Liberalism S Limits Carlyle and Mill On The Negro Question
Liberalism S Limits Carlyle and Mill On The Negro Question
Liberalism S Limits Carlyle and Mill On The Negro Question
To cite this article: David Theo Goldberg (2000) Liberalism's limits: Carlyle and Mill on “the negro
question”, Nineteenth Century Contexts, 22:2, 203-216, DOI: 10.1080/08905490008583508
II
Carlyle insisted that the feudal serf was (materially) better placed
than the Irish peasant, English needleworker, or "Negro" of his
day. He concludes that "the Negro Question" was to be answered
by turning "Negroes" into, a relationship of loyal serfdom to the
benevolent feudal-like lordship of their white masters. White men,
wisest by birth(right), were destined by nature and God to rule,
Negroes to serve; whites ought to try and convince Negroes to
assume their God-given role as servants, failing which masters
would be obliged to turn to "the beneficent whip."
Likely unaware first hand of any black people, Carlyle's "nigger"
of the "Nigger Question" was the stereotypical figure of "Quashee,"
a polygenic form of black lowlife—lazy, laughing, rhythmic,
musical, dance-loving, language defective (p. 12). "Horse-jawed
and beautifully muzzled" (p. 4), "Quashee" was the Carlylean equi-
valent of "Sambo," etymologically linked to squash and so to pump-
kin. Carlyle characterized "Quashee" as working only at eating
pumpkin—Carlyle's mean metaphor for any juicy tropical fruit like
watermelon, cantaloupe, mango, or papaya—and drinking rum.
Yet Carlyle insisted on finding "the Negro," "alone of wild-men,"
kind, affectionate, even lovable, and pointedly not the object of his
"hate" (p. 12). The abundance of tropical fruit in Carlyle's view
reduced the need on the part of West Indian natives to work. Car-
lyle's solution was to compel "the Negro" in the Islands to work by
restricting to the laborless the right to own fruit-producing land or
to enjoy its abundant products (p. 9).
In order to sustain this degraded image of the inherently
inferior "Nigger," Carlyle (like his counterpart D'Souza a century
and half later) was driven to reduce the debilitating effects of
slavery's experience for people of African descent. Carlyle accord-
ingly insisted that the debilitations of slavery were "much exagger-
ated" (p. 13). Slavery, and so mastery too, were considered "natural"
conditions; slaves, as Aristotle once put it, are slaves by nature.
Blacks are born to be servants (Carlyle's euphemistic bow to the
abolitionists, p. 22) of whites who "are born wiser...and lords"
over them (p. 32). Indeed, Carlyle insisted that there is a slavery far
worse than that of "Negroes" in the colonies, "the one, intolerable
sort of slavery" (as though enslavement of black people is not): this,
he remarked without a hint of irony, is the "slavery" throughout
Europe of "the strong to the weak; of the great and noble-minded
LIBERALISM'S LIMITS 207
to the small and mean! The slavery of Wisdom to Folly." (p. 14)
Thus Carlyle diminished the horrible experience and effects of real
slavery historically by reducing them to less than the "platonic"
manifestations of a metaphorical servitude of the strong and wise to
the weak and ignorant. Of course, it says little for the strength and
wisdom of the European wealthy and wise that they should be so
constrained by the weak and witless, a point to which Carlyle in all
his critical power seems oblivious.
Carlyle emphasized that it was Europeans who developed the
colonies from their supposed prehistory of "pestilence... and putre-
faction, savagery... and swamp-malaria" (p. 28); through their cre-
ativity, ingenuity, and productivity; that it was the English (or "Saxon
British," p. 27) who supposedly made the West Indies flourish and
without whom the islands would reduce to "Black Irelands" (p. 33)
or "Haiti" with "black Peter exterminating black Paul" (p. 29). Yet
Carlyle repeatedly contrasted the conditions of "Negroes," those
"Demarara Niggers," with the conditions of English laborers, white
working women, and Irish peasants. Fat from the abundance of
land, the consumption of fruit, and lack of labor, the character of
the Negro was measured against, if not silently considered the
cause of, working peoples' plight in the mother country and the
colonies. Carlyle's discourse nevertheless reveal beneath the racial-
ized overlay of this contrast a class induced ambivalence. Thus he
identified also the Distressed Needlewomen, Irish peasants, and
English working classes through a nineteenth-century version of
the discourse of an underclass (or lumpen) poverty of culture with
"the Nigger" of the West Indies (pp. 20-1). Most of the 30,000 Dis-
tressed Needlewomen, he objected, were really "Mutinous Serving-
maids" unable "to sew a stitch," and defying their inherent need for
a master: "Without a master in certain cases, you become a Distressed
Needlewoman, and cannot so much as live" (p. 21). Indeed, Carlyle
further reduced this equation of posing seamstress and free "nigger"
to the infantilized condition of babies and the animalized conditions
of dogs and horses (pp. 23, 12), all of whom needed accordingly to
be cared for, looked after, mastered by "philanthropic Anglo-Saxon
men and women" (p. 23). Equal in quantity to an entire English
county, black West Indians "in worth (in quantity of intellect, fac-
ulty, docility, energy, and available human valor and value)"
amounted to a single street of London's working class East End.
208 DAVID THEO GOLDBERG
Ill
not working at all... Does he mean that all persons ought to earn
their living? But some earn their living by doing nothing, and some
by doing mischief..." (pp. 42-3). Mill continued:
[L]et the whole produce belong to those who do the work which produces it. We
would not have black labourers [in the West Indies] compelled to grow spices which
they do not want, and white proprietors who do not work at all exchanging the spices
for houses in Belgrave Square [an expensive neighborhood in London].... Let
them have exactly the same share in what they produce that they have in the work.
If they do not like this, let them remain as they are, so long as they... make the best
of supply and demand" (pp. 44-5, my emphases).
ment" would enable a society, as Mill once said of himself "to effect
the greatest amount of good compatible with... opportunities"9
with the view to maximizing well-being and so happiness. Mill
attributed the success of such promotion fundamentally to eco-
nomic development which apparently would enable opportunities.
Civilized countries like Britain limited government intervention in
individuals' lives; those less civilized he thought should be ruled by
those more so with the view to promoting their capacity for self-
development. Liberal individualization was consonant with eco-
nomic, political, and cultural modernization. This would require
greater restriction in the ruled country on people's freedoms and
so more government regulation. Progress was considered a func-
tion of education and enlightened institutions but also of people of
"similar civilization to the ruling country," of Britain's "own blood
and language." The latter—Mill mentioned Australia and Canada—
were "capable of, and ripe for, representative government." India,
by contrast, was far from it, for India had stagnated for many cen-
turies under the sway of Oriental despotism.10 In India's case, and
even more perpetually in the case of the West Indies and African
colonies, "benevolent despotism"—a paternalistic "government of
guidance" imposed by more advanced Europeans—was the
rational order of the day.11
Thus, for Mill, the justification of colonization was to be meas-
ured according to its aid in the progress of the colonized, its educa-
tion of superstitious colonial subjects in the virtues of reason, and
the generation of new markets for capital accumulation through
the fashioning of desires. The purpose of education was to inform:
both to provide the informational basis to make rational decisions
and to structure the values framing practical reason in ways condu-
cive to the colonial ends Mill deemed desirable. Mill considered
progress to consist in being socialized in the values of liberal mod-
ernity, that is, in the sort of social, political, economic, cultural, and
legal commitments best represented by the British example. As a
colonized country exemplified such progress, the colonizing coun-
try progressively would give way to the colonized's self-governance.
So Mill's "benevolent despotism" amounts to a colonialism with a
human face. The world was to be directed by the most developed
and capable nations whose self-interests nevertheless would be
mitigated and mediated by the force of utilitarian reason.
212 DAVID THEO GOLDBERG
his son, and John Stuart never managed to shake this paternal(istic)
framing.15
However, even in their administrative advance, the Natives
(here Indian) were to be "Indian in blood and colour, but English
in tastes, in opinions, in morals and in intellect."16 Blood may run
thicker than water, but it was to be diluted by a cultural solution.
Cultural colonialism mediates racial inferiority, culture replacing
biology as the touchstone of racial definition. Accordingly English
was to be the language of administration, the local vernacular to be
used only to convey rules and regulations to the local population. Far
from "creating the conditions for the withering away of their rule,"17
Mill (even if inadvertently) was instrumental in identifying and
administering the sort of conditions that would perpetuate indirect
rule, postcolonial control from afar without the attendant costs.
IV
NOTES
1. E. August, ed., Carlyle, The Nigger Question and Mill, The Negro Question.
All parenthetical page references in the text are to this edition.
2. August includes in his little volume an editorial in a London newspaper
of the day, The Inquirer, protesting Carlyle's claims.
3. This is Fanon's cutting characterization in Black Skin White Masks, 79.
4. August, xvii.
5. Ann Laura Stoler, Race and the Education of Desire.
6. John Stuart Mill, Principles of Political Economy, 971.
7. Mill, 189-90.
8. Gyozo Fukuhara, "John Stuart Mill and the Backward Countries," 67.
9. J. S. Mill, Autobiography, Harold Laski, ed., 72.
10. J. S. Mill, Considerations on Representative Government, 563.
11. See Bearce, John Stuart Mill and India," 74-5; Pradhan, "Mill on India:
A Reappraisal," 16.
12. Mill, Principles, 749.
13. Mill, Parliamentary Papers, 30 (1852-3): 313-4.
14. Mill, 324-5.
15. Cf. Pradhan, 6.
16. Mill, quoted in H. Sharp, Selections from Educational Records, I, 1781-
1839 (Calcutta 1920): 116. See Abraham L. Harris, "John Stuart Mill:
Servant of the English East India Company," 195ff.
17. Harris, 201.
18. See Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 239.
19. See Frantz Fanon, 1 Dying Colonialism, 17.
216 DAVID THEO GOLDBERG
WORKS CITED
August, E., ed. Carlyle, The Nigger Question and Mill, The Negro Question.
New York: Appleton Century Crofts, 1971.
Bearce, George D. Jr. "John Stuart Mill and India." Journal of the Bombay
Branch of the Royal Asiatic Society 29.5 (1954).
Fanon, Frantz. A Dying Colonialism. London: Pelican Books, 1970.
_____. Black Skin White Masks. London: Paladin, 1970.
Fukuhara, Gyozo. "John Stuart Mill and the Backward Countries."
Harris, Abraham L. "John Stuart Mill: Servant of the English East India
Company." Canadian Journal of Economics and Political Science 30.2 (May
1964): 195ff.
Mill, J. S. Autobiography. ed. Harold Laski. London: Longmans, 1924.
_____. Considerations on Representative Government. In Collected Works, vol. 19.
Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
_____. Parliamentary Papers, 30. (1852-3).
_____. Principles of Political Economy. London: Longmans, 1900.
Pradhan, S. V. "Mill on India: A Reappraisal." Dalhousie Review 56.1 (Spring
1976).
Sharp, H. Selections from Educational Records, 1. [Calcutta 1920] (1781-1839).
Sidgwick, Henry. The Methods of Ethics, 7th edition. Indianapolis: Hackett,
1981.
Stoler, Ann Laura. Race and the Education of Desire. Durham: Duke Univer-
sity Press, 1995.