The Philosophy of The Social Sciences by Alan Ryan-204-225

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 22

g Prediction as a Goal of

Social Science

Up to this point, we have examined the two major and rival


theses regarding the nature of the social sciences that were
outlined in the opening chapter of this book. We have seen
that although there are some deeply disturbing anomalies in
the claim that there are no important differences between the
human sciences and the natural sciences, these anomalies do
not eliminate inquiries into the causes and effects of social
activities, and they do not much impinge on our initial
account of satisfactory causal explanation. In these two last
chapters, we shall try to justify the concerns of the third
thesis we mentioned, that which stresses the social causes and
effects of social theory. In this chapter we shall explore the
implications of the long-standing view that the aim of
developed social science is to produce the prediction of
large-scale social changes, and that its maturity as science can
be estimated by the yield of such predictions; in the final
chapter we shall raise some of the problems of 'objectivity' in
the social sciences, and briefly discuss the topic of ideology.
What provides a common link between these chapters is the
fact that the social sciences are preeminently 'policy
sciences'; {1) that is, they have been developed by and for
men who have wanted to use the knowledge they could gain
to bring about changes of one or another kind. Equally
importantly, they may well have policy effects, even where
they are not developed for policy purposes - just as any
other science may spawn technologically relevant side-effects,
though research was not initiated for technological reasons.
For in the case of the social sciences, one important con-
sideration is that how people act in society depends on what
they believe about society: if they come to believe a different
story, they will also come to behave differently. This fact was
as well-known by Burke, who as a conservative wished to
limit social speculation, as by Marx, who as a revolutionary
197
wished to harness it to the cause of revolution.
In this chapter then, we shall consider three issues. The
first is the validity of the claim that explanation and
prediction are logically identical, merely two faces of the
same knowledge, with the apparent implication that success-
ful explanation must entail an increased ability to predict
future events. The second problem begins at this point, for it
is that of the feasibility in principle of projects for large-scale
sociological prediction; and the final question again stems
from this problem, for - in the light of such current
phenomena as committees set up to predict what will happen
over the next thirty years - we must distinguish between
law-based and trend-based predictions, and evaluate Professor
Popper's claim that the neglect of this distinction has been
fatal to much sociology. (2) In the course of discussing these
issues, we shall be able to see rather further than before into
the distinction between logical and methodological con-
siderations, and also to see how these are - and are not -
related to substantial claims about the real world.
The claim that explanation and prediction are logically
'isomorphic' - that is, the claim that they are formally
identical - rests essentially on a simple logical point, made
earlier in our account of deductive explanation. According to
the deductive view of explanation, as we then described it,
explanations when completely spelled out are deductive
arguments. To explain a particular occurrence, we have to be
able to deduce the statement that this occurrence took place
as and when it did from the general law covering that class of
case together with some statement(s) about the holding of
the initial conditions for the occurrence. In the terminology
of causal connection, we assert the dependence of the event
to be explained on its causal antecedents in the light of an
underlying causal generalisation. Thus we could explain the
way in which Thomas Jones voted in the British general
election of 1966 by pointing to the fact that he had been a
staunch supporter of the National Union of Mineworkers for
the past thirty years. We know, now, that such an account is
not straightforwardly an explanation, by the rigorous
standards of such 'deductivists' as Professor Hempel: it is
rather an 'explanation sketch', (3) the outlines of what could,
were there any chance of people being misled, be trans·
198
formed into a 'complete' explanation. Moreover, we also
know by now that to cite membership of the N.U.M. as a
causal antecedent is subject to the qualifications we made
about the role of reasons as the causes of human action -
membership of the N.U.M. is a shorthand indication of the
kind of reasons for voting which will move Thomas ] ones.
Still, these are only qualifications; and the important point
remains the deductive mould into which we can put such
explanations. And in the case of this explanation, there is no
difficulty about doing just that. With the backing generalisa-
tion that 'All staunch, long-standing members of the N.U.M.
vote Labour' and the initial condition that 'Thomas] ones is a
staunch, long-standing member of the N.U.M.' we can infer
that 'Thomas] ones votes Labour'. The key element in all this
is the backing generalisation, for it is on this that the identity
of explanation and prediction hangs. It will be recalled from
our earlier discussion that a general statement of the form
'All X are Y' is not to be analysed as a conjunction of
singular statements about all the Xs which happen also to be
Ys, but is rather to be read as a hypothetical statement to the
effect that 'If anything is an X, then it is a Y', and as such a
statement it is said to be strictly speaking tenseless, and to
have no particular spatia-temporal reference. Thus 'All long-
standing, staunch members of the N.U.l\1. vote Labour' is to
be read as 'If there is someone who is a staunch, long-
standing member of the N.U.M., then he votes Labour'; and
as we saw, the formulation of such statements in the
predicate calculus as statements of the form (x) (Fx- Gx) is
designed to do justice to the logical structure hidden beneath
the grammatical surface. It is important to be clear about
how we read a symbol such as ' - ', as 'if ... then'; for it is
equally about past, present, future and hypothetical cases, so
that 'All X are Y' is to be read not just as 'If anything is an X
it is also a Y', but equally as 'If anything was an X, then it
was also a Y', 'If anything is (in future) an X, it will be a Y',
'If anything were to be an X, then it would be a Y'. (4) This,
it is plain, means that not merely are explanation and pre-
diction logically isomorphic, but so equally are explanation
and retrodiction, and explanation and hypothetical pre-
diction. That is to say that the generalisation about the
relationship between membership of the N.U.M. and voting
199
Labour equally governs such statements as 'Thomas Evans
was a long-standing and staunch member of the N.U.M., so he
must have voted Labour' or 'If Thomas Evans had been a
staunch, long-standing member of the N.U.M., he would have
voted Labour'. It goes almost without saying that this feature
of explanation is noticeable in day to day life, where we are
very frequently called on to take advantage of i i - especially
where we are concerned to reproach someone. Parents are
often to be heard telling their children 'If you had grown up
in the kind of household we did, you would take more notice
of what your father tells you', a counterfactual utterance
clearly predicated on the assumption that the children have
not grown up in such a house, and do not take much notice
of what father says. Radicals reproach conservatives in such
terms as 'If you were a Bolivian peasant, you would regard
Che Guevara as a hero', which again is predicated exactly on
the belief that the person addressed is neither a Bolivian
peasant nor an admirer of Che Guevara. And, of course, pre-
diction and explanation run everywhere hand in hand:
parents are likely to tell their children 'If you bring up your
children as permissively as we've brought you up, you'll be
sorry'; and the conservative is likely to tell the radical 'When
you reach my age, and know more about the world, you'll
see it's not so easy to change things for the better'. Now,
what all this means is that the only differences between
explanation and prediction lie in whereabouts in the
deductive argument we begin. With the case of explanation,
we begin with the event to be explained, i.e. with the con-
clusion of the argument, and look for the appropriate
generalisations and initial conditions from which to deduce this
conclusion. In the case of prediction, we begin with the general-
isation and the initial conditions and then go on to forecast the
coming occurrence. And in the case of our hypothetical
inferences, we simply suppose the initial conditions, and then
draw the inference as to the consequences of this supposition.
And one illumination which this sheds on a contentious point is
worth noting. The social sciences are often said to suffer
drastically from their inability to engage in controlled
experiment; but this charge is also often said to be nothing
more than a practical inconvenience, shared with such
strikingly successful sciences as astronomy, and thus not in any
200
sense a logical handicap. (5) The grounds for this charge and
rebuttal are now clear. If we are concerned with the testing of
explanations, and especially of the underlying generalisations
on which they rest, experiment will be extremely useful, in that
we can produce the initial conditions and see whether the
conclusion holds. Obviously, such a process gives us a degree on
control over science that is otherwise difficult to obtain. But it
is not logically necessary, in that we can wait until nature
provides our experimental situations for us, or we can infer
with care from the situations we do observe in nature to those
which we cannot observe or create, but can at least envisage.
But this is a merely practical consideration. It is plain that
as a matter of logic, the identity of explanation and predic-
tion is unshakeable. (6) However, this by no means entails
that the goal of science is to try to produce wide-ranging
predictions in practice. Two considerations come into play at
this point. The first concerns the kind of generalisations
available. We saw earlier that valid deductive arguments
required universal generalisations as their general premisses,
and that where we have not got such laws, we often offer
explanations as the best available, without claiming that they
are conclusive. The second concerns the consequences of the
hypothetical analysis of causal generalisations. A statement
to the effect that 'If anything is an X it will also be a Y' does
not tell us whether anything ever will be an X -- and hence
cannot tell us whether anything will be a Y. A generalisation
such as 'All trades unionists vote for radical parties', if it is
really meant as a causal law - and we shouldn't forget that it
may not be, that it may be no more than a summary of the
behaviour of trades unionists at the present day - does not
tell us anything about voters for radical parties in, say, 1983.
Unless we have such singular statements as 'there will be at
least 750,000 trades unionists in 1983', we have no predic-
tion at all; in short, we need statements about initial condi-
tions if we are to utilise hypothetical generalisation for
positive predictions. Now, it is not a matter of logic whether
we can in fact produce either appropriately universal
generalisations or secured statements about initial conditions;
it is a matter of how the world is actually constructed that
determines whether such statements and such generalisations
can be established. Methodological claims about what a
201
developed science ought to aim at thus depend both upon
assumptions about the logical requirements of explanation
and upon reasoned guesses as to what the world is like. What
will not do - and what has tended to happen - is to project
onto the world the image of strict deductive argument and
pass that off as the methodological aspirations of social
science, just as it will not do to project the present weakness
of social science explanations back onto logic and claim that
they invalidate deductive reasoning. Two questions dominate
this issue. The first is whether the social sciences can produce
anything other than approximate laws and generalisations,
and produce genuinely universal laws with an adequate
spatia-temporal range of applicability. The second is whether
we can make the necessary singular predictions about initial
conditions, such as would enable us to draw from our
generalisations predictions of a positive kind. The two issues
are connected in that predictive success and failure feed on
themselves: if we possessed strictly universal, non-
probabilistic generalisations, then we should be able to
predict with accuracy the states of affairs which form the
causal antecedents of those states of affairs which are the
subject-matter of more distant prediction. And, equally, if we
cannot predict with exactitude what will happen in the near
future our guesses as to the farther future will become
rapidly no more than guesses.
Now, it has been argued by some writers that the supposed
isomorphism between explanation and prediction defended
above is mythical, since there are successful and developed
branches of the physical sciences where we can explain in
general what is going on, but cannot predict particular
occurrences. Professor Hanson argued this for the case of
quantum mechanics, (7) where we cannot predict single
quantum jumps, and it could be extended to genetics, where
we can tell after the event why a successful mutation survives
- in terms of the theory of natural selection - but we cannot
predict before the event why a particular mutant should
appear. Now, the obvious retort to the claim that here we
have explanation without the possibility of prediction is that
this rests on an ambiguity about what is explained. In neither
of these cases is there any claim that we can explain the
single event which we cannot predict; that is, we can explain
202
the mutation's survival, but we cannot explain its initial
appearance, and it is this, and this only, which we cannot
predict. Or we can explain the probability of cases of
quantum jumps, but we cannot explain why one jump occurs
- and it is this that we cannot predict. In other words, what
we cannot explain we cannot predict, and conversely. (8)
Here as elsewhere, there is nothing to be gained by quarrel-
ling over the application of the label 'explanation' to some
particular theory. But what can be said is this: where we have
the result - after careful and prolonged scientific investiga-
tion - that no determinate laws are discovered, and we also
have a general theory which explains why this should be so,
then methodologically it is a futile occupation to bemoan
their absence. In social science it is presently the case that we
are quite well equipped, but with approximate and not very
far-reaching generalisations about how people behave in given
situations. Thus we have rather a good idea of what
motivated voters in Britain during the 1950s, but the
explanation of why the Conservative Party remained so
consistently in power would be extremely hard to extra-
polate to the United States of the 1950s, or to Britain in the
1960s, let alone to more remote societies and times. (9) Such
generalisations thus offer us little in the way of backing for
detailed prediction, though they may be invaluable in
providing us with day to day help in assessing our situation.
The other great problem for the social sciences is establishing
before the event rather than after which causal antecedents
are the important ones. This is obvious enough, in the light of
the need for initial conditions in causal explanation. But
there is a less obvious point relevant here. We have argued so
far that explanations of human affairs rest, directly or
indirectly, on what people have reasons for believing and
intending under the situations they are in; and this is
ineluctably to introduce into the initial conditions of social
events the beliefs and feelings of the social actors about those
initial conditions. Reasons are only effective reasons in the
light of beliefs and attitudes; but beliefs and attitudes are also
subject to more or less conscious reappraisal. Whether or not
this is a vital difference in the logic of explanation of human
affairs is momentarily beside the point; what is certainly true is
that (in any situation other than one where there is complete
203
control over what people can believe) it is as a matter of fact
much easier to reconstruct from hindsight what a person or a
group must have believed and wanted than it is to predict this
in advance of their acting at all.
If the only evidence about the possibility of prediction
were culled from our experience of everyday explanation and
explanation in the social sciences, it is doubtful that anyone
would have thought that scocial scientists ought to aim at
establishing long-term predictions. The image which seems
for so long to have dominated the intellectual scene,
however, is that of astronomy with its predictive triumphs
dating back so far as the Babylonians. There has indeed been
a debate since antiquity couched almost in the same terms
that Plato and Aristotle gave it; the former, impressed with
astronomy, and believing that a uniform natural order must
operate on uniform principles throughout, put forward
astronomical theories about the cycles of change and decay
and growth in social life; {10) Aristotle, judicious, impressed
by the multiplicity of different natural phenomena, insisted
that we ought only to aim at the kind of exactness which the
particular subject-matter permitted, and that it was folly to
erect anything grandiose on the weak foundations of our
social knowledge. ( 11)
But the attractions of a predictively successful social
science are obvious enough. The belief that there is a
'pattern' in history is one of the most \\idespread of human
beliefs; Stone Age tribes have their myths, and contemporary
states their generally accepted accounts of their history
which are often as mythical. There is not a great leap from
believing that there has been a pattern in what has happened
in the past to believing that this should provide evidence
about what can be· expected to happen in the future. Of
course there has usually been a good deal of ambiguity about
whether the guide is to what will happen, or whether it is a
guide to what ought to happen; but this ambiguity is
grounded in our own doubts about how much of our future
is under our control, and is as common in sociological theory
as in earlier theological and mythological accounts of history.
So obvious is this kinship between the theological systems
evident in Judaism, in such works as St Augustine's 'City of
God', (12) or in Plato's account of the 'Golden Year', that
204
more than one writer has argued that an allegedly sociological
system ought to be analysed as in reality a theological system
because of the needs it fulfils in this way. Thus Professor
Tucker argues that Marx was a covertly reli-gious thinker, and
that the sociological mask worn by his work is largely
delusive. (13) But it is equally true that many of the founders
of the contemporary sociological tradition happily accepted
that what they were doing was, so far as its social-purpose
went, a similar undertaking to that of the great religious
systems of the past. Saint-Simon, for instance, proposed to
found a New Christianity on Newton's law of universal
gravitation, a cornerstone to replace the old Christian claim
that God is love; and Saint-Simon's (14) ambitions rubbed
off on his greatest disciple, Auguste Comte, who gave a good
deal more than merely the word 'sociology' to the subject.
Comte shared with many other nineteenth-century thinkers
the belief that the sociological and cosmological theories
associated with Christianity were played out, and that they
no longer gave people the sense of where they had come from
and where they were going to which all societies needed if
they were not to be overtaken by anarchy. Sociology, and
especially a sociological account of hist<;>ry, together with
predictions about the way society would go on developing,
was intended to fill the gap left by scepticism and secularisa-
tion. Even those nineteenth-century thinkers to whom
Comte's mature, and bizarre, attempts to reformulate
medieval Catholicism and its hold on social life held no appeal
at all, saw that he grasped a point of great importance: they
agreed that there was a need for a scientifically respectable
account of how modern society had come about, what its
problems were, how it was solving them or failing to solve
them, and what means were available for the improvement of
the future it faced. (15) De Tocqueville, :tvlarx, Durkheim and
Weber all faced up to this need in their different ways.
It is, however, necessary at this point to reiterate what we
have already said, that the aspiration to this kind of predic-
tive social science was not an aspiration which anyone could
have contracted from a consideration of its existing achieve-
ments. Rather, it was culled from the apparent need for the
kind of doctrines which traditionally religion had provided
and was now failing to provide, and from an assumption,
205
largely fed by the success of the natural sciences, that the
social universe was predictable in the same way as the rest of
the natural world. The less a thinker felt this homogeneity
between the social order and the remainder of nature, the less
likely he was to aspire to prediction in sociology. Comte, Mill
and Marx all emerge as more inclined in this direction than
were, say, Weber or Durkheim. The assumption which
dominates Mill's picture of the goals of social science is the
Newtonian assumption that the universe is a determinist
order; what this means is that it is in principle possible to
predict every state of the universe from a consideration of
any other state together with a full knowledge of the causal
laws operating .at that time. What is true of the universe in
gross is true in detail of any subsystem within the universe
which i~ sufficiently isolated to be studied on its own. From
a consideration of the system at any time, we ought to be
able to predict (or retrodict) its state at any other time.
Writers like Mill were explicit about the origins of their
assumptions, and references to 'celestial mechanics' and to
hopes of a 'mecanique morale' are frequent. {16) The socio-
logical implication is that since societies are also determinist
systems, a full knowledge of any society at a particular point,
together with a knowledge of the causal laws operating on it,
should allow us to predict its state at any other time. Of
course, everyone agreed that the actual computation of these
predictions was quite impossible. The aim was to gain
agreement on the principles involved.
However, it is apparent after a moment's thought that this
is a much less plausible programme than it appears at first
sight. In exploring the doubts we must have, we can answer
the question posed in Chapter 1 as to whether the kind of
determinism and indeterminism in social science is like that
in the natural sciences, and also enforce the lesson we have
already received about the need to distinguish between the
demands of logic and the possibilities allowed us by the
phenomena. The first problem we need to raise is the
ambiguity we earlier touched on, as to whether religious,
mythic or sbciological predictions tell us what will happen or
what ought to happen. The problem is this. Ordinarily we
have a practical motive for wishing to know what will happen
next; we are not motivated by idle curiosity about what will
206
happen to our society. Rather, we want to be able to act: we
want to ensure that favourable trends will continue, and that
unfavourable trends will be stopped, or where this is
impossible that we shall circumvent their ill-effects. But now
we face the problem we raised in Chapter 1 about the inter-
action of the prediction and the behaviour predicted. The
initial puzzle is that if the prediction is meant as a prediction
of what will happen no matter what we do, then it is no use
as a guide to action. We can only utter an unconditional or
categorical prediction - what Popper calls a 'prophecy' -
when we are sure that no action of ours will materially affect
the outcome. (17) Thus once the Wall Street crash of 1929
was well under way, we could have predicted that prices
would slump all the way down, because we knew that in a
free market for securities, a panic once it has begun cannot
be terminated by the deliberate actions of buyers and sellers
in that market. This is analogous to predicting of a man who
has fallen from the top of the Eiffel Tower that he will fall to
the bottom - once started, there is absolutely nothing he can
do to stop himself. But unlike the case of a man falling from
the Eiffel Tower, the Wall Street crash prediction is likely to
be unrepeatable. For men learn from their mistakes, and thus
come to modify their future behaviour. Thus once it emerges
that the predictability of the Wall Street crash depends on
the fact that a freely operating stock market of the 1929
variety does not allow for co-operative efforts to slow down
or avert disasters, the natural result is a modification of the
system, and hence a falsification of attempts to repeat the
success of the previous prediction; and this, of course, is a
major point of difference between the kind of events which
form what we term the Wall Street crash and those which
form the sequence of someone's falling from the Eiffel
Tower. It remains true that as a matter of logic, there is
predictability in the sense that zf the same circumstances and
antecedents appeared again, and if the same causal laws
operate, then the same effects will occur. But methodologi-
cally, there is no room for the pursuit of prediction in this
sense, since we know that as a matter of fact the same laws
will not operate in future and the same initial conditions will
not recur. This, then, is one of the ways in which long-run
predictions will run into trouble; and it must be noted that it
207
is not analogous to anything at all in the case of the natural
sciences. For in the example we have chosen, the reason why
the prediction itself alters the future circumstances depends
upon people coming to understand why that prediction
would have been successful; that is, the prediction alters
subsequent behaviour, not in virtue of an independent status
as a causal antecedent, but because people come to under-
stand the prediction, and it then affords them reasons for
behaving differently. This can only be the case where the
phenomena in question have theories about their own actions
and can sensibly be said to understand explanations of their
own behaviour; and the only such phenomena of which we
have any knowledge are human beings. The importance of
this point will emerge a little later when we discuss self-
validating and self-defeating predictions.
Since it seems that predictions offered as accounts of what
will happen no matter what are of no use as guides to action,
or else are used as guides to action at the cost of their status
as unconditional predictions, what of those conditional
predictions which are used to tell us what would happen if no
one intervened? It is plain that at an everyday level, we
employ such predictions incessantly and essentially - though
it should be noted that their scope is usually limited. (18)
Thus we warn each other that the house will fall down about
us unless we get the roof fixed, or that we will run down the
little old lady on the crossing unless we slow down at once;
and generally, economists, public health officials and a
thousand and one inspectors and advisers tell families,
governments and private persons what causal sequences are in
train, precisely so that they will be able to intervene in them.
More and more detailed knowledge of such causal sequences
makes us more and more able to intervene successfully in
them, and thus brings events increasingly under our control.
But it makes a considerable hole in the ambition to predict
changes far into the future, since the causal sequences laid
out in such 'predictions' tend to be wide open to human
frustration and modification. If what we learn is thus almost
always what is happening, and what will happen if no one
intervenes, we obviously learn rather little about what will
happen, interventions and all. This conclusion, though a blow
to a determinist picture of social life, is in no way destructive
208
of our account of the need in explanation for the production
of such causal sequences; nothing in that account required
that such sequences should be shown to hold far into the
future, nor that they should be immune to future interven-
tion by human beings. This intervention is no matter for
logical disquiet.
It is, in principle, possible to stick to one's determinist
guns, and argue that long-range prediction is not in principle
impossible, even though it may be very difficult to achieve,
for all that is required is that we should be able to predict the
interventions as well as the initial sequences, and to assess the
effects of such interventions. Logically, this is obviously the
correct response, even though it raises the problems we came
across in Chapter 5 about giving a determinist analysis of
choice. For if we are to make such predictions, they must be
predictions of what will happen no matter what, only one of
the events which will happen no matter what will be our own
interventions. But this analysis of intervention is most
disturbing, since it is so at odds with precisely what is usually
thought to distinguish interventions, namely that they are a
matter of choice. (19} In what sense can intervention be a
matter of choice on this analysis? If what a prediction 'no
matter what' achieves is to rule out intervention to frustrate
the course of events predicted, we seem to plunge into very
deep water if we rule out our intervention in our own inter-
ventions. Such a move could only be made by a very
committed fatalist who was prepared to abandon the whole
concept of choice as a muddle. And such a fatalist would
plainly not share the practical aims which I have suggested as
the common motive behind an attempt to offer such predic-
tions. It is thus apparent that both as a practical matter and
an intellectually plausible goal, the attempt to rival
astronomy with the production of a predictive social science
is of dubious value.
Of course, none of this rules out predictions at short range,
and it should be said at once that almost all contemporary
social science does restrict itself precisely to this kind of
prediction - and as we shall later see, to the establishment of
trends of recognisedly limited predictive scope. But in
connection with such short-range predictions arises one of
the interesting differences between the social and the natural
209
sciences. It is one of the features of social life that some
persons are in a position of so to speak intellectual authority,
in that their word on the state of affairs obtaining or about
to obtain tends to be accepted as the truth; their say-so gives
people a good reason for believing that what they say is true.
Now, an effect of this which has been noticed by many
writers, and christened 'the self-fulfilling prophecy' by
Professor Merton, {20) is that the assertion by such
authorities that something will happen may make it happen.
The converse case of the self-defeating or suicidal prophecy
amounts to the case discussed above, where the utterance of
the prediction gives people a strong motive for making sure
that it comes false. The kind of example to which the notion
of the self-fulfilling prophecy appeals is the following: a man
who is regarded as a reputable financial expert may say that a
share will rise in price, and his word that this will happen is
enough to set in train that rush of buyers which will actually
bring about the rise in price which he has forecast. (21)
Again, it is a generally recognised duty of members of a
government to lie about the likelihood of devaluation, when
there are rumours of devaluation in the air; the reason is that
the statement of an official that devaluation was to take
place would start such a stampede out of the currency in
question as to bring about an inevitable devaluation. Now, it
is important to notice that in these cases, the way in which
the statement of the prediction would bring about the events
predicted is very different from the case raised in Chapter 1,
where a loud shout that an avalanche is coming is enough to
actually bring on the avalanche. The difference is that in the
case of human agents, the agents themselves have to both
understand what the prediction means and to believe it
before it can have any effect on their actions. It is only
because they believe what is said that they can use it as
grounds for the decisions which add up to the prediction's
being fulfilled. Ttte prediction, in Popper's terms, gives the
situation a certain logic to human agents. But in the case
where I simply shout loudly enough to set off an avalanche,
it is only the noise of my uttering the prediction that is at
issue. What was predicted is neither here nor there; it only
happens to be the case that the noise in question was the
noise of my uttering a prediction; any other noise of equal
210
loudness would have been just as causally effective. Equally,
it follows that the prediction would not have had any effect
on the avalanche, had it been only written or had it been
whispered; but in the case where human agents are involved,
it is plain that any mode of diffusing the prediction would be
equally effective as a causal agency, so long as the one
condition is fulfilled that people understand what is said and
believe it to be true. For in the case of prediction in human
affairs, it is the meaning of the prediction that matters and
not its status as a physical occurrence; (22) and it does not
just happen that the prediction is causally effective, in the
way it just happens that a loud noise will start an avalanche,
rather it is only in the light of what the prediction means that
it is logically possible for it to give someone a reason for
behaving one way rather than another. As we saw in Chapter
6, what we are elaborating here is in large part a conceptual
connection.
We have said enough to indicate the logical problems
associated with the idea that determinism reigns in social
matters and that long-term prediction is the goal of social
science. But before leaving the matter, I .should like to
illustrate very briefly the practical consequence of these
difficulties. The Marxist socialists of the German Social-
Democratic party - the S.P.D. -before the First World War
had grave intellectual, logical, ideological and policy troubles
as the result of their ambivalence about the proper interpreta-
tion of Marx's predictions of revolutionary historical change.
In principle, the S.P.D. was committed to bringing about the
revolutionary transformation of capitalist Germany into a
socialist society; but the question that baffled many of the
party's leaders was that of their role in this change. If Marx
had been right in saying that the changes were inevitably on
their way, it seemed to many of them that their role could
not be to promote violent upheavals but rather to wait for
the coming of socialism in the fullness of time, and to
prepare themselves to be socialists in the new socialist order.
Plainly, no one leading a mass working-class party like the
S.P.D. was going to propose a policy of total inactivity as the
only logical consequence of Marxian determinism; none-
theless, a book like Professor Gay's 'The Dilemma of
Democratic Socialism' (23) shows just how much the leaders
211
of the party felt themselves in a cleft stick. Were they to try
to stir up a working class which, on all the available evidence,
did not want a violent revolution, but was happy to make
steady progress under the Bismarckian welfare state? Or were
they to press through parliament and the organisations of the
working class for the limited reforms of the status quo which
the working class did want, in the hope that these would
somehow cumulatively become the revolutionary transforma-
tion predicted by Marx and Engels? Of course, the dilemma
of policy is that faced by all socialist parties in industrialised
countries, and there is no easy solution of it. But that is not
the point. The point is rather that the sociological beliefs of
the S.P.D. made the resolution of the dilemma impossible,
since they seemed to rule out a policy which could fulfil the
incompatible requirements of being revolutionary enough -
i.e. activist enough - to be plausible as a policy, and yet
fatalist enough - i.e. inactivist enough - to meet the logical
requirements of a determinist Marxism. It can, of course, be
said that this logical hiatus is not a sociologically adequate
explanation of the S.P.D.'s failure, since plenty of people
have been moved to action precisely by believing such
logically incompatible things as that the victory of their cause
was quite inevitable, and also that their fullest efforts were
essential to its triumph. This is (up to a point) true, but it is a
truth of less importance once a party or a group of any sort is
committed to a policy which supposedly relies not on
messianic faith but on a scientific assessment of the
possibilities of social and political life. For in such a situa-
tion, and this was the S.P.D. 's situation, intelligent, secular
politicians will find themselves in a dilemma over policy. And
no one who reflects on the contributory role of the S.P.D.'s
weaknesses in allowing the collapse of the Weimar Republic
and the subsequent accession of Nazism to power is likely to
think its policy dilemmas unimportant.
Thus far we have been sceptical about the goal of long-
term prediction in social science. Yet of course there are
examples of highly successful short-run predictions -
predicting election results from pre-election polls, (24)
predicting crime rates for short periods ahead, or birth rates
and the like. A certain amount of economic forecasting and
planning runs along similar lines, though, logically, it tends to
212
be a mixture of reported intentions, extrapolation of present
trends, and statements of an exhortatory kind as well. But
what we ought to notice about such short-run predictions is
that in a great many cases they are not susceptible of much in
the way of causal explanation, and rely not on causal laws-
at least in our present state of understanding - but on the
mere extrapolation of trends. Once we have made clear this
distinction between trends and laws we can see whether there
is any substance in Popper's claim that the addiction of many
philosophers, historians and social scientists to the goal of
large-scale prediction rests on confusing laws and trends. (25)
The existence of unexplained but successful predictions is
common knowledge. We have mentioned already the
nineteenth-century discovery of the remarkably steady
incidence of crime in France, made by two separate
observers. The discovery was thought at first to be the
beginnings of a truly scientific criminology; although, no
doubt, individual criminals acted for all sorts of reasons,
nonetheless, the results of these all but random events could
be forecast with considerable accuracy. But the delusiveness
of these hopes was soon realised, for it was seen that such
uniformities in how many people committed crimes brought
one no nearer discovering why people committed crimes, and
thus no nearer knowing the causes of crime; all one had
found out about was the rate of incidence of the effects.
Such attempts as Lombroso's to explain criminal behaviour
in terms of genetic defect and racial throwbacks were no
doubt mistaken about the facts, but they were at any rate
along the right logical lines in looking for the causal
generalisations which would analyse the trends thrown up by
Quetelet and Guerry as the outcome of the causal factors
involved, operating in the circumstances of the nineteenth
century. What criminologists need to know is what motivates
criminal behaviour, what sort of upbringing makes a person
vulnerable to temptation and so on. With this information to
hand, they would he in a position to explain both the trends
that existed at any particular time and changes in them,
because they could explain both the causation of individual
criminal actions and that of the gross statistical regularities
resulting from these particular acts. (26) It is only by being
able to understand the causal processes that underlie trends
213
that we are in a position to know how safely we can extra-
polate a trend into the future. For a trend is not a statement
of a lawlike kind at all; it is logically on a level with singular
statements, and is indeed simply equivalent to a summary of
singular statements: to say, for example, that the trend in
petty theft is steadily upwards is only to say that over the
period in question more crimes of petty theft were
committed in period tn ... tn + 1 than in the period
t n- 1 •.• tn. To plan a long way ahead on the basis of such a
trend is plainly foolish in the absence of any understanding
of the underlying causes. Economists and businessmen alike
realise how very unwise it is to estimate future income on
nothing more substantial than an unanalysed trend; and
where they refer to trends in economic life, it is almost
always with a suggestion that they wish to be committed for
no great length of time ahead. In recent years the trends in
population growth have offered some spectacular examples
of the dangers of extrapolation, partly because the nature of
birth rates is such that relatively small changes in the current
birth rate will extrapolate to remarkable changes in future
population over the long run, in just the same way as small
changes in compound interest rates will make spectacular
differences to one's savings over a long enough period. But it
is notorious that birth rates change suddenly, and in the
present state of our ignorance inexplicably. In fact when the
ceremony to mark the birth of the 200 millionth American
was held recently, it was estimated in various quarters that
the true figure was some two million less; the trend on which
the planners of the ceremony had relied, and on the basis of
which the computer counting the babies to the 200 millionth
American had been programmed, had reversed itself some
time before the ceremony. (27) At a more domestic level,
everyone who has been tempted to stake his earnings on a
horse knows that there is a great difference between relying
on a horse's winning streak - which is betting on a trend -
and knowing about its form, breeding, condition and so on -
which is betting on a set of causal sequences. If, for example,
he could discover that the horse was light on its feet and thus
particularly good in wet going, he would hesitate to risk his
all if the weather became warm and dry. Similarly with birth
rates, if we knew that the desire to have more children was a
214
response to increased well-being, rather than a response to
absolute levels of well-being, we should not expect a high
birth rate to persist either into a slump or into a long period
of settled prosperity. In other words, we can rely on trends
for predictive purposes only where we can explain how the
trend is caused, and thus estimate its ·reliability. And this
again explains why it is that we can safely rely on
unexplained trends only over rather short periods - it is only
over short periods that it is at all safe to assume that the
causes of which we are ignorant have not altered in any
significant way.
But are we to believe that this not very problematic
distinction between trends and laws was overlooked by those
who are rightly regarded as the founders of the modern social
sciences? There is no place here for a review of the enormous
nineteenth-century output of work on the trends then visible
in the fields of economic, political and social change; and
such a survey would in any case be superfluous, since
sociology today is quite sufficiently concerned with its
origins in the responses of these theorists to the rapid social
changes which took place before their own eyes. What,
however, we can simply enough do here is explain what the
argument hangs on. If it was possible to see in the work of
Marx, Mill, Comte, Durkheim or Webet: an uncritical projec-
tion into the far future of the changes visible in 1840, or
1860, or 1880, then there might be grounds for thinking that
such confusion had taken place. For it might then be thought
that they had failed to recognise the difference between
saying that such and such changes have been taking place,
and saying that whenever such and such a change occurs it
has such and such consequences. For only this latter causal
law would allow any kind of prediction - given that our
earlier requirements as to the law's universality and the
prediction of the initial conditions could be met. We may
agree that these thinkers get into difficulties of one kind and
another, but see these difficulties as the result of their doubts
about what causes were really operating at the time they
wrote, or how reliable the future operation of these causes
was, and how profitable would be attempts to control their
operation. For if they were well enough able to make the
distinction between laws and trends, they were equally able
215
to make the distinction between modifiable and unmodifi-
able causal sequences - and thus between the trends we can
readily reverse and those which we cannot. It is obvious that
in everyday life we use these distinctions quite unself-
consciously. For example, we may with many contemporary
sociologists see that our lives are becoming increasingly
suburban, and that the distinctions formerly existing between
urban and rural life are melting equally into suburbanism: this
is to talk of a trend; it is a trend which can be partly
explained in terms of our desire for fresh air, for living space
and ease of movement for our children and so on; thus
explained, we know that it is a trend which could in principle
be reversed if we were able to forgo these desires, but we see
that we are not likely to do so, and thus that the suburban
trend is likely to go on. In this there is nothing very logically
complex.
And in essence, such a commonsense account is exactly
what Mill for one offers in his essay on 'Civilisation' (28) -
and the same defence can be made of the writings of Marx
and Comte, though with allowances for the latter's curious
beliefs about which causes were at work; while writers such
as Weber and Durkheim were methodologically intensely
cautious about prognosis. When Mill accounts for the
_tendency of masses to predominate over individuals and for
uniformity of manners to permeate society, both geographi-
cally and through the class structure, he explicity claims that
he is describing a trend. For in analysing the causes of this
trend he inquires what we should have to do to reverse it or
at any rate modify it. Since the causes seem to lie in the
features of life which have also caused the industrial revolu-
tion and its attendant changes, Mill offers little hope for a
substantial reversal of the trend; but this is not because it is a
universal causal law, which it makes no sense to try to alter,
but simply because the costs of trying to alter a trend so
bound up with the increasing prosperity of the age would be
immensely high, and it would thus be foolish to try to reverse
the trend. It is not that no matter what, the processes of
industrialisation and the like must continue, but that their
reversal would be intolerably expensive; but Mill insists as
firmly as he can that while major reversals may be out of the
question, it is quite possible to modify the side-effects of the
216
trend, and he encourages us to do this.
Much the same analysis can be given of the seemingly more
awkward case of Marx's insistence on the inevitability of the
end of capitalism. (29) What Marx shows is simply that both
intervention and non-intervention will equally bring to an
end nineteenth-century capitalism of a pure and unregulated
kind. In some ways, Marx's case is almost too much a matter
of common sense. For often it boils down to saying that if
capitalism is allowed to continue under no government
surveillance, then increasingly violent booms and slumps will
equally continue unchecked, for reasons which any classical
economist would be forced to agree with. If this process goes
on unchecked, then chaos and revolution will follow. But if
there is to be intervention on a scale commensurate with the
problem, this will require such a degree of government
control and regulation as to amount in its turn to the revolu-
tionary overthrow of capitalism from a different direction.
Thus capitalism was caught in a cleft stick, and in that sense
its end was inevitable - though its endings might be very
different. It is of course quite likely that Marx was wrong
about the processes at work, and that he oversimplified the
range of alternatives open in the latter part of the nineteenth
century; but this is to say that he relied on causal generalisa-
tions that turned out eventually to be false; and this is a
totally different charge from saying that he mistook the
logical framework of a correct explanation. It would be no
comfort to a confirmed Marxist to have Marx saved from
charges of logical confusion only to have him condemned on
charges of factual error; but this is immaterial here, for we
are not concerned with the latter charges at all. All we are
concerned to ask is whether it is those charges that are
appropriate rather than the charges of logical error; and on
the face of it, the logic of his account is impeccable. As we
have said all along, if the goal of prediction fails, it does so
because the facts of social life defeat it; this would be enough
to account for any failures of which Marx may be accused;
the charge of philosophical confusion here is both
implausible and beside the point. The desire to predict the
future might well have led Marx, as it has led many other
writers, to overestimate the importance of the facts which he
particularly had concentrated on, to the neglect of others
217
more influential than he believed - but this is to do a
possible job less than perfectly, not to set out to do an
impossible job. In view of the immense difficulties under
which sociologists have always laboured, it ought to be
plainly said that were they at all times totally committed to
observing the distinction between the extrapolation of trends
and the establishment of causal laws, they would inevitably
make plenty of errors both in the one task and in the other.

NOTES

1. H. D. Lasswell and D. Lerner (eds}, 'The Policy


Sciences' (Stanford University Press, 1951).
2. Popper, 'Poverty', pp. 105-30.
3. Hempel, in 'Readings in Philosophical Analysis', p.
465.
4. Strawson, 'Logical Theory', pp. 82-90.
5. Nagel, 'Structure of Science', pp. 450-9.
6. Hempel, in 'Readings in Philosophical Analysis', p.
462.
7. N. Hanson, 'On the Symmetry between Explanation
and Prediction', 'Phil. Rev.' (1959).
8. Brown, 'Explanation in Social Science', pp. 158-60.
9. D. E. Butler and D. Stokes, 'Political Change in Britain'
(Macmillan, 1969).
10. Plato, 'Republic' p. 263.
11. Aristotle, 'Nicomachaean Ethics', (Oxford University
Press) sec. 3.
12. St Augustine, 'City of God'.
13. R. C. Tucker, 'Philosophy and Myth in Karl Marx'
(Cambridge University Press; 1961) pp. 21-7.
14. Saint-Simon, 'Selected Writings', ed. F. Markham
(Blackwell, Oxford, 1952} p. 18.
15.J. S. Mill, 'AugusteComte and Positivism' (University
of Michigan Press, 1961).
16. Mill, 'Logic', bk vi, ch. ix.
218

You might also like