Crumley II - Cap 2 - Anaysis of Knowledge
Crumley II - Cap 2 - Anaysis of Knowledge
Crumley II - Cap 2 - Anaysis of Knowledge
53
Review Copy
54 an Introduction to Epistemology
the same place. If both knowledge and true opinion get you to the same
place, if they both get you to the right answer, why worry about having
knowledge? Why not simply settle for true belief? There doesn’t seem to be
any difference between them.
Socrates, however, is impressed by the fact that true opinions have a
disturbing tendency to “fly away”; under pressure we may give up true
opinions. Perhaps you have also had the experience of having a true belief,
but for various reasons, such as the influence of friends, you changed your
mind and subsequently had a false belief, or gave the wrong answer. Now,
Socrates thinks that our true beliefs are less likely to fly away if they are
appropriately tied down. Our ability to tie down a true belief is merely
our ability to give an account, or an explanation of why we think that our
belief is the right or correct belief. Knowledge is distinguished from true
belief by this ability to give an account or explanation. Thus, knowledge is
true belief plus the account, in Plato’s view.
Many twentieth-century epistemologists adapted Plato’s view and
explained knowledge as justified true belief. It is this analysis of the con-
cept of knowledge—the justified true belief analysis—that is called the tra-
ditional analysis of the concept of knowledge.1 Prior to 1963, hardly anyone
actually used the terminology of the traditional analysis; very few actually
explained knowledge as justified true belief. After 1963, the widespread,
but not unanimous, opinion has been that the traditional analysis is not
quite right. Epistemologists thus have a tradition with little history and not
much of a future! Nevertheless, it is plausible to think that the common
core of various theories of knowledge is justified true belief. Thus, in the
previous chapter, we noticed that one way of understanding the concept of
knowledge is as follows:
(1) P is true.
(2) The subject or agent believes that P .
(3) P is infallible.
Notice that conditions (1) and (2) require that knowledge be at least
true belief. But it is perhaps plausible to think of condition (3) as specifying
the requirement for the justification of a true belief. Descartes could thus
be read as claiming that for a true belief to count as knowledge, it must
not be possible for the belief to be mistaken. More succinctly, infallibility
is the type or kind of justification required for knowledge. So, we might
1 Like the Meno, the Theaetetus provides an apparent formulation of the justified true
belief analysis. At 201c and following, Socrates distinguishes knowledge from true
opinion, and he subsequently seems to identify knowledge with true opinion plus
speech or a rationale. Both are widely available, including in Plato 1961a and Plato
1961b. Of course, one cannot do better than reading Plato’s dialogues, but three
accessible surveys and interpretations are Taylor 1926, White 1976, and Gosling,
1973.
Review Copy
Chapter Two An Introduction to the Analysis of Knowledge 55
Truth Conditions
We are specifically interested in the analysis of the concept of propositional
knowledge. Propositional knowledge differs, for example, from procedural
knowledge, or knowing how. Knowing how seems to involve a particular
skill or ability, as in knowing how to ride a bike or how to find a bit of
information on the Internet. But the focus of the traditional analysis is
knowing that. For example, Sara knows that Gödel proved the incomplete-
ness theorems. The object of Sara’s knowledge is a certain proposition or
sentence. The content of her knowledge, what she knows, is given by the
proposition or sentence “Gödel proved the incompleteness theorems.”
More generally, and somewhat schematically, the traditional or stan-
dard analysis attempts to provide the truth conditions for the general sort
of statement we’ll call (K ): “S knows that P ,” where “S ” stands for a per-
son and “P ” stands for the object or content of the person’s knowledge.
Epistemologists are attempting to give a perfectly general analysis. They
want to say what is true of any person when that person has propositional
knowledge. Somewhat formally, the aim of an analysis of the concept of
propositional knowledge is to provide the necessary and sufficient condi-
tions for the truth of (K ). Less formally, the idea is to state under what con-
ditions an agent knows something. We want to know what it is about the
agent or the agent’s situation that makes it the case that the agent knows
and is not, say, just guessing.
Notice that when we ask this sort of question about the appropriate
analysis, we are asking a different sort of question than asking when an
agent is justified in claiming that he or she knows. For example, I might
be justified in claiming to know that the test will be given on Wednesday,
Review Copy
56 an Introduction to Epistemology
but for various reasons I cannot foresee, the test may be postponed until
Friday. Nobody knows P if P is false. Hence, although I was justified in
claiming to know, it turns out that I did not in fact know.
One way to express this distinction is to say that we are interested in
the truth conditions of (K ), but not necessarily the assertibility conditions
of (K ). The assertibility conditions of knowledge specify when someone is
justified in claiming to have knowledge, regardless of whether that person
actually knows. The truth conditions of (K ), the necessary and sufficient
conditions for knowledge, are the conditions under which someone does
in fact have knowledge. Analyses of the concept of knowledge are typically
concerned with the truth conditions of the concept, not the assertibility
conditions. Providing the truth conditions of (K ) is a way of explaining the
nature of knowledge, of explaining in what knowledge consists.
(K A-1) P is true.
(K A-2) S is sure that P.
(K A-3) S has the right to be sure that P .2
Theories of Truth
Philosophers disagree about the nature of truth. One recent classification
distinguishes between nonepistemic and epistemic theories of truth. This
parallels, in some respects, the distinction between realist and nonrealist
views of the world. Nonepistemic theories of truth hold that the truth
of a proposition depends on the way the world is, independently of our
beliefs about the world. (Notice: Even your beliefs are part of the world.)
Epistemic theories hold that the truth of a proposition depends on our
beliefs about the world.
A more traditional classification distinguishes between correspondence,
coherence, and pragmatic views of truth. Roughly, correspondence theo-
ries hold that a proposition is true if and only if the proposition matches or
corresponds to the way the world is (or at least the part of the world rel-
evant to the proposition, sometimes called a “state of affairs”). Coherence
theories hold that a proposition is true if and only if it fits or coheres with
a system of propositions. Pragmatic theories claim that a proposition is
true if “it works,” that is, if acting or believing on the basis of that proposi-
tion produces the right sort of consequences.
For the purposes of this text, we assume a realist view and a correspon-
dence theory of truth. See “For Further Study.”
Notice that someone might “feel sure” of some belief, but for reasons
that have little or nothing to do with the truth of the belief. A person who
holds a belief based on mere superstition might nonetheless feel sure. Sam
might feel sure that his having a flat tire is due to his having walked under
a ladder. But such confidence is rarely a guide to the truth. Thus, one might
object to the psychological construal on the grounds that what we are
interested in is the epistemological issues concerning the concept of knowl-
edge, not the psychological issues. We need instead an explanation of why
a psychological state is an indication of the epistemic status of the belief.
Is the belief merely a good guess? Does it qualify as knowledge? Suppose
that Sam studied diligently for his upcoming logic test and answered all
the questions correctly. But suppose also that Sam has never been terribly
confident of his abilities in “abstract symbol” courses. Further suppose that
were you to show Sam incorrect uses of, say, De Morgan’s Rule, he would
not be inclined to change the answers he gave on the test. Indeed, Sam
checks his answers carefully and does not change any of them; nonetheless,
Sam is reluctant to say he did well.
Sam’s lack of confidence, in the preceding example, might indicate that
he does not think he has the best of reasons for giving the answers he has.
Review Copy
Chapter Two An Introduction to the Analysis of Knowledge 59
Thus, for this way of thinking about “being sure,” we might argue that a
person must believe that he has good reasons for holding the belief.
This line of thinking raises important issues, some of which we will
address shortly. But notice that this way of understanding “being sure” has,
in effect, introduced two new considerations for knowing: (a) the person
must have good reasons, and (b) the person must think that such reasons
are good reasons. Both of these must be considered in their turn. Note,
however, that the belief condition—that S believes that P —and consider-
ations (a) and (b) are logically independent of one another. Because they
are logically independent, it would perhaps be best to treat them separately.
We will, in fact, have to look at putative conditions for knowing like (a)
and (b), but for now, we rest content with the idea that (K A-2) should be
revised to read simply:
“Having the right to be sure” implies that whatever grounds the agent’s
confidence must be an adequate ground. That is, not just anything will
legitimate the agent’s confidence. This suggests that there is an important
normative component in knowledge, that an agent’s belief must in some
way satisfy a certain standard. How exactly this normative component is
to be explicated remains to be seen.
We noticed in considering condition (K A-2) that the idea of confidence
or sureness raised the issue of the reasons for the agent’s belief. So, one of
the things that we might view (K A-3) as suggesting is that in some as yet
unspecified sense, the agent must be justified in believing that P , where
“justification” means “having good reasons.”
A brief note on “having good reasons”: There are clearly inadequate
reasons for having a belief. Suppose Sam believes, as a result of consult-
ing a fortune-teller at a county fair, that he will someday be president.
Sam has a reason for his belief. But we might be reluctant to think that
this is a good reason, that the fortune-teller’s musings provide sufficient
evidence for Sam’s belief. More to the point, it is not a good reason if Sam
is interested in believing the truth and avoiding believing things that are
false. Compare this type of case with Sara’s belief that there will be a test
tomorrow. Imagine that she believes this because the test is scheduled on
the syllabus and the teacher reminded her of the test. We would be inclined
to think that Sara’s belief is based on good reasons.
At a minimum Ayer’s third condition suggests that the agent must have
good reasons for believing that P . That Sara studied diligently is a good
reason for her to believe that a particular answer is correct (assuming the
normal things we do about studying). However, condition (K A-3) leaves
open whether the agent must recognize that the reasons are good reasons
or whether it’s enough that the agent merely have good reasons, recognized
as such or not. Descartes offers an explicit version of the former sort of
view. His “indubitability” criterion indicates not only a reason for having
the belief but also the recognition by the agent of the indubitability as a
reason for having the belief. Indeed, the classical conception of knowledge
is one in which an agent not only has good reasons but recognizes that the
reasons are good.
On the other hand, to some people, this latter constraint, explicitly rec-
ognizing the reasons as good reasons, might seem too strong. We cannot
yet fully explain why some might want to opt for this weaker version of
the condition, but we should be aware of it in our formulation of the third
condition.
For the time being, we can avoid deciding between the stronger and the
weaker versions of condition (K A-3), and say merely that the agent must
be justified in believing that P . As we noticed early in the chapter, Socrates
distinguished mere true belief from knowledge. He did so by appealing to
the notion of a person having an account or explanation for the belief. This
account or explanation is roughly equivalent to our notion of justification.
Review Copy
Chapter Two An Introduction to the Analysis of Knowledge 61
The reasons for a person’s belief provide the justification for the belief.
Knowledge is more than a lucky guess; it is more than mere true belief.
We are unwilling to credit someone with knowledge unless the person
has acquired the belief by “one of the accredited routes to knowledge.”5
This provides us with a schema by which to approach the analysis of the
concept of knowledge:
(K ) S knows that P if and only if:
(1) P is true.
(2) S believes that P .
(3) S is justified in believing that P .
Gettier-type Counterexamples
Gettier’s own examples are straightforward enough, but we will consider
two other examples of the same type, the first offered by Keith Lehrer.8
Lehrer asks us to imagine a case in which an agent, the ubiquitous S ,
has a coworker, Ms. Nogot. Now, S has good reason to believe that Nogot
owns a Ford; imagine, for example, that S has seen Nogot driving a Ford,
S has been told by persons who have in the past been reliable that Nogot
owns a Ford, and so on. Hence, S has justification for her belief that Nogot
owns a Ford, and from this she infers her belief that P —someone in the
office owns a Ford. But Ms. Nogot does not own a Ford. Nevertheless, S ’s
belief that someone in the office owns a Ford is true, because Ms. Havit
owns a Ford.
Notice that S has a justified true belief. The belief that someone in the
office owns a Ford is true. Moreover, S had good evidence for arriving at
this belief. That is, S is justified in believing that P . But it is not obvious
that we would want to say in this case that S has knowledge. We might
think that S has been a bit lucky. It just so happened that someone owned
a Ford, but not the person S thought owned the Ford. S has reasons, but
we might think that S doesn’t have the right sort of reasons.
10 Shope 1983 lists some ninety-eight such counterexamples that have appeared in the
literature.
Review Copy
64 an Introduction to Epistemology
11 Johnson 1980.
Review Copy
Chapter Two An Introduction to the Analysis of Knowledge 65
After the publication of Gettier’s paper, the task was to amend the JTB
analysis in such a way as to preclude Gettier cases. We are concerned here
with only a small and influential sample of the various specific proposals.
Our aim is to get a general sense of the motivation and structure of these
proposals, as well as with major difficulties each encountered. Here we
consider three views: causal theories, indefeasibility theories, and the no-
false-premise view. In the next chapter, we will consider in more detail a
view known as reliabilism.
A General Diagnosis
It will be helpful to begin by giving at least a general account of what goes
wrong in Gettier-type cases. As we already noted, Gettier cases show that
as it stands, the JTB analysis permits that what accounts for the justifica-
tion of the target belief (the belief that is a putative instance of knowledge)
is not what accounts for the truth of the target belief. An agent’s evidence
or reasons for a belief may not adequately reflect the circumstances that
underlie the truth of the belief. For example, S ’s reasons for believing that
someone owns a Ford have no obvious connection to the truth of that
belief. In a sense, S has evidence, but it is the wrong evidence for the belief
that she has.
12 Robert Shope, Shope 1983, suggests that there are Gettier-type examples to which
even Johnson’s logical interpretation falls prey. Such counterexamples do not depend
explicitly on the appeal to a false proposition.
Review Copy
66 an Introduction to Epistemology
But you might wonder why this is a bad thing, especially given that we
have apparently rejected the obvious solution: the entailment strategy. We
can perhaps see what is at issue here by considering what we expect from
our concept of knowledge. If the entailment strategy is too stringent a cri-
terion, what weaker demands can we make?
Gettier cases give us some hint of what we might expect from a satis-
factory analysis of the concept of knowledge. The moral of Gettier cases
might be this: Gettier-type cases suggest that a belief might be justified and
true, but had things been just a little different, we might have had a false
belief. In some sense, it was merely good fortune or a happy accident that
we arrived at a true belief.13 Thus, in the Lehrer case, for all the evidence
our omnipresent S had, it still might have been false that anyone, includ-
ing Havit, owned a Ford. Or, S might simply have chosen not to make the
existential generalization, in which case S would have had the false, yet
justified belief that Ms. Nogot owns a Ford.14 Similarly, in Goldman’s case,
it was just good fortune that the father pointed to an actual barn, rather
than to a mere barn facade. Consequently, a plausible approach for dealing
with the counterexamples is to find a way to amend the JTB analysis that
limits the possibility of our having a false belief. To put it slightly differ-
ently, we might look for an analysis that ties our justification more closely
to the truth of the belief, such that it is less of an accident that the belief
turns out true, given the evidence the agent has. With this in mind, let us
turn to the more specific proposals.
Causal Theories
Causal theories are a remarkably clever way of resolving the “accidentality
problem.” As we will see, they involve a subtly different understanding of
the justification condition. Roughly, causal theories of knowledge hold that
a belief is an instance of knowledge if the belief is true and is caused in
the right way. Of course, we need to know something more about what it
means to be caused in the right way. For the moment, we can motivate the
causal theory by explaining how we can move from our more traditional
understanding of the justification condition to the causal theorist’s under-
standing of the analysis of knowledge.15
13 For a recent example of a defense of the “anti-luck” view of knowledge, see Heller
1999, pp. 115–129.
14 Existential generalization is the move from a specific case (Nogot) to a more general,
indefinite “someone.” Some have thought that the way to preclude Gettier-type
examples is to restrict such logical moves. This seems a bit arbitrary, and there are
examples that do not clearly depend on such inferences.
15 It should be noted that Goldman does not consider his causal analysis to be an
interpretation of the justification condition. See Alvin Goldman 1970, pp. 67–87,
esp. p. 84. The aim in the following paragraphs is to motivate the causal analysis, to
see how one might move from the traditional analysis to something like the causal
analysis.
Review Copy
Chapter Two An Introduction to the Analysis of Knowledge 67
ing of reasons as causal—that is, what caused the agent to believe that p.
In a more traditional view of “reason,” we might grant that an appropriate
causal connection exists between a fact and a belief, but we might not be
so willing to grant that an agent has a reason unless she is aware of this
causal connection. We can understand why she believes what she does, but
we might still ask whether she is justified in believing as she does.
Causal analyses of knowledge are explicit about the move from eviden-
tial to causal reasons. Marshall Swain, for example, distinguishes between
“causal” and “evidential” reasons, the latter being what we would be more
ordinarily inclined to think of as a reason.20 Swain acknowledges that evi-
dential reasons are sometimes causal reasons. However, he insists that the
relevant reasons for justification are causal reasons. Consider again the
belief that there is coffee in the cup. Clearly, a causal connection exists
between agent and cup, namely, perception. In the causal view, the fact of
this connection is enough to justify the agent’s belief; there is a reason for
the agent’s belief. In the evidential sense of reason, however, for the agent
to be justified, the existence of this causal connection is not enough. The
agent must also at the very least believe that this connection exists. The
causal theory counts the notion of causal reason as the primary sense of
reason. We will be especially interested in this kind of move as we turn to
reliability theories in the following chapter.
Indefeasibility Theories
A widely favored response to Gettier-type problems is some type of inde-
feasibility theory. In this view, knowledge requires indefeasible justification.
Roughly, an indefeasible justification is one for which there is no under-
mining evidence.
The motivation for this view lies in holding that what goes wrong in
Gettier cases is that the agent’s justification is somehow defective. It is true
that the agent’s belief is justified, that the agent has some evidence for the
belief. But there is other evidence that the agent does not possess. There are
other true propositions that the agent does not believe or recognize but that
are nonetheless relevant to the truth of target belief. This other evidence is
such that if the agent possessed it, the agent’s current belief would no lon-
ger be justified; the agent’s justification would be undermined. Thus, there
is a sense in which the agent’s justification is incomplete. The agent has
some evidence but lacks other evidence that would render the target belief
insufficiently justified to count as knowledge. This undermining evidence is
called defeating evidence. A justification is defeasible if and only if there is
defeating evidence. Hence, the sort of justification required for knowledge
is not simply justified true belief but also indefeasible justification.
does not have knowledge. Thus, we have to say that to have knowledge, S
must have a justification that is indefeasible—that there are no potential
defeaters lurking nearby. This means that S ’s actual or current justification
would have to be such that it screens out or blocks all potential defeaters.
Indefeasibility theorists do not require that an agent be able to show
that there are no defeaters. Nor do they require that the agent believe
there are no defeaters. Rather, for a justification to be indefeasible, these
theorists require merely that there in fact be no defeaters. Whether this fact
is reflected in the agent’s beliefs makes no difference to the defeasibility of
the agent’s justification. You might notice that this is a departure from a
more traditional conception of knowledge such as Descartes’. This sort of
departure proves to be somewhat controversial, and we will return to it.
But first, we need to consider how an indefeasibility condition might be
expressed.
A seemingly natural way to state such a condition is to claim that there
is no true proposition such that if it were added to S ’s justification, S would
no longer be justified. We should note just how strong a condition this is.
It claims that if there is any evidence that would, if believed by the agent,
undermine the justification, then the agent would no longer know. Thus,
according to this condition, the existence of even one defeater is sufficient
to preclude knowledge. Worse, it might seem as though even misleading
evidence could rule out knowledge.
Consider a slight modification of a case found in the literature. 22
Imagine that you attend a wedding of two close friends and that the cer-
emony is performed by a priest well known to you and the others at the
ceremony. The wedding is conducted and concluded without a hitch. On
the basis of this evidence, you come to believe that the couple is married.
Clearly, your belief is justified; you have every reason to think that you
know your friends are married. But let us suppose that unbeknownst to
you and the others present, including the priest, the bishop has gone crazy.
Among other things, the bishop falsely denounces the priest as a fraud.
Now, here is a true proposition: The bishop has denounced the priest as
a fraud. Were you aware of this proposition, you would not be justified
in believing your friends to be married, because fraudulent priests cannot
marry anyone, any more than fake barns can provide sanctuary for our
barnyard friends. Despite the apparent defeater, we are still tempted to say
that you know.
The crazy bishop case illustrates that a distinction must be drawn
between genuine and misleading defeaters. Misleading defeaters are defeat-
ers that can themselves be defeated; that is, still further evidence can be
obtained that would “restore” the original justification. What further evi-
dence defeats the defeater in the crazy bishop case? The bishop is crazy
seems a promising candidate.
Perhaps now we can see more clearly the connection between misleading
defeaters and indefeasible justifications. Misleading defeaters are true prop-
ositions. Yet when they are properly understood, they should not undermine
an adequate justification. For example, the true proposition that the bishop
denounced the priest as a fraud is, in a sense, not the whole story; we must
also consider the bishop’s insanity. So, there is some piece of information
out there showing that the defeater is misleading, that it does not actually
undermine the agent’s knowledge. By itself, the misleading defeater appears
to show that the agent does not have knowledge. But once the whole story
is revealed, it becomes clear that the agent does know.
Yet it is not easy to see exactly how to articulate the intuition that
knowledge is extendible or that we can acquire new information without
losing our original justification. We need a condition that will identify the
defeasible justifications but will not be so strong as to rule out knowledge
in those cases in which the defeaters are misleading defeaters. We can rule
Let us see if we can understand what Meyers has in mind. Again, sup-
pose that you have just witnessed the wedding of your friends. You believe
that they are married, and your justification for this belief is your belief
that a priest has performed the ceremony. You would thus appear to have
a justified true belief. But now you learn that the bishop denounced the
priest as a fraud. This new bit of information undermines the justification
for your belief about the wedding. You can “regain” your knowledge by
learning that the bishop is no longer trustworthy about certain matters.
But now it seems as though your justification is different. Previously, your
justification consisted of your belief that a priest performed the ceremony.
Your “new” justification seems to consist of your belief that a priest per-
formed the ceremony and that the bishop cannot be trusted.
Why does Meyers believe that the change in your justification matters?
Perhaps for something like the following reasons. Initially your original
justification appears to be enough or sufficient to give you knowledge. But
attempts to rule out misleading defeaters seem to have the result that your
original justification is not sufficient. Thus, indefeasibility analyses, which
attempt to deal with the problem of misleading defeaters, fail to distin-
guish between justifications that are defective and justifications that are
merely incomplete. In the former case, the agent is undermined by genuine
defeaters; the agent does not have adequate evidence, as in the Ford case.
In the latter case, the agent’s justification is adequate, but it simply does
not include the misleading defeater and the relevant counterevidence.
One might wonder whether conditions of knowledge should require an
agent’s justification include evidence sufficient to rule out any misleading
defeater. To require this would seem to be too strong a constraint. But the
indefeasibility theorist might suggest the following. A justification need not
include evidence sufficient to rule out misleading defeaters; it is only neces-
sary that the agent could acquire that evidence without changing or giving
up the beliefs that comprised the original justification. For example, in
learning that the bishop is crazy, you do not need to change your original
justification comprising various beliefs, including that Pierre and the made-
moiselle were married by the priest. Indeed, the new evidence vindicates
your original justification. This strategy seems to have some promise, but
we leave the matter here.
We can briefly recount the main features of indefeasibility views. We
sometimes fail to have knowledge in cases in which we have a justified true
belief because our justification is not quite good enough. We might have
done the best we could, given the evidence we possessed. Unbeknownst to
us, however, additional evidence or information is relevant to the target
belief. Were we to come to know about that evidence or information, we
would recognize that our original justification was inadequate; we would
no longer be justified with respect to our original belief. Hence, we do not
have knowledge in such cases.
Review Copy
Chapter Two An Introduction to the Analysis of Knowledge 75
No-False-Premise Views
Still another way to analyze Gettier cases is to note that the agent’s jus-
tification relies on a mistaken or false premise. In the Ford case, the false
premise is explicit: Nogot owns a Ford. In the barn case, the false premise
is more implicit but looks something like this: If it looks like a barn from
the highway, then it is a barn. (Another candidate is that there is nothing
unusual about the environment.) Thus, the fourth condition that might be
added to the JTB analysis is that the justification does not depend on any
false premises.28
As it stands, this proposed fourth condition is too strong. It may be that
an agent believes a false premise but that this premise does not, or need
not, play a central role in the agent’s justification, given what else the agent
believes. Consider a slight variation of the Ford case.
Suppose S believes that someone in the office owns a Ford because she
has seen the registration papers and seen Havit, who owns it, driving a
Ford. Suppose, however, S falsely believes that Havit bought the car at
East Ford. And suppose she infers that someone in the office owns a Ford
on the basis of her belief that Havit owns a Ford that was purchased from
East Ford.
We might nonetheless think that S knows that someone owns a Ford,
because where the car was purchased makes no difference to Havit own-
ing a Ford. The possibility of false but inessential premises requires some
explanation of what it means to say that a premise plays an essential
role in the justification. This further explanation centers on the idea that
the agent would not be justified in believing that P unless the agent also
believed some further proposition Q . The proposition Q is then said to be
essential to the agent’s justification.
There is a standard objection to this view. The idea behind this objec-
tion is that if an agent reasons cleverly enough, then the agent will not
be committed to believing any false premises. But such objections seem
to trade on the idea that if no false premise is explicitly articulated in the
agent’s reasoning, then the agent’s justification does not depend on a false
premise. Richard Feldman suggests an example that appears to undermine
the no-false-premise view.30 In the Ford case, Feldman argues that if S were
to use existential generalization prior to her inferring that Nogot owned
a Ford, then S ’s justification would not depend on the false proposition
that Nogot owns a Ford. That is, if on the basis of her evidence that she
had seen Nogot driving a Ford and she had been told that Nogot owned
a Ford, she had immediately inferred that someone in the office owned a
Ford, then S ’s justification would not depend on a false premise.
In response, we might reply that whether S articulates or reasons explic-
itly from a false proposition, S clearly seems to believe something false. In
particular, S clearly seems to believe that Nogot owns a Ford. Indeed, were
it not for S having this belief, it would seem strange to us that she would
infer that someone owns a Ford.
The point here is that the explicit premises in one’s justification may
well depend on further background beliefs. Feldman’s counterexample
seems to ignore these background beliefs. Doing so permits him to claim
that we need only consider the explicit premises of an agent’s justification.
But once we recognize that some background beliefs are essential to an
agent’s explicit reasoning, we can see that in a legitimate sense what goes
wrong in Gettier-type cases is that some false belief underlies the agent’s
justification.
This line of thought may be problematic. We do not want to understand
this condition so strongly that every background belief held by the agent
is an essential proposition for the agent’s justification. But the notion of
an essential proposition seems to trade on our intuition that some beliefs
matter more than others for particular cases of reasoning and that some
beliefs matter not at all. If this intuition proves to be well grounded, then
The Gettier problem and subsequent work on it have not been univer-
sally prized. As counterexample spawned counterexample, as rebuttal met
with rebuttal, and as yet a further subclause was added to the analysis of
knowledge, some suspected that the forest had been lost, not for the trees,
but for the pine needles. However, important issues have arisen as a result
of this process. We will restrict our discussion to two main issues: (a) the
nature of knowledge and (b) the nature of justification.
First, you may have already asked yourself what the proper response
to Gettier should be. Each of the three strategies presented previously was
motivated by intuitively plausible considerations, yet each faced certain
difficulties. So, can we expect a return to the widespread agreement in
evidence prior to Gettier?
Notice that the indefeasibility and no-false-premise views agree that
justified true belief is necessary, if not sufficient, for knowledge. Depending
on how we interpret the causal theory, it, too, might be viewed as holding
that justified true belief is necessary for knowledge. We should also notice
that our justified true beliefs can be “gettierized” in many ways. These
observations suggest two things. First, there may be no single account that
deals with each and every counterexample. In turn, we are led to a second,
perhaps more important consideration.
As characterized here, the Gettier problem results from a potential gap
between the satisfaction of the justification condition and the satisfaction
of the truth condition. The challenge is to find a way to close this gap.
It may be, however, that this gap can arise in different ways. Indeed, we
might view our three accounts as suggesting different ways in which a gap
might arise between the justification and the truth conditions. Thus, dif-
ferent ways of closing the gap may be necessary, just as is suggested by the
three views in the previous section. That is, different types of justification
may be appropriate under different circumstances.
We can elaborate the idea that different responses to Gettier cases might
address different ways in which the traditional analysis is inadequate.
Ernest Sosa has suggested that knowledge is apt or appropriate (true)
belief.32 We can view this suggestion as a schema whereby the challenge
31 It is perhaps worth noting that more recently Feldman suggests a version of the
no-false-premise view, which takes account of essential premises. See Feldman 2003,
pp. 36–37. Feldman does not explicitly mention “premises,” but condition (iv) of his
“modest proposal” reads “S ’s justification for p does not depend essentially on any
falsehood.”
32 Sosa 1991b, pp. 245–246.
Review Copy
78 an Introduction to Epistemology
33 Kaplan 1985.
34 See Conee 1996.
Review Copy
Chapter Two An Introduction to the Analysis of Knowledge 79
tional facts that explain why her justification is indefeasible, and she might
be able to use these new facts to guide her future inquiries.
Two final points can be made about Gettier cases. First, although there
may be an air of unreality about some of them, cases such as Goldman’s
barn example surely seem to involve genuine instances of justified belief.
Natural Gettier cases may be rare, but there are such cases. A recent issue
of Science News reports that researchers may have had a justified true
belief that “yo-yo dieting” can cause cancer but that recent studies sug-
gest they believed it for the wrong reasons.35 Such a case might count as
a “natural” Gettier case. However, although such cases might not be the
norm, they indicate that we are sometimes epistemically better off when
our justification reflects the facts, that is, when our justification does in fact
explain why the belief is true.
Second, Gettier cases can be used to draw our attention to certain aspects
of knowledge. At the very least, we might think that some Gettier cases sug-
gest that we can have knowledge only in a generally cooperative environ-
ment. If we rely on our generally “accredited routes to knowledge,” we count
on the world being more or less normal. We can fail to have knowledge due
to the global complications imagined by Descartes, but knowledge may also
elude us when the world is less dramatically abnormal. This “failure of nor-
mality” can go undetected, and thus preclude our having knowledge, even
though we have done all that we might reasonably be expected to do.
A distinction, which will be important to us in subsequent chapters, is
that between externalist and internalist accounts of knowledge and jus-
tification. Externalism is roughly the idea that an agent’s justification or
knowledge depends on some condition that need not be reflected in an
agent’s beliefs.36 Internalism, on the other hand, roughly holds that a belief
is justified only if the relevant justifying conditions are in some respect
reflected in the agent’s beliefs or cognitive perspective.
Some of the responses to Gettier may signal a move toward external-
ism.37 In discussing the causal theory, we noticed the shift from evidential
reasons to causal reasons. What matters is the causal mechanism that pro-
duces the agent’s belief. The causal theory does not appear to insist that
knowledge depends on the reasons for which an agent holds the belief.
This has led some to think that knowledge is externalist in nature, while
justification is internalist.38
Key Concepts
Traditional analysis of
No-false-premise theories
knowledge
Indefeasibility theories of
knowledge
Review Questions
1 Do you think that either the Ford case or the barn case is a case of
knowledge? Explain. If not, explain why each is a case of justified
true belief, but not a case of knowledge. Can you construct your own
Gettier case?