Ecological Economics-Principles and Applications-7
Ecological Economics-Principles and Applications-7
nature’s services are a huge infrastructure to the economy, and we are fail-
ing to maintain that infrastructure.
Why do our national accountants fail to subtract natural capital con-
sumption in calculating income? Neoclassical economics does not count
natural capital consumption as a cost because in its preanalytic vision of
the world, nature is not scarce. The reason natural funds and resource
flows are absent from the usual neoclassical production function is also
the reason there is no deduction for natural capital consumption in na-
tional income accounting.
GNP as Cost
Years ago, Kenneth Boulding suggested that GNP be relabeled GNC, for
gross national cost. While Boulding’s plea may have been tongue-in-
cheek, it bears close examination. GNP is a measure of the final goods and
services a society produces multiplied by the price at which they sell on
the market. But demand for the most important resources such as food,
energy, and life-saving medicines is inelastic. As you’ll recall from Chap-
ter 9, this means that large changes in price have little impact on how
much people want to consume, and conversely, that a small change in
quantity will lead to a large change in price. Imagine that one year the
food and oil industries decided to work less and reduced output by 20%
over previous years. Because people would not want to reduce their con-
sumption of food and energy, they would bid up the prices for these com-
modities dramatically. In fact, something like this really did happen, in
2008, when a small drop in grain supplies relative to annual consumption
led to a 200% increase in prices, and a drop in the rate of increase in oil
production led to a similar increase in oil prices. If we multiplied 80% of
2007’s output by 300% of 2007’s price, GNP would show a 140% increase
in economic activity in these sectors instead of a 20% decrease. Real GNP
would be lower, due to inflation, but the share of these commodities in
GNP would nonetheless soar.
Even when GNP reflects economic activity, it may not reflect well-
being. For example, compared to the other developed countries, the
United States ranks last on a wide variety of health care measures, rang-
ing from infant mortality to life expectancy. It also has by far the highest
percentage of uninsured individuals. By such measures, the U.S. health
care system provides fewer benefits than the systems in other developed
nations. However, in 2008 the United States spent 50% more per capita
on health care than any other nation,12 and these expenditures were ris-
ment/16/0,3343,en_2649_34631_2085200_1_1_1_1,00.html.
Chapter 14 Macroeconomic Concepts: GNP and Welfare • 273
ing rapidly. Aside from those who reap income from health care, no one
claims this is a good thing. Yet if we measure well-being by the market
value of health care goods and services, the United States has by far the
best health care system in the world.
The fact is that one person’s income is another person’s expenditure, so
GNP is also an explicit measure of costs. As long as costs and benefits are
closely correlated, this does not matter, but we can’t take such a correla-
tion for granted. Striving to maximize expenditures on health care, food,
energy, or anything else would obviously be crazy.
What should be done about GNP? One approach would be to disag-
gregate GNP into two separate accounts: a national benefits account and
a national costs account (we'll explore the challenges to this below). As the
scale of the economy grows, both benefits and costs will increase. We
could compare those benefit and cost increases at the margin to find the
optimal scale (see Figure 14.2).13 It makes absolutely no sense to add
them together.
Another option is to move beyond consumption-based measures of
well-being altogether, as we discuss below. If the aim of economic activity
is to maximize human well-being, then health, nutrition, literacy, family,
friends, social networks, and so on are probably the most important indi-
cators, perhaps best measured by overall levels of happiness and satisfac-
tion with life (see Box 14.1).
Nonetheless, absent more rational measures of well-being, we can’t
help feeling a certain nostalgia for the good old days when newscasters re-
galed us with quarterly changes in the GNP. Now we are subjected to
hammer-banging, gong-clanging reports of hourly changes in the Dow
Jones and Nasdaq stock price indices—numbers that are an order of mag-
nitude further removed from either welfare or income than GNP is. For
example, in 2008, global stock markets lost trillions of dollars in value
with virtually no change in real productive assets. This is because stock
market values are forward-looking, based on expectations of future earn-
ings (even on speculators’ estimates of the expectations of others). By con-
trast, GNP is backward-looking, a historical record of what has already
happened. Since the past is better known than the future, GNP is inher-
ently a more trustworthy number than stock market values.
12For an effort in this direction for Australia, see P. A. Lawn, Toward Sustainable Development:
In the late 1980s, the country of Bhutan declared that it would strive
to increase Gross National Happiness (GNH) rather than GNP, in an ap-
proach that “stresses not material rewards, but individual development,
sanctity of life, compassion for others, respect for nature, social har-
mony and the importance of compromise.”a Rather than attempting to
measure happiness itself, Bhutan seeks to measure and improve the fac-
tors that contribute to happiness. The first global study on GNH included
multicriteria measures of economic, environmental, physical, mental, so-
cial, workplace, and political wellness.b While initially seen as a
quixotic goal, GNH is much less of a departure from economists’ histori-
cal conceptions of utility than is GNP, and the idea has taken off, along
with the study of happiness. A related measure is the Happy Planet
Index, which divides a country’s happy life years (life expectancy ad-
justed by subjective well-being) by its ecological footprint as an estimate
of ecological economic efficiency or sustainable happiness. By this
measure, Costa Rica is the world leader in sustainable development.c
Online: http://www.iim-edu.org/polls/GrossNationalHappinessSurvey.htm.
chttp://www.happyplanetindex.org.
14W. Hordhaus and J. Tobin, “Is Growth Obsolete?” In Economic Growth, National Bureau of
forgot about MEW, and concentrated again on GNP. Although GNP was
not designed as a measure of welfare, it was, and still is, thought to be
sufficiently well correlated with welfare to serve as a practical guide for
policy.
Some 20 years later, Daly and Cobb revisited the issue and began to de-
velop an Index of Sustainable Economic Welfare (ISEW) with a review of
the Nordhaus and Tobin MEW. They discovered that if one takes only the
latter half of the Nordhaus-Tobin time series (i.e., the 18 years from 1947
to 1965), the positive correlation between GNP and MEW falls dramati-
cally. In this most recent half of the total period—surely the more relevant
half for projections into the future—a six-unit increase in GNP yielded on
average only a one-unit increase in MEW. This suggests that GNP growth
at this stage in U.S. history may be quite an inefficient way of improving
economic welfare—certainly less efficient than in the past.
The ISEW was then developed to replace MEW, since the latter omit-
ted any correction for environmental costs, did not correct for distribu-
tional changes, and included leisure, which both dominated the MEW
and introduced many arbitrary valuations.15 The Genuine Progress Indi-
cator (GPI) is a widely used, updated version of the ISEW that does ac-
count for the loss of leisure time. The ISEW and GPI, like the MEW,
though less so, were positively correlated with GNP up to a point (around
1980), beyond which the correlation turned slightly negative.16 Figure
14.3 shows estimates of GNP and ISEW for seven different countries.
Measures of welfare are difficult and subject to many arbitrary judg-
ments, so sweeping conclusions should be resisted. However, it seems fair
to say that for the United States since 1947, the empirical evidence that
GNP growth has increased welfare is weak and since 1980 probably non-
existent (see also Figure 14.1 for further support of this claim). Conse-
quently, any impact on welfare via policies that increase GNP growth
15The concept of leisure is an important part of welfare, but the problems of valuing leisure
are difficult. Is the leisure chosen or unchosen? Should sleep time count as leisure? Is commuting
time leisure or “time cost of working”? Should we use the wage rate? The minimum wage? Should
the “leisure” of mom taking care of children be valued at her opportunity cost if she’s a doctor, or
at the cost of avoided daycare? Such difficult choices have a big effect on the index.
16Neither the MEW nor the ISEW considered the effect of individual country GNP growth on
the global environment, and consequently on welfare at geographic levels other than the nation.
Nor was there any deduction for legal harmful products, such as tobacco or alcohol, or illegal
harmful products, such as drugs. No deduction was made for overall diminishing marginal utility
of income resulting from GNP growth over time (although a distributional correction for lower
marginal utility of extra income to the rich was included). Such considerations would further
weaken the correlation between GNP and welfare. Also, GNP, MEW, GPI, and ISEW all begin with
personal consumption. Since all four measures have in common their largest single category, there
is a significant autocorrelation bias, which makes the poor correlations between GNP and the three
welfare measures all the more surprising.
276 • Macroeconomics
Figure 14.3 • Indices of GNP (solid) and ISEW (dashed) for seven countries. 1970
= 100 in all cases. (Source: R. Costanza, J. Farley, and P. Templet, “Quality of Life
and the Distribution of Wealth and Resources.” In R. Costanza and S. E. Jør-
gensen, eds., Understanding and Solving Environmental Problems in the 21st
Century: Toward a New, Integrated Hard Problem Science, Amsterdam: Elsevier,
2002.)
would also be weak or nonexistent. In other words, the “great benefit,” ha-
bitually used to justify sacrifices of the environment, community stan-
dards, and industrial peace, appears, on closer inspection, not even likely
to exist.17 Certainly if economic growth is to be the number-one goal of
nations and the central organizing principle of society, then citizens have
a right to expect that the index by which we measure growth, GNP, would
reflect general welfare more accurately than it does. Continued use of
GNP as a proxy for welfare reminds us of the quote often attributed to
Yogi Berra: “We may be lost, but we’re making great time.”
The objective, accurate scientific measurement of national costs and
national benefits is not a realistic goal. Both costs and benefits of eco-
nomic growth are spread out over time, and how we treat costs and ben-
efits that affect future generations is an ethical issue, not a scientific one.
17For further evidence from other countries, see M. Max-Neef, Economic Growth and Quality
18See R. Costanza et al., The Value of the World’s Ecosystem Services and Natural Capital, Na-
ture 6630:253–260 (1997), in which the value of global ecosystem goods and services is found to
outweigh global GNP. While this article does put monetary values on natural capital for purposes
of comparison with manmade capital, it also explicitly discusses many of the problems with this
approach.
278 • Macroeconomics
$2.00 per day. These people have difficulty meeting even these absolute
needs.19 For this group, greater consumption is probably very closely cor-
related to greater welfare.
Once absolute needs have been met, as is the case for the remaining
three-fifths of the world’s population, then welfare is determined by the sat-
isfaction of a whole suite of primary human needs. Numerous researchers
have proposed a variety of human needs, typically claiming that they are
pursued in hierarchical order, with Maslow’s hierarchy (1954) (in which
consumption is the lowest rung on the needs ladder) being the most fa-
mous. The hierarchical ordering, though generally not seen as rigid by these
researchers, still leaves something to be desired. Even the 1.2 billion people
living in absolute poverty seek to fulfill needs other than mere subsistence.
Manfred Max-Neef20 has summarized and organized human needs into
nonhierarchical axiological21 and existential categories (Table 14.1). In
this matrix of human needs, needs are interrelated and interactive—
many needs are complementary, and different needs can be pursued si-
multaneously. This is a better reflection of reality than a strict hierarchy in
which we pursue higher needs only after lower ones have been fulfilled.
Also important in Max-Neef’s conception, needs are both few and finite.
This stands in stark contrast to the assumption of infinite wants, or the
nonsatiety axiom in standard economics.
If we are to evaluate the success of economic policies both now and in
the future (assuming that providing a high level of welfare for humans for
the indefinite future is our economic goal), then we must develop measur-
able indicators that serve as suitable proxies for needs fulfillment and
welfare.
To state the obvious, we cannot precisely measure welfare, which in the
present context is equivalent to quality of life (QOL). In the words of Clif-
ford Cobb,22
The most important fact to understand about QOL indicators is that all meas-
ures of quality are proxies—indirect measures of the true condition we are
seeking to judge. If quality could be quantified, it would cease to be quality.
Instead, it would be quantity. Quantitative measures should not be judged as
true or false, but only in terms of their adequacy in bringing us closer to an
unattainable goal. They can never directly ascertain quality. (p. 5)
19M. Ravallion and S. Chen, “The Developing World Is Poorer Than We Thought but No Less
Successful in the Fight Against Poverty.” Policy Research Working Paper Series 4211, The World
Bank. 2008.
20M. Max-Neef, “Development and Human Needs.” In P. Ekins and M. Max-Neef, Real-Life
Protection Care, adaptability, Insurance systems, Cooperate, prevent, Living space, social
autonomy, equilibrium, savings, social security, plan take care of, environment, dwelling
solidarity health systems, rights, cure, help
family, work
Affection Self-esteem, solidarity, Friendships, family, Make love, caress, Privacy, intimacy,
respect, tolerance, partnerships express, emotions, home, space of
generosity, with nature share, take care of, togetherness
receptiveness, passion, cultivate, appreciate
determination,
sensuality,
sense of humor
Creation Passion, determination, Abilities, skills, Work, invent, build, Productive and
intuition, imagination, method, work design, interpret feedback settings,
boldness, rationality, workshops, cultural
autonomy, inventiveness, groups, audiences,
curiosity spaces for
expressions, temporal
freedom
Continued
280 • Macroeconomics
I Table 14.1
MAX-NEEF’S MATRIX OF HUMAN NEEDS (CONTINUED)
Existential Categories
Axiological
Categories Being Having Doing Interacting
Identity Sense of belonging, Symbols, language, Commit oneself, Social rhythms,
consistency, religion, habits, integrate oneself, everyday settings,
differentiation, customs, reference confront, decide on, settings in which one
self-esteem, groups, sexuality, get to know oneself, belongs, maturation
assertiveness values, norms, recognize oneself, stages
historical memory, actualize oneself,
work grow
The column of Being registers attributes, personal or collective, that are expressed as nouns. The column of Having registers institu-
tions, norms, mechanisms, tools (not in material sense), laws, etc. that can be expressed in one or few words. The column of Doing
registers locations and milieus (as time and spaces). It stands for the Spanish estar or the German befinden, in the sense of time and
space. As there is no corresponding word in English, Interacting was chosen for lack of something better.
Source: M. Max-Neef, “Development and Human Needs.” In P. Ekins and M. Max-Neef, Real-Life Economics: Understanding Wealth
Creation. London: Routledge, 1992, pp. 197–213.
Objective Measures
Numerous efforts have been made to objectively measure welfare. The
problem is that these studies have found only weak relationships between
objective measures of welfare and the subjective assessments of the same
by the subjects concerned.23 However, both these studies and the various
types of national accounts seem to include a narrow range of objective in-
dicators, often placing what we consider to be an excessive emphasis on
consumption. Quite possibly the problem is that welfare is too rich a
gumbo for us to recapture its flavor with so few ingredients. An important
research agenda in economics is to develop a methodology for measuring
access to “satisfiers” (the means by which we satisfy a given need) for Max-
Neef’s axiological and existential categories of human needs as indicators
of welfare. With sufficient ingredients, we can produce something rea-
sonably close to the flavor of welfare.
23B. Haas, A Multidisciplinary Concept Analysis of Quality of Life, Western Journal of Nursing
24C. W. Cobb, Measurement Tools and the Quality of Life (San Francisco, CA: Redefining
S. Richardson, eds., Liberalism and the Good, New York: Routledge, 1990, pp. 203–252; R. Sug-
den, “Welfare, Resources, and Capabilities: A Review of Inequality Reexamined by Amartya Sen,”
Journal of Economic Literature 31 (December, 1993): 1947–1962.
282 • Macroeconomics
eliminated, it would not affect our welfare. In the human development ap-
proach, losing options restricts our capabilities and would therefore affect
our welfare. The human development approach is less concerned with the
actual choices that people make than with the options they are free to
choose from, and the marketplace is only one of many spheres in which
choice is important.
isfiers will best meet their needs, interactive discussion with people is
nonetheless essential to select and test appropriate indicators. We would
also need to develop group-based methodologies to determine the effec-
tiveness of our indicators in a social setting.
It is clear that Max-Neef’s approach is very difficult to operationalize,
even if his concept is theoretically more compelling than GNP or even
ISEW. The debate over which approach to take to national accounting—
theoretically sound measures or ease of accounting—is old. As Irving Fisher
argued back in 1906, the appropriate measure, even of income, is one that
captures the psychic flux of service (i.e., satisfaction of needs and wants)
and not simply the final costs of goods and services.28 And at the time
Fisher wrote, the absence of suitable data for calculating either psychic flux
of service or final costs no doubt led many to ignore the debate as entirely
academic. The widespread use of GNP indicates that in practice, Fisher lost
this earlier debate. However, measures such as the ISEW suggest that the
GNP is becoming increasingly incapable of measuring economic welfare,
much less general human welfare. Even if we can never quantify access to
satisfiers as precisely as we currently quantify GNP, as Sen suggests, perhaps
it is better to be vaguely right than precisely wrong.29
Accepting Max-Neef’s human needs matrix as a framework for the spe-
cific elements of human welfare, and access to satisfiers as potentially the
best objective indicator of welfare, has profound implications with respect
to scale, distribution, and allocation. First, most of the possible indicators
suggested by Max-Neef require few, if any, material resources beyond
those needed to sustain human life and hence are less subject to physical
exhaustion. Thus, for most elements of human welfare, increases for one
person or one generation do not leave less for others. Second, explicitly
accepting that there is a limit to material needs implies that we can limit
consumption greatly with little, if any, sacrifice of welfare. This result is
critical, because the laws of thermodynamics make it impossible to un-
couple physical consumption from resource use and waste production.
Abundant evidence suggests that current levels of consumption could not
be sustainably met with renewable resources alone, and we must therefore
limit consumption or else threaten the welfare of future generations.
The difficulty of operationalizing Max-Neef’s framework may actually
be a point in its favor. Why do we want to measure welfare in the first
place? It’s not just to track its rise or fall but to help us create policies to
28H. Daly and J. Cobb, For the Common Good: Redirecting the Economy Toward Community, the
opment Ethic, Part 2.” In M. Nussbaum and J. Glober, eds., Women, Culture, and Development: A
Study in Human Capabilities, Oxford, England: Oxford University Press, 1995.
284 • Macroeconomics
15
Money
M oney ranks with the wheel and fire as ancient inventions without
which the modern world could not function. Probably more people
today are run over and burned by out-of-control money than by out-of-
control wheels and fires. Money is mysterious. Unlike matter and energy,
it can be created and destroyed, evading the laws of thermodynamics. Pri-
vate citizens (counterfeiters) are sent to jail for making even small
amounts of it, yet private commercial banks make almost all of it, and we
pay them for it! Sometimes money is a costly commodity (gold) and some-
times a costless token (paper notes). It is easily transferable into real assets
by individuals, but the community as a whole cannot exchange its money
into real assets at all, since someone in the community ends up holding
the money. Some economists think the money supply should be deter-
mined by fixed rules, others think it should be manipulated by public au-
thorities. And some people think the love of money is the root of all evil!
Anyone who is not confused by money probably hasn’t thought about it
very much.
Money functions as a medium of exchange, a unit of account, and a
store of value. The functions are interrelated but worth considering sepa-
rately. To measure exchange value, we need a unit—call it a dollar, a peso,
a franc, or a yen. If the unit is stable over time (no inflation or deflation),
then money automatically serves as a store of exchange value. To function
as a medium of exchange and let us escape the inconvenience of barter,
money must hold its value at least long enough to effect both sides of the
transaction, which in barter, of course, are simultaneous. A moment’s re-
flection shows how tremendously inefficient barter is and consequently
how efficient money is. In barter there must be a coincidence of wants. It
is not enough that I want what you have to trade; you also have to want
whatever it is that I have to trade, and we have to find each other. Money
285
286 • Macroeconomics
1Though, of course, exchange value is real only if something exists for which money can ac-
tually be exchanged.
Chapter 15 Money • 287
limit to the accumulation of exchange value. Fifty hammers are not much
better than two (one and a spare) as far as use values are concerned. But
in terms of exchange value, fifty hammers are much better than two, and
better yet in the form of fifty hammers’ worth of fungible money that can
be spent on anything, anywhere, and at any time.
I Virtual Wealth
Frederick Soddy summarized all this by carefully distinguishing wealth
from debt.2 He noted that “a weight, although it is measured by what it will
pull up, is nevertheless a pull down. The whole idea of balancing one thing
against another in order to measure its quantity involves equating the quan-
tity measured against an equal and opposite quantity. Wealth is the positive
quantity to be measured and money as the claim to wealth is a debt” (p.
103).3 Monetary debt, the measure of wealth, is negative wealth, say minus
two pigs. It obeys the laws of mathematics but not of physics. Wealth, on
the other hand, plus two pigs, obeys the laws of thermodynamics as well as
mathematics. Positive pigs die, have to be fed, and cannot reproduce faster
than their gestation period allows. Negative pigs are hyper-fecund and can
multiply mathematically without limit. As Soddy put it, “You cannot per-
manently pit an absurd human convention, such as the spontaneous incre-
ment of debt (compound interest), against the natural law of the
spontaneous decrement of wealth (entropy)” (p. 30).
The holding of token money by the public to avoid the inconvenience
of barter gives rise to the curious phenomenon that Soddy called virtual
wealth, which he defined as the aggregate value of the real assets that the
community voluntarily abstains from holding in order to hold money in-
stead. Individuals can always convert their money holdings into real as-
sets, but they choose not to in order to avoid the inconvenience of barter.
This raises the question of whether money should be counted as a part of
the real wealth of the community. Yes, if money is a commodity like gold
that circulates at its commodity value. No, if it is token money like a dol-
lar bill whose commodity value is nil but whose exchange value is signifi-
cant. Even though each person can at an instant convert his money into
real assets, it is impossible for the community as a whole to do this, as we
have previously noted.
Money, therefore, represents not real wealth but, in Soddy’s term, vir-
tual wealth. More exactly, it is the magnitude of virtual wealth that deter-
mines the value of money. What happens if the government puts into
circulation more money than people currently want to hold? People will
exchange money for real assets and drive up the price of real assets. As the
price of real assets rises, the real value of money falls until it again coin-
cides with the virtual wealth of the community. If there is too little money,
people will exchange real assets for money, thereby driving down the price
2F. Soddy, Wealth, Virtual Wealth, and Debt, London: George Allen & Unwin, 1926.
3When banks create money by providing someone with a loan (see below), they actually cre-
ate a debt as the first step. On the asset side of the accounting books, the banker enters a debt for
the amount of money borrowed (to be paid off with interest). This borrowed money is then placed
in a bank account, which is listed in the bank’s books as a liability.
Chapter 15 Money • 289
of real assets. As the prices of real assets fall, the value of money increases
until it again equals the virtual wealth of the community. The value of a
dollar, then, is the virtual wealth of the community divided by however
many dollars are in circulation. It follows that the value of a unit of token
money is determined not by the total wealth of a community, nor by its
annual GNP, but by its virtual wealth relative to the money supply.
aJ. Tobin, “Money and Economic Growth,” Econometrica (October 1965), p. 676.
I Seigniorage
Who owns the virtual wealth? Since it does not really exist, we might say
that no one owns it. It is a collective illusion. Yet individuals voluntarily
hold money instead of real assets, and they behave as if money were a real
part of their individual wealth, even if they understand that collectively it
is only “virtual” or illusory. Every member of the community who holds
money had to give up a real asset to get it—except for the issuer of
money. The one who creates the money and is the first to spend it gets a
real asset in exchange for a paper token. The difference between the mon-
etary value and the negligible commodity value of the token, the profit to
the issuer of money, is called seigniorage, in recognition of the lordly na-
ture of this privilege. Who is this fortunate person? Historically it was the
feudal lord, or the king, the sovereign, who issued money within his do-
main. One might expect that this privilege would have been passed on to
the sovereign’s legitimate heir, the democratic state. To some extent this
is the case, because only governments can issue currency or legal tender.
However, over 90% of our money supply today is not currency but de-
mand deposits created by the private commercial banking system.4 They
4Demand deposits are ordinary checking accounts from which money is payable on demand
are created out of nothing and loaned into existence by the private com-
mercial banks under rules set up by the government. Who gets the seignior-
age? Seigniorage from currency goes to the government. Seigniorage from
demand deposits goes to the private sector, initially to commercial banks.
To the extent there is competition between banks for savings, they will re-
distribute some of the seigniorage to depositors. Sectors of society too
poor to save will receive nothing.
What does money consist of in our economy? A further mystery of
money is that it has several definitions. The most restrictive is “currency
plus demand deposits in the hands of the nonbank public.” More expan-
sive definitions include savings deposits and even credit card debt. Most
of our money supply bears interest as a condition of its existence. Who-
ever borrowed it into existence must pay back what he borrowed plus in-
terest. Thus, a requirement for growth (or else inflation) is built into the
very existence of our money supply. Moreover, the money supply, ceteris
paribus, expands during boom times when everyone wants to borrow and
invest, and contracts during recessions when loans are foreclosed, thereby
aggravating cyclical instabilities.
On learning for the first time that private banks create money out of
nothing and lend it at interest, many people find it hard to believe. In-
deed, according to Joseph Schumpeter, as late as the 1920s, 99 out of 100
economists believed that banks could no more create money than cloak-
rooms could create coats. Yet now every economics textbook explains
how banks create money. We will explain how it works in a minute, but
first we’ll let the strangeness of it sink in. Of course, this is not the only
way to create money. Nonetheless, most economists today accept this sit-
uation as normal. But the leading economists of the early twentieth cen-
tury, Irving Fisher and Frank Knight, thought it was an abomination. And
so did Frederick Soddy.
5If r is the required reserve ratio, then the demand deposit multiplier is this infinite series:
the next person. Since money is a public good, one would expect seignior-
age to be public revenue, not private. The virtual wealth of the commu-
nity could be treated as a publicly owned resource, like the atmosphere or
electromagnetic spectrum. But that is not the case. The money supply is
privately loaned into existence at interest. The fact that most of our money
was loaned into existence and must be paid back at interest imparts a
strong growth bias, as well as cyclical instability,6 to our economy. There
is no economic reason why the monetary system must be linked with the
private commercial activity of lending and borrowing.
What are the alternatives? Soddy offered three reforms. His first pro-
posal was to gradually raise the reserve requirement to 100%. That would
put the private banks out of the money creation business and back into
the business of borrowing and lending other people’s real money, provid-
ing checking services, and so on. Control of the money supply would then
belong to the government. How, then, would the government regulate the
money supply? Soddy’s second policy suggested an automatic rule, based
on a price level index. If the price level index is falling, the government
should finance its own activities by simply printing new money and
spending it into existence. If the price level is rising, the government
should cease printing money and tax more than it spends, that is, run a
surplus. This would suffice for a closed economy, but for an open econ-
omy, one that engages in international trade, the domestic money supply
can be increased or decreased by international payments balances. Soddy’s
third proposal (back in 1926, under the gold standard) was freely fluctu-
ating exchange rates. Currencies would trade freely and directly against
each other; an equilibrium exchange rate would eliminate any surplus or
shortage (deficit) in the balance of payments and consequently any inter-
national effect on the domestic money supply. Remember our discussion
of surplus and shortage in Chapter 9.
Of course, this is not what we have now.
The gold standard has been abandoned, and fixed exchange rate
regimes have given way to flexible exchange rates, but not to freely float-
ing exchange rates, which are thought (rightly or wrongly) to be too
volatile and disruptive of international trade. (We return to the topic of
exchange rates in Chapter 20.) The money supply is determined largely
by the commercial banking system, subject to some manipulation, but not
control, by the Federal Reserve (the Fed). The Federal Reserve System
6We will explain this instability in more detail in Chapter 17. In the meantime, it is enough
to understand that banks are eager to loan new money into existence during economic booms, in-
creasing the money supply and favoring more economic growth. During recessions, banks prefer
to collect more in old loans than they loan out in new ones, reducing the money supply and ag-
gravating the recession.
Chapter 15 Money • 295
sient phase in human history.7 The classic example of the power of expo-
nential growth is the story about putting a grain of wheat on the first
square of a chessboard, two grains on the second, four on the third, and
so on. At the next-to-last, or 63rd, square the board contains 263 grains of
wheat, far more than the world’s whole wheat crop, and the last, or 64th,
square will by itself contain that much again. Hubbert’s conclusion was
that the world cannot sustain 64 doublings of even a grain of wheat. In
our world, many populations are simultaneously doubling—populations
of people, livestock, cars, houses—things much bigger than a grain of
wheat. How many times can each of these populations double? How
many times can they all double together? A few tens at most, was Hub-
bert’s answer. Our financial conventions, on the other hand, assume that
this doubling will go on forever.
This expectation gets played out in reverse when we discount future
values to an equivalent present value. We simply run the exponential cal-
culation backward, asking: How much would we have to deposit in the
bank today at today’s interest (discount) rate in order to have the given fu-
ture amount at a given future date? This discounting procedure is, as we
have seen, at the heart of the financial model of present value maximiza-
tion, which has displaced the more traditional economic model of profit
maximization. The error that bothered Soddy is deeply ingrained in pres-
ent economic thinking. We have already encountered it in our discussion
of why renewable resources are driven to extinction.
It is convenient to dismiss Soddy as a “monetary crank” and to remark
what a pity it was that such a brilliant chemist wasted so much of his time
on a topic that he was unqualified to think about. This is exactly the treat-
ment that Soddy was given. It was harder to dismiss Irving Fisher and
Frank Knight, who also called for 100% reserve requirements, because
they were the leading economists of their generation. But their ideas on
money were simply classed separately from the rest of their economics,
treated as a peccadillo, and were ignored.
Our previous statement—that money does not obey the laws of
thermodynamics—needs some qualification. Exchange value is hardly a
value if there is nothing for which it can be exchanged. If money is issued
without real wealth to back it up, spending that money simply drives up
the prices of goods and services, causing inflation and bringing “real
money” back closer into line with real wealth (more on inflation later).
What about virtual wealth? Are there limits to the amount of real
wealth people are willing to forgo in order to hold money? If not, then the
amount of real money in circulation can continue to grow independently
H. Daly and K. Townsend, eds., Valuing the Earth, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993.
Chapter 15 Money • 297
of the production of real goods and services. Financial assets are neither
money nor real wealth, but they are bought and sold in the market, and
people will hold more money to be able to meet their demand for trans-
actions in these assets. In addition, people trade in money itself, using one
national currency to buy another, and this similarly increases the demand
for money. Both currency speculation and growth in financial assets have
increased dramatically in recent years.
The M—C—M* equation previously showed how money has become
less a means for facilitating exchange, more an end in itself. In reality, the
M—C—M* equation has itself been dwarfed by pure currency specula-
tion and trading in financial paper. John Maynard Keynes warned back in
the 1930s, “Speculators may do no harm as bubbles on a steady stream of
enterprise. But the position is serious when enterprise becomes the bub-
ble on a whirlpool of speculation. When the capital development of a
country becomes a by-product of the activities of a casino, the job is likely
to be ill-done.”8 While global production of marketed goods and services
is roughly on the order of $30 trillion per year,9 the trade in paper pur-
chasing paper (or, more accurately these days, electrons purchasing elec-
trons) with no intervening commodity is almost $2 trillion per day.10 This
means that the buying and selling of paper assets and currencies, M—M*,
is more than 20 times greater than exchanges in the real economy! Real
enterprise has indeed become a bubble on the whirlpool of speculation.
As no productive activity intervenes in these speculative purchases, the
sole result seems to be a magical growth in money. But is such growth ac-
tually possible indefinitely?
Growth in money is meaningless unless there is a corresponding in-
crease in real wealth, so now we must ask: Does financial speculation lead
to growth in real wealth? Some paper-paper purchases are purchases of
new stock offerings that do provide financial capital, which can mobilize
physical factors of production, but this is only an estimated 4% of stock
purchases. Speculation in currency, in which millions of dollars are traded
back and forth for very small margins over short time scales, clearly pro-
duce nothing. Indeed, such transactions almost certainly contributed to
the crises in several Southeast Asian economies in 1997–1998 as specula-
tors sold off regional currencies, and these crises meant dramatic decreases
in production from those economies. Yet such speculation would not be
8J. M. Keynes, The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money, Orlando, FL: Harcourt
year; the numbers for speculation are in nominal dollars, not PPP.
10D. Korten, The Post-Corporate World: Life After Capitalism, San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler,
1998.
298 • Macroeconomics
undertaken unless some profits were being made somewhere. For exam-
ple, George Soros, who participated in the financial speculation in South-
east Asia, is reported to have earned 1 billion pounds speculating on
England’s currency in 1995.11 The only possible explanation is that if
those who produce nothing are earning, through speculation, more
money that entitles them to more real wealth, then those who actually do
produce something must be becoming entitled to increasingly less wealth.
In summary, it appears that the illusion that money can grow without
physical limits results from three things. First, as long as the production
of real goods and services increases, more money is needed to pursue
them, so growth in money is justified. But such growth cannot, of course,
continue forever on a finite planet. Second, as the number or price of fi-
nancial assets grows, such as through speculative bubbles, demand for
money grows as well, and supply can increase to meet this demand. The
fact is, however, that financial bubbles inevitably burst. Third, holders of
financial capital see their capital grow because speculation can transfer re-
sources from those who produce to those who merely speculate. Such
transfer of wealth has limits, though the limits are obscured by continued
economic growth. Thus, the appearance that money is exempt from the
laws of thermodynamics is an illusion that can be maintained only while
scale is increasing, or the financial sector is expanding relative to the real
sector. It remains impossible for real money to grow without limit.
THINK ABOUT IT!
What do you think would happen if a national government tried the
same approach to seigniorage as Ithaca HOURs? For example, the gov-
ernment could impose 100% reserve requirements to prevent banks
from creating money, award every new entrant to the economy some
lump sum of money (perhaps by providing 18-year-olds sufficient
money to pay for a college education or start a business), and lend
money into existence at 0% interest for socially desirable projects.
11W. Greider, One World, Ready or Not: The Manic Logic of Global Capitalism, New York: Simon
16
Distribution
W e have emphasized that ecological economics is concerned with
three issues: the allocation of resources, their distribution, and the
scale of the economy. We have seen how the ecological sustainability of
the Earth is related to the size or scale of the macroeconomy. We have also
explored the economist’s meaning of efficient allocation in our discussion
of microeconomics and the basic market equation. We then looked at the
macroeconomic allocation problem in Chapter 14. But the second issue,
distribution and the fairness thereof, has remained largely in the back-
ground.
I Pareto Optimality
In dealing with allocation, we saw that economics defines efficiency as the
Pareto optimal allocation of resources by the market. This definition as-
sumes a given distribution of wealth and income. More specifically, an ef-
ficient allocation is one that best satisfies individual wants weighted by the
individual’s ability to pay—that is, by her income and wealth. Change the
distribution of income and wealth, and we get a different set of efficient
prices (since different people want different things), which define a differ-
ent Pareto optimum. Because different Pareto optima are based on different
distributions of income and wealth, economists are reluctant to compare
them; one optimum is as good as another. We saw that a major reason for
scale expansion—economic growth—has been to avoid the issue of dis-
tributive equality. As long as everyone is getting more from aggregate
growth, the distributive issue is less pressing, at least as a cure for poverty.
Besides, the efficiency of the allocation of aggregate growth loses its well-
defined meaning (Pareto optimality) once we accept the legitimacy of
changing distribution in the interest of fairness. Consequently, economics
301
302 • Macroeconomics
has tended to address distribution out of logical necessity but quickly sets
it aside in the interests of political convenience.
answer to our question, does the notion of Pareto optimal allocation as-
sume a given scale as well as a given distribution, appears to be yes. Size
cannot increase proportionally because (1) there is a fixed factor, namely
the size of the ecosystem, and (2) it is mathematically impossible even for
all relevant internal dimensions of the subsystem to increase in the same
proportion. In sum, it seems quite true that an optimal allocation assumes
a given scale, just as it assumes a given distribution.
2Wealth is measured in dollars (for example) and income in dollars/time. These magnitudes
I Table 16.1
U.S. PERCENTAGE SHARE OF WEALTH AND INCOME BY PERCENTILE GROUP
Percentile Shares
Year Top 1% Next 19% Bottom 80% Gini Coefficient
Net Worth (Wealth)
1983 33.8 47.6 18.7 0.799
1989 37.4 45.3 16.2 0.832
1992 37.2 46.6 16.3 0.823
1995 38.5 45.8 16.1 0.828
1998 38.1 45.3 16.6 0.822
2001 33.4 51.3 16.6 0.826
2004 34.3 50.4 16.3 0.829
Income
1983 12.8 39.0 48.1 0.480
1989 16.4 39.0 44.5 0.521
1992 15.7 40.7 43.7 0.528
1995 14.4 40.8 44.9 0.518
1998 16.6 39.6 43.8 0.531
2000 20.0 38.6 41.4 0.562
2003 17.0 40.9 42.1 0.540
Source: E. N. Wolff, Top Heavy, The Twentieth Century Fund Report, New York: New Press, 1995, p. 67 (years 1983–1992); E. N. Wolff,
Recent Trends in Wealth Ownership, 1983–1998, Working Paper No. 300, Table 2, Jerome Levy Economics Institute, April 2000 and E.
B. Wolff, Recent Trends in Household Wealth in the United States: Rising Debt and the Middle-Class Squeeze, SSRN eLibrary.
3See E. Wolff, Recent Trends in Household Wealth in the United States: Rising Debt and the Middle-
tween 1979 and 2006, Washington, DC: Center on Budget and Policy Prioirities, 2009.
306 • Macroeconomics
Figure 16.1 • The Lorenz curve. Because the Lorenz curve is in percentages, its
shape does not depend on units of measure. It is therefore useful for making
comparisons across countries and over time.
I Measuring Distribution
Although economists have no good theory by which to explain the distri-
bution of wealth and income, they do have useful ways of measuring and
describing it statistically.5 One useful representation is the Lorenz curve,
shown in Figure 16.1. The x-axis shows the number of income recipients
in terms of cumulative percentages, from lowest to highest income. The y-
axis shows the percentage of total income. The lengths of the axes are
equal, so that when closed in, they make a square.
The Lorenz curve plots the percentage of total income going to each
percentage of income recipient. We know that 0% of income recipients
will get 0% of the income, and that 100% of income recipients will get
100% of the income, so we already know the two extreme points on any
Lorenz curve. If each percentage of the population received the same per-
centage of the income (i.e., the bottom 20% got 20% of total income, the
bottom 70% got 70% of income), we would have perfect equality. The
Lorenz curve would be the 45-degree line connecting (0, 0) with (100,
100). But suppose the bottom 80% of recipients get 44% of the income.
That gives us another point, one that lies well below the 45-degree line. If
we fill in many points between the extremes, we get a curve shaped like
the one in Figure 16.1. The closer the curve to the 45-degree line, the
more equal the distribution; the farther away, the less equal. The shaded
5For a clear and insightful exposition, see J. Pen, Income Distribution, New York: Praeger, 1971.
308 • Macroeconomics
area defined by the curve and the 45-degree line measures inequality. In
the limit, if one person got 100% of income and everyone else got 0%, the
Lorenz curve would coincide with the axes and look like a backwards L.
The ratio of the shaded area (between the curve and the 45-degree line)
to the total triangular area under the 45-degree line is called the Gini co-
efficient. For perfect equality the shaded area is zero, and consequently
The Gini coefficient is used to the Gini coefficient is 0; for perfect inequality the shaded area takes up the
measure the inequality of the whole area under the 45-degree line, and consequently the Gini coeffi-
distribution of wealth or in-
cient is 1. Values of the Gini coefficient for U.S. wealth and income dis-
come across a population. A
tribution are given in Table 16.1.
Gini coefficient of 1 implies per-
fect inequality (one person A more familiar statistical description is the common frequency distri-
owns everything), and a coeffi- bution, shown in Figure 16.2. The x-axis shows income category, and the
cient of zero indicates a per- y-axis shows number of members in each income category (frequency).
fectly equal distribution. Income distribution does not follow a normal distribution, as does height
or many other personal characteristics. Rather, it is highly skewed, with
the mode well below the mean and a very, very long tail to the right
needed to reach the top income.
If we wanted to show the maximum income on Figure 16.2, we would
need a fold-out extending the horizontal axis by the length of a football
field. Graphical representations generally do not capture the extreme
inequality at the upper income range. Income categories are frequently
truncated at a maximum category of “$100,000 and over,” where “over”
means four orders of magnitude over.
Another interesting way to look at income distribution is to consider a
football field, where the zero yard line represents the poorest person, the
the 50 yard line the person with median income, and 100 yard line the
richest person in the U.S. Incomes are depicted as the height of a stack of
$100 bills. At the 50 yard line the median personal income (in 2005) of
$25,149 is represented by a one-inch stack of bills. Around the 99 yard
line, we see a stack of bills about a foot high—$300 million. Nearing the
100 yard line, the top hedge fund manager in 2008, a recession year,
earned $2.5 billion, a stack of bills 1.7 miles high. Bill Gates once earned
a stack nearly 30 miles high!6
Moreover, these data are just for the United States. The distribution of
wealth and income between countries is far greater than that found within
countries.
What is the proper range of inequality in the distribution of income?
Surely it is impossible to have one person owning everything and everyone
else owning nothing. Maybe we could have everyone else getting a subsis-
6L. Story, Top Hedge Fund Managers Do Well in a Down Year, New York Times, March 24,
tence wage, and the fortunate one person enjoying the entire social surplus
above subsistence. But most people would not consider that fair, even
though possible. At the other extreme, few people think a perfectly equal
distribution—a Gini coefficient equal to zero—would be fair either. After
all, some people work harder than others, and some jobs are more difficult
than others. Fairness in a larger sense would require some income differ-
ences. There is a legitimate case to be made that differences in distribution
provide a socially useful incentive for industriousness and innovation.
Is there a legitimate range of inequality, beyond which further inequal-
ity becomes either unfair or dysfunctional? What might such a range be?
Plato thought that the richest citizen should be four times wealthier than
the poorest. Ben Cohen and Jerry Greenfield, of Ben and Jerry’s ice cream
fame, at one time reportedly pledged that the highest-paid executive
would receive no more than five times the salary of the lowest-paid em-
ployee. Maybe Plato, Ben, and Jerry were wrong, though, and maybe a fac-
tor of 10 would be better. Or 20 or 50. Currently the acceptable ratio is
not defined, and in 1999 in the United States, the typical CEO earned 475
times the typical worker.7 Ecological economics does not accept the cur-
rent notion that real total output can grow forever. If the total is limited,
then the maximum for one person is implicitly limited. The issue of a
proper range of inequality in distribution is therefore critical for ecologi-
cal economics, even though it has not yet received due attention. The
standard economist’s effort to keep distribution at bay forever by eternal
growth is not a satisfactory solution.
Finally a word on the functional distribution of income. For industrial
countries, the division varies around the following: wages = 70%, profits
= 20%, interest = 8%, and land rent = 2%. For ecological economics, what
is striking is that essentially none of the value of the total product is
attributed to natural resources or services. Even land rent is mainly a lo-
cational premium, not a payment for resources in situ or natural serv-
ices—one more piece of evidence that the flow of low entropy from nature
is treated as a free good. If we think of two social classes struggling to di-
vide the pie, we have laborers getting 70% and capitalists, business own-
ers, and landowners together getting about 30%. This division represents
a kind of balance of power in the social struggle. Neither side wants to in-
clude nature as a participant in production, which would require that na-
ture’s services be paid according to their scarcity and productivity.
Even if one wanted to pay for nature’s contribution, who would collect
on nature’s behalf? There is no social class analogous to labor or capital
7J. Reingold and F. Jesperson, Executive Pay: It Continues to Explode—and Options Alone Are
Creating Paper Billionaires, Business Week, April 17, 2000. Online: http://www.businessweek.com/
careers/content/jan1990/b3677014.htm.
310 • Macroeconomics
.com/2007/09/18/introducing-this-blog/.
bJ. Anderson, Managers Use Hedge Funds as Big I.R.A.’s, New York Times, April 17, 2007.
that has an interest in seeing to it that nature’s services are properly ac-
counted and paid for. Historically the landlord class may to some extent
have played the role of defender of nature’s services, but that class hardly
exists anymore, and few lament its demise. The government is the biggest
landholder in the U.S., and it has followed a policy of cheap resources in
order to benefit and ease the tensions between labor and capital. The ex-
isting classes, labor and capital, see it in their mutual interest not to share
with a third party. Since in reality there is no third party, all that would be
necessary is to pay into a fund a scarcity rent for natural resources and
services, and then redistribute the fund back to labor and capital, perhaps
on the same 70–30 division. This would get the cost accounting and
prices right and improve the efficiency of allocation, without necessarily
affecting the distribution. Alternatively, since many of the goods and serv-
ices provided by natural capital are nonmarket goods, the scarcity rent
Chapter 16 Distribution • 311
4%
2%
1%
0%
1925
1928
1931
1934
1937
1940
1943
1946
1949
1952
1955
1958
1961
1964
1967
1970
1973
1976
1979
1982
1985
1988
1991
1994
1997
2000
Highest tax bracket Income share, top 0.1%
Figure 16.3 • The income share of the top 0.1% of U.S. society (left axis), and the
highest marginal U.S. Tax break (right bracket) between 1913 and 2002.
8See. G. Wilkinson, Mind the Gap, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2001.
312 • Macroeconomics
9E.g., J. Robinson, Essays in the Theory of Economic Growth, London: Macmillan, 1968; E.
Phelps, Second Essay on the Golden Rule of Accumulation, American Economic Review 55(4):
793–814 (1965).
Chapter 16 Distribution • 313
However, the onset of the atomic age made it apparent that technolog-
ical advance had the capacity to bring harm as well as good. Growth in
population and per-capita consumption raised the specter of resource de-
pletion. Worsening pollution caused alarm, and ecologists began to worry
that many systems were nearing irreversible, catastrophic thresholds. The
relevant question was no longer: How much should we sacrifice to make
the future even better off? Now it was: How much should we sacrifice to
keep the future from being worse off than the present? Paradoxically, at
least in the United States, a culture change was occurring at about the
same time. The work ethic was no longer “work hard, live frugally, and in-
vest in the future” but rather “work hard, borrow heavily, and consume as
much as possible now.” As a result, personal savings rates in the U.S.
plunged to historic lows and rapidly approached zero early in the twenty-
first century, while federal deficits reached historic highs.
Should people strive to make the future better off than the present? Do
we have at least an obligation to make sure it is not worse off than the
present? There are no easy answers to the “appropriate” distribution of
wealth between generations. Even a brief survey of philosophies is beyond
the scope of this text. We will quickly examine two alternative approaches:
the ecological economics approach, based on ethical judgments concern-
ing obligations to future generations (intergenerational justice), and the
more mainstream approach in economics that argues for an “objective”
decision-making rule (intergenerational allocation).
10For practical guidelines on investing scarcity rents, see S. El Serafy, “The Proper Calculation
of Income from Depletable Natural Resources.” In Y. J. Ahmad, S. El Serafy, and E. Lutz, eds., En-
vironmental Accounting for Sustainable Development, Washington, DC: World Bank, 1989.
Chapter 16 Distribution • 315
to deal with global climate change. Virtually all economic analyses of cli-
mate change place a lower weight on future costs and benefits than on
present ones. These analyses look at different policy scenarios and for
each sum up the present costs and benefits with discounted future costs
and benefits to arrive at a net present value (NPV). NPV basically tells
us what present and future costs and benefits are worth to us today (not
to the future tomorrow), which implies that future generations have no
particular right to any resources, and we have no obligation to preserve
any. Under this type of benefit-cost analysis, the higher the NPV relative
to required investments, the better the project.
Such analyses can carry a great deal of weight as society decides how
to address some of the most pressing problems we now confront. The cen-
tral importance of the discount rate in determining the outcome of such
analyses means the topic deserves our attention.
In many such models, the choice of a discount rate may be the single
most important factor, yet respected economists addressing the same
problem use dramatically different rates and arrive at dramatically differ-
ent results. Are such models actually objective decision-making tools?
a30 trillion is a number that’s hard to wrap your mind around. Putting it into perspec-
tive, 30 trillion seconds is slightly less than a million years (951,294 years, to be
precise).
Discounting Reconsidered
We have already explained why intertemporal discounting can make
sense for the individual and for market goods. We must now examine
whether it also makes sense for society and for nonmarket goods.
We saw why individuals might have a pure time rate of preference:
People are impatient; they don’t live forever; possessions can be lost, de-
stroyed, or stolen, and opportunities disappear. A reasonable individual
may discount the future for any one of these reasons—why should I pay
money now to reduce damages from global warming that will occur only
after I am dead?—but the same logic does not apply to society. Relative to
the individuals of which they are composed, societies are immortal, and
uncertainties are averaged out. For this reason, there is, in fact, fairly wide
consensus within the economics profession that social discount rates
should indeed be lower than individual discount rates. The social dis-
count rate is a rate of conversion of future value to present value that re-
flects society’s collective ethical judgment, as opposed to an individualistic
judgment, such as the market rate of interest.
When it comes to the opportunity cost of capital, however, the con-
sensus changes. Financial capital does function as a productive asset, and
if we have it now instead of in the future, we have the opportunity to in-
vest it in productive activities that will increase the quantity of market
goods in the future. There are a number of important issues we must bear
in mind, however.
First, the real value of money can grow only if the production of goods
and services that money can acquire also grows, and we know that the
production of goods and services cannot grow forever on a finite planet.
While there may always be some areas that are growing, justifying a dis-
count rate for the individual, the economy as a whole cannot grow in-
definitely, in which case a social discount rate into the indefinite future
may be inappropriate.
Second, we must recognize that many investments are “profitable” be-
cause we ignore many of the costs of production. We know that all human
productive activities use up natural resources and return waste to the en-
vironment, and these costs of production are often ignored. Many of these
318 • Macroeconomics
11Returns on investments will be high, but the total amount invested will be low, and there-
posite. Thus, if we allow the market interest rate to determine the discount
rate, there would theoretically be an inverse correlation between discount
rate and economic growth, the exact opposite of what would justify the
“richer future” rationale for discounting.
stein. Nudge: improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. Yale Univer-
sity Press, New Haven. 2008.
Finally, many economists argue that technology is the driving force for
economic growth. Not only does technology ensure we won’t run out of
resources and the economy won’t stop growing, but it offers yet another
reason to discount the value of resources in the future. Technology is
likely to develop substitutes for natural resources. When these substitutes
320 • Macroeconomics
become available, the resources they replace will lose value. Therefore,
they will be worth less in the future than they are today. After all, hasn’t
oil largely replaced coal, and haven’t fiber optics replaced copper in many
uses? However, technology ultimately complements resources and can
never completely replace them. Some 150 years ago, oil had little value.
Today, it is an integral part of an overwhelming number of industrial
processes and products. As we saw in Chapter 5, we are actually develop-
ing new uses for oil and other raw materials faster than we are developing
replacements, again suggesting that the value of raw materials will in-
crease in the future, not shrink.
What can we say about discount rates in the end? They do make sense
for individuals in the short run. For some small-scale, short-term social
projects, they may also make sense. However, justifications for discount-
ing the future on a large scale and over long time horizons are question-
able at best.12 Intertemporal allocation is the apportionment of resources
across different stages in the lifetimes of basically the same set of people
(the same generation). Discounting can make sense for someone effi-
ciently allocating resources intertemporally. But as we lengthen the time
period we are more and more talking about different people (different
generations) and less and less about the same people at different stages in
their lives. Intertemporal distribution is the apportioning of resources
across different generations, across different people. Distribution is fun-
damentally different from allocation, and, consequently, justice replaces
efficiency as the relevant criterion for policy when time periods become
intergenerational.
12See A. Voinov and J. Farley, Reconciling Sustainability, Systems Theory and Discounting,
17
The IS-LM Model
W e have now explored three of the major issues with which macro-
economics is concerned: gross national product (GNP), money,
and distribution. We questioned the appropriateness of GNP as the desir-
able end for economic policy and emphasized the importance of a just dis-
tribution as a desirable end but said little about policies for attaining
whichever ends we choose to pursue. In this chapter, we examine the pol-
icy tools at the macroeconomist’s disposal that can help us attain an econ-
omy with sustainable scale, just distribution, and efficient allocation.
Of course, to know how policies work, we have to know how the
macroeconomy works. One way of doing this might be to build on mi-
croeconomic principles to construct a model in which supply and demand
of all goods and services balances simultaneously. This approach would
extend the basic market equation presented in Chapter 8—MUxn*MPPax
= MUyn*MPPay—into a general equilibrium model encompassing all
goods (x, y, z . . .), all commodities (a, b, c . . .), and all consumers (n, m,
o . . .). Such a model can easily become overwhelming. A thousand si-
multaneous equations with a thousand unknowns is hard to come into
mental contact with. It does show that everything depends on everything
else, which is interesting and usefully humbling, but it is also crippling
from a policy perspective to have to face the implication that in order to
predict anything, you have first to know everything. But a smaller system
of two or three or five especially important aggregate sectors interacting
through two or three or five simultaneous equations that reflect key be-
havior can aid the understanding and give basic policy insights. This is the
kind of model that most macroeconomists have sought. They still look at
the whole economy, but they divide it into fewer but larger aggregate
321