but, as discussed previously, he favored experiments and
quasi-experimental demonstrations in much of his work. Furthermore, leading
theorists of the day in both sociology and linguistics were promoting ideas
whose analytical abstractness—e.g., Parsons (1937) on “the unit act” vs. concrete
actions in real time, and Chomsky (1957) on language as a formal system vs.
actual speech—ran against the grain of using concrete and ostensibly “messy”
everyday talk as data. Why and how, then, did recordings and transcriptions of
naturally occurring talk-in-interaction enter into Sacks’s research?
266 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
To address this puzzle, it bears emphasis that Sacks had an abiding interest in
developing a more rigorous science of social life. If his commitment was toward
an emic rather than a positivistic discipline, it was one characterized by greater
descriptive precision and the accountability of analytic judgments. In the schol-
arly community then concerned with the domain of everyday life, this ambition
was distinctive and was formed quite early in Sacks’s graduate career. It evidently
predates his first recorded lectures on conversation (in the fall of 1964), his dis-
sertation research on suicide calls, and even his fellowship year at the Center for
the Scientific Study of Suicide (1963–1964) from which the dissertation project
would emerge. In his very first publication, “Sociological Description,” which
appeared in the student-run Berkeley Journal of Sociology, Sacks (1963) expressed
dissatisfaction with prominent social science methods such as Durkheim’s sta-
tistical generalizations and Weber’s ideal types. The abstractness and impreci-
sion of such methods, he argued, were rooted in their elementary descriptive
practices, which relied on “common-sense categories as sociological resources
rather than as features of social life which sociology must treat as subject matter”
(Sacks 1963:16). This daunting problem was diagnosed in Garfinkelian terms,
but it was paired with a strikingly un-Garfinkelian expression of optimism about
the prospects for greater descriptive rigor:
Such optimism was part and parcel of Sacks’s overt commitment to scientific
advance:
I take it that at least some sociologists seek to make a science of the discipline;
this is a concern I share, and it is only from the perspective of such a concern
that the ensuing discussion seems appropriate. (Sacks 1963:2)
Sacks’s empirical research from the 1960s, conducted before conversation anal-
ysis had crystallized as a field of study, can be found in his dissertation project
and related publications (Sacks 1967, 1972b, 1972a), his UCLA and UC Irvine
lectures from that time period (Sacks 1992a, 1992b), and sole-authored articles
published later but originating in those early lectures (e.g., Sacks 1975, 1978).
An overarching interest in “methods,” “procedures,” or “devices” for doing things
permeates this work, each explicated through the detailed analysis of a single
case or comparative analysis of a small number of cases. Within this general ap-
proach, three thematic clusters may be discerned.
“Everyone Has to Lie,” published in 1975 but originating in lectures from 1967,
illustrates this range of interests. The paper explicates common-sense know-
ledge regarding social identities and personal information transfer, in conjunc-
tion with knowledge of conversational structure and sequence—namely the
exchange of greetings and personal state queries (e.g., How are you?) at conver-
sational openings. While this paper resembles other accounts-and-social-rea-
soning papers in its overall narrative trajectory, the sequential elements shade
over into the next type of paper.
Of the three main lines of work that Sacks would develop, this line on accounts
and social reasoning is most heavily indebted to Garfinkel, and in particular his
preoccupation with indexical expressions. Even so, the stark contrast between
Garfinkel’s breaching-experiment approach and Sacks’s naturalistic, conversa-
tional data-driven, and more action-focused approach to the same phenomenon
is an early harbinger of developments to come.
A second body of work concerns devices or practices for the performance of con-
versational actions. This work tends to exhibit greater attention to the situated
nature of such practices and the responses they receive, once again addressing
the indexical properties of expressions, but this time in relation to the sequencing
of action and thus anticipating the development of sequential organization as a
primary focus of CA research. Work in this vein can be found throughout Sacks’s
(1992a, 1992b) lectures and some of the sole-authored papers derived from them
(Sacks 1975), as well as later sole-authored papers on agreement and contiguity
(Sacks 1987), and joke-telling (Sacks 1974). Contrary to the widespread belief
that Sacks began focusing on accounts and social reasoning and only later devel-
oped an interest in action and sequencing, in reality both kinds of analytic efforts
are intermingled throughout the earliest lectures. This point is obscured by the
(often) delayed publications, which, as we noted earlier, have dates that bear little
relationship to the timing of the research on which they are based.
The most telling evidence for the simultaneous development of work on ac-
counts/social reasoning and action/sequence can be found in the first year
(1964–1965) of Sacks’s lectures on conversation. These lectures were contem-
poraneous with the dissertation research in progress and constitute the earliest
written record of his empirical research interests. His very first lecture at UCLA
is entitled “Rules of Conversational Sequence” and concerns telephone conversa-
tion openings, the organization of sequences devoted to greetings and identifica-
tion, self-identification as an indirect method of soliciting an interlocutor’s name
without explicitly asking for it, and “hearing trouble” as a method of avoiding
270 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
giving one’s name without explicitly refusing to do so. The next two lectures are
also focused on forms of action in sequence. Other lectures are concerned with
accounts, MCDs, and related forms of social reasoning (most notably Lecture
5: “Suicide as a device for discovering if anybody cares,” Lecture 6: “The MIR
membership categorization device,” and Lecture 9: “I am nothing”), but at least
half of that first year of lectures focus on matters arising from the production and
sequencing of action. For instance:
A third thematic cluster, emerging in the second year of Sacks’s lectures (1965–
1966), addressed the broader sociocultural implications of specific activity
frameworks. For instance, in an analysis plainly inspired by the Opies’ studies
of childhood games, Sacks (1980) argued that a game called “Button, button,
who’s got the button” offered children the opportunity to learn and practice
methods of dissembling and concealment. In a similar vein, Sacks (1979) exam-
ined teenagers discussing cars to develop the idea that teenage language use was
a means of creating specialized concepts and terminology that could escape the
control of adults. In a paper on responses to “how are you?” questions, Sacks
(1975) addressed (among other things) social constraints in the regulation of in-
formation about personal problems. And a dirty joke told by, and to, teenagers
(Sacks 1974, 1978) was explored by reference to the way such jokes can be “tests”
of sexual knowledge and understanding, and can partition knowing from un-
knowing joke recipients.
The generalizability offered in these lectures, and the papers that were sub-
sequently published from them, traded off the functionality he attributed to
the interactional practices he described, underwritten by reference to the eth-
nographic and cultural contexts in which they were situated. Some of the early
ETHNOMETHODOLOGY AND CONVERSATION ANALYSIS 271
The early 1960s, then, saw Sacks pursuing the development of an emic science
of what Eric Livingston would later call the “witnessable order” concerned with
“how members of society produce and sustain the observable orderlinesses of
their own activities” (Livingston 2008:124). He was also committed to the fun-
damental ethnomethodological theorem that was the centerpiece of Studies in
Ethnomethodology. As Garfinkel succinctly stated it, this was the proposal that
Later, Sacks commented (Hill and Crittenden 1968:41) that “there can be a set of
rules which can reproduce the problems in the data with which you started,” and
subsequently he was still more explicit:
the idea is to take singular sequences of conversation and tear them apart in
such a way as to find rules, techniques, procedures, methods, maxims [that]
can be used to generate the orderly features we find in the conversations we ex-
amine. The idea being, then, to come back to the singular things we observe in a
singular sequence, with some rules that handle those singular features, and also
necessarily handle lots of other events as well. (Sacks 1992b:339)
It was this focus on generativity that would eventually displace Goffman’s in-
fluence on Sacks’s approach to analysis. In place of normative rules in defining
272 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
and honoring self and other, Sacks substituted a focus on social action as a
product of formally describable methodic practices that could also serve as
resources in the management of intersubjective understanding. Treating sin-
gular specimens of action as constituted through, and evidence of, generative
methods for action production and recognition opened the door to a new ap-
proach to the study of action, one that contrasted with approaches pursuing
normative rules as independent causal factors identified through frequencies
and measures of association. Generative methods of action could be seen to
be operating anywhere, constituting a foundation not just for the generation
of action but also for its intelligibility and learnability. This was a completely
novel and distinctive conception of what generalizability in social science
could become (Sacks 1984:21).
In the early days, though, the search for this kind of generative generaliza-
bility was far from easy. The “terrible and essential” problem, as Sacks put it in
a later note to Schegloff (March 1974), was isolating “structure in particulars.”
This problem arises from the fact that methods for the production of actions ap-
pear in the midst of complex streams of singular actions in particular contexts.
Disentangling what might be context-free and generative about a practice
meant discerning “essence” from “accident” with little, if any, disciplinary guid-
ance (ibid.)
The identification of reproducible specimens of such methods in action, how-
ever, turned out to be critical. In his first lecture described earlier, focused on con-
versational sequences early in telephone conversations to a Suicide Prevention
Center (SPC), Sacks observed that, after an initial exchange, the conversations
could have alternative trajectories:
If the staff member used “This is Mr Smith may I help you” as their opening
line, then overwhelmingly, any answer other than “Yes, this is Mr Brown” (for
example, “I can’t hear you,” “I don’t know,” “How do you spell your name?”)
ETHNOMETHODOLOGY AND CONVERSATION ANALYSIS 273
meant that you would have serious trouble getting the caller’s name, if you got
the name at all.” (Sacks 1992a:4)
Among other things, Sacks observed that the self-identification of the first line
functions as an invitation for the caller to reciprocate, as happens in the first case
in the preceding, and that it does so in a way that is not overt and that does not
open the way to the provision of explanations in the way that “May I have your
name?” might. Moreover, in the second of the two cases, he observed, the caller
does not ignore the SPC staffer’s overture; rather, his assertion of not hearing the
name invites the staffer to repeat it. It thus fills the “slot” in which the caller might
have responded with his own name. At the same time, the caller’s response is not
hearable as a “withholding” of his name, but rather as addressed to a hearing
difficulty that preempts response and does so “reasonably.” Finally, after the re-
peat “This is Mr Smith,” the caller can use the following slot to acknowledge the
name rather than give his own. Here, then, several conversational practices are
deployed in a sequence in which a caller is invited to give his name “off the re-
cord” and avoids doing so in an equally “off record” fashion—the whole event
being intelligible in terms of a context-specific confluence of generic rules of
conversational sequencing.
At the core of Sacks’s argument is the claim that conversational objects like
“I can’t hear you”4 may cluster into a discernible practice, or set of practices,
that can have particular and singular consequences in different situations of
action. About this, Sacks comments that conversational objects such as “I can’t
hear you”
can be used for whole ranges of activities, where for different ones a variety of
the properties of those objects will get employed. And we begin to see alterna-
tive properties of those objects. That’s one way we can go about beginning to
collect the alternative methods that persons use in going about doing whatever
they have to do. (Sacks 1992a:11)
There was a very classical argument that it would not be that way; that sin-
gular events were singular events, given a historian’s sort of argument, that
they just happen and they get more or less accidentally thrown together. But
if we could find that there are analytically hard ways of describing these
things—where, that is, we’re talking about objects that can be found else-
where, that get placed, that have ways of being used; that are abstract objects
which get used on singular occasions and describe singular courses of
274 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
What we have seen so far, however, was a promissory note, embodying in-
tense theoretical intuitions, yet issued with, at best, a hazy notion of how
results could be delivered. The fundamental and “terrible” problem was
that, if social action is methodic in both its production and recognition, as
Garfinkel had proposed, this methodicity nonetheless emerges as situated in
particular occasions that are singular and locally contexted. How are these
contexts to be described and their relevant scope delimited? As Schegloff
(1992a) observes:
Starting out with a commitment to lay bare the methodicity of ordinary activ-
ities, and with his talent for seeing in singular occurrences the structural elem-
ents of which they were formed and composed, a world of data which refreshed
itself every moment . . . provided a virtual infinity of opportunities for new
observations, and new orders of observation. (1992a:lviii)
In addition, the respondent in (4) packs the unit prior to the disagreement with
items like “well” and “I don’t know” that can “get treated as ‘going in front of
disagreements,’ and that may have an import in signaling the future forthcom-
ingness of a disagreement” (Sacks 1987:59). Moreover, the disagreement itself
is “formed up so that the disagreement is as weak as possible” (Sacks 1987:58).5
Here, then, Sacks has identified a range of potentially recurrent practices used in
the formation of agreeing and disagreeing responses to question-based propos-
itions that accentuate agreement and downplay disagreement. These practices
operate at the level of sequence, concerning the relation between turns and, at
the level of the turn, concerned with the ordering of components within the turn.
Sacks next considers a set of related practices that avoid disagreement, but also
avoid accepting the proposition advanced by the question. For example, in (5),
the response could simply have been “No:”
Writing about this cluster of practices, Sacks articulates the import of non-rou-
tine or deviant cases within the analysis of specimen collections:
I am employing a strategy that we use a lot, and which therefore deserves a bit
of description. The strategy is this: if we can isolate, among the exceptions,
some classes—that does not mean some individual instances, but some
classes of instances (they have to have class-like characteristics)—which
278 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Thus far, we have focused on Sacks’s account of respondents’ practices for max-
imizing agreement, but questioners are also oriented to the same outcome. This
is shown in cases where, hearing a delay in response and anticipating disagree-
ment, questioners revise their questions in ways geared to promoting agreement.
The clearest cases are those in which the second question reverses the polarity of
the first.
Conclusion
continuation rather than closure. And the entire analysis is grounded in the
displayed understandings of the participants, understandings that inform the
turn-by-turn production of each closing episode and are the central means by
which the participants show each other “where they are” in the closing pro-
cess (e.g., “winding down,” “ready to close but still in conversation,” etc.). These
Garfinkelian themes are underscored in a well-known and frequently cited in-
troductory passage:
We have proceeded under the assumption (an assumption borne out by our
research) that insofar as the materials we worked with exhibited orderliness,
they did so not only for us, indeed not in the first place for us, but for the
co-participants who had produced them. If the materials (records of natural
conversations) were orderly, they were so because they bad been methodi-
cally produced by members of the society for one another, and it was a feature
of the conversations that we treated as data that they were produced so as to
allow the display by the co-participants to each other of their orderliness, and
to allow the participants to display to each other their analysis, appreciation,
and use of that orderliness. Accordingly, our analysis has sought to explicate
the ways in which the materials are produced by members in orderly ways
that exhibit their orderliness, have their orderliness appreciated and used,
and have that appreciation displayed and treated as the basis for subsequent
action. (Schegloff and Sacks 1973:290)
References
Button, G., and J. R. E. Lee, eds. 1987. Talk and Social Organisation. Clevedon, UK:
Multilingual Matters.
Chomsky, N. 1957. Syntactic Structures. The Hague: Mouton.
Clayman, Steven E. 1993. “Booing: The Anatomy of a Disaffiliative Response.” American
Sociological Review 58(1):110–30. doi: 10/c7p9jg.
282 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Clayman, Steven E. 2002. “Sequence and Solidarity.” Pp. 229–53 in Group Cohesion,
Trust and Solidarity, Advances in Group Processes, edited by S. R. Thye and E. J. Lawler.
Bingley, UK: Emerald Group.
Coulter, Jeff. 2016. “Ethnomethodology and ‘Linguistic Phenomenology.’ ” Paper
Presented at the Radical Ethnomethodology Conference, Manchester Metropolitan
University, UK. Radicalethno.Org, downloaded September 24, 2019. A video re-
cording of this paper is available at https://radicalethno.org/meetings.html, though the
text of the paper is no longer available.
Davidson, Judy A. 1984. “Subsequent Versions of Invitations, Offers, Requests, and
Proposals Dealing with Potential or Actual Rejection.” Pp. 102–28 in Structures of
Social Action: Studies in Conversation Analysis, edited by J. M. Atkinson and J. Heritage.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Davidson, Judy A. 1990. “Modifications of Invitations, Offers and Rejections.” Pp. 149–
80 in Interaction Competence, edited by G. Psathas. Washington, DC: International
Institute for Ethnomethodology and Conversation Analysis and University Press of
America.
Drew, Paul, and Elizabeth Couper-Kuhlen. 2014. Requesting in Social Interaction. Vol. 26.
John Benjamins.
Enfield, N. J., Tanya Stivers, Penelope Brown, Christina Englert, Katariina Harjunpää,
Makoto Hayashi, Trine Heinemann, Gertie Hoymann, Tiina Keisanen, Mirka
Rauniomaa, Chase Wesley Raymond, Federico Rossano, Kyung- Eun Yoon, Inge
Zwitserlood, and Stephen C. Levinson. 2019. “Polar Answers.” Journal of Linguistics
55(2):277–304. doi: 10/ghk6bn.
Garfinkel, H. 1959. “Aspects of the Problems of Commonsense Knowledge of Social
Structures.” Transactions of the Fourth World Congress of Sociology 4:51–65.
Garfinkel, H. 1962. “Commonsense Knowledge of Social Structures: The Documentary
Method of Interpretation.” Pp. 689–712 in Theories of the Mind, edited by J. Scher.
New York: Free Press.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1963. “A Conception of, and Experiments with, ‘Trust’ as a Condition of
Stable Concerted Actions.” Pp. 187–238 in Motivation and Social Interaction: Cognitive
Determinants, edited by O. J. Harvey. New York: Ronald Press.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1964. “Studies of the Routine Grounds of Everyday Activities.” Social
Problems 11(3):225–50.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1967. Studies in Ethnomethodology. Cambridge: Polity.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1974. “On the Origins of the Term ‘Ethnomethodology.’” Pp. 15–18 in
Ethnomethodology, edited by R. Turner. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1988. “Evidence for Locally Produced, Naturally Accountable
Phenomena of Order, Logic, Reason, Meaning, Method, Etc. in and as of the Essential
Quiddity of Immortal Ordinary Society, (I of IV): An Announcement of Studies.”
Sociological Theory 6(1):103–9. doi: 10.2307/201918.
Garfinkel, Harold. 2002. Ethnomethodology’s Program: Working Out Durkeim’s Aphorism.
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Garfinkel, Harold. [1948] 2006. Seeing Sociologically: The Routine Grounds of Social
Action. Boulder, CO: Paradigm.
Garfinkel, Harold. [1962] 2019. “The Program of Ethnomethodology.” Pp. 327–38 in
Parsons’ Primer, edited by A. W. Rawls. New York: Springer.
Garfinkel, Harold, and Harvey Sacks. 1970. “On Formal Structures of Practical Actions.”
Pp. 337–66 in Theoretical Sociology: Perspectives and Developments, edited by J. C.
ETHNOMETHODOLOGY AND CONVERSATION ANALYSIS 283
Sacks, H. 1975. “Everyone Has to Lie.” Pp. 57–80 in Sociocultural Dimensions of Language
Use, edited by M. Sanches and B. G. Blount. New York: Academic Press.
Sacks, H. 1978. “Some Technical Considerations of a Dirty Joke.” Pp. 249– 69 in
Studies in the Organization of Conversational Interaction, edited by J. Schenkein.
New York: Academic Press.
Sacks, Harvey. 1979. “Hotrodder: A Revolutionary Category.” Pp. 7–14 in Everyday
Langauge: Studies in Ethnomethodology, edited by G. Psathas. New York: Irvington.
Sacks, Harvey. 1980. “Button Button Who’s Got the Button.” Sociological Inquiry
50(3–4):318–27. doi: 10.1111/j.1475-682x.1980.tb00025.x.
Sacks, Harvey. 1984. “Notes on Methodology.” Pp. 2– 27 in Structures of Social
Action: Studies in Conversation Analysis, edited by J. M. Atkinson and J. Heritage.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sacks, Harvey. 1987. “On the Preferences for Agreement and Contiguity in Sequences in
Conversation.” Pp. 54–69 in Talk and Social Organisation, edited by G. Button and J.
R. E. Lee. Clevedon, UK: Multilingual Matters.
Sacks, Harvey. 1992a. Lectures on Conversation. Vol. 1, edited by G. Jefferson. Oxford;
Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.
Sacks, Harvey. 1992b. Lectures on Conversation. Vol. 2, edited by G. Jefferson. Oxford;
Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.
Sacks, Harvey, and Emanuel A. Schegloff. 1973. “Opening up Closings.” Semiotica
8(4):289–327. doi: 10.1515/semi.1973.8.4.289.
Sacks, Harvey, Emanuel A. Schegloff, and Gail Jefferson. 1974. “A Simplest Systematics
for the Organization of Turn-Taking for Conversation.” Language 50(4):696–735.
doi: 10.2307/412243.
Scheflen, A. E. 1966. “Natural History Method in Psychotherapy: Communicational
Research.” Pp. 263–89 in Methods of Research in Psychotherapy, edited by L. A.
Gottschalk and A. H. Auerbach. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Schegloff, E. A. 1988. “Goffman and the Analysis of Conversation.” Pp. 89–135 in
Erving Goffman: Exploring the Interaction Order, edited by P. Drew and A. Wootton.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
Schegloff, E. A. 2006. “Interaction: The Infrastructure for Social Institutions, the
Natural Ecological Niche for Language and the Arena in Which Culture Is Enacted.”
Pp. 70–96 in The Roots of Human Sociality: Culture, Cognition and Interaction, edited
by N. J. Enfield and S. C. Levinson. New York: Berg.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1968. “Sequencing in Conversational Openings.” American
Anthropologist 70(6):1075–95. doi: 10.1525/aa.1968.70.6.02a00030.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1992a. “Introduction.” Pp. ix–lxii in Harvey Sacks, Lectures on
Conversation (Vol. 1: Fall 1964–Spring 1968). Vol. 1, edited by G. Jefferson. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1992b. “Introduction.” Pp. ix–lii in Harvey Sacks: Lectures on
Conversation (Vol. 2: Fall 1968–Spring 1972. Vol. 2, edited by G. Jefferson. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1997. “Practices and Actions: Boundary Cases of Other‐initiated
Repair.” Discourse Processes 23(3):499–545. doi: 10.1080/01638539709545001.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 2007. Sequence Organization in Interaction: A Primer in
Conversation Analysis, Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Schegloff, Emanuel A., Gail Jefferson, and Harvey Sacks. 1977. “The Preference for Self-
Correction in the Organization of Repair in Conversation.” Language 53(2):361–82.
286 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Introduction
This echoes Sacks’s (1992:226) point that “a culture is an apparatus for gener-
ating recognizable actions; if the same procedures are used for generating as for
detecting, that is perhaps as simple a solution to the problem of recognizability
as is formulatable.”
The production of accountable action is both locally situated and ordered.
In this respect, ethnomethodology and CA have often been contrasted for their
complementary focus: the former on the indexical, the latter on the systematic
features of action. Often ethnomethodology has been reduced, even caricatured,
to a perspective uniquely focused on the “hic et nunc” of social action; CA has
been depicted as primarily interested in the “machinery,” or the “apparatus,”
accounting for the reproducibility of social life. Consequently, the former has
been criticized for being too descriptive and not generalizable, and the latter for
a reductionist style of formal analysis. However, CA has been deeply engaged in
showing the context-shaping as well as context-shaped organization of action,
and ethnomethodology has continuously stressed the orderliness of social life as
the product of the methodical action of its members (Heritage 1984b). Against
the antagonistic versions that tend to oppose the two disciplines, rather than see
METHODIC PRODUCTION OF ACCOUNTABLE ACTION 291
their common history and concerns, in this chapter I attempt to develop a view of
situated and methodical action that takes into consideration both contributions.
Garfinkel’s legacy is important in this respect. On the one hand, he helps us
to consider the indexicality of multimodal resources (including language) as
being both an irremediable and a necessary feature of social action (Garfinkel
and Sacks 1970). Communicative resources—even the more conventionalized
ones, like grammar—are characterized by indefiniteness and underdetermina-
tion, which are contextually “filled-in” in actual usages. This points at the im-
portance of considering the haecceity of these resources: “The term ‘haecceity’
refers to the character of being here and now, the ‘just-thisness’ of any activity.
It is related to the hic of ‘hic et nunc’ ” (Garfinkel and Liberman 2007:4). The
study of haecceities is important for the disclosure of the local contingencies of
action (Lynch 1991:98). These aspects are even more crucial for multimodal ana-
lyses than for analyses only dealing with talk: the relevance of embodied details
depends largely on the features the participants locally exploit within the ecology
of the situated activity they are engaged in (Mondada 2014c), as we will see in the
following extracts.
On the other hand, the issue is to consider the orderliness of practices and
methodic mobilization of multimodal resources. Here too, Garfinkel’s inspi-
ration is important: “The technical, distinctive jobs of ethnomethodology, the
craft of ethnomethodology, consists of in vivo tasks of discovering phenomena
of order* as instructable achievements in and as of their coherent details”
(Garfinkel 2002:170).1 This relates to the production of the accountability of ac-
tion: “Phenomena of order are identical with procedures for endogeneous pro-
duction and accountability” (Garfinkel 2002:72). This means that recognizably
shared methods/methodic practices create the patterned orderliness of social
life; this order is interactively achieved in an occasioned, situated way by and for
the participants; consequently, this order is accountable, intelligible, mutually
recognizable for and b y them.
to talk alone (Goodwin 1981, 2000; Heath 1986; Streeck, Goodwin, and LeBaron
2011). Participants produce and interpret social action by recruiting a range of
resources for building its intelligibility. Even if language is a key resource for
some types of activities, it is not a priori the most fundamental one (there is no
principled priority of language over other resources, and their eventual prioriti-
zation depends on the type of situated activity). Rather, action is methodically
organized through multimodal resources (i.e., language, gesture, gaze, head
orientations, body postures, movements, etc.) that are locally assembled in a sit-
uated and occasioned way (Mondada 2014c).
The issues of multimodality in conversation analysis have raised several
questions. They have produced different forms of skepticism, on the one hand
against the possibility of any systematic form of multimodal analysis, on the
other hand against the possibility of using CA notions for multimodal anal-
ysis, considering them as bound and restricted to talk-in-interaction. Moreover,
the analysis of multimodality has reproduced in new ways the old tension be-
tween in-depth analyses of single instances and analysis of collections of cases
(Schegloff 1988).
Multimodal analyses have also been conducted in rather different ways: mul-
timodal resources have been considered in more selective ways—e.g., by iso-
lating a particular resource or fragment of the body and showing its systematic
contribution to (talk-in-)interaction—see, for example, Schegloff (1984) on
gestures produced by speakers; Goodwin (1981) on gaze prompting restarts at
the beginning of the turn; Mondada (2007) on pointing as displaying imminent
speaker’s self-selection; Stivers (2008) on nods as expressing affiliation in sto-
rytelling; Peräkyla and Ruusuvuori (2006) on facial expressions as manifesting
alignment and affiliation in assessment sequences; Rossano (2012) on gaze at se-
quence boundaries. Other multimodal analyses are more holistic—e.g., by con-
sidering the embodied character of language and by considering the entire body
in action as well as bodies in interaction (see, for example, Broth and Mondada
2013 on mobile body movements; Goodwin 2000 on gaze, body positions,
space, and material objects; Heath 1989 considering together gaze, body pos-
ture, and body manipulations). In this latter perspective, talk and embodied
details feature in the organization of social interaction as constituting complex
multimodal Gestalts (Mondada 2014c; Mondada 2015), which are both specif-
ically adjusted to the context and systematically organized. In this context, my
aim in the present chapter is to discuss the very fact that when the entire body
is taken into consideration in its complexity, multimodal resources appear as
being strongly related to the specificity, situatedness, and uniqueness of a par-
ticular action in a particular ecology of action, raising the question of their or-
derliness, systematicity, and reproducibility.
METHODIC PRODUCTION OF ACCOUNTABLE ACTION 293
From the perspective of a praxeological analysis taking into account the mul-
timodal resources mobilized by members for the production and recognition of
social action, we are invited to study how participants assemble sets of resources
as they are mobilized to achieve the accountability of their actions. These resources
are constantly selected, made relevant, made meaningful, and redefined as a
feature of the methodic accomplishments of the participants. They are index-
ical, situated, occasioned, adjusted to the contingencies and specificities of the
interaction; they are endogenously organized and recognized (as part of the
participants’ work). They combine both linguistic and embodied features, in a
way that orients to the constraints, but also the affordances and potentialities of
the local ecology.
the aim is to find it and provide an account of it empirically and precisely, not
imaginatively or typically or hypothetically or conjecturally or experimen-
tally, and to use actual, situated occurrences of it in naturally occurring social
settings to control its description. (1996b:167)
Unmotivated inquiry is the departure point of the analysis, which then can be
elaborated in different ways:
The trajectory of such analyses may begin with a noticing of the action being
done and be pursued by specifying what about the talk or other conduct—in
294 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
This description comprises: (a) what action is being accomplished, (b) how the
participants orient to it as such, and understand what it is doing, and (c) what, in
the production of talk/action, provides for the recognizability of that action for
the participants (Schegloff 1996a:172–73).
The result is a “discovery” of something that was not imagined, not
presupposed. So,
one cannot simply go through the stream of conduct seeking to identify which
previously known action, phenomenon, practice, and so on, a given “bit” exem-
plifies. [ . . . ] One needs to ask about each new object of examination what it
could be possibly doing, and ask, as well, what could constitute an object of ex-
amination to which this question could be put, that had not been so considered
before. (Schegloff 1996a:211)
Within the history of CA, collections have then been constituted by scholars in
different ways: some start with an action and describe the way it is implemented
in a particular sequential environment and with specific resources; others start
from a resource—typically a linguistic form—and study how it can be exploited
in particular actions and sequences.
Within the perspective of a multimodal analysis, collections raise the issue of
how to preserve the complexity and ecological specificity of the phenomenon
without losing its orderly character. Given the potential infinity of the multi-
modal features involved, the issue is also how to establish which multimodal
resources are made relevant by the co-participants: if the analysis and the col-
lection aims not to be just an etic model emanating from a scientific tradition,
but also an emic device that is oriented to endogenously by the co-participants,
the issue is indeed to identify the “apparatus” that constitutes the methodicity of
their practices.
Accordingly, I discuss the idea of collection by taking into consideration both
the situated specificity and the ordered systematicity of embodied actions. The
aim is also to show that collections are not just a methodological issue, and that
they cannot be reduced to a mere formal exercise based on equivalent classes of
patterns. Rather, the challenges of building collections address the fundamental
methodicity of human action: given that accountable action is methodically pro-
duced by assembling a multitude of details in an ordered way, this gives a clear
METHODIC PRODUCTION OF ACCOUNTABLE ACTION 295
indication about the way in which to build collections of instances, paying atten-
tion both to the methods and to the details disclosed by members’ practices.
The fragments were analyzed on the basis of the video recording and presented
through their multimodal transcription. I have used the aligning software ELAN
for this, which allows the transcriber to annotate temporal segments of action at
different levels (or tiers).2
Each analyzed fragment is presented first on the basis of a textual transcript
representing verbal turns through talk, then on the basis of an ELAN transcript
representing the multimodal organization of the action. There is no need today to
remind readers that a transcript dealing only with talk is not sufficient to account
for situated co-present action; nonetheless, the characteristics of the turn might,
given the complexity of the transcripts that follow, be useful to be apprehended
first. The ELAN transcripts are a way to represent the multiple unfolding tem-
poralities of talk, gaze, gesture, and body movements in relation to a general
timeline. They are also a tool allowing the annotation of multiple streams of con-
duct within the same temporal environment—thanks to the possibility of freely
multiplying lines of annotations. Although transcription is a practice and a tool
that contributes in important ways to the establishment of regularities of talk and
embodied action, this chapter will not discuss the features of transcriptions per
se, but rather focus on features of the actions and interactions.
The analysis deals with two fragments from this visit. The detailed analysis of
the first is followed by the study of a second, which presents some similarities
with the former and allows us to sketch the methodical production of a specific
type of noticing, paying attention to both its systematicity and its indexicality.
In the first piece of data, as the group is walking in silence, Yan initiates a new
action: he produces a noticing concerning a detail of the architecture: a large
glass roof above them.
We first look at the verbal transcript, before engaging in a detailed analysis of the
fragment.
1 (22.4)
2 YAN: c’est vraiment c’que: j—moi j’adore, (.) c’est
METHODIC PRODUCTION OF ACCOUNTABLE ACTION 297
responded to with a minimally audible token by Sophie (line 9). At this point,
Yan closes the noticing: he organizes the end of his action by recycling (Schegloff
2011) the material he used at the beginning, the initial “(que) j’adore.”
This recycling closes the Gestalt that was opened by the pseudo-cleft: Yan’s
noticing can be described as mobilizing grammatical and syntactical features
that are both prospectively projecting the specification of the object noticed and
retrospectively referring to it.
We might wonder how and why the participant formats his turn in this way
and why he chooses these grammatical resources rather than other possible
forms, and how they are intertwined with other resources that format his action.
The responses by Jean and Sophie might constitute a warrant for Yan to both
expand his turn, offering new occasions to respond to it, and close it, orienting
to their minimal alignment. But at this point the verbal transcript is clearly not
enough to understand how the noticing is interactionally built. We turn to the
video and its multimodal transcription in order to provide an account of noticing
as a situated and embodied action.
If we look at the moments preceding the beginning of Yan’s turn, while the group
walks in silence, we can observe the emergent and dynamic ecology in which his
noticing takes place.
Figure 11.1 is the ELAN transcript of the 22.4 second silence preceding Yan’s
noticing (see Extract 1.0 on p. 296).
Figure 11.1a
Figure 11.1b
The group is walking down from the first to the ground floor, along a ramp
that has the form of a hairpin bend (Figure 11.1a).
The screen shot is taken 3.2 seconds before Yan begins to talk. We notice that
the “group” is walking in a dispersed way: Jean and Sophie walk together, and ex-
change smiles; Elise follows a bit behind; Yan is not yet visible on the camera view,
he is walking behind them, still above on the ramp and before the hairpin bend.
So, various participation frameworks characterize this moment of the visit, in
which the group is fragmented in smaller vehicular units, all progressing in the
walk forward but not within a unit that could be called a “with” (Goffman 1971).
At this point, Yan is looking at the glass roof above his head (Figure 11.1b). He
has stopped walking a bit before (2.6 seconds before) and the camera glass shows
that he is visually orienting toward the ceiling.
One second later, the participants continue to move forward and turn at the
hairpin bend (Figure 11.2).
Jean passes the hairpin bend: at this point, he is able to spot Yan’s position,
delayed in his walking, separated from the group, stopping and looking up. Jean
stops and looks up toward the ceiling, too (Figure 11.3). Thus, Yan’s noticing
is seen by Jean. The particular ecology of the pathway makes spotting and fol-
lowing the other’s gaze possible, without any other form of interaction between
300 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Figure 11.2
Figure 11.3
the two participants. Meanwhile, Sophie and Elise continue to walk forward
(Figures 11.2, 11.3).
A Recipient-Designed Turn-Beginning
At this point, as shown in the next extract (and the ELAN transcript,
Figure 11.4), still without saying anything, Yan turns his head toward the
group, below on the ramp (Figure 11.5.a/b).
Extract 1.2—line 2
2 YAN: c’est vraiment c’que: j—moi j’adore, (.) c’est
it’s really what I—me I adore, (.) it’s
Gazing down, Yan can see that all the participants but Jean are walking
along the ramp, that Jean is looking at him, but that this is not the case for
Elise and probably not for Sophie (Figures 11.5a and 11.5b). The participants
are moving forward in disparate order and they are not gazing in the same
direction.
The practical problem encountered by Yan is how to initiate a noticing
within a context characterized by a dispersed interactional space, by different
METHODIC PRODUCTION OF ACCOUNTABLE ACTION 301
foci of attention and a mobile formation dynamically moving ahead. The very
fact that Yan, after having spotted the transparent roof, shifts his gaze to the co-
participants before beginning to speak, displays that he organizes his turn-be-
ginning and initiation of a new action and sequence by orienting first toward his
recipients. In this ecology, Yan’s practical task is to reconfigure the interactional
space and consequently rearrange the co-participants’ bodies (Mondada 2009),
in a way that is adequate for producing a noticing to be shared with them. He
achieves it by choosing a particular turn-beginning, a strongly projective gram-
matical construction.
302 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Figure 11.6
The beginning of Yan’s turn is formatted in such a way as to mobilize the atten-
tion of his recipients. Yan mobilizes a series of linguistic resources as an attention
getting device: (a) by using a bipartite (pseudo-cleft) construction projecting
more to come (and even by combining it with a first cleft construction “c’est
vraiment” /“it’s really” also projecting more to come); (b) by referring to “it,”
projecting “it,” but without yet specifying “it”; (c) by assessing it with a strong
subjective expression, (“j—moi j’adore”), made even made stronger by the self-
repair (“j-“self-repaired into ‘moi j’ ”), Yan exploits lexis and syntax in such a way
that he mobilizes the attention of his recipients (Goodwin 1981). As a matter of
fact, Jean is already looking at him, Sophie turns her head toward him as soon as
he initiates his turn, Elise does so later on (the exact moment is not clearly visible
on the video view) (Figure 11.6). So, the initial construction is designed in such a
way to accommodate various responses that are produced at different moments,
and even the later ones.
During this turn-beginning, Yan maintains his gaze on the co-participants,
monitoring them: he can see them progressively looking at him. As a conse-
quence, when all look at him, he gazes away from the group and turns up to the
noticed object again. Moreover, he begins to point at it. Both his gaze toward the
object and the pointing gesture work as instructions to look in a certain direc-
tion (Hindmarsh and Heath 2000). They are produced as soon as the collective
gaze has moved to him, thus achieving the reconfiguration of the interactional
space as a preliminary to the indexical reference (Mondada 2014a). The next in-
teractional task for Yan consists in guiding their gaze from him as a speaker and
METHODIC PRODUCTION OF ACCOUNTABLE ACTION 303
pointing them toward the object he is pointing at, as observable in the next ex-
tract (and ELAN transcript, Figure 11.7).
Extract 1.3—line 3
3 YAN: (0.6) ces plans là où on est: dans une cour:be,
(0.6) these plans there where we are in a curve,
Fig. 11.8
After the first part of the initial cleft and pseudo-cleft construction, Yan pauses
(0.6), before engaging in the specification of the initial and projected prospective
indexical “it.” Just before he utters this second part, he looks down at the group
again: in this way, he monitors the gaze of the co-participants and is able to see
that they have progressively looked up in the instructed direction. While Sophie
and Elise are the first to look up the former during the pause, the latter at the
exact moment at which the second part of the description begins, Jean looks up
only later on, while the description of the object is already unfolding.
This late gaze might be understood in relation to the fact that Jean had already
seen Yan’s looking up and had already looked up (see Figure 11.1, 20.7–21.7
seconds, on p. 298); moreover, as the guide of the visit and expert in the visited
building, he displays in this way that he knows what Yan is talking about, thus
gazing at the pointing speaker rather than at the pointed-at object.
Again, the progressivity of Yan’s action is adjusted to the embodied responses
of the co-participants: until the beginning of the description’s second part, he
was walking down toward them; after the pause, he stops, and while he describes
the roof, he even walks back up the upper part of the ramp. If walking down
304 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Figure 11.8
adjusts to the move forward of the co-participants, walking up again and back-
ward is a way of stopping that progressivity and offering an alternative dynamic
ecology for the ongoing action.
At this point, the description of the noticed and pointed-at object is defin-
itively launched. First, the mention of the object with a double deictic expres-
sion (“ces plans là”/“these plans there”) constitutes an extra invitation to look at
it. Second, its expansion in the form of a locative relative clause (“où”/“where”)
gives the opportunity for Jean’s late gaze up to join the other participants in their
posture of shared attention. Finally, all of the participants look up toward the
pointed-at referent (Figure 11.8).
Furthermore, the locative clause is further expanded in a list of features char-
acterizing the “plans,” accompanied by some iconic gesticulations. At this point,
another issue emerges for Yan: until now, the responses of the co-participants
have been implemented in the embodied form of an instructed looking by them
aligning with his instructions and looking at the referent pointed at. But they
have not yet produced any verbal response. By expanding his description, Yan
creates further opportunities for a substantial response, which would not only
bodily align with his action but also verbally affiliate with it (see the ELAN tran-
script, Figure 11.9).
with eh
5 (0.3)
6 JEA: ouais (ouais)
yeah (yeah)
7 YAN: les deux aut’ courbes qui repartent,
the two other curves that go away,
8 celle-ci qui vient, les fenêtres,
this one that comes in, the windows,
9 SOP? hm
Responses to Yan’s description remain minimal. Jean responds after the pause
following the first part of the locative relative: at this point, Yan has projected a
continuation (“avec eh”/“with eh”) which is not immediately followed (see the
pause of 0.6). By responding with “ouais (ouais)”/“yeah (yeah),” Jean displays
that for him the description is complete, for all practical purposes, within an ad-
ditional manifestation of him as a knowing recipient.
Nonetheless, Yan continues, ignoring this response and implicitly orienting
to the other, non-knowing, recipients (Goodwin 1979). They have responded
in an embodied way first by looking up, but then looked back at him, without
any verbal response. Quite the opposite, at the beginning of the expansion fol-
lowing the 0.6-second pause, and initiating a list of features, Jean looks in front
of him and walks down; Elise looks in front of her, still standing; and Sophie
walks backward a bit later on. The two latter participants orient to a double
possible progression of the activity: by standing (Elise) and by continuing to
look at Yan (Sophie), they orient toward Yan; by looking forward (Elise) and
306 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
by beginning to walk (Sophie), they orient toward the progressivity of the visit.
The backward walk is an instance of body torque (Schegloff 1998) in which the
co-participant both looks at Yan and restores the progressivity of the visit.
These movements are seen by Yan when he gazes down toward the group, on
the last item of his list: at this point, all of the participants are at least partially
oriented toward moving forward. Moreover, the only response he gets is a min-
imal “mh” from Sophie. Yan aligns with the projection of the completion of the
sequence by his recipients and organizes a proper completion of his turn (see the
ELAN transcript Figure 11.10).
Yan organizes the end of his noticing by producing the final construction
(“c’est des details que j’adore”/“it’s details that I love”; literally in French, “I
adore”) which recycles the elements of the initial one (“ce que j’—moi j’adore”/
“what I—me I love”). But while the initial pseudo-cleft was prospectively organ-
ized, projecting more to come, the final cleft construction is retrospectively or-
ganized, synthesizing the previous description within the formulation “c’est des
details”/“it’s details.” In this way, Yan organizes a global pivot format (what I love
METHODIC PRODUCTION OF ACCOUNTABLE ACTION 307
is N =N it’s details that I love) that closes his turn. In the absence of any substan-
tial response, he produces a formal closing of the emergent Gestalt. Moreover, he
begins again to walk forward and to look forward, bodily orienting to the pro-
gressivity of the activity.
The co-participants orient to him: Jean pivots and looks at him, Sophie stops
her walk and also looks at him. Both of them stop and bodily orient to him,
turning their back toward the direction of the progression of the visit. In this way,
they wait for Yan. Jean also produces some final responses (“ouais”/“yeah” and
“>oui oui< c’est ça.”/“>yes yes< that’s it.”), which confirms what Yan has just said,
rather than acknowledging his talk as new.
The solution to the practical problem encountered by Yan consists in
accountably organizing his action. The recipient-designed character of that
action is visible in the fact that prior to delivering his utterance, Yan checks
and monitors the co-participants’ positions and movements. Given the una-
vailability of the co-participants at turn-initial position, Yan uses a delaying
and projecting construction: he situatedly exploits the projective features of
a pseudo-cleft (opens a frame for more to come; cf. Günthner and Hopper
2010; Hopper 2004). The first part is delayed by the coordination of bodies and
glances; the second part emerges contingently by adjusting to the recipient’s
responsiveness and attention. His instruction to look at the architectural detail
is designed as finely coordinated with the movements and emergent common
focus of attention. The turn is brought to completion when the co-participants
look away and continue to walk. The syntactic and bodily temporal features
are accountably coordinated and assembled by Yan and responded to by the
co-participants.
This piece of data shows how an action, a noticing by a participant, is for-
matted by carefully monitoring the co-participants and their fine-grained set of
responses, to which the unfolding action is reflexively adjusted. Although Yan’s
turn is not responded to in a substantial verbal way, and indeed the speaker
orients to that, it is treated and responded to in an embodied way. Yan’s action
emerges as an instruction to look and the responses align with it as instructed
looking, progressively constituting the conditions for joint attention toward the
pointed-at referent.
The analysis describes how a series of practical problems is treated in me-
thodic ways by the speaker mobilizing and selecting multimodal resources,
arranged in order to achieve practical tasks such as getting the attention of the
co-participants, constituting a shared object of vision, suspending the progres-
sivity of a competing activity, expanding the current activity, and occasioning
new opportunities to respond, organizing the closing of the activity in the ab-
sence of substantial responses, etc.
308 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Intermediary Discussion
The preceding analysis has shown how a participant mobilizes and orients to
various multimodal details, such as grammatical constructions, lexical choices,
gaze, different types of gesture, body postures, mobility, in order to produce a
noticing; and how co-participants respond with their gaze, their body postures,
their movements.
The analysis of an action lasting about 15 seconds has shown the complexity of
the multimodal Gestalts that are progressively and reflexively achieved, as well as
the intricate relationships between the ecology of the action, the situated contin-
gencies, the reflexivity of action and the (non)responses it gets, etc. This analysis
accounts for the indexicality of social action, as well as for the fundamental so-
cial and interactional reflexive organization of action, even when it is apparently
done by a speaker without much verbal responsiveness from the hearers. This
analysis also shows how action is reflexively built by integrating the continuous
embodied responses of the co-participants, and not only by taking into account
the “next turn” they could produce.
The issue discussed in this chapter concerns the very possibility of at the
same time, respecting the indexicality, specificity, and complexity of human
action and exploring its methodic and systematic character. In order to do so,
more instances are needed. The issue is how to build a (small) collection even
for phenomena that are quite specific, complex, and situated. In this condi-
tion, encountering a second instance is not straightforward. The more situ-
ated details and multimodal practices are considered, the more difficult it is
to find a similar case. This nourishes the skepticism of some scholars about
fine-grained multimodal analyses regarding making collections difficult if not
impossible.
So, how does one go from a first to a second instance? Searching for other
exemplars of noticings (i.e., for the same type of action) is not enough, since
they can be produced in very different contexts and with very different mul-
timodal resources and formats. In a similar way, the issue is not to search
for other cases of pseudo-cleft constructions in order to build a collection of
syntactic forms. This could be interesting for the grammatical study of the
construction in social interaction, but not necessarily for the type of action
documented in the first example. Rather, this action concerns instructions
to look at something in the co-present environment, organized as emer-
gent embodied Gestalts sensitive to the complex spatial arrangement of the
participants, and their partial (un)availability.
METHODIC PRODUCTION OF ACCOUNTABLE ACTION 309
A Second Instance
A second instance was found in the same data set, which will be analyzed both in
detail and in comparison with the previous example.
The participants have entered a classroom within the same building. Jean, Sophie,
and Elise stay near the door, while Yan walks across the room and approaches a
window. He contemplates the building’s architecture as it is visible from that view-
point. After a silent glance through the window, he produces a noticing, prefaced
by the same construction as in the first case.
310 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
As in the previous case, I reproduce first the verbal transcript of the entire
extract.
Yan initiates a new sequence with a turn beginning, using a similar con-
struction as in the first instance, a pseudo-cleft using also the same lexical
verbal form, “moi c’que j’adore, c’est que:”/“me what I adore, it’s that.” This
projects the description of what he sees from the window. At line 3, his turn
could be syntactically complete, but the prosody projects more to come, and
none of the participants responds. After a longish pause (line 4), he continues
with an “et”/“and”–prefaced cleft sentence, referring to the architect of the
building and finishing in an incomplete way with “parce que:”/“because.”
What it projects is not implemented in the next unit, after a pause (line 8).
Rather, he adds a comment referring to his own professional category, “we
the architects” (line 10), which is overlapped by a first response, from Elise,
aligning with his previous description and producing a change-of-state token
(Heritage 1984a) (line 9) and an aligning response from Jean (line 11). The
unit is left unfinished (line 12).
METHODIC PRODUCTION OF ACCOUNTABLE ACTION 311
After a short pause, Jean provides a more substantial response, beginning with
a conjunction (“de”/“to,” line 14) which operates as a syntactical link with the
previous turn and expands it collaboratively, recycling some preceding resources
that Yan used (cf. line 3).
Contrary to what happened in the first instance, in the second one Yan’s de-
scription is substantially responded to by the co-participants and the episode
continues for a while.
But the initial problem Yan faces is similar to the former one: a dis-
persed arrangement of the bodies of the co-p articipants, not propitious
for a noticing or for an action requiring joint attention. Yan treats this
problem with similar practices to those in the first instance, namely spe-
cific syntactic resources initiating the turn, whose projective potential
and emergent unfolding adjusts to the progressive reorientation of their
bodies and gaze.
We join the action as the group has entered the classroom. Jean, Elise, and Sophie
stand near the entrance, inspecting it without engaging more fully with the
room. Displaying that the space can be globally apprehended from the entrance,
the guide, Jean, remains close to the door. Quite the opposite, Yan walks through
the room and approaches the window opposite the door (Figure 11.11). In this
way, he displays that there are alternative viewpoints from which the architecture
can be appreciated.
Having reached the window, Yan engages in the silent contemplation of
the view.
Figure 11.11
312 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
The beginning of the ELAN transcript (Figure 11.12) shows different positions
of the co-participants. After a few seconds, Yan, who was looking through the
window, turns toward the co-participants and sees them standing near the en-
trance of the room
Figure 11.13
Figure 11.14
METHODIC PRODUCTION OF ACCOUNTABLE ACTION 313
Just before initiating his noticing, Yan turns from the window (Figure 11.13)
toward the co-participants; he sees that they are far away and that the architec-
tural scene he is looking at is not accessible to them (Figure 11.14).
So, prior to launching his turn, Yan checks the position of his imminent
recipients. His choice of a pseudo-cleft construction at turn-beginning selects
a strongly projective linguistic resource in a context in which the interactional
space is fragmented, projecting more to come and providing an opportu-
nity to reconfigure that interactional space. The co-participants respond in an
embodied way: at the end of the first part of the pseudo-cleft, they are beginning
to move (see ELAN transcript in Figure 11.15):
problem Yan faces concerns the coordination between his emergent description
and the trajectory of the walk of his recipients. At a first possible syntactical com-
pletion, before the long pause (0.9), the participants are still in the middle of the
room (Figure 11.16).
Figure 11.16
Yan’s turn adjusts to this progressive movement by adding further details, refer-
ring to the “game” liked by the architect of the building. This leaves extra time for
the participants to walk through the room (see ELAN transcript in Figure 11.17):
At the end of the expansion referring to the author of the building, Yan,
who is still gazing at the group, sees that they have almost reached the
window. At this point, his turn is left unfinished, with “pa’c’que”/“’cause” and
a pause follows (0.8), while he moves his gaze from the participants to the
window again.
He begins a new unit (see ELAN transcript, Figures 11.17, 11.18):
METHODIC PRODUCTION OF ACCOUNTABLE ACTION 315
During the pause (0.8), Jean and Sophie have reached the window. Elise
continues to come closer. Sophie is the first to respond to Yan: she stands
316 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
These two instances are similar in their beginning and different in their outcome.
In both cases, a participant initiates a new action, a noticing, and a new sequence,
in a context in which the co-participants are dispersed and at a distance within
the surrounding environment, within a fragmented interactional space, and in
which he is not expected to say anything. This constitutes an ecology that is not
very favorable for a joint action.
METHODIC PRODUCTION OF ACCOUNTABLE ACTION 317
Before initiating his noticing, the speaker redirects his gaze from the details
he was looking at to the co-participants: in this way, he checks their availability,
orienting to it as a possible condition for his action. Indeed, his turn begins with
a complex syntactical construction, which being articulated in one first part,
projecting a second one, organizes the unfolding of the action within time, lit-
erally giving time to the participants to align and to respond. So, the choice of
linguistic resources for formatting the turn is directly related to the inspection
of the interactional space; the progression of the turn is embedded in the gaze
alternating between the described referent and the participants, being reflex-
ively adjusted with the monitoring of the participants’ movements. The noticing
emerges as an action that is not merely communicating a personal feeling of the
speaker, but as an instruction to look at the environment constituting an instance
of instructed vision and even professional vision.
The co-participants respond in various ways: by stopping their trajectories,
reorienting their bodies, looking in an instructed way, and producing verbal
tokens. In this respect, the two instances differ. In the first, the co-participants
can see at a glance what Yan is referring to, and they momentarily suspend the
progression of their walk (as well as the visit), though they immediately resume
it. The noticing is responded to as an insertion in the progressivity of the visit; it
constitutes a delay by a delayed participant, an obstacle to the visit’s progressivity.
In the second instance, the referent that is noticed cannot be seen from where the
co-participants are. The progression of the visit is suspended and delayed, and
they engage in a new activity, aligning with what is proposed by Yan, an invita-
tion to bodily engage in a different view of the room, walking through it instead
of staying at its entrance. The noticing is responded to as an invitation to share
the professional vision of the architect and to redirect the bodies to do so. This
also ends in a general discussion, prolonging the episode even more.
The two instances open up for an analysis of the practices by which people
look at things together, respond to noticings by sharing the perspective of the
person initiating the sequence, and engage together in instructed vision. Joint
attention—following the gaze of the other, seeing together—is an interactional
accomplishment, which emerges in time, through the reflexive organization of
turns/actions and the responses they get, in a way that is organizationally sensi-
tive to the local changing ecology.
Together, these two cases constitute an incipient collection of turn formats
used for introducing a new object, instructing the co-participants how to look
at it, analyzed as emergent Gestalts. They both are sensitive to the local con-
tingencies of action in context (indexicality) and they present systematic, me-
thodically assembled, ordered practices for dealing with the practical problems
encountered in situ (orderliness). The incipient collection shows the challenges
raised by the analysis of multimodality: multimodal details are possibly infinite,
318 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
although only a limited range of them are considered as relevant and oriented
to by the participants; they constitute complex multimodal Gestalts clustering
various embodied and linguistic features unfolding within intertwined (related
but not isochronic) temporalities; these Gestalts are locally assembled by the
participants in a way that is contingent on the local material environment and
that shows the continuity between the specific formats of embodied conduct and
their ecology.
All these characteristics build highly specific contextures of multimodal re-
sources that seem to escape any generalizability across instances. However, the
analysis of these two instances has also shown that specificity and systematicity of
conducts are not mutually exclusive dimensions to consider, but different faces of the
same coin. Multimodal Gestalts are established as responses to practical problems
and as implementations of recognizable actions: they are recipient-designed and
thus adjusted to the local dynamic embodied-participation framework; they are
responded to and are formatted in a way that reflexively considers others’ responses,
embedding them in the emergent action formation; various multimodal elements
of conduct have a sequential implicativeness that can be responded to at different
moments, by diverse multimodal practices and by different co-participants, showing
how complex sequential organization can be (characterized by multiple temporali-
ties that run in parallel, articulating both multiple sequentialities and simultaneities;
Mondada 2018). These principles of sequential organization (Garfinkel 2002; Rawls
2005; Schegloff 2007) constitute the foundations of the methodicity of human ac-
tion, as they are oriented to by the co-participants/members and are documented by
the analysts looking over their shoulders.
References
Broth, M., and L. Mondada. 2013. “Walking Away: The Embodied Achievement of
Activity Closings in Mobile Interactions.” Journal of Pragmatics 47:41–58. doi: 10.1016/
j.pragma.2012.11.016.
Button, Graham, and Neil Casey. 1985. “Topic Nomination and Topic Pursuit.” Human
Studies 8(1):3–55. doi: 10/bhqpxv.
Eilan, N., C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, and J. Roessler, eds. 2005. Joint Attention:
Communication and Other Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1967. Studies in Ethnomethodology. Cambridge: Polity.
Garfinkel, Harold. 2002. Ethnomethodology’s Program: Working Out Durkeim’s Aphorism.
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Garfinkel, Harold, and Kenneth Liberman. 2007. “Introduction: The Lebenswelt Origins
of the Sciences.” Human Studies 30(1):3–7. doi: 10/cspm6m.
Garfinkel, Harold, and Harvey Sacks. 1970. “On Formal Structures of Practical Action.”
Pp. 338–366 in Theoretical Sociology: Perspectives and Developments, edited by J. C.
McKinney and E. A. Tiryakian. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
METHODIC PRODUCTION OF ACCOUNTABLE ACTION 319
Introduction
WORK OF A DISCOVERING SCIENCE 323
sample. For more than 40 years, however, no model could account for this aston-
ishing material property. This changed in the 1950s, when a theoretical model
was developed that succeeded in explaining superconductivity in terms of “paired
electrons” which, at temperatures close to absolute zero (–273.15°C), would form,
slip through the crystalline structure of metallic compounds, and create an elec-
tric current circulating without resistance (cf. Blundell 2009:48–65). The model
also predicted a threshold temperature (of ca. –253°C) above which superconduc-
tivity would cease to exist. In 1986, a Swiss physicist and his German colleague,
K. A. Müller and J. G. Bednorz, managed to find a ceramic compound which,
upon repeated inspection, displayed superconducting properties at –243°C (that
is, 10° above the predicted threshold temperature). The discovered anomaly
gained them the Nobel Prize in 1987 and gave new impetus to the field of super-
conductivity (cf. Nowotny and Felt 1997). Ever since, the discovered “high-tem-
perature superconductivity” has remained a mystery (cf. Cho 2006), yet a highly
promising one (notably in view of energy-saving electricity grids).
It is against this background that the members of the laboratory studied in
this chapter would conduct their inquiries on superconducting materials. Lab
members adopted a strategy of diversification, investigating a range of materials
both below and above the classic, yet falsely predicted, threshold temperature.
For example, PbMo6S8 had at first been found to display “single-band” supercon-
ductivity (i.e., at one energy level) below the stated threshold temperature (at –
271.35°C). This initial finding constituted a potential anomaly, as it did not fit the
canonical model from the 1950s (which would have predicted superconductivity
at several energy levels, cf. Dubois et al. 2007). Yet subsequent measurements at
the lab, conducted on related materials under more stringent conditions (e.g.,
high vacuum), had suggested that this anomaly might be a methodological arti-
fact. The presently examined experiment—the local spectroscopy of PbMo6S8—
was then designed to answer the open question, as an experimentum crucis of
sorts. Indeed, the experiment should either confirm the previous anomaly (po-
tentially leading to a theoretical innovation) or produce a new, yet prosaically
empirical discovery (insofar as it would prove consistent with, if not confirm, the
canonical model).2
Accordingly, the experiment to be analyzed in this chapter was to determine
what kind of superconductivity characterized PbMo6S8, “single-” or “multi-
band.” The kind of discovery to be made would hinge upon that determination,
which in turn was to be made in terms of a local spectroscopy, which involves
subjecting a sample to a range of bias voltages, as the tunneling current could be
varied in that sense, and recording the resulting pattern of (super-)conductivity.
More specifically, a “local” spectroscopy designates any such measurement that
is made at a particular position above the sample surface (where the measured
values are derived from the varying tunneling current, It).
324 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
The experiment was made and filmed during its making on November 9, 2008.
The experimental physicist in charge, identified as Pete in this chapter, had man-
ifestly discovered PbMo6S8 to transport electricity without resistance at several
energy levels or “bands”—hence “multi-band superconductivity.” Luckily, I had
managed to be present at the lab that Sunday morning and film the discovery’s
local production, before arranging to engage in its tentative re-enactment at a
later stage. This chapter, accordingly, describes how the empirical discovery was
made, while making explicit the heuristic interest of its tentative re-enactment
to understand the discovery’s initial production. In short, the chapter offers a
practice-based video analysis (Sormani 2016). Finally, the chapter reflects upon
the “discovery status” of the experimental finding in physics, as well as technical
self-instruction in the vein of Garfinkel’s (2002a, 2002b, 2002c) later work as an
integral part of the proposed video analysis and ethnomethodological inquiry
more broadly.
At around 11:30 a.m., Pete lifted his arms in celebration: “YES!” His low-tem-
perature STM, alias Aurora, had just triggered the long-sought and hitherto un-
known spectrum of PbMo6S8: its signature “double gap” spectrum as a multi-band
superconductor (see Appendix). The empirical discovery was manifestly made,
in situ and in vivo, and Pete’s instant celebration suggested that it had physical
significance. So did his initial acknowledgment of our shared moment, on the
one hand, and a later observation in the light of additional spectra commented
upon in the subsequently published paper, on the other: “the moment when we
discovered multi-band superconductivity in PbMo6S8 together was truly special”
(Petrović 2010:165); “such a dramatic spectral variation as a function of local
topography has not previously been observed in any other superconductor”
(Petrović et al. 2011:2). We shall return to this suggestion of disciplinary rele-
vance in the concluding section of the chapter. This core section of the chapter,
in turn, describes the local production of the electronically probed/visually dis-
covered spectrum. The section’s key interest is thus similar to that of the seminal
“pulsar paper” (cf. Garfinkel et al. 1981), as the paraphrase of the latter’s central
question best suggests: Just what did the electronically probed/visually discovered
spectrum consist of as Pete and Phil’s Sunday morning work, on November 9, 2008?
Yet the paraphrase has been twisted, too: it marks my practical involvement in
discovering work. What’s the point of marking this reflexive involvement? What’s
the point of re-examining discovering work in superconductivity research that
way? The basic idea was to exploit my “technical idiocy” for heuristic purposes—
that is, to turn the technical difficulties of my practical involvement and tenta-
tive re-enactment of the initial discovery into “tutorial problems,” problems that
highlight “members’ discipline-specific procedures” (Garfinkel 2002c:145, em-
phasis in original). Their distinctive mastery, in a nutshell, was to appear against
the background of my technical incompetency. The latter, indeed, constitutes “an
opportunity to see what [an] expert [would] ‘assume’ and ‘take for granted’ as
326 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
the most ordinary, pervasive, and characteristic features of [her] work practice”
(Livingston 2008:132). In particular, the tentative re-enactment of Pete’s experi-
ment will allow us to make explicit one key feature and basic requirement of his
local practice: the constitutive contribution of its technical procedures, as they
did and had to contribute to the local production of their intended Gestalt, the
long-sought and hitherto unknown “double gap” spectrum of PbMo6S8.
As we shall see, each of the technical procedures, enacted by Pete and exhibited
via his STM equipment, was achieved as a recursive three-part routine: a “field of
view” (Sherman 2011) would be established first, followed by an action engaged
in that field, and the evaluation of its displayed result, prior to the next procedure,
engaged in similar fashion. This three-part routine was (and had to be) made
visible in its course, via the equipment used by Pete. Yet this manifest three-part
routine begs the question of its constitutive contribution to the unfolding exper-
iment: How was each procedure achieved, not for its own sake or technical cor-
rectness per se, but for the purpose of the local spectroscopy of PbMo6S8? How
would Pete achieve those procedures, task by task, so as to discover its multi-
band superconductivity? To answer these questions, the ensuing video analysis
will be practice-based and proceed in three steps, procedure by procedure. First,
a transcript-assisted analysis will be offered of each experimental procedure.
Second, and by drawing upon a descriptive “Vignette” for each step, I will report
upon my tentative re-enactment of each procedure. Third, the problems encoun-
tered in the re-enactment will be drawn upon to clarify the initial experiment, es-
pecially with respect to the constitutive contribution of each technical procedure
to the local production of its empirical discovery: multi-band superconductivity
in PbMo6S8.3
To set out with STM measurements, tip and sample must be brought into ex-
tremely close—nanometric vicinity—with one another. Only within the minute
interval between the tip, acting as the probe, and a selected sample can its (po-
tentially) superconducting properties be probed, due to the so established “tun-
neling current” from which they are derived. To achieve this feat, Pete would
engage in a two-step procedure: first, engage in a [[manual approach]] in the
course of which he would monitor the progressively approaching tip with the
help of its mirror image, a mirror image that gradually appears on the sample
surface when the task is accomplished and correctly monitored with a magni-
fying lens (Sormani 2014:Chapter 4); second, Pete would control the subsequent
nanometric steps of the tip in approaching the sample with the help of an elec-
tronic feedback loop. Sitting at the computer of his STM facility Aurora, Pete
WORK OF A DISCOVERING SCIENCE 327
would monitor and explain this [[automatic approach]] to me, as can be gleaned
from Excerpt 1.4
(a)
As the excerpt shows, Pete does much more than he can explain in so many
words. He surely launches, monitors, and comments on the [[automatic ap-
proach]] in terms of the three-part routine outlined in the introduction to this
328 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
(b)
Figure 12.1 Continued
section. Let us attempt a first analysis of the observed three-part routine, and
then, in Vignette 1, examine the ethnographic annotations deriving from my
novice questions put to Pete (see my successive action descriptions in double
parentheses in the transcript).
Regarding the [[automatic approach]] as a three-part routine, we may note
that Pete first formulates the return to a previously selected tip-position above
the sample surface (line 002), while turning his gaze to the computer screen
(003), thereby fixing the relevant “field of view” (the “approach” window opened
in the STM onscreen interface). Second, he formulates the action engaged in that
field, the tip approach (010–012, #1). Third, he evaluates and formulates, while
observing (015–018, #2, 023, 026), the result of the approach, as displayed on the
oscilloscope above the computer screen (his “field of view” having been extended
in the course of the engaged procedure). Finally, and despite his manifestly neg-
ative evaluation, he decides to engage in the next experimental procedure: “we
will try to put it anyway” (037). Why?5
What were the local grounds, in other words, for Pete’s experimental noncha-
lance? Why would he envisage a first [local spectroscopy] at all (027–037), given
WORK OF A DISCOVERING SCIENCE 329
Upon Pete’s invitation, I take his seat at the STM facility Aurora. Equipped with
the video camera in my right hand and the detailed transcript of his experiment
in the left, I start reading out and following the transcript as a script, as a set of
written instructions to reproduce the [[automatic approach]], the task now at
hand. At the same time, I film my first attempt at task re-enactment from within
its tricky course. Fortunately, Pete is overseeing my tribulations at his STM fa-
cility! First, I read out loud “we get back to where we were before” and then,
hesitantly, “clicks tip approach button” which, eventually, I do—to have the [[au-
tomatic approach]] initiated. Then, I direct my gaze and searching camera to the
oscilloscope. What’s there to be seen, if not filmed? Nothing yet, it seems. Indeed,
Pete invites me to check the tip position as indicated elsewhere, not on the os-
cilloscope, but on the rack to the right of it. As I do so, he asks me: “Did you see
the jump?” Apparently, the oscilloscope has just indicated the relevant phenom-
enon! Well, I missed it. So we redo the approach, and Pete shows me what to look
out for and film: a “downward jump” on the oscilloscope, indicating tunneling
current detection.
What Pete showed me that I missed—the “downward jump” on the oscil-
loscope—had afforded him with the local grounds—a detected tunneling
current—to proceed with his spectroscopy. Conversely, my tentative re-enact-
ment and manifest failure at spotting the relevant phenomenon afford us with
a “look again” procedure (Watson 1998), a resource to re-examine Pete’s ini-
tial [[automatic approach]] and its first transcription (see Excerpt 1). Consider
330 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
the series of films stills in Figure 12.2 of Pete’s approach procedure, as I could
assemble the series by drawing upon my task re-enactment as an instructive
resource.
The film stills in Figure 12.2 of the [[automatic approach]] document its
monitored achievement by Pete (1a–1f), including his negative assessment of
its apparent result (as facially expressed in 1f). First, it may be noted that Pete,
WORK OF A DISCOVERING SCIENCE 331
after having clicked “approach” (see Excerpt 1, line 006), not only leans back-
ward (ibid., 008), but also, as the first film still suggests (1a), monitors the os-
cilloscope and, more specifically, the horizontal middle line that it displays (his
gaze, indeed, being fixed at that line). Second, his pointing gesture, as the sub-
sequent film stills suggest (1b, 1c, 1d), is not only directed at the oscilloscope
(Excerpt 1, 011–013, #1) but, more specifically, it also anticipates the change that
the oscilloscope is expected to indicate (the “downward jump” of the middle
line, due to the detected tunneling current). Third, that change, the anticipated
phenomenon, is produced on the oscilloscope, as the displayed line “jumps”
one unit below its initial position (1e). Pete’s negative assessment (as facially, 1f,
and onomatopoetically expressed, “pfffh::.”, Excerpt 1, 015–019, #2) may thus be
re-examined, too. That assessment, it should be emphasized, is proffered after
the relevant phenomenon has been produced and monitored (the “downward
jump,” 1e, which I had overlooked). The negative assessment, then, bears on
the sudden disappearance of the phenomenon, the displayed and detected tun-
neling signal, all covered up by an important sum of deviating signals, in one
word: noise (see 1f and #2, which are identical). Technically put, the negative
assessment expresses a disappointing “signal-to-noise ratio” (1e–1f), rather
than a “very noisy signal” (Excerpt 1, 014, #2). However, the very detection of a
tunneling current invites Pete to launch his experiment, despite its noisy back-
ground. In that, his [[automatic approach]] proves experimentally adequate,
making possible a first [local spectroscopy], even if the particular circumstances
of the approach’s technical execution remain suboptimal. In sum, readers should
now know why Pete envisaged his first experiment. Contrary to my own effort,
he controlled the tip position with the help of the STM regulation electronics
rack (see Excerpt 1, line 001, [A]), prior to launching the tip approach (Excerpt 1,
line 006) and monitoring it via the oscilloscope (Excerpt 1, lines 008–023, [C]).
This, notably, allowed him to avoid missing the single relevant phenomenon,
the anticipated “downward jump,” as displayed on the oscilloscope and indi-
cating tunneling current detection.
Recall that the spectroscopy examined here involves subjecting the sample to a
range of bias voltages at a particular position above the sample surface, and re-
cording the resulting pattern of superconductivity. Before continuing to review
Pete’s work in the light of further re-enactments, a close look at Pete’s first at-
tempt at [local spectroscopy] of PbMo6S8 is in order:
332 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
(a)
(b)
Figure 12.3 Continued
to obtain a satisfactory spectrum: Pete aborts the subsequent one, indeed (lines
078–079). Why is that?7
The local rationale for Pete’s technical stringency to abort the subsequent
spectrum may not be apparent, since he has just switched off the “topo filter.”
In fact, this question came into my mind only from the “standpoint of the
performer”(Sudnow 1978:xiii), as I noticed the question’s relevance when re-
enacting the procedure at hand. Consider the following vignette.
After having re-established the tunneling current, I try to redo Pete’s first at-
tempt at [local spectroscopy], while reading out the required actions: “opens
the window ‘spectro’ [ . . . ] moves to the entry ‘area coordinates’ [ . . . ].” It
takes ages! But as Pete assists and the transcript instructs me: “we will try to
put it anyway.” So I enter the area coordinates and, via a drag-and-drop move,
reposition the tip in the upper left corner of the “spectro” window. “Launches
a 1st spectroscopy—voilà, that’s it!” So I press the “Go” button. After two
seconds, a zigzag line moves in from left to right, not the intended spectrum.
Pete: “you see, it’s just noise.” Me: “so I need to switch off the filter.” Yet, as my
finger and camera search for it, I miss another “downward jump,” this time
in the “spectro” window, namely that of spectrum detection. A second later,
the STM indeed reproduces a new, unfiltered, well-shaped spectrum, so I ask
Pete why he would abort it. His blunt answer: “the mean of spectra is taken, so
I had to avoid taking the mean of junk [i.e., noise] and the good ones [i.e., the
projected series of superconductivity spectra].” Indeed, the upper right-hand
panel displays the “monstrous means” of the two successive measurements, as
Pete further explains.
My re-enacted procedure again affords us with a useful resource—a “look
again” procedure—to re-examine Pete’s first attempt at [local spectroscopy] and
its initial transcription (see Excerpt 2). That attempt, indeed, can now be expli-
cated for just how it was achieved, not simply by means of a correct technical
procedure (i.e., a first, single spectroscopy, correctly launched), but in view of its
experimentally adequate, disciplinarily oriented purpose (i.e., as a first in a se-
ries, a first reproducible spectroscopy). Pete’s technical stringency, to wit, finds its
procedural explication in this disciplinary orientation of his instrumental prac-
tice (whose manifest purpose escaped my initial transcription). Again, the serial
arrangement of film stills appears useful to expose that orientation and to revisit
the initial transcript (Excerpt 2).
WORK OF A DISCOVERING SCIENCE 335
Figure 12.4 The first [local spectroscopy] and its monitoring procedure
(Pete’s 1st attempt re-examined)
Pete, for a start, does not simply press the “Go” button (see Excerpt 2, 049), look
at the oscilloscope (051) and notice the disappearing “noise” (053, #5); rather,
he monitors, once again, the oscilloscope for the attempted entry into tunneling
regime, as eventually displayed (see the “downward jump” on the oscilloscope,
Figure 12.4, 2a). As the tunneling current has been re-established, recognizably
so, Pete lowers his gaze from the oscilloscope to the computer interface and the
336 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
upper central “spectro” window in particular (2b). The zigzag trace appearing in
the “spectro” window (2c), however, does not match the intended one (the m-
shaped superconductivity curve; see Appendix), a mismatch oriented to by Pete.
Indeed, Pete does not simply switch off the “topo filter” (062–063), but he aligns
that operation with its experimental purpose: the [local spectroscopy], probing
superconductivity. This alignment can be seen in the orientation of his gaze,
directed at the “spectro” window prior to the switch off (2d). The relevant change
in the “spectro” window, the “downward jump” of the spectroscopic trace, can
thus be monitored on time (see 12.4, 2e, which is identical to #6 in Excerpt 2).
The immediate abortion of the next spectrum, prior to its displayed completion
(2f and Excerpt 2, 078–079), affords us with a more determinate expression of the
attempted achievement: the experimental demonstration not simply of a first de-
tectable spectrum, but of the first reproducible one. The disciplinary orientation
of discovering work, by consequence, appears to encapsulate, from the outset, re-
producibility as an additional one of its internal requirements, rather than as the
external and isolated problem post hoc (e.g., in the form of an “experimenter’s re-
gress,” Collins 1985). The offered practice-based re-examination makes explicit
how the first [local spectroscopy], although technically correct, proved experi-
mentally inadequate and, by consequence, had to be aborted, where that abortion,
in turn, displayed Pete’s disciplinary orientation, aiming at “first time through
reproducibility” in particular (to adapt Garfinkel et al.’s 1981 expression). Task
re-enactment, in sum, afforded us with that second tutorial problem, explicating
Pete’s “technical stringency” in terms of its experimental relevance in situ.
(a)
(b)
Figure 12.5 Continued
“Now, shiu::: we will reposition the tip.” As I formulate this next action, I drag the
“tip” from the upper left corner in the “spectro” window to drop it in the lower
right one. After checking tunneling current detection, I relaunch the spectros-
copy at the new position by pressing “Go.” The result of that relaunch is shown in
the upper central “spectro” window. First, a zigzag line is traced once again, from
left to right. Second, the trace appearing in the “spectro” window a moment later
exhibits the first key property of a superconductivity spectrum, namely: a pos-
sible “gap,” displayed as a single gap, moving in from the left. A tenth of a second
later, the picture is completed. Indeed, the second key property of the intended
spectrum is displayed, namely: symmetry. That symmetry, although not perfect,
can be recognized as the spectrum comes to a halt, with its gap placed in the
middle of the “spectro” window. I immediately press the “print screen” button
to get the spectrum on the record. Yet my attempt fails to replicate Pete’s initial
experimental result. As Pete points out, “well, here you won’t get the double gap,
since we’re at 9 Tesla [i.e., not in the ground state].” Another single gap, rather
than a double gap, spectrum is reproduced, indeed.
Again, the demonstrative account of task re-enactment affords us with a “look
again” procedure to re-examine Pete’s achievement of the heuristic experiment,
his second trial at [local spectroscopy] leading to the empirical discovery of
multi-band superconductivity in PbMo6S8. On the basis of my practical expe-
rience and the practiced visual skill, film stills of Pete’s successful achievement
could be arranged as follows (see Figure 12.6), if only to have its initial transcrip-
tion re-examined (Excerpt 3).
From the outset, again, Pete’s achievement of the physical experiment, not
solely the technical procedure, can be made apparent. Indeed, he appears not
simply to press the “spectro” button (see Excerpt 3, 090) and gaze at the oscil-
loscope (Excerpt 3, 092). To the contrary, he manifestly uses the oscilloscope
to monitor the phenomenon it should display, namely: once again, the “down-
ward jump” of the current/time line, indicating the STM tip’s entry into the tun-
neling regime at the newly selected position (as pictured in Figure 12.6, 3a). As
the phenomenon has been produced and noticed, Pete’s attention shifts to the
upper central “spectro” window (3b and Excerpt 3, 100 onward). He then appears
to monitor the spectroscopy, as it is traced from left to right, for its physically
relevant properties. At first, a zigzag line appears—possibly the intended phe-
nomenon, possibly not (3b). The first property of physical relevance is then dis-
played: a potential “gap,” in fact the intended “double gap,” with the small one
340 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Figure 12.6 The second [local spectroscopy] and its monitoring procedure
(Pete’s 2nd attempt re-examined)
lodged inside the big one (3c). The second key property, the symmetry of the
double gap, is displayed a tenth of a second later, as the gap can be anticipated to
come to a halt in the middle of the “spectro” window (3d). Taken together, those
two properties, double gap and symmetry of the double gap, appear as the locally
displayed properties, for a well-shaped spectrum of physical relevance to be pro-
duced and the experimentalist to exult: “YES!” (3d, and Excerpt 3, 102–106, #9).
His positive exclamation, indeed, is only produced as the launched spectrum
WORK OF A DISCOVERING SCIENCE 341
displays both properties, yet still in the course of its tracing (3d, 102). These
features, manifestly, are the local grounds for Pete’s “early exultation.” He then
claps his hands to mark the spectrum’s imminent completion (103–104) and, in
and upon its actual completion, lifts his arms in silence (104 onward, #10, which
is identical to 3e).9
Pete’s disciplinary orientation, with respect to the first reproducible spectrum
of good shape, appears in his timing of its recording, his pressing of the “print
screen” button (see Figure 12.6, 3f, and Excerpt 3, 115–117). He presses that
button (115) after the completion of the first spectrum (107, #10), yet only in
mid-course of the second one (110–119). Pete, in other words, doesn’t record
the first well-shaped spectrum immediately as I did (see Vignette 3). In fact,
he doesn’t record the first spectrum at all. Why? And: what does he record in-
stead? Readers may have guessed the answer: he records the first reproducible
spectrum, as and upon its well-shaped display in the upper right-hand panel of
the “spectro” window (3f, 115–117), rather than the first well-shaped spectrum
tout court, as displayed in the middle panel before (098–101, #9) and greeted
with instant celebration (102–106, #9). It is then the first detectable, reproduc-
ible, and well-shaped spectrum that is commented upon—“that, that’s the thesis”
(118), “you see, big gap, small gap, BIG” (126–133, #11)—and, since it has been
searched for long since, first found and distinctively qualified from within an
unprecedented physical inquiry at last, acknowledged as the “[truly special] mo-
ment when we discovered multi-band superconductivity in PbMo6S8 together”
(Petrović 2010:165) and eventually published as part of a “dramatic spectral var-
iation [ . . . ] [that] has not been previously observed” (Petrović et al. 2011:2).
This “double gap” spectrum of PbMo6S8, in other words, constitutes—or, at least,
constituted—the most reliable promise worldwide for “subsequent [spectra] [to]
systematically tease out an ordered set of relations retrospectively congruent
with the initial observation” (Bjelić and Lynch 1992:64)—that is, the empirical
discovery of multiband superconductivity in PbMo6S8.
Conclusion
In the late 1980s, Garfinkel and his colleagues asked what a physicist’s “discov-
ering work” would consist of, in its “discipline-specific work-site details as the
most ordinary organizational achievement of practical reasoning and practical
action in the world?” (Garfinkel et al.’s 1989:1, emphasis added). The description
offered in this chapter answered the pending question in terms of a hybrid study
of discovering work, thus closing the gap in the literature outlined in the intro-
duction. In so doing, the chapter afforded us with a perspicuous case to specify
342 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Acknowledgments
Prior versions of this chapter have been presented at various workshops and
conferences, including the International Institute of Ethnomethodology and
Conversation Analysis (IIEMCA) in Fribourg, Switzerland, July 2011, and
the American Sociological Association’s annual meeting in New York City,
August 10–13, 2013. I wish to thank attending participants for their remarks.
Special thanks are due to John Heritage and Doug Maynard, as well as Alex
Petrović, Michael Lynch, Wes Sharrock, and Rod Watson. A prior version
of the chapter has been published in Sormani (2014). I would like to thank
Routledge for its copyright permission. The finalization of the chapter
benefitted from and was funded by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft
(DFG, German Research Foundation)—Project-ID 262513311—SFB 1187.
Remaining mistakes are mine.
WORK OF A DISCOVERING SCIENCE 345
Appendix
References
Bjelić, Dušan I., and Michael Lynch. 1992. “The Work of a (Scientific) Demonstration:
Respecifying Newton’s and Goethe’s Theories of Prismatic Color.” Pp. 52–78 in Text
in Context: Contributions to Ethnomethodology, edited by G. Watson and R. M. Seiler.
London: SAGE.
Blundell, Stephen. 2009. Superconductivity. A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Brannigan, Augustine. 1980. “Naturalistic and Sociological Models of the Problem of
Scientific Discovery.” British Journal of Sociology 31(4):559–73.
Cho, Adrian. 2006. “High Tc: The Mystery That Defies Solution.” Science 314(5802):1072–75.
doi: 10.1126/science.314.5802.1072.
Collins, Harry M. 1985. Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice.
London: SAGE.
Czyzewski, Marek. 1994. “Reflexivity of Actors versus Reflexivity of Accounts.” Theory,
Culture & Society 11(4):161–68. doi: 10.1177/026327694011004006.
van Delft, Dirk. 2007. Freezing Physics. Heike Kamerlingh Onnes and the Quest for the Cold.
History of Science and Scholarship in the Netherlands, Vol. 10. Amsterdam: Royal
Academy of Arts and Sciences.
346 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Doing, Park. 2008. “Give Me a Laboratory and I Will Raise a Discipline: The Past, Present,
and Future Politics of Laboratory Studies in STS.” Pp. 279–318 in The Handbook of
Science and Technology Studies, edited by E. Hackett, O. Amsterdamska, M. Lynch, and
J. Wajcman. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dubois, Cédric, Alexander P. Petrović, George Santi, Christophe Berthod, Alfred A.
Manuel, Marc Decroux, Øystein Fischer, Michel Potel, and R. Chevrel. 2007. “Node-
like Excitations in Superconducting PbMo6S8 Probed by Scanning Tunneling
Spectroscopy.” Physical Review B 75(10):1–4. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevB.75.104501.
Garfinkel, Harold. 2002a. Ethnomethodology’s Program: Working Out Durkeim’s Aphorism,
edited and introduced by A.W. Rawls. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Garfinkel, Harold. 2002b. “Instructions and Instructed Actions.” Pp. 197– 218 in
Ethnomethodology’s Program: Working Out Durkeim’s Aphorism, edited and intro-
duced by A. W. Rawls. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Garfinkel, Harold. 2002c. “Tutorial Problems.” Pp. 145–68 in Ethnomethodology’s
Program: Working Out Durkheim’s Aphorism, edited and introduced by A. W. Rawls.
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Garfinkel, Harold, and Kenneth Liberman. 2007. “Introduction: The Lebenswelt Origins of
the Sciences.” Human Studies 30(1):3–7. doi: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-007-9045-x.
Garfinkel, Harold, Eric Livingston, Michael Lynch, Douglas Macbeth, and Albert B.
Robillard. 1989. “Respecifying the Natural Sciences as Discovering Sciences of
Practical Action, I & II: Doing So Ethnographically by Administering a Schedule
of Contingencies in Discussions with Laboratory Scientists and by Hanging
around Their Laboratories.” Unpublished Manuscript. Los Angeles: Department of
Sociology, UCLA.
Garfinkel, Harold, Michael Lynch, and Eric Livingston. 1981. “The Work of a Discovering
Science Construed with Materials from the Optically Discovered Pulsar.” Philosophy of
the Social Sciences 11(2):131–58. doi: 10.1177/004839318101100202.
Garfinkel, Harold, and Harvey Sacks. 1970. “On Formal Structures of Practical Actions.”
Pp. 337–66 in Theoretical Sociology: Perspectives and Developments, edited by J. C.
McKinney and E. A. Tiryakian. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, Educational
Division.
Garfinkel, Harold, and D. Lawrence Wieder. 1992. “Two Incommensurable,
Asymmetrically Alternate Technologies of Social Analysis.” Pp. 175–206 in Text in
Context: Contributions to Ethnomethodology, edited by G. Watson and R. M. Seiler.
Newbury Park, CA: SAGE.
Güntherodt, Hans-Joachim, and Roland Wiesendanger, eds. 1992. Scanning Tunneling
Microscopy I: General Principles and Applications to Clean and Adsorbate-Covered
Surfaces. Berlin; Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag.
Hacking, Ian. 1983. Representing and Intervening. Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of
Natural Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hammersley, Martyn. 2016. “What Was Radical about Ethnomethodology? A Look Back
to the 1970s.” Radical Ethnomethodology, 22–23 June 2016. Manchester: Manchester
Metropolitan University. https://radicalethno.org/documents.html.
Koschmann, Timothy, and Alan Zemel. 2009. “Optical Pulsars and Black Arrows:
Discoveries as Occasioned Productions.” Journal of the Learning Sciences 18(2):200–246.
doi: https://doi.org/10.1080/10508400902797966.
Latour, Bruno. 2004. “Why Has Critique Run Out of Steam? From Matters of Fact to
Matters of Concern.” Critical Inquiry 30(2):225–48.
WORK OF A DISCOVERING SCIENCE 347
Introduction
In line with Garfinkel’s abiding way of working, in this chapter we explore his
re-specification of the problem of method in the social sciences both concep-
tually and empirically via an example of some practical features of research
with numbers. The example is drawn from a small-scale field study of a group
of social science researchers engaging in and with statistical analysis as part of
mixed-method research attempting to integrate qualitative and quantitative
work (see, e.g., Hesse-Biber 2015; Tashakkori and Teddlie 2010). Instead of fo-
cusing on what goes into gathering quantitative data (Maynard 2011; Maynard
and Schaeffer 2000) or on producing statistical analyses via model-building per
se (Greiffenhagen, Mair and Sharrock 2015; Greiffenhagen, Mair, and Sharrock
2012; Mair, Greiffenhagen, and Sharrock 2016), we focus on how statistical ana-
lyses are incorporated within research practice. Rather than look at what is vari-
ously involved in working up statistical analyses, in other words, we are going to
look at what is involved in organizing research around them—something which
will enable us to more clearly outline what we think an appreciation of Garfinkel’s
work can contribute to contemporary debates on knowledge making, as well as
numbering practices in the social sciences more broadly (e.g., Camic, Gross, and
Lamont 2014; Day, Lury, and Wakeford 2014; Lamont, Camic, and Gross 2011;
Mair, Greiffenhagen, and Sharrock 2013).
Quantitative research practices make for a particularly compelling, indeed
perspicuous, case study, as ethnomethodology, not known for its easy rela-
tionship with the social sciences in general, is often thought of as being par-
ticularly and markedly antagonistic to the project of quantification. This is
misplaced, however, and part of the reason why this misconception arises is
that ethnomethodology’s interest in problems of method in the social sciences
has been widely misunderstood. Garfinkel was no more presenting a critique of
quantification than he was presenting a critique of any aspect of social scientific
work (see also Heritage 1984:136, 167–68; Maynard and Schaeffer 2000). Rather,
he was pursuing a reorientation to social science as a practically organized en-
terprise and hence a reorientation to social scientific research—quantitative
Research with Numbers 349
The social science movement carries out its work, at its work sites,
with highest priority of attention to methods. Many of its methods
are deliberately designed. In the practical burdens of their use they
are carefully administered . . . [and those] careful methods are every-
where accompanied by incongruities.
—Garfinkel (2002:121–22)
Methods have long been a major preoccupation of social scientists, and Garfinkel’s
intense interest in the working practices of sociological inquiry interrogates the
practical grounds of that fixation and the troubles which fuel and sustain it. The
various troubles that Garfinkel comments on are not, however, ones that were,
prior to his noting them, unknown to professional social scientists. That there is
a problematic slippage and hence a mismatch between the actual and intended
objects of inquiry, i.e., between the phenomenon of investigation and the materials
collected to exhibit that phenomenon, is a common complaint. One of Garfinkel’s
most noted observations, for instance, concerns the distinction between the
ragbag of problematically opaque, situated, context-dependent expressions that
are the materials of social scientific research, and the methodologically preferred
practice of recasting them in forms regarded as suitable for scientific purposes
(and see here Hutchinson, Read, and Sharrock 2008). In Garfinkel’s (1967:6) own
words, this is the “promised distinction and substitutability of objective for index-
ical expressions.” As Garfinkel notes, this “remains programmatic in every partic-
ular case and in every actual occasion in which the distinction or substitutability
must be demonstrated” (Garfinkel 1967:6, emphasis in original). Garfinkel (1967)
mentions the “virtually unanimous agreement” among logicians and linguists on
the nature of indexical expressions and notes that:
[ . . . ] drawing upon their experience in the uses of sample surveys, and the
design and applications of practical actions, statistical analyses, mathematical
models, and computer simulations of social processes, professional sociologists
are able to document endlessly the ways in which the programmatic distinction
and substitutability is satisfied in, and depends upon, professional practices
of socially managed demonstration. . . . [Nonetheless] wherever studies of
Research with Numbers 351
practical action are involved, the distinction and substitution is always accom-
plished only for all practical purposes. (1967:6–7)
[It] is hard to pretend that you have . . . the equivalent of a telescope, micro-
scope, linear accelerator, or the like when . . . [you] plod along handing out
questionnaires and conducting interviews . . . [T]o the extent that sociology
continues to produce verbal and written texts, devoid of instrumentation, the
discipline will continue to have problems in convincing skeptics that it has any
“hard data” or findings. (1999:10–11)
While Turner and Kim’s critique is perhaps more barbed than others2, the imme-
diate force of their account of problems of methods in the social sciences—that
they compare unfavorably to their counterparts in the natural sciences, that they
produce equivocal results, that they are irremediably textual, and so on—would
be conceded by the majority of social scientists. When the comparison is set out
in these terms, the social sciences do come out badly. Rather than assert other-
wise, the contemporary sociological approach has been to take a different tack
and argue that methods in the social sciences ought to be judged against different
standards from those that characterize the natural sciences (Osborne 2013). To
judge the social sciences in terms other than their own, as Turner and Kim do,
is thus positioned as unreasonable (Becker 2009). Taking the natural sciences
as the model to emulate, it is difficult to see how social science could amount
to anything more than a “clumsy imitation” (Gomez, Merino, and Tur 2010).
If using the natural sciences as a model for assessing social scientific inquiry is
352 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
unreasonable, however, the question then becomes, what might constitute more
reasonable terms of assessment?
There are two broad strands to recent thinking on this question, one exter-
nally facing and one internally facing. There is, first, the attempt to reappraise
what methods are, the role they play in the production of “social knowledge”
(Lamont et al. 2011) and the different standards at work in their evaluation. This
moves outward from specific research projects, disciplines, or even the social sci-
ences as a whole, and treats the problem of method as one variant of larger issues
affecting those seeking knowledge of society wherever and whenever they do so
(as in, e.g., Camic et al. 2014; Lamont et al. 2011; and see Mair et al. 2013 for
an overview). There is also, second, an attempt to develop justifications for the
ways in which research gets done despite all the recognized problems of method.
This kind of licensing activity is directed inward, toward other practicing social
scientists, and it is predicated on the claim that it is reasonable to proceed de-
spite both the global and local difficulties encountered as a matter of course by
those undertaking social scientific research. Taken together, the effect of both
arguments is to refocus discussion of methods on their relative strengths and
weaknesses and on their socially, culturally, and historically embedded and con-
tingent character.3 Instead of principled solutions, the emphasis is placed, at the
level of the local study, on “what works” and, at the level of disciplines, on of-
fering analyses of how what has been accepted as “what works” came to be ac-
cepted as such over time—i.e., in the emergence, consolidation, and diffusion of
different methods.
This body of work on the methodological bases of knowledge in and of so-
ciety redefines what can reasonably be expected from the social sciences. By
situating social science in wider fields of “social knowledge in the making,” we
are being asked to accept that it would not be reasonable to assess social science
methods using standards we would not apply to other forms of social knowledge
(Benzecry and Krause 2010; Camic et al. 2014; Lamont et al. 2011). By com-
paring and contrasting the relative merits of, for example, interviewing and eth-
nographic fieldwork using these pragmatic, pluralistic standards, we are being
asked to accept that it would not be reasonable to ask too much of either (or even
any) method—each has its strengths and weaknesses, each will generate unre-
solvable problems, and none will be suited for every task (Lamont and Swidler
2014). Nor will the question of which method might be most appropriate for any
given task be capable of being settled on a principled basis either—any decision
will itself be pragmatically oriented to considerations of circumstance, them-
selves subject to change.
When turned around, the argument is that it is perfectly legitimate to pro-
ceed despite and whatever the problems known to attend the use of any given
method because to let those problems curtail research would be unreasonable.
Research with Numbers 353
Our stance is that each technique has its own limitations and advantages and
that a technique does not have agency: all depends on what one does with it,
what it is used for. . . . We believe that debating techniques per se leads us down
an unproductive path. We are [thus] coming out against methodological trib-
alism. . . . (2014:154)
(1967:98)—for “all practical purposes,” dealt with in ways that prevent methodo-
logical failings from counting as invalidating weaknesses of actual inquiries. This
is effected through the operation of research practice via a combination of meth-
odological stringency and methodological reasonableness. In line with this, our
treatment of our empirical example is designed to bring out the ways and extent
to which methodological troubles, and the practical, ad hoc, solutions advanced
in relation to them, are treated as entirely reasonable matters, given the practical
circumstances in which professional sociological research is done.
However, Garfinkel’s stance on the social sciences is not easy to pin down. His
comments are not programmatic and unified, but fragmentary, dispersed, and
occasioned. Moreover, although he did explicitly and regularly disavow any crit-
ical motivation, he was far from consistent in that regard. Nonetheless, based
on a re-reading of Studies and a series of publications which appeared after its
publication (principally Garfinkel 1975, 2002; Garfinkel and Sacks 1970; Hill and
Stones-Crittenden 1968), we want to suggest that there are three recurrent lines
of analysis running through his engagement with method.
First, Garfinkel consistently came back to what he saw as an enduring as-
pect of social scientific practice: namely, its location within (and dependence on
knowledge of) the very societies and cultures which it sets out to analyze. For
Garfinkel, these were the practical conditions within which researchers were able
to make the social structures of everyday life accountable, i.e., observable and
reportable. Taking Garfinkel’s line, quantitative research, for example, involves
practical methods of social and cultural inquiry that assume the availability of
the features of the societies and cultures they set out to analyze. Sociologists’ ca-
pacity to find and make available social structures depends on their practical fa-
miliarity with them—they rely on that knowledge and rely on the fact that others
will rely on it, too, in assessing their work. They know that if they look, in other
words, they will find something to talk about and will be understood when they
do. It is for this reason that Garfinkel referred to them as “no-fail” enterprises
(1975:Seminar 2, line 1158)—the phenomenon of interest can’t escape their in-
vestigative inquiries because the phenomenon’s appearance is not reliant on their
formal methods.4
Second, Garfinkel’s work urges a reorientation to methods texts and methods
talk, not as reconstructed logics but as logics of reconstruction—i.e., ways of
making research available through disciplinarily-accepted accounting practices
that selectively rework and thus re-render whatever actually happened to be
done, which is typically treated as “specifically uninteresting” (Garfinkel 1967:7–9,
2002:107).5 Investigators use what the work could be said to amount to or show
to retrospectively (re)formulate what was done, and this in general terms rather
than in terms of specifics. Reconstructions are successful where they yield legiti-
mate and recognizable glosses for the specifics of what was done that speak to the
356 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
In the final substantive section of this chapter, we want to concretize the dis-
cussion with reference to a study that looked at how researchers go about doing
research, in our case research with numbers. Looking at what is involved in
working with numbers in a setting where numbers provided the interface
Research with Numbers 357
Day, Lury, and Wakeford (2014:124) have recently discussed what we gain
when we reorient to what they call “numbering” as “a practised or cultural ac-
tivity.” Such an approach would not begin with “those formulae, accounts, or
practices in which numbers feature as (always already situated) integers or se-
miotic entities, but by addressing the ways in which numbering is composed or
accomplished as a form of practice” (Day et al. 2014:128). For Garfinkel and for
ethnomethodology more broadly, the challenge here is that of grasping the con-
stitutive features of different ways of working with numbers. The example we
work through in this section is an attempt to do just that in one particular case.
Social scientific inquiry is not undertaken in a vacuum—it presupposes and
references wider disciplinary surrounds, operating in dialogue (friendly or crit-
ical) with, and taking its lead from, what are regarded as significant past studies,
canonical texts, exemplary theoretical and methodological frameworks, and ex-
isting bodies of (more or less) secure empirical data and findings (Fish 2000:767;
Kuhn [1962] 2012:181–86; Wittgenstein 1956:Part VII:47, 413). In the majority
of cases, these connections are indirect and loose—on precisely whose shoulders
anyone might be standing can be endlessly revisited, particularly when it comes
to what are regarded as “the classics” (Osborne and Rose 1999:369). In a sizable
minority of cases, however, the connections are much more direct: these are
cases, and our example is one such, where a particular study serves as the imme-
diate point of departure for another.
The example is drawn from a field study we conducted of work on a collabora-
tive project involving qualitative and quantitative researchers with backgrounds
in various social science disciplines who had come together to undertake a meth-
odologically focused study designed to show the payoffs of mixing methods. The
study took the data sets generated by a much bigger national-level longitudinal
study (which one of the principal investigators had access to) as its starting point.
The plan was to conduct an analysis of a subset of the statistical data from this
large-scale study, focusing on social relationship variables indexing type, fre-
quency, and intensity of social contacts between different kinds of people, such
as family, friends, neighbors, and so on, that would be undertaken in conjunction
with qualitative field research with 25–30 of the study participants on a range
of related topics. The aim was to see how quantitative and qualitative methods
could be used in tandem to inform one another, and whether new insights into
358 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
The original intention was that the study would adopt what is termed a “se-
quential” mixed-method design (Hesse-Biber 2015). As one of the researchers
Research with Numbers 359
put it: “we started off with different scenarios as to what we would do—one
of them was that the quantitative data would offer us some puzzles that we
would investigate qualitatively; the other was that we would use the quanti-
tative findings to sample people” (interview). The initial idea was that a first
phase of quantitative analysis would lead into a first phase of qualitative re-
search by supplying, among other things, a sampling frame. The quantitative
research would thus inform (but not direct) the qualitative research, which in
turn would feed back into the quantitative research, in an iterative and dialog-
ical process (the capitalization in this notation indicates the equal weighting
given to both aspects of the research, where lowercase would indicate a lesser
weighting for one or the other, and the arrows represent timing): QUAN →
QUAL (→ QUAN → QUAL . . .).
The quantitative aspect thus had logical precedence, a form of “conditional
complementarity” (Maynard and Schaeffer 2000:332), with the rest of the re-
search following on from it. However, given the complexity of the data, the
quantitative analysis turned out to be more difficult and to take longer than
had first been imagined. Indeed, the complexities were such that they went
analytically beyond the expertise of the quantitative researchers, necessitating
a turn to a statistician for support (and see Mair et al. 2016 for a discussion
of the relationship between quantitative domain experts, as they are called,
and statisticians). The research thus acquired an additional and initially un-
foreseen element: (STAT & QUAN) → QUAL. Together they began isolating
and recasting elements within the larger data set, creating a smaller data set
that linked 12 socio-demographic variables (i.e., age, marital status, ethnicity,
education, health, place of residence, neighborhood characteristics, and so
on) with 4 categories of social relationship (i.e., those with spouses, children,
other family, friends and neighbors), each with 4 dimensions (i.e., close-
ness, quality, frequency, and “mode,” e.g., face-to-face contact, phone calls,
texts, letters, etc.). Once this initial preparatory work was done, they then
analyzed the statistical relationships between the resulting 48 variables (12
initial variables multiplied by the 4 categories of social relationship). Based
on that analysis, they created a range of composite variables, or factors, that
captured different patterns of variation in participants’ social relationships
linked to their socio- demographic characteristics and assigned them
different scores.
The final step was to find ways of differentiating the population they were
focusing on in terms of these factors. This procedure is known as a cluster anal-
ysis because it identifies clusters of individuals with broadly equivalent factor
scores within the target population. Factor scores were thus here a way of pro-
ducing profiles of groups of respondents by weighting and quantifying similar-
ities in the answers they provided to particular items in the underlying survey,
360 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
The cluster analysis and the derivation of types were not purely intellec-
tual exercises. In the context of the wider study, this approach was functional;
others were waiting on the results. The cluster analysis had been meant to pro-
vide a principled sampling strategy for selecting respondents for the qualitative
interviews. However, given the time it took and the limited “window” available
for conducting the qualitative interviews,7 the first round of interviewing had to
proceed before the cluster analysis was complete. Working without the numbers,
the qualitative researchers had to devise a way of deciding whom to contact for
interviews so as to get the field research underway. Reflecting on the process as
a whole, one researcher put the difficulties as follows: “a lot of people have tried
this, but actually, for logistical and research reasons, it’s quite difficult to do both
within one project; because they both need their own timescale. . . . We started
off with different scenarios . . . [but the analysis] on the quantitative data, that
took a long time; and meanwhile we couldn’t just wait for that to finish; we basi-
cally had to start sampling for the qualitative research” (interview).
Doing a proper job on the statistics was thus understood to need the extra
investment of time, but that meant the interviewing had to be done so as to get
things underway, despite a research design in which the interviewing was to
follow the quantitative analysis.
As the qualitative research had to begin while the quantitative analysis was
still being conducted, this meant formulating an alternative rationale for sam-
pling that remained consistent with the broad goals of the project. More spe-
cifically, they sought to anticipate what the numbers might say so that the two
aspects of the project would remain at least potentially compatible later. In the
course of their deliberations on this thorny question, they settled on selecting
whom to contact by the types of place in which those people lived. So what had
been designed as a sequential study turned into a parallel study, at least in the
first wave: STAT & QUAN | QUAL not QUAN → QUAL.
Our study took place at a time when the team were preparing for a second
wave of qualitative fieldwork, when further decisions had to be made on whom to
contact next and on what basis. The quantitative analysis was (largely) complete
so the interface problem was posed anew: How were they going to combine what
emerged from that analysis, with its emphasis on formally determined clusters of
participants, and the emphasis on place for selection purposes? How was this to
be done by the numbers? A series of meetings were held in which various sam-
pling strategies and options were discussed by members of the team. We focus
on two meetings, the first involving the qualitative researchers—“A” and “B”—
alone, and the second involving the whole team, including the individual, “C,”
362 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
leading the quantitative research. The main concern in both meetings was on
agreeing to a rationale for the selection of areas where they would contact indi-
viduals to interview. We start with the earlier of the two; transcriptions reflect
standard orthography. In Extract 1, “C” is the lead quantitative researcher who
was not present:
A:
We were thinking, and C agrees with this doesn’t he, but
[even though it’s now complete] we only take the cluster
analysis so far in the sampling. So it’s not something we
would want to drive our sampling. We’re interested to see
how the clusters fall within the areas that we’re going
to take.
B: I’ve chosen areas that I think are interesting.
A: But for other reasons, yeah?
B: Yeah.
A:
But I suppose what I’m saying here is that when we’re
looking at the clusters then we’re thinking about sam-
pling on the basis of people. And I’m really keen that we
keep that edge which is sampling on the basis of place be-
cause we’re interested in place.
B: I am trying to cross them. So I’m choosing areas that I think
are different and interesting in their own ways. Originally
we were talking about place, doing the first batch around
place, with the second batch more cluster driven. I was at
least trying to make this second batch do both.
A: Yeah, well I know we agreed that we’d look at those, doing
both is a good idea isn’t it.
A:
So we feel comfortable that we’re sampling on the basis
partly of clusters, partly on the demographics of place
but partly on the physical environment. The other thing
Research with Numbers 363
A:
So you’ve suggested some areas, C, and we talked about
these because we were thinking about having a continued
interest in place, different types of places, but also
different types of socioeconomic characteristics amongst
the sample.
C: Mm.
A:
And also a range of cluster membership, which we’ll try
to cover.
364 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
B: Yeah.
C:
So the areas you’ve highlighted are they on the basis of
all of those things? They’re place and . . . clusters?
B: They’re a combination of place and cluster.
C:
But do we want to randomly, semi-
randomly, pick some
cluster fives . . . and some cluster twos?
A: That might be a good idea actually.
C:
Just so . . . depending on who agrees and doesn’t agree,
we have some additional [interviewees].
A: So we’d know they were at the end of the list.
Research with Numbers 365
C:
Yeah, so if we don’t get enough fives and twos, we could
add them in. Maybe do more than thirty, maybe just get an-
other three twos and another three fives.
B: Just randomly.
C:
Semi-
randomly, so areas we can get to and areas that in
some sense connect with the areas we’ve already chosen.
consistent with each side’s criteria, but both sides were not interested in the same
way. Where the concerns of the researchers did directly align, this centered on
their common status as researchers, rather than on their operational roles as
researchers of different kinds. For instance, the researchers were unified by the
practical demands of the research: all involved had an interest in (a) making sure
the process ran as smoothly for them as possible, and in (b) ensuring that it ran
smoothly for others, too, even if on a different side of the project’s division of
labor. That an “interesting area” was to be identified, for instance, in terms of
whether they could get there by means of the transport available to them (i.e.,
car or bus, depending on who was doing the interviewing) is crucial. If the statis-
tical analysis told them to go somewhere they could not readily get to, what the
analysis was pointing to had to be adjusted. The soundness of the decisions they
made around area selection remained an open question, one that could only be
answered by seeing what the results turned out to be. No external standard was
in place by which they could judge this prior to actually doing the work and man-
aging unforeseen troubles along the way. As a consequence, the research had a
“wait and see” proviso (cf. Garfinkel 1967:3, 40–41) appended from the start, and
developed in response to ad hoc considerations throughout.
Here, in pursuing the practical task of getting “this thing put together and
into the streets by Friday” (Garfinkel 1975:Seminar 2, lines 1066–67), that is, in
getting the research work done, their capacity to move forward was thus secured
by the notion of “an interesting area anyway” as a practical methodological de-
vice. Its workings were not explicated but remained intrinsically vague: they
were indexical, situation-dependent. Indeed, the utility of the “interesting area”
gloss, its usability, was a function of its vagueness. Had it been rendered more
specific, its capacity to do the stitching work it was formulated to do at a project
level might have been called into question. As Garfinkel (1975:Seminar 1, lines
527–36) once noted about actual methods in the social sciences: “[The social sci-
ences] are simply loaded to overflowing with . . . natural language-dependent
devices. . . . They have one very gorgeous property. They’ll do any goddamn pro-
ject you want to make them do. They just do.”
Our study highlights the perennial tension and simultaneous complemen-
tarity between collecting data for a specific objective in a particular way and
seeing what you have collected and what you can make of it. Garfinkel’s point
was that this tension cannot be resolved; rather, it has to be managed. What is
more, in managing it, the research itself is changed, although far from fatally.
In our case, by exploiting ambiguities and vagueness in the sampling catego-
ries being worked with, the relevance of the numbers to the exercise alters. The
project began as an attempt to improve data collection by trying to connect the
data collected to the variables being used to analyze that data statistically, and
selecting interview participants by drawing them from the relevant cluster. But
Research with Numbers 367
this procedure was loosened in the face of practical difficulties. Sample selec-
tion was ultimately determined on the basis of general themes rather than a
“strong analysis.” Far from being problematic, and consistent with Garfinkel’s
central point, this strategy represented not just a problem overcome, but a vic-
tory for the project.
Conclusion
We’re talking here about the most practical work in the world.
—Garfinkel (1975:Seminar 1, line 614)
In this chapter we set out, following Garfinkel, to explicate and elaborate what is
involved in actually doing research with numbers. As we have tried to show, and
as Garfinkel puts it in the preceding quotation, it is practical work through and
through. The situation of inquiry that our example details is not aberrant, anom-
alous, or unusual: it is run-of-the-mill, and represents what, in their research,
social scientists are doing—it is the practice. As the example shows, it is not that
working social scientists, unlike ethnomethodologists, are unaware of these is-
sues, nor of their largely unresolved condition, nor is there any such suggestion
in Garfinkel’s meditations on the methods in use in professional sociological
inquiries. That we learn of these issues from social scientists should underline the
trouble with that claim (see also Maynard and Schaeffer 2000:335).
Garfinkel’s (1967 and elsewhere) comments on method are best understood
descriptively as offering the view that professional social scientists understand
their work as pervaded by methodological troubles, but these are lived with,
and handled, as occasions demand, rather than being systematically resolved.
Furthermore, that any study will depart in all manner of ways from textbook
methodological stringencies does not prevent its subsequent circulation as a fac-
tual report. As our example illustrates, the fact that pervasive methodological
troubles are provided with solutions adequate for “all practical purposes” rather
than in terms of strict compliance with rules of “method” reflects the extent to
which the problematic implementation of methodological policies comprises
the most widespread of “normal, natural troubles” (e.g., Garfinkel 1967:187–91)
within these disciplines. As a result, the way in which the management of the
operationalization of method is encountered is as the most matter-of-course as-
pect of the research task at hand.
We are pointing to instances that participating colleagues would acknowl-
edge as “good work” involving, in the example we have been looking at, the
articulation of data collection and analysis tasks with the management of organi-
zational constraints on the coordination of concerted research activity. Handling
368 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
problems, such as how can time lost here be made up there, and if so with what
implications for initially projected outcomes, means abiding by reasonable
standards, good enough for all practical purposes. Such accommodations are
ubiquitous and they are also eminently reasonable. What Garfinkel sought to
make visible as a topic, and what we have sought to highlight in our example, are
serious efforts at doing the work the research demands in the light of ever-arising
and ever-unforeseen complications. That effort is invested not in circumventing
those demands, but in finding a best solution where doing what was supposed to
be done, in a strict sense, is all but impossible. That work typically goes unseen
or, at least, unspoken. Garfinkel’s lasting contribution has been to redirect our at-
tention to that work as the praxiological foundation of social scientific research,
whether with numbers or without.
Acknowledgments
This research was made possible by the UK Economic and Social Research
Council through funding to the National Centre for Research Methods, project
code RES-576-25-0022. We would like to thank the researchers we studied for
their time, patience, and generosity in facilitating our study.
References
Becker, Howard S. 2009. “How to Find Out How to Do Qualitative Research.” International
Journal of Communication 3:545–53.
Benzecry, Claudio E. [2015] 2017. “What Did We Say They’ve Said? Four Encounters
between Theory, Method and the Production of Data.” Ethnography 18(1):24–34.
doi: 10.1177/1466138115592423.
Benzecry, Claudio E., and Monika Krause. 2010. “How Do They Know? Practicing
Knowledge in Comparative Perspective.” Qualitative Sociology 33(4):415–22.
doi: 10.1007/s11133-010-9159-8.
Camic, Charles M., Neil Gross, and Michèle Lamont. 2014. “Looking Back at ‘Social
Knowledge in the Making.’” Sociologica 8(2):1–8.
Day, Sophie, Celia Lury, and Nina Wakeford. 2014. “Number Ecologies: Numbers and
Numbering Practices.” Distinktion: Journal of Social Theory 15(2):123–54. doi: 10.1080/
1600910X.2014.923011.
Derrida, Jacques. 1989. “Biodegradables: Seven Diary Fragments.” Critical Inquiry
15(4):812–73.
Fish, Stanley. 2000. “Theory Minimalism.” San Diego Law Review 37:761–76.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1967. Studies in Ethnomethodology. Cambridge, UK: Polity.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1975. “The Boston Seminars, 1–5.” Available via the EMCA Legacy
Project (www.emca-legacy.info). Boston, MA.
Research with Numbers 369
Mauthner, Natasha. 2015. “‘The Past Was Never Simply There to Begin with and the
Future Is Not Simply What Will Unfold’: A Posthumanist Performative Approach
to Qualitative Longitudinal Research.” International Journal of Social Research
Methodology 18(3):321–36. doi: 10.1080/13645579.2015.1022298.
Maynard, Douglas W. 2011. “An Intellectual Remembrance of Harold Garfinkel: Imagining
the Unimaginable, and the Concept of the ‘Surveyable Society.’” Human Studies
35(2):209–21.
Maynard, Douglas, and Nora Cate Schaeffer. 2000. “Toward a Sociology of Social Scientific
Knowledge: Survey Research and Ethnomethodology’s Asymmetric Alternates.” Social
Studies of Science 30(3):323–70. doi: 10.1177/030631200030003001.
Osborne, Thomas. 2013. “Inter That Discipline!” Pp. 82–98 in Interdisciplinarity:
Reconfigurations of the Social and Natural Sciences, edited by A. Barry and G. Born.
London: Routledge.
Osborne, Thomas, and Nikolas Rose. 1999. “Do the Social Sciences Create Phenomena?
The Example of Public Opinion Research.” British Journal of Sociology 53(3):367–96.
Rughiniș, Cosima, and Bogdana Humă. 2015. “Who Theorizes Age? The ‘Socio-
Demographic Variables’ Device and Age–Period–Cohort Analysis in the Rhetoric of
Survey Research.” Journal of Aging Studies 35:144–59. doi: 10.1016/j.jaging.2015.07.005.
Sacks, Harvey. 1972. “On the Analyzability of Stories by Children.” Pp. 325–45 in
Directions in Sociolinguistics: The Ethnography of Communication, edited by J. J.
Gumperz and D. Hymes. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
Tashakkori, Abbas, and Charles Teddlie. 2010. SAGE Handbook of Mixed Methods in
Social & Behavioral Research. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.
Teplitskiy, Misha. 2016. “Frame Search and Re-Search: How Quantitative Sociological
Articles Change during Peer Review.” American Sociologist 47(2):264–88.
Turner, Jonathan H., and Kyung-Man Kim. 1999. “The Disintegration of Tribal Solidarity
among American Sociologists: Implications for Knowledge Accumulation.” The
American Sociologist 30(2):5–20. doi: 10.1007/s12108-999-1014-6.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1956. Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics. London: Basil
Blackwell.
Zimmerman, Don H., and Melvin Pollner. 1970. “The Everyday World as a Phenomenon.”
Pp. 80–104 in Understanding Everyday Life: Toward the Reconstruction of Sociological
Knowledge, edited by J. D. Douglas. Chicago: Aldine.
14
The Sherlock Experiment
Eric Livingston and John Heritage
372 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
The Experiment
The Sherlock Experiment was based on the board game 221B Baker Street,
produced by John N. Hansen Co., Inc. The following text, adapted with minor
changes from Case #22, “The Adventure of the Pillaged Pawnbroker,” was given
to each of the members of the experimental group—“Ava,” “Bea,” “Chuck,” and
“Debbie,” all (pseudonymized) undergraduate students. It was then read out
loud to the group as a whole.
The lock on the Pawnshop’s front door had been broken and
$34.16 had been taken from the cash register.
In the Baker Street game, players take turns rolling a die and moving their tokens
to various locations on the game board—the Museum, the Boar’s Head Inn, and
the Tobacconist, to name three. Upon reaching such a location, if another player
hasn’t temporarily “locked” the location, a player is allowed to read the clue associ-
ated with that site and to make written notes. Various strategies and tactics can come
into play, with the players competing to gather information and solve the crime.
In our experiment, the aim wasn’t to hide information from the subjects, to make
them search for clues, or to have them compete with each other. We wanted them
to talk together and to work toward a common, mutually recognized solution of
the crime. Our procedure, after we read the account of the murder, was to give each
of the subjects his or her own set of individual clues. We encouraged the subjects
to read their clues to each other as many times as they wanted or found neces-
sary. The subjects were not, however, allowed to share the pieces of paper on which
their individual clues were written or to make written notes on their deliberations.
We wanted to deter them from turning the crime problem into a pencil-and-paper
logical puzzle which they tried to solve individually on their own.
The four sets of clues, based on those from 221B Baker Street but modi
fied, expanded, and fitted to the experimental situation, were as follows
(Boxes 14.1–14.4).
4. The killer didn’t bring the murder weapon to scene of the crime.
5. A valuable art object form the 15th century was stolen recently from the
Cultural and Natural History Museum.
6. Henry Kirk’s hobby is collecting old coins and medals.
374 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
10. The murder weapon was too unwieldy and heavy for most women and
many men to use.
11. The police have no clues or suspects in the museum robbery.
12. Why was the cash register emptied?
The experimental session lasted one hour within which the subjects were
asked, collectively, to identify in writing the killer, the murder weapon, the mo-
tive for the crime, and the overall story of the murder.
Three Conjectures
Prior to the experiment, we had anticipated three general findings: (1) that the
experimental group would be able to solve the problem; (2) that we would be
flooded with phenomena of reasoning seldom considered in conventional
studies; and (3) that we would be able to observe how the group worked and rea-
soned together to arrive at their solution.
Regarding the first conjecture, both before conducting the experiment and
for a considerable time afterward, we had naively accepted that the solution
of the crime was the one given in the Baker Street game. We had tried to make
finding that solution easier through our development of the individual clues;
at the same time, we had worried that we might be making the crime problem
too easy. As it turned out, the experimental group found the problem quite
difficult. Only by the end of the hour did the group have, for the most part,
an agreed solution of the crime. Even then, members of the group were still
attempting to account for some of the details, and one of the experimental
The Sherlock Experiment 375
subjects continued to maintain that two separate crimes had been com-
mitted—one involving the theft of $34.16 from the cash register, the other
involving the murder.
Concerning the second conjecture, the range of the groups’ discussion
and actions surprised us. The group members had difficulty keeping track
of which of the dramatis personae they had eliminated as suspects; they
returned repeatedly to considerations of how they should proceed; they
tried to implement various procedures for reasoning about the problem and
switched intermittently between different lines of inquiry. Substantively, they
considered things such as the nature of a pawnshop’s business, the meaning
of the word “parcel,” the relative physical strengths of newspaper reporters
and theater managers, and the possibility that two of the suspects had collab-
orated with each other, with one of them hiding, possibly for days, in a locked
prop box.
Our third conjecture—that we would be able to observe how the group rea-
soned together to find a solution—was the most problematic. We had difficulty
distancing ourselves from the naturalness and mundaneity of what the members
of the group were doing. They would remind themselves of the uncertain and
conditional character of a current working hypothesis, discuss possible courses
of action that might lead to a summary description of the crime, consider stereo-
typical characteristics of people and essential properties of real-world objects in
order to find ways in which the clues might be related to and inform one another.
They would interrogate the meanings of words, weigh the relative importance of
the details of the crime, and question whether some of the clues had been given
so as to purposefully mislead them.
Although what the experimental group did was unanticipated, we found, in
repeatedly viewing and listening to the video record, that the collaborative actions
of the members of the group were predominantly ordinary, understandable in
and as the course of their deliberations, and seemingly without theoretical in-
terest other than that they were not making the connections or following the in-
ferential procedures that we thought they should. Our aim was to begin to see
people’s ongoing reasoning with each other as the foundational phenomenon of
reasoning: regardless of whatever odd ideas the experimental group considered,
we wanted to examine how the experimental subjects did whatever they were
doing to make their actions and reasoning practically accountable to and for each
other. On that score, although we watched the video over and over, the work of
their reasoning and the distinctiveness of that reasoning as the work of solving
the crime problem remained hidden in the midst of its seemingly unexceptional
character.
376 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
A Prejudicial Assumption
Both in designing the experiment and, initially, in trying to analyze the exper-
imental session, we had thought that the explanation of the crime given in the
221B Baker Street game—the “book solution”—was, in fact, the solution of the
crime. This assumption hindered our research considerably. We only began to
understand the work of the experimental group when we realized (1) that the
“book solution” had its own inadequacies, (2) that it was only one of many pos-
sible explanations of the crime, and (3) that trying to explain what the students
were doing in terms of their failure to find the book solution didn’t make par-
ticularly good sense. The conversational fragment in the following drew our at-
tention to these problems and allowed us to begin to attend to what the students
were doing.
Prior to the conversational fragment, the experimental group had reached
seeming agreement that the pawnshop owner Miles Balfour had been killed
using the knight’s broadsword. More immediately, the group was trying to assess
the values of the objects that had been stolen, as well as the values of some pos-
sible objects that the crook had left behind.
In line 1, Chuck, considering this situation, asks why anyone would want to
steal the vase. In response, Bea proposes that vases are things for women and that
the thief probably took it as a present for his wife. Seven seconds of silence follow.
Chuck and Ava’s “okay’s” (lines 14 and 15) indicate that they see—and agree that
they see—no immediate way of building on Bea’s suggestion.
At this point, Ava starts a new topic: she begins questioning the mechanics of
how Miles Balfour was stabbed to death and, in lines 22–24, raises the problem
of the crook sneaking up on someone in the pawnshop while lugging around a
broadsword. In response, starting in lines 25–26, the group tries to build a plau-
sible scenario for the murder.
Extract 1 (continued)
15 AVA: O
kay .hh ((reading)) "was found stabbed to death"=How many
16 times was he [stabbed.
17 CHU: [Oh they did-didn't say
18 (1.5)
19 CHU: ((reading)) "behind the main counter of establish[ment."
20 AVA: [Yeah.
21 (0.8)
22 AVA: So I mean (1.2) I'm assuming the armor wasn't close by:.
23 (.) In that (.) he had to the bring the sword to him,
24 ((gesture of a direction of carrying the sword))
25 CHU: >
Okay< let's pretend to be the killer then.=Right we walk
26 intuh thu:h (.) to the sto:re.
27 AVA: Mm hm,
28 CHU: We see: (.) Miles Balfour and he['s
29 AVA: [No we break into the store.=
30 DEB: =[Right
31 CHU: =[Okay so we break into the sto:re,(0.2) Where would Miles
32 Balfour be.
33 DEB: [[Behind the counter.
34 AVA: [[Behind [the counter.
35 CHU: [Probably behind the counter.
36 BEA: Right.
37 CHU: We go over there:.
38 DEB: Well [we
39 CHU: [We=
40 AVA: =grab the sword,
41 DEB: We grab the sword fi[rst
42 CHU: [How do we grab the sword though.=
43 =See the thing is if you walk-if you go in >okay< do it
44 let's say we sneakily. I mean sneak.
45 (1.2)
46 CHU: We sneak
378 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Extract 1 (continued)
50 CHU: But we need to g-but it’s heavy for us (0.2) tuh (.) to use
51 the swor:d.
52 (1.5)
53 CHU: But we’re ab-we’re able to manage to (0.7) See the broadsword
54 I-I know the broadsword’s pretty lo:ng. ((stretches arms to
55 full arm-span to show its length)) Yeah it is heavy.
56 AVA: Like Excalibur
57 (): [(laughter)
58 CHU: [No like it’s lo:ng. It’s kinda like-
59 DEB: Maybe it was close to her.
60 AVA: Yeah.
61 CHU: Okay so let’s say it’s close
62 DEB: Counter.
63 CHU: Yeah. Let’s say it[’s close to the counter
64 AVA: [But you still have-
65 Are we assuming that (.) like the counter is like (.) across
66 or you can walk around it.
67 (0.3)
68 o
r you believe you jump over the counter ((gestures indicating,
69 first, a possible layout of the counter, second, walking around
70 it and, last, thumping on the table following “jump over”))
71 CHU: See I’m not su:re.
Following Debbie’s suggestions in lines 73 and 76 below, Chuck closes the dis-
cussion in lines 80 and 83–84, stating summarily that Balfour “probably had his
back to [the killer] or something and so the killer took the sword and stabbed
him.” The discussion then shifts with Debbie’s proposal (lines 85 and 87) that the
killer must have been “pretty quick” and “muscled.” Chuck recalls one of Ava’s
individual clues (that “the murder weapon was too unwieldy and heavy for most
women and many men to use”) and, in lines continuing beyond the transcribed
The Sherlock Experiment 379
fragment, the group tries, as a way of winnowing the remaining suspects, to com-
pare the relative strengths of the male protagonists.
Extract 1 (continued)
72 BEA: ( [ )
73 DEB: [Maybe he was just like not looking and then he just
74 like pshhh ((gesture of thrusting a sword forward and stabbing))
75 BEA: Yeah.
76 DEB: Y
ou know what I mean like he was [probably doing stuff=
77 CHU: [Yeah
78 CHU: He was probably doing something like-
79 DEB: and then like
80 CHU: He probably had his back [to him or something
81 DEB: [Yeah and
82 DEB: the swo[rd
83 CHU: [And so (0.8) the killer: took the sword and stabbed
84 [him.
85 DEB: [So the killer must have been like pretty quick and ()
86 CHU: Yeah
87 DEB: muscled to like
88 CHU: which why-which is why which is why we ruled out the women
89 because (0.5) you ((Ava)) said ...
(26.01)
Breaking this conversational sequence into sections helps clarify the devel-
oping structure of the group’s immediate discussion. At the same time, it distorts
the predominant feature of our experience trying to analyze the video recording.
A sense of this experience comes by reading the 89 lines of the transcript straight
through without the commentary. The recorded sequence lasts about two
minutes; the rest of the experimental hour is pretty much more of the same. The
conversation seemed to be going nowhere; rather than moving toward a solution
of the crime, the subjects had trouble resolving almost any feature of it. We un-
derstood and could follow the experimental subjects’ conversation, but the char-
acter of that conversation as the work of solving the crime was elusive.
The breakthrough came when, viewing this part of the video repeatedly, we
realized that we actually agreed with the subjects: if Miles Balfour had been
stabbed with the broadsword behind the main counter, the sequencing of the
murderer’s and Balfour’s actions were difficult to visualize and understand. The
experimental group had found, through their discussion, that the granularity of
detail in the story and clues was insufficient to sustain an interrogation of how the
murder was physically committed. The group ended up settling for the account
380 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
that, simply, “the killer took the sword and stabbed him.” This is essentially the
same statement as the first line of the crime story.
For us, the researchers, once the correspondence between the fictional situ-
ation and conceivably real-world actions was questioned, we realized that any
number of scenarios could have resulted in the same summary description of
the crime. While Paulie “The Pick” Chandler might be eliminated as a suspect
because he could pick locks and wouldn’t need to break the front door, he might
not have been able to crack that particular lock or he might have broken the door
as a matter of expediency. Similarly, it’s conceivable if unlikely that two separate
crimes did occur on the same night or that Henry Kirk, as a newspaper reporter
possibly familiar with the museum robbery, recognized the vase when he came
into the pawnshop (to redeem, of all things, some books), and decided to steal it
for himself.
Both in the Baker Street game and in the experimental setting, the crime
story and associated clues were made up; they are works of fiction. There is no
real crime against which to compare the adequacy of reasoning about it, no
real situation that could be inspected and whose details could be interrogated.
The “book solution”—the one given in the board game and the one that we
had naively accepted as the solution—wasn’t the solution of a real-world crime.
We couldn’t hold the experimental group to such a solution, nor could they
possibly hold themselves to it. Whatever the circumstances and reasoning of a
solution to the crime could be, those circumstances and reasoning would have
to be generated and developed in course, in situ, by the members of the exper-
imental group.
Freed from judging the group’s work in terms of a hypothesized correct solu-
tion, we began to see that three features of the experimental session dominated
everything the group was doing. One was the subjects’ continual effort—their
observable work—trying to get mutual agreement about what happened, why
it happened, and who the person or persons were who did it. The second was
that, in engaging in that work of mutual recognition, the subjects were repeat-
edly frustrated reaching it. And, lastly, there was the repetitiveness of the group’s
conversation with, seemingly, very little progress toward a solution of the crime.
The Sherlock Experiment 381
Some of the technical detail involved in the effort to speak truthfully about
the crime is illustrated in the next fragment. In it, Ava suggests that Henry Kirk
might be the perpetrator: Kirk collects old coins; he may have mistakenly used
one of those coins to redeem his books; later he might have broken into the
382 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
pawnshop to retrieve the coin. In making this case, Ava refers to Kirk’s coins as
“expensive,” a word that helps motivate the theft and murder but a word that
doesn’t literally appear in the written clues. Ava immediate corrects herself;
Chuck reinforces the correction while improving the grammar, and Ava accepts
the correction.
Although one might infer that the coins had some value because they were old
and Kirk was collecting them, the relevant individual clue (which, like all such
clues, had been repeatedly read to the group) says only that “Henry Kirk’s hobby
is collecting old coins and medals.” The qualification of “collectible” makes the
immediately given evidence for Kirk’s culpability less secure.
A similar situation arose when the group tried to examine the physical murder
of Miles Balfour.
Members of the group differentiated between the literal texts of the crime and
what might be said about or inferred from them: while all manner of hypothetical
The Sherlock Experiment 383
conjectures might be entertained, this was not the case for matters of textual
“fact.” The account of the crime and the additional clues don’t say that Kirk’s
coins were valuable, nor do they say where Balfour was when the perpetrator
broke (rather than walked) into the store.
Distinguishing in such ongoing ways between “inference” and textual “fact”
served a practical purpose: by maintaining the difference, the group was also
maintaining their uncertainty about the nature of the crime and, therein, the ter-
rain within which and against which a solution might be discovered.
Obstructed Accountability
A little later in the session, Chuck points out that the group had previously
ruled out women as potential murderers. He asks Ava to read once again one of
her personal clues—that “the murder weapon was too unwieldy and heavy for
most women and many men to use.” Ava elaborates on eliminating the female
characters, suggesting that the murderer “must have been a pretty big guy.” The
following fragment begins at this point in the discussion. Chuck offers a compar-
ison between playhouse managers (like Wilbur Partridge) who do heavy lifting,
pull curtains, and are probably muscular guys, and newspaper reporters (like
Henry Kirk) who are “just mainly typing in the office.” Chuck wants to differen-
tiate the male suspects based on their relative strengths. Ava exposes a problem
with this procedure by asking in line 36 about the strength of John Cahill. In this
case, they don’t seem to have any information. Debbie (line 42) tries to rescue
the approach by suggesting that John’s presence in the crime story may be a ruse
to confuse the group. The group has reached an apparent dead end. Chuck then
The Sherlock Experiment 385
attempts to institute a new procedure beginning in line 46, this time considering
each of the male subjects one at a time.
seems to forget about John Cahill and suggests a different prospective killer
(“the wife of the guy that died”). Bea (lines 26–28) then offers a list of re-
maining potential killers. Chuck and Ava in lines 32–36 extend the list.
Pausing and, it seems, considering the length of the list and the fact that
the preceding discussion has neither clarified nor substantially reduced the
number of suspects, Chuck (lines 36–37) suggests that they return to and go
over the individual clues once again.
Textures of Detail
A third general feature of the group’s work was the repetitiveness of its consid-
erations—the return to the same clues, to the same concerns about them, and
to the repeating obstruction of almost any partial account of crime. Two issues
of developing, general agreement were that the broadsword was the murder
weapon and that the murderer was a man. Progress toward anything else was
difficult to see.
Discussions regarding the porcelain vase provide an example. Six minutes
into the session, Chuck summarized one of the clues by saying that the vase
belongs to “Miss Cahill”; shortly thereafter Ava proposed that “the string and the
newspaper were used to wrap . . . either the helmet or the vase.” At 10 minutes,
Chuck suggested that the vase could have been the object stolen from the mu-
seum, which led to a discussion of its possible value and, then, to Debbie’s as-
sertion that Phyllis Cahill didn’t commit the pawnshop crime. Shortly after 12
minutes, while the group was again rereading the clues, Chuck offered the vase
or the helmet as very likely the object stolen from the museum. Two minutes
later, while again reading through the clues, Chuck attributed to Ava the idea
that the newspaper and string were probably used to wrap the helmet, to which
Ava added “or the vase.” At 21 minutes, considering the clue that the object
stolen from the museum was from the fifteenth century, Ava asked whether
there was porcelain in the 1400s; she then thought that this could have been
the case in China. The discussion led to a concern over how the vase could
have been carried from the crime scene: if the helmet and vase had both been
wrapped with newspaper and tied with string, it would look like the thief was
carrying two bowling balls.
Giving a quantitative measure of the instances of the discussion of the vase
is difficult. Including when it was just mentioned in the reading of clues doesn’t
seem appropriate; at the same time, one discussion of the role of the vase could
immediately lead to different considerations which, in varying circumstances,
might or might not be treated as a single instance. A conservative estimate of the
The Sherlock Experiment 389
substantive discussion of the vase was 14 times in the first 45 minutes of the ex-
perimental hour.
A similarly conservative count is that Henry Kirk was discussed eight or
more times in the first 45 minutes. This included talk about whether he had
taken the newspaper from the pawnshop because, as a newspaper reporter, his
name might have appeared in the paper. At 16.40 minutes, Ava suggested that
Kirk had the strongest motive for the crime because he might have mistakenly
paid to redeem his books with one of his “special” coins and had broken into
the pawnshop to retrieve the coin. At 33.30 minutes, Ava proposed that if Kirk
were the killer, his motive would be “the money” (presumably the retrieval of
his “special” coin), raising again, for the group, the question of why he would
steal the helmet and the vase. At 44 minutes, Chuck suggested that the murderer
could be either Kirk or Partridge, the former because “he likes to collect coins”
and the latter because he’s a “big” (that is, a strong) guy.
Much of our frustration with the group’s conversation was that they didn’t
seem to be making any progress toward solving the crime. Oddly, on reflec-
tion, the group’s actions had some similarity with a practical technique of
discovery work. In the course of reviewing the individual clues and re-exam-
ining things said about them, the details of the crime were nuanced differ-
ently, they became associated in different ways, and they were viewed in
different contexts and in terms of different conjectures: at one time, certain
details were associated with each other and, at another, different (and some-
times new) configurations and relationships between the crime details were
entertained.
This situation had a consequential if indirect effect on the group’s work. The
details of what the members of the group had said about the crime became
overlaid and interwoven, including the compatibilities and inconsistencies
found through their discussion. This process gave increased “texture” to the
crime story and to the group’s search for the coherence of their own tellings of
the crime.
Forty-five minutes into the experimental hour, Ava pointed out a feature of the
crime story and clues that had been neglected in the group’s welter of conjectures,
statements of “fact,” and occluded argumentation. By foregrounding this aspect
of the narrative, Ava was able to build what came to be the group’s basic story of
the crime.
390 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Previous to Ava’s discovery, Chuck had been reiterating his belief that Paulie
“The Pick” had stolen the money in the cash register and that, later, someone
else had broken into the pawnshop, killed Balfour, and taken the other objects.
Undeterred by resistance to his theory, the lack of agreement on the murderer,
and no overall account of the crime or a motive for it, Chuck announced that
he would begin—and did begin—writing “our story” of the crime, referring to
Paulie’s conjectured theft as the “petty crime” (lines 1–4/6). In the ensuing si-
lence as Chuck began writing, Ava started muttering “the vase, the vase, the vase
in John’s attic” and ended up asking why the attic was described as John’s rather
than “their” (John and his wife Phyllis’s) attic. This led her to outline an account
of the crime in lines 31–33:
25 CHU: Yeah.
26 BEA: Weird thing to ( )
27 CHU: ((talking to himself about what he is writing)) “Sees”
28 (2.5)
29 BEA: (°John’s attic°)
30 (1.0)
31 AVA: John stole the vas:e from: the museum, left it in
32 his attic, (.) his wife found it took it to the pawnshop,
33 (0.4) he went back and stole it,
34 CHU: Yeah I feel like it’s something like that because the
35 wife doesn’t know the value of it,
36 AVA: Yeah.
Much earlier in the experiment, about nine minutes in, Chuck had posited a
similar account. There are, however, a number of differences. First, Chuck makes
the association of the vase with the object stolen from the museum just because
two clues were given, not because of any relationship between them:
okay see the thing the thing with my clue is that a valuable art object from the
sixteenth century was stolen recently from the cultural and natural history
museum if this is the clue a-um it leaves me to believe that one of these items
are pre-was previously stolen
Ava, on the other hand, points to literal features of the crime texts—that the attic
belongs to John but that it was Phyllis, not John, who decided to sell the vase.
Next, the group had trouble establishing whether the vase was valuable. In Ava’s
account the vase is simply the object stolen from the museum without consid-
ering its value. One problem with Chuck’s account remained and stayed with the
group to the end: if the vase was the object of the pawnshop theft, why steal the
helmet?
Whatever bearing these features of the two accounts may have had on their
reception, a more consequential difference lay in the contexts in which they
were given. We tend to think, as a seemingly natural prejudice, that the 221B
Baker Street crime story and clues remained the same throughout the experi-
ment. Phenomenologically, this isn’t correct. Ava’s account was given against
the background and in the midst of 45 minutes of accumulated associations
between the crime details and indeterminacies therein. By foregrounding
the ownership of the attic, much like adjusting a camera lens, Ava provided
392 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
the focal distance to begin to review and reassess—to see more clearly—the
details of the crime.
While the metaphor of focal distance seemed clarifying, the critical issue
for us, the researchers, was what the “object” was for which focal distance
was provided. It couldn’t be the real-world truth of the crime (for which
there isn’t any), and it didn’t seem to be how the clues, in and of themselves,
could now be seen as fitting together: following Ava’s proposal, the group
members did not start re-reading and reviewing the clues as they had done
repeatedly up to that point. Instead, the group, including Ava, spent the rest
of the hour rehearsing the details of Ava’s proposal, revisiting their previous
discussions and theories, and comparing those discussions and theories
with Ava’s account.
The following fragment gives the flavor of these discussions. Ava recalls one of
Chuck’s ideas that Paulie “The Pick” Chandler had hidden in the locked prop box
which the playhouse manager Partridge had pawned. The group, however, can’t
establish a reason for Chandler or Partridge doing this. Chuck then suggests that
they consider John Cahill (line 17) as the culprit. Ava points out (lines 19–20)
that Cahill seems “irrelevant” to the crime story, but this lack of his presence
comes to be viewed as a factor supporting his guilt. In this roundabout way, the
fragment ends with Chuck, in lines 35–36, again offering John Cahill’s culpa-
bility as a working hypothesis.
18 (2.0)
19 AVA: But he-you know like is he seems so irrelevant in
20 the story:,
21 DEB: Well maybe-
22 CHU: Who.
23 DEB: that’s
24 AVA: John. Yeah that’s that’s (sounds right)
25 CHU: But maybe that’s why because
26 DEB: Yeah.
27 CHU: I mean even your clue-one of your clues says like you
28 know the police don’t even have a
29 DEB: Yea:h.=
30 AVA: =Yeah.
31 CHU: thing [or information on
32 DEB: [Yeah
33 AVA: the museum robbery. Yeah.
34 (1.7)
35 CHU: Okay let’s say it’s John->what’s his name<
36 John Cahill,
Discussion
(Broeder 1959). Listening to the tapes, Garfinkel didn’t hear the jurors engaged
in legal argumentation or proper scientific reasoning, nor did the jurors’ actions
seem to reflect academic studies of decision-making in small groups. Calling
the envisioned discipline “ethnomethodology,” Garfinkel proposed the study of
people’s methods, studies of the ways that ordinary people—like jurists in a jury
room, but also like people waiting for an elevator, ordering dinner in a restau-
rant, or driving through crowded four-way stop intersections—go about their
ordinary, everyday affairs.
Prior to developing our experiment, we had become dissatisfied with
psychological experiments of reasoning: the theorizing associated with the
experiments seemed abstract, in-house, and self-sustaining; the solutions of
the experimental test questions typically involved mathematical reasoning
unlikely to be familiar to most of the experimental subjects; how the exper-
imental subjects came to give the answers that they gave was unexplored;
and the experiment procedures that were used precluded any interest in the
possible social dimensions of reasoning. Our aim was to create an experi-
mental situation where we could literally observe people reasoning together.
We adopted this approach because, at the time and still today, it seems like a
sensible thing to do.
A second research directive was embedded in Garfinkel’s teaching in the
1970s. The recommendation—itself one form of “reflexivity”—might be called
the “thesis of the radically situated, locally produced practical accountability
of practical action and reasoning.” A problem and, equally, a challenge for
researchers is associated with this recommendation: it doesn’t tell us, for any spe-
cific setting, what might be discovered or how someone might discover it. It isn’t
clear what it might mean for people driving in traffic, ordering dinner in a restau-
rant or, for that matter, the subjects of the Sherlock Experiment.
One of our findings is that, from the very beginning, from the first reading
of the individual clues, the experimental subjects oriented to what they them-
selves were saying about the crime; they were looking into what they were
saying to find whatever they would find a solution to be. They had no access
to any supposedly objective, situationally independent account of the crime;
they had no access to “the objective facts.” What they did have was what they
were saying to each other, and the subjects oriented to what they had said and
were saying to find what, in their immediate circumstances, they were doing
together.
Not only was the group orienting to what they were saying, they were continu-
ally and specifically focused on the accountability of what they were saying—dis-
tinguishing between what was true and what was only probably true, demarking
The Sherlock Experiment 395
Acknowledgments
We thank Fiona Utley for the suggestion that a crime game might be used to help
reveal idiosyncrasies of people’s reasoning and Sara Saleh for a draft transcript
of the experimental session. We are indebted as well to Michelle Arens, Chuck
Livingston, and Doug Maynard for their comments on, respectively, different
versions of the chapter. Eric Livingston thanks Estrid Sørensen and the Mercator
Research Group 2 for a year appointment as a Senior Research Fellow at the Ruhr
University Bochum, giving him the opportunity to work further on the project.
All procedures for the implementation of the experiment, including its videotape
recording, were approved by UCLA Human Subjects Protection Committee IRB
#G08-01-055-01. Pseudonyms have replaced the experimental subjects’ names
throughout the paper.
Appendix A
A Solution to the Problem in Figure 14.1
Figure 14.1 at the beginning of this chapter gives a test question from a psy-
chology experiment by Goldvarg and Johnson-Laird (2000):
Only one of the following premises is true about a particular hand of cards:
Suppose that there is an ace in the hand. By formal logic, if there is an ace in the
hand, it is true that if there is a king in the hand, then there is an ace. This has
nothing to do with some type of causality between kings and aces, only with the
fact that an ace is already known to be in the hand. Similarly, if there is an ace in
the hand, it is true that if there is a queen in the hand, then there is an ace in the
hand. The first sentence of the problem says that only one of the listed premises is
true. If there is an ace in the hand, then two of the premises are true, so there can’t
be an ace in the hand.
References
Broeder, Dale W. 1959. “The University of Chicago Jury Project.” Nebraska Law Review
38(3):744.
Evans, Jonathan St. B. T. 1993. “The Cognitive Psychology of Reasoning: An Introduction.”
The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology Section A 46(4):561–67. doi: 10.1080/
14640749308401027.
Evans, Jonathan St. B. T., Julie L. Barston, and Paul Pollard. 1983. “On the Conflict be-
tween Logic and Belief in Syllogistic Reasoning.” Memory & Cognition 11(3):295–306.
doi: 10.3758/BF03196976.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1974. “On the Origins of the Term ‘Ethnomethodology.’” Pp. 15–18 in
Ethnomethodology, edited by R. Turner. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin.
Goldvarg, Yevgeniya, and P. N. Johnson-Laird. 2000. “Illusions in Modal Reasoning.”
Memory & Cognition 28(2):282–94. doi: 10.3758/bf03213806.
Griggs, Richard A., and James R. Cox. 1982. “The Elusive Thematic-Materials Effect in
Wason’s Selection Task.” British Journal of Psychology 73(3):407–20. doi: https://doi.
org/10.1111/j.2044-8295.1982.tb01823.x.
Johnson-Laird, P. N., and P. C. Wason. 1970. “A Theoretical Analysis of Insight into a
Reasoning Task.” Cognitive Psychology 1(2):134–48. doi: 10.1016/0010-0285(70)90009-5.
Manktelow, Ken. 2012. Thinking and Reasoning. London; New York: Psychology Press.
Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman. 1980. “Causal Schemas in Judgments under
Uncertainty.” Pp. 49–72 in Progress in Social Psychology, Vol. 1, edited by M. Fishbein.
Hillsdale, NJ: L. Erlbaum.
Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman. 1982a. “Evidential Impact of Base Rates.” Pp. 153–
60 in Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, edited by D. Kahneman, P.
Slovic, and A. Tversky. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman. 1982b. “Judgments of and by Representativeness.”
Pp. 84–98 in Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, edited by D. Kahneman,
P. Slovic, and A. Tversky. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
15
Technology in Practice
Christian Heath and Paul Luff
Introduction
Technology in Practice 399
The analytic concern with the contingent deployment of rules, and the
ways in which rules gain their sense and significance within the practical
circumstances of social action, is reflected in a substantial corpus of eth-
nomethodological studies of technology. An important strand of this re-
search has addressed the ways in which plans, schedules, and procedures are
embedded within computer-and paper-based systems and explores how
working knowledge and practical reasoning enable the collaborative pro-
duction of organizational activities. Consider for example, studies of call
centers that examine how operators, in their interaction with callers, con-
tingently deploy the data presented by a system to produce organizationally
relevant assessments and accounts (Whalen 1995; Whalen and Vinkhuyzen
2000; Whalen, Whalen, and Henderson 2002; Whalen and Zimmerman
2005), or how production managers schedule and reschedule work flows
and make these changes visible in ways that are sensitive to the contingen-
cies of the organization’s requirements (Bowers, Button, and Sharrock 1995;
Button and Sharrock 1997, 2002). Studies of complex computer-based sys-
tems exposed the resilience of more mundane tools and artifacts, including
paper documents that proved surprisingly resistant to digital transformation.
For example, studies of air traffic control and the paper flight strip (Harper,
Hughes, and Shapiro 1991), of design and the significance of drawings and
sketches (Büscher et al. 1999; Luff, Heath, and Pitsch 2009; Murphy 2004), and
of urban transport networks and the paper timetable (Filippi and Theureau
1993; Heath and Luff 1992) have exposed the complexities that enable the
use of such basic artifacts as documents, diaries, and notepads (Harper 1998;
Harper and Sellen 2000). These studies draw analytic attention to the insti-
tutional character of technology, the ways in which tools and technologies
feature in the collaborative and contingent production of work and the com-
plex forms of knowledge, practice, and reasoning that enable the concerted
accomplishment of social action.
Alongside the burgeoning corpus of workplace studies (see, for example,
Button 1993; Engeström and Middleton 1996; Heath and Button 2002; Luff,
Hindmarsh, and Heath 2000; Rawls 2008; Rouncefield and Tolmie 2011;
Szymanski and Whalen 2011), we have witnessed the emergence of a broad
range of research that addresses phenomena, activities, and domains not typ-
ically associated with studies in ethnomethodology. These initiatives have
been facilitated by close collaboration with computer scientists and engin-
eers, and through developments in digital technology over the last two or three
decades. Consider, for example, ethnomethodological studies of the home and
of the ways in which members of the family rely upon a complex assortment
of tools, technologies, objects, and artifacts to order and organize their eve-
ryday activities (Hughes et al. 2000; Licoppe 2017; Swan, Taylor, and Harper
400 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
2008; Tolmie et al. 2002). We have also seen a growing interest in exploring
how technologies, ranging from mobile devices to highly sophisticated virtual
environments, inform and transform the ways in which people experience and
engage art, science, and performance (Hemmings et al. 2000; Hindmarsh et al.
2005; vom Lehn 2013; vom Lehn, Heath, and Hindmarsh 2001); studies that
expose the practices through which participants, in interaction with others,
encounter and make sense of seemingly unique objects, artifacts, and envir-
onments that encompass both the material and the digital (Licoppe and Morel
2014; Mondada 2014).
This growing interest in the use of novel and in some cases prototype tech-
nologies, installations, and environments poses important methodological
challenges for ethnomethodology with its commitment to the analysis of nat-
urally occurring activities within everyday settings. Drawing inspiration from
Garfinkel’s (1967) well-known breaching experiments, there is a growing interest
in undertaking various forms of naturalistic or quasi-naturalistic experiments
to explore the use of particular tools and technologies (Benford et al. 2006;
Crabtree 2004; Flintham et al. 2003; Fraser et al. 1999; Hindmarsh et al. 2001).
These studies include both laboratory and field experiments. They have made
an important contribution to the design and development of particular systems
and more fundamentally revealed phenomena that hitherto remained unex-
plored, such as the background expectancies, presuppositions, and procedures
on which participants rely in rendering intelligible the unfamiliar, the unusual,
and in some cases, seemingly bizarre. These studies powerfully demonstrate how
the naturalistic experiment can indeed serve as an “aid to sluggish imagination”
(Garfinkel 1967:38) for the analysis of practical action.
More generally, studies of technology reveal a methodological diversity
that is less evident in other fields of ethnomethodological research but is re-
flected in the substantial corpus of studies within CSCW and HCI that draw
on the analytic commitments found within ethnomethodology. This meth-
odological diversity in studies of technology is perhaps most clearly exem-
plified in studies of command and control centers—settings that Suchman
(1997) aptly characterised as “centres of coordination.” Alongside a number
of important ethnomethodologically-informed ethnographic studies (e.g.,
Harper et al. 1991; Hughes et al. 1988), we have witnessed the emergence of
a growing corpus of video-based field studies that address the ways in which
tools and technologies, ranging from simple artifacts to complex multimedia
systems, feature in command and control; research that is inspired by conver-
sation analysis (Goodwin and Goodwin 1996; Heath and Luff 1996; Suchman
1996). These studies have addressed analytic concerns that remained rel-
atively unexplored within research on language use and interaction, in par-
ticular the highly contingent forms of co- participation that arise in the
Technology in Practice 401
One of the more pervasive technologies within command and control is closed
circuit television, or CCTV as it is commonly known. CCTV provides an impor-
tant resource for the real-time surveillance of human behavior and is widely used
in such areas as security operations, policing, traffic management, and manu-
facturing. The widespread deployment of CCTV within public areas, including
malls, city streets, football stadia, railway stations, and the like have led to a cor-
responding rise in a particular form of workplace, namely the operations or con-
trol center; a setting in which personnel use CCTV and related information and
communication systems to detect and manage problems that can be a threat to
public safety and security.
CCTV and surveillance provide the opportunity to explore an issue that has
been of long-standing interest to the social sciences yet has proved analyti-
cally challenging, namely behavior in public places (see, for example, Goffman
1963; Joseph 1998; Lee and Watson 1993; vom Lehn 2013). Garfinkel’s dis-
cussion of perspicuous settings provides a distinctive approach to addressing
such matters:
To find a perspicuous setting the EM policy provides that the analyst looks to
find, as of the haecceities of some local gang’s work affairs, the organizational
thing that they are up against and that they can be brought to teach the ana-
lyst what he needs to learn and to know from them, with which, by learning
from them, to teach them what their affairs consist of as locally produced, lo-
cally occasioned, and locally ordered, locally described, locally questionable,
counted, recorded, observed, etc., phenomena of order, in and as of their in
402 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
vivo accountably doable coherent and cogent detail for each another next first
time. (Garfinkel 2002:182)
of the station routinely suffers a range of incidents and disruptions. These in-
clude, for example, overcrowding, accidents, thefts, robberies, fights, unruly
passengers, security threats (suspect packages and the like), and people falling
onto the track, known euphemistically in London Underground as “one
unders.”
The widespread deployment of CCTV and the corresponding development
of surveillance centers have led to a growing recognition that the “human
operator” may become overwhelmed by information and unable to reliably
monitor all available data. It is suggested that “cognitive overload” can become
a pervasive problem and that it could undermine the ability of personnel to
detect and manage potentially significant incidents and events. In this re-
gard there has been a long-standing interest in developing information sys-
tems (image recognition systems) that analyze real-time data from CCTV
cameras and automatically identify particular incidents and events. The
materials discussed in this chapter were gathered as part of a pan-European
project called PRISMATICA primarily concerned with developing systems
that could be deployed within the operation centers of rapid urban trans-
port networks to assist operators in discovering and identifying incidents and
events (Velastin et al. 2002). For reasons that will become clear, the design
and deployment of the systems posed significant challenges for both the de-
velopment teams and senior management of the various European transport
operators.
404 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Like other rapid urban transport networks, overcrowding during the weekday
rush hours is a pervasive feature of many stations on London Underground.
Overcrowding undermines the free flow of traffic through the station, it causes
discomfort and irritation to passengers, and poses dangers—people tripping on
escalators and staircases and more severely, falling from the platform onto the
track due to the pressure of crowds. There has been a long-standing interest in
developing “intelligent” systems that automatically detect overcrowding and fa-
cilitate intervention by staff. The automatic detection of overcrowding was one
of the principal issues addressed by PRISMATICA (Velastin et al. 1993; Velastin
and Remagnino 2006). Despite substantial research and development, the de-
ployment of a system that can reliably identify overcrowding has met with little
success.
It is worthwhile considering the following fragment (Fragment 1, Figure 15.2),
drawn from the rush hour at Victoria Station in central London. The supervisor
is looking through the window at passengers passing through the entrance foyer.
He glances down at a monitor that displays the northbound Victoria Line plat-
form and immediately delivers the following announcement(s).
406 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
of the station and the routine patterns of navigation and traffic flow it affords.
To resolve particular problems, supervisors issue a series of instructions that
reconfigure the conduct and interaction of staff and passengers. Through these
instructions, they deploy an organizational arrangement that serves to trans-
form, in an orderly patterned manner, the progress of passengers and thereby
resolve potential overcrowding in the station.
Considering Fragment 1, the announcement involves distinct, but interre-
lated actions, designed to engender particular activities from different categories
of participants. “Station control way in please <station control vic way in please”
(lines 1–2) is for the three station assistants, to have them temporarily hold
passengers at the barriers; “Ladies and gentlemen we are asking you please to
remain behind the barriers” (lines 4–5) is addressed to passengers to have them
wait and queue in an orderly manner, until staff give the all clear. It provides those
entering the foyer with the resources with which to make sense, to recognize, the
actions of the station assistants and to produce sequentially relevant conduct—to
wait and form an orderly queue at the barriers. It also provides passengers with
ways of seeing the conduct of fellow passengers and the resources with which to
coordinate their actions with others, to create an arrangement that will enable
an orderly process through the barriers once the ‘all clear’ is received. The an-
nouncement creates and deploys an interactional and sequential organization
through which staff and passengers are able to make sense of each other’s con-
duct and coordinate their actions with each other.
The organization that the supervisor seeks to deploy provides the resources
with which to determine whether passengers are producing the sequentially
appropriate conduct, that is, responding to the announcement and the actions
of the station assistants. Watching the action in the foyer for a few moments,
the supervisor repeats the request, or transforms the request into an instruc-
tion: “Remain behind the barriers: please. Remain behind the barriers”
(lines 6–7). The instruction is addressed to a number of passengers who are
attempting to force their way past the station assistants and, more generally, to
those now entering the foyer who may not have heard the original announce-
ment. Within a short time queues form the length of the foyer; an order is es-
tablished that temporarily transforms the routine pattern of traffic within the
station, enabling crowds to be removed from platforms so that passengers can
be released at the barriers.
The selection and inspection of CCTV images provides the resources both
to identify particular problems and to deploy an organization that serves to re-
solve those difficulties. It enables staff to determine how particular passengers
respond to requests and instructions, and to assess the actions of those on the
ground, responsible for the implementation of particular courses of action.
Take, for instance, the discovery of a suspect package and station evacuation,
Technology in Practice 409
an incident that it is all too familiar during times of heightened terrorist threat.
An evacuation is typically foreshadowed by the issue of a coded instruction for
staff (“Inspector Sands to the Operations Room” or equivalent), followed by suc-
cessive public announcements. The announcements, for example, “Attention
please: all passengers on the station: (.) this station is being evacuated because
of a security alert,” serve to transform the ways in which passengers see and
make sense of the conduct of fellow passengers, of staff, of gatherings, patterns of
movement, and so forth. They provide the resources to enable the supervisor to
determine whether people are acting in accord with the instruction. Successive
announcements serve to deploy an organization, or reorganization of con-
duct, and to implement remedial action, if the sequentially relevant activities
do not arise. Indeed, successive announcements are routinely issued to address
recalcitrant passengers in particular areas who are failing to produce the rele-
vant courses of action. It is not unusual for particular announcements to have
a double-edged sequential implicativeness, on the one hand to have passengers
leave the station with dispatch, on the other to instruct staff to deal with certain
recalcitrant groups who are reluctant to leave. In turn, in selecting a series of
CCTV images, the supervisor can determine whether passengers, and for that
matter, staff, are undertaking the courses of action rendered sequentially rele-
vant through successive announcements.
The operation of rapid urban transport networks relies upon the “well-behaved”
passenger. For station staff and fellow passengers, the orderly and organized pro-
cess of passengers through the station is dependent upon people who are familiar
with the structure and layout of the station, the ways in which particular equip-
ment operates, and the appropriate pathways and the patterns of navigation
that enable smooth access to foyers, platforms, trains, and exits. It relies upon
passengers who are aware of the routine problems and difficulties that arise, such
as overcrowding, delays, even evacuations—passengers who will produce the
circumstantially relevant forms of conduct that enable a reasonable service to be
maintained. For all practical purposes, the well-behaved passenger passes un-
noticed and is unnoticeable, a familiar object within a known ecology, who (re)
produces organizationally relevant courses of action in concert and coordination
with others—namely, like-minded passengers.
The familiar and the routine, “normal appearances” to coin Sacks’s (1972)
phrase, provide supervisors with ways to watch and scrutinize CCTV images, to
notice the less familiar and the untoward. Seemingly insignificant differences in
an individual’s conduct, ways of walking, looking, dressing, standing, carrying
410 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
objects, gathering together, and many other things besides, are noticed by virtue
of the ways in which they stand in contrast to the familiar and the routine, the
conduct of well-behaved passengers. Consider, for example, individuals who
walk “unsteadily” along the platform who might be “the worse for wear,” those
that carry musical instruments and other equipment who may be planning to
busk, those who repeatedly fail to catch the train and may intend to jump in front
of a train. Indeed, the most delicate features of conduct and appearance, unno-
ticeable to the untrained eye, are noticed and recognized as organizationally rel-
evant. Take, for instance, pickpockets. In a station such as Oxford Circus, the
supervisor selects CCTV views of the upward escalators during peak shopping
times, and scrutinizes the behavior of passengers to determine whether some
are looking toward peoples’ rear pockets or bags rather than, more commonly,
the advertisements on the wall or the back of the person in front. In detecting
one or two suspects the supervisor will produce a series of announcements, such
as, “Passengers should be aware that pickpockets are operating on this station.”
These announcements are as much concerned with warning pickpockets they
have been spotted as they are with having passengers take more care of their
belongings.
Many problems and difficulties are noticed therefore by virtue of how they
stand in contrast to the normal and the routine, and the ways in which they ex-
hibit typical and familiar characteristics—characteristics that provide schemes
of interpretation that enable the recognition and determination of particular
forms of conduct and appearance.
Consider the following fragment. Three youths enter the ticket hall together and
move toward the perimeter of the hall. They then separate and walk toward the
ticket barriers, each young man heading toward a different gate. As they each near
a gate, they momentarily stall to enable a passenger to enter the ticket barrier. They
then slip close behind and pass through the barriers without using a ticket or card.
Supervisors notice such conduct by virtue of how it stands in contrast to the
ways in which passengers ordinarily navigate the ticket hall and the activities
Figure 15.3 three ‘doublers ‘walking across foyer from right to left, then each
passing through the gates without a ticket.
Technology in Practice 411
in which they engage. Rather than immediately walk across the hall toward
the ticket barrier or the ticket machines, the young men move to the perimeter
while watching other passengers approaching the barriers. The conduct of the
youths is noticeable and recognizable, even prior to performing the illegal act,
both by virtue of the how their conduct stands in contrast to the well-behaved
passenger, and with regard to the ways in which it exhibits the character-
istic behavior of a particular category of persons, namely “doublers”—people
who avoid payment by passing through gates close behind an unwitting
accomplice.
Noticing problems and difficulties, potential threats to the routine oper-
ation of the station, is dependent upon the supervisor’s working knowledge
of the local environment and the ways in which particular scenes and locales
occasion and expose routine forms and patterns of conduct. Familiarity with the
local environment and its routine operation at certain times of the day and week
provides the supervisor with the ability to select and scrutinize CCTV images,
to notice and identify problems and difficulties. It also enables the supervisor
and colleagues to discover problems and difficulties that arise within the station
but beyond the scope of the camera and CCTV system; locales, corners, and
spaces within the station that are known colloquially as “off the world.”
Staff know that those who exploit passengers for nefarious purposes, to beg, steal,
sell drugs, and the like, are aware of the presence of cameras and surveillance of the
station. They go to some trouble to undertake their activities beyond the scope of the
system. In turn, supervisors are sensitive to the limitations of the field of view afforded
by the cameras, and their working knowledge of the station and the incidents that can
arise provide ways of scrutinizing CCTV images to detect problems and difficulties.
A principal resource in detecting problems that arise “off the world” is the conduct
and interaction of those that can be seen—the well-behaved passengers.
Consider the images in Figures 15.4, drawn from the CCTV of one of the
principal passageways at Leicester Square; they show passengers walking down
one of the passsageways.
The supervisor notices the scene by virtue of the ways in which passengers
are navigating the passageway. As they walk toward the camera, they mo-
mentarily glance to their right, and one or two passengers extend their hand
to seemingly pass what appears to be small change to someone out of view.
A moment later the supervisor calls a station assistant to remove a beggar from
the passageway. The inaccessible obstacle, beyond the scope of the camera, is
noticed and rendered intelligible by virtue of the conduct of those who can be
seen. The supervisor’s familiarity with the characteristic navigation patterns
that arise within particular locales, coupled with an understanding of the type
of incident that commonly arises within certain areas of the station, provides
the resources with which to detect the incident and deploy an organizationally
relevant solution.
Familiarity with the station and the routine patterns of conduct and in-
cident that arise within particular regions, coupled with an understanding
of the characteristic features of particular actions, events, and incidents,
provides the resources through which an occasioned combination of CCTV
images can be selected and surveyed. A familiar and routine world, in-
cluding patterns of conduct and navigation, provides ways of looking at and
remaining sensitive to the images displayed on the screen and the world
beyond. Many of the incidents and events discovered through CCTV are
recognized unambiguously, an image or combination of images enabling
supervisors at a glance to identify a particular problem and to deploy an or-
ganizationally appropriate course of action. Other difficulties serve to pro-
voke an “investigation,” the search for an account, where a moment’s noticing
is often considered with regard to the prospective and retrospective course
of a (possible) action or activity; the sense and significance of the incident
or event is assembled with regard to what happens next and what might have
happened a moment before. So, for example, seeing smoke in the foyer can
have the supervisor following the smoke’s trail to find teenagers having a sur-
reptitious cigarette or joint; finding a break or gap in people leaving an es-
calator can enable the supervisor to discover that a passenger has collapsed
in the stairwell below; or noticing a number of waiting passengers looking
toward the entrance of a platform can lead the supervisor to discover that
a brawl has broken out in a passageway. Supervisors discover incidents by
virtue of noticing that passengers themselves have noticed “something”
within their immediate environment; indeed noticing noticings is a critical
resource through which supervisors discover and manage incidents that
arise both within and “off the world.”
Technology in Practice 413
References
Anderson, R. J. 1994. “Representation and Requirements: The Value of Ethnography
in System Design.” Human-Computer Interaction 9(2):151– 82. Doi: 10.1207/
s15327051hci0902_1.
Benford, Steve, Andy Crabtree, Martin Flintham, Adam Drozd, Rob Anastasi, and Mark
Paxton. 2006. “Can You See Me Now?” ACM Transactions on Computer-Human
Interaction 13(1):100–33. Doi: 10.1145/1143518.1143522.
Blomberg, Jeanette L., and Helena, Karasti. 2013. “Reflections on 25 Years of Ethnography in
CSCW. Computer Supported Cooperative Work (CSCW).” The Journal of Collaborative
Computing and Work Practices 22(4–6):373–423. Doi: 10.1007/s10606-012-9183-1.
Bowers, John, Graham Button, and Wes Sharrock. 1995. “Workflow from Within and
Without: Technology and Cooperative Work on the Print Industry Shopfloor.” Pp.
51–66 in Proceedings of the Fourth Conference on European Conference on Computer-
Supported Cooperative Work, ECSCW ’95, Stockholm Sweden, edited by Y. Sundblad, H.
Marmoli and K. Schmidt. Amsterdam: Kluwer Academic. Publishers.
Broth, Matias, Eric Laurier, and Lorenza Mondada. 2014. Studies of Video Practices: Video
at Work. London: Routledge.
Büscher, Monika, Preben Mogensen, Dan Shapiro, and Ina Wagner. 1999. “The
Manufaktur: Supporting Work Practice in (Landscape) Architecture.” Pp. 21–40 in
ECSCW ’99: Proceedings of the Sixth European Conference on Computer Supported
Cooperative Work 12–16 September 1999, Copenhagen, Denmark, edited by S. Bødker,
M. Kyng, and K. Schmidt. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands.
Button, Graham, ed. 1993. Technology in Working Order: Studies in Work, Interaction and
Technology. London: Routledge.
Button, Graham, and Wes Sharrock. 1997. “The Production of Order and the Order of
Production: Possibilities for Distributed Organisations, Work and Technology in the
Print Industry.” Pp. 1–16 in Proceedings of the Fifth European Conference on Computer
Supported Cooperative Work, edited by J. A. Hughes, W. Prinz, T. Rodden, and K.
Schmidt. Dordrecht: Springer.
Button, Graham, and Wes W. Sharrock. 2002. “Operating the Production Calculus:
Ordering a Production System in the Print Industry.” British Journal of Sociology
53(2):275–90. Doi: 10.1080/00071310220133340.
Crabtree, Andy. 2003. Designing Collaborative Systems: A Practical Guide to Ethnography.
London: Springer.
Crabtree, Andy 2004. “Design in the Absence of Practice: Breaching Experiments.”
Pp. 59–68 in 5th Conference on Designing Interactive Systems: Processes, Practices,
Methods, and Techniques (DIS2004), edited by J. A. Hughes, W. Prinz, T. Rodden, and
K. Schmidt. Cambridge, MA. New York: ACM Press. Doi: 10.1145/1013115.1013125.
Dourish, Paul 2006. “Implications for Design.” Pp. 541–50 in Proceedings of the 2006 ACM
conference on Computer-Human Interaction (CHI 2006), edited by G. Olson and R.
Jeffries, Montreal, Quebec, New York: ACM Press. Doi: 10.1145/1124772.1124855.
Engeström, Yrjo, and David, Middleton, eds. 1996. Cognition and Communication at
Work. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Filippi, Geneviève, and Jacques Theureau. 1993. “Analyzing Cooperative Work in an
Urban Traffic Control Room for the Design of a Coordination Support System.” Pp.
171–86 in Proceedings of the Third European Conference on Computer-Supported
416 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Cooperative Work, 13–17 September 1993, Milan, Italy, ECSCW ’93, edited by G. de
Michelis, C. Simone, and K. Schmidt. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands.
Flintham, Martin, Rob Anastasi, Steve, Benford, Terry, Hemmings, Andy Crabtree,
Chris Greenhalgh, and Tom, Rodden. 2003. “Where On- Line Meets on- the-
Streets: Experiences with Mobile Mixed Reality Games.” Pp. 569–76 in CHI Conference
on Human Factors in Computing Systems, edited by G. Cockton and P. Korohen,
New York: ACM Press, Doi: 10.1145/642611.642710.
Fraser, Mike, Steve Benford, Jon Hindmarsh, and Christian Heath. 1999. “Supporting
Awareness and Interaction through Collaborative Virtual Interfaces.” Pp. 27– 36
in Proceedings of the 12th Annual ACM Symposium on User Interface Software and
Technology, edited by B. V. Zanden and J. Marks, New York: ACM Press. Doi: 10.1145/
320719.322580.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1967. Studies in Ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1988. “Evidence for Locally Produced, Naturally Accountable Phenomena
of Order, Logic, Reason, Meaning, Method, Etc. in and as of the Essential Quiddity
of Immortal Ordinary Society, (I of IV): An Announcement of Studies.” Sociological
Theory 6(1):103–9. Doi: 10.2307/201918.
Garfinkel, Harold. 2002. Ethnomethodology’s Program: Working Out Durkeim’s Aphorism.
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Goffman, Erving. 1963. Behavior in Public Places: Notes on the Social Organization of
Gathering. New York: Free Press.
Goodwin, Charles. 1994. “Professional Vision.” American Anthropologist 96(3):606–33.
doi: 10.1525/aa.1994.96.3.02a00100.
Goodwin, Charles, and Marjorie Harness Goodwin. 1996. “Seeing as Situated
Activity: Formulating Planes.” Pp. 61–95 in Cognition and Communication at Work, ed-
ited by Y. Engeström and D. Middleton. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Harper, Richard. 1998. Inside the IMF: An Ethnography of Documents, Technology and
Organisational Action. London: Academic Press.
Harper, Richard, John Hughes, and Dan Z. Shapiro. 1991. “Working in Harmony: An
Examination of Computer Technology and Air Traffic Control.” Pp. 225–34 in Studies
in Computer Supported Cooperative Work: Theory, Practice and Design, edited by J.
Bowers and S. D. Benford. Amsterdam: North-Holland.
Heath, Christian, and Graham Button. 2002. “Editorial Introduction: The Emergence of
a Growing Corpus of Sociological Studies with Work, Technology, and Interaction in
Organizational Environments.” British Journal of Sociology 53(2):157–61. doi: 10.1080/
00071310220133278.
Heath, Christian, and Paul Luff. 1992. “Collaboration and Control: Crisis Management
and Multimedia Technology in London Underground Line Control Rooms.” CSCW
Journal 1(1–2):69–94.
Heath, Christian, and Paul Luff. 1996. “Convergent Activities: Line Control and Passenger
Information on London Underground.” Pp. 96–129 in Cognition and Communication at
Work, edited by Y. Engeström and D. Middleton. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hemmings, Terry, David Randall, Liz Marr, and David Francis. 2000. “Talk, Task and
Closure: Situated Learning and Working with an ‘Interactive’ Museum Artefact.” Pp.
223–44 in Local Educational Order: Ethnomethodological Studies of Knowledge in Action,
edited by S. Hester and D. Francis. Amsterdam; Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Hindmarsh, Jon, Mike Fraser, Christian Heath, and Steve Benford. 2001. “Virtually
Missing the Point: Configuring CVEs for Object-Focused Interaction.” Pp. 115–39 in
Technology in Practice 417
Collaborative Virtual Environments: Digital Places and Spaces for Interaction, edited by
E. F. Churchill, D. N. Snowdon, and A. J. Munro. London: Springer.
Hindmarsh, Jon, and Christian Heath. 1998. “Video and the Analysis of Objects in
Interaction.” Journal of Communication and Cognition 31(2–3):111–30.
Hindmarsh, Jon, Christian Heath, Dirk vom Lehn, and Jason Cleverly. 2005. “Creating
Assemblies in Public Environments: Social Interaction, Interactive Exhibits and
CSCW.” Computer Supported Cooperative Work: The Journal of Collaborative Computing
14(1):1–41. doi: 10.1007/s10606-004-1814-8.
Hughes, John, Val King, Tom Rodden, and Hans Andersen. 1995. “The Role of Ethnography
in Interactive Systems Design.” Interactions 2(2):56–65. doi: 10.1145/205350.205358.
Hughes, John, Jon O’Brien, Tom Rodden, Mark Rouncefield, and Stephen Viller. 2000.
“Patterns of Home Life: Informing Design for Domestic Environments.” Personal and
Ubiquitous Computing 4(1):25–38.
Hughes, John, Dan Z. Shapiro, Wes W. Sharrock, Richard A. Anderson, Richard Harper,
and Stephen C. Gibbons. 1988. The Automation of Air Traffic Control: Department of
Sociology. Final Report, SERC/ESRC Grant No. GR/D/86157, Lancaster University.
Joseph, Isaac. 1998. La Ville sans qualities. Paris: L’Aude.
Lee, J. R. E., and Rod D. Watson. 1993. Social Interaction in Urban Space: Final Report.
Paris: Plan Urbain.
Licoppe, Christian, and Julien Morel. 2014. “Mundane Video Directors in Interaction:
Showing One’s Environment in Skype and Mobile Video Calls.” Pp. 135–60 in Studies
of Video Practices: Video at Work, edited by M. Broth, E. Laurier, and L. Mondada.
Abingdon, UK: Routledge.
Licoppe, Christian. 2017. “Showing Objects in Skype Video-Mediated Conversations:
From Showing Gestures to Showing Sequences.” Journal of Pragmatics 110(1):63–82.
doi: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pragma.2017.01.007.
Luff, Paul, Christian Heath, and Karola Pitsch. 2009. “Indefinite Precision: The Use
of Artefacts-in-Interaction in Design Work.” Pp. 213–22 in Routledge Handbook of
Multimodal Analysis, edited by C. Jewitt. London: Routledge.
Luff, Paul, John Hindmarsh, and Christian Heath, eds. 2000. Workplace Studies:
Recovering Work Practice and Informing System Design. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Mondada, Lorenza 2014. “Bodies in Action: Multimodal Analysis of Walking and
Talking.” Language and Dialogue 4(3):357–403. doi: 10.1075/ld.4.3.02mon.
Murphy, Keith M. 2004. “Imagination as Joint Activity: The Case of Architectural
Interaction.” Mind, Culture & Activity 11(4):267–78. doi: 10/cztnmj.
Plowman, Lydia, Yvonne Rogers, and Magnus Ramage. 1995. What Are Workplace Studies
For? Pp. 309–24 in Proceedings of the Fourth Conference on European Conference on
Computer-Supported Cooperative Work, ECSCW ’95, Stockholm Sweden, edited by Y.
Sundblad, H. Marmoli and K. Schmidt. Amsterdam: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Stockholm, Sweden.
Randall, David, Richard Harper, and Mark Rouncefield. 2007. Fieldwork for Design: Theory
and Practice. London: Springer.
Rawls, Anne Warfield. 2008. “Harold Garfinkel, Ethnomethodology and Workplace
Studies.” Organization Studies 29(5):701–32. Doi: 10.1177/0170840608088768.
Rouncefield, M., and P. Tolmie, eds. 2011. Ethnomethodology at Work. Farnham,
UK: Ashgate.
418 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Sacks, Harvey. 1972. “Notes on Police Assessment of Moral Character.” Pp. 280–93 in
Studies in Social Interaction, edited by D. N. Sudnow. New York: Free Press.
Sacks, Harvey. 1992. Lectures on Conversation. Vol. 2, edited by G. Jefferson. Oxford;
Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.
Sellen, Abigail J., and Richard H. R. Harper. 2003. The Myth of the Paperless Office.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Suchman, Lucy A. 1987. Plans and Situated Actions: The Problem of Human Machine
Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Suchman, Lucy. 1996. “Constituting Shared Workspaces.” Pp. 35–60 in Cognition and
Communication at Work, edited by Y. Engeström and D. Middleton. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Suchman, Lucy. 1997. “Centers of Coordination: A Case and Some Themes.” Pp. 41–62 in
Discourse, Tools, and Reasoning: Essays on Situated Cognition, edited by L. B. Resnick,
R. Säljö, C. Pontecorvo, and B. Burge. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
Suchman, Lucy. 2007. Human-Machine Reconfigurations: Plans and Situated Actions.
2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Swan, Laurel, Alex S. Taylor, and Richard Harper. 2008. “Making Place for Clutter and
Other Ideas of Home.” ACM Transactions on Computer-Human Interaction 15(2):9.
Doi: 10.1145/1375761.1375764.
Szymanski, Margaret H., and Jack Whalen, eds. 2011. Making Work Visible: Ethnographically
Grounded Case Studies of Work Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tolmie, Peter, James Pycock, Tim Diggins, Allan MacLean, and Alain Karsenty. 2002.
“Unremarkable Computing.” Pp. 399–406 in Proceedings of the SIGCHI Conference
on Human Factors in Computing Systems edited by L. Terveen and D. Wixon.
New York: ACM.
Velastin, Sergio A., Maria. A. Vincencio-Silva, Benny Lo, Jie Sun, and Louhadi A. Khoudor.
2002. “Distributed Surveillance System for Improving Security in Public Transport
Networks.” Measurement and Control 35(8):209–13. doi: 10.1177/002029400203500704.
Velastin, Sergio A., J. H. Yin, Maria A. Vincencio-Silva, Anthony C. Davies, Richard E.
Allsop, and Alan Penn. 1993. “Analysis of Crowd Movements and Densities in Built-
up Environments Using Image Processing.” Pp. 8/1:86 in IEE Colloquium on Image
Processing for Transport Applications. London: Institute of Electrical Engineers.
Velastin, Sergio A., and Paolo Remagnino, eds. 2006. Intelligent Distributed Video
Surveillance Systems. London: The Institution of Institution of Electrical Engineers.
vom Lehn, Dirk. 2013. “Withdrawing from Exhibits: The Interactional Organisation
of Museum Visits.” Pp. 65–90 in Interaction and Mobility: Language and the Body in
Motion, edited by P. Haddington, L. Mondada, and M. Nevile. Berlin: De Gruyter.
vom Lehn, Dirk, Christian Heath, and Jon Hindmarsh. 2001. “Exhibiting Interaction:
Conduct and Collaboration in Museums and Galleries.” Symbolic Interaction
24(2):189–216. doi: 10.1525/si.2001.24.2.189.
Whalen, Jack. 1995. “A Technology of Order Production: Computer-Aided Dispatch in
Public Safety Communications.” Pp. 187–230 in Situated Order: Studies in the Social
Organisation of Talk and Embodied Activities, edited by Paul ten Have and George
Psathas. Washington, DC: University Press of America.
Whalen, Jack, and Don Zimmerman. 2005. “Working a Call: Multiparty Management and
Interactional Infastructure in Calls for Help.” Pp. 309–45 in Calling for Help: Language
and Social Interaction in Telephone Helplines, edited by Carolyn Baker, M. Emmison,
and Alan Firth. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Technology in Practice 419
Whalen, Jack, and Eric Vinkhuyzen. 2000. “Expert Systems in (Inter)Action: Diagnosing
Document Machine Problems over the Telephone.” Pp. 92– 140 in Workplace
Studies: Recovering Work Practice and Informing Systems Design, edited by J. H. Paul
Luff and C. Heath. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Whalen, Jack, Marilyn R. Whalen, and Kathryn Henderson. 2002. “Improvisational
Choreography in Teleservice Work.” British Journal of Sociology 53(2):239–58.
doi: 10.1080/00071310220133322.
16
Occam’s Razor and the Challenges of
Generalization in Ethnomethodology
Iddo Tavory
Sociologists, like other scientists, have often been quick to espouse a simplified
version of “Occam’s razor”: the notion that the more parsimonious an explana-
tion, the better it probably is. Compared to this aesthetic, the ethnomethodolog-
ical sensibility provides a stark contrast: rather than simplifying and providing
a picture that is stripped from many of its specifics, the ethnomethodologist re-
mains with the precise and locally produced ways in which actors continuously
co-construct a working order. Rather than a neat razor-like “cut” into social life,
ethnomethodology exposes social life as messy and over-abundant; rather than
simplifying the world, it gains its power from remaining with the world’s com-
plexities and its ongoing emergence.
Beginning from this point of departure, the chapter makes two contributions.
First, as Garfinkel noted, a consistent application of ethnomethodology rejects
all forms of sociological generalization. This kind of consistency, however,
precludes any simple inclusion of ethnomethodology into the sociological canon.
As Garfinkel and Wieder (1992) wrote, ethnomethodology must remain an “al-
ternate technology.” To the extent that generalization is a part of the ethnometh-
odological tradition, it is in the ways it investigates actors’ own generalizations in
producing “ordinary, immortal society.” As I then argue, different ethnomethod-
ological programs such as conversation analysis (CA), institutional conversation
analysis, and ethnomethodology-inspired ethnography attempted to square this
circle—remaining close to ethnomethodology’s insights, while moving toward
a more generalizable account. Conversation analysis does so by suspending the
grounds for generalization while de facto claiming extremely wide generaliz-
ability (cf. Mondada, Chapter 11 in this volume); institutional CA does so by
focusing on recurring “institutional fingerprints” that mesh CA patterns with
institutionally specific structures (Drew and Heritage 1992) and local prag-
matics, and ethnomethodology-inspired ethnography does so by either focusing
on institutions, or generalizing what I call a space of legibility in analyzing their
observations.
GENERALIZATION IN ETHNOMETHODOLOGY 421
I conclude the piece by returning to Occam’s razor. I point out that the
common way of conceiving this principle—as a rule of parsimony—is a bastard-
ization of the original intent of the metaphor. Occam’s razor, sometimes called
“the nominalists’ razor,” was an attack against realist positions that claimed that
universals (which include generalizations) have an equal ontological status to
that of actual, specific, cases. Against this position, Occam’s razor was an admon-
ishment to keep the ontological playing field simple, and avoid “multiplying enti-
ties”: to only assume that actual, specific cases exist, and to treat generalizations
as constructions that have no real existence of their own. Seen in this light, eth-
nomethodology is in fact an extremely “simple” argument. Even if the descrip-
tion of any actual interaction becomes exceedingly complex, it makes fewer
assumptions about social life. As against positions that see social structures
as over “there” and beyond their specific emergence in action and interac-
tion, and against positions that see “culture” as relatively autonomous from its
instantiations, ethnomethodology describes a world in which only one “entity”
exists—people constantly creating their world and imbuing it with orderliness.
Theoretical Considerations
In a series of papers, Garfinkel (1988, 2002; Garfinkel and Wieder 1992) argued
that ethnomethodology and professional sociology were “incommensurable,
asymmetrically alternate technologies of social analysis.” In one of the most co-
gent exegeses of his position—a reaction to Jeffrey Alexander’s attempt to incor-
porate ethnomethodology into his micro-macro program—Garfinkel (1988)
stressed that ethnomethodology is concerned with what he calls Parsons’s
“plenum,” the everyday “haecceities” of action and interaction. That is, ethno-
methodology is committed to explain the “just-thisness” of action. In his expli-
cation, Garfinkel mentions eight reasons for the incommensurability between
the professional sociology program and ethnomethodology; reasons why, as he
maintains elsewhere (Garfinkel and Wieder 1992:180), “their reconciliation is
pointless.” Although not all the differences Garfinkel lists are relevant here, two
of them are of particular interest:
These, in fact, are not really two reasons; this is a general statement and its prac-
tical specification. To re-cast his argument, the tension between ethnomethod-
ology and professional sociology is that of the tension between generalization
and reduction, as against the minute description of the local construction of
“immortal-ordinary-society.” For generalization, ipso facto, is an attempt to
shave off aspects of the ongoing local construction of the social world. It doesn’t
lose information by accident, but by design. Reduction lies at the heart of gen-
eralization: giving up on some data and simplifying a detail-filled social world
so that different cases can be described in terms of properties that transcend the
particular instance. The local specificity of every case as-such must be reduced.
It is this incommensurability that can be thought of in terms of the popu-
larized notion of Occam’s razor, understood as “a criterion for privileging one
theory over another. When two different theoretical interpretations seem equally
successful in accounting for variation or change, the preferable explanation is the
one that is the most simple” (Powers 2010:70). In other words, the assumption is
that the simpler explanation is usually the right one.
And, in any collection of cases, it seems simpler to generalize. The act of gen-
eralization eliminates aspects of the situation that make particular situations
precisely what they are, with all their specific histories, their exigencies and idi-
osyncrasies. Thus, even complex generalizations are far simpler than an attempt
to trace the ongoing production of the social world’s orderliness (Garfinkel 1967,
2002) as it is constructed anew in each case, in the contextuality of people’s ori-
entation, and to assume that this work is precarious and ongoing. Indeed, when
newcomers are introduced to ethnomethodology, one of the striking points of
both attraction and aversion is how complicated the everyday world becomes.
To take one example, Pollner’s (1987) “mundane reason” is one of the most
compelling examples of this ethnomethodological transformation of the world.
Pollner’s core argument is that the assumption that we inhabit a common world
needs to be constructed and reconstructed in action and interaction. Rather
than a given, that sense of a common world is an ongoing achievement produced
by way of its “ethnomethods,” or situated members’ practices. Looking at traffic
courts as a particularly illustrative setting—where actors’ practical challenges
force them to make explicit what is implicit in other situations—Pollner shows
how the co-inhabiting of reality is done and re-done. When parties in court are
arguing about whether the defendant, for example, drove through a red light—
or did not—they may go out of their way to explain how the two versions of re-
ality (“what actually happened” in a case) align. Perhaps the driver couldn’t see
the light because of a tree blocking his view? Or because the sun was in his eyes?
As Pollner shows, beyond the specificities of the case, parties defend a much
more basic assumption—that there is one true reality that they both inhabit;
that the two versions of reality they submit to court are commensurable. Like
GENERALIZATION IN ETHNOMETHODOLOGY 423
This also means that the incommensurability between the popularized rule of
parsimony and Garfinkel’s program is not a matter of perspectival change. As
such, the distinctions made by ethnomethodology are quite different from other
apparent dichotomies in sociological work: distinctions between “emic” and
“etic” categories, based on the point of view of the “native” as opposed to that
of the sociologist (Pike 1967); between “categories of practice” that actors use
to explain their actions, and “categories of analysis” that are used by researchers
(Brubaker 2013); or, “first person” vs. “third person” points of view, based on
the difference between categories emerging from the actors’ own experience as
opposed to experientially distant explanations that don’t take these experiences
into account (Martin 2011). Although there are subtle differences among these
distinctions, these are all puzzles of perspective. The question within each dis-
tinction is always “whose categories?,” “whose experience?” Categories of prac-
tice, emic categories, and the first-person point of view are all based on the way
in which the people we study perceive or experience the world. On the other side
of this divide, categories of analysis, etic categories, and the third-person point of
view are the picture of the world from the analyst’s position.
The distinction drawn by Garfinkel between “professional sociology” and
the ethnomethodological stance is based upon an altogether different logic.
Although it is closer to emic, first-person sensibilities, ethnomethodology
suggests that theorizing based upon perspective misses its mark. Generalizing
from either the point of view of the researched, or from that of the researcher,
has the same pitfalls. Since actors’ own categories are often glosses on the on-
going work of sustaining and constructing their world, we must treat actors’
generalizations with much the same suspicion as we treat those of the profes-
sional sociologist.
GENERALIZATION IN ETHNOMETHODOLOGY 425
The only way in which generalizations work their way into ethnomethod-
ology, then, is when an investigator analyzes the ways in which actors themselves
see their own action through the lenses of generalization. That is, ethnomethod-
ology, in a by now familiar move, turns resources—such as generalization—into
topics (Zimmerman and Pollner 1970). Rather than generalization being some-
thing of a resource for theorists who work to shave off contingencies of action
from the social patterns they find, ethnomethodologists study how actors con-
struct the generalized meaning of their own actions as these unfold.
Perhaps the best formulation of this ethnomethodological engagement with
generalization is the notion of the social as “immortal-ordinary society” (see
Garfinkel 1996:10; Rawls 1996). Borrowed from Durkheim, although he does
with it something quite different, the notion of society as “immortal” is best sum-
marized by Garfinkel (1996) in the following note:
Seen from this angle, then, to the degree that generalizations are of concern to
ethnomethodology, they are generalizations made by actors, as they go about
living their lives. In the midst of everyday conduct, actors construe their world
as immortal, a world that “preceded them and will be there after they leave.” It is
actors who construct or achieve the ways in which their world transcends their
own situated experience.
The incommensurable approaches to generalization in ordinary social theory
as compared with ethnomethodology raise a practical challenge for the ethno-
methodological program. For, with few exceptions, most ethnomethodology
practitioners are enmeshed in multiple communities of inquiry that incite them
to make broader generalizations. That is, they are pressured by their peers, as by
reviewers of the journals they publish in, to show how their findings do more
than show, for yet another case, that the world is constructed in the making. The
next section addresses this predicament—asking whether is it possible to pro-
duce something like generalization, while being enmeshed in a form of inquiry
that explicitly rejected or avoided traditional approaches to making broad prop-
ositions about how social life works.
426 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
As many have pointed out (e.g., Maynard and Clayman 1991), there are varieties
of “doing ethnomethodology,” as ethnomethodology and ethnomethodology-
inspired disciplines have emerged through the past decades. These, in turn, take
different stances regarding the question of generalization. Earlier, I have pro-
vided what I see as Garfinkel’s position, at least as it is presented in the papers
in which he directly confronted the relation between professional sociology
(or “formal analysis”) and ethnomethodology. There are, however, other ways
to approach the relation between the observable and instructable locally pro-
duced ordering of the world and the challenges of generalization. As these are
important in thinking about how to practically organize ethnomethodology-in-
spired possible research agendas, I point toward three such options—ordinary
talk-
in-
interaction (CA), institutional CA, and ethnomethodology- inspired
ethnography.1
Conversation Analysis
Across all the different kinds of actions which people do through talk, are there
any sorts of general patterns or structures which they use (and which we can
describe) to co-produce and track an orderly stretch of talk or other conduct in
which some course of action gets initiated, worked through, and brought to a
closure? (2007:3, emphasis added)
CA, then, is the search for general patterns of talk-in-interaction, as these emerge
in participants’ own ways for assembling actions.
But how are these generalizations to be defended? In this regard, CA takes an
empirical stance, which can be seen most clearly in CA’s arguments against the-
oretical specifications of the conversational order. Schegloff critiques structural
GENERALIZATION IN ETHNOMETHODOLOGY 427
linguistics (similar to his approach to Parsons, e.g., Schegloff 1991) for assuming
generalized structures, rather than tracing their emergence in interaction. And
yet, it is important to note that this critique is not the same as Garfinkel’s: it is
not the possibility of generalization, but analytic presuppositions positing its
structures that Schegloff (2007) engages. Generalizations need to be empirically
discovered and theoretically open to revision based on ongoing research. Like
any rigorous endeavor, there is an inherent openness to generalization, condi-
tioned on the availability of revision in the event that new data problematizes
previous generalizations.
CA is cagey, however, about the theoretical grounding of such generalization.
In certain places, the architects of CA note that the structures of talk emerge
from the exigencies of communication, and the ongoing attempt to understand
“why that now?” (Sacks and Schegloff 1973), which can be safely assumed to
be a question with which actors are continuously engaged. This pragmatist
assumption of ongoing “problem-solving” as an ever-relevant concern is fur-
ther buttressed by drawing from phenomenological notions that actors are
attempting to construct, sustain, and defend intersubjectivity in interaction
(Heritage 1984; Schegloff 1992).3
However, as much as CA addresses intersubjectivity as an ongoing achieve-
ment, it is quite distant from Garfinkel’s remarks on the relationship between
ethnomethodology and professional sociology. As Schegloff (1991) wrote re-
garding the relationship between generalizations of social structures and CA,
one concern is
. . . the balance between the focus on social structure and the focus on conversa-
tional structure in studying talk-in-interaction. These two thematic focuses (we
would like to think) are potentially complementary. (1991:57)
As Drew and Heritage (1992) and Heritage (2004) put it, the differences be-
tween CA and institutional talk can be organized around the following three
considerations. First, the goal of interaction analyzed in institutional CA is more
narrowly defined. In regular talk-in-interaction, one can assume that intersub-
jectivity, and the pragmatics of “why that now” are ever present locally. In insti-
tutional talk, however, there are other, institutionally organized, goals. One goes
to the doctor and expects to get a diagnosis; one goes to, or participates in, court
proceedings (Atkinson and Drew 1979; Maynard 1984) and expects specific
outcomes. Second, institutions place constraints on what can, and cannot, be
done (a conversation about shopping would usually be out of place in the doctor’s
office). Third, talk will be understood and shaped based on these assumed
goals and constraints (see also Arminen 2005). Importantly, these differences
mean that specific identities and goals are already anticipated in institutional talk
(see also Zimmerman 1998). Rather than simply asking “why that now?” as does
regular talk-in-interaction, the question may be, in effect, “why that now, for the
ongoing construction of these institutional concerns?”
This institutional move does not mean that we return to a scripted notion
of the social. Even the most seemingly scripted of institutional moments is an
ongoing construction, and actors can (and do) weave in and out of their insti-
tutional identities and goals in interaction. Interactions, also, quite often, fail
(see, e.g., Whalen, Zimmerman, and Whalen 1988). Although we can talk about
“institutional fingerprints” (Drew and Heritage 1992; Heritage and Greatbatch
1991), the institution is still being constructed turn-by-turn in interaction. And
yet, institutional CA is based on a doubling of the epistemological grounds. On
the one hand, we look for the ongoing co-construction of the institution in inter-
action; on the other hand, we assume that the primary context of interaction is
that of institutionally defined goals and identities. In the first moment we remain
in the realm of Garfinkel’s ethnomethodology; in the second moment the ana-
lyst steers closer to interactional assumptions regarding the ways in which insti-
tutional contexts, as exhibited procedurally in participants’ talk and embodied
conduct (Schegloff 1987), can shape interaction by requiring or allowing some
actions, foreclosing others, and thereby creating pragmatic constraints (see
Rock 1979).
Methodologically speaking, analysts discern patterns and generalizations
from a collection of cases. The here-and-now and the problems at hand have
unique aspects and auspices, but the interactional resources by which people
make sense and cooperate for institutional ends are considered to be recur-
rent. Situations are reproduced by institutional actors who face similar interac-
tional challenges in specific settings, and as aspects of the interaction become
incorporated into nonhumans that produce their own sets of pressures. Thus,
for example, race emerges as relevant for intelligible action in the case of a 911
430 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
emergency call whether or not the caller mobilized race in their initial descrip-
tion of troubles, as the need to fill standardized forms and protocols shapes the
interaction (Kameo and Whalen 2015).
Although couched in a different methodology and sensibility to the ongoing
production of the situation, however, the mode of generalization here is very
close to certain interactionist versions of “professional sociology,” especially
where institutional CA becomes more pointedly applied. Thus, to take a well-
known example of such applied institutional CA, Heritage et al. (2007) show
how the specific ways in which doctors construct their questions in the medical
interview matter for the responses they receive. As the authors show, using the
word “any” (as in the question “do you have any more problems . . . ?”) will tend
to generate a negative response; using the word “some” tends to generate more
medical concerns. As the interaction is co-constructed in situ, the word “any”
tends to cue the other interactant to sustain the smoothness of the interaction
by replying in the negative and moving toward closing the interview. Thus, when
doctors changed their question construction to ask “do you have some other
concerns . . . ?” patients tend to raise medical matters that they brought to the in-
terview but which the word “any” discourages from articulating.
In terms of generalization, a few things may be noted here. First, the article
not only makes a generalization about the cases it has analyzed, but makes both a
predictive and a prescriptive generalization. If doctors want patients to tell them
of their woes, they should avoid the word “any” since it tends to be no-preferring,
whereas “some” tends to be yes-preferring. In order to assess these tendencies, the
paper uses quantification—including crucially the average number of concerns
raised in relation to question design. Whereas Schegloff had been uncomfortable
with the quantification of talk-in-interaction, Heritage et al. base their analysis
on such quantification (see also Maynard, Freese, and Schaeffer 2010; Schaeffer
et al. 2013; Stivers and Majid 2007).
At least in these applied studies, institutional CA moves farther from the
ethnomethodological position that avoids generalization because of the “just-
thisness” of everyday life, as well as classic CA’s unease with quantification.
The assumptions regarding recurring institutional pragmatics, as these are
superimposed on conversational structures, allow institutional CA to construct
wider generalizations, even as the data and mode of analysis still draw inspira-
tion from ethnomethodology, and its mode of analysis from classical CA.
Ethnomethodology-Inspired Ethnography
on the wider sociological community has often been more elusive. And whereas
there are different reasons for this relative lack of engagement (e.g., simple igno-
rance, ethnomethodology’s sharp rhetorical self-positioning, as well as the opacity
of Garfinkel’s writing), one key reason may be ethnomethodology’s rejection of gen-
eralization on behalf of capturing the “just-thisness” of episodes in everyday life. In
a discipline that has moved toward increasingly sophisticated statistical techniques
and aspirations, qualitative researchers often feel the need to prove their worth by
producing both empirical and theoretical generalizations (see, e.g., Glaser and
Strauss 1967; Tavory and Timmermans 2014). As research students quickly learn,
the ongoing question that haunts qualitative sociologists is “what is this a case of?”
(Becker 2014; Becker and Ragin 1992), a question that assumes the movement from
one context to another as an important aspect of the research project.
At least within academic sociology in the United States, ethnography thus
seems to have relatively little contact with ethnomethodology. And yet, with
its attention to the details of everyday life and the Chicago School focus on
the ongoing construction of meaning, it seems that pragmatist-inspired inter-
actional ethnography and ethnomethodology are kindred projects (see also
Emirbayer and Maynard 2011). If there is a “natural” disciplinary space for
ethnomethodology to take root in the field of sociology, it may be ethnog-
raphy. After all, despite recognizing the deep theoretical differences between
the positions, Pollner and Emerson (2001:118) noted somewhat optimistically
that “the once pronounced differences [between ethnomethodology and eth-
nography] may be dissolving into an integrated methodological sensibility.”
While such an integrated sensibility seems to still be indistinctly hovering
in the distance, some lines of argument constructed by ethnomethodology-in-
spired ethnographers—and some ways of attempting to reconcile the razor of
generalizations with the details of locally constructed order—can be glimpsed.
In the following I provide examples of two such possibilities. First, following
writers such as Dorothy Smith (e.g., 1987), as well as being inspired by talk-in-
interaction, ethnomethodology-inspired ethnographers can move between local
construction and recurrent institutional affordances and pressures. Thus, some-
what as in institutional CA, ethnographers can trace institutional fingerprints,
relying on the local construction of order, sometimes even poaching CA
techniques. Second, ethnographers can treat the constructions of meaning
as local accomplishments, while generalizing what we may term the field site’s
“space of legibility.” This is the idea that within specific social worlds, subjects
find some actions to be more easily and commonly accountable than others. For
subjects, such actions emerge again and again as recognizably “another instance
of x.” Thus, when ethnographers encounter such moments again and again,
they can assume that subjects’ work to make sense of the specific is immediately
shared and obvious—or, in other words, “legible.”
432 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Institutional Fingerprints
Much like the institutional CA’s grounding of generalization in the interac-
tion between local constructions and institutional pragmatics and pressures,
writers such as Smith (e.g., 1987) have attempted to infuse ethnomethodology
with a more structural appreciation of power. Thus, Smith’s “Institutional
Ethnography” oscillates between an ethnomethodology-inspired account and a
Marxist-feminist critique of institutional life. Although Smith assumes a macro-
context within which action takes place, her work shows how—within these
parameters—actors constantly recreate their world.
To take one recent example of an ethnography that is explicitly indebted to
Smith, Goodman (2008) studied the ways in which racialization occurred in the
context of prisoner intake. As officers process new inmates and fill in official doc-
umentation, they use the pre-given rubric of “race” in the form as a way to de-
termine where to put the inmates (see also Kameo and Whalen 2015). Thus, in
this setting, ethnicity becomes omni-relevant as a way to organize people’s lives.
See the following conversation, taking place in an inmate-processing center in
a California prison that Goodman calls “Central.” As they arrive, the inmates
are unshackled, and processed by an officer, with other officers and incoming
inmates in close proximity (Goodman 2008:759):
Officer: Race?
Inmate: Portuguese.
Officer: Portuguese? [pause] You mean White?
Inmate: Nah, I’m Portuguese, not White.
Officer: Sure, but who do you house with?
Inmate: Usually with the “Others.”
Officer: We don’t fuck with that here. It’s just Black, White, or Hispanic.
Inmate: Well, I’m Portuguese.
Second officer, looking on the whole time: Put him with the Negros, then
[“Negro” pronounced in Spanish].
Inmate: What?!
Second officer: Oh, now you’re serious, huh. So you want to house with the
Whites, do you?
Inmate: Fine, with the Whites.
Officer: OK, with the Whites it is.
GENERALIZATION IN ETHNOMETHODOLOGY 433
The attempt to break the racial typology is a problem both of abstract classifi-
cation and practical work. The officers need to place the inmate in a category,
but his choice of an alternative classification (apparently allowed in other states)
doesn’t fit the Black/White/Hispanic options on the forms they fill, causing an
ongoing practical problem. If there is no “other” category, where does the in-
mate fit? The officers, as the excerpt shows, proceed to solve this problem first by
giving the inmate the “right” options he can choose from (disabusing him of the
category of “other”), and then by threatening to house him with black inmates, in
a move that they correctly assume would jolt him into submission.
Through this example of a “bumpy” interaction, as well as other, smoother,
moments of racial classification, Goodman (2008) documents how officers
achieve not only regularities in categorization but also patterns of segregation
in prisons. Officers must attend to the physical form as, under pressures of time,
they process the inmates and place them in particular cells. When they encounter
unexpected resistance, they can utilize their institutional power, manifested
here in the threat to house the inmate “with the Negros,” and the dismissal of
the category of “other.” And although Goodman does not use CA, this form of
ethnographic inquiry—like institutional talk-in-interaction—can potentially
reveal, through the analysis of identifying detail and their ordered regularities,
the institutional fingerprints of prison intake (see also Brubaker et al. 2006;
Duneier 1999). Such inquiry may appear to be a type of “formal analysis,” in-
sofar as it goes some ways to explain how racialization in California prisons has
become an entrenched feature of the penal system. However, it is based on the
close analysis of both talk and the required use of placement documents as they
infuse the talk and social interactions between officers and inmates.
toddler’s mother had added her own magnetic accoutrements, cutting them,
as she later told me, out of an old refrigerator magnet she had. Adding these
new magnets, she changed “Snow White” into “the Eidel Princess” (the modest
Princess), and the Prince into the “Ben Torah” (the Torah boy). The two chil-
dren, who were too young to read the names of the characters, were calling
them by these new names. When I asked the mother about the reworked toy,
she answered that she did not want her children to tell others about playing
with “Snow White”—not because there was anything wrong with the toy or
the images, she said, but because if they used these names, others might think
436 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
that they knew who and what “Snow White and the Prince” were, implying
that they have seen the movie, and thus have transgressed into the secular
world of entertainment.
How then to analyze such a moment? A culturalist approach may latch on
to the details provided by an informant about a social world as providing a
kind of “thick description” of the scene. The informant provides a general-
ization about the Orthodox social world as one in which members will be
judged if their children know “profane knowledge,” which the ethnogra-
pher loyally reproduces. But another way to think about this episode is more
ethnomethodology-inspired, more like Wieder’s notion of the “code.” Rather
than assuming that he now knows what the Orthodox “norm” is, the re-
searcher assumes that—with just the resources at hand, at just this moment—
subjects construct an account that they expect others in the neighborhood
would understand.
And yet, thinking about this episode as a local production does not mean
that it doesn’t tell us something generalizable about the field. Like “the code,”
we can assume that the episode is a legible one. Of course, this does not mean
that all Orthodox people sustain their image in the same way (as it turns out,
they don’t), or that they see the same items as equally defiling (they don’t), or
even that the same items are always considered defiling by the same people.
And yet, whereas the ethnographer cannot argue that the specific claims his
interlocutor makes are right in the sense of transparently telling us “what the
world is like,” they tell us something important about the kinds of arguments
that subjects expect that others in their social world would immediately make
sense of. This, in turn, may reveal quite a lot about the given social world—
one where secular leisure culture is seen by some members as problematic
enough to need justification; where people may expect others to read their own
patterns of religious conduct from their children’s behavior; where tinkering
with secular leisure-forms to produce religious forms is possible.
Such arguments about the Orthodox world, although couched in the language
of legibility, still form generalizations about the social world the ethnographer
studies—that secular leisure culture needs to be managed, and that private con-
sumption of such leisure is anticipated by actors to require translation into reli-
gious terms for others in the community. As such, the researcher needs to check
them against other cases (perhaps this move is only legible for this actor? At this
time? Perhaps others would see this mother as completely mad?). Yet, the pro-
cess through which the researcher makes these generalizations, as well as their
nature, is still indebted to ethnomethodology. While it is a leap into generaliza-
tion, such an analysis does not reduce indexical expressions to instantiations of
a general rule, norm, or habit, but uses such moments to study what actors can
expect to make sense in their world.
GENERALIZATION IN ETHNOMETHODOLOGY 437
This chapter began with an image of Occam’s razor as a rule of parsimony. This
popular rendition of the razor leads one to accept the simplest analytic descrip-
tion or theory of action (see, e.g., Biggs 2009). In these terms, ethnomethodology
is probably the farthest away one can be from the neat cut of a razor. The messi-
ness of action and the ongoing construction of order, I have suggested, is far from
simple. Ethnomethodology’s effectiveness as social theory and inquiry has little
to do with that form of neatness.
But as I noted earlier, the usual understanding of Occam’s razor itself is quite
far from its original meaning. Occam’s razor—the pithy warning that “entities
should not be multiplied beyond necessity”—was constructed to answer a very
different challenge (Ariew 1976). Rather than a rule of scientific parsimony, it was
an ontological position in the struggle between realism and nominalism. Indeed,
Occam’s razor is sometimes referred to, in this context, as “the nominalists’
razor.” The context was a debate in medieval philosophy about the ontological
status of universals—whether things such as “redness” or “bigness” (or “class” for
this matter) that seem to be attributes of different particular observations have
some kind of ontological status, or whether they are simply words (hence “nomi-
nalism”) that gloss over the particularities of specific cases, and are devoid of any
reality of their own. Occam’s razor was an attempt to shore up nominalism, and
resist our impulse to assume that collective terms exist beyond their enactment.
In emphasizing the “just thisness” of the world, Garfinkel was waging a sim-
ilar battle with generalizations that are assumed to be a substance in their own
right, now in the shape of “norms,” “values,” or “rules.” And, seen from this angle,
the relationship between ethnomethodology and Occam’s razor radically shifts.
Ethnomethodology’s analyses may be painstaking, and may be exceedingly
complex in any given case. But as a position, ethnomethodology is ontologically
minimalist. It makes fewer, not more, assumptions about the kinds of things
there are in the social world.
Although the complexity of any given analysis seems to belie this assertion, in
terms of social ontology, ethnomethodology is exceedingly simple. Both meth-
odologically and theoretically, ethnomethodology rejects assertions such as that
there are different “spheres” of life, that culture and interaction are two relatively
autonomous environments of action, or that generalizations such as “class” and
“social structure” exist beyond their specific instantiations. Rather than a world
populated by people, values, codes, and culture, the world that ethnomethod-
ology depicts is of people co-constructing a working order—“ordinary, immortal
society”—moment by moment.
Where does this leave us? Clarifying the relationship between generalization
and ethnomethodology’s various projects does not make our lives as practicing
438 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
sociologists any easier. If we are to make claims that go beyond the ongoing,
in situ, construction of the world, we end up with assumptions that Garfinkel
attempted to banish. And yet, even for those of us who still feel the urge to
generalize, ethnomethodology forces us to realize the intellectual shortcuts,
assumptions, and presumptions that we make in generalization to remind us
that we are “multiplying entities.” And, if we remain attentive to the price we pay
for generalizations in the form of the glosses and assumptions that we introduce,
we may at least strive to ask ourselves how defensible these are.
Finally, it is not only that ethnomethodology and professional sociology
are incommensurable, but that, as Garfinkel came to see, they were “alternate
Janus faces of accountability as the objective reality of social facts.” (Garfinkel
2002:103). If we are to understand the myriad ways through which social life
goes on, we may have to constantly move between the two faces of Janus. For at
the end:
The prize is one for both technologies, that ties both technologies, and that nei-
ther technology can have by itself. It ties them in that they are incommensu-
rable alternates. To win the prize not only requires the competence of both, but
each requires the competence of the other for itself. (Garfinkel 2002:103–4)
References
Ariew, Roger. 1976. “Ockham’s Razor: A Historical and Philosophical Analysis of
Ockham’s Principle of Parsimony.” Unpublished PhD dissertation, University of
Illinois at Urbana-Champaign.
Arminen, Illka. 2005. Institutional Interaction: Studies of Talk at Work. Aldershot,
UK: Ashgate.
Atkinson, J. Maxwell, and Paul Drew. 1979. Order in Court: The Organization of Verbal
Interaction in Judicial Settings. London: Macmillan.
Becker, Howard S. 2014. What about Mozart? What about Murder: Reasoning from Cases.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Becker, Howard S., and Charles C. Ragin. 1992. What Is a Case? Exploring the Foundations
of Social Inquiry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Biggs, Michael. 2009. “Self-Fulfilling Prophecies.” Pp. 294–315 in The Oxford Handbook
of Analytical Sociology, edited by P. Bearman and P. Hedström. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Brubaker, Rogers. 2013. “Categories of Analysis and Categories of Practice: A Note on the
Study of Muslims in European Countries of Immigration.” Ethnic and Racial Studies
36(1):1–8.
Brubaker, Rogers, Margit Feischmidt, Jon Fox, and Liana Grancea. 2006. Nationalist
Politics and Everyday Ethnicity in a Transylvanian Town. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
GENERALIZATION IN ETHNOMETHODOLOGY 439
Drew, Paul, and John Heritage. 1992. “Analyzing Talk at Work: An Introduction.” Pp. 3–65
in Talk at Work: Interaction in Institutional Settings, edited by P. Drew and J. Heritage.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Duneier, Mitchell. 1999. Sidewalk. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux.
Emirbayer, Mustafa, and Douglas W. Maynard. 2011. “Pragmatism and Ethnomethodology.”
Qualitative Sociology 34(1):221–61. doi: 10.1007/s11133-010-9183-8.
Evans-Pritchard, E. E. 1937. Witchcraft, Oracles and Magic among the Azande. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1967. Studies in Ethnomethodology. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1988. “Evidence for Locally Produced, Naturally Accountable
Phenomena of Order, Logic, Reason, Meaning, Method, Etc. in and as of the Essential
Quiddity of Immortal Ordinary Society, (I of IV): An Announcement of Studies.”
Sociological Theory 6(1):103–9. doi: 10.2307/201918.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1996. “Ethnomethodology’s Program.” Social Psychology Quarterly
59(1):5–21. doi: 10.2307/2787116.
Garfinkel, Harold. 2002. Ethnomethodology’s Program: Working Out Durkeim’s Aphorism.
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Garfinkel, Harold, and D. Lawrence Wieder. 1992. “Two Incommensurable, Asymmetrically
Alternate Technologies of Social Analysis.” Pp. 175–206 in Text in Context: Contributions
to Ethnomethodology, edited by G. Watson and R. M. Seiler. Newbury Park, CA: SAGE.
Glaser, Barney G., and Anselm L. Strauss. 1967. The Discovery of Grounded Theory.
New York: Aldine.
Goffman, Erving. 1983. “The Interaction Order: American Sociological Association, 1982
Presidential Address.” American Sociological Review 48(1):1. doi: 10.2307/2095141.
Goodman, Philip. 2008. “‘It’s Just Black, White, or Hispanic’: An Observational Study of
Racializing Moves in California’s Segregated Prison Reception Centers.” Law & Society
Review 42:735–70. doi: 10.1111/j.1540-5893.2008.00357.x.
Heritage, John. 1984. Garfinkel and Ethnomethodology. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Heritage, John. 2004. “Conversation Analysis and Institutional Talk.” Pp. 103– 46
in Handbook of Language and Social Interaction, edited by R. Sanders and K. Fitch.
Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Heritage, John, and Steven Clayman. 2010. Talk in Action: Interactions, Identities, and
Institutions. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
Heritage, John, and David Greatbatch. 1991. “On the Institutional Character of
Institutional Talk: The Case of News Interviews.” Pp. 93–137 in Talk and Social
Structure: Studies in Ethnomethodology and Conversation Analysis, edited by D. Boden
and D. H. Zimmerman. Cambridge: Polity.
Heritage, John, Jeffrey D. Robinson, Marc N. Elliott, Megan Beckett, and Michael Wilkes.
2007. “Reducing Patients’ Unmet Concerns in Primary Care: The Difference One
Word Can Make.” Journal of General Internal Medicine 22(10):1429–33. doi: 10.1007/
s11606-007-0279-0.
Kameo, Nahoko, and Jack Whalen. 2015. “Organizing Documents: Standard Forms,
Person Production and Organizational Action.” Qualitative Sociology 38(2):205–29.
doi: 10.1007/s11133-015-9302-7.
Martin, John L. 2011. The Explanation of Social Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Maynard, Douglas W. 1984. Inside Plea Bargaining: The Language of Negotiation.
New York: Plenum.
440 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Maynard, Douglas W., and Steven E. Clayman. 1991. “The Diversity of Ethnomethodology.”
Annual Review of Sociology 17(1):385–418. doi: 10.1146/annurev.so.17.080191.002125.
Maynard, Douglas W., Jeremy Freese, and Nora Cate Schaeffer. 2010. “Calling for
Participation: Requests, Blocking Moves, and Rational (Inter)Action in Survey
Introductions.” American Sociological Review 75(5):791– 814. doi: 10.1177/
0003122410379582.
Pike, Kenneth L. 1967. Language in Relation to a Unified Theory of the Structure of Human
Behavior. 2nd ed. The Hague: De Gruyter Mouton.
Pollner, Melvin. 1987. Mundane Reason: Reality in Everyday and Sociological Discourse.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pollner, Melvin, and Robert M. Emerson. 2001. “Ethnomethodology and Ethnography.”
Pp. 118–35 in Handbook of Ethnography, edited by P. Atkinson, A. Coffey, S. Delamont,
J. Lofland, and L. Lofland. London: SAGE.
Powers, Charles H. 2010. Making Sense of Social Theory: A Practical Introduction. Lanham,
MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
Rawls, Anne W. 1987. “The Interaction Order Sui Generis: Goffman’s Contribution to
Social Theory.” Sociological Theory 5(2):136–49. doi: 10.2307/201935.
Rawls, Anne W. 1996. “Durkheim’s Epistemology: The Neglected Argument.” American
Journal of Sociology 102(2):430–82. doi: 10.1086/230952.
Rawls, Anne W. 2002. “Editor’s Introduction.” Pp. 1–64 in Ethnomethodology’s Program:
Working Out Durkheim’s Aphorism, edited by H. Garfinkel. Lanham, MD: Rowman &
Littlefield.
Rock, Paul. 1979. The Making of Symbolic Interactionism. Totowa, NJ: Rowman &
Littlefield.
Sacks, Harvey. 1984. “Notes on Methodology.” Pp. 2–27 in Structures of Social Action:
Studies in Conversation Analysis, edited by J. M. Atkinson and J. Heritage. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Sacks, Harvey, and Emanuel A. Schegloff. 1973. “Opening up Closings.” Semiotica
8(4):289–327. doi: 10.1515/semi.1973.8.4.289.
Schaeffer, Nora Cate, Dana Garbarski, Jeremy Freese, and Douglas W. Maynard. 2013.
“An Interactional Model of the Call for Survey Participation: Actions and Reactions
in the Survey Recruitment Call.” Public Opinion Quarterly 77:323–51. doi: 10.1093/
poq/nft006.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1987. “Between Micro and Macro: Contexts and Other Connections.”
Pp. 207–34 in The Micro-Macro Link, edited by R. M. Jeffrey, C. Alexander Bernhard
Giesen, and N. J. Smelser. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1991. “Reflections on Talk and Social Structure.” Pp. 44–70 in Talk
and Social Structure: Studies in Ethnomethodology and Conversation Analysis, edited by
D. Boden and D. H. Zimmerman. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1992. “Repair after Next Turn: The Last Structurally Provided Place
for the Defense of Intersubjectivity in Conversation.” American Journal of Sociology
95(5):1295–345. doi: 10.1086/229903.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1993. “Reflections on Quantification in the Study of Conversation.”
Research on Language & Social Interaction 26(1):99–128. doi: 10/fggjpm.
Schegloff, Emanuel A. 2007. Sequence Organization in Interaction: A Primer in Conversation
Analysis, Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Schütz, Alfred. [1932] 1967. Phenomenology of the Social World. 1st edition. Evanston,
IL: Northwestern University Press.
GENERALIZATION IN ETHNOMETHODOLOGY 441
Ethnomethodology and Atypical Interaction 443
sense and its analysis is the study of autism spectrum disorder (ASD) and re-
search on atypical interaction more generally.
. . . The missing what that ethnomethodologists have been at the work of dis-
covering is available to lay and professional versions of organization in ordi-
nary activities as the earth stands to the presence of Mount Everest. Orderings
of ordinary activities are unimaginably extensive phenomena. . . . The claim is
this: there is one hell of a lot of it, more than we can ever imagine, more than we
ever would have imagined, where the more is such that we couldn’t have imag-
ined it without the work behind us. (Chapter 5:157, this volume)
This massive presence of orderly, common-sense actions also means that there is
an immense variety of practices whose presence for our everyday, ordinary, oc-
cupational, workaday, playful, and other social worlds have yet to be fully inves-
tigated and understood.
This legacy, at least from Garfinkel’s early work, comes with a limitation, how-
ever. On the one hand, Garfinkel (1967:31, our emphasis) argues, “Not a method
of understanding but immensely various methods of understanding are the pro-
fessional sociologist’s proper and hitherto unstudied and critical phenomena.”
Indeed, the ethnomethodological approach to common sense is one in which
analysts drop the assumption that common sense is a “what”—a substance
involving shared agreement—and instead take up the stance that common
sense is a “how” (Garfinkel 1967:28–29). The “how” question targets—among
444 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
of the disabled person as they are about the threats to abled common sense and
its strictures.
Conversation analytic (CA) scholars of language and neurological impair
ments in “atypical” interactions have been taking a similar tack for many years,
and they open a related topic, which is the possibility for alteration to or mod-
ification of common sense.2 Goodwin (2003a:8–10) has observed that, al-
though the inability to produce relevant speech—as in aphasia—can be “a major
failing in human competence,” interactions involving those with impairments
always occur within an “ecology of sign systems,” which includes the sequen-
tial organization of talk. More recently, in an edited volume drawing on CA for
investigations of atypical interaction, Wilkinson, Rae, and Rasmussen (2020) list
major features of turn-taking activities involving those with impaired linguistic
capabilities. These include delayed “progressivity” or movement through adja-
cency pair sequences, distinct patterns of repair initiation and repair, heightened
use of the indexical properties of talk by relying on gesture and “enactments”
and “re-enactments” (cf. Sidnell 2009), and an intensification of co-construction
or mutuality in assembling actions. Close inspection of sequential organization,
and the ecology of which it is a part, demonstrate that those with impairments
may be using forms of reasoning and communication via other-than-usual or
taken-for-granted practices. Furthermore, although resourceful in their own
right for persons with impairments, these practices may stimulate or elicit
awareness among co-participants of interactional differences, as opposed to
deficits. These typically performing members can then expand their repertoires
of common sense to facilitate the collaborative achievement of mutual under-
standing and joint action. In effect, this implicates reorganizing the local ecology
of sign systems, producing an expansion of common-sense knowledge.
We return to the topic of reorganizing local ecologies at the end of the chapter,
where we address how ethnomethodological inquiry can be informative about
ways to support and enhance the learning and understanding of those with im-
paired linguistic or social skills, such that they may better fit the social fabrics in
home, school, and other settings. However, this means changing or reweaving
those very fabrics, rather than attempting to alter the persons who have difficulty
fitting them. That is, our empirical analysis may show how children with ASD
can violate common-sense assumptions in clinics,3 and thereby aid our “slug-
gish imaginations” (Garfinkel 1967:38), increasing awareness of what clinicians’
“professional stocks of interactional knowledge” (Peräkylä and Vehviläinen
2003) in such environments take for granted as they implement testing and
other protocols. At the same time, analysis can go beyond the taken-for-granted
structures of common-sense and professional knowledge to reveal what Ochs
and Solomon (2004) call the “practical logic” that goes into the seeming violation
as it is constructed in the first place. In the end, ethnomethodological inquiry
446 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
suggests that there can be mutual adjustments between individuals with ASD or
other impairments and the clinical as well as ordinary settings they occupy.
The data for this chapter include video recordings of two children being tested
for autism or other developmental disabilities. Data were collected in a devel-
opmental disabilities clinic, hereafter called Central Developmental Disabilities
Clinic (CDDC), which is associated with a university-based medical school.
Family members, pediatricians, educators, and others refer children to the clinic
for diagnosis and treatment of intellectual, speech, behavioral, and other dif-
ficulties. An interdisciplinary team of clinicians representing the fields of psy-
chology, psychiatry, speech pathology, developmental pediatrics, occupational
therapy, and/or others may see the child, administer their tests, and combine
their findings to determine a diagnosis.
Both children in our examples were eventually diagnosed with autism, al-
though the exact parameters of this diagnosis changed from one period to the
next (Maynard and Turowetz 2019). In our first case, a nine-year-old boy, “Dan
Chapman” (all names, including that of the CDDC, are pseudonyms) received
the diagnosis of ASD in 2014 under the auspices of the Diagnostic and Statistical
Manual of the American Psychiatric Association (DSM-5; APA 2013). In our
second case, recorded in 1985, a seven-year-old boy, “Tony Smith,” was offi-
cially labeled as having infantile autism (Turowetz and Maynard 2018; Turowetz
2015b) based on the then-operative version of the Diagnostic and Statistical
Manual (DSM-III; APA 1980). Each example exhibits how a child can fail a sub-
test, not just because of errors in answering, but because of more fundamental
flaws he exposes in the scaffolding upon which testing depends. Maynard and
Marlaire (1992) call this scaffolding an interactional substrate:
We show how, in each of our two cases, clinicians report on what happens, not
as part of the official test results, but in an anecdotal way, casting the matter op-
timistically and depicting the failure as nevertheless having positive aspects for
the child. Valid as the clinical approach and official nomenclature may be, our
Ethnomethodology and Atypical Interaction 447
The astounding vocabulary of the speaking children, the excellent memory for
events of several years before, the phenomenal rote memory for poems and names,
and the precise recollection of complex patterns and sequences, bespeak good in-
telligence in the sense in which this word is commonly used. (1943:247–48)
feats of vocabulary use, memory, orientations to local patterns, and the like.
When we discuss autistic intelligence, we mean more basic proficiencies, such as
those that make other actions and interactions possible. We regard these skills as
forms of first-order competence. Although those who work with someone on the
spectrum may be excellent at appreciating such skills, the practices comprising
them often exist at a level of detail that requires the tools of ethnomethodology
and CA for their analysis as socially organized phenomena—practices of talk and
embodied behavior that lead to achieving orderly engagement with another par-
ticipant. We also have referred to such practices as “fundamental” competence,
a term meant to convey the primacy of these skills as a mode of collaboratively
engaging the world (Maynard and Turowetz 2022: Chapter 4). By contrast, what
we call “second-order” or “structural” competence refers to the capacity or ability
to use first-order competences to perform particular tasks, such as those that a di-
agnostic test is designed to assess. First-order competence involves such practices
as providing an “answer” in the sequential slot after a question, independent of
whether the answer is correct or, on a more basic level, orients to the question as
a test question per se. Accordingly, second-order competence is parasitic upon
first-order competence for its realization; first-order competence, meanwhile, is a
necessary condition for second-order competence, but not a sufficient one.
First-order competence and the interactional substrate of which it is a part
comprise, by Garfinkel’s metaphor, the surface of the billiard ball or the earth.
To adopt the earth-based analogy, second-order competence includes the pro-
ficiency to scale a mountain, starting from that autochthonous surface. As we
examine two clinical cases, we address why understanding the social orderliness
exhibited in and as autistic intelligence and first-order competence is a conse-
quential matter, both for individuals with ASD and for the communities in which
they exist. At the end of the chapter, when we return to the topic of common
sense, it is to recap how pervasive a phenomenon it is, and how it demands al-
legiance from society’s members, even in clinical settings. When that allegiance
is apparently lacking, we also can see how common-sense pervasiveness comes
with exclusionary tendencies, at worst, and a kind of bemused tolerance, even
positivity, at best. In contrast, our data allow us to explore how, within the
exhibits of autistic intelligence, there may be hidden-in-plain-sight, suppressed
contributions to learning and knowledge on the part of individuals with ASD.
Clinical Cases
In each of our two clinical cases, there is a failure to achieve a feature of the inter-
actional substrate of psychological testing required for successful completion of
Ethnomethodology and Atypical Interaction 449
a task. That is, common-sense features of test administration are violated. One
of these features is that the clinician is to provide testing prompts in a directive
fashion, with the child complying by producing the called-for action—an an-
swer, performance, etc. In essence, testing often consists of a series of directive-
response sequences— a subtype of “adjacency pairs,” which are so- named
because such pairs consist of two utterances, adjacently positioned, with a first
utterance initiating and a second one responding and completing the sequence
(Schegloff and Sacks 1973). More specifically, directive-response sequences con-
sist of (A) utterances designed “to get someone else to do something” (Goodwin
2006:517)—offers, requests, orders, prohibitions, etc.—and (B) responses indi-
cating compliance, avoidance, refusal, and the like (Cekaite 2010; Craven and
Potter 2010; Ervin-Tripp 1976; Goodwin 2006). Such sequences also involve
prosody—pitch, emphasis, volume, stress, pacing—and embodiment, including
gaze, gesture, and other movements (Goodwin, Cekaite, and Goodwin 2012).
They are embedded “. . . within a larger temporal horizon” (Goodwin and Cekaite
2013)—in our data, the overall testing activity.
At the time of his evaluation at the CDDC, Dan Chapman was nine years and two
months of age and in the third grade at school. Dan’s pediatrician referred him
because of his “significant behavioral challenges,” including a history of aggres-
sive and disruptive behavior at school, difficulty with two-way conversations—
although he could talk for hours on topics of interest to him, such as cars—and
other matters. At CDDC, a number of specialists saw Dan. We are concen-
trating on a small subtest that the psychologist, Dr. “Jennifer Carson,” gave to
Dan as she administered the Autism Diagnostic and Observation Schedule
(ADOS-2, module 3), the so-called gold standard (Dawson et al. 2007:659) for
ASD assessments. The subtest is called a “Demonstration Task,” in which the
clinician is to assess “the participant’s ability to communicate about a familiar
series of actions using gesture or mime with accompanying language” (Lord
et al. 2012:113).4 The test manual instructs the clinician to say, using appro-
priate gestures, “Let’s pretend that this is the sink, this is the hot water, and this
is the cold water,” and then to “pretend to draw the toothbrush.” Next, the cli-
nician should state, “Now I want you to show me and tell me how to brush my
teeth. Start right at the beginning. You’ve just come into the bathroom to brush
your teeth. What do you do now?” Although Jennifer follows these directions
closely, Dan consistently refuses the directives and requests to do the demonstra-
tion task.
450 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
(a) Dan moves his head to his right (b) Dan moves head to his left (c) Dan moves head back
During what may be termed instructional directives at lines 6, 8–9, which both
inform Dan and suggest using pretend items in the demonstration, Dan is gazing
at Jen. Following a micropause (line 10), Jen shifts from the previous entitled
form (“I want you to show me . . . ,” line 3) to one featuring a lesser, but still enti-
tled, modal preface (“Can you . . . ,” line 11; cf. Curl and Drew 2008). Further, as
Craven and Potter (2010:437) formulate the matter, “can you”–type directives
potentially orient “to the recipient’s capacities and desires.” There is a subtle, im-
portant distinction here between ability and motivation, as we will see. At this
point, Dan shifts his gaze downward and away from Jen (line 12), maintaining
this head posture as she produces a further instructional directive that tacitly
characterizes the task as a playful one (line 13). During this utterance, Dan shifts
his gaze back to Jen.
As Jen produces laughter tokens (line 15), Dan engages in a second instance of
lateral head shaking (line 16). Next, Jennifer proposes his lack of compliance is
motivationally based (line 18), indicating that the directive at line 11 also impli-
cated a motivational feature. She does this by way of a negative declarative—a re-
quest for confirmation—that goes up upward on the gradient of epistemic stance
(Heritage 2010). The source of Dan’s refusal to do this task is within Dan’s own
epistemic domain, yet Jen (at line 18) is asserting knowledge of Dan’s internal
state by proposing that his refusal is attributable to not wanting to do the task. In
that sense, this is a strong exhibit of clinical if not lay common-sense knowledge.
It also is in line with how members regularly handle a breach of common-sense
conduct, such as the conditional relevance of an answer to a test question: as
Garfinkel (1963, 1967) demonstrated, the inference is that there must be a moti-
vational problem of some kind (cf. Heritage 1984b:99). By inviting confirmation
of what it declares, and in following a series of refusals, the form and placement
of the sequence at lines 18–19 are closure-implicative, rather presumptively set-
tling the matter of Dan’s performance so far.
Jen, the professional and common-sense actor, interprets Dan’s refusal to
her relatively entitled requesting (starting with “I want you to sho::w me and
tell me how you brush your teeth,” lines 3–4), first as a matter of ability (“Can
you . . . ,” line 11), and then as a matter of willfulness (line 18). In the absence of
452 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
any claim that he cannot do the task (line 12), Dan’s ability to do the task comes
to be presumed; accordingly, Jen’s suggestion, “you don’t wanna . . .” (line 18),
treats the issue as one of volition. Again, this is consonant with Garfinkel’s
suggestions about the way that a violation of trust conditions results in motiva-
tional imputations and the psychologizing of noncompliance.
Modeling a Demonstration
The instruction manual for the ADOS Demonstration Task (Lord et al. 2012:113)
states that if a participant “does not understand the idea of the task” and “does
not attempt the task,” then it is permissible to enact “a different event” for the
subject, such as how one drives a car. Jennifer does this next. She proposes such
an enactment (lines 20 and 21 in the following), but Dan now does a fourth re-
fusal gesture (line 22).
Jennifer ignores Dan’s refusal gesture and, miming how to drive a car, she
narrates the process (lines 23, 25, 28, 30). Dan now deploys head-shaking that
Ethnomethodology and Atypical Interaction 453
Dan’s Withdrawal
Dan’s mother, Mrs. Chapman, asks Dan (not on transcript here), “Are you
all done right now,” and “Do you want a break?” Dan then crouches behind
the chair with his back to it and to Jennifer, who is diagonally across the room
from the chair. He is not visible from her position, and he remains behind the
chair for nearly 20 seconds before standing up again. Concurrently, his mother
observes, “At this point he is basically . . .” and draws her hand in a cutting ges-
ture across her neck. Jennifer offers some “cards,” to which Dan (still standing
behind the chair) responds “Uh uh” [no] as she tells him that they do not have
to do the tooth brushing. She also retrieves a fire truck, but he shows disinterest
by observing that he has “more than one at home.” As he and Mrs. Chapman
discuss the truck and cars they have at home, Jennifer pulls out a toy with three-
dimensional movable metal pins for making impressions of hands, small toys,
and other objects—sometimes called a “pin art game.” That this toy draws Dan
back to the table from where he started suggests that its tactile affordances may
have been central. More crucially, just as Dan takes the toy and forms it around
Ethnomethodology and Atypical Interaction 455
his hand, he says, “This is easy,” which, from his own perspective, suggests a tacit
contrast with the preceding demonstration task as something hard or difficult.
That is, whereas Jen distantly, from a lesser epistemic position, interprets Dan’s
refusals as “won’t,” he displays an orientation to “can’t.”8
Motivational Accounting
After his return, Jennifer is able to complete the ADOS exam with Dan. When
she scores his exam, it meets the cutoff for the ASD diagnosis, which is not of
central concern here (however, see Maynard and Turowetz 2022). Rather, our
concern is with the interpretations of Dan’s conduct, however fleeting—partic-
ularly the ways in which clinicians, not only within the exam itself, but also in
their discussions afterward, orient to Dan’s noncompliance as a problem of mo-
tivation. His “pre-staffing”—a case conference where clinicians decide on diag-
nosis—included the developmental pediatrician, Dr. “Leah Grant;” Dr. Carson
(Jennifer), the psychologist; and a psychology student intern (“Leslie”). At lines
88–89, Jen refers to the episode captured in Extracts 1a–1c as showing Dan’s
“most a:typical response,” a term that in clinical settings indexes ASD. It takes
several more turns of talk for her and the student to recall the part of the test
where it occurred. At lines 90–92, Leslie, the student, characterizes Dan’s action
using a phrase, “he just got up . . .” that, by way of the “just” term, suggests that
the behavior was less than the required performance.
Furthermore, at line 95 the student, Leslie, depicts Dan as not wanting to par-
ticipate—using the “just” term in a slightly different way, but one that still
456 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
conveys less than optimal performance. Jen (at lines 98, 100) also formulates
Dan as feeling “on the spot” in a way that occasioned his abandonment of the
demonstration.
While Jen suggests an optimistic take on the event—“but he came back” (lines
100, 102)—the motivational account and Leslie’s sense of frustration (line 92) are
in accord with regular features of recipients’ emotional reactions to breaching
as they formulate perpetrators’ moral accountability. The account and even the
frustration (with reference to “it” and Dan’s own behavior) abstract details from
a much more complex set of interactions, including Dan’s full-bodied orienta-
tion to Jennifer throughout the episode, and the sheer number and persistence
of Dan’s refusals.9 These refusals exhibit forms of first-order competence—
practices that lie in the interactional substrate of testing and that are an earth-
wise grounding, so to speak, for the Mount Everest of his withdrawal. There is
also the strong possibility that he is being asked to do something he is unable to
do, rather than will not do. The tacit contrast that Dan’s “this is easy” statement
may draw in relation to the pin art task suggests that, from his perspective, the
problem in complying with the task may have had to do with his ability, rather
than his motivation.
At line 35, Jen produces a newsmark (cf. Heritage 1984a:note 13; Jefferson
1981) that asks for confirmation. However, as Dan confirms by nodding and
smiling (line 36), she immediately continues with the demonstration (lines 37–38
and subsequently). Although this fits with instructions for administering the
instrument, to which examiners orient as a basis for achieving standardized test
Ethnomethodology and Atypical Interaction 457
results, we can only imagine or speculate as to how differently this task may have
gone had Jen responded (or been allowed to respond10) more fully to Dan’s an-
nouncement, and whether following up may have facilitated a “demonstration”
performance after all.11 We return to this point in our Conclusion.
Tony Smith was seven years and ten months old when his parents, at the rec-
ommendation of a school social worker, referred him to CDDC because of his
repetitive utterances and other “autistic-like behaviors.” We examine an episode
that occurred during the administration of a subtest from the Psychoeducational
Profile (PEP) that requires a child to assemble puzzle pieces into images, in this
case a cow. During this episode, Tony and Laura (a special education clinician)
had difficulty in achieving joint attention, or co-orientation, and eventually the
subtest was abandoned.
This tension between three dimensions and kinesthesia, on the one hand,
and two dimensions (requiring visual concentration), on the other, persists
throughout the episode and parallels a kind of strain between following an exter-
nally imposed (picture) plan and, for Tony, the immediate tactile availability of
the puzzle pieces themselves.
In the analysis to follow, it will be shown that Tony’s failure to properly as-
semble the puzzle results from pursuing an activity that exhibits first-order
competence—indulging the “affordances” (Gibson 1986) of the puzzle pieces as
manipulatable objects—rather than following the clinician’s directives to make
a picture. Although at odds with test requirements, Tony’s resistance suggests
not so much an inability to understand Laura, or the interactional objective
prescribed by the test, as an orientation to a different interactional objective.
Laura’s initial move is a bald directive (line 1), one with no modality or politeness
markers, and includes a possibly enticing “for me” appendage.
7 (12.5) ((Tony bangs & lines up 2 pieces, puts 3rd piece on board))
8 Lau: That’s right. This is a picture of a co:::w.
9 (4.2) ((Tony shakes head, bangs/slides pieces of puzzle))
10 Tony: .hh (°Wa°)ss-((“watch”))
11 (18.0) ((Laura writes in booklet, Tony lifts puzzle pieces))
12 Lau: Want me to show you?
13 (1.5) ((Laura leans in and grabs upper left piece))
14 Lau: Loo:k I’ll make the cow for you.
15 (0.9) ((Laura moves upper right piece to upper left))
16 Lau: I’ll help you, put that one here. ((Laura points; Tony resists))
17 Tony: Eh- [↑NO DON’[T HELP me::! ((slides 2 upper left pieces back))
18 Lau: [You- [((Laura withdraws arm and leans head on r. hand))
19 Lau: You wanna try it yourself?
20 (6.0) ((Tony slides pieces to line them up))
21 Lau: Oka:::y?
22 (5.2) ((Tony slides upper row to line up with lower))
23 Lau: ((pointing to and gesturing with upper middle piece)) Turn this
24 one arou::nd. °Turn this one arou:nd.°
25 (2.8) ((Tony turns it quarter way around))
26 Lau: One muh-all:: the way around.
27 (2.0) ((Tony turns it further))
28 Lau: Oka::y?
29 (1.2) ((T moves lower l. & r. pieces slightly))
30 Lau: No:::w::? let’s see . . .
Instead of complying with Laura, Tony, from the very outset (lines 2–4), takes
over the manipulation of puzzle pieces and, immediately after Laura’s line 1 di-
rective, issues a counter-directive (“watch,” line 3).
incorporating the design of the test instrument—the affordances for tactile em-
bodiment presented by the puzzle pieces—such that Tony can orient to the task dif-
ferently from what is proposed to him. Tony’s first-order competence in knowing
how to redirect the activity is also collaborative, in that he does obtain compliance
from Laura. Following her initial exhibit of watching (line 4), she eventually (line
19) aligns to his activity (“you wanna try it yourself?”). This follows his display
of affect through the prosody of his “No don’t help me” response (line 17). Tony’s
stance, and indeed its very prosody, in the way that it occasions such alignment, is
also a form of first-order competence that children in typical family environments
use to resist parental directives (Goodwin, Cekaite, and Goodwin 2012:29).
Motivational Accounting
The directive-response sequences do not work well—there continues to be in-
tense competition over first and second position, and eventually the participants
give up on the matter. Or, more accurately, Laura gives up and, shortly after the
more successful exchange at lines 23–30 in Extract 2a, says to Tony, “We’re all
done with the cow.” They then put the puzzle pieces away.
Subsequently, in both the pre-staffing case conference and the staffing—the
informing interview where the results and diagnosis were delivered to Tony’s
parents and teachers—the clinicians refer to Tony’s actions during the cow puzzle
episode. In the case conference, an occupational therapist (OT) was discussing
Tony’s “tactile system” and his “hyper” responsiveness when she next stated,
“Uh, he’s very much into not being helped.” Laura immediately began nodding
her head, produced several beats of laughter and, when the OT began a further
report, “And it seemed more like . . . ,” finished the utterance with “HIS way,”
adding “You have to help him his way.” During this talk, a speech and language
student produced continuous laughter, and the OT finalized matters by saying,
“Yeah, it’s an independence thing, not so much that he doesn’t like to be han-
dled or touched; it’s more—he wanted to do it his way,” thereby fully agreeing
with Laura. Accordingly, the interactional dynamics during the puzzle episode
are reduced to a matter of Tony’s motivation, while the parties also exhibit an af-
fective dimension to their perceptions by smiling and laughing.
These features are also exhibited at the informing interview involving the
parents. The following episode (Extract 2 below) occurs during the discussion
of testing results, where the diagnosis has not yet been broached. “Molly” is the
psychiatrist on the team who examined Tony; at lines 1–5, on the parents’ be-
half, she asks her colleagues for an example of “some of the concepts” that Tony
is “currently working on.” At line 6, Laura prefaces a story referencing the cow
puzzle (although not explicitly naming it). The story follows a pattern with three
aspects: First, Laura offers contrastive versions of Tony’s tendencies. One is that
“awhile ago he wanted help with everything” (line 8), whereas “now” (lines 8,
462 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Remarkably, after Laura pulls her arm back and says, “You wanna try it yourself,”
as a kind of permissive directive (line 19), leaning her chin on her arm to watch
what he does with the tiles (Figures 17.2b and c) and subsequently issuing direct-
ives about placement (lines 23–24, 26, and Figure 17.2d), Tony complies (lines
25, 27). But now these directives by Laura are not strictly in first position within
Figure 17.2b After Tony says, “No don’t help me!” (line 17)
464 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Figure 17.2c Laura watches Tony slide the puzzle pieces (line 20)
Figure 17.2e “He opens the door;” Laura watches (line 41).
466 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
and Tony also takes the piece and returns it to where it was. He responds with
further, embodied counter-directives, persisting with exhibits of three-dimen-
sional manipulations of the puzzle pieces (Figure 17.2f and lines 54, 56, 58),
and rejecting her offer of help with the verbalization at line 59.
47 (2.0)
48 Tony: Watch:.
49 Lau: No::? This piece goes up here.
50 (1.4)
51 Lau: We put that piece ov[er here
52 Tony: [↑Don’t help me::.
53 Lau: Then ↑you do it.
54 (16.4)
55 Lau: Did you make a co:::w?
56 (2.0)
57 Lau: Or do you need help.
58 (1.3)
59 Tony: I don’t need he::lp.
60 Lau: You ↑do::n’t. Oka::y.
61 (1.8)
62 Lau: Okay, hey you know what?
63 (1.0)
64 Lau: We’ve got a:nother puzzle here to ma:ke.
Finally, Laura gives up, closing the current activity and transitioning to a new
one (lines 62, 64).
As with Dan’s experience of announcing that he knows “how to learn to
drive,” we can wonder if Tony may have been successful with this exercise had
Laura continued with her so-far inadvertent relinquishing of control to him, as
in Extract 17.2a, and use of follow-in directives to guide him through assem-
bling the puzzle, as in 17.2a, lines 19–30 and 17.2c. Such an approach may have
facilitated Tony’s completion of the puzzle and provided for the particulariza-
tion of his diagnosis and treatment. The protocols also permit it—Tony, having
“partially” completed the puzzle (“at least two of the pieces are correctly placed”)
could have been scored on this item as showing “emerging” skills (Schopler and
Reichler 1979:28). According to the test instructions, it also was permissible
for the clinician to demonstrate the task. However, it is not our aim to second-
guess or critique Laura’s handling of the cow puzzle exercise. She was, overall,
following the directions for “Completing the Six-Piece Cow Puzzle” from the
Psychoeducational Profile, fully engaged in competent common-sense testing
as a form of assessment in the clinic. More generally, her reactions to Tony’s
noncompliance were in line with how anyone might deal with the violation of
assumptions surrounding the requirements of ordinary, common-sense con-
duct, whether inside or outside of the clinic per se.
468 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Discussion
In the now vast literature on ASD, a focus on the disability as a property of the in-
dividual child is reflected in many ways. A prominent one has been the idea that
children with autism lack “theory of mind” or the capacity to infer the thoughts
or perspective of another person (e.g., Frith 2003:80). This position has been
subject to critique because, for example, it has “individualized the problem of so-
cial understanding,” pointing toward properties of mind or cognition to explain
conduct as if it occurred in a social vacuum (Leudar and Costall 2009:2, 12). In
the clinic, by minimizing the potential contributions both of test instrument de-
sign and their own practices to a child’s performances, clinicians contribute to
this individualizing process (Turowetz 2015a).
We have explored a further feature of this individualizing, which is the psy-
chologizing of disruption—seeing it as stemming from the motivational stance
of a child. Faced with lack of compliance withīn the common-sense order of
testing, there is an inherent inclination—a sense of “moral outrage,” as Heritage
(1984b:82) puts it in relation to Garfinkel’s (1967) demonstrations—to see such
conduct as either willful or deranged; the perpetrator is the “stranger,” or Other,
who “has to place in question what seems unquestionable to the in-group”
(Schütz 1944:499). In the two instances we analyzed (which represent a larger
collection), it is not so much that, during an examination, the child fails par-
ticular items, but rather that he withdraws from participation in the interac-
tional substrate that makes the completion of testing possible in the first place
(Maynard and Marlaire 1992). However, this withdrawal is not necessarily pur-
poseful or contrived, and instead is demonstrative of what can be construed as
among the “immensely various forms of reasoning” to which Garfinkel (1967:31)
originally called attention. It is strategic.
During Dan’s examination, accordingly, there was recurrent refusal to follow
what the clinician repeatedly asked him to do: demonstrating how to brush one’s
teeth. From the interior of the test, clinicians saw Dan as not wanting to do the
tooth-brushing demonstration. And retrospectively, the suggestion was that
Dan was feeling “put on the spot,” whereas his own sense could better be seen as
an inability skill-wise or performance-wise, rather than a matter of intention-
ality. In Tony’s testing, there was defiance regarding who could direct whom to
do what with the six-piece cow puzzle—that is, whether the task would involve
assembling a two-dimensional picture or engaging the pieces in a more tac-
tile, three-dimensional activity. Laura’s insistent efforts to align Tony to assem-
bling a picture tacitly suggest an orientation to motivating him, and her later
characterizations suggest she was unable to do this because of Tony’s struggles
for independence and, in the psychiatrist’s words, his emerging “pride.” In in-
teractional terms, however, it is apparent that he was oriented to an entirely
Ethnomethodology and Atypical Interaction 469
Conclusion
References
Antaki, Charles, and Ray Wilkinson. 2012. “Conversation Analysis and the Study of
Atypical Populations.” Pp. 533–50 in Handbook of Conversation Analysis, edited by J.
Sidnell and T. Stivers. New York: Blackwell.
APA. 1980. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders: DSM-III. Washington,
DC: American Psychiatric Association.
Ethnomethodology and Atypical Interaction 471
APA. 2013. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders: DSM-5. Arlington,
VA: American Psychiatric Association.
Asperger, Hans. [1944] 1991. “‘Autistic Psychopathy’ in Childhood.” Pp. 37–92 in Autism
and Asperger Syndrome, edited by U. Frith. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Brigham, Nicolette Bainbridge, Paul J. Yoder, Melanie A. Jarzynka and Jon Tapp. 2010.
“The Sequential Relationship between Parent Attentional Cues and Sustained Attention
to Objects in Young Children with Autism.” Journal of Autism and Developmental
Disorders 40:200–8.
Cekaite, Asta. 2010. “Shepherding the Child: Embodied Directive Sequences in Parent-
Child Interactions.” Text & Talk 30:1–25.
Coulter, Jeff. 1975. “Perceptual Accounts and Interpretive Asymmetries.” Sociology
9:385–96.
Coulter, Jeff. 1979. The Social Construction of Mind. London: Macmillan.
Craven, Alexandra, and Jonathan Potter. 2010. “Directives: Entitlement and Contingency
in Action.” Discourse Studies 12(4):419–42.
Curl, Traci S., and Paul Drew. 2008. “Contingency and Action: A Comparison of Two
Forms of Requesting.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 41:129–53.
Dawson, Michelle, Isabelle Soulière, Morton Ann Gernsbacher, and Laurent Mottron.
2007. “The Level and Nature of Autistic Intelligence.” Psychological Science 18:657–61.
Erickson, Frederick. 2007. “Some Thoughts on ‘Proximal’ Formative Assessment of Student
Learning.” Yearbook of the National Society for the Study of Education 106(1):187–216.
Ervin-Tripp, Susan. 1976. “Is Sybil There? The Structure of Some American English
Directives.” Language in Society 5:25–66.
Eveleth, Rose. 2011. “The Hidden Potential of Autistic Kids.” Scientific American. Retrieved
at https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/the-hidden-potential-of-autistic-kids/.
Foucault, Michel. 1975. The Birth of the Clinic: An Archaelogy of Medical Perception.
New York: Vintage.
Frith, Uta. 2003. Autism: Explaining the Enigma. 2nd edition. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1963. “A Conception of, and Experiments with, ‘Trust’ as a Condition
of Stable Concerted Actions.” Pp. 187–238 in Motivation and Social Interaction, edited
by O. J. Harvey. New York: Ronald Press.
Garfinkel, Harold. 1967. Studies in Ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Gibson, James J. 1986. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum.
Glenn, Phillip. 1995. “Laughing at and Laughing with: Negotiations of Participant
Alignments through Conversational Laughter.” Pp. 43–56 in Situated Order: Studies
in the Social Organization of Talk and Embodied Activities, edited by P. T. Have and G.
Psathas. Washington, DC: University Press of America.
Goffman, Erving. 1971. Relations in Public: Microstudies of the Public Order. New York:
Harper and Row.
Goode, David. 1984. A World without Words: The Social Construction of Children Born
Deaf and Blind. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Goodwin, Charles. 2003a. “Introduction.” Pp. 1–20 in Conversation and Brain Damage,
edited by C. Goodwin. New York: Oxford University Press.
Goodwin, Charles, ed. 2003b. Conversation and Brain Damage. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Goodwin, Marjorie, and Asta Cekaite. 2014. “Orchestrating Directive Trajectories in
Communicative Projects in Family Interaction.” Pp. 187–214 in Requesting in Social
472 THE ETHNOMETHODOLOGY PROGRAM
Chapter 1
purpose was to develop training protocols for mechanics to perform aircraft main-
tenance duties for cargo planes. Often the trainees were lacking education, had occu-
pational experiences (farming, baking, teaching, construction) unrelated to airplane
mechanics, were without real engines to work on, adequate equipment, and basic
tools such as screwdrivers. Classroom lectures and instruction did not help with the
hands-on work of maintenance. Trainees were provided with “mock-ups” or models
meant to illustrate how the machinery would look in situ, and what manipulations
would be needed. However, these models were of limited use for configuring main-
tenance as actual embodied tasks. The ways in which Garfinkel’s study anticipates
later concerns with what he called the shop floor problem, instructed action, and hy-
brid studies of work are developed insightfully in Rawls and Lynch’s (2019) intro-
duction to the Gulfport Field study, which suggests the possibility for a re-reading
of the genealogy of ethnomethodology different from the usually cited influences of
Parsons, Schutz, Gurwitsch, and related others. That is, Garfinkel’s identification of
phenomena associated with bricolage, hands-on work, improvisation, and order in
detail is already present in the heavily ethnographic Gulfport Field history of 1942.
14. Garfinkel’s approach to the assembly of suicide statistics reaches back to earlier
studies of homicide, discussed earlier in this chapter. See also Cicourel (1964).
15. Here, we are distinguishing more strictly ethnomethodological studies from studies
involving “membership categories” and “membership categorization devices,” which
were discussed earlier.
Chapter 2
1. Unless otherwise specified, the positions attributed to these men is either taken di-
rectly from or is based on the following writings. For Talcott Parsons: The Structure of
Social Action, McGraw-Hill Book Co., 1937; Actor, Situation, and Normative Pattern,
unpublished manuscript, 1939; Essays in Sociological Theory Pure and Applied, The
Free Press, 1949, especially Chapters I, II, III, and IV; The Social System, The Free Press,
1951; Talcott Parsons and Edward Shils: Toward a General Theory of Action, Harvard
University Press, 1951; especially Part I, Chapter I, and Part 2; Max Weber: The
Theory of Social and Economic Organization, Oxford University Press, especially the
Introduction.
For Alfred Schütz: Der Sinnhafte Aufbau Der Sozialen Welt, Verlag von Julius
Springer, Wien, 1932; “The Problem of Rationality in the Social World,” Economica,
Vol. X, May, 1943, 130– 149; “Phenomenology and the Social Sciences,” in
Philosophical Essays in Memory of Edmund Husserl, edited by Marvin Farber,
Harvard University Press, 1940, pp. 164–186; “Language, Language Disturbances
and the Texture of Consciousness,” Social Research, Vol. 17, September, 1950,
pp. 365–394; “Sartre’s Theory of the Alter Ego,” Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, Vol. IX, December, 1948, pp. 181–199; “On Multiple Realities,” Philosophy
and Phenomenological Research, Vol. V, June, 1945, pp. 533–575; “Choosing among
Notes 479
Chapter 3
1. The words Self, Black, Jew, Race, Gender, Transsexual, Transgender, and Other are cap-
italized here to indicate that they are names for social facts and not natural or biolog-
ical states. Trust is also capitalized to indicate that it names the prerequisites for social
fact-making and not a state of the person.
2. There was a collaboration between Garfinkel and Goffman in 1962 to publish
Stigma and the “Agnes” chapter together in a book that was to be titled “On Passing.”
Garfinkel got the new material on Agnes that would appear in the appendix to Studies
in Ethnomethodology about a month before publication. He told Goffman to find out
whether the publisher would go ahead with a monograph on Stigma. If not, then if
Goffman would wait Garfinkel would be ready. The publisher was happy to go ahead,
and so the book Stigma was published alone by Goffman.
3. Early correspondence with Tamotsu Shibutani in the Garfinkel Archive shows that
Goffman was giving Shibutani early drafts of Garfinkel’s work and that Shibutani had
sent at least one early draft of his own work to Garfinkel with the comment that his
ideas had been inspired by Garfinkel.
480 Notes
4. See note 8.
5. Garfinkel undertook this adventure on advice from a Quaker instructor at the
University of Newark on how to make connections with students from outside the
Newark Jewish community. It was students at this camp who told him about the pro-
gram at North Carolina under Odum.
6. Unknown to Garfinkel at the time, the incident involved Pauli Murray, a well-known
feminist civil rights activist. To complicate matters, Murray was secretly a cross-
dressing female—identified by Garfinkel as an adolescent boy. Garfinkel’s descrip-
tion of Murray as a “boy” is consistent with his discussion of Agnes (a Transgendered
person) as a woman. Murray “presented” as a boy—and hoped to be seen as a boy.
Garfinkel obliged. But this apparently upset the civil rights activists who objected
to his description of Murray. Garfinkel considered the successful performance of
Gender to settle the question. In this he was ahead of his time. That Garfinkel “mis-
took” Murray for a boy is not an “error” in his analysis. It was due to her own success in
presenting herself as a boy and consistent with his later analysis of Agnes (which has
also been misunderstood). Murray—performing successfully as a boy—was a boy.
It is interesting to note, however, that in his description Garfinkel refers to the “boy”
as “flat chested,” which suggests he may have been sensitive to some Transgender as-
pect of the presentation. Murray recognized Garfinkel’s description of the incident
while still in jail and the article has become associated with Murray’s arrest in the
history of the civil rights movement. Glenda Gilmore (2008) wrote about it in Defying
Dixie, taking Garfinkel to task for not being clear that the incident was true (likely be-
cause it was reprinted in 1941 and 1945 without his knowledge as fiction). Rosalind
Rosenberg (2017), a civil rights historian, focused on discrepancies between the
accounts of Garfinkel and Murray. Murray’s account can be found in the Harvard
University Schlesinger archive.
7. Garfinkel’s admission to North Carolina is a case in point. When he showed up on
Odum’s doorstep, having hitchhiked from Georgia, he reports Odum saying, “You are
a Jew from Newark come to the South. I admit you.”
8. The 1940s were a time of profound anti-Semitism in sociology. In his 1943 Presidential
Address to the ASA, Lundberg explicitly named Jews as the problem with sociology
because they were interested in social justice (Lundberg 1944). Others strongly iden-
tified sociology with Christianity (Madge 1962). Lewis Coser (1975), in his 1974 pres-
idential address to the ASA, criticized Garfinkel with reference to the Bible, referring
to his students and colleagues as apostles. During the war, Jewish sociologists and so-
cial philosophers fled to America from Europe. The country may have provided a safe
haven from Hitler, but it was not welcoming to Jews. Heims (1991:49) cites a letter
written on behalf of a Jewish faculty member at Harvard protesting his dismissal in
1943 that is instructive. In defense of this Jewish scholar, the letter says he “has a Jewish
name but his Jewish ancestry is remote. He has none of the unpleasant characteris-
tics sometimes associated with the Jew.” Garfinkel came out of Newark with a cohort
of Jewish friends and they were the ones who finally got him the job at UCLA. The
striking lack of recognition of Garfinkel from the “recorders” of disciplinary history
may well have racial overtones.
Notes 481
Chapter 4
1. The idea that ethnomethodology is an “improbable sociology” was used in the title for
a meeting “Ethnomethodology, an Improbable Sociology?” held in 1997 at Cerisy-la-
Salle, Normandy. The published volume from the meeting substituted “radical” for
“improbable” in the title (Ogien, Fornel, and Quéré 2001).
2. When Garfinkel proposed to make a radical break from previous sociological and
ethnomethodological studies, including his own studies, he did not abandon the
major themes developed in Studies in Ethnomethodology (1967), such as indexicality,
reflexivity, and accountability, and he drew upon materials from research that he had
begun years and decades earlier. He also deployed pedagogical exercises and equip-
ment such as inverting lenses, which he had used for many years for disrupting, and
thus revealing, the coherence and coordination of embodied actions (Garfinkel
2002:207ff.). To put it very succinctly, Garfinkel’s “radical” program, which Arminen
(2008) distinguishes from “scientific” ethnomethodology and Wilson (2012)
distinguishes from the “classical” ethnomethodology represented in Garfinkel’s re-
search up until around 1962, severed any residual links with traditions of interpretive
social science. Garfinkel eschewed the use of “formal analysis” in studies of practical
actions; analysis that posits tacit rules and underlying orders, deploys mechanical
analogies, and/or administers theoretical and methodological constructs. And, via
the unique adequacy requirement, he insisted that the grounds of adequate social
482 Notes
for addressing how such talk may be, or should be, accountable to patients, jurors, or
clients. But formal structures of institutional talk, or even generic features of visuali-
zation in science, medicine, and other fields (Goodwin 1994, 1995; Koschmann et al.
2011; Lynch 1991; Mondada 2003), are not what Garfinkel was after in his, perhaps
quixotic, pursuit of the “just what” constitutes the distinctive competencies through
which legal relevancies and evidences are achieved, discoveries are established, or
possible diagnostic evidences are explored and tested. His aim (or, rather, his hope)
was that uniquely adequate “hybrid” studies would become contributions to the fields
with which the studies engaged, in addition to adding to the literatures in sociology,
sociolinguistics, and ethnomethodology/conversation analysis.
16. On the question of whether this presumption is in play in a given case, compare
Suchman and Jordan (1990) with Maynard and Schaeffer (2000).
Chapter 5
Chapter 6
1. The Golden City Police Department outlines these exceptions: “The law . . . does not
apply to any person: (1) sitting or lying on the sidewalk due to a medical emergency;
(2) using a wheelchair, walker or similar device as a result of a disability, (3) operating
or patronizing a commercial establishment conducted on a public sidewalk under a
sidewalk use permit; (4) participating in or attending a parade, festival, performance,
rally, demonstration, meeting or similar event conducted on a sidewalk under and in
compliance with a street use or other applicable permit; (5) sitting on a fixed chair or
bench supplied by a public agency or abutting private property owner; (6) sitting in
Notes 485
line for goods or services if not impeding pedestrians from using the sidewalk or en-
tering a door or other entrance along the sidewalk; (7) who is a child in a stroller; and
(8) in an area designated as a Pavement to Parks project” (Golden City Police Code
Article 2 § 168 (D) (2010)).
2. We add “chronic” as a modifier of “homeless” because persons who are only tempo-
rarily homeless may live in cars, move between the houses of friends and relatives, or
stay briefly in shelters, and thus may not live for sustained periods on the street in the
way that chronically homeless residents do (e.g., with their sleeping bags and other be-
longings). Thus, when members of the public refer to the “homeless” they are typically
referring to chronically homeless persons.
3. The Golden City Police Department outlines these penalties: “A first offense is an in-
fraction and could result in a citation. If that citation results in a conviction, the pen-
alty is a fine between $50–100 and/or community service. If someone violates the law
again, within 24 hours of receiving a citation, the person is guilty of a misdemeanor.
The penalty for a conviction increases, to a fine between $300–500, and/or community
service, and/or up to 10 days in County Jail. If someone violates the law within 120
days of a conviction, that offense is also a misdemeanor, and the penalty for a convic-
tion is a fine between $400–500, and/or community service, and/or up to 30 days im-
prisonment in County Jail.”
4. As written, the CSO also applies to every person in the city. In practice, however, po-
lice officers and members of the public treat the ordinance as applying specifically to
homeless persons. For example, patterns of enforcement adopted by the GCPD are
specifically sensitive to the daily routines of homeless residents, and persons who
claim they should not be subject to its provisions typically do so by claiming that
they are not homeless. A news article on the law quotes the experience of one res-
ident of the city, “Thirty-one-year-old Derrick Gomez has lived in Golden City on
and off for the past seven years. He recently came back to the [Park neighborhood]
and says it only took a few days to encounter an officer. ‘I was sitting down talking
to a kid, I was having my coffee,’ he says. ‘It was literally breakfast—7:30, 8 a.m.—
just kneeled down to talk to a kid. A cop just happened to roll up, just assumes that
I’m homeless and whatnot.’ ” (http://kalw.org/post/how-effective-are-sitlie-laws#str
eam/0). As this quote suggests, members of the public treat being subject to enforce-
ment of the CSO as category bound to a person’s status as homeless (see Sacks 1992;
Schegloff 2007).
Chapter 7
1. See Goodwin and Goodwin (1987) for more detailed analysis of such format tying or
dialogic syntax (Du Bois 2014).
2. Conversation analysts note that turns-at-talk that are NOT to be heard as tied to the
utterance they follow (from the perspective of the present argument as not to be ana-
lyzed as operations on the current local substrate) characteristically begin with an ex-
plicit misplacement marker (Sacks and Schegloff 1973).
486 Notes
Chapter 8
1. Garfinkel used the terms “sex,” “sex status,” and “sexual” in instances where sociologists
would now typically use “gender” and “gender identity.”
2. Sociologist Raewyn Connell (2009) argues that Agnes’s case carries a canonical status in
sociology that is comparable to Freud’s case study of “the Wolf Man” in psychoanalysis.
Notes 487
3. I am indebted to Anne Rawls for her generosity in providing access to these materials.
4. The term “passing” had been in colloquial use since the nineteenth century to refer to
racial minorities in America who were able to live and work as white (see Hobbs 2014
for a detailed history). Garfinkel adopted a sociological understanding of “passing”
as a general social process whereby members of a marginalized or oppressed mi-
nority seek to escape persecution or discrimination by “losing their identity with the
minority and becoming absorbed into the majority” (Burma 1946:18). While Erving
Goffman (1963) used this concept in a similar way in Stigma, Garfinkel adopted it first
in a 1960 article he coauthored with Stoller (Stoller, Garfinkel, and Rosen 1960).
5. Suzanne Kessler and Wendy McKenna (1978:155) would later transform this insight
into their concept of “cultural genitals,” “the one[s]assumed to exist and which, it is
believed, should be there” on the basis of a person’s appearance.
6. While early sociologists of gender, such as Mirra Komarovsky and Alice Rossi,
and second wave activists, such as Betty Friedan, critiqued the classist and sexist
assumptions embedded in this functionalist perspective, a narrow analytic focus on
sex roles persisted in sociology well into the 1980s (Fuchs-Epstein 1988).
7. Simone De Beauvoir had made such an analytic split much earlier in The Second Sex
with her now-famous line, “One is not born but rather becomes a woman” (Meyerowitz
2002). Sexologist John Money also championed a split between sex and gender, though
his definition did not gain the same prominence as that of Stoller (Goldie 2014).
8. A similar passage is included in his 1967 chapter on page 183–184. However, he tem-
pered his critique, as he attributes this critique to Agnes’s worldview, rather than
his own.
Chapter 9
1. Pollner’s critique of Becker anticipated by over a decade Woolgar and Pawluch’s (1985)
critique of what they called “ontological gerrymandering,” or the strategically selec-
tive commitment to both a radical constructionism and orthodox objectivism. For
a sample of the debates that ensued among social constructionist theorists of social
problems concerning ontological gerrymandering, see Holstein and Miller (1993),
Schneider (2019) and Weinberg (2014:113–33). For a recent discussion of Pollner’s
continuing relevance to social constructionist debates about social problems, see
Crawley (2019).
Chapter 10
1. Later we address Sacks’s decision to focus on the analysis of individual social actions
rather than common-sense knowledge or reasoning, his investigation of sequences of
action both for capturing the orderly temporal unfolding of talk, and as a method for
488 Notes
Chapter 11
1. The use of the asterisk (*) refers to order as a member’s phenomenon and ordinary
achievement “as the most ordinary achieved organizational thing[s]in the world”
(Garfinkel 2002:117), and therefore treated as a topic to be investigated, rather than a
notion theorized by the analyst.
2. See http://www.mpi.nl/corpus/html/elan/index.html.
Chapter 12
have been one of the latter kind (an “anomaly”). In this respect, we may note that the
positive bias toward potential theoretical innovation, rather than actual empirical
discovery (what Brannigan calls “simple factual discovery”), has been particularly
common among philosophers of science (Hacking 1983:149–50).
3. While the “pulsar paper” acknowledged the Gestalt character of the astronomical
discovery in analogical terms (as a progressively shaped “potter’s object,” Garfinkel
et al. 1981), it did not describe the “functional significance” of the successive
procedures, in and for the discovery’s local production. In turn, the present “spec-
trum chapter” makes explicit the heuristic interest of reflexive re-enactment, in and
for the video analysis of experimental physics and the local production of (one of) its
current discoveries.
4. A Jefferson-style transcription notation is used in the following. Additionally, the
onset of nonverbal activity is indicated by one sign per participant (see also Mondada,
Chapter 11 in this volume). If there is a verbal line, the onset of activity is marked on
the verbal line and again on the comment line, as in the following example:
In turn, double square brackets, [[ ]], have been used in the bulk of the text to indi-
cate that the mentioned tasks were devised as part of a [tip-sample approach] proce-
dure. On the analytic use of brackets, see Garfinkel and Sacks (1970); see also Lynch
(1993:289–90). Finally, I have circled the phenomena of manifest interest to the ex-
perimentalist and, whenever judged necessary, added schematic drawings to indicate
them (see the lower right corner of film stills in question).
5. I did not manage to ask this question in situ, let alone to have it answered right away.
Indeed, once Pete had formulated one task, he was already engaging in the next one,
leaving me at least with two questions and no slot to have them raised. For further
analysis along these lines, see Sormani (2014:201–211).
6. As Pete would open the “approach” window of the STM interface on his computer
screen to launch the [[automatic approach]] of tip and sample, he would open the
“spectro” window to prepare his subsequent [local spectroscopies]. In particular, this
window presented him with a grid view of the sample surface, allowing him to position
the tip in various corners of the sample, just prior to its spectroscopic inspection in the
selected position.
7. Having been used during prior topography to scan the sample surface, the “topo filter”
is useless for spectroscopy—worse: it renders spectroscopy impossible, as it filters out
the signal of physical interest. This was Pete’s answer to one of my later transcript-re-
lated questions.
8. The “double gap” displayed in the “spectro” window, in contrast to a “single gap,” would
be taken as the decisive indication of multi-band superconductivity in PbMo6S8. As
Pete put it subsequently to the transcribed episode, “now I know it’s true, the physical
model in there is true.” For a detailed analysis of this formulated confirmation and its
sequential context, see Sormani (2011).
490 Notes
9. Similar patterns of celebration are to be observed on the football pitch, at the very
moment a goal is about to be scored. Exploring the possible connection between
Pete’s “primary socialization” as an amateur football player and his manifest expertise
in experimental physics is beyond the scope of this chapter. However, I observed Pete
watching a Premier League game of soccer, once he had finished his [local spectros-
copy] that Sunday morning of November 9, 2008.
10. Or a double m-shaped curve (the so-called double gap) since a “multi-band” super-
conductor was (or appears to have been) successfully probed, as in the case of the
local spectroscopy of PbMo6S8. For a tentatively technical explication of the graphi-
cally displayed equation, see Sormani (2014:26–32).
Chapter 13
be said to be, to have involved, or to have shown is therefore not fixed but mutable, and
necessarily so: without the ad hoc adjustments, researchers would have no phenomena
to exhibit.
5. Here is Garfinkel (1967:8–9): “When I propose that members are ‘not interested’ . . . ,
I do not mean that members will have none, a little, or a lot of it. That they are ‘not
interested’ has to do with reasonable practices, with plausible argument, and with rea-
sonable findings. . . . [T]hough they would, they can have none of it.”
6. It is not that the statistical operations are irrelevant: far from it, it is the strength of that
work which would be assessed by the professional audiences to whom it would ulti-
mately be directed. Nonetheless, those evaluations would also take for granted what
is known in common as the parameters within which judgments could be made about
the work’s social scientific qualities, i.e., whether it could be adjudged to offer a reason-
able account of what we all already know about the social world.
7. The entire research project had to take place in the period between successive waves
of the annual longitudinal survey, ensuring they left enough of a gap that participants
wouldn’t complain of being over-surveyed.
8. The references to “fives” and “twos” in these extracts relate to people who fall within
the cluster groups generated by the quantitative analysis—among other things, sam-
pling decisions meant identifying areas where “cluster incumbents,” i.e., “ones,” “twos,”
“threes,” “fours,” and “fives,” could be found in particular concentrations. As an array,
“ones” and “fives” would be at different ends of a respondent spectrum that ranged
from the socially well connected to the socially disconnected.
Chapter 14
Chapter 16
1. There are other possibilities—such as the way Actor-Network Theory used and
reworked some ethnomethodological sensibilities, the use of ethnomethodology in
the social studies of science, where ethnomethodology had been influential, or the
combination of ethnomethodology sensibilities with conversation analytic and eth-
nographic methods in studies of work and other endeavors. I hope, however, that
practitioners within these traditions will recognize their predicament in the examples
I have chosen.
2. There is a rich literature on CA. For the purposes of this section, I mostly rely on the
work of Schegloff and (to a lesser extent) Sacks, since they are its prime architects.
3. Note here that, consistent with CA’s critique of other theoretical stances, intersub-
jectivity is not assumed (as it is with Schütz [1932] 1967, where it is considered an
492 Notes
immediately given experience of the other) but is shown to require ongoing, delicate,
work: it is an achievement, not a given.
4. This section is heavily indebted to Jack Katz’s mode of training graduate students.
Chapter 17
1. As the title implies, Watts means that once we know an outcome of some social process,
it is easy and tempting to engage in post hoc theorizing or storytelling to suggest how
it was made possible. We select a few factors that, by the compelling nature of common
sense, seem utterly relevant, and figure that we’ve explained the phenomenon, whereas
really all we have done is to describe the orderly process of what happened rather than
why it happened. Despite its inbuilt power to convince, we are not going to be able to
predict anything with this retrospective use of commonsense. That critique is most
certainly a valid one.
2. Mates (2013), Mikesell (2013), and Smith (2013) take explicitly ethnomethodolog-
ical approaches to the understanding and analysis of interactions where patients with
fronto-temporal dementia (FTD) engage in behaviors that caregivers perceive, and
may treat, as inappropriate, thus making visible such properties of interaction as the
expectation of “progressivity.” See also Goodwin’s edited book on conversation and
brain damage (2003b) and especially Schegloff ’s (2003) chapter in that volume.
3. The relation between the disorderly aspects of autism and commonsense is well rec-
ognized in autobiographical (Grandin 1995:37–38) as well as scholarly literature (e.g.,
Frith 2003:47) regarding the syndrome.
4. More specifically: “This activity assesses the participant’s ability to communicate about
a familiar series of actions using gesture or mime with accompanying language, and to
report on a routine event” (Lord et al. 2012:113).
5. See Hollin and Pilnick’s (2018:1220–21) consideration of a case in which a young adult
is being assessed by way of the ADOS. About the Demonstration Task, the clinician
proposes that he “might feel a bit silly doing it,” and then asks him to pretend that she
is a “small child” who does not know how to do the task. The client refuses to perform
the task, and when asked why, he says, “I can’t imagine you to be a ch(h)ild.” (The par-
enthetical “h” in “ch(h)ild)” indicates a laughter token.)
6. The “you-did” utterance is like the “newsmarks” that Heritage (1984a:342) investigates,
which are not syntactically formatted as queries and can signal pre-disagreement.
7. Stivers and Sidnell (2016) show that in everyday play activities, children use “Let’s X”
to propose a new joint activity, whereas “How about X” signifies a modification of the
ongoing activity in a way that decreases the distance between the new and the prior
activities.
8. The helping literature on autism discusses the importance of distinguishing between
“can’t” and “won’t” in the responses to instructions and requests on the part of individ-
uals on the spectrum. See, for example, Notbohm (2012).
9. As Hollin and Pilnick (2018:1217) suggest, clinicians may formulate behavior such as
Dan’s “as evidence of fixed traits, rather than responses to the specific environment.”
Notes 493
10. As developers of the ADOS note (Lord et al. 1989:187), the exam is an “interactive
schedule,” where the attempt is to standardize the social context for observing the
behavior of a child. The purpose is “to encourage an interaction that appears natural,”
while also providing “comparable social stimuli for all subjects.” This allows for fol-
lowing relevant social leads of the child.
11. From Dan’s perspective, Jen may be doing something inapposite (in addition to
ignoring his refusals): since he already knows what she’s telling him, she is pro-
viding redundant information—and doing so despite her newsmark, which appears
to treat Dan’s announcement as newsworthy. If so, the possibility is that Jen is also
committing a breach relative to the sense-making of Dan’s embodied conduct, albeit
one that’s invisible to her because of her own anchoring in the common-sense order
of testing.
12. As Maynard (2005) observes about a different subtest from the Brigance Diagnostic
Inventory of Early Development, a child taking the subtest needs not only to be com-
pliant with the immediacy of what he is being asked to do. The child also needs to
understand the overall structure of the testing—the larger course of action in which
specific test items and associated directives are embedded.
13. See note 4.
14. It is not only that Tony increases his volume with this utterance. A pitch diagram,
using Praat software, shows Tony’s normal pitch is about 200–400 Hertz, whereas the
“No don’t help me utterance” starts at 309 hertz and rises to 618 hertz before dropping
back into his normal pitch range. In their data from parent-(typical) child interactions
at home, Goodwin et al. (2012:29) found that children’s refusals of parental direct-
ives were done most dramatically through pitch leaps with rise-fall contours, to
which Tony’s refusal is quite parallel. In addition, children’s refusals exhibited vowel
stretching, as does Tony’s on the word “me” at utterance end. The overall suggestion is
that Tony is using ordinary prosodic skills for his “emphatic” opposition to Laura as
he attempts to align her to his activity rather than pursue the testing activity as such.
15. See Wootton’s (1997:Chapter 2) documentation of how, by the third year of life,
children are able to take sequential understandings into account when engaging in
interaction. Exhibits of distressed behavior on the part of a child may be less an ex-
pression of an internal state and based more on breaches to trajectories that the child
has initiated. The child’s initiation and the action(s) it launches provide a moral war-
rant for the expression of indignation when the co-participant undermines the given
trajectory.
16. See note 7.
17. The concepts of summative and formative evaluation derive from the literature on
educational testing (Heritage 2013; Popham 2008; Sadler 1989). These concepts de-
rive from Scriven’s (1967) original publication and are applied mostly to classroom
learning. In our view, they are also relevant to clinical testing, although we have not
seen previous discussions of this potential.
18. For a thorough review, see Antaki and Wilkinson (2012).
Name Index
Abbott, Andrew, 27 Bittner, Egon, 12, 32, 36–37, 162, 165–166, 173,
Agha, Asif, 486n4 232–233, 236, 243, 477n7, 477n10
Alac, Morana, 123 Bjelić, Dušan I., 123, 341
Alexander, Jeffrey C., 184 Blalock, Hubert M., 14
Allsop, R. E., 405 Blomberg, Jeanette L., 27, 413
American Sociological Association, 2 Bloor, David, 119–121, 163
Anastasi, R., 400 Blumer, Herbert, 27
Andersen, H., 399, 413 Blundell, Stephen, 322–323, 325
Anderson, Elijah, 47 Boas, Evert van Emde, 19
Anderson, R. A., 400 Boden, Deirdre, 21, 32, 38, 126, 483n13
Anderson, R. J., 413 Body, R., 447
Angell, Beth, 172 Bogen, David, 24, 32–33, 238, 240, 349
Antaki, Charles, 21, 24, 493n18 Bolaños-Carpio, Alexa, 172
Antunes, Anna B., 325, 341 Bolden, Galina B., 172
Arar, Raphael, 39 Bourdieu, Pierre, 207, 245
Ariew, Roger, 437 Bowers, John, 399
Arminen, Illka, 429, 481n2 Bowman, Brett, 26
Asperger, Hans, 447 Brahe, Tycho, 189
Atkinson, Maxwell J., 12, 15–16, 19, 33, 40, 236, Brannigan, Augustine, 488n2
238, 429 Brasier, Martin D. 192
Brigham, Nicolette Bainbridge, 465
Baccus, Melinda, 356 Broeder, Dale W., 394
Bakhtin, Mikhail, 196 Broth, M., 292, 402
Bannister, Robert C., 229 Brown, Barry, 130, 295
Barlow, Alexandra, 41 Brown, Penelope, 19, 279
Barnes, Barry, 119 Brubaker, Rogers, 424, 433
Barnes, Rebecca, 38 Bruner, Jerome, 108, 111, 481nn13–15
Barston, Julie L., 371 Burma, John, 487n4
Barth-Weingarten, D., 486n4 Burnham, John P., 218, 220
Becker, Howard S., 27, 43, 117, 143–145, Burns, Stacy, 123, 127, 131, 236
230–231, 234, 241–242, 351, 431, 482n4, Büscher, Monika, 399
484n2, 487n1 Button, Graham, 34, 37–39, 43, 116, 120, 126,
Beckett, Megan, 430 128, 132, 252, 297, 399
Bell, Daniel, 230
Benford, Steve, 117, 400 Calhoun, Craig, 4
Benzecry, Claudio E., 352, 490n3 Callon, Michel, 121
Berard, Tim, 33, 241, 483n12 Camic, Charles M., 162, 348, 352
Berger, Peter L., 43 Casey, Neil, 297
Bergmann, Jörg, 23, 182 Cassirer, Ernst, 80
Berthod, Christophe, 323, 325, 341 Cekaite, Asta, 449, 453, 461, 465, 493n14
Best Short Stories of 1941, 96 Chambliss, William J., 167
Best, Joel, 228, 232 Chevrel, Roger, 323
Bierstedt, Robert, 159 Cho, Adrian, 323
Biggs, Michael, 437 Chomsky, Noam, 265
Billig, Michael, 24 Cicourel, Aaron, 12, 14, 16, 41–42, 150, 232–233,
Bishop, Somer L., 449, 452, 492n4 236, 477n10, 478n14, 484n6
496 Name Index
Clayman, Steven E., 17, 19, 21, 165, 182, 184–185, Dupret, Baudouin, 33, 236, 483n12
238–239, 245, 264, 278–279, 423, 426, 477n8, Durkheim, Émile, 14–15, 94, 111, 128, 236
483n12
Clegg, K., 447 Edge, David, 119
Cleverly, Jason, 400 Edwards, Derek, 22, 24, 477n5
Clift, Rebecca, 19, 488n6 Eglin, Peter, 240, 242
Cloward, Richard A., 230 Eilan, N., 295
Cohen, Albert K., 230 Elliott, Marc N., 430
Collins, Harry, 119, 121, 336, 482n5 Emerson, Robert M., 27, 236–237, 431, 434,
Collins, Patricia Hill, 45–46 477n7
Connell, Raewyn, 214, 222, 486n2 Emirbayer, Mustafa, 30, 477n8
Coser, Lewis, 17, 480n8 Enfield, Nicholas J., 19, 188, 279, 486n4
Costall, Alan, 468 Engelke, Christopher R., 44
Coulter, Jeff, 23–24, 236, 243, 295, 444, 477n5, Engeström, Y., 399
482n6, 488n2 Englert, Christina, 19, 279
Couper-Kuhlen, Elizabeth, 19, 49, 279 Erickson, Frederick, 465, 469
Cox, James R., 371 Erikson, Kai T., 230
Crabtree, Andrew, 116, 132, 400, 413 Ervin-Tripp, Susan, 449
Craven, Alexandra, 449, 451, 453 Euclid, 123
Crawley, Sara L., 487n1 Evaldsson, Ann-Carita, 47
Crittenden, Kathleen, 7–8, 271, 293 Evans, Jonathan St. B. T., 371
Csibra, Gergely. 207 Evans-Pritchard, E. E., 423
Curl, Traci S., 450–451, 459 Eveleth, Rose, 447
Czyzewski, Marek, 344 Ewick, Patricia, 179
David, Gary C., 33 Farber, Marvin, 478n1, 479n2
Davidson, Judy A., 276, 279 Fasula, Alessandra, 36
Davies, A. C., 405 Feischmidt, Margit, 433
Davis, Kingsley, 230 Felt, Ulrike, 323
Dawson, Michelle, 447, 449 Feltovich, Paul, 36, 38, 484n15
Day, Lincoln, 15 Fenstermaker, Sarah, 46, 215
Day, Sophie, 348, 357 Filippi, Geneviève, 399
De Beauvoir, Simone, 487n7 Fine, Gary Alan, 27
De Ruiter, Jan Peter, 19, 279 Finestone, Harold, 230
Decroux, Marc, 323, 325, 341 Fischer, Øystein, 323, 325, 341
Demuer, Alfredo, 325, 341 Fish, Stanley, 118, 357
Denzin, Norman K., 28, 214 Fitch, W. Tecumseh, 204
Derrida, Jacques, 349 Fitzgerald, Richard, 21–22
The Dictionary of Occupational Titles, 482n3 Flintham, M., 400
DiDomenico, Stephen M., 172 Ford, Cecilia E., 38
Diggins, T., 400 Fornel, Michel, 481n1
DiLavore, Pamela, C., 449, 452, 492n4 Foucault, Michel, 469
Dingemanse, Mark, 19 Fox, Jon, 433
Doing, Park, 322, 482n8 Francis, D., 400
Donnellan, Anne M., 465 Fraser, Mike, 400
Douglas, Jack, 15, 40 Freese, Jeremy, 430
Dourish, P., 413 Freud, Sigmund, 80, 486n2
Drew, Paul, 19, 21–23, 32–33, 41, 171, 236–238, Friedan, Betty, 487n6
279, 420, 429, 450–451, 459 Frith, Uta, 468, 492n3
Drozd, A., 400 Fuchs-Epstein, Cynthia, 487n6
Du Bois, W. E. B., 90, 485n1
Dubois, Cédric, 323, 325, 341 Galileo, 123
Duck, Waverly, 25–26, 47 Garbarski, Dana, 430
Duneier, Mitchell, 47, 433 Garcia, Angela Cora, 44
Name Index 497
Garfinkel, Harold, 1–12, 16–18, 21, 23, 26, Gross, Niel, 348, 352
28–29, 31–32, 34–35, 39–47, 50–51, 90–93, Gubrium, Jaber F., 236
95–102, 105, 107–110, 114–129, 131–132, Güntherodt, Hans-Joachim, 324
141, 148, 160, 162–166, 171, 178, 184, 214– Günthner, Susanne, 297, 307
225, 227–228, 232–233, 235–236, 239–240, Gurwitsch, Aron, 9, 316
252–265, 269, 271, 280, 289, 290–291, 295,
309, 316, 318, 322, 324–326, 336, 341–342, Hacking, Ian, 488–489n2
344, 349–351, 353–356, 358, 366–368, 393– Haebig, Eileen, 465
394, 398, 400–402, 420–429, 433, 437–438, Hammersley, Martyn, 344
442–445, 448, 451–452, 468–469, 477n1, Harjunpää, Katariina, 19, 279
477n9, 477n12, 477–478n13, 479nn2–3, Harper, Richard, 38, 399–400, 413
480nn5–8, 481nn9–10, 481n12, 481nn14–15, Harris, Roy, 253
481–482n2, 482n4, 482n9, 483nn10–14, Hart, H.L.A., 164
484nn4–5, 484n7, 484n15, 486n1, 487n4, Hayashi, Makoto, 19, 279
487n8, 488nn1–2, 489nn3–4, 490n1, 490n4, Heath, Christian, 38, 41, 123, 292, 302, 399–400,
491n5 402, 486n4
Garot, Robert, 236, 242 Heemsbergen, Jacquelyn, 493n10
Gergely, György, 207 Heims, S. J., 480n8
Gernsbacher, Morton Ann, 447, 449 Heinemann, Trine, 19, 279
Gibbons, S. C., 400 Hemmings, T., 400
Gibson, James J., 458 Hempel, Carl, 163
Gilbert, G. Nigel, 24, 36 Henderson, Kathryn, 37, 399
Gill, Virginia Teas, 242, 244 Heritage, John, 9–10, 12–14, 17–19, 21–22,
Gilmore, Glenda E., 94, 480n6 29–30, 40, 42, 43–44, 49, 115, 162–165, 170,
Glaser, Barney G., 431 177, 182, 202, 206, 228, 238–239, 252–253,
Glenn, Phillip, 469 255, 265, 278–279, 290, 310, 348, 351, 354,
Gödel, Kurt, 123 420, 423, 427, 429, 430, 443–444, 451, 456,
Goffman, Alice, 47 468–469, 483n12, 488n5, 492n6
Goffman, Erving, 28–29, 31, 193–194, 196–197, Heritage, Margaret, 469, 493n17
231, 241, 252–254, 261–265, 271, 280, 299, Hesse-Biber, Sharlene, 348, 353, 358
398, 401, 427, 444, 479nn2–3, 487n4, 488n3 Hesselbein, Chris, 130
Goldie, Terrie, 487n7 Hester, Stephen, 240, 242
Goldvarg, Yevgeniya, 372, 396 Higginbotham, David Jeffery, 44
Gomez, José Andrés, 351 Hilbert, Richard A., 477nn10–11
Goode, David, 44, 237, 243, 444, 470, 493n10 Hill, Richard J., 7–8, 271, 293, 355, 482n4
Goodman, Nelson, 360, Hindmarsh, Jon, 38, 302, 399–400, 402, 486n4
Goodman, Philip, 432–433 Hobbes, Thomas, 83
Goodwin, Charles, 13, 19, 24, 36, 38, 44, 123, Hobbs, Allyson, 487n4
188, 190, 192, 194, 196–201, 203, 205–206, Hoerl, C., 295
236–237, 243, 292, 295, 302, 305, 400, 402, Hollin, Gregory, 492n5, 492n9
445, 449, 461, 470, 484n15, 485n1, 486n4, Holstein, James A., 236, 243–244, 487n1
486nn7–8, 486n11, 492n2, 493n14 Holt, Elizabeth, 237
Goodwin, Marjorie Harness, 19, 36, 47, 196– Homans, George C., 162–163
197, 400, 449, 453, 461, 465, 485n1 Hopper, Paul J., 297, 307
Gotham, Katherine, 449, 452, 492n4, 493n14 Housley, William, 21–22
Gougeon, Pierre, 325, 341 Hoymann, Gertie, 19
Gouldner, Alvin W., 231 Hoymann, Gertie, 279
Grancea, Liana, 433 Hughes, Everett, 145
Grandin, Temple, 492n3 Hughes, J., 399–400, 413
Greatbatch, David, 238–239, 279 Humă, Bogdana, 358
Greenhalgh, C., 400 Husserl, Edmund, 34, 71, 80, 130, 202, 478n1
Greiffenhagen, Christian, 35, 42, 123, 127, 348, Hutchby, Ian, 239
352, 354, 359–360 Hutchins, Edwin, 38, 201
Griggs, Richard A., 371 Hutchinson, Phil, 128, 350
498 Name Index
accomplishment, achievement, 5, 16, 27–28, 32, attitude of daily life (ADL), 6–7, 30, 76, 442
43, 46–48, 92–93, 109, 145–147, 154, See also natural attitude
159, 215, 221–222, 224–225, 289, 291, atypical interaction, 44, 442–445, 470
293–294, 317, 349, 401, 423, 431, 445, audio/video recordings, 7, 33, 35, 105, 108, 166,
488n1, 491–492n3 197, 237, 254, 259, 265, 267, 281, 289,
accountability, accountable, accounting, 8, 295, 446
13–14, 16, 18, 22, 26, 28–30, 36, 49, 94, autism, Autism Spectrum Disorder (ASD),
154–155, 158, 165, 169–170, 172, 181– 442–443, 445–448, 455–457, 468,
185, 221, 232, 260–261, 271, 290–291, 492n3, 492n8
293, 307, 316, 355, 371, 375, 381, 383, Autism Diagnostic and Observation Schedule
425, 431, 438, 446, 481n2, 483n15 (ADOS), 449–456, 492n5, 493n10
motivational, 454, 456, 460–462, 468–469 autistic intelligence, 447–448, 469–470
obstructed, 383, 386
organization(s), 142 body torque, 306
reflexive and reflexivity, 153 breaching experiments and demonstrations,
scientific, 33, 42, 261, 266–267, 280 1, 7, 9–11, 98, 217–218, 232, 269, 400,
accounts, 30–31, 96, 103, 268–270, 436 444, 468
narrative, 102–103 See also trust
action, 1, 4–5, 10–14, 16, 18–19, 21–22, 25, bureaucracy, bureaucratic, 29–30, 142
47, 252, 254–255, 257–262, 265, 267,
269–272, 274, 276, 280–281, 289, 294, calibration, 207–208
421–426, 429, 431, 434, 437 camera, video camera, camera glasses, 295, 299
accumulative practices or accumulative category, categories, 20, 25, 170, 178, 184, 424,
combinatorial organization of, 201–205 433, 481n9, 485n4
collaborative, cooperative, 190, 201, 203, accounts, 25
206, 208 assignment, 99, 109
See also social action descriptive, 22
theory of, 71–72, 105–106, 253 membership, 17, 20–23, 47–48
actor-network theory (ANT), 121, 491n1 See also Membership Categorization
ad hocing, 12, 40–41, 259 Analysis (MCA)
adjacency pairs, 276, 445, 449, 460 categorize, categorization, 22, 90–91, 170, 178,
agency, 165, 184, 198 184, 433
agent, 165, 184–185 See also Membership Categorization Analysis
Agnes, 4, 16, 21, 24, 29, 45–46, 91, 148, 214–225, (MCA)
232, 236–237, 479n2, 480n6, 486n2, “centres of coordination”, 400
487n8 characterization problem, 124–125
See also gender See also unique adequacy
See also transgender, transsexual Chicago School, 27–28, 31, 93, 117, 230, 431
aphasia, 198, 244, 445 civil sidewalk ordinance (CSO), 13, 166–172,
apparatus, 20, 225, 271, 290, 293–294 174–175, 177–185, 484–485n1,
apprenticeship, 207, 209 485nn3–4
assessment(s), 279 “move-alongs” as a way of enforcing, 167,
formative, 463, 469–470, 493n17 173, 175, 178–179, 181–182
summative, 469, 493n17 sit/lie ordinance, 166–168, 177–179, 181
asymmetric alternates, 129–130 “classic studies”, 125, 129
See also Lebenswelt pairs Closed Circuit Television (CCTV), 401–413
504 Subject Index
gesture, 193, 197–200, 292, 492n4 interaction, 17, 194, 253–256, 259, 264
Gulfport Field history, 478n13 See also atypical interaction
centrality of, 6, 105–106, 264
haecceity, 28, 35, 116, 291, 401, 421, 426, 437 local nature of, 19, 154, 262–263, 273–274
contrasted to quiddity, 28, 116 methodological prescriptions for the study
hermeneutic circle, 9, 48 of, 92, 279
See also “Documentary Method of See also social interaction
Interpretation” interaction order, 92, 253, 263–265, 280, 427
homeless, 167–170, 173–175, 178–181, 184, interactional
485n4 substrate, 446, 448, 456, 460, 468–470
chronically homeless, 169–170, 172–174, what. See missing what
178–179, 181, 485n2 interactionism, 430
human action. See social action interpretation
human computer interaction (HCI), 37–38, quantitative results, 360
398, 400 rules, 12
See also workplace and work practice studies interpretive,
human tools, 203–207 sociology, 27
hybrid studies, 41, 115, 131–132, 341, 478n13, tradition, 27
484n15 interrogative
dialogue, 267
ideal types, framework, 261
logical status and uses of, 71, 76, 79 intersubjectivity, 44, 49, 256, 262, 272, 482n4,
illness, 45, 217 491n3
See also mental illness breakdowns of, 7
image recognition systems, 403, 413 See also breaching experiments and
See also PRISMATICA demonstrations
incongruity, 94, 98, 254, 256, 260, 444 See also trust
See also breaching demonstrations/ invitation sequences, 273, 279
experiments
deontic, 460 jazz music, 39, 117, 127, 143–144, 482n4
See also understanding judgment, 15–16, 23, 81, 164, 491n6
indexical, indexicality, 11, 13–14, 49, 109, 254– judgmental dope. See cultural dope
256, 258–260, 262, 265, 269, 290–291, jury,
293, 297, 302–303, 308, 317, 445, 481n2, project, 8, 393–394
488n2 studies, 3, 7–8, 29, 31–32, 42, 44, 232
See also context See also Garfinkel, Harold
expressions, 13, 36, 235, 240, 350, 428, 436
information apperception test, 105–108 knowledge, 189, 482n6
inquiry. See unmotivated inquiry common-sense. See common-sense
institutional, distribution of, 168–169
accounts, accountability, accounting scientific, 35
practices, 91, 96–97, 102–104 See also social knowledge making
See also accounts
Conversation Analysis (CA), 420, 426, labeling theory, 43–44, 231–232, 234, 241,
428–432, 483n12 243–244
ethnography, 45, 420, 426, 431–432 Pollner’s critique of, 234
fingerprints, 420, 429, 431–433 laminate, laminated, lamination, 193, 196, 200,
instructed actions, 127, 129, 131, 478n13 204
maps and, 31, 128–129, 150, 158, 484n5 action, 191, 194, 198, 201
intelligence, 447 organization, 193–194
artificial, 38, 398 structure, 198–199
See also autistic intelligence language, 188, 198, 205, 207, 241, 289, 291–292
military, 107 concision of, 254
Subject Index 507
norms, normative, normative structure, 5–6, 11, practice-based video analysis, 324–325
23, 28, 163–165 practice, practices, 16, 18, 28, 30, 51, 92–94, 115,
ethnomethodological respecification of, 8, 164–165, 173, 185, 442–444, 448, 456,
11–14, 16, 31, 49, 162, 165, 184, 235–236 469–470
expectations, 163 praxeological, 123, 368, 380, 389
legitimacy of, 5 analysis, 293
See also rules field
normative paradigm, 11–12, 14, 162–164, 184 focal distance, 389, 392
noticing, foregrounding, 389, 391, 395
departure point for analysis, 259, 293–294 coherence and coherence of detail, 389, 393
members’ work, 295–298, 300, 306–309, 313, reasoning, 42
316–317, 412 pragmatism, 261, 477n8
See also unmotivated inquiry predicates, accidental, spurious, or bogus,
identifiability of, 360
observer preference organization, preference structure,
role of, 71, 79, 80–81, 85 25–26, 274–276, 488n5
Occam’s Razor, 420–422, 437 for agreement, 278
offer sequences, 279 for contiguity, 276
ontological gerrymandering, 487n1 principled resolutions to recurrent
operations room, 402, 409 methodological problems,
“order at all points”, 265 absence of, 350
orderliness, 87, 92, 289–292, 317 PRISMATICA, 403, 405, 413–414
organization deployment, 405, 408–409, 412 See also image recognition systems
organizational, problem of order, 71, 85, 154
achievement, 154 Hobbesian, 5–6
activity, 151 See also voluntaristic theory of action
items, objects, 150–152, 156–158 Garfinkel’s respecification, 5–6, 162
reasoning, 148 de facto,
setting(s), 38 within Parsonian framework, 88
See also workplace and work practice within Schützian framework, 89
studies premises of conduct,
organizations, 36–37, 236 within Parsonian framework, 89
overcrowding, 405–408 within Schützian framework, 89
process, processes, 162–163, 257, 281
participation framework, 199 professional video, 402
passing, 91, 218, 232, 237, 259, 487n4 professional vision, 207–208, 316–317
peacekeeping, 32, 165, 184 professions, 115–117, 120, 123–124
perspicuous, 45, 193, 341, 348 ‘anti-professionalism’ in social science and
setting, 295, 358, 401–402 humanities, 118
phenomenology, phenomenological, 2–4, 35, progressivity, 303–304, 306–307, 317, 492n2
43, 80–82, 122, 130, 254, 256, 260, 280 delayed, 445
“bracketing”, 43, 224 projection, projectability, 297–298, 302, 307,
pointing, 292, 295, 302–303 311–312, 316
police, police officer, policing, 33, 165–176, prosody, 190–191, 193, 195–196
178–185, 484n1, 485nn3–4 pseudo-cleft, 297–298, 302–303, 306–308, 310,
law enforcement officials, 167 312, 316
police-able matters/conduct, 168, 178 psychiatric, psychiatry, 215, 217, 224
police scrutiny, 176 Psychoeducational Profile (PEP), 457, 467
practical, psychological, psychology, 448–449
action, 114–116, 141–143, 149–150, 159, 162 cultural, 111
actor, 159 discursive, 23–24
exigencies, 41 experimentation, 371, 394, 396
logic, 445 See also reasoning
Subject Index 509
public announcements, 409–410 rule(s), 27–28, 37, 43, 162–168, 170, 174, 178,
public behavior, 401–402 184, 232, 293, 398–399, 481n2, 481n9
public focus of attention, 200 accountable to, 165
Purdue symposium on ethnomethodology, 7 basic, 10
determinacy of, 8, 11
quantitative research methods, quantitative ethnomethodological respecification of, 8,
analysis, 348–349, 355, 359–362, 490n4, 11–14, 16, 30–31, 49, 162–164, 184
491n8 flexibility of, 12
question-answer sequences, 270, 276, implementation of, 29–30, 38
277–279 interpretation of, 12
moral accountability, 162, 170, 172
race, racism, 24–26, 45, 47–48, 90, 92–95, See also norms
97–104, 110, 241–242, 479n1, 480n8, See also trust
481n10, 487n4
rationality, 84, 163 scaffolding, 446
common-sense, 239 scanning tunneling microscopy (STM), 324–326,
See also common-sense 331, 336, 489n6
See also reasoning science,
scientific, 239 social studies of, 482n5, 491n1
sociology of error, 86, 119 See also science and technology studies (STS)
realism, 437 and technology, 16, 34, 42
reality disjunctures, 444 Lebenswelt origins of, 35
reasoning, 48 see also Workplace Studies
collaborative production of, 38, 45, 395 science and technology studies (STS), 34–37,
literal texts vs hypothetical conjectures, 39, 42, 114, 119
383–384 scientific discovery, 35
See also common-sense second-order constructs, 118
deductive, 163 self, 90, 91, 109–110
indexical and reflexive features of, 9, 11 territories of, 444
practical and situated, 10, 16, 149–150, 159 semiosis, 193
problem-solving, 375, 381 cooperative, 198
psychological experimentation, 371 semiotic, 208–209
See also psychology entities, 357
See also experimentation field, 193, 196–200
See also rationality materials, 188, 194, 196, 198, 201
scientific, 42, 233 resources, 36, 192, 198, 200, 486n4
reciprocal perspectives. See “general thesis of structure, 189, 193, 201, 486n6
reciprocal perspectives” sequence, sequentiality, sequencing, sequential,
recognition, recognizable, recognizability, 9, 19, 20, 23, 49, 408–409
290–291, 293–294, 318 analysis, 49
record-keeping, 41 organization of action, 49, 254, 262, 269, 445,
reflexive accountability. See accountability, 487–488n1
accountable setting, perspicuous setting, 290, 295
reflexivity, 9, 16, 30, 49, 91, 153, 258, 274, 279, sense, sense-making, 6, 8, 45, 49, 92, 98, 109–110,
308, 316–317, 344, 481n2 406, 408–409, 444, 460, 493n11
relevance(s) See also common-sense knowledge and
congruency of, 76, 444 reasoning
problem of, 78, 125 sex, sex status, 214–218, 221–225, 486n1, 487nn6–7
See also characterization problem sherlock experiment, 371–397
repair, 18–19, 25, 488n4 situated, 32, 290–291, 293
request sequences, 279 knowledge. See knowledge
research procedures. See methods practice, 208–209
roles, 27–28, 163, 221–224 See also practice
510 Subject Index
See also common-sense knowledge and University of California Los Angeles (UCLA),
reasoning 2, 477n7
temporal character, 404 gender clinic, 16, 214–216
temporality, 36, 78–79, 87–89, 311, 316 See also Los Angeles
testing, 108–109, 448–467, 468–470, 493nn11– understanding, 49, 258, 262, 272
12, 493n14, 493n17 displaying, 259, 262, 281
textures of detail, 388 incongruity, 6, 23
theory of mind, 468 unique adequacy, 121–125, 155, 481–482n2,
theory of objects, 484n15
Parsons, 71–72, 77–79, 81, 84 adequacy, postulate of in sociological
Schütz, 71–72, 77–79, 81 methodology, 122
theory of reality, and actor’s point of view, 122, 123
coherence theory, 479n4 See also characterization problem
congruence theory, 72–76, 479n4 and thick description, 125
correspondence theory, 72–76, 84, 86, unmotivated inquiry, 293–294
479nn3–4 utilitarian theories of social action, 162
multiple realities, 74–75
topic/resource distinction, 230, 233, 235–236, value(s), 5, 23, 229, 231, 233, 235–236, 241, 243
239–241 ethnomethodological respecification of, 49,
traffic, 155 235–236
engineering, 146–147 neutrality, 227, 229–230
trans rights, 225 vehicular unit, 299
transcripts, transcription, 265, 267, 280, 296, vernacular, 118, 144, 152–153, 156, 240
298, 489n4 accounts and ethnomethodology, 118
transformative operations, 191, 196, 203, 209 laboratory, 118
transgender, transsexual, 46, 48, 91, 96, 214, video, 289, 291, 295–296
216–217, 220, 223, 225, 479n1, 480n6 Vienna school, 163
See also Agnes vision, 295, 298, 307, 317
transgender media representation, 225 See also professional vision
See also documentary, Framing Agnes voluntaristic theory of action, 4–5, 86
transit networks, 402–412
See also London Underground “with”, 299
trust, trust conditions, 16, 47, 49, 90, 92, 95, 99, workplace and work practice studies, 34–37,
102, 105, 107, 109–111, 221–222, 442, 39, 114–117, 119–122, 124, 126–127,
444, 452, 479n1 131–132, 399, 477–478n13, 483n12
See also breaching experiments and cognition, distributed cognition and, 37–38
demonstrations See also computer-supported cooperative
See also Garfinkel, Harold work (CSCW)
Garfinkel’s conception of, 7 See also human-computer interaction (HCI)
See also “general thesis of reciprocal See also organizations
perspectives” See also science
turn-taking, 18, 151, 275, 280, 445 See also workscapes
tutorial problem, 325–326, 329, 331, 336, 342 workscapes, 37