"Karl Marx's Realist Critique of Capitalism - Freedom, Alienation, and Socialism" by Paul Raekstad
"Karl Marx's Realist Critique of Capitalism - Freedom, Alienation, and Socialism" by Paul Raekstad
"Karl Marx's Realist Critique of Capitalism - Freedom, Alienation, and Socialism" by Paul Raekstad
Karl Marx’s
Realist Critique of
Capitalism
Freedom, Alienation, and Socialism
Paul Raekstad
Marx, Engels, and Marxisms
Series Editors
Marcello Musto, York University, Toronto, ON, Canada
Terrell Carver, University of Bristol, Bristol, UK
The Marx renaissance is underway on a global scale. Wherever the critique
of capitalism re-emerges, there is an intellectual and political demand for
new, critical engagements with Marxism. The peer-reviewed series Marx,
Engels and Marxisms (edited by Marcello Musto & Terrell Carver, with
Babak Amini, Francesca Antonini, Paula Rauhala & Kohei Saito as Assis-
tant Editors) publishes monographs, edited volumes, critical editions,
reprints of old texts, as well as translations of books already published
in other languages. Our volumes come from a wide range of political
perspectives, subject matters, academic disciplines and geographical areas,
producing an eclectic and informative collection that appeals to a diverse
and international audience. Our main areas of focus include: the oeuvre
of Marx and Engels, Marxist authors and traditions of the 19th and 20th
centuries, labour and social movements, Marxist analyses of contemporary
issues, and reception of Marxism in the world.
Paul Raekstad
© The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer
Nature Switzerland AG 2022
This work is subject to copyright. All rights are solely and exclusively licensed by the
Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights
of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on
microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and
retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology
now known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc.
in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such
names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for
general use.
The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and informa-
tion in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither
the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, expressed or implied, with
respect to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been
made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps
and institutional affiliations.
This Palgrave Macmillan imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature
Switzerland AG
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
Acknowledgements
v
vi ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
Throughout this book, I provide two references to quotes from Marx and
Engels’ writings, the first in the most widely available English translation I
can find, followed by one in one of the two editions of Marx and Engels’
collected works in German, where possible.
The current edition of the Marx-Engels Gesamtausgabe—Marx, K. and
Engels, F. 1975-. Karl Marx, Friedrich Engels Gesamtausgabe. (MEGA 2 ).
Berlin: Dietz/ Akademie Verlag —has been cited by volume such that
volume 1:2, page 234, is cited as I:2, p. 234. There are some cases where
I reference texts without quoting, in which case I refer to them only as
e.g. I:2, p. 234.
In a few cases where I’ve been unable to get hold of the German
original in MEGA 2 , I’ve also instead cited from MEGA 1 —Marx, K. and
Engels, F. 1927–1932, 1935. Karl Marx-Friedrich Engels-Historische-
kritische Gesamtausgabe: Werke, Schriften, Briefe. Berlin: Marx-Engels
Verlag—in the same way, but preceded with MEGA1 , such that e.g.
volume I:3, page 206 is cited as MEGA1 I:3, p.206.
The English-language collection of Marx and Engels’ collected
works—Marx, K. and Engels, F. 1975–2004. Karl Marx, Frederick Engels:
collected works. London: Lawrence and Wishart—are cited by volume and
page number, such that volume 6, page 192, is cited as MECW 6, p. 192.
The Marx and Engels selected works in English—Marx, K. and Engels,
F. 1969. Karl Marx and Frederick Engels: Selected Works in Three Volumes.
Moscow: Progress Publishers—have been abbreviated MESW, followed
vii
viii ABBREVIATIONS
by the volume number, followed by the page number, such that e.g.
volume 1, page 502 will be cited as MESW 1, p. 502–503.
All other citations are given by author, date, and page number.
Contents
1 Introduction 1
ix
x CONTENTS
Introduction
1 For just a small handful of examples, see Dixon (2014), Graeber (2009, 2015),
Holloway (1997, 2010), Mészáros (1972, 1995), and Lebowitz (2003, 2010, 2012,
2020).
2 There are too many to list here, but they include Carver (2018), Heinrich (2012,
2021), Jones (2016), Musto (2020), Roberts (2017), Lebowitz (2010, 2020), and Saito
(2017).
3 Following many others in the literature, I prefer to speak of “socialism” rather than
“communism”. Largely, this is done because the term “communism” today is commonly
associated with the centrally planned single-party dictatorships of e.g. the USSR, which
were very different from the vision Marx himself lays out under that term. For the
literature on Marx and republicanism, see Abensour (2011), Fischer (2015), Isaac (1990),
Jones (2016), Leipold (2020, 2022), Leopold (2007), Roberts (2017, 2018), Thompson
(2019), and Vrousalis (2021). It’s worth pointing out that there are two very different
senses in which thinkers are labelled “republicans” in contemporary anglophone political
theory, including (a) adopting the republican/neo-Roman concept of freedom as not
being subject to the will/arbitrary power of another and (b) sharing a broad cluster of
concerns about domination, slavery, servitude, and the emancipation of at least some
people. In the former sense, Marx is not a republican, but in the latter sense he certainly
is in various ways, and there’s a growing cottage industry exploring it.
4 See Rawls (1999, 2001, 2005).
5 For more on this, see Raekstad (2015, 2020b, and forthcoming b).
6 For the discussions most relevant to my concerns here, see Baderin (2014), Brinn
(2019), Duff (2017), Finlayson (2015), Floyd and Stears (2011), Frazer (2008, 2010),
Galston (2010), Geuss (2008, 2010, 2014, 2016, 2020), Hall (2015, 2017), Honig
(1993), Menke (2010), Mészáros (2011), Mouffe (2006), Newey (2010), Philp (2012),
Prinz (2016), Prinz and Rossi (2017), Raekstad (2015, 2018b, 2020b, 2020c, forth-
coming b), Rossi (2010, 2012, 2014, 2019), Rossi and Sleat (2010, 2014), Sangiovanni
(2008), Sleat (2013), Valentini (2012), Williams (2008), Wolff (2011), and Wright
1 INTRODUCTION 3
above all seek to make sense of and guide real politics.7 On this view, the
tasks of political theory are first and foremost to help make sense of and
guide various forms of real politics—such as social and political move-
ments, political parties, and so on. This requires starting from questions
of the available forms of agency and their contexts, questions of timing
and priority of possible actions, and questions of motivation, justifica-
tion, and legitimation. Realists typically argue that doing this well entails
rejecting what they call the “moralist” or “ethics-first” approaches to
political theory of Rawls and others, because they tend not to be very
good at fulfilling this vocation. By contrast, realists tend to avoid abstract
theories of moral rules and rule-like systems of perfect justice and their
application, in favour of more embedded and contextual reflections on
political values; understanding and explaining the operations of different
forms of real politics; orienting political agents; evaluating achievable
alternative institutions, actions, and the like; various forms of genealogy
and ideology critique; and conceptual development and innovation.8 Key
realist thinkers like Raymond Geuss explicitly draw on Karl Marx’s work
as a paradigm case of the approach they advocate, yet nobody has so far
produced a detailed realist interpretation thereof.
Reading Marx through a realist lens enables a holistic reconstruction
of his critique of capitalism, tying together his normative commitments,
diagnosis of capitalist alienation and unfreedom, and positive vision of
(2010). Interestingly, these methodological developments are connected with the re-birth
of normative approaches focusing on human development—both within Marxist scholar-
ship (see esp. Lebowitz, 2003, 2010, 2012; other writers who have emphasised Marx’s
critique of capitalism in terms of human development include Booth, 1992; Hamilton,
2003; Mészáros, 1972, 1995, 2011, 2014; Ollman 1976; Sayers 2007a, b) and among
political theorists more broadly (see Nussbaum 1992a, b, 2011; Sen, 1984a, b, 1987,
1992, 1999, 2010; Wolff and de-Shalit, 2007). I’ve previously argued that Sen’s human
development approach and his methodology connects to Marx’s in Raekstad (2015,
2018a). Finally, it’s worth noting that Sen himself is an advocate of what he calls a
comparative approach to political theory, which I’ve argued elsewhere (Raekstad 2015) is
a kind of realism.
7 Realism is sometimes confused with non-ideal theory, which focuses more on what the
role of feasibility constraints should be in political theory. While they can come apart (one
can do e.g. realist ideology critique that makes no use of feasibility constraints) there’s a
lot of overlap between the two, with thinkers like Adam Smith, Karl Marx, Amartya Sen,
and Charles Mills arguably falling into both camps. For a bit more on this, see Raekstad
(2015).
8 Geuss (2008, Part I).
4 P. RAEKSTAD
9 Esp. Mészáros (1972, 1995), Lebowitz (2010), Leopold (2007), and Sayers (2007a,
b, ch. 9).
10 Esp. Blackledge (2012), Sayers (2007b, 2011), Swain (2019a, b), and Tabak (2020).
1 INTRODUCTION 5
11 See e.g. Anderson (2017), Breen (2015), González-Ricoy (2014) Gourevitch (2015),
Hsieh (2008, 2012), and White (2011). Naturally, there’s a lot more detail to their
proposals, and differences among them, than can be discussed here.
6 P. RAEKSTAD
Marx is not reading a normative ideal of capitalism off from its existing
institutions, nor from the ideas and values of pro-capitalist theoreticians.
Instead, he’s analysing the inherent potentials and limitations of capitalist
societies from the perspective and interests of the oppressed who already
are fighting for their self-emancipation. Marx doesn’t need some abstract
theory of justice to do this, nor impose some enlightening principles on
the working-class movement from the outside. Instead, this critique is
offered to a (potentially) revolutionary working-class movement that’s
already perceiving the unfreedom of capitalism and seeking to overthrow
it. In this way, Marx is fulfilling the realist vocation of making sense of real
politics and contributing to the actions of the agents involved, helping the
present give birth to one of the futures it’s already pregnant with.
The book is structured as follows. Part I begins by laying out a unified
account of the normative commitments that Marx’s critique of capi-
talism builds on, namely a commitment to human development and to a
notion of freedom as self-direction as an important aspect thereof. Thus,
Chapter 2 develops a more sophisticated interpretation of Marx’s concep-
tion of human development than others so far. I argue that Marx is
committed to a conception of human development as the development
of powers, i.e. as real possibilities to do and/or to be, and that these can
only be understood through their interaction with human needs in lived
human practice/praxis.12 Chapter 3 builds on this analysis to explicate his
concept of freedom and the role it plays in his critiques of capitalism. Here
I argue that Marx has a conception of freedom as self-direction, according
to which humans have an internal species-specific power for free or self-
directed activity. The realisation or exercise of this power is both valuable
in itself and valuable because it positively impacts the development of
many other humans powers. This view is contrasted with conceptions of
12 Praxis and practice are two different translations for the same German original. The
theory of practice is explained in Chapter 2 and in Raekstad and Gradin (2020), so readers
of that book may wrongly think that I first figured out the theory of practice and then
used it to reconstruct Marx’s theory of human development. The reality is the other way
around. During my PhD research (specifically during 2012–2013), I first reconstructed
Marx theory of human development based on readings in social movement Marxism
(which I felt didn’t quite nail his theory of needs and its role correctly), work by Bertell
Ollman, and Deleuze’s first book on Spinoza; then realised that was simultaneously his
theory of practice; and then that many historical anarchists also shared that theory and
that it was a core component of their political theory and practice, including their views
on prefigurative politics.
1 INTRODUCTION 7
inter alia, that prior to 1844 Marx has a distinct critique of capitalism
from the later, socialist Marx, and that this theory of alienation and his
conception of an alternative form of society—democracy—jointly consti-
tute a realist critique of capitalism which is distinct both methodologically
and substantively from the one he articulates later on. Once this is under-
stood, we can see how this provides the radical democratic core of Marx’s
later diagnosis of capitalist unfreedom and vision of socialism.
Chapter 4 presents a novel reading of what I call Marx’s first theory
of alienation, which he develops during the years 1842–1843. On this
view, Marx’s first theory of alienation consists in a critical diagnosis of
capitalism and the state, according to which they are both alienating on
the grounds that they thwart the human species-specific power for partic-
ipating in deliberation and decision-making on public affairs. This chapter
argues for four original theses with respect to the existing literature: that
the early Marx did in fact have a developed theory of alienation distinct
from the one he developed in the 1844 manuscripts13 ; that this theory is
not centred solely on a critique of the modern state, or Hegel’s concep-
tion thereof14 ; that this theory centred on the suppressing of human
species-powers principally by their being subjected to seemingly external
power and domination, rather than in any significant way consisting in
some sort of “split” between citizen and private person distinctive of
the modern society/state complex15 ; and that this in turn means that
this early account of alienation applies much wider than merely to capi-
talist civil society and the state, but also e.g. to feudalism.16 Already at
this stage, Marx critiques how capitalist social relations subject people to
alien powers which those subject to them cannot control, driving him
to develop a vision of democracy that’s significantly more radical than is
typically recognised.17
13 Contra Colletti (1992), Lukács and Livingstone (1974), and Plamenatz (1975).
14 Contra Berki (1990), Breckman (1999), McGovern (1988), and Mészáros (1972).
Against this view, and for mine, see Draper (1977).
15 Contra Avineri (1968), Duquette (1989), Hudis (2013), McGovern (1988), and
Tucker (1970, 1972).
16 Although these points have not all been noted and fully explicated together, some
authors do come close, esp. McLellan (1970, 1971).
17 This relates to another controversial issue, namely my choice to distinguish explic-
itly between two different “theories” of alienation, despite the fact that they have
very different structures. What I call Marx’s first theory of alienation, and examine in
1 INTRODUCTION 9
References
Secondary
Anderson, E. (2017). Private government: How employers rule our lives (and why
we don’t talk about it). Princeton University Press.
Avineri, S. (1968). The social and political thought of Karl Marx. Cambridge
University Press.
Baderin, A. (2014). Two forms of realism in political theory. European Journal
of Political Theory, 13(2), 132–153.
Berki, R. N. (1990). Through and through Hegel: Marx road to communism.
Political Studies, 38(4), 654–671.
Blackledge, P. (2012). Marxism and ethics: Freedom, desire, and revolution. State
University of New York Press.
Booth, W. J. (1992). Households, markets, and firms. In McCarthy (Ed.),
pp. 243–271.
Breen, K. (2015). Freedom, republicanism, and workplace democracy. Critical
Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 18(4), 470–485.
Breckman, W. (1999). Marx, the Young Hegelians, and the origins of radical
social theory. Cambridge University Press.
1 INTRODUCTION 13
Brinn, G. (2019). Smashing the state gently: Radical realism and realist anar-
chism. European Journal of Political Theory, 19(2), 206–227.
Carver, T. (2018). Marx. Polity.
Colletti, L. (1992). Introduction to Marx 1992, pp. 7–56.
Dixon, C. (2014). Another politics: Talking across today’s transformative move-
ments. University of California Press.
Draper, H. (1977). Karl Marx’s theory of revolution, Volume I: State and
bureaucracy. Monthly Review Press.
Duff, K. (2017). The criminal is political: Policing politics in real existing
liberalism. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 3(4), 485–502.
Duquette, D. A. (1989). Marx’s idealist critique of Hegel’s theory of society and
politics. Review of Politics, 51(2), 218–240.
Finlayson, L. (2015). The political is political: Conformity and the illusion of
dissent in contemporary political philosophy. Rowman & Littlefield Interna-
tional.
Fischer, N. (2015). Marxist ethics within Marxist ethics within western polit-
ical theory: A dialogue with republicanism, communitarianism, and liberalism.
Palgrave Macmillan.
Floyd, J., & Stears, M. (Eds.). (2011). Political philosophy versus history?:
Contextualism and real politics in contemporary political thought. Cambridge
University Press.
Frazer, E. (2008). Political theory and the boundaries of politics. In D.
Leopold & M. Stears (Eds.), Political theory: Methods and approaches. Oxford
University Press.
Frazer, E. (2010). What’s real in political philosophy? Contemporary Political
Theory, 9(4), 490–507.
Galston, W. A. (2010). Realism in political theory. European Journal of Political
Theory, 9(4), 385–411.
Geuss, R. (2008). Philosophy and real politics. Princeton University Press.
Geuss, R. (2010). Politics and the imagination. Princeton University Press.
Geuss, R. (2014). A world without why. Princeton University Press.
Geuss, R. (2016). Reality and its dreams. Harvard University Press.
González-Ricoy, I. (2014). The Republican case for workplace democracy. Social
Theory and Practice, 40(2), 232–254.
Gourevitch, A. (2015). From slavery to the cooperative commonwealth: Labor and
republican liberty in the nineteenth century. Cambridge University Press.
Graeber, D. (2009). Direct action: An ethnography. AK Press.
Graeber, D. (2015). The Utopia of rules: On technology, stupidity, and the secret
joys of bureaucracy. Melville House.
Hall, E. (2015). Bernard Williams and the basic legitimation demand: A defence.
Political Studies, 63(2), 466–480.
14 P. RAEKSTAD
Hall, E. (2017). How to do realistic political theory (and why you might want
to). European Journal of Political Theory, 16(3), 283–303.
Hamilton, L. A. (2003). The political philosophy of needs. Cambridge University
Press.
Heinrich, M. (2021). How to read Marx’s capital: Commentary and explanations
on the beginning chapters. Monthly Review Press.
Holloway, J. (1997). A note on alienation. Historical Materialism, 1(1), 146–
149.
Holloway, J. (2010). Crack capitalism. Pluto Press.
Honig, B. (1993). Political theory and the displacement of politics. Cornell
University Press.
Hsieh, N.-H. (2008). Workplace democracy, workplace republicanism, and
economic democracy. Revue de Philosophie Economique, 9, 57–78.
Hsieh, N.-H. (2012). Work, ownership, and productive enfranchisement. In M.
O’Neill & T. Williamson (Eds.), Property-owning democracy: Rawls and beyond
(pp. 149–162). Wiley Blackwell.
Hudis, P. (2013). Marx concept of the alternative to capitalism. Haymarket Books.
Isaac, J. C. (1990). The lion’s skin of politics: Marx on republicanism. Polity,
23(3), 461–488.
Jones, G. S. (2016). Karl Marx: Greatness and illusion. Belknap Press.
Lebowitz, M. (2003). Beyond capital: Marx’s political economy of the working
class. Palgrave Macmillan.
Lebowitz, M. (2010). The socialist alternative: Real human development.
Monthly Review Press.
Lebowitz, M. (2012). The contradictions of real socialism: The conductor and the
conducted. Monthly Review Press.
Lebowitz, M. (2020). Between capitalism and community. Monthly Review Press.
Leipold, B. (2020). Marx’s social republic: Radical republicanism and the political
institutions of socialism. In K. Nabulsi, S. White, & B. Leipold (Eds.), Radical
republicanism: Recovering the tradition’s popular heritage (pp. 172–193).
Oxford University Press.
Leipold, B. (2022). Chains and invisible threads: Liberty and domination
in Marx’s account of wage-slavery. In A. de Dijn & H. Dawson (Eds.),
Rethinking liberty before liberalism. Cambridge University Press.
Leopold, D. (2007). The Young Marx: German philosophy, modern politics, and
human flourishing. Cambridge University Press.
Lukács, G., & Livingstone, R. (trans.). (1974). History and class consciousness:
Studies in Marxist dialectics. Merlin Press.
McGovern, A. F. (1988). The Young Marx on the state. In Wood (Ed.), pp. 166–
193.
McLellan, D. (1970). Marx before Marxism. Penguin.
McLellan, D. (1971). The thought of Karl Marx: An introduction. Macmillan.
1 INTRODUCTION 15
Menke, C. (2010). Neither Rawls Nor Adorno: Raymond Geuss’ programme for
a ‘realist’ political philosophy. European Journal of Philosophy, 18(1), 139–147.
Mészáros, I. (1972). Marx’s theory of alienation (3rd ed.). Merlin Press.
Mészáros, I. (1995). Beyond capital: Towards a theory of transition. Merlin Press.
Mészáros, I. (2011). Social structure and forms of consciousness, volume II: The
dialectic of structure and history. Monthly Review Press.
Mészáros, I. (2014). The necessity of social control. Monthly Review Press.
Mouffe, C. (2006). The return of the political. Verso.
Musto, M. (Ed.) 2020. The Marx revival: Key concepts and new interpretations.
Cambridge University Press.
Newey, G. (2010). Two dogmas of liberalism. European Journal of Political
Theory, 9(4), 449–465.
Nussbaum, M. (1992a). Nature, function, and capability: Aristotle on political
distribution. In McCarthy (Ed.), pp. 175–212.
Nussbaum, M. (1992b). Human functioning and social justice: In defense of
Aristotelian essentialism. Political Theory, 20(2), 202–246.
Nussbaum, M. (2011). Creating capabilities: The human development approach.
Belknap.
Ollman, B. (1976). Alienation: Marx’s conception of man in capitalist society.
Cambridge University Press.
Philp, M. (2012). Realism without illusions. Political Theory, 40(5), 629–649.
Plamenatz, J. (1975). Karl Marx’s philosophy of man. Clarendon Press.
Prinz, J. (2016). Raymond Geuss’ radicalization of realism in political theory.
Philosophy & Social Criticism, 42(8), 77–796.
Prinz, J., & Rossi, E. (2017). Political realism as ideology critique. Critical
Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 20(3), 334–348.
Raekstad, P., & Gradin, S. (2020). Prefigurative politics: Building tomorrow today.
Polity Press.
Raekstad, P. (2015). Two contemporary approaches to political theory. Interna-
tional Critical Thought, 5(2), 226–240.
Raekstad, P. (2018a). Human development and alienation in the thought of Karl
Marx. European Journal of Political Theory, 17 (3), 300–323.
Raekstad, P. (2018b). Realism, utopianism, and radical values. European Journal
of Philosophy, 26(1), 145–168.
Raekstad, P. (2020a). Adam Smith: Radical neo-roman and moderate realist.
Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 103(1), 70–92.
Raekstad, P. (2020b). Realism, utopianism, and human rights. Political Studies
Review, 18(4), 542–552.
Raekstad, P. (2020c). The present and future of political realism. Res Publica,
26(2), 293–297.
Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice (Revised Edition). Belknap.
Rawls, J. (2001). Justice as fairness: A restatement. Belknap.
16 P. RAEKSTAD
Human Development
1 See Lebowitz (2003, and esp. 2010) for a similar Marxist account of human
development, but with a different specification of socialism/communism’s institutional
requirements. Other Marxist writers who have emphasised Marx’s critique of capitalism in
terms of human development include Booth (1992), Hamilton (2003), Leopold (2007),
Mészáros (1972, 2011), and Sayers (2007a, b, ch. 9). For well-established non-Marxist
approaches see Nussbaum (1992a, b, 2011) and Sen (1984a, b, 1987, 1992, 1999).
2 This overall view, albeit with modifications of point 1 regarding the details of Marx’s
normative foundations and without the detailed structure I have laid out, is largely in
agreement with Collier (2009), Raekstad (2015), and Wright (2010).
2 HUMAN DEVELOPMENT 23
the various operations, what Marxists often call the laws of motion,
of capitalist economies. “Wealth” refers instead to what the political
economist in question takes to be valuable, desirable, worthy, and so on.
For obvious reasons, this often trips contemporary readers up.
Marx is clear that, for him, true wealth—i.e. what’s really valuable—
consists in human development as an end in itself. He writes that:
[T]he society that is fully developed produces man in all the richness of his
being, the rich man who is profoundly and abundantly endowed with all
the senses...3
[T]he rich man and the wealth of human need [should or must] take
the place of the wealth and poverty of political economy. The rich man is
simultaneously the man in need of a totality of vital human expression; he
is the man in whom his own realisation exists as inner necessity, as need.4
how, let’s begin with the idea of functionings, which consist of “beings”—
states like being well-fed, being educated, being literate, and so on—and
“doings”—activities we undertake like eating, reading, voting, deliber-
ating, and so on. Often things can be described as either a being or a
doing—like a person being housed in a pleasantly warm house and that
person consuming a lot of energy to keep their house warm. For Marx,
who sees all beings in terms of processes of becoming of various kinds, the
two terms are co-extensive. Powers or capabilities, in turn, are a person’s
real possibilities for achieving functionings—like having the real possibility
of feeding oneself, of reading, and so on. In other words, functionings are
beings and doings, and powers are real possibilities to do and/or to be.
A functioning is thus the realisation of a power, and a range of powers is
a range of really possible functionings.11
A power in this sense consists of the right combination of two things.
First of all, it consists of a context or set of conditions which enables
one to do or be certain things (e.g. a book for learning German and
not having a boss forcing me to work so much that I’m prevented from
using it). Secondly, it consists of what I shall call internal powers, i.e. the
abilities or capacities internal to a person required to take advantage of the
relevant context or conditions (e.g. being able to read the instructional
language that the book for learning German is in).12 To have a (full)
power is thus to have the right combination of both the requisite external
context or conditions and the internal powers required to take advantage
of them.
We must understand these complexes as an inherently processual and
relational kind of thing.13 My power to learn German is predicated on
access to certain external materials—for instance, books devoted to that
purpose. Such access requires me to be in certain relations which enable
me to get hold of that book—viz., relations of property, access to a place
to purchase or borrow the book, being able to transport myself or the
book to a suitable location for pickup, and so on. The particularities of
these conditions are only obtained as a result of the continual production
and reproduction of complex social relations and institutions in which I
must partake.
Secondly, in order to be able to learn German from the book in ques-
tion, I need certain internal powers to understand the language the book
is written in, to see, to read, to write, to learn in some systematic way, and
so on. These powers are themselves currently constituted by an ongoing
process in which my body (including my brain) continually reproduces
itself through time in interaction with the world around it (breathing,
drinking, eating, etc.).
Thirdly, any such powers I presently possess are the result of a wider
process of maturation and development, of which its current time-slice is
a moment. This process of maturation and development, through which
I have come to acquire and maintain the internal powers to do things like
process natural language, hear, read, and write, etc., is in turn a function
of the interplay between my powers and needs at previous moments of
development on the one hand, and the context and conditions within
which that development has taken place on the other. In this manner, not
only do complex powers consist of a conjunction of internal powers and
external conditions, these internal powers are, in turn, constituted by a
processual unity itself consisting of an interplay between internal powers
13 It might be objected to the following discussion that it really speaks only of the
acquisition of human powers, or perhaps also of their development and maintenance.
This objection only makes sense if we ignore Marx’s process ontology and philosophy
of internal relations, according to which things are thought of as processes and as partly
constituted in and through processes of interaction with other things. I cannot examine
this issue here, but for an excellent account see Ollman (2003).
2 HUMAN DEVELOPMENT 29
and external conditions, and this process goes, as it were, all the way
down.
We should therefore not think of powers, in Marx’s usage, merely
in terms of an abstract set of possibilities. Instead, we should think of
them as the range of options available to an organism constantly engaged
in turning (some of) its powers into functionings, in interaction with
its wider environment, in order to satisfy its needs.14 Doing so in turn
continually maintains, alters, destroys, and/or creates new powers and
needs—hence Marx’s comment, in the Grundrisse, about a society where
one “does not reproduce himself in one specificity, but produces his total-
ity”, where one “[s]trives not to remain something he has become, but is
in the absolute movement of becoming?”.15
Finally, the passages quoted earlier in this section express an intimate
connection between powers, needs, and the senses. We can now begin
to make sense of this. Powers, in Marx’s sense, include abilities both to
affect things in the world (like being able to hold someone’s hand or join
them in defending a picket line) and to be affected by things in the world
(like transforming the sound waves hitting your ear into the experience
of enjoying Beethoven’s 9th symphony). On Marx’s view, the production
of various pleasures and enjoyments, and the drives and desires they are
connected to, is an inherent part of his theory of human development. To
understand how, we must unpack his theory of needs and see how they’re
connected with his theory of powers.
Needs
For Marx, there is an intimate relationship between what he calls “needs”
(Bedürfnisse) and human powers, a relationship that must be understood
in order to make sense of his conception of human development. Having
already discussed powers, I turn first to discuss Marx’s conception of
needs and thereafter to the nature of their interaction.
To do this, it’s first necessary to dispel a common misunderstanding in
what Marx means by “need”. Some believe that Marx has what might be
14 This, as well as the importance of the passions, drives, and strivings in Marx is
explored further in van Ree (2020).
15 Marx (1993, p. 488/II.1.2, p. 392).
30 P. RAEKSTAD
It is evident that (e) is broader than and extends over (d). The sense of
“drive” in (e) is to be broadly understood to include not only individuals’
conscious intentions and desires, but also something’s stated goals, values,
or concerns (where the “something” in question might even be a theory
or an ideology), as well as the unconscious motivations or tendencies of
16 See esp. Hamilton (2003), Leopold (2007), Soper (1981), and Springborg (1981).
The positions of the two former will be discussed below. Those of the latter are too
complex to be dealt with here.
17 Examples of such a theory include Doyal and Gough (1991), Geuss (1981, 2012),
and one of the two senses Leopold (2007) takes Marx to have. Note that I am referring
to these as instances of a conception of needs of this kind, nor claiming that all of the
authors hold this to be an accurate reading of Marx’s conception of needs.
18 Hamilton (2003) and Leopold (2007).
19 E.g. Chitty (1993), Ollman (1976, ch. 7), and Maslow (1970) and many other
psychological theories of need.
20 See Springborg (1981, ch. 6).
2 HUMAN DEVELOPMENT 31
21 I thus, like Soper (1981), not only refuse to categorically distinguish between wants
and needs; I also, unlike Soper, explicitly subsume the former under the latter.
22 To support the first part of this claim further it would be necessary to discuss each
and every instance of the term’s usage in the first few volumes of Marx’s collected works.
Doing so is impossible here. If the empirical premise my argument rests on is not fully
demonstrated here, it is at least easily testable: all that is required is to find one, or a
significant number of, instances in the early works in which Marx uses “Bedürfniss(e)” in
a manner incompatible with the readings I advocate, namely (d) and/or (e).
23 For more on this see Hamilton (2003, p. 57).
32 P. RAEKSTAD
basic physiological needs, like “a human need for sustenance (he talks
about ‘eating, drinking’ and, more generally, ‘nourishment’), for warmth
and shelter (he lists ‘heating’ and ‘clothing’ as well as a ‘dwelling’),
for certain climatic conditions (he mentions both ‘light’ and ‘air’), for
physical exercise (the need ‘to move about’ and the need for ‘physical
exercise’), for basic hygiene (‘the simplest animal cleanliness’), and for
reproduction and (heterosexual) sexual activity (he writes of ‘procreation’
and describes sexual relationships between women and men as charac-
teristic of the ‘species’)”.24 Marx’s usage also includes needs for things
like self-development and community. However, he also mentions a range
of other needs which would be difficult to fit into any plausible single,
unitary, and predetermined set of criteria of the kind required for (a) or
(b). These include a “human need for recreation (to ‘go drinking’, to
‘go dancing’, to ‘fence’, to ‘sing’), for culture (to ‘go to the theatre’),
for education and intellectual exercise (to ‘think’, to ‘theorise’, to ‘buy
books’, to engage in ‘learning’), for artistic expression (to ‘paint’), for
emotional fulfilment (to ‘love’), and for aesthetic pleasure (Marx identi-
fies ‘a musical ear, an eye for the beauty of form’ as among our essential
human capacities and powers)”.25 It’s hard to square this with any other
reading than one in terms of (socially and historically mediated) drives.
Such uses were common at the time, as when e.g. the anarchist Peter
Kropotkin writes that once “material wants are satisfied, other needs,
which, generally speaking may be described as of an artistic character,
will thrust themselves forward”.26 It might be argued that many of these
are mentioned only in passing and that a reconstruction of Marx’s views
on human needs need not necessarily be bound by the strictures of off-
hand remarks and singular mentions in notebooks and letters. This reply is
correct, but inadequate. The fact remains there is at least one reading, that
of (e) (and, as far as our argument so far has been concerned, also (d)),
on which these uses are all made coherent. Consequently, this alternative
reading is the most plausible one.
Fourthly, whenever Marx talks about what “needs” are, he clearly takes
every instance of a human drive or impulse to constitute a need, including
all manner of wants, desires, and preferences, regardless of origin. As a
result, he does not distinguish at all between “true” and “false” needs or
between “actual” needs and “imaginary” ones, because these aren’t the
sort of things that can be true or false—though one can, of course, desire
things that are contrary to one’s interests. In Volume I of Capital, for
instance, Marx asserts that a necessary condition for being a commodity
is for an object to satisfy a need, regardless of “nature” of these needs,
“whether they arise, for example, from the stomach, or the imagination,
makes no difference”.27 In an associated footnote, Marx quotes from
Nicholas Barbon’s A Discourse on Coining the New Money Lighter. In
Answer to Mr Locke’s Considerations about Raising the Value of Money,
where Barbon explicitly talks in terms of “Desire” and “appetite” using
(as does Marx in his discussions of “needs”) the example of hunger.28
This makes no sense at all from the point of view of the more objective
and normatively laden conceptions of needs in (a)–(c). Simply creating
a desire does not of itself make it into a requirement for avoiding harm
or pathology, a requirement for human development or flourishing, or
a requirement for achieving some particular purpose (other than merely
the satisfaction of that particular desire). By contrast, all of this fits snugly
within readings (d) and (e), since desires clearly and unproblematically fall
within the scope of needs conceived of as drives or strivings.
Relatedly, throughout his oeuvre, Marx talks about creating wants or
demand for commodities in a capitalist marketplace in terms of creating
(unsatisfied) needs.29 As we’ll see in Chapter 7, this plays an important
role for understanding some of the harms of alienated, unfree labour, as
when Marx argues that alienated labour results in that labour becoming
undesirable, so it’s no longer itself the satisfaction of a “need”, i.e. people
feel no drive or impulse to do it apart from in order to satisfy needs
external to it, like hunger. This clearly supports a reading of needs in
terms of drives or strivings.
Finally, in other instances Marx writes about things becoming “needs”
only if and when they become actual drives:
Here it is clear that new needs are developed when and only when they
become driving forces for concrete living beings, which fits perfectly with
how we’ve just seen that Marx talks about what “needs” are in Capital.
By contrast, if needs are, as they must be according to readings (a)–(c),
the requirements Y for ensuring certain ends Z, and if society is important
for human beings, then society becoming a conscious human end cannot
plausibly be accepted as an instance of acquiring a new need, since the
mere fact of becoming the object of a conscious human end does not, in
itself, affect whether or not that particular Y is a requirement for some
Z—unless Z is nothing more than e.g. the realisation of ends or satis-
faction of desire, in which case it collapses into a version of (d). On
the other hand, a reading of needs as drives as per (d) and (e) coheres
perfectly with Marx’s wording: since conscious ends, desires, and so forth
fall under needs, the acquisition of a desire for society is unproblematically
the acquisition of a new need which one did not previously possess.
It might be argued that the links Marx makes between needs and
desires do not show that he conceives of needs as drives, but instead
that he conceives of them as an individual’s perceived requirements for
the avoidance of harm. This would be a variant of interpretation (a). The
connection between desires and needs would then be that if someone
has a sufficiently strong and enduring desire for X, then they will come
to see the non-satisfaction of X as causing them suffering, which is a
kind of harm, they will perceive X as a requirement for them to avoid
a harm, and so will come to “need” X in the above sense. If this is the
kind of thing Marx has in mind, we would expect him to mention the
strength or endurance of a drive for it giving rise to a need. He never
does so. Furthermore, we would expect some sort of distinction between
drives and needs, where the latter would be associated with strength
and/or endurance, and perhaps also with consciousness (in the sense of
self-awareness) and consequent plasticity and variation across contexts—
like we see in Hegel.31 No such distinction appears in Marx. Finally, if
“needs” were conceived in terms of strongly felt requirements, we would
also expect some sort of distinction to be made between “natural” and
“constructed” needs, “real” and “false” or “imaginary” ones, etc., of the
kinds we see in writers such as Rousseau and the Frankfurt School. As
I’ve shown, Marx makes no such distinctions with respect to “needs”.
In short, if Marx held a view of needs as perceived requirements in a
sense beyond merely drives, it would be extremely surprising that these
kinds of distinctions are never even alluded to, especially since they are
made in literature which he was intimately familiar with. If, however, he
was in fact construing “needs” differently, as drives, these interpretative
difficulties disappear.
One might also worry that a concept of needs as drives risks leaving
Marx unable to distinguish the requirements for healthy life and func-
tioning from things like luxuries and mere wants. The answer to this is
that Marx already has a concept for this, namely “necessity”, and that
this enables him to make just such a distinction. While Marx doesn’t
distinguish “needs” from mere wants, he does write that “[l]uxury is
the opposite of the naturally necessary”.32 On this view, “necessities” are
requirements for survival, healthy functioning, or the like, and the “natu-
rally necessary” is what we require to survive and function well by virtue
of being the kind of animal we are. Of course, what is, and what is consid-
ered to be, necessary varies according to natural, social, and historical
context, and Marx thinks it is a “tendency of capital” to transform “what
was previously superfluous into what is necessary, as a historically created
necessity”.33 We see again and again that what once was a luxury—cars,
31 Hegel mentions how “psychology relates and describes these [immediate and natu-
rally given] drives and inclinations and the needs derived from them” (Hegel, 1991,
p. 45), and distinguishes between the “universal needs, such as food, drink, clothing,
etc.” (ibid, p. 227), and the further development of human needs as “taste and utility
become criteria of judgement” (ibid, p. 229). This clearly involves a distinction between
more instinctive drives and inclinations on the one hand and more socially and historically
mediated impulsions on the other. By contrast, Marx talks of e.g. hunger and insists that
hungers for different things are different hungers.
32 Marx (1993, p. 528/II.1.2, p. 427).
33 Ibid.
36 P. RAEKSTAD
34 One way of attempting to salvage a properly normative function for Marx’s concep-
tion of needs is arguing that there are two different senses in which Marx uses that
concept: on the one hand, a restrictive normative conception according to which some
goals and desires are of particular importance; on the other hand, a more expansive and
developmental conception of needs according to which it consists in mere wants or goals
of some sort. The problem with this is not only that Marx makes no such distinction; it
is also rendered wholly unnecessary on a sufficiently broad specification of “needs” as per
(e). If “needs” just refers to all drives and impulses, all goals and desires count without
any problems—regardless of their origin, normative value, and so on. In other words, a
distinction between different senses of “need” in Marx is neither conceptually necessary
nor textually well-founded.
2 HUMAN DEVELOPMENT 37
for a medium-rare steak, for strips of raw flesh, for dried fish, and so on).
As Marx writes:
Hunger is hunger, but the hunger gratified by cooked meat eaten with a
knife and fork is a different hunger from that which bolts down raw meat
with the aid of hand, nail and tooth. Production thus produces not only the
object but also the manner of consumption, not only objectively but also
subjectively. (…) Production not only supplies a material for the need, but
it also supplies a need for the material. As soon as consumption emerges
from its initial state of natural crudity and immediacy - and, if it remained
at that stage, this would be because production itself had been arrested
there - it becomes itself mediated as a drive by the object. The need which
consumption feels for the object is created by the perception of it. The
object of art - like every other product - creates a public which is sensitive
to art and enjoys beauty. Production thus not only creates an object for
the subject, but also a subject for the object. Thus production produces
consumption (1) by creating the material for it; (2) by determining the
manner of consumption; and (3) by creating the products, initially posited
by it as objects, in the form of a need felt by the consumer. It thus produces
the object of consumption, the manner of consumption and the motive of
consumption. Consumption likewise produces the producer’s inclination
by beckoning to him as an aim-determining need.35
35 Marx (1993, p. 92/II.1.1, p. 29 (emphasis in the original), see also 1992, p. 352–
6/I:2, p. 269–73/393–7, and p. 391/I:2, p. 409).
38 P. RAEKSTAD
can understand the human senses by means of powers then we can likely
also understand the other things that human beings do in the same way.
To begin, it is important to understand that Marx has an expansive
conception of the human senses. By a sense being expansively conceived,
I mean that in the “sense” of, for instance, the ear or hearing, Marx would
certainly include not only the external organ (such as the outer ear), but
also the full range of auditory stimulation and processing which goes on
in a human being in response to the relevant kind of stimuli. Not only is
the outer ear thus included, but so too are the inner ear and the relevant
cognitive processes taking place in the brain.
Conceived of in this manner, senses are human powers which, like
others, develop and flourish within certain contexts and conditions, and
in response to their inputs. So having, for instance, a musical ear, means
that one has the internal power to partake in musical appreciation and
one is in the state of being able to appreciate (at least of some particular
kind of) music.36 Put differently, the internal power of, say, hearing is
the power to produce certain kinds of affects or affective experiences in
response to certain kinds of stimuli.
The requisite conditions for the development of these senses natu-
rally include the necessary nutrients and other basic requirements for
normally healthy physical growth and maintenance; but they also include
another set of inputs specific to the sense in question. Without attempting
a definition, I shall call this more restricted class a “power-specific” set
of inputs. According to Marx, humans’ internal powers will either not
develop at all, or will develop much less, without their required power-
specific inputs. Having a sense of hearing means being able to appreciate
(at least certain kinds of) music. It also creates a need—i.e. a drive, in this
case a desire—for the person to listen to (at least some kind of) music.
If and when this need is satisfied, one’s internal power of hearing, expan-
sively conceived, develops in response to these power-specific stimuli.
This, in turn, causes the needs associated with the relevant sense to alter,
as a result of which new needs emerge (and the old ones may or may
not disappear).37 To be sure, when human beings and other animals use
36 This is of course a state of being, and therefore a functioning. Since functionings are
actualised powers, and since something being actual entails (trivially) that it is also really
possible, this functioning is also (trivially) a power.
37 It should by now be clear that Bookchin’s (1974, p. 276) charge that “Marxism”
has neglected to form a concrete image of sensuous man, while correct about much that
2 HUMAN DEVELOPMENT 39
their powers in order to satisfy their needs they are not only using their
sensory powers. They are using many of their other individual and social
powers as well—such as powers to play instruments, to compose music,
to purchase audio equipment, to stand, to walk, to read notes, and many
more—and the interaction between their powers and needs is crucial for
understanding how humans grow, develop, and flourish in and through
our lived activities.
For Marx, this theory of human development also constitutes a frame-
work for making sense of human activity, of lived human experience,
of praxis.38 We can get some sense of how this works by seeing how
the theory I’ve sketched generalises throughout human activities, from
gaming to theories of revolution. When you first start playing a new
computer game, simply learning the mechanics and completing a few
initial tasks or goals is enough. You may have long-term ambitions of
completing the game, but in the early stages, your focus tends to be
more on learning the basics and making immediate gains in the starting
location(s). Having developed your gaming powers and won these initial
victories, your needs develop further as well. Simply repeating these same
basic tasks is no longer as rewarding and doesn’t fill you with the same
excitement as it once did, so you set your sights higher—learning more
complex mechanics, carrying out more difficult tasks, and so on. Even-
tually, as your powers grow enough, you shift your focus to winning the
game completely, often by facing and defeating one or more final bosses.
The basics of socialist theories of revolution are not so different. Most
of them argue that, with or without grander ambitions in mind, you start
small and local, bringing people together to develop powers of organ-
ising and acting in concert, so that you can use those powers to win
small, particular victories that help better satisfy your needs (e.g. for better
has gone under the banner of “Marxism”, does not touch the thought of Marx himself.
In fact, Marx, especially in the Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844, criticises
the classical political economists on precisely this point with regard to their conceptions of
needs. For more detail on this kind of process-reading of Marx, see esp. Adams (1991),
Lebowitz (2003, 2010), Ollman (1976), Parsons (1971, chs. 5–7), and Sayers (2007b,
2011).
38 I cannot, for obvious reasons, expand upon this here, but for some more of this
view from the perspective of social organisation and struggle, see Raekstad and Gradin
(2020). I’m currently working on another book reconstructing what are called Marx’s
materialist dialectics, theory of praxis, base and superstructure, and materialist conception
of history, where this will be explored in greater depth.
40 P. RAEKSTAD
39 This, in Marx’s very broad conception of “power”, includes not only broader forms
of social power conferred e.g. by being a capitalist or high-level manager dominating their
workers, or the political supremacy wielded by party apparatchiks, but also that conferred
by greater wealth and privilege more broadly.
40 Naturally, Marx does not hold this to be the case for each and every individual
capitalist, as is pointed out e.g. in The German Ideology.
42 P. RAEKSTAD
41 These concerns are at the heart of Marx’s critique of Proudhon, the Lassalleans,
and other contemporaneous socialists who built their critique of capitalism and vision
of socialism on theories of distributive justice, which you can find more about in the
appendix.
42 Note that this is only an appeal to intuitions about the principled feasibility of making
comparative judgements of human development. It makes no claims about certain powers
being (intuitively or otherwise) more valuable than others (although I think Marx, Sen,
and myself would all agree that this is the case) or about only some powers being valuable
and others not. This is why the ceteris paribus clause is important here: it excludes from
the thought-experiment the logical possibility that those who are e.g. less capable of acting
courageously have other (potentially more valuable) powers which those to whom they
are being compared lack. This may of course be a problem in cases of actual comparisons,
but this is a distinct empirical issue and must be treated as such. The empirical concern
makes sense, but it is not clear, especially in light of the further simplifying mechanisms
discussed below, that it poses any significant threat to the practical usefulness of this
approach in general.
44 P. RAEKSTAD
45 For a good discussion of this from the capabilities-approach point-of-view, see Wolff
and de-Shalit (2007, ch. 7.).
46 Sen (1999, xii, cf. 38–53, 1993, 31–32); for its connection to Marx, see Raekstad
(2018a).
46 P. RAEKSTAD
In the next one, I will use this theory to reconstruct his conception of
freedom and its value.
References
Secondary
Adams, W. (1991). Aesthetics: Liberating the senses. In Carver (ed.), pp. 246–
274.
Bookchin, M. (1974). Post-scarcity anarchism. Wildwood House.
Booth, W. J. (1992). Households, markets, and firms. In McCarthy (Ed.),
pp. 243–271.
Callinicos, A. (2000). Equality. Polity.
Callinicos, A. (2006). The Resources of Critique. Polity.
Chitty, A. (1993). The early Marx on needs. Radical Philosophy, 64, 23–31.
Collier, A. (2009). Marx and conservatism. In A. Chitty & M. McIvor (Eds.),
pp. 99–104.
Doyal, L., & Gough, I. (1991). A theory of human need. Palgrave Macmillan.
Geuss, R. (1981). The idea of a critical theory: Habermas and the Frankfurt
school. Cambridge University Press.
Geuss, R. (2012). Economies: Good, bad, indifferent. Inquiry, 55(4), 331–360.
Hamilton, L. A. (2003). The political philosophy of needs. Cambridge University
Press.
Hegel, G. W. F., Wood, A. W. (Ed.), & Nisbet, H. W. (trans.). (1991). Elements
of the philosophy of right. Cambridge University Press.
Kropotkin, P. (1995). The conquest of bread and other writings. Cambridge
University Press.
Lebowitz, M. (2003). Beyond capital: Marx’s political economy of the working
class. Palgrave Macmillan.
Lebowitz, M. (2010). The socialist alternative: Real human development.
Monthly Review Press.
Leopold, D. (2007). The Young Marx: German philosophy, modern politics, and
human flourishing. Cambridge University Press.
Marx, K., Fowkes, B. (trans.) & Mandel, E. (intro.). (1991). Capital: A critique
of political economy (Vol. 3). Penguin.
Marx, K., Livingstone, R. (trans.), Benton, G. (trans.) & Colletti, L. (Intro.).
(1992). Karl Marx: Early writings. Penguin.
Marx, K., & Nicolaus, M. (trans.). (1993). Grundrisse: Foundations of a Critique
of Political Economy. Penguin.
Maslow, A. H. (1970). Motivation and personality (2nd ed.). Harper & Row
Publishers.
Mészáros, I. (1972). Marx’s theory of alienation (3rd ed.). Merlin Press.
2 HUMAN DEVELOPMENT 47
Mészáros, I. (2011). Social structure and forms of consciousness, volume II: The
dialectic of structure and history. Monthly Review Press.
Nussbaum, M. (1992a). Nature, function, and capability: Aristotle on political
distribution. In McCarthy (Ed.), pp. 175–212.
Nussbaum, M. (1992b). Human functioning and social justice: In defense of
Aristotelian essentialism. Political Theory, 20(2), 202–246.
Nussbaum, M. (2003). Capabilities as fundamental entitlements: Sen on social
justice. Feminist Economics, 9(2–3), 33–59.
Nussbaum, M. (2011). Creating capabilities: The human development approach.
Belknap.
Ollman, B. (1976). Alienation: Marx’s conception of man in capitalist society.
Cambridge University Press.
Ollman, B. (2003). Dance of the dialectic: Steps in Marx’s method. University of
Illinois Press.
Parsons, H. L. (1971). Humanism and Marx’s thought. Charles C. Thomas
Publisher.
Raekstad, P., & Gradin, S. (2020). Prefigurative politics: Building tomorrow today.
Polity Press.
Raekstad, P. (2015). Two contemporary approaches to political theory. Interna-
tional Critical Thought, 5(2), 226–240.
Raekstad, P. (2018a). Human development and alienation in the thought of Karl
Marx. European Journal of Political Theory, 17 (3), 300–323.
Sayers, S. (2007a). Marxism and morality. Philosophical Researches (9), 8–12.
Sayers, S. (2007b). Marxism and human nature. Routledge.
Sayers, S. (2011). Marx and alienation: Essays in Hegelian themes. Palgrave
Macmillan.
Sen, A. (1984a). Well-being, agency and freedom: The Dewey lectures 1984.
The Journal of Philosophy, 82(4), 169–221.
Sen, A. (1984b). Resources, values and development. Basil Blackwell.
Sen, A. (1987). The standard of living (the Tanner lectures). Cambridge
University Press.
Sen, A. (1992). Inequality reexamined. Clarendon Press.
Sen, A. (1999). Development as freedom. Oxford University Press.
Sen, A. (2010). The idea of justice. Penguin.
Soper, K. (1981). On human needs: Open and closed theories in a Marxist
perspective. Harvester Press.
Springborg, P. (1981). The problem of human needs and the critique of civilisation.
George Allen & Unwin.
van Ree, E. (2020). Productive forces, the passions and natural philosophy: Karl
Marx, 1841–1846. Journal of Political Ideologies, 25(3), 274–293.
Wilkinson, R., & Pickett, K. (2010). The spirit level: Why equality is better for
everyone. Penguin.
48 P. RAEKSTAD
Freedom
1 This has long been the standard view, see inter alia Blackledge (2012), Sayers (2007,
2011), Swain (2019), and Tabak (2020).
anything happens to be like at any one slice of time—its size, shape, speed,
colour and shading, texture, reading abilities, preference for chocolate
chip cookies, etc. Marx would think of this through his lens of powers
and needs, such as our powers to read books or complete a computer
game and our needs to drink good coffee. Any such collection will be
highly contingent in nature; vary a great deal both within and between
any natural, social, and historical contexts; and likely change a great deal
over time in lots of different ways.
Another sense of “nature” refers to something much more limited,
namely to whatever makes a thing the kind of thing that it is. Accord-
ingly, in Capital Marx distinguishes between the nature shared by human
beings by virtue of being the kinds of animals we are, or “human nature
in general” and our contingent nature as shaped by our growth and
socialisation in our particular contexts, or “human nature as historically
modified in each epoch”.6 When, in the Poverty of Philosophy, Marx writes
that “[a]ll history is nothing but a continuous transformation of human
nature”,7 what he’s saying is that what human history, and in particular
historical change, consists in is the continuous transformation of our natu-
rally, socially, and historically configured sets of powers and needs. This is,
as we’ve seen, incompatible with the kind of static and ahistorical concep-
tion of an essential human nature that Marx attributes to Feuerbach.
However, it’s perfectly compatible with the idea that there is some such
thing as an essential human nature—provided that it’s of a different kind.
Indeed, it would be shocking if Marx didn’t think there are any inborn
differences between human beings and other animals. We’ve just seen
that Marx writes about the historical modification and transformation of
human nature. This logically presupposes that there must be a human
nature to modify. Just like (as Marx famously points out to Proudhon)
it’s logically impossible to commit theft in the absence of pre-existing
property, so too is it logically impossible to modify or transform a human
nature that doesn’t exist. The other side of this coin is that it’s only
6 Marx (1990, p. 759, footnote 51/II:6, p. 559, footnote 64). This distinction is
essentially the same as one of the ways of explaining the Hegelian distinction between
First Nature (e.g. the evolved potentials we’ve inherited from our biological evolution)
and Second Nature (the natures we develop on the basis of our First Nature, rooted in
our evolved powers of consciousness and the resulting forms of socially and historically
created contexts we develop within and are shaped by).
7 MECW 6, p. 192/I:6, p. 207.
52 P. RAEKSTAD
8 Some of the most interesting and challenging developments of this idea can be found
in Mészáros (1972, 1995, 2011). For some of the best commentary discussing all of these
aspects of Marx’s notion of species-being see Fromm (2004), Geras (1983), Hudis (2013),
Kain (1988, 1992), Kamenka (1969, 1972), Leopold (2007), Ollman (1976), Sayers
(2007, 2011), and Wood (2004). All of these, in various ways, expand upon the different
elements that I’ve only alluded to here, such as humans’ powers of consciousness, of
self-direction, their role and importance for human flourishing and happiness, the notion
of universality at play here, humans’ capacity for mutual recognition, humans’ greater
plasticity and contextual variation compared to animals, and the importance of human
artistry and creativity in labouring activity.
3 FREEDOM 53
the basis of the view of human powers and needs sketched in Chapter 2,
does Marx conceptualise the human species-being or species-nature?9
For Marx, species are distinguished by their powers. More precisely,
they’re distinguished by what I have termed their internal powers. The
internal powers the human species-being consists in are, on Marx’s
account, universal among human beings,10 restricted to human beings,
and distinctive of human beings as a species. A human being realises
their species-being/nature in any given activity if and only if these
species-specific internal powers are exercised in the performance of
that activity. Concerns about human self-direction and participation in
social/collective deliberation and decision-making go back as far as
Marx’s earliest philosophical and political writings.11 A turning point is
marked by the shift, in the Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of
1844, to focus more specifically on human activity, especially on everyday
labour. Here he writes that “free conscious activity constitutes the species-
character of man” and that capitalism, because of the alienation it entails,
“tears away from him his species-life”.12
Marx describes the human species-being or nature in the following
way:
The animal is immediately one with its life activity. It is not distinct from
that activity; it is that activity. Man makes his life activity itself an object of
his will and consciousness. (…) Conscious life activity directly distinguishes
man from animal life activity. Only because of that is he a species-being.
(…) Only because of that is his activity free activity.13
9 Note that these are two different English translations for the same German term in
Marx: Gattungswesen.
10 Barring pathology and exceptional circumstances, on which see below.
11 See this and the following chapter, as well as Hudis (2013, p. 37–55).
12 Marx (1992, p. 328–329/I:2, p. 240–241/369–370). Note that the original “him”
refers to the preceding masculine German noun der Mensch (the human being) which
makes the original sentence, unlike its English translation, semantically gender-neutral.
13 Marx (1992, p. 328/I:2, p. 240/369).
54 P. RAEKSTAD
It is true that animals also produce. They build nests and dwellings, like
the bee, the beaver, the ant, etc. But they produce only their own imme-
diate needs or those of their young; they produce one-sidedly, while man
produces universally; they produce only when immediate physical need
compels them to do so, while man produces even when he is free from
physical need and truly produces only in freedom from such need…14
In other words, what sets human beings apart from other animals
is their internal power of conscious self-directed activity, or self-
direction/self-activity for short. Human beings are endowed with
consciousness, and this immediately sets their activities apart from those
of other animals. Consciousness enables human beings to set themselves
apart from their activity because it enables them to critically reflect on,
deliberate on, direct, and alter that activity as needed. It enables them
to produce universally, as opposed merely for the benefits of their own
and those close to them, and to produce even when free from immediate
physical needs—i.e. when not experiencing the push of simple, instinctual
impulses. Finally, these passages suggest (as I return to in Chapter 7), that
a particularly important realm of freedom is that of productive activities,
or labour, where humans use their consciousness to determine and realise
their own ends or purposes through their interaction with each other and
the rest of nature.
This is a view that stayed with Marx for the rest of his life. In Volume
I of Capital, for instance, he writes that:
and the less, therefore, he enjoys it as the free play of his own physical and
mental powers, the closer his attention is forced to be.15
17 This might sound very Aristotelian, minus Aristotle’s sexism, ethnocentrism, and
peculiar doctrine of natural slavery. While I think that Aristotle’s influence on Marx is
undeniable, there are some important differences between their views here and in general,
for some of which see earlier on in this chapter and for others see the appendix.
3 FREEDOM 57
comes in degrees. Ideas of language and recursion would likely then play
a central role in explaining why, as far as we can tell at present, human
beings have greater cognitive capacities than other animals we’ve encoun-
tered so far. It’s not very fruitful to speculate about the exact forms
these modifications would take, but it is worth noting that, in the end,
they might well generate many of the same conclusions with respect to
humans’ greater powers of consciousness than other animals, along with
a connected commitment to the value of consciously self-directing our
activity.
Freedom as Self-Direction
For Marx, freedom consists in conscious self-direction. As we’ve just seen,
“[c]onscious life activity [that] directly distinguishes man from animal
life activity” and only “because of that is his activity free activity”.18 On
this view, a person is free in an activity if and only if they self-direct that
activity. This requires one to be able to determine one’s own purposes,
decide on the means to realise them, and control how the activity is
carried out. An inherently materialist conception of freedom, it rejects
any kind of metaphysical separation between thinking, willing, and the
rest of the world. Human capacities for freedom are created and continu-
ously reproduced by the material world and our knowledge of that world
further empowers us to direct our interactions with it, increasing our
freedom. On this view, the laws of nature don’t oppose our freedom,
they enable it.
Like all other powers, having and exercising the (full) power to self-
direct one’s activity requires the right combination of internal powers and
external conditions. The previous section showed that, for Marx, human
beings have the internal powers required to consciously self-direct their
activity. In this section, we look at some of the external conditions that
it requires. These conditions include the normal requirements for human
growth and survival, as well as the right kinds of social relations and level
of material production. Since human beings are social animals, many of
our activities will be collective in nature. For Marx, this is simply a fact
about human beings. If we accept this fact, a question presents itself: how
can we find ways of structuring our collective activities such that they are
self-directed by all who are part of them, rather than directed by someone
or something else?
As the exercise of an internal power, freedom can be prevented in a
variety of ways. One way it can be prevented is by being subjected to
the will or arbitrary power of another person. Activities in which you
are subjected to the will or arbitrary power of another—like patriarchy,
slavery, or capitalist labour processes—subject you to the uncontrolled
power and thus direction of another person, which prevents you from
directing that activity yourself. Even if the power holders never exer-
cise their power, the fact of its existence hinders you from being able
to fully determine your own purposes and decide on your preferred
means for realising them in important ways, thus thwarting your poten-
tial self-direction. Another way that self-direction can be prevented is
by subjecting someone to certain socially generated, impersonal forms
of power which they cannot control, like the impersonal powers of capi-
talist competitive markets. When such impersonal powers similarly prevent
people from being able to fully determine their own purposes, decide on
their preferred means in important ways, and/or control their activities,
such forms of impersonal domination likewise prevent those subject to
them from directing their activities themselves, rendering them unfree.
Marx never explains what exactly the necessary and sufficient conditions
for impersonal powers counting as dominating are. However, the case of
impersonal domination he focuses on, capitalism’s competitive markets,
combines four very clear elements. They contain a socially generated form
of power, this power is not controlled by those subject to them, it does
not reduce to power wielded by identifiable individual power-holders,
and it undermines self-direction, e.g. by preventing people from fully
determining their own purposes. In Chapter 7, we will see how Marx
argues that capitalism features both personal and impersonal forms of
domination.
A third way in which people can be made unfree is through impositions
of natural necessity, as when Marx, in Volume III of Capital, writes that:
Freedom, in this sphere, can consist only in this, that socialized man,
the associated producers, govern the human metabolism with nature in
a rational way, bringing it under their collective control instead of being
dominated by it as a blind power; accomplishing it with the least expen-
diture of energy and in conditions most worthy and appropriate for their
human nature. But this always remains a realm of necessity. The true realm
3 FREEDOM 59
We can now see that Isaiah Berlin’s famous accusation that Marx’s
positive concept of freedom allows people to force you to be free is incor-
rect.22 Briefly put, Berlin’s argument is that positive concepts of freedom
like Marx’s involve living and/or acting in the right way. If this is the
case, it’s possible that somebody else knows better than you how you can
and should live and act in the correct, free ways, and it’s therefore also
possible for them to force you to live and act in the correct, free ways,
thereby forcing you to be free.23
There may be concepts of freedom that such an argument might apply
to, but Marx’s is not among them. For Marx, if you are being forced
to act or live in certain ways by someone or something else, then you
are no longer determining your own purposes and means and you are
thus rendered unfree. Berlin’s argument can be salvaged by adding the
premise that the right kind of institution (e.g. state, party, church, etc.)
can rightly be said to constitute a “real you”, in which case its actions and
directions would count as yours, so its directing you would now count as
a (now very different) kind of self-direction. There are two problems with
this. First, the work here is done by an extremely implausible premise that
few followers of freedom would accept, and its conclusion would follow
regardless of which concept of freedom one has. On a negative concept
of freedom as the absence of interference, for instance, if a state or party’s
actions count as your own, you’d only be interfered with by yourself, so
here too, once we add this premise, you would be forced to be free for
the very same reasons. In other words, what does the work here isn’t any
concept of freedom and its supposed risks, but rather a very peculiar and
implausible idea about selfhood. It thus completely fails as a critique of
Marx’s positive concept of freedom.24 At no point does Marx embrace
anything like such a conception of the self. The second problem with this
addition is that it’s not one that Marx ever makes and that it has no basis
whatsoever in any of his writings.25 It therefore cannot be accepted as a
which is why I prefer to speak of “powers of production” and “productive powers” from
here on.
22 Berlin (2002), in particular the essay “Two Concepts of Liberty”.
23 See Geuss (2005, p. 69).
24 As has been shown in Geuss (2005, p. 70).
25 It might be argued that this idea is implied when Marx points out that people only
develop and individuate themselves within society. While this may be part of where this
misinterpretation comes from, it’s certainly a mistake. Obviously, the fact that people grow
3 FREEDOM 61
up, are shaped by, and become the particular individuals they are only in and through
interaction with others within some society does not entail that the society one grows up
in equates or amounts to their selves, “true” or otherwise.
26 Roberts (2017, 2018).
27 Republican/neo-Roman concepts of freedom can, of course, account for how e.g.
internalised norms and impersonal relations contribute to and reinforce relations of
personal domination. What they cannot do without becoming positive theories is account
for how e.g. impersonal relations make people unfree in ways that don’t reduce to personal
relations of domination.
62 P. RAEKSTAD
30 For more on this sort of understanding of concepts, see Raekstad and Gradin (2020).
31 Here I should point out that I agree with most commentators that Marx uses the
terms Entäusserung and Entfremdung largely, if not completely, synonymously, although
there is some scholarly disagreement on this issue which I cannot discuss here.
64 P. RAEKSTAD
For a man who is starving the human form of food does not exist, only
its abstract form exists; it could just as well be present in its crudest form,
and it would be hard to say how this way of eating differs from that of
animals. The man who is burdened with worries and needs has no sense
for the finest of plays; the dealer in minerals sees only the commercial
value, and not the beauty and peculiar nature of the minerals; he lacks
a mineralogical sense; thus the objectification of the human essence, in a
theoretical as well as a practical respect, is necessary both in order to make
man’s senses human and to create an appropriate human sense for the whole
of the wealth of humanity and of nature.37
two theses.38 SDT begins from the same basic conception of human
beings that Marx does: human beings are animals which are continu-
ously engaged in reciprocal interaction with their environments, activating
their powers in order to realise their needs, and in so doing giving rise to
new collections of powers and needs. The environments within which
these processes take place, for Marx as for SDT, can enable, preclude or
prevent, aid and nurture, or hinder and forestall the developing organ-
ism’s powers.39 SDT posits three universal human psycho-social needs:
competence, the feeling of mastery and being able to operate and act
effectively in one’s environment; relatedness, the need to interact with,
connect with, and care for others; and autonomy, which I get into
below.40 The concept of “needs” utilised by SDT is not, obviously, the
same as the one I am attributing to Marx. Instead, needs in SDT’s sense
are defined as “the innate psychological nutriments that are essential for
ongoing psychological growth, integrity, and well-being”.41 What SDT
here posits as “needs” are innate and universal. To the extent that they
are realised in human activity they greatly promote human development
and functioning and conversely to the extent that they are not realised in
such activities. In other words, the realisation of e.g. autonomy is taken
to positively impact the development of a wide range of human powers.
The importance of these ideas here is that some of their associated
experimental findings provide support for the importance that Marx
attributes to self-directed activity and for the claimed universality of this
importance. To make sense of this, we need to know what exactly SDT
means by a need for “autonomy”. According to SDT:
as when one acts out of internal or external pressures that are experienced
as controlling.…42
42 Ryan and Deci (2018, p. 86); see also Ryan and Deci (2006, p. 1562). The detail
of their formulations sometimes vary subtly, but the core point about autonomy being
defined in terms of certain experiences is crucial.
43 Note that, despite some interesting historical connections, this should not be
confused with, e.g. Kant’s conception of autonomy as acting in accordance with the
laws laid down by reason.
44 See Ryan and Deci (2018, Ch. 6). This has even been confirmed on a neurolog-
ical level, see Murayama et al. (2010). For an overview of the neuroscience of intrinsic
motivation, see Di Domenico and Ryan (2017). For a brief overview of the undermining
effects of rewards, see Ryan and Deci (2018, pp. 145–147).
3 FREEDOM 69
put food on the table.45 ,46 Furthermore, empirical studies indicate that
securing autonomy in human activities consistently leads to improvements
in the experience of happiness, esteem, and general health and well-being.
By contrast, a lack of autonomy, and a greater degree of controlled moti-
vation—like actions being motivated solely by attaining money, power,
status, and so forth—over intrinsic motivation is associated with the
opposite of the aforementioned, e.g. with lack of esteem, as well as
with greater risks of physical and psychological ill-health and patholo-
gies, including depression, problems with social functioning, and even
lower productivity.47 These findings thus provide some support for the
nature of the importance Marx attributes to self-direction. They support
Marx’s general claim that self-direction is important for living healthier
and happier lives, for nurturing intrinsic enjoyment and motivation, and
for positively impacting the development of a range of valuable powers.
Let us move on to the question of the universality of the impor-
tance that Marx attributes to self-directed activity. An argument against
Marx’s position along these lines can easily be imagined: The impor-
tance that Marx attributes to self-directed activity merely reflects his
own cultural biases, the value he attributes to it is simply absent in
other human cultures and it is therefore plausible to suppose that the
importance of self-directed activity is not, pace Marx’s parochial presup-
positions, universal among human beings. Now, since the importance that
Marx attributes to self-directed activity is not dependent on the beliefs
that people have about the value of self-direction or their attempts to
attain it, it is in principle possible to test the universality of its impor-
tance empirically. The same can obviously be said for SDT’s conception
of autonomy. Just like we can test how human beings react by performing
essentially the same tasks under more or less autonomous conditions,
we can also run these tests in different human societies that either do
or do not value autonomy and see whether or not the same effects are
observed. Such studies have been carried out, and they support the claim
that autonomy and its importance for human development is in fact
universal among human beings across cultures—including ones in which
autonomy is explicitly and widely valued and ones in which it is not.48
This too provides some support for Marx’s thesis that the importance of
self-direction for human development is in fact universal among human
beings.
In this chapter, we have seen how Marx develops a positive concept
of freedom as self-directed activity or self-activity. Under conditions
of unfreedom, he argues that the intrinsic motivation and enjoyment
inherent in a given activity is thwarted, and the development of numerous
and significant other human powers is corroded. Conversely, being able
to exercise these powers, realising human freedom, is valuable both as a
particularly important aspect of human development in itself and because
it furthers the development of a wide variety of other valuable powers.
With this understanding in place, we can now turn to consider how Marx
uses a concept of human freedom to critique first the state and capitalism
(Part II) in favour of democracy, and then more specifically capitalism
(Part III) in favour of socialism.
References
Primary
Marx, K., & Nicolaus, M. (trans.). (1993). Grundrisse: Foundations of a critique
of political economy. Penguin.
Marx, K., Fowkes, B. (trans.) & Mandel, E. (intro.). (1990). Capital: A critique
of political economy (Vol. 1). Penguin.
Marx, K., Fowkes, B., (trans.) & Mandel, E. (intro.). 1991. Capital: A critique
of political economy (Vol. 3). Penguin.
Marx, K., Livingstone, R. (trans.), Benton, G. (trans.) & Colletti, L. (Intro.).
(1992). Karl Marx: Early writings. Penguin.
Secondary
Berlin, I. (2002). Liberty: Incorporating four essays on liberty. Oxford University
Press.
48 See e.g. Chen et al. (2015), Chirkov et al. (2003, 2005), Deci et al. (2001), Lynch
et al. (2009), Rudy et al. (2007), Soenens et al. (2012), and Soenens and Beyers (2012).
3 FREEDOM 71
Blackledge, P. (2012). Marxism and ethics: Freedom, desire, and revolution. State
University of New York Press.
Chen, B., Vansteenkiste, M., Beyers, W., Boone, L., Deci, E. L., Van der Kaap-
Deeder, J., Duriez, B., Lens, W., Matos, L., Mouratidis, A., Ryan, R. M.,
Sheldon, K. M., Soenens, B., Van Petegem, S., & Verstuyf, J. (2015). Basic
psychological need satisfaction, need frustration, and need strength across four
cultures. Motivation and Emotion, 39(2), 216–236.
Chirkov, V., Ryan, R. M., Kim, Y., & Kaplan, U. (2003). Differentiating
autonomy from individualism and independence: A self-determination theory
perspective on internalization of cultural orientations and well-being. Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, 84, 97–109.
Chirkov, V., Ryan, R. M., & Willness, C. (2005). Cultural context and psycho-
logical needs in Canada and Brazil: Testing a self-determination approach to
the internalization of cultural practices, identity, and well-being. Journal of
Cross-Cultural Psychology, 36, 423–443.
Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (2000). The “what” and “why” of goal pursuits:
Human needs and the self-determination of behavior. Psychological Inquiry,
11(4), 227–268.
Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (2002). Overview of self-determination theory:
An organismic dialectical perspective. In E. L. Deci & R. M. Ryan (Eds.),
pp. 3–33.
Deci, E. L., & Vansteenkiste, M. 2004. Self-determination theory and basic
need satisfaction: Understanding human development in positive psychology.
Ricerche di Psicologia, 27 (1), 23–40.
Deci, E. L., Ryan, R. M., Gagné, M., Leone, D. R., Usunov, J., & Kornazheva,
B. (2001). Need satisfaction, motivation, and well-being in the work orga-
nizations of a former eastern bloc country: A cross-cultural study of
self-determination. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 27 (8), 930–942.
Di Domenico, S. I., & Ryan, R. M. (2017). The emerging neuroscience of
intrinsic motivation: A new frontier in self-determination research. Frontiers
in Human Neuroscience, 11(145).
Fromm, E. (2004). Marx’s concept of man. Continuum.
Geras, N. (1983). Marx and human nature: Refutation of a legend. Verso.
Geuss, R. (2005). Outside ethics. Princeton University Press.
Hudis, P. (2013). Marx concept of the alternative to capitalism. Haymarket Books.
Kain, P. J. (1988). Marx and ethics. Clarendon Press.
Kain, P. J. (1992). Aristotle, Kant, and the ethics of the young Marx. In
McCarthy (Ed.), pp. 213–242.
Kamenka, E. (1969). Marxism and ethics. Macmillan.
Kamenka, E. (1972). The ethical foundations of Marxism (2nd ed.). Routledge &
Kegan Paul.
72 P. RAEKSTAD
turn means that this early account of alienation applies much wider than
merely to capitalist civil society and the state, but also e.g. to feudalism.4
The fact that Marx’s theory of alienation applies not just to the modern
state, but also to capitalist civil society, sets even the very early Marx apart
from a great deal of liberal and more moderate republican ideas.
There are both substantive and methodological reasons for dealing
with Marx’s early critique here. For one, the development of Marx’s
later theory of alienation and socialism in 1844 and beyond cannot
be understood in the absence of his earlier political theories. His later
theories developed from his earlier thoughts, retaining their core commit-
ments. For another, Marx’s approach to, or method of, political theory
changes in important ways over the period during which Marx develops
from a radical democrat to a socialist, but, critically, both approaches are
instances of Marx developing a realist political theory on the basis of the
normative commitments canvassed in Part I. Despite its importance, the
relation between these two critiques of capitalist society has not received
sufficient attention and is not well-understood.
Consequently, Part II has three goals in relation to Part III. Firstly,
together they demonstrate how Marx developed a radical realist political
theory based on a commitment to human development in two distinct
ways. Secondly, they show that and how a theory of this kind rightly
changes in response to further descriptive knowledge. The basic structure
of many of Marx’s normative commitments, his views on human nature
and society, and so on, remain very similar from his first critique to the
second. Marx’s deeper investigations into the nature of capitalism and its
alienation, through his study of political economy, leads him to develop
his vision further into a form of socialism. At the same time, and this is my
third point, we can see that his conception of democracy remains central
to his vision of a future society both genealogically and ideologically. His
notion of democracy retains ideological centrality because the vision he
outlines in some of his earliest writings remains an essential component
of his later vision of socialism. It retains genealogical centrality because it
is this vision that, along with its underlying normative components, is the
key to understanding the development of Marx as a socialist thinker.
4 Although these points have not all been noted and fully explicated together, some
authors do come close, esp. McLellan (1970, 1971).
PART II: ALIENATION AND DEMOCRACY 77
Marx’s recommended vision must be not only possible, but also achiev-
able under the conditions of contemporary capitalist societies. This is why
his search for a viable form of revolutionary agency, to be discussed in
Chapter 6, becomes so crucial. It is also why, having discovered the revo-
lutionary agent in capitalism, his investigations of the nature and effects
of capitalism shifts so greatly with his adoption of the “Standpoint of the
Proletariat”.7
being unachievable, despite perhaps being both possible and viable, in the sense that there
is no agent in our current context which can bring about the alternative in question. For
democracy to be an achievable alternative it must not only be possible in light of basic
planetary conditions, human nature, and other basic facts about the world we inhabit
and plausibly manage to do what its proponents claim without too many negative side-
effects. There must also be a political agent (or combination thereof) that can introduce
democracy in or from the context within which it’s being proposed.
7 Cf. Part III of “Reification and the Consciousness of the Proletariat” in Lukács
(1974), and Löwy (2005). Note that Lukacs, unlike Löwy, seems to miss the fact and
timing of this vital shift in Marx’s thinking.
CHAPTER 4
The earliest uses of one of Marx’s two main terms for alienation (Entfrem-
dung), occur not in dedicated discussions of capitalism, but, more broadly
and rather sparsely—and with virtually no explication. This being said,
it seems to be focused on forms of socially generated powers seemingly
external to and independent of those who create them, which then come
back to dominate and oppress their creators. It also invokes connections
with freedom and subordination; empowerment and disempowerment;
thoughts on the causes and ways of overcoming religious delusions; as
well as with powers unique to, universal among, and distinctive of human
beings as a species. In this chapter, I unpack these ideas by looking at
Marx’s views on the development of capitalist society out of feudalism,
his argument that both feudalism and capitalism are alienating, and his
diagnosis of how both the capitalist state and the economy are alienated
and unfree.
Let’s begin with Marx’s claim that feudal society of the Middle Ages
constituted a perfection of Entfremdung. Marx writes that the feudal
“political constitution was the constitution of private property, but only
because the constitution of property was political”.1 In other words, the
basic nature of feudal society, according to Marx, is a result of the nature
In the Middle Ages there were serfs, feudal property, trade guilds,
scholastic corporations, etc. That is to say, in the Middle Ages property,
trade, society and man were political; the material content of the state was
defined by its form; every sphere of private property had a political char-
acter, or was a political sphere, in other words politics was characteristic
of the different spheres of private life. (…) In the Middle Ages the life of
the people was identical with the life of the state [i.e. political life]. Man
was the real principle of the state, but man was not free. Hence there was
a democracy of unfreedom, a perfected system of alienation. The abstract
reflected antithesis of this is to be found only in the modern world. The
Middle Ages were an age of real dualism; the modern world is the age of
abstract dualism.2
This quotation will require some unpacking. To begin, the term “state”
(der Staat) here refers to political life, but, I contend, not to political
life in the sense of concerns to do with the polity per se, but in terms
of the general public concern. I believe that Marx’s use of the term
“der Staat” here is his translation of “res publica”, which means the
“public thing”, or public concerns or affairs. This is a reading that sits
well both with the letter to Ruge in 1842, where Marx discusses his
work on a critique of Hegel and complains that res publica is “quite
untranslatable into German”.3 It is further supported by Marx’s use of
the term throughout his journalism of 1842–1843 where it is used in the
sense I have outlined.4 Correspondingly, Marx contrasts, inter alia, the
law of a state for its citizens to the law of one party or faction against
another,5 and distinguishes between a “state” and things like the “state
organ” (Staatsorgan),6 “government” (Regierung),7 or “state adminis-
tration” (Staatsverwaltung).8 Lastly, reading “state” as a translation of res
publica denoting public concerns or affairs is confirmed by Marx’s explicit
definition of “the state” as the matter of general concern: “the state is the
‘matter of general concern’, and in reality by ‘matters of general concern’
we mean the state”.9
Clarifying this definition of “the state” allows us to see what Marx
means when he writes that the material content of “the state” was defined
by its form, and that every sphere of private life had a political char-
acter. All of this simply means that the social relations and institutions
that make up the social structure of feudal society were defined by the
legal forms that recognised, defined, and maintained them. Consequently,
every sphere of a person’s life was formally and politically recognised as
the kind of thing that it was. Social roles like serfs, freemen, noblemen,
guild apprentices, guild masters, and so on, were all subject to formal,
3 MECW 1, p. 383/III:1, p. 22. The point Marx is making here is notoriously unclear,
but is likely a political one, possibly expressing exasperation with German thinkers, in
particular Hegel, the value of republican ideas and institutions, or perhaps even that
censorship made it impossible to translate res publica into the German Republik (see
Hunt 1974, p. 31).
4 For particularly good examples of this not referred to below, see I:1, p. 153, 156,
and 276–7.
5 I:1, p. 108.
6 Ibid.
7 Ibid, p. 164, and p. 285.
8 I:1, p. 124. For some discussion of this particular point, see Chitty (2006).
9 Marx (1992, p. 187/I:2, p. 127).
82 P. RAEKSTAD
What Marx is saying here is that in Antiquity, the Middle Ages, and
so on, the human being was the principle of the state in the sense that
people’s day-to-day material lives were identical with their political lives.
Either the state was the public concern of the people, or it was the
concern merely of a minority (either a group or an individual) and those
who did not participate were not, in Marx’s terminology, members of
the state (=the public concern) at all. In either case, those who partici-
pated actively in social decision-making controlled social life (relatively)
transparently.
it is obvious that their very social existence already constitutes their real
participation in it. (…) To be a conscious part of a thing means to take
part of it and to take part in it consciously. Without this consciousness the
member of the state would be an animal.12
is distinguished from that which preceded it by the fact that civil society
does not sustain the individual as a member of a community, as a
communal being [Gemeinwesen]. On the contrary, whether an individual
remains in a class or not depends partly on his work, partly on chance.
The class itself is now no more than a superficial determination of the
individual, for it is neither implicit in his work, nor does it present itself
to him as an objective community, organized according to established laws
and standing in a fixed relationship to him. It is rather the case that he
has no real relation to his substantive activity, to his real class. (…) (The
civil society of the present is the principle of individualism carried to its
logical conclusion. Individual existence is the ultimate goal; activity, work
content, etc. are only means).16
The members of the political state are religious because of the dualism
between individual life and species-life, between the life of civil society and
political life. They are religious inasmuch as man considers political life,
which is far removed from his actual individuality, to be his true life and
inasmuch as religion is here the spirit of civil society and the expression of
the separation and distance of man from man.21
The perfected political state is by its nature the species-life of man in opposi-
tion to his material life. All the presuppositions of this egoistic life continue
to exist outside the sphere of the state in civil society… Where the political
state has attained its full degree of development man leads a double life, a
life in heaven and a life on earth, not only in his mind, in his consciousness,
but in reality. He lives in the political community, where he regards himself
as a communal being, and in civil society, where he is active as a private
individual, regards other men as means, debases himself to a means and
becomes a plaything of alien powers.23
this, in turn, means that this early account of alienation applies much
wider than merely to capitalist civil society and the state, but also e.g. to
feudalism. Having an understanding of the critical diagnosis of modern
society that the early Marx develops, I now proceed to the cure he
proposes: democracy.
References
Secondary
Chitty, A. (2006). The basis of the state in the Marx of 1842. In Moggach (Ed.),
pp. 220–241.
Marx, K., Livingstone, R. (trans.), Benton, G. (trans.) & Colletti, L. (Intro.).
(1992). Karl Marx: Early writings. Penguin.
CHAPTER 5
Democracy
For the early Marx, the solution to the alienation and unfreedom of
capitalism and the modern state is democracy. To show why, I will first
briefly explain some of the ideological background for Marx’s radical
ideas, before turning to his conception of democracy and his discussion
of its most important requirements—like freedom of the press and over-
coming the split between polity and economy. We will then see how Marx
proposes democracy to replace both the modern state and capitalism.
In so doing, the early democratic Marx develops a notion of democracy
that’s much more emancipatory and ambitious than many republicans of
his day and prefigures his socialism to come.
Marx’s positive political programme as a radical democrat seems to
have been well-established before he developed his first theory of alien-
ation. The latter really develops in his 1843 notebooks on Hegel1 and is
then more fully elaborated in On the Jewish Question. However, there is
solid evidence in Marx’s notes, earliest letters, his doctoral dissertation, his
early journalism, and from the radical company he kept while at univer-
sity, that he fits a mould of ideas often associated with the more radical
enlightenment and republican thinkers all the way through to the Young
1 “Entfremdung” does make sporadic appearances in earlier writings, like his doctoral
dissertation. However, these appearances seem to fall short of the developed theories of
alienation found from 1843 onwards.
2 While Marx agrees with equality before the law, it’s worth noting that he explicitly
rejects equality as a useful political value, e.g. in Critique of the Gotha Programme.
3 See Leopold (2007, pp. 204–205).
4 Marx (1992, p. 89/I:2, p. 32).
5 Marx (1992, p. 88/I:2, p. 31).
5 DEMOCRACY 93
6 Note that the term Marx uses in these kinds of statements, der Mensch (literally the
human being, almost always translated as “man”), is gender-neutral, unlike its English or
French counterparts.
7 Marx (1992, p. 87/I:2, p. 31), cf. McLellan (1970, p. 150).
8 Marx’s notes on Spinoza’s works in IV:1, p. 233–276 should be mentioned here,
along with the fact that Marx was, throughout his life, an avowed fan of many
radical enlightenment writers such as Diderot. The way he discusses democracy is very
close to the one that can be found in his notes on Spinoza’s Tractatus, see IV:1, p. 240–
241 (785). Linking Marx to Spinoza has a long pedigree including Engels, Plekhanov,
Althusser, and Negri, who tend to emphasise the importance of Spinoza’s materialism.
Linking Marx’s ideas to more specifically to Spinoza’s ideas on democracy is also far
from rare, see e.g. Abensour (2004), Balibar (2008), Igoin (1977), Kouvelakis (2003),
and Matheron (1977). The connection between Marx and Spinoza himself should not,
however, be overstated, as Marx clearly criticises Spinoza’s philosophy in The Holy Family
and The German Ideology as a kind of metaphysics he believes to be rendered irrelevant
by later forms of materialism. It goes without saying that his concept of freedom is also
stamped by Spinozist influence.
9 Colletti (1992, p. 41), though I reject his indication of any significant Rousseauan
influence. See also Katz (1994).
94 P. RAEKSTAD
The question is not whether civil society should exercise legislative power
through deputies or through all people as individuals. What is crucial is
the extension and greatest possible universalization of the vote, i.e. of both
active and passive suffrage…
[T]he vote is the immediate, direct, not merely representative but actually
existing relation of civil society to the political state. (…) Only when civil
society has achieved unrestricted active and passive suffrage has it really
raised itself to the point of abstraction from itself, to the political existence
which constitutes its true, universal, essential existence.12
12 Marx (1992, p. 191/I:2, p. 130). I will show below how this extension of political
suffrage will, Marx believes, result in the introduction of true democracy.
13 In the passage cited Marx is, of course, discussing the perfection of the political
state and not of a democratic society—though he believes the former will bring about the
latter.
14 I:1, p. 121–169. See also some of the discussions on the ban of the Leipziger
Allgemeinen Zeitung in I:1, p. 291–293, and 328–333, as well as, in a slightly different
context, I:1, p. 313–318. See also Hardt (2000).
5 DEMOCRACY 97
defended” and that if “the immaturity of the human race is the mystical
ground for opposing freedom of the press, then the censorship at any rate
is a highly reasonable means against the maturity of the human race”.15
Importantly, these ideas are spelled out in terms that refer back to his
commitment to human development. Marx thus writes that:
On the positive side, Marx claims that freedom of the press is a posi-
tive good qua its embodiment of the idea of freedom; that a free press
has a value distinct from, and independent of, that of its particular prod-
ucts; that it is essential for securing criticism of, and rational and collective
deliberation on, political actors and actions; and that it is vital for over-
coming mystification in social and political life. Furthermore, he criticises
the Preussische Staats-Zeitung specifically for, inter alia, its conception of
its audience as merely passive receptacles to be mastered by the command-
ments of great works and national media. In so doing, Marx claims, the
newspaper reveals the medieval foundations hiding behind its modern
rhetoric17 —a statement which sits well with his conception of feudalism
as perfected domination, subjugation, and alienation discussed above.
Fifth, unlike modern republics, democracy for Marx does not involve
an essential contradiction between private and particular interests on the
one hand and general ones on the other, because no separate economic
sphere is excluded from communal rule.18 Since there is no separate
economic sphere, Marx’s vision of democracy is distinct from a merely
political democratic republic, which upholds such a split. Accordingly,
Marx criticises the debates between monarchies and republics for still
remaining a “conflict within the framework of the abstract state” (Marx
1992, p. 89/I:2, p. 32). In so doing, Marx could not be clearer that
his vision of democracy goes beyond simply transforming political states
into democratic republics. However, he does think that the political state,
once “perfected” by the introduction of universal suffrage, will neverthe-
less serve to bring about full democracy. Thus “the perfection of this
abstraction is also its transcendence”.19 He expands on this as follows:
What Marx seems to be saying here is that by allowing all the members
of a society to participate in the political process—i.e. by allowing all
members of the economy also to become real, participating parts of the
political state—the existence of these two spheres, qua distinct social
spheres, is dissolved. This can mean one of two things. Either it can mean
that simply extending political participation to all persons implies, in a
logical sense, that the two spheres are no longer distinct because they
now have all the same real members. Or it can mean that the extension
of political participation will suffice to bring it about that the economy
becomes subjected to democratic control, as a result of which the sepa-
ration between state and civil society is dissolved by the fact that they
now both become, where they previously were not, subjected to demo-
cratic control. The former reading holds that the extension of universal
suffrage logically entails the elimination of any civil society/state separa-
tion, whilst the latter reading holds that universal suffrage will suffice to
bring it about that this separation is overcome by the democratic polity
taking over control over the economy and subjecting it to democratic
rule.
In the former interpretation, the extension of voting rights is viewed as
constituting democracy; in the latter interpretation, it is seen as something
which will bring about democracy. I believe the latter reading is to be
preferred for the following reasons:
Only when real, individual man resumes the abstract citizen into himself
and as an individual man has become a species-being in his empirical life,
his individual work and his individual relationships, only when man has
recognized and organized his forces propres as social forces so that social
force is no longer separated from him in the form of political force, only
then will human emancipation be completed.23
proposes is really a plausible one for contemporary societies. In doing so, however, we
must bear in mind both that Marx’s highly optimistic expectations to universal suffrage
seemed plausible to him in light of the history he was drawing on. Lastly, we should point
out that something like this path to revolution—i.e. full social reconstruction beginning
with the implementation of universal suffrage within the modern state—is revised after,
and in response to, the experiences of the Paris Commune in 1871, as he very explicitly
discusses both in The Civil War in France and in the 1872 Preface to the Communist
Manifesto.
23 Marx (1992, p. 234/I:2, p. 162–163).
5 DEMOCRACY 101
The religious spirit can be realized only in so far as that stage in the devel-
opment of the human spirit of which it is the religious expression emerges
and constitutes itself in its secular form. This happens in the democratic
state. Not Christianity but the human foundation of Christianity is the
foundation of this state…
The sovereignty of man – but of man as an alien being distinct from
actual man – is the fantasy, the dream, the postulate of Christianity, whereas
in democracy it is a present and material reality, a secular maxim.24
References
Primary
Marx, K., Livingstone, R. (trans.), Benton, G. (trans.) & Colletti, L. (Intro.).
(1992). Karl Marx: Early writings. Penguin.
Secondary
Abensour, M. (2004). La Démocratie contre l’État: Marx et le moment machi-
avélien (2nd ed.). Éditions du Félin.
Balibar, E. (2008). Spinoza and politics. Verso.
Colletti, L. (1992). Introduction to Marx 1992, pp. 7–56.
Collier, A. (2009). Marx and conservatism. In A. Chitty & M. McIvor (Eds.),
pp. 99–104.
Hardt, H. (2000). Communication is freedom: Karl Marx on press freedom and
censorship. Javnost—The Public, 7 (4), 85–100.
Igoin, A. (1977). De l’ellipse de la théorie politique de Spinoza chez le jeune
Marx. Cahiers Spinoza, 1, 213–228.
Katz, C. (1994). The socialist polis: Antiquity and socialism in Marx’s thought.
The Review of Politics, 56(2), 237–260.
Kouvelakis, S. (2003). Philosophy and revolution: From Kant to Marx. Verso.
Leopold, D. (2007). The young Marx: German philosophy, modern politics, and
human flourishing. Cambridge University Press.
McLellan, D. (1970). Marx before Marxism. Penguin.
Matheron, A. (1977). Le Traité théologico-politique lu par le jeune Marx. Cahiers
Spinoza, 1, 159–212.
CHAPTER 6
Two related shifts in Marx’s work occur in the latter half of 1843 and the
beginning of 1844, both of which turn on the proletariat. Both are also
the outcome of a longer developmental process Marx went through
during the years 1842–1844 and must be understood in that context.
That process begins with Marx’s early journalistic discovery of the impor-
tance of underlying social and economic relations to political and legal
conflicts. It moves on through historical analyses, critiques of Hegel and
others to the formulation of his first theory of alienation along with its
proposed cure in democracy. It takes a decisive step, in A Contribution to
the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right: Introduction, with his identifi-
cation of the proletariat as the revolutionary class. This leads Marx further
into political economy, socialist literature, and becoming acquainted with
working-class organisations. The first shift that occurs is one of theoret-
ical focus. Marx’s political theory goes from being principally focused on
a diagnosis and critique of modern society to becoming a diagnosis and
critique of capitalist society from the perspective of the proletarian class.
Consequently, he shifts from one kind of realist approach to another, from
1 Shortly after coming up with this term, I discovered that it has already been employed
to denote realist approaches to political theory in Geuss (2010, p. 46). By contrast, my
usage of the term denotes one specific class of possible realist approaches.
2 See. I:1, pp. 199–236, and 296–327.
6 FROM REALISATION-ORIENTED TO AGENT-CENTRED … 105
French thinkers of the eighteenth century, embraces within the term ‘civil
society’; that the anatomy of this civil society, however, has to be sought in
political economy. The study of this, which I began in Paris, I continued in
Brussels, where I moved owing to an expulsion order issued by M. Guizot.
The general conclusion at which I arrived and which, once reached, became
the guiding principle of my studies can be summarized as follows. In the
social production of their existence, men inevitably enter into definite rela-
tions, which are independent of their will, namely relations of production
appropriate to a given stage in the development of their material forces
of production. The totality of these relations of production constitutes
the economic structure of society, the real foundation, on which arises a
legal and political superstructure and to which correspond definite forms
of social consciousness…3
This is a claim which Engels, in his letter R. Fischer dated the 15 April
1893, corroborates in even stronger terms, writing that he heard Marx
say that it was specifically the debates on the laws against theft of wood
which shifted his focus from purely political questions to economic ones,
thereby ultimately turning him towards socialism. This spurred Marx, as
he himself points out, to a critical examination of Hegel in his 1843 notes.
As Part II has shown, the diagnosis of capitalism and the state that Marx
develops there is partly economic, in that it briefly discusses the alien
powers that capitalism imposes on people and its exclusion from conscious
control, in addition to his critique of the modern state as alienating. Marx
also offers an envisioned cure, democracy, which he believes can overcome
this alienation.
However, if such a cure is to be instituted, democracy must not just
be possible and viable; it must also be an achievable alternative in modern
societies. Recall that this means: (i) that it is viable; (ii) that there is a
factor, process or agent A; (iii) in context or kind of context c; (iv) such
that, in c, A can bring about the alternative in question. Marx already
believes that: (i’) democracy is a viable institutional alternative to capitalist
civil society and the state. His commitment to introducing democracy to
cure the ills of contemporary society therefore naturally leads Marx to a
concern with (ii)–(iv). He reflects that:
remains central. It thus makes sense to see the shift to agent-centred polit-
ical theory as developing a more sophisticated form of realisation-oriented
realism, rather than something entirely separate from it.
The proletariat, on Marx’s view, is a revolutionary subject, in my sense,
in that it is both the principal factor, process, or agent proposed to bring
about socialism and the agent Marx’s theory needs to appeal to for this
to succeed. The principal factors, processes, or agents he thinks will bring
about his desired alternative is therefore the same as the agent he seeks to
influence. In other agent-centred thinkers, the two can come apart. For
instance, Adam Smith sees the capitalist economy as the factor or process
that will bring about the greater freedom and improved living conditions
for workers, while appealing to the agency of beneficent legislators to put
the right laws and policies in place to allow this to occur.9
An agent-centred approach differs from a merely realisation-oriented
one in a number of respects. Perhaps the most important of these is
that an agent-centred approach insists, as per (1) and (2), on the greater
importance of first attaining an adequate understanding of the context the
theorist is located and acting within. This understanding, in turn, yields
the knowledge the theorist requires concerning the means available for
any possible political action in the relevant context and of the restric-
tions they are under. Only after such an understanding has been attained
does the agent-centred theorist move on to examine which alternatives
are available for political theorising. Having examined these alternatives,
and recommended one or more alternatives over one or more others, an
agent-centred theorist moves on to the question of how best to bring
this or these about. Of the relevant social forces a society generates, the
theorist must address themselves to at least one viable agent that can
act appropriately in the manner required to bring about the theorist’s
preferred alternative. This forms the basis for some of Marx and Engels’
critiques of other socialists. For example, in the Communist Manifesto,
Marx and Engels criticise the utopian socialists for failing to ground their
approach in an accurate understanding of capitalism and its class struggle.
Because they don’t recognise that proletarian class struggle is necessary to
bring about socialism, they try appealing to a wealthy and powerful agent
that cannot be relied upon to do so, namely the capitalist class, and in so
doing (by trying to avoid class struggle and successfully appeal to capital-
ists) end up undermining the only social agency (working class struggle)
that can.
In this chapter, we have seen how Marx’s search for an agent of social
change leads him to identify the proletariat as a revolutionary subject,
and how that changes his approach to political theory from a realisation-
oriented one to an agent-centred one. Before moving on, I will stop
to note the most important effects that this shift had on Marx’s work,
namely the further development of Marx’s critical theory of capitalism.
Once re-examined from this new methodological perspective, along with
his newly added insights from political economy and the socialist move-
ment of his day,10 Marx’s diagnosis of capitalism develops into a new and
much more extensive theory of alienation. Alongside this, he also develops
a new conception of the cure it requires, namely socialism. Building on
this more developed critique of capitalism, Marx further shifts his views
on how political theorists ought to relate themselves to, and interact with,
the social forces and agents of their society. The chapters in Part III will
thus reconstruct this new theory of alienation along with its proposed
cure in socialism, as well as his views on how theorists should act and
relate themselves to the agents they seek to address.
References
Primary
Engels, F., & Henderson, W. O. (Ed. and Intro.). (1967). Engels: Selected
writings. Penguin.
Marx, K., Livingstone, R. (trans.), Benton, G. (trans.) & Colletti, L. (Intro.).
(1992). Karl Marx: Early writings. Penguin.
Secondary
Geuss, R. (2010). Politics and the imagination. Princeton University Press.
10 In this regard, Marx notes mentions the importance of English, French, and German
socialist works, singling out Moses Hess’s writings, those of Wilhelm Weitling, and
Friedrich Engels’ Outlines of a Critique of Political Economy (in Engels, 1967, pp. 148–
176) among the latter as especially influential, see Marx (1992, pp. 280–282/I:2,
pp. 325–326). Hess’ Über das Geldwesen is particularly interesting for its connections
with Marx’s work of the period 1844–5.
6 FROM REALISATION-ORIENTED TO AGENT-CENTRED … 113
1 This should not be confused with (other) discussion of “subjective” versus “objective”.
It’s thus not about e.g. subjective versus objective conditions for revolution or whether
conscious awareness or ideas are involved in it (since obviously ideas are necessary for
social relations with generalised commodity exchange, like capitalism), or about whether
it is in some sense “real” or merely imagined.
PART III: ALIENATION: THE UNFREEDOM OF CAPITALISM 117
these aspects in turn, showing that and how they’re connected to each
other. In so doing, we will see how Marx diagnoses both the personal
and impersonal forms of domination and unfreedom inherent in capitalist
social relations in ways that we would do well to pay more attention to.
3 Including, inter alia, Avineri (1968), Bronfenbrenner (1973), parts of Jaeggi (2005)
and Schacht (1971), Swain (2012, 2019), and Wood (2004).
4 Including, inter alia, Allen (2011), Arthur (1986), Holloway (1997, 2010), Gray
(1986), Hudis (2013), Israel (1971), other parts of Jaeggi (2005), Schacht (1971),
Leopold (2007), Lukács (1974), Mészáros (1972), Musto (2010), Ollman (1976),
Padgett (2007), Postone (1996), Sayers (2011), Swain (2012, 2019), Tabak (2012),
Walliman (1981), and Wolff (1992, 2003). Note that Swain (2012, 2019) appears in
both camps, since his view is a hybrid of the two.
5 Kamenka (1972, p. 77).
6 By “coherent” here I mean not just negatively coherent in the sense of logical consis-
tency, but also in the further positive sense which Kamenka denies, namely in the sense of
there being comprehensible and plausible (in their own terms) links between the different
kinds of alienation Marx distinguishes and discusses.
122 P. RAEKSTAD
Labour not only produces commodities; it also produces itself and the
workers as a commodity and it does so in the same proportion in which it
produces commodities in general.9
In other words, the labour process produces not only goods and
services; it also produces and reproduces the network of social relations
within and through which it takes place. Capitalist labour processes don’t
just make goods and services—though that’s one thing they do. They also
continuously produce and reproduce the capitalist social relations that
these labour processes are part of.
In these two respects, then, the worker becomes a slave of his object; first
in that he receives an object of labour, i.e. he receives work, and secondly in
that he receives means of subsistence. Firstly, then, so that he can exist as a
worker, and secondly as a physical subject. The culmination of this slavery is
that it is only as a worker that he can maintain himself as a physical subject
and only as a physical subject that he is a worker.17
19 For more on this, see I:2, pp. 189–207 and 327–51. Note that this argument, as it
appears in Marx, originally speaks of survival at all, i.e. of minimal physical subsistence.
However, as his more considered passages in published works such as Volume I of Capital
bear witness to, and in the interests of more charitable interpretation in light of certain
minimum welfare provisions currently available in welfare states (though less and less
so), we are justified in modifying the premise to securing a minimally decent level of
subsistence, in part determined by contextual moral and historical factors (as Marx calls
them).
20 The final clause of the last cited sentence is very tricky, and less important in this
context. Consequently, I leave it aside for the time being.
21 Marx (1992, pp. 325–326/I:2, pp. 237/366), translation of “Entfremdung”
modified from “estrangement” to “alienation”.
126 P. RAEKSTAD
indeed, it is also distinct from the simpler, violently physical, and perhaps
more easily perceivable forms of coercion which prevail under, e.g. slavery.
This kind of capitalist coercion is made possible only by the fact that
a class of capitalists control the products of the labour process—both
means of production and consumable commodities. If workers were not
excluded from the consumable commodities they produce, they would
not need to receive wages from someone or something else in order
to gain access to those commodities. If capitalists did not monopolise
society’s productive property, workers would have no need to work for
capitalists. They could simply set up their own small farms and businesses,
a network of cooperatives, a collection of communes, or any number of
other configurations to meet their needs themselves.22
Failing to notice this has led to some hilarious misadventures on the
part of individual capitalists:
A Mr Peel (…) took with him from England to the Swan River district of
Western Australia means of subsistence and of production to the amount
of £50,000. This Mr Peel even had the foresight to bring besides, 300
persons of the working class, men, women and children. Once he arrived
at his destination, ‘Mr Peel was left without a servant to make his bed
or fetch him water from the river.’ Unhappy Mr. Peel, who provided for
everything except the export of English relations of production to Swan
River!23
Mr. Peel had not neglected any purely physical items necessary
for successful capitalist production—consumable commodities, means of
production, and workers to utilise them. The source of Mr. Peel’s error,
according to Marx, lies in the fact that once these items are moved out
of the context of capitalist social relations they cease to function as they
do under the capitalism of his native England. In Western Australia, the
would-be workers were faced with alternative consumable commodities
and/or means of production which they could access. In other words,
they were no longer excluded, as a class, from productive property. They
were thus no longer under any material compulsion to work. In the
absence of such force, these workers were able to choose to use their
labour-power to enrich themselves rather than Mr Peel, the capitalist.
To many liberals, the exclusion of workers from the means of produc-
tion and forcing them to work for capitalists seems natural and inevitable.
In reality, these conditions are the product of violent state intervention
and enforcement at the behest of the ruling classes both within and
(through imperialism and colonialism) outside of the imperial core. Marx
writes:
24 Marx (1990, p. 382/II:6, p. 274). For more thorough accounts, see Kropotkin
(1997, 2013) and Polanyi (2001).
25 Marx (1990, pp. 915–916/II:6, p. 674).
26 Marx (1990, p. 933/II:6, p. 685).
128 P. RAEKSTAD
such things only when they are the bearers of certain social relations
between persons and they become the bearers of such relations only
if and when there is a class of people which is systematically excluded
from them. The same point is made in Theories of Surplus Value, where
Marx writes that “[c]apital is productive of value only as a relation,
in so far as it is a coercive force on wage labour, compelling it to
perform surplus-labour” and that it “only produces value as the power
of labour’s own material conditions over labour when these are alienated
from labour”.27 In other words, the production of value in the capitalist
mode of production presupposes workers’ exclusion from the product of
labour—in particular the means of production and necessary consumable
commodities—because this is what forces workers to work for capitalists.
Moving the discussion to Capital brings me to an important point:
the fact that what Marx in the Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of
1844 calls alienation from product is retained, minus the terminology, at
the heart of Marx’s diagnosis of capitalism throughout all of his subse-
quent works. Indeed, it’s in the later writings on political economy that
Marx most precisely articulates not only how capitalism forces workers
into dominating labour relations, but also how the impersonal powers
inherent in capitalist social relations themselves dominate those who are
subject to them. In The German Ideology, Marx and Engels point out that
“[i]n history up to the present it is certainly likewise an empirical fact that
separate individuals have (…) become more and more enslaved under a
power alien to them”, which has “become more and more enormous
and, in the last instance, turns out to be the world market ”.28 Among
many other places, Marx returns to point out that people under capitalism
are dominated by impersonal social relations in Volume 1 of Capital,
where he distinguishes between “the power of landed property, based on
personal relations of domination and servitude” on the one hand, and,
on the other hand, the “power of money [under capitalism], which is
impersonal”, going on to quote the French proverb “L’argent n’a pas de
maître” /“money has no master”.29
41 I fully intend to stay away from the complexities of Marx’s economic theories,
including issues regarding the labour theory of value, surplus labour, profits, etc.
7 ALIENATION AND UNFREEDOM 133
How could the product of the worker’s activity confront him as some-
thing alien if it were not for the fact that in the act of production he
was alienating himself from himself? So if the product of labour is alien-
ation, production itself must be active alienation, the alienation of activity,
the activity of alienation. The alienation of the object of labour merely
summarizes the alienation, the alienation in the activity of labour itself.42
the fact that labour is external to the worker, i.e. does not belong to his
essential being; that he therefore does not confirm himself in his work, but
denies himself, feels miserable and not happy, does not develop free mental
and physical energy, but mortifies his flesh and ruins his mind. Hence the
worker feels himself only when he is not working; when he is working he
does not feel himself. He is at home when he is not working, and not at
home when he is working.44
Since alienated labour prevents the exercise of our powers for conscious
self-direction, it becomes undesirable. Nevertheless, it is something
workers are materially coerced into doing, rendering it involuntary or
forced labour. Such labour is not the satisfaction of a need: the labour
itself does not satisfy any particular drive on the part of the worker.
Instead, the labour becomes merely a means to satisfy needs outside of
itself—needs for basic survival and financial security, for example. The
alien character of this labour, the sense in which the labour is something
workers are forced to do because of their social subjection to external
powers and imperatives, is verified, Marx claims, by the fact that as soon as
such compulsion disappears, the work itself is avoided as much as possible.
Third and finally:
the external character of labour for the worker is demonstrated by the fact
that it belongs not to him but to another, and that in it he belongs not
to himself but to another. Just as in religion the spontaneous activity of
the human imagination, the human brain and the human heart detaches
itself from the individual and reappears as the alien activity of a god or of
a devil, so the activity of the worker is not his self-activity. It belongs to
another, it is a loss of self.46
Work under capitalism is sold like any other commodity; and in that
sense, and for that reason, it can be described as belonging to another
for as long as it lasts. Human practical activity, in an alienated economy,
is not workers’ own self-activity in and through which they employ
their powers to fulfil their needs intrinsic to the process, and in turn
develop and increase their individual and collective powers. Instead, it
is a process through which workers do not satisfy any intrinsic needs—
only extrinsic ones—and through which they generate certain powers over
which they have no control, which impose a variety of external purposes
and imperatives and thus come to dominate and control them.
Insofar as these powers are nothing more than workers’ own powers,
and insofar as they are outside of workers’ control and subjects them to
its purposes and imperatives, workers’ activity under capitalism is not their
forced or involuntary labour in some sense; and (iii) the workers’ activity
belongs to another.
Not only does Marx retain this analysis in his later works; he deepens
it to explore the relations of domination and unfreedom that characterise
capitalist labour processes and develops a striking analysis of capitalism’s
hierarchical division of labour. In The German Ideology, Marx and Engels
had clearly derided the separation between mental and manual labour, and
the relations of domination and authority that it’s part and parcel of. But
it’s only in later works of political economy that Marx begins to explore
this in a more fine-grained way that arguably prefigures later Marxist and
anarchist discussions of the forms of power and privilege operating not
just between owners and workers, but between a small elite of highly
powerful and privileged managers and workers as well.
In Volume I of Capital, he writes that:
54 For discussions of this concept, see Walker (1979) and Wright (1980). This concept
should not be confused with the much broader and less coherent idea of a “Professional-
Managerial Class”, which, unlike the Coordinator Class, is not precisely defined in terms
of a particular set of relations with respect to the means of production.
55 It’s perhaps worth pointing out that Marx is often, wrongly, accused of thinking that
there are only two classes under capitalism. This has no basis in fact. For one, throughout
his later works discussing history and politics—like the Communist Manifesto, The 18 th
Brumaire of Napoleon Bonaparte, and the Civil War in France—there’s a much larger
number of classes identified in capitalism alone, and though he does think that, at the
time, society is getting polarised into two main camps, he also clearly says that there are
several classes in each camp, not that there are, or ever will be, only two. For obvious
reasons, this also means that the idea that Marx takes a view of class so narrow-minded
as being based only in property ownership, rather than in social-relational positions, is
ruled out. On the other hand, the fact that Volume I of Capital only focuses on two
main classes is the obvious result of it zooming in only on certain very particular parts of
the social relations of capitalism. It does not follow from that that real-existing capitalist
societies only have two classes (and as is clear from Marx’s other writings, he doesn’t
think this), for the same reasons that zooming in on a few laws of physics explaining how
gravity works (in abstraction from, e.g. friction, air resistance, lift, and so on) doesn’t
mean that, or that those physicists think that, birds can’t fly.
7 ALIENATION AND UNFREEDOM 139
56 In 1872, Engels writes a text called On Authority that is sometimes argued to conflict
with this. I can’t get into the details of the text or its arguments here, especially because
the wording of On Authority requires careful attention to detail and is often misleading
to those who don’t know the exact debates within the socialist movement it’s responding
to. Engels’ text is primarily about large-scale organisation requiring binding decisions and
the importance of delegation, which many later organisations and movements set up by
anarchists and syndicalist did feature. Engels can be interpreted in a number of different
ways here, including as making a general point about certain anarchists’ doubts about how
the First International should be structured or as straw-manning a more general rejection
of top-down modes of organisation that Marx, anarchists, and many left Marxists share.
Either way, we have seen that Marx’s views on this are clear from his writings.
57 Marx (1992, p. 327/I:2, pp. 239/368).
140 P. RAEKSTAD
Another point one might raise against Marx’s account is that with the
advent of the modern welfare state the old material coercion that once
forced people to work for capitalists has disappeared—either in part or in
whole. Since modern welfare states enable people to survive and repro-
duce, at some minimal level, without working, it simply is no longer the
case that workers have no other choice to satisfy their most basic needs
by going to work for capital. It is hard to see how such an objection is
not either deeply mistaken about Marx’s account or either overly opti-
mistic or pessimistic (depending on the attitude one takes towards it)
about the nature and generosity of modern welfare states. On the one
hand, material coercion in Marx should probably not be read as limited
merely to threats of things like thirsting or starving to death. Arguably,
beggars could survive even in Marx’s day without a job; at least some
of the old and sick could as well from minimal support systems avail-
able in families or local communities (including church aid of various
kinds); and so forth. A decent standard of living is the sort of thing
which varies considerably with natural, social, and historical contexts, a
fact of which Marx was well aware. Modern welfare states do provide
their citizens with a certain minimum; the fact that this is so in the more
privileged countries of the world is in large part thanks to the successes of
social movements of the last centuries. Historically speaking, however,
they have been highly limited responses to such movements. Further-
more, they tend to be rolled back and coercively re-shaped in order to
eliminate, as far as possible, any negative impacts it might have in terms
of reducing the material coercion to labour under capital.60 Briefly put,
modern welfare states do provide significant benefits for workers, but they
are far from sufficiently generous, all things considered, to reliably secure
workers from coercion to labour over time.
Furthermore, it is far from clear that the level of benefits that modern
welfare states provide in fact succeeds in eliminating the material coercion
workers experience to work under the yoke of capital. Even the most
privileged welfare states in the Nordic countries fail to provide their poor
with what is considered to be an acceptably high standard of living for
themselves and their children, considering the requirements for decent life
in those countries, and this is well-known among those affected. There is
no reason to suspect that these kinds of conditions will be better in any
other part of the world. The objection, then, fails. It is not the case that
modern welfare states are sufficiently generous to remove the material
coercion to work for capital (or, in mixed economies, the state) both
because it is not clear that the benefits they provide are sufficiently high,
stable, and free from restrictions and coercion to work and because it
is not clear that the benefits provided are high enough in light of the
naturally, socially, and historically mediated requirements for a decent life
in the societies in question. With that objection behind us, let us move
on to some of the further two kinds of alienation that Marx discusses.
61 See Fromm (2004), Geras (1983), Hudis (2013), Kain (1988, 1992), Kamenka
(1969, 1972), Leopold (2007), Mészáros (1972), Ollman (1976), Sayers (2007, 2011),
and Wood (2004). See also section (C) of Appendix 1.
62 Marx (1992, p. 328/I:2, p. 369/240).
144 P. RAEKSTAD
Man makes his life activity itself an object of his will and consciousness.
(…) [Man] is a conscious being, i.e. his own life is an object for him,
only because he is a species-being. Only because of that is his activity free
activity. Alienated labour reverses the relationship so that man, just because
he is a conscious being, makes his life activity, his being [Wesen], a mere
means for his existence.63
Marx’s point here is that it’s above all in production that humans live
their collective species-lives. It’s in our characteristic (conscious) forms of
productive activity that we distinguish ourselves from the rest of nature
and come to realise ourselves within that nature. In other words, produc-
tion is what constitutes human species-life in general. I thus agree with
Sean Sayers that, for Marx (at least from 1844 onwards) “work is the
fundamental and central activity in human life”65 and a “fundamental part
of the human process of self-development”66 and with Mehmet Tabak
that “objective activity (production, labor, etc.) is the essential human
characteristic responsible for the concretization of human essence in and
through nature”.67
Now, recall what workers are alienated from when they are alienated
from their objects: they are alienated not from physical things as such, but
from the social relations which the objects they produce are the bearers
of. As we’ve seen in the discussion of the first two kinds of alienation
above, Marx argues that alienation from productive activity is entailed,
in a very specific sense, by the alienation from products seen under capi-
talism. On Marx’s view, this productive activity is the “fundamental and
central activity in human life”,68 which he calls the “objectification of the
species-life of man”.69 If alienation from product entails the alienation
from productive activity, and if productive activity can truly be said to
amount to humans’ species-life in general, then alienation from product
can also be said to entail the alienation from human species-life in general.
This explains how, on Marx’s view, alienation results in the “tearing
away” of humans’ species-life, but in what sense does alienation make
human life activity—their being—into a mere means for their existence?
As we have seen above, Marx argues that alienated labour thwarts the
intrinsic enjoyment that workers’ productive activity might otherwise
contain. Because of this, people engage in productive activity only for
purely extrinsic ends, such as maintaining one’s physical existence. If
alienated production thus inevitably results in one’s productive activity
becoming a mere means for extrinsic ends, and if production can be said
to amount to one’s species-life in general, then it follows that alienated
production can be said to inevitably result in making human species-life
and activity in general a mere means for securing one’s extrinsic ends,
such as one’s continued existence.
The argument I have just sketched provides a valuable reply to a
possible counter-argument to Marx’s critique of capitalism. It might be
argued that even though conditions of alienation in a capitalist economy
do thwart certain human powers for conscious self-directed activity, there
are—at least in some very privileged countries—many opportunities to
exercise such powers in other realms of human life and endeavour. We can
use such powers in the formation, execution, and revision of our plans of
life; we can use such powers in the enjoyment of our leisure time; we can
use, perhaps, some of them in political activities; we can exercise them in
areas of civil society such as directly democratic propaganda organisations;
and so on.
70 It was widely accepted at least among the Scottish Enlightenment thinkers such as
Adam Smith, see for instance Berry (1997, Ch. 4).
71 Smith (1976, pp. 781–782). Note that by “understandings” here Smith does not
mean merely our cognitive grasp of things, but the development of our wider cognitive
and moral virtues. For more on this, see Raekstad (2016, 2020a). In the latter, I made
this case as part of a reconstruction of Adam Smith’s shift from focusing on freedom
and independence in the polity to freedom and independence in the workplace, which he
does in ways that I argue prefigure later labour republican ideas (on which see Gourevitch,
2015). Note that by 1844 Marx was well-acquainted with both sets of ideas. Finally, I
want to point out that one of the limitations of this view, which Marx inherits, is its
relative neglect of the relations and processes structing much of the lived activities of so
many women at the time, and still, involved in unpaid reproductive labour, an oversight
that later generations of Marxist feminists have rightly worked to remedy. I cannot explore
this further, but for an excellent place to start see Bhattacharya (2017).
7 ALIENATION AND UNFREEDOM 147
regards the product of his labour, (...) as an alien, hostile, and powerful
object which is independent of him, then his relationship to that object is
such that another man – alien, hostile, powerful and independent of him –
is its master. If he relates to his own activity as unfree activity, he relates to
it as activity in the service, under the rule, coercion and yoke of another
man.75
[T]hrough alienated labour man not only produces his relationship to the
object and to the act of production as to alien and hostile powers; he also
produces the relationship in which other men stand to his production and
product, and the relationship in which he stands to these other men. Just
as he creates his own production as a loss of reality, a punishment, and
his own product as a loss, a product which does not belong to him, so
he creates the domination of the non-producer over production and its
product…76
(…)
Thus through estranged, alienated labour the worker creates the rela-
tionship of another man, who is alien to labour and stands outside it, to
that labour. The relation of the worker to labour creates the relation of the
capitalist (…) to that labour. Private property [of the means of production
in its capitalist form] is therefore the product, result and necessary conse-
quence of alienated labour, of the external relation of the worker to nature
and to himself.
Private property thus derives from an analysis of the concept of alienated
labour…77
The propertied class and the class of the proletariat present the same
human self-estrangement. But the former class feels at ease and strength-
ened in this self-estrangement, it recognises estrangement as its own power
and has in it the semblance of a human existence. The latter feels annihi-
lated in estrangement; it sees in it its own powerlessness and the reality of
an inhuman existence…
Within this antithesis the private property-owner is therefore the conser-
vative side, the proletarian the destructive side. From the former arises the
action of preserving the antithesis, from the latter the action of annihilating
it…
When the proletariat is victorious, it by no means becomes the absolute
side of society, for it is victorious only by abolishing itself and its opposite.
Then the proletariat disappears as well as the opposite which determines
it, private property.79
78 This process of argument is evidently a deeply Hegelian one that he also essentially
follows both in the introduction to the Grundrisse and in the construction of Capital. I
shall not discuss it further here since it would take us far off topic.
79 MECW 4, p. 36/MEGA I:3, p. 206.
1
7 ALIENATION AND UNFREEDOM 151
As we can see, Marx thinks that while workers and capitalists are both
subject to the alienation of capitalist social relations, their resulting social
situation and experiences are very different. Workers are disempowered,
unfree, and experience their lives and activities as such, and as a result
they will seek to overthrow these oppressive social relations with free
ones. By contrast, capitalists feel empowered and in control by virtue of
their relational positions of greater power, wealth, and privilege vis-à-vis
workers. Consequently, they will seek to preserve these relations of alien-
ation and unfreedom against the actions of workers. Just like it’s fruitless
to appeal to the moral sense of our oppressors, Marx thinks it is fruit-
less to appeal to those in positions of great power, wealth, and privilege
to grant us emancipation.80 If capitalists succeed, capitalism remains. If
workers succeed, capitalism is overthrown, and since overthrowing capi-
talism entails abolishing capitalist social relations, the positions defined by
these relations, like worker and capitalist, will be abolished as well. As we
will see in Chapter 9, this plays an important role in Marx’s later thoughts
on the revolutionary contradictions of capitalism.
Before moving on to a discussion of Marx’s conception of a cure for
capitalism, it’s worth summarising the diagnosis his second theory of
alienation pioneered. I have argued that Marx’s second theory of alien-
ation is a diagnosis of the ways, in which capitalism, by its (relational)
nature, thwarts human freedom. It does so by describing how, under capi-
talism, workers in the process of production produce and reproduce the
social relations which keep them in bondage at the same time as they
produce the products which are their bearers. This also involves a process
of production from which workers are alienated, which in turn entails
that workers are alienated from their (human) species-being. Finally, the
production and reproduction of capitalist social relations also requires the
production and reproduction not only of workers as workers, but also of
some other people as capitalists, from whom those workers are alienated.
We have thus traced the nature and origins of the four kinds of alien-
ation Marx discusses in his second theory of alienation: alienation from
product; alienation from labour process; alienation from species-being;
and alienation from others. We have also seen that the basic components
of this second theory of alienation are retained throughout Marx’s later
works all the way through Capital. In Chapter 9, we will even see that
80 This becomes an important part of his critique of the utopian socialists, see the
Communist Manifesto.
152 P. RAEKSTAD
it forms the core of one of Marx’s most enduring tenets, that capitalism
is characterised by two revolutionary contradictions: between the powers
and relations of production and between workers and capitalists. With an
understanding of Marx’s diagnosis of capitalism’s ills, it’s time to turn to
remedy that he proposes: socialism.
References
Primary
Marx, K., & Burns, E. (trans.). (1969). Theories of surplus value: Part I .
Lawrence & Wishart.
Marx, K., Fowkes, B. (trans.) & Mandel, E. (intro.). (1990). Capital: A critique
of political economy (Vol. 1). Penguin.
Marx, K., Fowkes, B., (trans.) & Mandel, E. (intro.). 1991. Capital: A critique
of political economy (Vol. 3). Penguin.
Marx, K., Livingstone, R. (trans.), Benton, G. (trans.) & Colletti, L. (Intro.).
(1992). Karl Marx: Early writings. Penguin.
Marx, K., & Nicolaus, M. (trans.). (1993). Grundrisse: Foundations of a critique
of political economy. Penguin.
Secondary
Allen, K. (2011). Marx and the alternative to capitalism. Pluto Press.
Arrighi, G., Hopkins, T. K., & Wallerstein, I. (2012). Anti-systemic movements.
Verso.
Arthur, C. J. (1986). Dialectics of labour: Marx and his relation to Hegel. Basil
Blackwell.
Avineri, S. (1968). The social and political thought of Karl Marx. Cambridge
University Press.
Berry, C. J. (1997). Social theory of the Scottish enlightenment. Edinburgh
University Press.
Bhattacharya, T. (Ed.). (2017). Social reproduction theory: Remapping class,
recentering oppression. Pluto Press.
Bronfenbrenner, M. (1973). A harder look at alienation. Ethics, 83(4), 267–282.
Foster, J. B., Clark, B., & York, R. (2010). The ecological rift: capitalism’s war
on the earth. Monthly Review Press.
Fromm, E. (2004). Marx’s concept of man. Continuum.
Geras, N. (1983). Marx and human nature: Refutation of a legend. Verso.
González-Ricoy, I. (2014). The republican case for workplace democracy. Social
Theory and Practice, 40(2), 232–254.
7 ALIENATION AND UNFREEDOM 153
1 In fact, as late as 1851 Marx re-published his articles defending freedom of the press
without changes. See Draper (1977, p. 59). For more discussion on Marx and Engels’
views on freedom of the press, see also Hunt (1974, 1984).
2 For more on this, see especially Marx’s discussion of the Paris Commune in The Civil
War in France.
3 It’s perhaps worth parenthetically noting that a number of things that might seem
anti-democratic to contemporary liberals are in fact just the opposite. For instance, in his
text on “The Constitution of the French Republic”, Marx writes of “the old constitu-
tional folly. The condition of a ‘free government’ is not the division, but the UNITY
of power. The machinery of government cannot be too simple. It is always the craft
of knaves to make it complicated and mysterious” (MECW 10, p. 570/I:10, p. 540).
Talk of “UNITY of power” may seem anti-democratic to contemporary liberals, but
Socialism as Emancipation
The fundamental goal of replacing capitalism with a free society remains
throughout Marx’s works from 1844 onwards. In the Economic and
Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844, Marx writes that “free conscious
activity constitutes the species-character of man”5 then socialism is “the
true appropriation of the human essence through and for man; it is the
complete restoration of man to himself as a social, i.e. human, being…”.6
It thus constitutes “the genuine resolution of the conflict between man
and nature, and between man and man… It is the solution of the riddle
of history and knows itself to be the solution”.7
Footnote 3 continued
the reality is just the opposite. Recall that the doctrine of the separation of powers is in e.g.
Montesquieu (1998), to the US Founding Fathers (Hamilton et al., 2003) and beyond,
designed not to achieve democracy, but rather to divide political rule between different
powers, limiting the democratic element to one of them and ensuring the others are more
monarchical and aristocratic. In other words, the standard doctrine of the separation of
powers is an explicitly anti-democratic idea used to deliberately prevent democracy. Marx’s
opposition to this doctrine is thus in reality a radically democratic move in opposition
to the anti-democratic tenets of liberalism, past and present. I think it says something
important about how subject to liberal ideology we are that we keep confusing anti-
democratic liberal ideas with the very essence of democratic governance.
4 For more detailed discussion, see Ollman (1977), Campbell (2011), and Hudis
(2013).
5 Marx (1992, p. 328/I:2, pp. 240/369).
6 Marx (1992, p. 348/I:2, pp. 263/389).
7 Marx (1992, p. 348, pp. 263/389).
8 THE SOCIALIST ALTERNATIVE 157
Later, Marx and Engels write that “things have now come to such a
pass that the individuals must appropriate the existing totality of produc-
tive powers, not only to achieve self-activity, but, also, merely to safeguard
their very existence”.8 They go on to write that:
In other words, socialist society will be the first to fully realise human
freedom as self-direction, which in turn enables greater development
among the united individuals. Under these conditions, we will see that in
“the real community the individuals obtain their freedom in and through
their association”.10 As Marx points out in the Grundrisse, socialism
enables and generates “[u]niversally developed individuals, whose social
relations, as their own communal [gemeinschaftlich] relations, are hence
also subordinated to their own communal control”.11 This includes social
ownership of the means of production, i.e. ownership and control by the
associated producers themselves, rather than by states or capitalists.12
By restoring full communal control over the social relations that
determine their lives, socialism restores the full range of modern social
and individual powers to the collective self-rule of its participants.
8 MECW 5, p. 87/I:5, p. 111. Here too I have modified the translation of “productive
forces” to “productive powers”.
9 MECW 5, p. 88/I:5, pp. 113–114. Here too I have modified the translation of
“productive forces” to “productive powers”.
10 MECW 5, p. 78/I:5, p. 96.
11 Marx (1993, p. 162/II.1.1, p. 91), square brackets in the translation.
12 The misunderstanding that socialism amounts to state ownership is nowhere to
be found in Marx or Engels. In response to this misunderstanding developing, Engels
ridicules the idea e.g. in a note added to the 1892 edition of Socialism, Utopian and
Scientific. In his Critique of the Gotha Programme Marx even argues against states funding
workers’ cooperatives, arguing that socialist cooperation “has nothing in common with
establishing co-operative societies with state aid!” and that cooperatives under capitalism
“are only of value if they are independent creations of the workers and not creatures of
the government or the bourgeoisie” (Marx 1996, p. 221/I:25, p. 20).
158 P. RAEKSTAD
Participatory Planning
In order to prevent the personal domination of lords and capitalists,
as well as the impersonal domination of competitive markets, socialism
must be organised through some sort of participatory democratic plan-
ning. In the German Ideology, Marx and Engels write of socialism as a
“society [that] regulates the general production”,13 and of the need for
the associated producers to collectively appropriate the totality of soci-
ety’s productive powers. Later in the Grundrisse, Marx writes of “[f]ree
individuality, based on the universal development of individuals and on
the subordination of their communal, social productivity as their social
wealth”.14 Nothing, Marx writes, could be more “absurd than to postu-
late the control by the united individuals of their total production, on
the basis of exchange value, of money”.15 Generalised exchange of the
products of labour, and market organisation of social wealth and activity,
“stands in antithesis” to the “free exchange among individuals who are
associated on the basis of common appropriation and control of the means
of production”,16 because these kinds of “private exchange create[s]
world trade” and so this particular form of “private independence creates
complete dependence on the so-called world market”.17
In other words, socialist planning must replace capitalist-type markets,
because retaining them would keep workers subject to the dependence
18 Dependence and domination are generally used interchangeably. The German term
Marx uses here is Abhängigkeit, which can be translated into either. The translation in
question chooses to translate this and its complementary term as dependence and inde-
pendence, respectively, and which retains Marx’s play on Abhängigkeit/Unabhängigkeit
in the passage, and I’ve chosen not to modify this for the same reason.
19 For one famous example of Marx doing this explicitly, see his critique of Lassallean
proposals for economic reform in Critique of the Gotha Programme.
20 Marx (1990, pp. 171–172/II:6, p. 109).
21 Marx (1990, p. 447/II:6, p. 326).
160 P. RAEKSTAD
the division of labour offers us the first example of the fact that, as long
as man remains in naturally evolved society, that is, as long as a cleavage
exists between the particular and the common interest, as long, there-
fore, as activity is not voluntarily, but naturally, divided, man’s own deed
becomes an alien power opposed to him, which enslaves him instead of
being controlled by him. For as soon as the division of labour comes into
being, each man has a particular, exclusive sphere of activity, which is forced
upon him and from which he cannot escape.25
forced into particular social roles or spheres, being hindered from leaving
them, and how this leads to people being subjected to alien powers that
dominate them, making them unfree. Delving further into the political
economy of capitalism naturally deepens this analysis.
Perhaps the most extensive collection of Marx’s discussion on the divi-
sion of labour, and the necessity of its overcoming under socialism, is to
be found in Volume I of Capital, where three distinct but related issues
are broached: (a) the hierarchical division of labour and of labour’s organ-
isation within workplaces; (b) the division of labour seen under capitalism
(especially in factory production); and (c) the necessity of overcoming
both of these in a future socialist society. My discussion will move through
all three, respectively.
According to Marx, the advent of capitalist manufacture “not
only subjects the previously independent worker to the discipline and
command of capital, but creates in addition a hierarchical structure
amongst the workers themselves ”.26 We saw in the previous chapter how
Marx argues that as capitalist cooperation “extends its scale, this despo-
tism develops the forms that are peculiar to it”, by capitalists devolving
“the work of direct and constant supervision of the individual workers and
groups of workers to” to a dedicated apparatus of managers comparing
the “industrial army of workers under the command of a capitalist” to
real armies.27
Thus, “in the society where the capitalist mode of production prevails,
anarchy in the social division of labour and despotism in the manufac-
turing division of labour mutually condition each other”.28 The effects
this has on relations of power and domination between workers and
capitalists are clear-cut:
Here too Marx stresses not only the hierarchical division of labour, but
also its effects on workers’ development:
Factory work exhausts the nervous system to the uttermost; at the same
time, it does away with the many-sided play of the muscles, and confiscates
every atom of freedom, both in bodily and in intellectual activity. Even
We saw in Part IV (…) that within the capitalist system all methods for
raising the social productivity of labour are put into effect at the cost of
the individual worker; that all means for the development of production
undergo a dialectical inversion so that they become means of domination
and exploitation of the producers; they distort the worker into a fragment
of a man, they degrade him to the level of an appendage of a machine,
they destroy the actual content of his labour by turning it into a torment;
they alienate [entfremden] from him the intellectual potentialities of the
labour process in the same proportion as science is incorporated into it as
an independent power; they deform the conditions under which he works,
subject him during the labour process to a despotism the more hateful
for its meanness; they transform his life-time into working-time… But all
methods for the production surplus-value are at the same time methods of
accumulation… Accumulation of wealth at one pole is, therefore, at the
same time accumulation of misery, the torment of labour, slavery, igno-
rance, brutalization and moral degradation at the opposite pole, i.e. on
the side of the class that produces its own product as capital.35
where nobody has one exclusive sphere of activity but each can become
accomplished in any branch he wishes, society regulates the general
production and thus makes it possible for me to do one thing today and
another tomorrow, to hunt in the morning, fish in the afternoon, rear
cattle in the evening, criticise after dinner, just as I have a mind, without
ever becoming hunter, fisherman, shepherd or critic.39
45 See e.g. Schweickart (1996). Such models are more detailed than I can adequately
describe here, including models of banking, taxation, investment, and interaction with
familiar types of state institutions.
46 Kasmir (1996, 2018).
168 P. RAEKSTAD
and physical labour, has disappeared; after labour has become not merely
a means to live but the foremost need in life; after the multifarious devel-
opment of individuals has grown along with their productive powers, and
all the springs of cooperative wealth flow more abundantly - only then can
the limited horizon of bourgeois right be wholly transcended, and society
can inscribe on its banner: from each according to his abilities, to each
according to his needs!49
61 For discussion of this model, see Albert (2003), Albert and Hahnel (1978, 1991,
1999), Hahnel (2005, 2012) and Raekstad (2011, 2013). These are also often called “Bal-
anced Job Complexes” rather than “Balanced Jobs”. I follow Hahnel (2012) in preferring
the latter term, for no other reason than that it’s less bulky and conveys its meaning just
as well.
8 THE SOCIALIST ALTERNATIVE 175
62 Mészáros (1986).
176 P. RAEKSTAD
63 Apart from the other books on ParEcon already mentioned, see the essays collected
in Walker (1979) and also Wright (1980).
64 See Ness and Azzellini (2011).
8 THE SOCIALIST ALTERNATIVE 177
65 Pérotin, 2018, p. 3. For an older review of relevant literature, see Levine and Tyson
(1990) and for two metastudies, see Doucouliagos, 1995 and Doucouliagos, 1997.
66 Quoted in Schweikart (1996, p. 100).
178 P. RAEKSTAD
may be described as one in which the group takes over complete respon-
sibility for the total cycle of operations involved in mining the coal-face.
No member of the group has a fixed work role. Instead, the men deploy
themselves, depending on the requirements of the on-going group task.
Within the limits of technological and safety requirements they are free to
evolve their own way of organising and carrying out their task. They are
not subject to any external authority in this respect, nor is there within the
group itself any member who takes over a formal directive leadership func-
tion. Whereas in conventional long-wall working the coal-getting task is
split into four to eight separate work roles, carried out by different teams,
each paid at a different rate, in the composite group members are no longer
paid directly for any of the tasks carried out. The all-in wage agreement
is, instead, based on the negotiated price per ton of coal produced by the
team. The income obtained is divided equally among team members.68
In this firm we will show that at the same time: thousands of workers
operated virtually without supervision as conventionally understood, and
at high productivity; the highest wage in British industry was paid;
high quality products were produced at acceptable prices in extensively
mechanised plants; the management conducted its affairs at unusually
which may or may not be valued, but that it is, or is taken to be, some-
thing which is neutral with respect to other evaluative commitments like
freedom and human development. This premise is false. Efficiency is often
construed as the value-neutral comparison between the costs and bene-
fits of various inputs and outputs, where one solution is more efficient
than another if and only if it has a higher benefit-cost ratio. The very
conceptual possibility of imagining such a ratio—ignoring the practical
issues of assigning sensible values and using them—presupposes that we
have some way of reducing the many qualitatively different inputs and
outputs in question to some single quantitative measure; and usually this
measure is taken to be that of monetary value as determined by a real or
hypothetical capitalist marketplace.
It also ignores the vital question that determines the outcome of any
cost-benefit analysis, namely deciding what to count as costs and what to
count as benefits. Based on what they considered to be costs and bene-
fits, the Nazis considered gas chambers to be highly efficient (compared
to alternatives like shooting and throat-cutting). Based on what they
consider to be costs and benefits, the roughly 100 corporations that are
responsible for around 71% of CO2 emissions prefer to keep destroying
the conditions for human and other animal life on our planet (which they
don’t have to pay for) than bearing the much more minor costs of swap-
ping energy sources (which they do have to pay for).78 Any decent person
would make very different assessments, primarily on the basis of what to
count as costs and what to count as benefits.
The general point here is that efficiency estimates depend entirely on
what we count as costs and benefits, and this is often ignored by critics of
socialism. Goods that Marx and many others hold to be important—such
as freedom and human development—are often excluded from such esti-
mates entirely.79 This is important, because some things which are costly
in terms of money and time can also be considered as valuable in them-
selves once we consider human development as a valuable factor. Higher
78 It might be pointed out that a number of these corporations are owned by some
state or other, but this is irrelevant to the point being made here, which is about efficiency
judgments.
79 There have been efforts to develop things like the Human Development Index as
an alternative to GDP, but this is a different kind of thing altogether from considering
inputs and outputs in a process of production.
8 THE SOCIALIST ALTERNATIVE 183
levels of education, for instance, while they cost money and may not—
although this has been challenged—lead to more objects being produced
per person, also entail a greater development of human powers. If we
consider this to be a valuable output, then it is by no means obvious that
the greater time required for educating more people yields a lower total
benefit-cost ratio all other things being equal. In other words, what counts
as efficient or not is completely dependent on what we choose to assign
value to when we estimate the costs and benefits of inputs and outputs.
This is a point that any critical discussion of Max’s critique of capitalism
must take into consideration.
Let me make one final point about the division of labour under
socialism as Marx conceives of it. If a socialist society can feasibly solve
the issue of the structural division of labour, along with being structured
by a network of federated councils organising a participatory democratic
form of planning, then there is no principled obstacle to spreading indi-
viduals’ labours across different workplaces. Again, this does not mean
that anyone can do whatever they like. It only means that society will
now be able to, consistent with its various priorities and the powers and
capacities of its members, arrange production in such a way that people
who want to, and can, work in various branches or workplaces can do
so without additional social hindrances. Having discussed the arguments
against replacing the hierarchical division of labour, I turn now to Hayek’s
challenge to planning.
1. The IFBs estimate the different social costs of various goods and
services, taking into account the resources they require, materials,
work inputs, as well as things like damages or benefits to people,
society, and the environment. These will be based on last year’s plan,
and will mostly be minor modifications to take into account new
developments.
2. Workers’ councils meet to suggest what they want their workplace to
produce, and what they want to request in order to get this done.
Consumers’ councils meet to collate their individual consumption
proposals, and to decide which public goods and services they want
to request. These too are based on modifications of last year’s plan,
and are suggestions formulated by the individuals and councils who
would be carrying them out.
3. In light of this new information, the IFBs calculate the excess supply
and demand for all goods and services, labour, investment, and
natural resources, and modify their estimates based on what people
and councils say they want to consume and produce.
4. Workers’ and consumers’ councils and federations then send in
revised proposals until they deliver one which the other councils
in their group can accept, and so on upwards until a final plan is
reached.
5. Plans will include necessary margins for the flexibility and revision
that people will obviously require throughout the year.
6. In accordance with the plan that is reached, workplaces will be
assigned a limited quantity of consumption rights based on their
collected work rates. These are then distributed among individual
workers in accordance with the specific work rates of the individual
tasks that they perform, e.g. monthly or bi-monthly.
This is not, and does not aim to be, a complete account of the planning
model, nor will I attempt a proper defence of it here. A few key points
from the literature are, however, worth noting. First, all meetings here
happen within councils, not between them. Proposals are formulated by
individuals and councils themselves, and finally have to be accepted by the
other individuals and councils within their group. None of this requires
anyone else to go into the details of anyone’s proposals. All they have to
do is look at the relation between the collected costs and benefits of the
proposals and vote yes or no. If someone makes an exceptional request,
they may have to justify it, or risk having it rejected. Nobody in this model
has any interest in voting against someone else’s proposal unless it is very
unbalanced and deemed to be unjustified, since there are no gains to be
had from doing so.
The most important thing, however, is that it is only the individuals
and councils involved who themselves make their own activity proposals.
Other councils and federations only get to either accept or reject these
proposals. Robin Hahnel stresses the importance of this:
When worker councils make proposals they are asking permission to use
particular parts of the productive resources that belong to everyone. In
effect their proposals say: “If the rest of you—with whom we are engaged
in a cooperative division of labor -- agree to allow us to use productive
resources belonging to all of us as inputs, then we promise to deliver the
following goods and services as outputs for others to use.” When consumer
councils make proposals they are asking permission to consume goods and
services whose production entails social costs. In effect their proposals say:
“We believe the effort ratings we received from our co-workers together
with allowances members of households have been granted indicate that
we deserve the right to consume goods and services whose production
entails an equivalent level of social costs.”
The planning procedure is designed to make it clear when a worker
council production proposal is inefficient and when a neighbourhood
186 P. RAEKSTAD
84 Hayek (1945, 1960, 1973, 1976, 1978, 1979, 1988), cf. also Gamble (1996, ch. 3;
2006).
188 P. RAEKSTAD
86 For more on everything discussed in this paragraph, see Hahnel (2015, 2021).
87 See the discussion and sources in Foster, Clark and York (2010, Ch. 5) and Schröder
and Storm (2020).
190 P. RAEKSTAD
88 For details on this in the case of Participatory Economics, see Hahnel (2005).
8 THE SOCIALIST ALTERNATIVE 191
References
Primary
Marx, K., & Carver, T. (ed. and trans.). (1996). Marx: Later political writings.
Cambridge University Press.
Marx, K., & Nicolaus, M. (trans.). (1993). Grundrisse: Foundations of a critique
of political economy. Penguin.
Marx, K., Fowkes, B. (trans.) & Mandel, E. (intro.). (1990). Capital: A critique
of political economy (Vol. 1). Penguin.
Marx, K., Livingstone, R. (trans), Benton, G. (trans) & Colletti, L. (intro.).
(1992). Karl Marx: Early writings. Penguin.
Secondary
Albert, M. (2003). ParEcon: Life after capitalism. Verso.
Albert, M., & Hahnel, R. (1978). Unorthodox Marxism: An essay on capitalism,
socialism and revolution. South End Press.
Albert, M., & Hahnel, R. (1991). The political economy of participatory
economics. Princeton University Press.
Albert, M., & Hahnel, R. (1999). Looking forward: Participatory economics for
the twenty first century. South End Press.
Braverman, H. (1998). Labour and monopoly capitalism: The degradation of work
in the twentieth century (25th Anniversary ed.). Monthly Review Press.
Broué, P. & Témime, E. 2008. The revolution and the cvil war in Spain. Chicago,
IL: Haymarket Books.
Campbell, A. (2011). Marx and Engels’ vision of building a good society (pp. 9–
32). Marangos.
Chomsky, N. (1969). American power and the new mandarins. The New Press.
Cockshott, P. W., & Cottrell, A. (1993). Towards a new socialism. Spokesman.
Cohen, G. A. (2001). Karl Marx’s theory of history: A defence (Expanded
Edition). Princeton University Press.
Devine, P. (1988). Democracy and economic planning: The political economy of a
self-governing society. Polity Press.
Doucouliagos, C. (1995). Worker participation and productivity in labor-
managed and participatory capitalist firms: A meta-analysis. Industrial and
Labor Relations Review, 49, 58–77.
192 P. RAEKSTAD
Hunt, R. (1974). The political ideas of Marx and Engels, volume 1: Marxism and
totalitarian democracy, 1818–1850. Macmillan.
Hunt, R. (1984). The political ideas of Marx and Engels, volume 2: Classical
Marxism 1850–1895. Macmillan.
Kasmir, S. (1996). The myth of Mondragon: Cooperatives, politics, and working-
class life in a Basque town. State University of New York Press.
Kasmir, S. (2018). Cooperative democracy or competitiveness? Rethinking
Mondragon. Socialist Register, 54, 202–223.
Larrabure, M. (2013). Human development and class struggle in Venezuela’s
popular economy: The paradox of ‘twenty-first century socialism.’ Historical
Materialism, 21(4), 177–200.
Leval, G. (2018). Collectives in the Spanish revolution. Oakland, CA: PM Press.
Levine, D., & Tyson, L. A. (1990). Participation, productivity and the firm’s
environment. In A. Blinder (Ed.), Paying for productivity: A look at the
evidence (pp. 203–214). Brookings Institution.
Melman, S. (1958). Decision-making and productivity. Basil Blackwell.
Mészáros, I. (1986). Philosophy, ideology and social science: Essays in negation and
affirmation. Wheatsheaf Books.
Mintz, F. (2013). Anarchism and workers’ self-management in revolutionary
Spain. AK Press.
Montesquieu, C. (1998). Montesquieu: The spirit of the laws. Cambridge Univer-
sity Press.
Ness, I., & Azzellini, D. (Eds.). (2011). Ours to master and to own: Workers’
control from the commune to the present. Haymarket Books.
Ollman, B. (1977). Marx’s vision of communism: A reconstruction. Critique,
8(1), 4–41.
Peirats, J. (2011). The CNT in the Spanish Revolution: (Vol. 1). PM Press.
Peirats, J. (2012a). The CNT in the Spanish revolution: (Vol. 2). PM Press.
Peirats, J. (2012b). The CNT in the Spanish revolution: (Vol. 3). PM Press.
Pérotin, V. (2018). What do we really know about worker co-operatives? Co-
operatives UK.
Phillips, L., & Rozworski, M. (2019). The people’s republic of Walmart: How the
world’s biggest corporations are laying the foundation for socialism. Verso.
Raekstad, P. (2011). Deltakende demokrati – en sosialisme for fremtiden. Rødt!:
Marxistisk Tidsskrift, 40(3), 116–126.
Raekstad, P. (2013, July 30). Review of the people, by the people: The case for a
participatory economy. Marx and Philosophy Review of Books. Available online
at: http://marxandphilosophy.org.uk/reviewofbooks/reviews/2013/792
Schröder, E., & Storm, S. (2020). Economic growth and carbon emissions: The
road to “hothouse earth” is paved with good intentions. International Journal
of Political Economy, 49(2), 153–173.
Schweickart, D. (1996). Against capitalism. Westview Press.
194 P. RAEKSTAD
Trist, E. L., Higgin, G. W., Murray, H., & Pollock, A. B. (1963). Organiza-
tional choice: Capabilities of groups at the coal face under changing technologies.
Tavistock Publications.
Walker, P. (Ed.). (1979). Between labor and capital. South End Press.
Weber, M., Lassman, P. (ed.), & Speirs, R. (ed.). (1994). Weber: Political
writings. Cambridge University Press.
Wright, E. O. (1980). Varieties of Marxist conceptions of class structure.
Politics & Society, 9(3), 323–370.
CHAPTER 9
Having laid out the diagnosis of capitalism Marx presents in his second
theory of alienation and the socialist cure he proposes to it, three ques-
tions immediately present themselves. First, what was the role that this
critique was to play within his agent-centred approach to political theory?
Secondly, why does Marx, in post-1844 works, continue to emphasise
and expand greatly on some aspects of alienation (especially alienation
from product and alienation from others), while emphasising its more
normatively laden aspects less? One answer is that Marx simply abandons
alienation and its concerns altogether. This answer cannot be satisfactory,
because as we’ve seen all four kinds of alienation reappear throughout
Marx’s later discussions of capitalism and feed into his vision of socialism.
This leads us to the third question: what role, if any, does the theory of
alienation come to play in Marx’s later thoughts on human society and
social change? I will answer each of these questions in turn, emphasising
that Marx’s critique of capitalism forms the core of the two revolutionary
contradictions of capitalism he does the most to pinpoint in his later
works: between the powers and relations of production and between
workers and capitalists. This is why Marx keeps returning to the ways
in which capitalism thwarts freedom and human development. With this
done, I will briefly argue that the reasons Marx seems to have had for
thinking that the more normatively laden aspects of his diagnosis were
Revolutionary Midwives
and the Birth of the Future
The agent-centred position Marx developed in the latter parts of 1843,
which formed the basis for the Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts
of 1844, underwent a significant change during 1844–1845, moving
away from a perspective which saw ideas as the active element in social
change. On the view that Marx adopts during the writing of the 1844
manuscripts, such ideas would be formulated in some critical political
theory and find their (passive) material basis in an agent capable of real-
ising its recommendations. During 1844–1845, this changes to a view
where the proletariat is seen as much more active, an agent which can and
will tend to generate the powers, needs, and consciousness it requires to
bring about a process of socialist revolution.
Accordingly, Marx adopts the maieutic or obstetric conception of the
practice of the theorist. Present capitalist society is in the process of (at
least potentially) giving birth to that of the future through the active
agency of the working-class movement. The task of the theorist, like that
of the midwife, is to help this process unfold and achieve some sort of
successful result—e.g. a process of giving birth resulting in a healthy new-
born child, or a process of social struggle on the part of the proletariat
resulting in a successful transition to a socialist society. It’s hard to pin
down all of the decisive factors of this shift, but they almost certainly
include his enduring contacts with French communist/socialist workers’
organisations, interactions with thinkers like Moses Hess and Friedrich
Engels, and, crucially, the revolt by the Silesian weavers. Michael Löwy
has summed this development up as follows:
Between the weavers’ revolt (June 1844) and the Theses on Feuerbach
(about March 1845), the process of formation of the Marxist Weltan-
schauung was completed. This was the great ideological turning point in
the evolution of the young Marx. The Silesian rising, together with the
communist movement he encountered in Paris, faced him concretely with
the problem of the revolutionary praxis of the proletarian masses. In the
Vorwärts article, Marx discovers the proletariat as the active element in
9 RADICAL THEORY AND REVOLUTIONARY PRACTICE 197
emancipation, but he does not yet draw the philosophical conclusions from
this discovery. A few weeks later, he sketches, in The Holy Family, a first
attempt at a theoretical solution of the problem. He believes he can grasp
revolutionary activity—which is evidently outside the Young Hegelians’
world of thought—through the categories of the French materialism of
the eighteenth century. Soon, however, he perceives that the revolutionary
praxis of the masses cannot be fitted into the narrow framework of the
“theory of circumstances”: this is his break with “the old materialism”,
which at once spreads to all levels. The Theses on Feuerbach expose the
“practical essence” of history and of social life, of “sensuousness” and
of theory, of the relations of men with nature and among themselves,
and, finally, outline a coherent set of ideas, a significant global structure:
the philosophy of praxis, the general theoretical foundation for the idea of
revolutionary self-emancipation of the proletariat.1
These various conditions [the natural, social and historical conditions under
which individuals interact, especially the relations of production], which
appear first as conditions of self-activity, later as fetters upon it, form in the
whole development of history a coherent series of forms of intercourse, the
coherence of which consists in this: an earlier form of intercourse, which
has become a fetter, is replaced by a new one corresponding to the more
developed productive powers and, hence, to the advanced mode of the
self-activity of individuals—a form which in its turn becomes a fetter and is
then replaced by another. Since these conditions correspond at every stage
to the simultaneous development of the productive powers, their history is
at the same time the history of the evolving productive powers taken over
by each new generation, and is therefore the history of the development
of the powers of the individuals themselves.10
12 Marx (1992, pp. 425–426/II:2, pp. 100–1). Here too I have modified the
translation from “forces” to “powers”, for the aforementioned reasons.
13 MECW 4, p. 36/MEGA I:3, p. 206.
1
9 RADICAL THEORY AND REVOLUTIONARY PRACTICE 201
Let’s see how this plays out in Volume I of Capital, where Marx
writes14 :
14 For reasons of time and space, I’ve restricted the sources discussed below to Volume
I of Capital only, but the same claims can be found throughout his published and
unpublished works until the end of Marx’s life.
15 Marx (1990, p. 929/II: 6, p. 682).
16 Marx (1990, p. 449/II:8, p. 329).
202 P. RAEKSTAD
There’s a lot going on here, all of which, I will show, builds upon
Marx’s critique of capitalism, in particular the theory of alienation. By
productive powers, Marx means the collected real possibilities that a given
human society has for producing things (in the broadest possible sense)
to satisfy human needs. This includes all forms of land, machinery, labour,
technology, levels of scientific achievement, and even forms of social
organisation or intercourse. By forms of social intercourse, Marx means
the relational structures within and through which human beings work
on and with one another and the natural world to secure the produc-
tion and reproduction of their societies—including, but not limited to,
economic production. The totality of the available means for satisfying
human needs, as expressed in the idea of a society’s productive powers,
both restrict and enable changes in these relational structures.
Powers and relations of production come into contradiction when and
only when the totality of productive powers available enables a much
greater development of human powers—including, but not limited to,
powers of production—than is possible within the constraints of the
current relations of production. As we’ve seen, Marx thinks that capi-
talism has developed the powers of production—especially the kinds of
machinery, technology, and socialised forms of production—in ways that
have made socialism possible—not just in societies that have gone through
this process, but any society thereafter.17 He also thinks that our ability
to make full use of these powers is fettered by the continued existence of
capitalist relations of production. The contradiction between the powers
and relations of production thus consists in the fact that the same capi-
talist social relations both enable human emancipation (by developing the
powers of production in the right ways) and prevent human emancipation
(until they are abolished/replaced by socialist ones).
A real movement towards socialism begins, Marx believes, when this
contradiction has developed. Ironically, by developing the powers of
production in ways that enrich themselves, capitalists spur “the creation
of those material conditions of production which alone can form the real
17 That is, to any society thereafter that can acquire them. Marx clearly points out in
both his letter to Vera Zasulich and in the 1872 preface to the Communist Manifesto that
it is not necessary for each society to first reach the stage of capitalism before transitioning
to socialism, only that capitalism must have evolved in some society and developed the
means of production. In fact, in both places he argues the exact opposite, that e.g. Russia
may be able to transition to socialism without first introducing capitalism.
9 RADICAL THEORY AND REVOLUTIONARY PRACTICE 203
basis of a higher form of society, a society in which the full and free devel-
opment of every individual forms the ruling principle”.18 Capitalism has
also brought workers together into collective workplaces; improved their
means of communication and thus organisation; and unified them under
common interests against the dominating social relations of capitalism.
As a result, workers also come to perceive the powers of production that
are available, the potentials for emancipation and further human devel-
opment they entail, and how the personal and impersonal domination of
capitalism prevents them from realising these potentials.
This explains why, in his Preface to A Contribution to the Critique of
Political Economy, Marx writes that “[m]ankind thus inevitably sets itself
only such tasks as it is able to solve, since closer examination will always
show that the problem itself arises only when the material conditions
for its solution are already present or at least in the course of forma-
tion”.19 Applied to socialist revolution, the point here is that it’s only
when the material conditions for socialism have developed that the poten-
tial inherent in them can be perceived. It’s only when these potentials are
perceived that we can begin to ask questions about how we can change
relations of production to better take advantage of the potentials we’re
aware of. And it’s only when we do that that we can form a revolutionary
movement seeking to realise these potentials by replacing the relations of
production.
It’s clear how this results in the contradiction between workers and
capitalists. Capitalists, being in a position of greater power, wealth, and
privilege, will fight to retain their position, which in turn entails that they
work to maintain capitalism and suppress any attempted socialist revo-
lution. Workers not only experience their situation as alienated, unfree,
and impoverished. They also rightly perceive that the development of the
powers of production has made it possible to change these conditions,
replacing the unfree capitalist relations with free socialist ones that better
enable their development and flourishing—hence Marx’s point in Volume
I of Capital that capitalism uses workers “to satisfy the need of the existing
values for valorization” instead of employing its resources to “satisfy the
worker’s own need for development”.20 In other words, workers’ need
for development, for expanding their powers to do and to be, leads them
to develop an interest in replacing capitalism with socialism. Note that
for Marx, as he writes in the Grundrisse, even “private interest is itself
already a socially determined interest, which can be achieved only within
the conditions laid down by society and with the means provided by soci-
ety”, as a result of which “its content, as well as the form and means of its
realization, is given by social conditions”.21 In this way, workers’ interest
in socialist revolution is rooted in the contrast between the emancipatory
potentials capitalism has enabled and how its alienating, dominating, and
unfree social relations prevent workers from taking advantage of them.22
The contradiction between workers and capitalists consists in the fact that
the same conditions, the same social relations of capitalism, generate both
a social force interested in and seeking to replace capitalism with socialism
and a social force interested in and seeking to retain capitalism and prevent
socialism.
Where Chapter 7 showed that Marx retains all the ideas expressed in
his four kinds of alienation throughout his later works, here we have seen
that they form the core of his understanding of the revolutionary contra-
dictions of capitalism. If [c]ommunism is “the real movement which
abolishes the present state of things”, the theory of alienation and the
revolutionary contradictions of capitalism explain how the “conditions of
this movement result from the premises now in existence”.23
There’s thus no incompatibility between Marx’s theory of alienation
and his later theories of society and social change. Quite the contrary: the
theory of alienation essentially grows into his understanding of capital-
ism’s contradictions as the basis for socialist revolution. Alienation thus
the effect that this is indeed so or to the effect that its vices are partic-
ularly harmful for their freedom and human development. The second
and third kinds of alienation thus seem less valuable for helping to guide
working-class movements in ways that better enable them to carry out
socialist revolution, so there’s little value in harping on about them. While
“[p]hilosophers have only interpreted the world, in various ways; the
point is to change it”.25
This hinges on the efficacy of normative argumentation for motivating
and guiding political agents. Marx de-emphasises the second and third
kinds of alienation because he believes them not to be very useful contri-
butions that a theorist can make to the struggle to replace capitalism
with socialism. What use could these more normative aspects of Marx’s
thought have for the kind of agent-centred realism that Marx advocates?
One major virtue of returning to Marx’s ideas about freedom, its value,
and its obstruction by capitalism, is that they are at least in principle
amenable to empirical testing. It is in principle possible to try to discover
whether human beings have some powers of conscious self-directed
activity; whether or not conscious self-directed activity is important and
significant for the development of human beings; whether or not capi-
talist and other labour processes do thwart conscious self-direction; and
whether or not labour processes are particularly important, for whichever
reasons, in this regard. Marx is a realist, and his arguments are consciously
highly descriptive in character. At no point does he try to retreat from
the descriptive and contingent to the necessary and normative in order to
insulate his normative political thought from possible refutation. This is
important, because it makes it possible to gather various kinds of evidence
which we can use to either accept or reject his argument for good reasons.
If conscious self-directed activity turns out not to be important for human
development, then we should not, in Marx’s view, value it. Explicit atten-
tion to the nature and value of self-directed activity can enable us to
gather evidence either for or against Marx’s central contention that capi-
talism thwarts human development, supporting or undermining his claims
for good reasons. But what positive purpose could this have for the agency
of the existing working-class struggle that Marx intends to address?
A focus on Marx’s conception of freedom as self-direction, its impor-
tance, and its thwarting by capitalist domination, can contribute to
References
Primary
Heinrich, M. (2012). An introduction to the three volumes of Karl Marx’s capital.
Monthly Review Press.
Marx, K., & Nicolaus, M. (trans.). (1993). Grundrisse: Foundations of a critique
of political economy. Penguin.
Marx, K., Fowkes, B. (trans.) & Mandel, E. (intro.). (1990). Capital: A critique
of political economy (Vol. 1). Penguin.
Marx, K., Livingstone, R. (trans), Benton, G. (trans) & Colletti, L. (intro.).
(1992). Karl Marx: Early writings. Penguin.
Lebowitz, M. (2020). Between capitalism and community. Monthly Review Press.
Löwy, M. (2005). The theory of revolution in the young Marx. Haymarket Books.
Raekstad, P. (2015). Two contemporary approaches to political theory. Interna-
tional Critical Thought, 5(2), 226–240.
CHAPTER 10
I have shown that Marx’s political theory was realist in nature, that it
presents a critique of capitalism for thwarting human freedom and thereby
human development, and that this critique remains defensible in light of
the findings of the contemporary human sciences. After a brief recap, I
will here offer some pointers on how Marx’s critique of capitalism remains
important for opening up new and important avenues in theorising both
the expanding ills of capitalism and the necessities of emancipation.
Part I laid out Marx’s rich and neglected theory of human devel-
opment in terms of powers and needs, and showed how he uses it to
articulate a positive concept of freedom as self-direction. On this view,
freedom is valuable both in itself as the realisation of a particularly impor-
tant human power and for positively impacting a wide range of other
human powers.
Next, Part II detailed Marx’s first critique of modern society, showing
one of the ways in which he critiques both capitalism and the state for
thwarting human freedom and thereby human development. There we
saw that Marx advocates a radical idea of democracy to replace capi-
talism and the state in ways that go beyond merely democratic states
and prefigure his later socialist ideas. The discussion of Marx’s shift from
a realisation-oriented to an agent-centred approach to political theory
explained not only how Marx’s approach to political theory differs in the
two theories of alienation, but also how added descriptive content rightly
altered his realist method of political theorising.
Building on this, Part III reconstructed the second theory of alien-
ation as a diagnosis of specifically how capitalism thwarts human freedom
and thereby human development, his expanded conception of its cure
in socialism, and, finally, his conception of the (correct or best) practice
of the theorist. There we saw his theory of alienation being employed
to diagnose capitalism’s interconnected forms of personal and impersonal
domination and how he recommends a socialism to cure it that includes
the full democratisation of social life, replacing competitive markets with
democratic planning, abolishing the hierarchical division of labour, and
distributing according to need. Finally, we saw how this theory not only
is retained throughout Marx’s later works, including Capital, but also
constitutes the core of his analysis of capitalism’s revolutionary contradic-
tions. While Marx turned to focus more on the descriptive side of this
critique, I’ve argued that we have good reason to revive it today. Now,
what does this do for contemporary political theory and practice?
This contributes to contemporary methodological debates in political
theory by showing two detailed ways in which a critical political theory
was developed along realist lines. Despite the growing interest in realism
in recent years, there has been little work that can compare to the radical
critical endeavour of thinkers like Marx. The work of such thinkers has
played an important role in influencing recent human history, so their
approaches to the subject deserve considerable attention in their own
right. There is also good reason to think that political theorists who wish
to influence real politics today would do well to understand the methods
and approaches which have proven effective in the past—whether they
wish to follow them or not.
One way this can be done would be to open up a research programme
that seeks to do realist political theory in an empirically well-informed
and interdisciplinary way. This could draw on recent advances in history,
anthropology, archaeology, and psychology, as well as the sociology of
social movements and on the ideas of non-Western forms of political
theorising. Such a programme could explore our foundational polit-
ical concepts, values, and commitments, including through forms of
genealogy and ideology critique; it could use these lessons to assess the
relations and institutions we are subject to; it could develop models of
future relations and institutions and strategies for reaching them; and it
10 TOWARDS A NEW WORLD 215
1 For example Foster and Magdoff (2009), Foster and McChesney (2012), and Harvey
(2011, 2015).
216 P. RAEKSTAD
experiences of most people. There are many things wrong with this
critique, but the main problem is that it’s wrong in both of the main ways
that it needs to be right. First, as Immanuel Ness points out, from 1980
to 2007 the standard industrially defined working class has actually grown
“from 1.9 billion to 3.1 billion workers—far more working people than at
any time in the history of capitalism”, mostly in the Global South and in
large part in “response to the restructuring of financial capital”.2 He goes
on to argue that “Marx’s depiction of an alienated and estranged work-
force in the nineteenth century can be applied to the condition of workers
in the Global South today”,3 including living in the margins of major
cities, lacking many citizenship and residency rights with resulting lack
of access to public services, thorough-going casualisation and precarity,
and much more. Furthermore, the Marxist proletariat was always defined
not in terms of any industrial character, but in terms of its social rela-
tions. It therefore includes service sector workers just as much as it does
factory workers, and their conditions, whether in the Global North or the
Global South, remain alienated and unfree. From the perspective of global
humanity, Marx’s critique of capitalism has never been more relevant.
The diagnosis of impersonal forms of domination can also help us make
sense of the subtle forms of power involved in a variety of current high-
technology transformations our capitalism is undergoing. New dynamics
of surveillance capitalism, the rule of algorithms in managing platform
workers and other office workers, and the subtle forms of manipulation
exercised by automated systems in various different ways all demand a
more sophisticated way of thinking about freedom than current liberals,
or their concepts of freedom, can provide. Marx’s concept of freedom as
self-direction, and his understanding that it can be undermined by either
personal or impersonal forms of domination, can provide a starting point
for understanding how many of these new socio-technical systems exercise
power over those subject to them regardless of whether they’re controlled
by particular nefarious bosses or not.
Perhaps most importantly, Marx’s critique also leaves us with a number
of resources for thinking about human emancipation in more positive
terms. Indeed, nothing could be more obvious than the growing impor-
tance of Marx to movements fighting for universal emancipation. A
proper understanding of what his political theory consists in, the vision
of a future it includes, and the nature of the critique it levels against
capitalism, can provide such movements with a greater understanding of
what it is that they’re up against, which institutions need replacement or
reform, and how one might go about doing so.
First, a renewed understanding of Marx’s critique should help us to
re-frame how we think about Marx’s work as fundamentally a project of
universal human emancipation through intersectional working-class self-
emancipation. For Marx, this entails the democratisation of all aspects of
social life. We’ve seen that for Marx, this requires replacing both capi-
talism and the state with a network of bottom-up democratic councils,
restoring the powers of society to the collective control of the totality
of its participants. He also argues that such a socialist society must
be organised through participatory democratic planning; replace capital-
ism’s hierarchical division of labour; and distribute goods and services
according to need, while members will contribute according to ability.
I’ve also argued that these commitments call us to think about which
specific institutional forms they can be realised through. How exactly
can we go about participatory democratic planning on large, medium,
and small scales? How can we reorganise the division of labour in ways
that best serve the free self-development of all? And how do we make
distribution according to need a concrete reality? These questions should
be central to thinking about the socialist alternative to capitalism going
forwards.
Second, this should be accompanied by an honest and ruthless criticism
of proposed alternatives to capitalism that fail to address the forms of
unfreedom Marx discusses. Contemporary academics, even many who call
themselves socialists, tend to favour either some renewed form of social
democracy or a form of market socialism. The problem with these models
is that neither of them can seriously address Marx’s diagnoses of the forms
of domination between managers and workers, embodied in the division
between mental and manual labour; the impersonal forms of domination
entailed by the kinds of competitive markets they include; or the latter’s
inherent dynamics of ecological devastation. A renewed socialism cannot
settle for such half-measures, nor can anyone who wants our species to
survive.
Third, Marx’s focus on democratisation and his theory of human devel-
opment can inform the way we think about social change and especially
collective emancipation. If capitalism is alienating and a socialist society
218 P. RAEKSTAD
4 For example Dixon (2014), Gordon (2018), Raekstad (2018), Raekstad and Gradin
(2020), Swain (2019b), and van de Sande (2015).
10 TOWARDS A NEW WORLD 219
flow from the bottom up, rather than from the top down? Do our move-
ments and organisations develop their participants’ powers, needs, and
consciousness in the ways required for them to replace capitalism and the
state with a free socialist society, if and when the opportunity arises? This
demands not only that we more systematically begin to study the forms
and substance of prefigurative politics, but also that we work to bring
together the best parts of different socialist traditions that have worked
much more on these questions than many Marxist theorists.5 In my view
this demands that we develop a non-sectarian, new synthesis of the best
parts of Marxist, anarchist, decolonial, antiracist, feminist, and syndicalist
ideas.
These questions and more are being asked and beginning to be
answered by a plethora of organisations and movements worldwide.
Through them, Marx’s thought is once again a living element in polit-
ical struggles, and one which we’re beginning to understand better than
was possible before. If this is correct, then it seems that philosophy is
again becoming a material force in social and political struggles—a force
not only for understanding the world, but also for changing it.
References
Secondary
Dixon, C. (2014). Another politics: Talking across today’s transformative move-
ments. University of California Press.
Foster, J. B., & Magdoff, F. (2009). The great financial crisis: Causes and
consequences. Monthly Review Press.
Foster, J. B., & McChesney, R. (2012). The endless crisis: How monopoly-finance
capital produces stagnation and upheaval from the USA to China. Monthly
Review Press.
Gordon, U. (2018). Prefigurative politics between ethical practice and absent
promise. Political Studies, 66(2), 521–537.
Harvey, D. (2011). The enigma of capital: And the crises of capitalism (2nd ed.).
Oxford University Press.
Harvey, D. (2015). Seventeen contradictions and the end of capitalism (Reprint
ed.). Oxford University Press.
Ness, I. (2016). Southern insurgency: The coming of the global working class. Pluto
Press.
Raekstad, P., & Gradin, S. (2020). Prefigurative politics: Building tomorrow today.
Polity Press.
Raekstad, P. (2018). Revolutionary practice and prefigurative politics: A clarifica-
tion and defence. Constellations, 25(3), 359–372.
Swain, D. (2019a). None so fit to break the chains: Marx’s ethics of self-
emancipation. Brill.
Swain, D. (2019b). Not not but not yet: Present and future in prefigurative
politics. Political Studies, 67 (1), 47–62.
Van de Sande, M. (2015). Fighting with tools: Prefiguration and radical politics
in the twenty-first century. Rethinking Marxism, 27 (2), 177–194.
Appendix: A Brief Overview
of the (Other) Principal
Interpretations of Marx’s Normative
Commitments
© The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive 221
license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2022
P. Raekstad, Karl Marx’s Realist Critique of Capitalism,
Marx, Engels, and Marxisms,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-06353-4
222 APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL …
1 Unfortunately, there are interesting commentators on this issue that fall outside of
this typology, such as MacIntyre (2009), Martin (2008), and Blackledge (2012). Their
positions are too unique, and require a much too detailed and lengthy treatment than it
is possible to provide here.
2 See for instance Geras (1985, p. 47).
APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL … 223
rest on which are not my own, in their most plausible formulations, and
briefly present the reasons why I find them to be implausible.
It is difficult to get a simple overview of the state of the discussion
concerning the normative components of Marx’s theory, partly because
many of the various participants proceed from very different ethical and
political assumptions, and partly because the participants use different,
and sometimes inconsistent, terminology. Different writers read Marx’s
critique in terms of concepts such as the “normative”, the “ethical”, the
“moral”, the “amoral”, and many more, and they often do not take care
to use these in the same way, or to clarify or compare their uses to those of
other writers. In light of this fact, I will begin my discussion by outlining
the terminology it will employ. In this way, my account of the different
positions and their vocabularies can be made commensurable, hopefully
rendering the subsequent discussion more comprehensible.
The word “normative” employed can be taken in a few different
ways. “Normative” here does not simply mean something being of, or
pertaining to, a norm. Nor does it mean a separate kind of thing distinct
from, and necessarily opposed to, the descriptive tout court. To use the
term in this way would be implicitly to commit Marx to a substantive kind
of meta-ethical dualism which I do not believe he holds. “Normative” is,
however, used to denote that aspect of a theory—Marx’s or others’—
which deals with all matters concerning what’s good or bad, better or
worse, and how, very broadly speaking, things should or ought to be. This
includes the realm of concerns about ethical rules and norms, conceptions
of the good life, etc., but also other realms such as the correct or incor-
rect use of language, aesthetics, considerations to do with rationality and
reasonableness, and so on. For the purposes of this appendix, the “nor-
mative” and the evaluative will be used synonymously to denote this class
of considerations.
There is a common way of thinking about the “normative” which
contrasts it with the “descriptive” in such a way that the two are wholly
separate categories. I leave aside the question of whether or not this is a
correct or a useful way of thinking about things, noting only that this is
not how the term “normative” will be employed here. For one, there is
no reason whatsoever to believe Marx adhered to a dualism of this kind
and for another, there are a number of things which fall within the scope
of the normative as just construed which are clearly also descriptive enti-
ties. For example, it is perfectly possible to hold up an existing society
or individual as an ideal of ethical, aesthetic, or rational perfection (e.g.
224 APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL …
3 This example may be controversial, insofar as it abstracts away from the harms caused
to listeners upon experiencing the horror of “literally” used in the sense of figura-
tively+emphasis. Insofar as the action of doing so causes harm, it would indeed fall under
the category of the ethical as well.
APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL … 225
4 I write “ethical” rules and norms to distinguish those rules and norms which are
ethical from those rules and norms that are purely pragmatic conventions, rules of
aesthetics (e.g. rules of musical composition), and so on.
5 If one believes, as I do, that everything formulated by a human being is significantly
sensitive to, and in part dependent on, the context within which it is formulated, then
there can be no such thing as an abstract formulation of the kind shortly to be discussed,
only attempts at doing so which are doomed to fail. In order to simplify the discussion, I
term those approaches which attempt to proceed abstractly in the above sense as “abstract”
approaches—even though, if I and its other critics are correct in the basic premise of its
factual impossibility, there is, strictly speaking, no such thing.
226 APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL …
6 E.g. Bukharin (1925), Hodges (1964, 1966), Leiter (2015), and Plekhanov (1898).
The names cited make it obvious why this position is labelled an “orthodox” one.
7 There is another version of simple amoralism developed by Tucker (1970, 1972)
which argues that the extremely partisan nature of Marx’s quasi-religious world-view
supposedly rules out any genuinely ethical or moral components. Since this is no longer
accepted by virtually anyone, I leave discussion of it aside for our purposes here.
228 APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL …
10 Wood and others use the term “non-moral” here, leaving it unclear what “moral”
means in this particular context. In our terms outlined above, however, it seems clear that
what these writers term “non-moral” is what I would term non-ethical.
11 Wood (2004, p. 129). This view was developed by Wood (1972a, 1972b, 1979,
2004). A sufficiently similar position reading Marx in amoralistic terms is that of Acton
(1955) and Miller (1983, 1984). Relatedly, Buchanan (1982) reads needs in the sense of
undistorted preferences, although he would probably reject identifying Marx’s position as
“amoral”.
230 APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL …
best regulated. As such, modern private property laws and normal13 wage
labour exchanges are just in capitalist societies because they constitute,
regulate, and/or reinforce a well-functioning aspect of capitalist soci-
eties; in a hunter-gatherer society, by contrast, they would likely be both
pointless and harmful.14
Moving on from right and justice to morality, Wood argues that since
what we normally call everyday morality is similarly concerned with regu-
lating and directing the actions and interactions of individuals and groups
within and only within the context of a given mode of production—stipu-
lating what we should do in certain situations, banning certain courses of
action or ways of treating others, and so on—it follows that these notions
are completely unsuited to making recommendations of one such mode
of production over another. Furthermore, Wood argues, a shift from one
mode of production to another—e.g. by means of social revolution—
likely entails that the rules (morality, right, justice, law) of the former
mode of production must not only change, but also be violated in the
very act of change itself. Not only can a revolutionary critique of capi-
talism not base itself on such notions, it plausibly has to violate them in
order even to get off the ground.15
As a reading of Marx, Wood’s sophisticated amoralist position has some
major virtues. First, it can explain Marx’s own silence on the subject of
justice, both distributive and commutative, in his critical discussions of
capitalism. Secondly, it can make sense of Marx’s repeated insistence that
13 “Normal” in the sense that they do not involve what are taken to be untoward
elements such as direct coercion, slave-like contracts or contractual conditions, do not
involve illicit transfers such as bribes, etc.
14 There is of course another, merely descriptive, sense in which the terms “right”
and “justice” are used by others and, occasionally, by Marx himself. This is the purely
descriptive sense in which a given legal system, state, or whatever, recognises or upholds
certain principles as people’s rights or certain arrangements as being just simply as a
matter of fact. There is, in other words, a sense in which a principle X can be a principle
of justice in a given kind of society because it is one which is well-suited to the proper
functioning of that society and thus ought to be implemented and adhered to in some
way, and a distinct sense in which X can be a principle of justice in a given society in
that it simply is a principle which as a matter of fact is adhered to in that society. Wood’s
sophisticated amoralist reading holds that Marx discusses politico-juridical terms in both
senses—though Marx himself, especially in his earlier writings, is often far from clear about
when he is employing these terms in their normative or in the merely descriptive senses.
15 Wood (1972b).
232 APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL …
16 The legalistic conception of justice and the distributive conception of justice are
often not clearly delineated in this literature.
17 Marx (1990, p. 301/II:6, p. 207).
18 Marx (1990, p. 178n2/ II:6, p. 114).
19 Marx (1996, p. 211/I:25, p. 12).
20 Marx (1996, p. 215/I:25, p. 15).
21 See Wood (1972a).
APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL … 233
reasons, but it is also equally clear that they can be valued for purely
amoral reasons—that is, by appeal only to someone’s desires, preferences,
and interests. So far so good. However, Marx’s critique of capitalism rests
on, and Wood’s account consequently includes, many other concepts—
concepts like freedom and human development—which do not, or at
least not immediately, appear to have the same structure. Wood’s early
comments on this are too vague to be of any use, initially amounting
simply to a claim that the normative foundations for Marx’s critique lie
in the developing desires and needs of the proletariat which are satisfiable
by the means of production, but are fettered by capitalistic relations of
production.22 The reason this account is too vague to be useful is that it
fails to specify any distinction between putatively ethical and non-ethical
goods which can account for why the more contentious goods Wood
discusses are bona fide instances of non-ethical goods.
Wood’s later account23 does much better and provides a fuller distinc-
tion according to which ethical—what he calls “moral”—goods are those
things we value or want because our conscience or moral law tells us to,
whereas non-ethical goods are things we value because they satisfy our
own conceptions about our wants, needs, or the good life. On this view,
Marx criticises capitalism because it “frustrates many important nonmoral
[in our terminology non-ethical] goods: self-actualization, security, phys-
ical health, comfort, community, freedom”, but he “never claims that
these goods ought to be provided to people because they have the right
to them, or because justice (or some other moral norm) demands it”.24
But how do we make sense of the idea of non-ethical goods? If
the critique of capitalism in terms of freedom, self-direction, etc., is
cashed out in terms of one kind of ethics versus an ethics centred on
notions of right and justice, then it either becomes a moralist or internal-
critique position—depending on how the principles or ideals for action
are conceived. On the other hand, the non-ethical goods in question
could be derived in some way from a normative conception of human
nature or a notion of human development, but neither of these preserves
an interesting distinction between an amoralist position and these other
22 Wood (1972b).
23 I.e. Wood (2004), but some less developed discussion is also to be found in Wood
(1979).
24 Wood (2004, p. 129).
234 APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL …
two kinds. If, however, these options are to be avoided, as Wood wants,
then we must ask whether or not it is possible to make sense of his distinc-
tion in a way which manages to preserve an interestingly non-ethical
character of the goods involved, while at the same time being able to
ground a critique of capitalism.
The best way I believe that Wood’s conception of non-ethical goods
can be re-cast is by formulating the notion of non-ethical goods in
terms of objective interests. If we define a person’s objective interests as
the wants or preferences they would have under conditions of perfect
(complete and correct) information, perfect clarity of cognition, and
under ideal conditions of reflection and deliberation, then non-ethical
goods can be conceived as those general-purpose goods which everybody
would want under such (and perhaps also under less strict) conditions.
This construal allows us both to preserve the “amoral” character of the
goods in question—they are clearly normative, not obviously ethical, and
certainly not moral—while at the same time managing to make sense of
that category of goods as something valuable, on the basis of which a
critique of social relations and institutions may be mounted. On such a
construal, Marx’s critique of capitalism would appeal specifically to the
objective interests of the proletariat, in the sense of giving one or more
arguments for it being in their objective interests, qua members of the
proletarian class, to overthrow capitalism.
This last point raises an obvious question: Why should others who are
not proletarians care about such a critique of capitalism? Consider one
of the more straightforward cases of a non-ethical good, efficiency, and
consider two possible forms of society, S1 and S2 , that differ only in that
S1 is more efficient than S2 , and that the benefits of this greater effi-
ciency accrue entirely to the proletariat—all things remaining equal for
non-proletarians. In such a case, why should or might non-proletarians,
like Marx himself, care? This is a complicated question to answer, but we
can mention the three most obvious lines of reply an amoralist like Wood
might make. First, he might argue that this is a relatively unimportant
issue. Since proletarians are by far the majority of society, and since their
interests can be appealed to in a straightforward way that is all that is
needed for Marx’s critique to be able to motivate a revolutionary change,
and that’s all that it attempts and needs to do.
A second line of reply could argue that even though Marx’s critique of
capitalism appeals only to non-ethical goods, non-proletarians may well
APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL … 235
have good ethical reasons to care about the non-ethical goods of proletar-
ians. For instance, a wealthy capitalist might, in principle, care about the
individual well-being and preference-satisfaction of proletarians because
they adhere to certain ethical commitments which they believe require it
of them. They may, for instance, be a utilitarian of some sort, committed
to whichever social, economic, and political institutions maximise overall
utility and believe that capitalism does a worse job than socialism would
of providing proletarians with non-moral goods essential to maximising
(their) utility. As a result, a capitalist utilitarian of this sort might come
to adhere to socialist revolution on moral grounds, based on its short-
comings with respect to providing non-moral goods to the proletariat. In
this case, Marx’s critique of capitalism, despite appealing only to the non-
ethical objective interests of the proletariat, would nevertheless be able to
appeal indirectly to non-proletarians via their ethical commitments. Obvi-
ously, this could also very well happen for proletarians. They too could
find Marx’s amoralist critique of capitalism appealing not just by reflecting
on their own objective interests, but also indirectly because their ethical
commitments require that they care about the relevant non-ethical goods
and/or their effects, e.g. on utility.
A third possible line of reply would be that non-proletarians could
be brought to care about Marx’s critique of capitalism through various
kinds of non-ethical concerns about the non-ethical goods available to
the proletariat, for instance through simple sentiment (e.g. an emotional
reaction of compassion or concern) or through strategic instrumental
thinking (e.g. through thinking the proletariat’s well-being is essential for
carrying out victorious military campaigns in the future, and thus, indi-
rectly, for one’s own future well-being), but this reply is likely to be far
less interesting or satisfactory to most Marxists, so I won’t elaborate on
it further.
These replies can be expanded in a number of different ways, but there
is insufficient space to do so here. All I’ve attempted to show with them
is that reading Marx as basing his critique of capitalism on non-ethical
goods such as the objective interests of the proletariat—as amoralists such
as Wood do—is not inherently contradictory or ridiculous, and that it still
leaves space to argue for additional ethical or moral considerations to play
a role among both proletarians and non-proletarians.25
25 As we see in Chapter 9, Marx doubts at least some of the efficacy of these things,
but that is a distinct issue.
236 APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL …
clearly not enjoyable, but these are the inherent results and implications
of conditions of alienation, not what alienation consists in. In defending
Wood, we could allow that the various forms of alienation Marx discusses
are general-purpose obstacles to attaining other things everyone wants or
would want because of their corrosive impacts on things like freedom,
solidarity, community, and so on, which in fact seems to be Wood’s posi-
tion. This, however, leads us back to the initial criticism, which was that
the key underlying concerns of Marx’s theories of alienation are not prop-
erly accounted for by such an appeal to an unconnected multiplicity of bad
things.
In summary, then, simple amoralism is rejected due to the fallacious
account it entails about the nature and development of Marx’s theories
and the fact that there is at least one more plausible account available.
Sophisticated amoralism, however, succeeds in capturing some of Marx’s
insights and beliefs about the nature of right, justice, and so on, as well
as his views on revolutionary theoretical advocacy—principally by appeal
to wants and interests rather than the articulation and application of
abstract ethical principles and theories. However, this position too should
be rejected. It cannot make sense of the clear persistence of different and
seemingly unrelated normative concerns in Marx’s writings and it cannot
give a satisfactory account of the linchpin of Marx’s life work developed
in his second theory of alienation, which, as I show in Part I, rests on
other normative commitments.
29 This paradigmatically includes both the category of writers who view Marx as crit-
icising capitalism for its injustice, such as Arneson (1981), Cohen (1981, 1983, 1989),
DeGoyler (1992), Elster (1983, 1985), Geras (1985, 1992), Green (1983), Husami
(1978), Nielsen (1988), Riley (1983), Ryan (1980), van de Veer (1973), van der Linden
(1984), and Young (1978, 1981), as well as others such as Allen’s (1974) utilitarian
reading and Gregor’s (1968) interpretation in terms of nomic redefinition of man from
which different sets of abstract ethical principles follow, and other readings in terms of
(moral) principles of freedom, individuality, etc.
APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL … 239
would expect him to first articulate, presumably with some clarity, the
abstract principles on which his critique of capitalism was based, demon-
strate how capitalism both fails and is likely to keep failing to meet them,
and critique capitalism in one way or another on those grounds. It is
therefore absolutely vital for a moralist reading that it can demonstrate
either that Marx had, or that he must have had, some principles of the
required kind that he in fact uses in a critique of capitalism. I will argue
that no such principles are to be found.
Before moving on, we should note that the normative principles in (1),
(2), and (3) above are held, on moralist readings of Marx, to be abstract
and ahistorical in nature, and thus not properly subject to variance across
different natural, social, and historical contexts. By this I mean that the
contextual variance in question is believed to be in some way ethically
legitimate or salutary. If, on the contrary, one holds the view that the prin-
ciples in terms of which Marx critiques capitalism are of such a nature that
they rightly vary across different contexts, then one’s position collapses
into a variant of internal critique. Why? Because the first kind of internal
critique discussed in (D) below is one which draws its principles from a
particular context, in terms of which actions, institutions, etc. within that
context are then critiqued. On such an account, capitalism is critiqued in
terms of the principles which arise in capitalist societies and in terms of
which those societies tend to legitimate themselves. If the principles in
question properly vary across contexts as a result of being generated only
within and in part by such contexts, then they are, in a sense, principles
internal to that context (or range of relevantly similar contexts). A critique
in terms of such internal principles can then, logically, be one of two
kinds. Either an action, institution, or whatnot can be critiqued in terms
of principles external to the context in which that action, institution, or
whatnot appears—external critique—or it can be critiqued in terms of
principles internal to that context or range of contexts—internal critique.
It is hard to see how an external critique of capitalism in this sense can
make any sense of Marx’s work. It seems wildly implausible to suppose
that any of the principles in question are not valued in the context of capi-
talist societies and there is no clear way that such a critique, in light of the
global spread of capitalism, can serve to bring about any change in human
societies—a concern central to Marx’s work. Since external critique in this
sense is completely implausible, an internal critique is the only coherent
alternative. As such, if the normative foundations of Marx’s critique of
capitalism along the lines of the kinds of principles in (1), (2), and (3)
APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL … 241
33 I should perhaps note that I take my rejection of all alternative ethical components—
especially those based on ethical principle of various kinds—also to give good grounds for
rejecting the idea that Marx’s theory of “exploitation” is an ethical critique of capitalism.
Any remotely plausible textual interpretation of this idea as one with ethical content must
presuppose one or another of these alternative conceptions of Marx’s ethical views, all of
which I argue we have good reason to reject. I should also point out that Marx never says
he is doing anything at all ethical with his theory of exploitation, that given the actual
definition of exploitation and its rate in his economics it can only occur in capitalist society
(since it presupposes the production of value, which is the hallmark of capitalism), that
he explicitly points out that capitalist exchange is not unjust in Capital, and that Marx
consistently says he does not mean anything ethically loaded by it—and, as we have seen,
he criticises those who, like Proudhon and the Lasalleans, attempt to critique capitalism
on these grounds (e.g. in the Critique of the Gotha Programme). The reader will note
that these points have been discussed in section (A) of this appendix, as important aspects
of the amoralist position that, unlike its analysis of Marx’s critique of capitalism, I wish to
preserve (both because they’re correct interpretations of Marx and because I find them
compelling).
34 Especially Geras (1985).
242 APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL …
37 Recall that Wood’s (1972a, 1972b, 2004), and some others’, early work, to which
Geras’ arguments are in part responses, tended to conflate these two distinct kinds of
concerns. This point is largely a rejection of that conflation.
38 Marx also rejected distributive principles, to which moralists generally reply with
points (viii) and (x) below.
39 Marx (1996, p. 215/I:25, 15).
40 Geras (1985, p. 62).
41 Cohen (1983).
244 APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL …
42 These points summarise in particular the excellent work in Geras (1985). It should
be noted that (x), unlike the others, is not formulated by Geras as a proposition in the
defence of the justice-theoretical interpretation. Instead, it is defended as the only viable
way of reconciling Marx’s explicit statements with what he takes to be the overwhelming
case made for that interpretation by points (i)–(ix).
APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL … 245
context. And this has further implications for the consideration of points
(vii) and (viii).
Starting with (vii), there is no reason to assume that right and justice
cannot be categorised in merely politico-juridical terms. In fact, there is
a good argument for saying, as amoralists like Wood do, that this was
precisely how those terms were understood by Marx. On this reading,
when Marx criticises politico-juridical conceptions of right and justice he
was criticising precisely what he understood “justice” in general to be.
As far as reconstructing what Marx took himself to be doing, then, the
justice-theoretical claim Geras makes in (vii) has no force unless it can
demonstrate that Marx in fact held a conception of justice which goes
beyond merely politico-juridical concerns. Such a demonstration remains
outstanding. Naturally, our concepts of right and justice may differ from
Marx’s, in which case one can argue that Marx held something which we
would, and he would not, recognise as falling under the terms of right
and justice. If this is indeed the case, then the weight of the argument
falls on whether (ii) and (iii) enables the justice-theorist to excavate such
a principle or set thereof. I shall shortly argue that they do not.
Moving on to (viii), it seems correct to say that “from each according
to his ability, to each according to his needs” can rightly be called a
principle of distributive justice—or at least a principle of distribution—
in the sense that it is an abstract principle which is supposed to guide the
distribution of goods and services in a society. There is, however, no inde-
pendent reason to believe that this in any way conflicts with the amoralist
reading43 of principles of distribution, along with other principles guiding
and constraining the interactions between groups and individuals, as
appropriate or not only to certain contexts and not others, and therefore
good/bad or better/worse only relative to those contexts. When Marx
mentions this distributive maxim, it is in the context of describing socialist
society, and this maxim is offered precisely as the one most appropriate to
that kind of society (for more on which see Chapter 8). There is no inde-
pendent reason to believe that this distributive maxim is a stand-alone,
abstract, and ahistorical principle of justice by which capitalism is judged
and found wanting by Marx. If anything, it is part of a package—socialist
society—which is held, as a whole, to be superior to capitalism. Because
the distributive principle in question only appears as part of this wider
right, and justice. Since it is now clear that (ii) and (iii) must shoulder
the entire burden of Geras’ justice-theoretical interpretation, it is to these
that I now turn.
If the foregoing is correct, then Geras’ entire remaining case for
supposing that Marx had some principle(s) or a theory of justice rests
on nothing more than the claim that the language of “theft”, “robbery”,
etc., that he employs must imply a prior conception of justice which is
violated by the capitalist appropriation of surplus value. Since the distribu-
tive maxim mentioned in (iii) has already been dealt with, I shall focus
now on this sole remaining argument. It can be presented in syllogistic
form as follows:
44 The most thorough treatment available are those of Geras (1985, pp. 65–69; 1992).
248 APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL …
strongest reasons why I believe (a) should be rejected are the following.
First, using the descriptive cognates mentioned need not be taken to
presuppose a principle of justice being violated. Rather than necessarily
relying on an antecedent conception of justice of a very particular kind,
Marx may be read as engaging in an attempt to reform existing concep-
tions and/or usages of “theft” and its cognates in line with what he takes
to be their core meanings and centres of normative force, in order in
turn to help reform popular judgements about the nature of capitalist
appropriation for political purposes. The core meanings in question may
consist in, for instance, that in both capitalist appropriation and in more
familiar cases of theft, something is being appropriated from someone
else without their acceptance, that in (at least some of instances of) both
cases something is being so appropriated without the “losers’” awareness
and knowledge, and so on. By shifting the way in which this kind of
normatively laden language is used, certain actions and processes which
are normally thought of as morally salutary per definitionem—such as the
everyday purchase of labour-power in a capitalist economy—now come
to be described in terms which are more negatively laden. Even if no
new facts are added, such a shift in how these concepts are used may
nevertheless help bring about a change in the way the process of capi-
talist appropriation is thought of and evaluated—one which better suits
the political needs and interests of the proletariat qua revolutionary class.
Another possible interpretation of the relevant passages—again, at
least as well-founded as Geras’ justice-theoretical reading thereof—is
that by describing the process of capitalist appropriation in terms of
unequal exchange, theft, plunder, and so on, Marx is re-describing a
familiar process—a description buttressed by his economic theory and
its problem-solving power (e.g. its ability to explain the origin of profits
under equal exchange, or its ability to explain the possibility of economic
crises)—in a new way such that certain elements which were previously
obscured or unknown now come to be illuminated. These elements turn
out in fact to be the opposite of what they look like—viz. what looked
like free and equal exchange is shown in fact to be coerced and unequal
exchange and thus, in some sense, “theft”, “robbery”, etc.—and this in
turn causes, or at least is supposed to cause, the addressees to change their
conceptions and assessments of the object(s) of this re-description. In this
case no new concepts need to be added and no familiar concepts need to
shift either their meanings or their general usage. Instead, what changes
APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL … 249
users. If we grant this, and if we further accept that concepts can influence
political practice in a significant way, then it follows that language and
language-use is itself something which can be, at least in principle, some-
thing which it is worth trying to change in order better to further one’s
political purposes. Again, this coheres much better with the alternative
readings suggested than it does with that of the justice-theorists.
Fourthly, the more fluid and indeterminate conception of language
and language-use, its connections to human practical activity and the
needs and interests inherent therein, and the resulting thesis about the
pragmatic revisability of language, all seem to cohere better with Marx’s
consistent emphasis—throughout his life—on developing the concepts
one employs to understand an aspect of reality such that they are best able
to match the “real movements” of the object of study, rather than setting
up an antecedently defined framework which the objects of study are
then subsequently analysed and/or evaluated in terms of. This includes
not only Marx’s discussions and analyses of straightforwardly descrip-
tive matters, such as in his critique of the classical political economists’
superficial analysis of capitalist social relations in the Economic and Philo-
sophical Manuscripts of 1844 46 and or his critique of Proudhon in the
Poverty of Philosophy for setting up a scheme of abstract and ahistor-
ical concepts prior to detailed empirical study—badly compromising the
latter as a result. It also occurs in at least one context, namely in the
1837 letter to his father, in which Marx has both normative and descrip-
tive concerns in one and the same investigation—namely his projected
study of law and legal systems.47 In this letter, one of Marx’s main stated
concerns is, as in the other instances just mentioned, that the concepts
needed to understand and evaluate something need to be developed
alongside, and in response to, the object of study. He contrasts this with
his own earlier idealistic attempts—as well as those of Kant and Fichte—
at proceeding from antecedently defined concepts and categories which
are then subsequently applied to the objects of study. Not only does this
further underscore that such concepts are malleable and should, when
appropriate, be altered or further developed in response to the needs and
interests of their users; it also explicitly presents an approach to language
and its use precisely in line with the alternative conception I have outlined
In summary, then, I have argued that a close look at the evidence and
arguments that Geras offers in favour of the justice-theoretical reading of
Marx reveals that his case is extremely flimsy, resting, at best, solely on the
syllogism (a)–(c). Furthermore, I have argued that there is little reason to
accept the major premise (a) in light of the availability of competing and
more plausible interpretations of what Marx is doing with the norma-
tively charged concepts in question—interpretations which need not rely
on implicit conceptions of justice. This, together with other good reasons
to reject the conclusion in (c), means that the interpretation in (a) ought
to be rejected. However, even if (a)–(c) is not rejected, the non-existent
principle(s) of justice required to make sense of these claims still do not
deserve serious consideration as the normative foundations of Marx’s
critique of capitalism, if only because the only diagnostic critiques he does
develop and retain rest on other foundations altogether.
One moralistic way in which these other grounds can be understood
is in terms of abstract and ahistorical principles or ideals of freedom,
equality, community, rationality, and so on.48 I believe that this position
carries a major and important insight—namely that Marx’s chief objec-
tions to capitalism were made in terms of its detrimental effects on human
freedom, self-rule, or self-direction, as diagnosed in his critique of capi-
talism that I’ve discussed throughout this book. Where this account goes
wrong, however, is in the way it posits these principles or ideals without
sufficient attention to the way they are grounded in Marx’s accounts of
human development, human beings, and human society. This is what I
have tried to provide throughout Part I, setting the stage for the later
chapters’ accounts of alienation, democracy, and socialism. Furthermore,
the way this other moralist kind of approach posits values externally—
either from the point of view of another society, or from some supposed
48 Brenkert (1979), Comninel (2010), arguably DeGoyler (1992) and Kamenka (1972)
(Kamenka 1969, by contrast, seems to claim these commitments in turn derive from a
normative conception of human nature or species-being), Lukes (1985), Mcbride (1975),
Peffer (1990), Sichel (1972), Soper (1987) and Sowell (1963). Allen’s (1974) appeal to
utility may also, arguably, fit into this category. There is a version of this claim according
to which Marx criticises capitalism in terms of the socialist and/or communist distributive
maxims as higher forms of society (cf. Lukes 1985; McBride 1975; Miller 1983; Nielsen
1988; Riley 1983; Sayers 1989, 1994, 2007a). Such a view, it seems to me, must in
turn rest on some other kind of normative foundations in terms of which the “higher”
and “lower” forms of society are determined as such. As a result of this they collapse,
ultimately, into more familiar variants (an argument Geras advances against Sayers in the
former’s 1992).
254 APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL …
51 Aronovitch (1980), Avineri (1968), Booth (1992) and Buchanan (1982) (for the
young Marx of 1844, but not the later one). Fromm (2004), Gilbert (1992), Leopold
(2007), probably Miller (1992) and Wilde (1998), see also McMurty (1978).
52 Kain (1988, 1992), Kamenka (1969), and Nasser (1975). Wood (2004) has inter-
esting points when it comes to the connection between Aristotle’s and Marx’s view of
human nature, but denies that this plays any non-amoralist normative role in Marx.
256 APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL …
53 For discussion of the use of the term “alienation” in the older Marx, see Cowling
2006.
APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL … 257
55 Some writers who read Marx’s work in part or in whole in terms of such a notion
(to be clarified below) include Antonio (1981), Benhabib (1984), Buchanan (1981),
Buchwalter (1991), Chitty (1997), Geuss (1981), Lohmann (1986), Lukes (1985) and
Sayers (1989, 1994, and possibly 2007a).
56 Antonio (1981).
APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL … 259
57 Lohmann (1986).
58 Benhabib (1984), Buchanan (1981) and Geuss (1981).
59 This seems to be, at least part of, Geuss (1981), McCarney (1990) and Chitty
(1997).
60 Lohmann (1986), for instance, reads Marx as both engaged in immanent critique
of the kind just discussed, but also developing a (rather unclear) form of abstract and
ahistorical critique as well. Buchwalter (1991) believes Marx must rest on some abstract
and ahistorical values of rationality, self-realisation, and so on. Lukes (1985) holds Marx
to mix forms of internal and a more moralistic form of critique.
260 APPENDIX: A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE (OTHER) PRINCIPAL …
Primary
Engels, F., & Henderson, W. O. (Ed.). (1967). Engels: Selected writings. Penguin.
Marx, K., & Carver, T. (ed. and trans.). (1996). Marx: Later political writings.
Cambridge University Press.
Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1969). Karl Marx and Frederick Engels: Selected works
in three volumes (MESW). Progress Publishers.
Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1975–2004). Marx Engels Collected Works (MECW).
Lawrence & Wishart.
Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1975). Karl Marx Friedrich Engels Gesamtausgabe
(MEGA2 ). Dietz/Akademie Verlag.
Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1927–1932, 1935). Karl Marx-Friedrich Engels-
Historische-kritische Gesamtausgabe: Werke, Schriften, Briefe (MEGA1 ). Marx-
Engels Verlag.
Marx, K., & Nicolaus, M. (trans.). (1993). Grundrisse: Foundations of a critique
of political economy. Penguin.
Marx, K., & Burns, E. (trans.). (1969). Theories of surplus value: Part I .
Lawrence & Wishart.
Marx, K., Fowkes, B. (trans.) & Mandel, E. (intro.). (1990). Capital: A critique
of political economy (Vol. 1). Penguin.
Marx, K., Fowkes, B., (trans.) & Mandel, E. (intro.). 1991. Capital: A critique
of political economy (Vol. 3). Penguin.
Marx, K., Livingstone, R. (trans.), Benton, G. (trans.) & Colletti, L. (Intro.).
(1992). Karl Marx: Early writings. Penguin.
© The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive 263
license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2022
P. Raekstad, Karl Marx’s Realist Critique of Capitalism,
Marx, Engels, and Marxisms,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-06353-4
264 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Secondary
Abensour, M. (2004). La Démocratie contre l’État: Marx et le moment machi-
avélien (2nd ed.). Éditions du Félin.
Acton, H. B. (1955). The illusion of the epoch. Cohen & West Ltd.
Adams, W. (1991). Aesthetics: Liberating the senses. In Carver (ed.), pp. 246–
274.
Albert, M. (2003). ParEcon: Life after capitalism. Verso.
Albert, M., & Hahnel, R. (1978). Unorthodox Marxism: An essay on capitalism,
socialism and revolution. Boston: South End Press.
Albert, M., & Hahnel, R. (1991). The political economy of participatory
economics. Princeton University Press.
Albert, M., & Hahnel, R. (1999). Looking forward: Participatory economics for
the twenty first century. South End Press.
Allen, D. P. H. (1974). Is Marxism a philosophy? The Journal of Philosophy,
71(17), 601–612.
Allen, K. (2011). Marx and the alternative to capitalism. Pluto Press.
Alexander, R. J. (1999). The anarchists in the Spanish Civil War (2 Vols.). Janus.
Anderson, E. (2017). Private government: How employers rule our lives (and why
we don’t talk about it). Princeton University Press.
Antonio, R. J. (1981). Immanent critique as the core of critical theory: Its origins
and developments in Hegel, Marx and contemporary thought. The British
Journal of Sociology, 32(3), 330–345.
Arneson, R. J. (1981). What’s wrong with alienation? Ethics, 91(2), 202–227.
Aronovitch, H. (1980). Marxian morality. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10(3),
357–376.
Arrighi, G., Hopkins, T. K., & Wallerstein, I. (2012). Anti-systemic movements.
Verso.
Arthur, C. J. (1986). Dialectics of labour: Marx and his relation to Hegel. Basil
Blackwell.
Avineri, S. (1968). The social and political thought of Karl Marx. Cambridge
University Press.
Baderin, A. (2014). Two forms of realism in political theory. European Journal
of Political Theory, 13(2), 132–153.
Balibar, E. (2008). Spinoza and politics. Verso.
Bavister-Gould, A. (2013). Bernard Williams: Political realism and the limits of
legitimacy. European Journal of Philosophy, 21(4), 593–610.
Bhattacharya, T. (Ed.). (2017). Social reproduction theory: Remapping class,
recentering oppression. Pluto Press.
Benhabib, S. (1984). The Marxian method of critique: Normative presupposi-
tions. PRAXIS International, 4(3), 284–298.
Berki, R. N. (1990). Through and through Hegel: Marx road to communism.
Political Studies, 38(4), 654–671.
BIBLIOGRAPHY 265
psychological need satisfaction, need frustration, and need strength across four
cultures. Motivation and Emotion, 39(2), 216–236.
Chirkov, V., Ryan, R. M., Kim, Y., & Kaplan, U. (2003). Differentiating
autonomy from individualism and independence: A self-determination theory
perspective on internalization of cultural orientations and well-being. Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, 84, 97–109.
Chirkov, V., Ryan, R. M., & Willness, C. (2005). Cultural context and psycho-
logical needs in Canada and Brazil: Testing a self-determination approach to
the internalization of cultural practices, identity, and well-being. Journal of
Cross-Cultural Psychology, 36, 423–443.
Chitty, A. (1993). The early Marx on needs. Radical Philosophy, 64, 23–31.
Chitty, A. (1997). Introduction: The direction of contemporary capitalism and
the relevance of theory. Review of International Political Economy, 4(3), 435–
447.
Chitty, A. (2006). The basis of the state in the Marx of 1842. In Moggach (Ed.),
pp. 220–241.
Chitty, A., & McIvor, M. (Eds.). (2009). Karl Marx and contemporary philos-
ophy. Palgrave Macmillan.
Chomsky, N. (1969). American power and the new mandarins. The New Press.
Cockshott, P. W., & Cottrell, A. (1993). Towards a new socialism. Spokesman.
Cohen, G. A. (1981). Freedom, justice and capitalism. New Left Review, 126,
3–16.
Cohen, G. A. (1983). Review of Karl Marx by Allen W. Wood. Mind, 92(367),
440–445.
Cohen, G. A. (1989). History, labour and freedom: Themes from Marx. Clarendon
Press.
Cohen, G. A. (2001). Karl Marx’s theory of history: A defence (Expanded
Edition). Princeton University Press.
Cohen, G. A. (2008). Rescuing justice and equality. Harvard University Press.
Cohen, G. A. (2009). Why not socialism? Princeton University Press.
Colletti, L. (1992). Introduction to Marx 1992, pp. 7–56.
Collier, A. (2009). Marx and conservatism. In A. Chitty & M. McIvor (Eds.),
pp. 99–104.
Comninel, G. (2010). Emancipation in Marx’s early work. Socialism and
Democracy, 24(3), 60–78.
Cowling, M. (2006). Alienation in the older Marx. Contemporary Political
Theory, 5(3), 319–339.
Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (2000). The “what” and “why” of goal pursuits:
Human needs and the self-determination of behavior. Psychological Inquiry,
11(4), 227–268.
Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (Ed.). (2002a). Handbook of self-determination
research. University of Rochester Press.
BIBLIOGRAPHY 267
Foster, J. B., Clark, B., & York, R. (2010). The ecological rift: capitalism’s war
on the earth. Monthly Review Press.
Foster, J. B., & McChesney, R. (2012). The endless crisis: How monopoly-finance
capital produces stagnation and upheaval from the USA to China. Monthly
Review Press.
Forrester, K. (2012). Judith Shklar, Bernard Williams, and political realism.
European Journal of Political Theory, 11(3), 247–272.
Foucault, M. (1988). The history of sexuality, volume 3: The use of pleasure.
Vintage.
Foucault, M. (1990a). The history of sexuality, volume 1: An introduction.
Vintage.
Foucault, M. (1990b). The history of sexuality, volume 2: The care of the self .
Vintage.
Foucault, M. (1995). Discipline and punish: The birth of the prison (2nd ed.).
Vintage.
Frazer, E. (2008). Political theory and the boundaries of politics. In D.
Leopold & M. Stears (Eds.), Political theory: Methods and approaches. Oxford
University Press.
Frazer, E. (2010). What’s real in political philosophy? Contemporary Political
Theory, 9(4), 490–507.
Fromm, E. (2004). Marx’s concept of man. Continuum.
Furner, J. (2011). Marx’s sketch of communist society in The German ideology
and the problems of occupational confinement and occupational identity.
Philosophy and Social Criticism, 37 (2), 189–215.
Galston, W. A. (2010). Realism in political theory. European Journal of Political
Theory, 9(4), 385–411.
Gamble, A. (1996). Hayek: The iron cage of liberty. Polity Press.
Gamble, A. (2006). Hayek on knowledge, economics, and society. In E. Feser
(Ed.), pp. 111–131.
Geras, N. (1983). Marx and human nature: Refutation of a legend. Verso.
Geras, N. (1985). The controversy about Marx and justice. New Left Review,
150, 47–85.
Geras, N. (1992). Bringing Marx to justice: An addendum to a rejoinder. New
Left Review , 195, 37–69.
Geuss, R. (1981). The idea of a critical theory: Habermas and the Frankfurt
school. Cambridge University Press.
Geuss, R. (2001). History and illusion in politics. Cambridge University Press.
Geuss, R. (2003). Public goods, private goods. Princeton University Press.
Geuss, R. (2005). Outside ethics. Princeton University Press.
Geuss, R. (2008). Philosophy and real politics. Princeton University Press.
Geuss, R. (2010). Politics and the imagination. Princeton University Press.
Geuss, R. (2012). Economies: Good, bad, indifferent. Inquiry, 55(4), 331–360.
BIBLIOGRAPHY 269
McGovern, A. F. (1988). The young Marx on the state. In Wood (Ed.), pp. 166–
193.
MacIntyre, C. (2009). Alasdair MacIntyre’s engagement with Marxism: Selected
writings, 1953–1974. Haymarket Books.
McLellan, D. (1970). Marx before Marxism. Penguin.
McLellan, D. (1971). The thought of Karl Marx: An introduction. Macmillan.
McMurty, J. (1978). The structure of Marx’s world-view. Princeton University
Press.
Mack, E. (2011). Nozickian arguments for the more-than-minimal state. In R.
M. Bader & J. Meadowcroft (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Nozick’s
Anarchy, state, and Utopia (pp. 89–115). Cambridge University Press.
Marangos, J. (Ed.). (2011). Alternative perspectives of a good society. Palgrave
Macmillan.
Martin, B. (2008). Ethical Marxism: The categorical imperative of liberation.
Open Court.
Maslow, A. H. (1970). Motivation and personality (2nd ed.). Harper & Row
Publishers.
Matheron, A. (1977). Le Traité théologico-politique lu par le jeune Marx. Cahiers
Spinoza, 1, 159–212.
Melman, S. (1958). Decision-making and productivity. Basil Blackwell.
Menke, C. (2010). Neither Rawls Nor Adorno: Raymond Geuss’ programme for
a ‘realist’ political philosophy. European Journal of Philosophy, 18(1), 139–147.
Mészáros, I. (1972). Marx’s theory of alienation (3rd ed.). Merlin Press.
Mészáros, I. (1986). Philosophy, ideology and social science: Essays in negation and
affirmation. Wheatsheaf Books.
Mészáros, I. (1995). Beyond capital: Towards a theory of transition. Merlin Press.
Mészáros, I. (2011). Social structure and forms of consciousness, volume II: The
dialectic of structure and history. Monthly Review Press.
Mészáros, I. (2014). The necessity of social control. Monthly Review Press.
Mill, J. S. (1989). ‘On liberty’ and other writings. Cambridge University Press.
Miller, D. (Ed.). (2006). The liberty reader. Edinburgh University Press.
Miller, R. W. (1983). Marx and morality. Nomos, 26, 3–32.
Miller, R. W. (1984). Analyzing Marx: Morality, power, history. Princeton
University Press.
Miller, R. W. 1992. Marx and Aristotle: A kind of consequentialism. In McCarthy
(Ed.), pp. 275–302.
Mintz, F. (2013). Anarchism and workers’ self-management in revolutionary
Spain. AK Press.
Moggach, D. (Ed.). (2006). The new Hegelians: Politics and philosophy in the
Hegelian school. Cambridge University Press.
Montesquieu, C. (1998). Montesquieu: The spirit of the laws. Cambridge Univer-
sity Press.
274 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Ryan, C. C. (1980). Socialist justice and the right to the labour product. Political
Theory, 8(4), 503–524.
Ryan, R. N. (1995). Psychological needs and the facilitation of integrative
processes. Journal of Personality, 63(3), 397–427.
Ryan, R. N., & Deci, E. L. (2006). Self-regulation and the problem of human
autonomy: Does psychology need choice, self-determination and will? Journal
of Personality, 74(6), 1557–1586.
Ryan, R. N., & Deci, E. L. (2020). Intrinsic and extrinsic motivation from a self-
determination theory perspective: Definitions, theory, practices, and future
directions. Contemporary Educational Psychology, 61(101860).
Rækstad, P. (2010). Marx fra demokrati til kommunisme. Rødt!: Marxistisk
Tidsskrift, 39(4), 90–99.
Rækstad, P. (2011a). Class and state in the political theory of Adam Smith: A
chapter in the history of a neglected strand of political thought (107 p) (Master’s
Thesis). University of Oslo.
Rækstad, P. (2011b). Deltakende demokrati – en sosialisme for fremtiden. Rødt!:
Marxistisk Tidsskrift, 40(3), 116–126.
Rækstad. (2012a). “Menneskelig utvikling og menneskelige behov”/“Human
development and human needs” as part of the seminar on “growth, wealth
and happiness—Are they connected?” (together with Roar Eilertsen and
professor Ove Jakobsen). The Welfare Conference 2012a, Oslo.
Rækstad, P. (2012b, August 7). Den Radikale Opplysningen. Klassekampen
(pp. 12–13).
Sabio, O. (2015). Rojava: An alternative to imperialism, nationalism, and
Islamism in the Middle East (an introduction). Published independently at
www.lulu.com.
Saito, K. (2017). Karl Marx’s ecosocialism: Capitalism, nature, and the unfinished
critique of political economy. Monthly Review Press.
Sangiovanni, A. (2008). Justice and the priority of politics to morality. The
Journal of Political Philosophy, 16(2), 137–164.
Sayers, S. (1989). Analytical Marxism and morality. Canadian Journal of
Philosophy, Supplementary Volume, 15, 81–104, reprinted in Sayers 2007b,
pp. 111–129.
Sayers, S. (1994). Moral values and progress. New Left Review, 204, 67–85,
reprinted in Sayers 2007b, pp. 130–148.
Sayers, S. (2007a). Marxism and morality. Philosophical Researches (9), 8–12.
Sayers, S. (2007b). Marxism and human nature. Routledge.
Sayers, S. (2011). Marx and alienation: Essays in Hegelian themes. Palgrave
Macmillan.
Schacht, R. (1971). Alienation. George Allen & Unwin Ltd.
278 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Schröder, E., & Storm, S. (2020). Economic growth and carbon emissions: The
road to “hothouse earth” is paved with good intentions. International Journal
of Political Economy, 49(2), 153–173.
Schweickart, D. (1996). Against capitalism. Westview Press.
Sen, A. (1984a). Well-being, agency and freedom: The Dewey lectures 1984.
The Journal of Philosophy, 82(4), 169–221.
Sen, A. (1984b). Resources, values and development. Basil Blackwell.
Sen, A. (1987). The standard of living (the Tanner lectures). Cambridge
University Press.
Sen, A. (1992). Inequality reexamined. Clarendon Press.
Sen, A. (1999). Development as freedom. Oxford University Press.
Sen, A. (2010). The idea of justice. Penguin.
Sen, A. (2012a). Values and justice. Journal of Economic Methodology, 19(2),
101–108.
Sen, A. (2012b). A reply to Robeyns, Peter and Davis. Journal of Economic
Methodology, 19(2), 173–176.
Sichel, B. A. (1972). Karl Marx and the rights of man. Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 32(3), 355–360.
Sitrin, M. (2012). Everyday revolutions: Horizontalism and autonomy in
Argentina. Zed Books.
Sitrin, M., & Azzellini, D. (2014). They can’t represent us!: Reinventing
democracy from Greece to occupy. Verso.
Skinner, Q. (1998). Liberty before liberalism. Cambridge University Press.
Skinner, Q. (2006). A third concept of liberty. In D. Miller (Ed.), pp. 243–254.
Skinner, Q. (2008). Hobbes and republican liberty. Cambridge University Press.
Sleat, M. (2010). Bernard Williams and the possibility of a realist political theory.
European Journal of Political Theory, 9(4), 485–503.
Sleat, M. (2013). Liberal realism: A realist theory of liberal politics. Manchester
University Press.
Smith, A. (1976). An Inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Soenens, B., Park, S.-B., Vansteenkiste, M., & Mouratidis, A. (2012). Perceived
parental psychological control and adolescent depressive experiences: A
cross-cultural study with Belgian and South-Korean adolescents. Journal of
Adolescence, 35, 261–272.
Soenens, B., & Beyers, W. (2012). The cross-cultural significance of control and
autonomy in parent-adolescent relationships. Journal of Adolescence, 35, 243–
248.
Soper, K. (1981). On human needs: Open and closed theories in a Marxist
perspective. Harvester Press.
Soper, K. (1987). Marxism and morality. New Left Review, 163, 101–113.
BIBLIOGRAPHY 279
Sowell, T. (1963). Karl Marx and the freedom of the individual. Ethics, 73(2),
119–125.
Spinoza, B. (1996). Ethics. Penguin.
Springborg, P. (1981). The problem of human needs and the critique of civilisation.
George Allen & Unwin.
Strangers in a Tangled Wilderness (Ed.). (2015). A small key can open a large
door: The Rojava revolution. Combustion Books.
Swain, D. (2012). Alienation: An introduction to Marx’s theory. Bookmarks.
Swain, D. (2019). None so fit to break the chains: Marx’s ethics of self-
emancipation. Brill.
Swain, D. (2019). Not not but not yet: Present and future in prefigurative
politics. Political Studies, 67 (1), 47–62.
Tabak, M. (2012). Dialectics of human nature in Marx’s philosophy. Palgrave
Macmillan.
Tabak, M. (2020). Marx’s philosophy of revolution and freedom: A critical
reconstruction. Self-published.
Taylor, R. (2014). The new PKK: Unleashing a social revolution in Kurdistan.
ROAR Magazine. Available online: https://roarmag.org/essays/pkk-kurdish-
struggle-autonomy/.
Thomas, A. (2014). Sen on Rawls’s “transcendental institutionalism”: An analysis
and critique. European Journal of Political Theory, 13(3), 241–263.
Thompson, M. J. (2019). The radical Republican structure of Marx’s critique of
capitalist society. Critique, 47 (3), 391–409.
Trist, E. L., Higgin, G. W., Murray, H., & Pollock, A. B. (1963). Organiza-
tional choice: Capabilities of groups at the coal face under changing technologies.
Tavistock Publications.
Tucker, R. C. (1970). The Marxian revolutionary idea. George Allen & Unwin
Ltd.
Tucker, R. C. (1972). Philosophy and myth in Karl Marx. Cambridge University
Press.
Valentini, L. (2011). A paradigm shift in theorizing about justice? A critique of
Sen. Economics and Philosophy, 27 (3), 297–315.
Valentini, L. (2012). Ideal vs. non-ideal theory: A conceptual map. Philosophy
Compass, 7 (9), 654–664.
Van de Sande, M. (2015). Fighting with tools: Prefiguration and radical politics
in the twenty-first century. Rethinking Marxism, 27 (2), 177–194.
Van de Veer, D. (1973). Marx’s views of justice. Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, 33(3), 366–386.
Van der Linden, H. (1984). Marx and morality: An impossibly synthesis? Theory
and Society, 13(1), 119–135.
van Ree, E. (2020). Productive forces, the passions and natural philosophy: Karl
Marx, 1841–1846. Journal of Political Ideologies, 25(3), 274–293.
280 BIBLIOGRAPHY
C D
Capital, 122, 127, 132, 137, 140, Democracy, 4, 7–11, 70, 82, 84, 87,
143, 148, 163, 164, 201, 203, 89–101, 103, 105, 107–109,
241 155, 156, 172, 213, 253
Capitalism, 1–12, 21–23, 31, 41–43, Division of labour, 5, 11, 131, 136,
45, 50, 53, 58, 62–65, 70, 79, 137, 139, 156, 158, 161–163,
© The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive 283
license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2022
P. Raekstad, Karl Marx’s Realist Critique of Capitalism,
Marx, Engels, and Marxisms,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-06353-4
284 INDEX
F
Freedom, 1, 2, 4–7, 9–12, 21, 25, N
26, 40, 45, 46, 49, 50, 52, 54, Nature, 10, 11, 21, 22, 24, 29, 33,
57–64, 70, 79, 83, 84, 91–93, 49–51, 53–55, 57, 58, 65, 69,
96, 97, 111, 119, 130, 140, 141, 79, 80, 86–88, 109, 132, 134,
146, 151, 155, 157, 160, 163, 137, 138, 140, 142–144, 146,
166, 170, 172, 182, 189, 195, 149, 151, 156, 164, 169, 170,
198, 204, 207–210, 213, 214, 173, 197, 198, 200, 205, 207,
216, 221, 229, 233, 236, 238, 208, 213, 215, 217, 221, 224,
239, 241, 243, 253–256, 259, 226, 228, 238, 240, 248, 249,
260 252, 254, 256, 258–260
human nature, 50, 51, 58
P
H
Planning, 5, 61, 131, 158–161, 166,
Hayek, Friedrich, 10, 156, 172, 183,
175, 178, 183–188, 190, 214,
186–188, 190
217
Human nature, 7, 10, 37, 40, 49, 51,
52, 55, 56, 58, 87, 109, 141,
147, 189, 221, 222, 228, 232, R
233, 244, 253–258, 260 Realism, 2–5, 23, 111, 207, 209, 214
INDEX 285