Corvino FactOpinionDistinction

Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 5

THE FACT/OPINION DISTINCTION

By John Corvino
04 March 2015 | The Philosophers Magazine
https://philosophersmag.com/essays/26-the-fact-opinion-distinction

John Corvino argues that the claim "That's just your opinion" is pernicious and should be
consigned to the flames.
 
When debating ethics and other controversial topics, one frequently hears the claim “That’s just
your opinion.” It is a pernicious claim, devoid of clear meaning, and it should be consigned to
the flames – or so I shall argue here.

In calling something an opinion, one presumably wants to contrast it with something that
is not an opinion, and the obvious candidate for the contrast class is “fact”. Philosophers might
be tempted to draw this contrast by identifying facts as states of affairs – occurrences that are
there in the world regardless of what anyone may think about them – and identifying opinions as
beliefs (or some other mental state) about states of affairs. According to this approach, we can
separate facts from opinions by using what Perry Weddle has called the “Whose?” test: It always
makes sense to ask “Whose opinion is it?” but never “Whose fact is it?”

But this way of drawing the contrast merely pushes the problem back further. For among the
beliefs that people have about the world, there are some that people tend to put in the “fact”
column and some that they tend to put in the “opinion” column. That is, they
contrast factual beliefs from opinions (opinion beliefs), and it is quite appropriate to ask “Whose
belief?” in either case. The same goes for expressions of belief: We can talk about statements of
fact vs.  statements of opinion, or factual claims vs. opinion claims, and so forth, and all of
these are in the mouths of subjects.

Suppose, then, we narrow our inquiry to statements, so that when we ask, “What is the difference
between facts and opinions?” what we’re really asking is “What is the difference
between statements of fact and statements of opinion?”

This seems like it should be an easy question, but it actually tends to stump most people on the
street. Mind you, they have no trouble in offering examples of either, or in categorising others’
examples. So for instance, given

(1a) There is beer in my refrigerator. (1b) Wine tastes better than beer.
(2a) The earth revolves around the sun. (2b) The earth was created by an omnipotent God.
(3a) Thousands were killed in Darfur. (3b) Genocide is wrong.
(4a) The current US president is a Democrat.(4b) A Democrat will win the presidency in 2016.

they’ll say that the A statements are facts and the B statements are opinions. When asked to
explain the principle of distinction between the two, however – the rule that tells us how to
assign statements to one category or the other – they often get tongue-tied.
Some have tried to explain the distinction to me by arguing that facts are true. This answer is not
at all helpful, since opinions are typically put forth as true, and some factual claims turn out to be
false. For example, most people would say that it’s true  that genocide is wrong, and there may
or may not be beer in my refrigerator. The fact/opinion distinction varies independently of the
true/false distinction.

Others say that factual statements are “concrete” rather than “abstract”, but that answer would
render all mathematical statements non-factual, since mathematics involves abstract concepts
(e.g. numbers). Neither does it help, at least at first glance, to say that facts are “objective”
(rather than “subjective”), since at least some statements in the “opinion” column involve matters
that would be true (or false) regardless of what any particular subject believes. For example,
whether or not God created the earth is an objective matter, albeit a controversial and difficult-to-
prove one. If it happened, it happened whether anyone believes it or not. Ditto if it didn’t happen.
(I’ll say more about the subjective/objective distinction later on.)

Perhaps the last example suggests a better answer: the difference between facts and opinions is
that factual statements are uncontroversial. But this answer doesn’t seem right either, since it
would make it audience-relative whether something is a fact: for example, “the earth revolves
around the sun” would be a fact for modern Europeans but not for medieval ones; “God created
the earth” would be a fact for believers but not for sceptics; “The earth is flat” would be a fact for
Flat-Earthers but not for the rest of us. How useful would the fact/opinion distinction be if any
statement could count as either one, depending on who hears it?

If everyday observers are confused about the distinction, “experts” fare little better. Curious as to
the standard explanation, I Googled “facts vs. opinions”. (This is not how to conduct serious
philosophical research, but it can be a useful way of gauging common thoughts on a subject.)
Here’s the first result I received, from a “Critical Thinking Across the Curriculum Project”
website:

“Fact: statement of actuality or occurrence. A fact is based on direct evidence, actual experience,
or observation.

“Opinion: statement of belief or feeling. It shows one’s feelings about a subject. Solid opinions,
while based on facts, are someone’s views on a subject and not facts themselves.”

This way of drawing the distinction makes “The earth revolves around the sun” an opinion – or
at least, not a fact – since no one directly observes it happening (not even astronauts!). It also
jumbles together occurrences (what we earlier called “states of affairs”), statements about
occurrences, and the evidence for those statements.

Perhaps more confusing is its labelling opinions as “statement(s) of belief.” As we’ve been using
the terms, all  statements express beliefs, and our task is to determine which of them express
factual beliefs and which express opinions.

So I looked further. Here are the second and third results from my quick internet search, from an
“Education Oasis” and “Enchanted Learning” website, respectively:
“A fact is a statement that can be proven true.”

“An opinion expresses someone’s belief, feeling, view, idea, or judgment about something or
someone.”

and

“Facts are statements that can be shown to be true or can be proved, or something that really
happened. You can look up facts in an encyclopedia or other reference, or see them for yourself.
For example, it is a fact that broccoli is good for you (you can look this up in books about
healthy diets).

“Opinions express how a person feels about something – opinions do not have to be based upon
logical reasoning. For example, it is an opinion that broccoli tastes good (or bad).”
Both of these connect fact with provability. But in common parlance, “provability” seems
audience-relative as well: While one person might find Anselm’s ontological argument to be a
sufficient proof for God’s existence (thus rendering “God exists” a fact for that person); others
may not.

The Education Oasis site announces that “An opinion expresses someone’s belief ... about
something.” So if I believe that there’s beer in my refrigerator, is that just an opinion? The
Enchanted Learning site muddies the waters even further by claiming that you can look up facts
in an encyclopaedia (always? but then were there no facts before books?), and by including an
evaluative notion (“good for you”) among examples of facts.

If this is “Critical Thinking”, I’d hate to see what Sloppy Thinking looks like.

Let me offer a conjecture: the fact/opinion distinction is ambiguous, and in trying to explain it,
people typically conflate it with other distinctions in the neighbourhood.

Let’s consider three of those other distinctions. Take, first, the familiar philosophical distinction
between belief and reality. In common understanding, there’s a world (reality), and then there
are our representations of that world (beliefs: sometimes true, sometimes not). I might believe
that there’s beer in the refrigerator, whether or not there’s any there. I might believe that God
created the earth, whether or not God did – indeed, whether or not God exists at all. Generally,
we strive to make our beliefs as accurate as possible in representing reality, but that doesn’t
remove the gap (some would say “gulf”) between the two.

The problem, obviously, is that attempts to bridge that gap always proceed via our own fallible
cognitive capacities. Beliefs about reality are still beliefs, and some of them, despite our best
efforts, turn out to be false. That’s true whether we’re talking about beliefs that usually show up
in the “fact” column (“There’s beer in the refrigerator”) or in the “opinion” column (“God
created the earth”). In other words, both facts and opinions can be either successful or
unsuccessful in representing reality, and thus the fact/opinion distinction is not the same as the
belief/reality distinction.
Second, consider the subjective/objective distinction. Something is subjective insofar as it is
mind-dependent, objective insofar as it is mind-independent. Given this definition, all beliefs
(qua beliefs) are subjective, because beliefs depend on minds. And since we’ve been treating
both facts and opinions as statements of belief, facts and opinions are similarly subjective: In
other words, we can always ask “Whose belief?” or “Whose statement?”

Of course, there are different kinds of beliefs and statements. Some are about objective matters,
such as whether there is beer in the refrigerator. Others are about subjective matters, such as
whether one would enjoy a Guinness more than a Corona. Perhaps the fact/opinion distinction
tracks the distinction between statements with objective content (facts?) and those with
subjective content (opinions?). But if so, we would need to revise what usually gets put in each
column. In particular, the statement that “God created the earth” will need to move over to the
“fact” column, since whether God created the earth is an objective matter – it happened (or not)
independently of whether we believe it happened. The same is true for “God exists” – not an
opinion, on this schema, but a factual claim (maybe true, maybe false).

It is also by no means obvious that “Genocide is wrong” should remain in the “opinion” column.
While some philosophers hold that moral beliefs are subjective, many do not. Moreover, there is
a strong commonsense intuition that genocide would be wrong whether anyone believes it’s
wrong, suggesting that the claim is objective, not subjective. So while the subjective/objective
distinction might be useful in explaining the fact/opinion distinction, adopting this approach
would require us to revise our common thinking about facts and opinions. That’s not necessarily
a bad thing, since – as we have seen – our common thinking about facts and opinions appears
rather confused.

Finally, consider the descriptive/normative distinction. Descriptive statements describe or


represent the world; normative statements evaluate it. For example: the statement that thousands
were killed in Darfur is descriptive; the statement that such killing was wrong is normative.

The descriptive/normative distinction is sometimes called the fact/value distinction, which might
lead it to be confused with the fact/opinion distinction. But it’s controversial whether all
normative claims are matters of opinion. Moreover, many of the standard “opinion” examples
are not normative: consider “God exists” or “A Democrat will win the presidency in 2016”. If
the fact/opinion distinction were identical to the fact/value distinction, then once again we would
need to revise our common thinking about facts and opinions.

Having teased apart these various distinctions, and looking back over the several attempts to
explain the difference between fact and opinion, we might propose the following definitions:

o A statement of fact is one that has objective content and is well-supported by the available
evidence.

o A statement of opinion is one whose content is either subjective or else not well supported by
the available evidence.
These definitions have several advantages. First, they capture some of the concerns that lead
people to insist on the fact/opinion distinction in the first place – in particular, the concern that
claims not be accepted without good evidence. Second, they explain why some objective matters
– in particular, controversial matters such God’s existence or predictions about the future – get
placed in the category of opinion, despite their objective content. And third, they avoid the
sloppiness of some of the earlier proposals. That said, they are still somewhat revisionist: They
do not fully capture everyday usage (since everyday usage is messy and confused), but instead
serve to refine that usage.

Why worry about the fact/opinion distinction? One reason is that precise thinking is valuable for
its own sake. But there’s another, more pragmatic reason. Despite its unclear meaning, the claim
“That’s just your opinion” has a clear use: It is a conversation-stopper. It’s a way of diminishing
a claim, reducing it to a mere matter of taste which lies beyond dispute. (De gustibus non est
disputandum: there’s no disputing taste.)

Indeed, the “opinion” label is used not only to belittle others’ stances, but also to deflate one’s
own. In recognising that a personal belief differs sharply from that of other individuals and
cultures, one may conclude, “I guess that’s just my  opinion – no better than anyone else’s.” This
conclusion may stem from an admirable humility. On the other hand, it can have pernicious
effects: it leads to a kind of wishy-washiness, wherein one refrains from standing up for one’s
convictions for fear of imposing “mere opinions”. Such reticence conflicts with common sense:
surely some opinions are more thoughtful, more informed, more coherent, and
more important than others.

This diminishment is especially troubling in moral debates. Moral debates are practical –


they’re debates about what to do – and they concern our values: things that matter to us. Either
we send troops to Syria or we don’t. Either we allow same-sex couples to marry or we don’t.
Either we lie to our parents about what happened to the car or we don’t. Categorising these issues
as “matters of opinion” doesn’t make them any less urgent or vital.

I therefore propose that we abandon the ambiguous fact/opinion distinction, and especially the
dismissive retort “That’s just your opinion.” We should focus instead on whether people can
offer good reasons for the claims they make – reasons that might compel us to share their views.
That’s my opinion, anyway. If you think yours is better, don’t merely say so: Say why.

John Corvino is Chair of the Philosophy Department at Wayne State University, the author
of  What's Wrong With Homosexuality?, and the co-author (with Maggie Gallagher)
or  Debating Same-Sex Marriage. Read more at  www.johncorvino.com.
 

You might also like