Blum Moral Perception and Particularity
Blum Moral Perception and Particularity
Blum Moral Perception and Particularity
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics.
http://www.jstor.org
Moral Perceptionand Particularity*
LawrenceBlum
701
702 Ethics July1991
the gap between moral rules (and principles)and particularsituations.
I will show that the phenomenon of moraljudgment does speak to an
importantlacuna in principle-basedtheoriesof morality.Yet I will also
explore the limitations-as a wayof capturingwhatis missingin theories
which focus only on the general or the universal-of the metaphor of
"bridgingthe gap between the general and the particular."
Thus moral perception,I willargue, cannot be identifiedwithmoral
judgment. In a given situation moral perception comes on the scene
prior to moral judgment; moral perception can lead to moral action
outsidetheoperationofjudgmententirely;and, moregenerally,perception
involvesmoral capacitiesnot encompassed by moraljudgment.I willalso
argue that moral perception should not be conceived of as a unified
capacity,butthatitinvolvesmultifarious moraland psychological processes.
Finally,while I willbe criticizingprinciple-basedtheoriesforfailing
to recognize the importanceof the operation of moral perception and
moraljudgment, the boundaries are not sharp between those capacities
involved in moral perception and judgment and those more commonly
associated with the moral agent portrayedin principle-basedtheories
(rationality,commitmentto principles,sense of duty,testingmaximsfor
moralacceptability, and thelike).Moral perceptionis formedand informed
by our general values and principles,and the converse is true as well.
I willnot be discussingimpartialityper se but,rather,a featureoften
(though perhaps not necessarily) connected with it-namely, action-
guiding principleas the heart of morality.Principle-basedethical views
need not be "impartialist";W. D. Ross (The Rightand the Good) is an
example. However,at the end I willmake some briefremarksconnecting
my critiquewithother familiarcritiquesof impartialistviews.
I willbegin withthreeexamples of the operationof moralperception
in particularsituationsand willdrawon thesein thesubsequentdiscussion.
I
Example1. -John and Joan are sittingridingon a subwaytrain.There
are no emptyseats and some people are standing;yetthe subwaycar is
not packed so tightlyas to be uncomfortablefor everyone. One of the
passengersstandingis a woman in her thirtiesholding two relativelyfull
shopping bags. John is not particularlypaying attentionto the woman,
but he is cognizant of her.
Joan,by contrast,is distinctlyaware thatthe woman is uncomfortable.
Thus differentaspects of the situationare "salient" forJohn and Joan.
That is, whatis fullyand explicitlypresenttoJohn'sconsciousnessabout
the woman is thatshe is standingholding some bags; but what is in that
sense salient forJoan is the woman's discomfort.That an aspect of a
situationis not salientforan agent does not mean she is entirelyunaware
of it. She could be aware of it in a less than fullyexplicitway. One can
imagine, for example, that Joan asks John, "Does that woman seem
uncomfortableto you?" This question mighthave the effectof making
Blum Moral Perception 703
Johnrealizethatat some levelhe had been awareofthewoman'sdiscomfort
all along but thathe had failed fullyto take it in. This mightbe because
he simplywas not paying more attentionto the situation.
It seems natural here to talk of awareness of a situation,or of an
aspect of it, existing"at differentlevels." An aspect or feature can be
more or less salientfor,or "takenin" by,an agent. This notionof salience,
admittingof degrees, preservesthisidea; by contrast,thatof "perceiving
situationsunder differentdescriptions"-sometimes used to express the
way the same situationcan be seen differently by differentperceivers
does not readilydo so. (This is not meant to deny that some aspect of
a situationnot encompassed in an agent's salience-consciousnesscould
be totallyoutside of the perceiver'sawareness.)3
In thissituation,the differencebetweenwhat is salientforJohn and
forJoan is of moral significance.Joan salientlyperceives(hereafterI will
just say "perceives") the woman's good (i.e., her comfort)as at stake in
a way that John does not. Joan perceives a morallyrelevant value at
stake,whileJohn does not.
One morally significantaspect of this differenceis the way that
perceptionis the settingforaction.John's perceptionprovideshim with
no reason to offerto help thewoman.4Whereas,in involvingthewoman's
good, Joan's perception of the situation already provides her with a
reason for action not based in her self-interest or projects.
But the moral significanceof the differencebetween John's and
Joan's perception of the situationlies not only in the relation between
that perception and the takingof beneficentaction. It lies in the factof
perceptionitself.We can see thismore clearlyif we imagineJohn's and
Joan's perceptionsto be fairlytypicalof each of them.John, let us say,
oftenfailsto take in people's discomfort,whileJoan is characteristically
sensitiveto such discomfort.It is thus in characterforthe discomfortto
be salientforJoan but not forJohn. That is to say, a morallysignificant
aspect of situationsfacingJohn fails to be salient for him, and this is a
3. Note that to speak of a feature of a situationas "salient" for an agent does not
(necessarily)mean thatthe agent takes thatfeatureto be action-warranting. It only means
thatthe given featureoccupies the agent's most explicitlevel of consciousnessconcerning
the situation. I mean for perceptual salience to provide the settingin which an agent
decides to act but not to be definitionallytied to action or reasons for action. A salient
perceptionof some morallysignificantaspect of a situationcould in some situationsinform
sympathy,indignation,or regretyetnot action. In factit mightbe misleadinghere to refer
to the "agent" the way I am doing (but I can thinkof no bettersingleterm).For the aspect
of the individual as a full moral person withwhich I am concerned here is not so much
her agency but somethingwhich takes place prior to her takingherselfto be called upon
to exercise that agency. Unless she already perceives her situationin a certainway in the
firstplace, she will not engage her agency. See n. 8 below.
4. This may be overstated.John might believe that out of politeness he as a male
should give up his seat for a female, or for an older female, and he mightofferher his
seat forthisreason. One mightor mightnotcall such an act of politenessmorallysignificant,
but in any case it would be a differentmoral significancethan to offerher the seat out of
a perception of her discomfort.
704 Ethics July1991
defectin his character- perhaps not a veryserious moral defect,but a
defectnevertheless.5 He missessomethingof the moralrealityconfronting
him.
Again, the deficiencylies not only in his failureto act. For we can
contrastwithJohn someone who does perfectlyclearlyperceive other
people's discomfortbut is totallyunmoved by it; he simplydoes not care,
and thisis whyhe does not offerto help. John,as I am envisioninghim,
is not callous and uncaringin thisway.We can imagine him as someone
who,when others'discomfortis broughtto hisattention,is as sympathetic
and willingto offerhelp as a person of average moral sensitivities.His
failureto act stemsfromhis failureto see (withthe appropriatesalience),
not fromcallousness about other people's discomfort.His deficiencyis
a situationalself-absorptionor attentionallaziness.6So thereis a different
moral significanceto "failingto act" depending on the characteror ex-
planation of thatfailure.(To say thatmoral perceptionis of significance
in its own rightis not to take a stand on whetherit is betterto perceive
and not to act than not to perceive in the firstplace. Accurate moral
perceptionis a good in its own right,but like other moral goods it is so
only ceterisparibus.)
Example2. -Theresa is the administratorof a department.One of
her subordinates,Julio, has been strickenwitha debilitatingcondition
in his leg causing him frequent pain. He approaches Theresa to help
work out a plan by which the company and in particularshe and his
divisioncan accommodate his disability.Theresa is unable to appreciate
Julio'sdisabilityand the impactitis havingon hiswork.While in principle
Theresa accepts the company's legal obligation requirementto accom-
modate to Julio's disability,in factshe continuallyoffersJulio less than
he needs and is entitledto.
More generally, Theresa makes Julio feel uncomfortablein ap-
proachingher and giveshim the impressionthatshe thinkshe is perhaps
too self-pityingand should just "pull himselftogether."It is not that
Theresa failsentirelyto see Julio as "disabled" and as "in pain," but she
does fail fullyto grasp what thismeans forhim and failsfullyto take in
12. Larmore, p. 5.
13. DiscussingAristotle'saccount of deliberation,David Wigginspointsout thatmuch
deliberationis not an attemptto findthe best means to a given end, but a search for the
"best specification"of that end. David Wiggins, "Deliberation and Practical Reason," in
Essayson Aristotle's Ethics,ed. A. Rorty(Berkeley: Universityof CaliforniaPress, 1980), p.
228. My point here is that knowinghow best to apply a principle(whichone already sees
as applicable to a givensituation)to the situationrequiresa kindof moraljudgment neither
encompassed nor guaranteed by the possession of the principle itself.It is a form of
judgment involvedwithgrasping the morallysignificantparticularsof a given situation.
14. For a more detailed argumentforthe view thatdifferentmoral capacitiesmay be
broughtintoplayin applyinga principlethanin comingto hold the principle,see Lawrence
Blum, "Gilligan and Kohlberg: Issues for Moral Theory," Ethics98 (1988): 485-86.
710 Ethics July1991
Kant's notion of "imperfectduties."15 In contrastto "perfect"duties,
imperfectduties (such as beneficence)do not prescribea specificaction
in a specificsituation; they prescribethe adoption of a general end or
maxim (e.g., the happiness of others) but do not specifyexactlyhow or
towardwhom the beneficentactions are to be carriedout. On one inter-
pretation,it is morally indifferentwhen and how one carries out the
duty-for example, helping others-as long as one does so on some
(appropriate) occasions.16 Such a view would appear to implythatthere
is no distinctivelymoral work to be done in choosing when to act from
imperfectdutyand in knowinghow to do so. Since thescope of imperfect
duties is verygreat,this could be taken as a defense of the view thatan
ethic of principleis adequate to cover virtuallythe entiredomain of the
moral life.
But this view of duty neglectsthat it is in facta moral matter,and
not merelyone of personal preferenceor moral indifference,how one
carriesout a dutyor precept. It takes moral sensitivity (a) to know what
counts as exemplifyingparticularmoral principles,(b) to know when it
is and is not appropriate to instantiategivenprinciples,and (c) to be able
oneself to carryout the action in question (e.g., of being beneficent).
This sensitivitygoes beyond possessing the principle (plus the strength
of will to act on it); it is neither guaranteed nor encompassed by the
commitmentto the principle (plus strengthof will) itself.
My argument here is meant not as a critique of the notion of an
"imperfectduty" but only to show that a distinctcapacity for moral
judgment,as the abilityto bringprincipleto bear on particularsituations,
is needed for moral agents to produce action in accord with imperfect
duties. While Kant recognized the need for such moral judgment, he
did not appear to regard this capacityas a distinctlymoral one, and, at
least in his major ethical writings,seemed to think his moral theory
complete withoutan account of what is specificallyinvolved in (moral)
judgment.
A second feature of moral judgment not generally taken up by
philosophersin the principle-basedtraditionsis the recognitionof features
of a situationas having moral significanceand thus as being features
whichmustbe takenintoaccountin constructing a principlefullyadequate
20. The collapsing of the significanceof moral perception into judgment of right
action-and a consequentmaskingofitsfullvalue-is particularly strikinginJohnMcDowell's
influentialarticle "Virtue and Reason" (Monist62 [1979]: 331-50). For McDowell, citing
Iris Murdoch,givesa centralrole to perceptionin ethics.He rightlyconnectstheimportance
of perception to the limitationsof an ethic of articulatablerules or procedures, arguing
(followingAristotle)thatrules cannot capture the fullmoral sensibilityof a person of good
character.McDowell speaks of sensitivities to aspectsof moralrealityas (in a givensituation)
being "salient" for the agent. In doing so he points toward the Murdochian view that
awareness of moral realityis a moral task and accomplishmentin its own rightand action
is only one part of the appropriate response to the perceivingof moral reality.However,
as McDowell develops his argument,the notions of perception,salience, and sensitivity
become defined solelyin termsof the generatingof rightactions.What is to be perceived
becomes, for McDowell, thatconsiderationin a situationthe actingon whichwill produce
rightaction (cf. p. 331 and elsewhere). The notion of salience is cashed out as that moral
considerationamong all those present which would be picked out as the one to act on if
the agent is to engage in rightaction.Lost is theidea of moralrealitytheaccurateperception
of whichis both morallygood in itsown rightand also providesthe settingin whichmoral
response in its broadest sense takes place. Early in the article(p. 332) McDowell speaks of
"specialized sensitivities"to differentaspects of moral reality.(I discuss thisissue below in
714 Ethics July1991
To summarize:There are threeimportantly distinctmoraloperations
omittedfromtraditionalprinciple-basedaccounts of ethics and needed
at least to supplement it: (1) perceiving (what are in fact the morally
significant)featuresof a situationconfrontingone (includingherein the
perceptual individuatingof the 'situation'as a morallysignificantone in
the firstplace); (2) recognizingthose featuresas morallysignificantones,
to be taken into account in deliberatingabout what to do-specifically
about whichprinciplesgovernthesituation;(3) knowinghow to implement
the principlesone takes to be conclusive in determiningwhat to do-
discerningwhatactionsconstitutethe best specification of thoseprinciples.
And thereare twowaysthatmoral perceptionrevealsa limitto principles
themselves:(1) moral perception,and action stemmingfromit, can go
on outsidethe contextof principlesentirely;(2) accuratemoral perception
is good in its own right.
IV
Let us returnto somethingthatCharles Larmore saysabout "judgment."
Larmore says that Aristotlehimselfhad littleto say about the way in
whichsuchjudgment is exercised-only thatitis acquired by experience
and practice. Yet Larmore does not regard this absence as a defect in
Aristotle'sview. For he agrees that,"although we can understandwhat
kindsof situationscall formoraljudgment, the kindsof tasksthatmoral
judgment is to accomplish,and the preconditionsforitsacquisition,there
24. The character of Mrs. Hoffman in Carol Ascher's The Flood (Freedom, Calif.:
Crossing Press, 1987) is a wonderfulexample of someone compassionate toward anyone
she is able to see as a victimof discrimination,or as a kind of refugee (e.g., due to the
flood), but oftenuncompassionate,insensitive,and harsh to others.
Blum Moral Perception 717
This oversimplificationand overunificationof moral/psychicphe-
nomena is not confined to discussions of the limitationsof an ethic of
rule and principle.One can see it also in philosophies which centeron
emotion-basedphenomena such as sympathyor empathy.My discussion
suggeststhatsympathyand empathyare in a sense themselvesnot unitary
phenomenabut,rather,collectionsof at leastsomewhatdistinctsensitivities
to differentaspects of other people's well-being (discomfort,physical
pain,thehurtofinjustice,thehurtofdisappointment, etc.).One implication
of thisis thatwhen moralphilosophersand educatorstalkabout cultivating
sympathyand empathy, accomplishing this will involve nurturingor
developing some distinctsensitivitiesand willinvolvedifferenttasksand
processesfordifferentpersonswithrespectto different objectsof sympathy
or empathy.25
Larmore's idea that "practicaljudgment" is a unitaryfacultyabout
whichlittlecan be said (since it depends on intuitingparticulars)accom-
panies the idea that the only way one can improve one's capacity for
such judgment is through practice and habit. There is nothing to tell
people about how to exercisejudgment; one simplyhas to "do it." But
seeing the multifariousnature of practicaljudgment as perception of
particularsboth throwslighton the ways and extentto which practice
and habit do teach practicaljudgment and also broadens the methods
by which people can learn to perceive particulars.
Iris Murdoch'snotionof an "obstacle"(discussedabove),whichdistorts
or blocks accurate perception of moral reality,is helpful here. Such
obstacles may preventan individual frombeing able to learn fromex-
perience and practice how to perceive and judge well in some area of
life.For example, Theresa maydeal withmanypeople who have physical
pain yetmay never get any betterat graspingwhatis going on withthem
and judging what to do about it. Her own unconscious resistance to
opening herselfto others' physicalpain may constitutean obstacle not
only to accurate perceptionbut also to learning in the way suggestedin
25. E. V. Spelman, "The Virtue of Feeling and the Feeling of Virtue," in Feminist
Ethics:New Essays,ed. C. Card (Lawrence: UniversityPress of Kansas, 1991), develops this
point in connection with race and class differenceswithinthe same gender. She argues
that persons (and in particularwomen) who are caring and concerned toward others of
theirown race and class may yetnot be so towardwomen of otherraces and classes. Owen
Flanagan and KathrynJackson,"Justice,Care, and Gender: The Kohlberg-GilliganDebate
Revisited,"Ethics97 (1987): 622-37, make the point that several distinctmoral capacities
mightwell be part of what Gilligan calls the moralityof care. See also Owen Flanagan,
VarietiesofMoral Personality: Realism(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
Ethicsand Psychological
UniversityPress, 1991), chaps. 9-11, for an importantassessmentof Gilligan's work. In
"Three Mythsof Moral Theory" (in Rorty,Mind in Action[Boston: Beacon, 1988], p. 291),
Amelie Rortynotes the diversityof attitudescovered by conceptslike "respect"and "love."
In general, Rorty'swork (in the above volume and elsewhere) is an importantsource of
insight into the multifariousnature of moral sentiments,attitudes,and virtues,and a
caution against the oversimplificationof the realm of moral psychologyfound in much
moral theory.
718 Ethics July1991
Aristotle'sidea of habit, practice,and experience.26Coming directlyto
grip with one's obstacles may in some cases be necessaryfor opening
oneself to certainaspects of one's moral reality,as well as to being able
to learn from experience and practice. Theresa may need to work
through-perhaps in some formof therapy-her deep and partlyun-
conscious association of physicalpain withweakness,though Murdoch
herselfwould be suspicious of such therapy,and, more generally,of any
attemptto come to gripswithone's moral obstaclesby focusingexplicitly
on them.27Yet Murdoch's pessimismabout moral change in the face of
such obstacles,though insightfulabout the dangers of self-absorptionin
the attemptto rid oneself of that veryself-absorption, seems overdone.
Progress in workingthrough and mitigatingthese moral obstacles can
be made.28
V
I want brieflyto situate the criticisms(developed through considering
moral perceptionand particularity)that I have made of principle-based
ethicaltheoriesin relationto some otherimportantand influential
criticisms
also made of impartialistor principle-basedviews: (1) Those whichchal-
formof moralprinciples-forexample,byclaiming
lenge the (impartialist)
thatsome principlesrequiregreatermoralconcerntowardpersonsrelated
to us.29 (2) Those addressing the relativeforceof moral and nonmoral
considerations(e.g., connected with the notion of a "personal point of
view"),criticizingimpartialismforthe assumptionthatimpartialmorality
necessarilytakes precedence over all other practical standpoints.30(3)
38. This point is argued in Nancy Sherman, "The Place of Emotions in Kantian
Morality,"in Identity,
Character, and Morality:Essaysin Moral Psychology,
ed. Owen Flanagan
and Amelie 0. Rorty(Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1990).
39. Position C (as well as B) can be found in Herman, pp. 426-28.
724 Ethics July1991
principlethat one should treatothers as ends encompasses the psychic
capacity which leads the agent to perceive distresswhen it is present.
Hence Kantian notions would not have fullyaccounted for moral per-
ception.
Yet, if positionA is abandoned, it is difficultto see the plausibility
of the other view, C2, either. Rationalityin one's maxims, testingfor
universalizability, and the like do not seem to capture what it is about
someone that makes her sensitiveto other persons' distressor able to
discernthe best specificationof a principleofjustice.These seem distinct
(though related) aspects of an individual's moral economy. Perhaps a
better candidate would be (again) 'treatingsomeone as an end. Yet if
whatone means by thisis commitmentto the principleof treatingothers
as ends, then such a commitmentwill guarantee neither seeing when
the principleis applicable (i.e., perception),nor knowingexactlythe best
way to implementthat principleeven when one sees thatit is applicable
(i.e.,judgment). On the other hand, if one includes the lattercapacities
withinone's verynotion of "treatingas an end," then one willhave made
C2 true only by definitionalfiat,ratherthan actuallydemonstratingthe
Kantian characterof the capacities of perceptionand judgment.
It mightbe worthexploringin the contextof a specificexample the
idea that sensitivity to an issue of principleguarantees perceptionof all
significant moral features of situations.
In the cab drivercase, let us imagine that as Tim thinksabout the
driver'saction he comes to see it as racist,unjust, and wrong. He sees
that the action violates principles of justice. Contrast Tim here with
Yasuko, who like Tim perceivesthe wrongnessof the cab driver'saction,
but in addition directlyperceivesthe indignitydone to the black woman
passed up by the driver.So Tim perceives the injustice-the violation
of principle-without perceivingthe indignityto the person who suffers
theinjustice.As thisexampleillustrates, itis possibleto graspthewrongness
of an unjust action withoutactuallyregisteringor takingin the affront
to dignitysustained by the suffererof the injustice.
If this is so it calls into question the idea that sensitivity
to actions
as violating principle (e.g., a principle of injustice) guarantees or can
account for sensitivityto the indignitysufferedby the victimsof the
violation of that principle. Thus it calls into question the idea that the
Kantian capacityforrecognizingviolationsof principleencompasses or
guarantees the perceptual sensitivityto the morallysignificantfeature,
the sufferingof indignity.40