New Text Document
New Text Document
New Text Document
fasdun9hnnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnh
nhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhnhh
frwouyabdiyyyyyyiyiyiyiyiyiyiyiyiyiyiyiyiyiyiyiyiyiyiyiyiyiyiiiijiiiiiiijijijijijij
ijijijijijijijijijijijijijijijijijj
fwehuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuuu Art is a diverse range of human
activity, and resulting product, that involves creative or imaginative talent
expressive of technical proficiency, beauty, emotional power, or conceptual ideas.
[1][2][3]
The nature of art and related concepts, such as creativity and interpretation, are
explored in a branch of philosophy known as aesthetics.[9] The resulting artworks
are studied in the professional fields of art criticism and the history of art.
Contents
1 Overview
2 History
3 Forms, genres, media, and styles
3.1 Skill and craft
4 Purpose
4.1 Non-motivated functions
4.2 Motivated functions
5 Public access
6 Controversies
7 Theory
7.1 Arrival of Modernism
7.2 New Criticism and the "intentional fallacy"
7.3 "Linguistic turn" and its debate
8 Classification disputes
8.1 Value judgment
9 Art and law
10 See also
11 Notes
12 Bibliography
13 Further reading
14 External links
Overview
20th-century bottle, Twa peoples, Rwanda, Artistic works may serve practical
functions, in addition to their decorative value.
Over time, philosophers like Plato, Aristotle, Socrates and Kant, among others,
questioned the meaning of art.[12][full citation needed] Several dialogues in Plato
tackle questions about art: Socrates says that poetry is inspired by the muses, and
is not rational. He speaks approvingly of this, and other forms of divine madness
(drunkenness, eroticism, and dreaming) in the Phaedrus (265a–c), and yet in the
Republic wants to outlaw Homer's great poetic art, and laughter as well. In Ion,
Socrates gives no hint of the disapproval of Homer that he expresses in the
Republic. The dialogue Ion suggests that Homer's Iliad functioned in the ancient
Greek world as the Bible does today in the modern Christian world: as divinely
inspired literary art that can provide moral guidance, if only it can be properly
interpreted.[13][full citation needed]
With regards to the literary art and the musical arts, Aristotle considered epic
poetry, tragedy, comedy, Dithyrambic poetry and music to be mimetic or imitative
art, each varying in imitation by medium, object, and manner.[14][full citation
needed] For example, music imitates with the media of rhythm and harmony, whereas
dance imitates with rhythm alone, and poetry with language. The forms also differ
in their object of imitation. Comedy, for instance, is a dramatic imitation of men
worse than average; whereas tragedy imitates men slightly better than average.
Lastly, the forms differ in their manner of imitation—through narrative or
character, through change or no change, and through drama or no drama.[15]
Aristotle believed that imitation is natural to mankind and constitutes one of
mankind's advantages over animals.[16][full citation needed]
The more recent and specific sense of the word art as an abbreviation for creative
art or fine art emerged in the early 17th century.[17] Fine art refers to a skill
used to express the artist's creativity, or to engage the audience's aesthetic
sensibilities, or to draw the audience towards consideration of more refined or
finer work of art.
Within this latter sense, the word art may refer to several things: (i) a study of
a creative skill, (ii) a process of using the creative skill, (iii) a product of
the creative skill, or (iv) the audience's experience with the creative skill. The
creative arts (art as discipline) are a collection of disciplines which produce
artworks (art as objects) that are compelled by a personal drive (art as activity)
and convey a message, mood, or symbolism for the perceiver to interpret (art as
experience). Art is something that stimulates an individual's thoughts, emotions,
beliefs, or ideas through the senses. Works of art can be explicitly made for this
purpose or interpreted on the basis of images or objects. For some scholars, such
as Kant, the sciences and the arts could be distinguished by taking science as
representing the domain of knowledge and the arts as representing the domain of the
freedom of artistic expression.[18][full citation needed]
Often, if the skill is being used in a common or practical way, people will
consider it a craft instead of art. Likewise, if the skill is being used in a
commercial or industrial way, it may be considered commercial art instead of fine
art. On the other hand, crafts and design are sometimes considered applied art.
Some art followers have argued that the difference between fine art and applied art
has more to do with value judgments made about the art than any clear definitional
difference.[19] However, even fine art often has goals beyond pure creativity and
self-expression. The purpose of works of art may be to communicate ideas, such as
in politically, spiritually, or philosophically motivated art; to create a sense of
beauty (see aesthetics); to explore the nature of perception; for pleasure; or to
generate strong emotions. The purpose may also be seemingly nonexistent.
The nature of art has been described by philosopher Richard Wollheim as "one of the
most elusive of the traditional problems of human culture".[20] Art has been
defined as a vehicle for the expression or communication of emotions and ideas, a
means for exploring and appreciating formal elements for their own sake, and as
mimesis or representation. Art as mimesis has deep roots in the philosophy of
Aristotle.[21] Leo Tolstoy identified art as a use of indirect means to communicate
from one person to another.[21] Benedetto Croce and R. G. Collingwood advanced the
idealist view that art expresses emotions, and that the work of art therefore
essentially exists in the mind of the creator.[22][23] The theory of art as form
has its roots in the philosophy of Kant, and was developed in the early 20th
century by Roger Fry and Clive Bell. More recently, thinkers influenced by Martin
Heidegger have interpreted art as the means by which a community develops for
itself a medium for self-expression and interpretation.[24] George Dickie has
offered an institutional theory of art that defines a work of art as any artifact
upon which a qualified person or persons acting on behalf of the social institution
commonly referred to as "the art world" has conferred "the status of candidate for
appreciation".[25] Larry Shiner has described fine art as "not an essence or a fate
but something we have made. Art as we have generally understood it is a European
invention barely two hundred years old."[26]
History
Main article: History of art
Sculptures, cave paintings, rock paintings and petroglyphs from the Upper
Paleolithic dating to roughly 40,000 years ago have been found,[32] but the precise
meaning of such art is often disputed because so little is known about the cultures
that produced them.
In Byzantine and Medieval art of the Western Middle Ages, much art focused on the
expression of subjects about Biblical and religious culture, and used styles that
showed the higher glory of a heavenly world, such as the use of gold in the
background of paintings, or glass in mosaics or windows, which also presented
figures in idealized, patterned (flat) forms. Nevertheless, a classical realist
tradition persisted in small Byzantine works, and realism steadily grew in the art
of Catholic Europe.[34]
Renaissance art had a greatly increased emphasis on the realistic depiction of the
material world, and the place of humans in it, reflected in the corporeality of the
human body, and development of a systematic method of graphical perspective to
depict recession in a three-dimensional picture space.[35]
The stylized signature of Sultan Mahmud II of the Ottoman Empire was written in
Islamic calligraphy. It reads "Mahmud Khan son of Abdulhamid is forever
victorious".
The Great Mosque of Kairouan in Tunisia, also called the Mosque of Uqba, is one of
the finest, most significant and best preserved artistic and architectural examples
of early great mosques. Dated in its present state from the 9th century, it is the
ancestor and model of all the mosques in the western Islamic lands.[36]
In the east, Islamic art's rejection of iconography led to emphasis on geometric
patterns, calligraphy, and architecture.[37] Further east, religion dominated
artistic styles and forms too. India and Tibet saw emphasis on painted sculptures
and dance, while religious painting borrowed many conventions from sculpture and
tended to bright contrasting colors with emphasis on outlines. China saw the
flourishing of many art forms: jade carving, bronzework, pottery (including the
stunning terracotta army of Emperor Qin[38]), poetry, calligraphy, music, painting,
drama, fiction, etc. Chinese styles vary greatly from era to era and each one is
traditionally named after the ruling dynasty. So, for example, Tang dynasty
paintings are monochromatic and sparse, emphasizing idealized landscapes, but Ming
dynasty paintings are busy and colorful, and focus on telling stories via setting
and composition.[39] Japan names its styles after imperial dynasties too, and also
saw much interplay between the styles of calligraphy and painting. Woodblock
printing became important in Japan after the 17th century.[40]
In The Origin of the Work of Art, Martin Heidegger, a German philosopher and a
seminal thinker, describes the essence of art in terms of the concepts of being and
truth. He argues that art is not only a way of expressing the element of truth in a
culture, but the means of creating it and providing a springboard from which "that
which is" can be revealed. Works of art are not merely representations of the way
things are, but actually produce a community's shared understanding. Each time a
new artwork is added to any culture, the meaning of what it is to exist is
inherently changed.
Historically, art and artistic skills and ideas have often been spread through
trade. An example of this is the Silk Road, where Hellenistic, Iranian, Indian and
Chinese influences could mix. Greco Buddhist art is one of the most vivid examples
of this interaction. The meeting of different cultures and worldviews also
influenced artistic creation. An example of this is the multicultural port
metropolis of Trieste at the beginning of the 20th century, where James Joyce met
writers from Central Europe and the artistic development of New York City as a
cultural melting pot.[47][48][49]
Extreme Intentionalism holds that authorial intent plays a decisive role in the
meaning of a work of art, conveying the content or essential main idea, while all
other interpretations can be discarded.[54] It defines the subject as the persons
or idea represented,[55] and the content as the artist's experience of that
subject.[56] For example, the composition of Napoleon I on his Imperial Throne is
partly borrowed from the Statue of Zeus at Olympia. As evidenced by the title, the
subject is Napoleon, and the content is Ingres's representation of Napoleon as
"Emperor-God beyond time and space".[52] Similarly to extreme formalism,
philosophers typically reject extreme intentionalism, because art may have multiple
ambiguous meanings and authorial intent may be unknowable and thus irrelevant. Its
restrictive interpretation is "socially unhealthy, philosophically unreal, and
politically unwise".[52]
The Creation of Adam, detail from Michelangelo's fresco in the Sistine Chapel
(1511)
Art can connote a sense of trained ability or mastery of a medium. Art can also
simply refer to the developed and efficient use of a language to convey meaning
with immediacy or depth. Art can be defined as an act of expressing feelings,
thoughts, and observations.[58]
Non-motivated functions
The non-motivated purposes of art are those that are integral to being human,
transcend the individual, or do not fulfill a specific external purpose. In this
sense, Art, as creativity, is something humans must do by their very nature (i.e.,
no other species creates art), and is therefore beyond utility.[67]
Basic human instinct for harmony, balance, rhythm. Art at this level is not an
action or an object, but an internal appreciation of balance and harmony (beauty),
and therefore an aspect of being human beyond utility.
Imitation, then, is one instinct of our nature. Next, there is the instinct for
'harmony' and rhythm, meters being manifestly sections of rhythm. Persons,
therefore, starting with this natural gift developed by degrees their special
aptitudes, till their rude improvisations gave birth to Poetry. – Aristotle[68]
Motivated functions
Motivated purposes of art refer to intentional, conscious actions on the part of
the artists or creator. These may be to bring about political change, to comment on
an aspect of society, to convey a specific emotion or mood, to address personal
psychology, to illustrate another discipline, to (with commercial arts) sell a
product, or simply as a form of communication.[67][72]
Art as entertainment. Art may seek to bring about a particular emotion or mood, for
the purpose of relaxing or entertaining the viewer. This is often the function of
the art industries of Motion Pictures and Video Games.[74]
The Avant-Garde. Art for political change. One of the defining functions of early
20th-century art has been to use visual images to bring about political change. Art
movements that had this goal—Dadaism, Surrealism, Russian constructivism, and
Abstract Expressionism, among others—are collectively referred to as the avant-
garde arts.
By contrast, the realistic attitude, inspired by positivism, from Saint Thomas
Aquinas to Anatole France, clearly seems to me to be hostile to any intellectual or
moral advancement. I loathe it, for it is made up of mediocrity, hate, and dull
conceit. It is this attitude which today gives birth to these ridiculous books,
these insulting plays. It constantly feeds on and derives strength from the
newspapers and stultifies both science and art by assiduously flattering the lowest
of tastes; clarity bordering on stupidity, a dog's life. – André Breton
(Surrealism)[75]
Art as a "free zone", removed from the action of the social censure. Unlike the
avant-garde movements, which wanted to erase cultural differences in order to
produce new universal values, contemporary art has enhanced its tolerance towards
cultural differences as well as its critical and liberating functions (social
inquiry, activism, subversion, deconstruction ...), becoming a more open place for
research and experimentation.[76]
Art for social inquiry, subversion or anarchy. While similar to art for political
change, subversive or deconstructivist art may seek to question aspects of society
without any specific political goal. In this case, the function of art may be
simply to criticize some aspect of society.
Public access
The Metropolitan Museum of Art in Manhattan. Museums are important forums for the
display of visual art.
Since ancient times, much of the finest art has represented a deliberate display of
wealth or power, often achieved by using massive scale and expensive materials.
Much art has been commissioned by political rulers or religious establishments,
with more modest versions only available to the most wealthy in society.[93]
Nevertheless, there have been many periods where art of very high quality was
available, in terms of ownership, across large parts of society, above all in cheap
media such as pottery, which persists in the ground, and perishable media such as
textiles and wood. In many different cultures, the ceramics of indigenous peoples
of the Americas are found in such a wide range of graves that they were clearly not
restricted to a social elite,[94] though other forms of art may have been.
Reproductive methods such as moulds made mass-production easier, and were used to
bring high-quality Ancient Roman pottery and Greek Tanagra figurines to a very wide
market. Cylinder seals were both artistic and practical, and very widely used by
what can be loosely called the middle class in the Ancient Near East.[95] Once
coins were widely used, these also became an art form that reached the widest range
of society.[96]
Another important innovation came in the 15th century in Europe, when printmaking
began with small woodcuts, mostly religious, that were often very small and hand-
colored, and affordable even by peasants who glued them to the walls of their
homes. Printed books were initially very expensive, but fell steadily in price
until by the 19th century even the poorest could afford some with printed
illustrations.[97] Popular prints of many different sorts have decorated homes and
other places for centuries.[98]
The Museum of Art in Basel (Switzerland), is the oldest public museum of art in the
world.
In 1661, the city of Basel, in Switzerland, opened the first public museum of art
in the world, the Kunstmuseum Basel. Today, its collection is distinguished by an
impressively wide historic span, from the early 15th century up to the immediate
present. Its various areas of emphasis give it international standing as one of the
most significant museums of its kind. These encompass: paintings and drawings by
artists active in the Upper Rhine region between 1400 and 1600, and on the art of
the 19th to 21st centuries.[99]
Public buildings and monuments, secular and religious, by their nature normally
address the whole of society, and visitors as viewers, and display to the general
public has long been an important factor in their design. Egyptian temples are
typical in that the most largest and most lavish decoration was placed on the parts
that could be seen by the general public, rather than the areas seen only by the
priests.[100] Many areas of royal palaces, castles and the houses of the social
elite were often generally accessible, and large parts of the art collections of
such people could often be seen, either by anybody, or by those able to pay a small
price, or those wearing the correct clothes, regardless of who they were, as at the
Palace of Versailles, where the appropriate extra accessories (silver shoe buckles
and a sword) could be hired from shops outside.[101]
Special arrangements were made to allow the public to see many royal or private
collections placed in galleries, as with the Orleans Collection mostly housed in a
wing of the Palais Royal in Paris, which could be visited for most of the 18th
century.[102] In Italy the art tourism of the Grand Tour became a major industry
from the Renaissance onwards, and governments and cities made efforts to make their
key works accessible. The British Royal Collection remains distinct, but large
donations such as the Old Royal Library were made from it to the British Museum,
established in 1753. The Uffizi in Florence opened entirely as a gallery in 1765,
though this function had been gradually taking the building over from the original
civil servants' offices for a long time before.[103] The building now occupied by
the Prado in Madrid was built before the French Revolution for the public display
of parts of the royal art collection, and similar royal galleries open to the
public existed in Vienna, Munich and other capitals. The opening of the Musée du
Louvre during the French Revolution (in 1793) as a public museum for much of the
former French royal collection certainly marked an important stage in the
development of public access to art, transferring ownership to a republican state,
but was a continuation of trends already well established.[104]
Most modern public museums and art education programs for children in schools can
be traced back to this impulse to have art available to everyone. However, museums
do not only provide availability to art, but do also influence the way art is being
perceived by the audience, as studies found.[105] Thus, the museum itself is not
only a blunt stage for the presentation of art, but plays an active and vital role
in the overall perception of art in modern society.
Museums in the United States tend to be gifts from the very rich to the masses.
(The Metropolitan Museum of Art in New York City, for example, was created by John
Taylor Johnston, a railroad executive whose personal art collection seeded the
museum.) But despite all this, at least one of the important functions of art in
the 21st century remains as a marker of wealth and social status.[106]
There have been attempts by artists to create art that can not be bought by the
wealthy as a status object. One of the prime original motivators of much of the art
of the late 1960s and 1970s was to create art that could not be bought and sold. It
is "necessary to present something more than mere objects"[107] said the major post
war German artist Joseph Beuys. This time period saw the rise of such things as
performance art, video art, and conceptual art. The idea was that if the artwork
was a performance that would leave nothing behind, or was simply an idea, it could
not be bought and sold. "Democratic precepts revolving around the idea that a work
of art is a commodity impelled the aesthetic innovation which germinated in the
mid-1960s and was reaped throughout the 1970s. Artists broadly identified under the
heading of Conceptual art ... substituting performance and publishing activities
for engagement with both the material and materialistic concerns of painted or
sculptural form ... [have] endeavored to undermine the art object qua object."[108]
Versailles: Louis Le Vau opened up the interior court to create the expansive
entrance cour d'honneur, later copied all over Europe.
In the decades since, these ideas have been somewhat lost as the art market has
learned to sell limited edition DVDs of video works,[109] invitations to exclusive
performance art pieces, and the objects left over from conceptual pieces. Many of
these performances create works that are only understood by the elite who have been
educated as to why an idea or video or piece of apparent garbage may be considered
art. The marker of status becomes understanding the work instead of necessarily
owning it, and the artwork remains an upper-class activity. "With the widespread
use of DVD recording technology in the early 2000s, artists, and the gallery system
that derives its profits from the sale of artworks, gained an important means of
controlling the sale of video and computer artworks in limited editions to
collectors."[110]
Controversies
The content of much formal art through history was dictated by the patron or
commissioner rather than just the artist, but with the advent of Romanticism, and
economic changes in the production of art, the artists' vision became the usual
determinant of the content of his art, increasing the incidence of controversies,
though often reducing their significance. Strong incentives for perceived
originality and publicity also encouraged artists to court controversy. Théodore
Géricault's Raft of the Medusa (c. 1820), was in part a political commentary on a
recent event. Édouard Manet's Le Déjeuner sur l'Herbe (1863), was considered
scandalous not because of the nude woman, but because she is seated next to men
fully dressed in the clothing of the time, rather than in robes of the antique
world.[113][114] John Singer Sargent's Madame Pierre Gautreau (Madam X) (1884),
caused a controversy over the reddish pink used to color the woman's ear lobe,
considered far too suggestive and supposedly ruining the high-society model's
reputation.[115][116] The gradual abandonment of naturalism and the depiction of
realistic representations of the visual appearance of subjects in the 19th and 20th
centuries led to a rolling controversy lasting for over a century.
Theory
Main article: Aesthetics
Before Modernism, aesthetics in Western art was greatly concerned with achieving
the appropriate balance between different aspects of realism or truth to nature and
the ideal; ideas as to what the appropriate balance is have shifted to and fro over
the centuries. This concern is largely absent in other traditions of art. The
aesthetic theorist John Ruskin, who championed what he saw as the naturalism of J.
M. W. Turner, saw art's role as the communication by artifice of an essential truth
that could only be found in nature.[119]
The definition and evaluation of art has become especially problematic since the
20th century. Richard Wollheim distinguishes three approaches to assessing the
aesthetic value of art: the Realist, whereby aesthetic quality is an absolute value
independent of any human view; the Objectivist, whereby it is also an absolute
value, but is dependent on general human experience; and the Relativist position,
whereby it is not an absolute value, but depends on, and varies with, the human
experience of different humans.[120]
Arrival of Modernism
Composition with Red Blue and Yellow (1930) by Piet Mondrian (Dutch, 1872–1944)
The arrival of Modernism in the late 19th century lead to a radical break in the
conception of the function of art,[121] and then again in the late 20th century
with the advent of postmodernism. Clement Greenberg's 1960 article "Modernist
Painting" defines modern art as "the use of characteristic methods of a discipline
to criticize the discipline itself".[122] Greenberg originally applied this idea to
the Abstract Expressionist movement and used it as a way to understand and justify
flat (non-illusionistic) abstract painting:
Realistic, naturalistic art had dissembled the medium, using art to conceal art;
modernism used art to call attention to art. The limitations that constitute the
medium of painting—the flat surface, the shape of the support, the properties of
the pigment—were treated by the Old Masters as negative factors that could be
acknowledged only implicitly or indirectly. Under Modernism these same limitations
came to be regarded as positive factors, and were acknowledged openly.[122]
After Greenberg, several important art theorists emerged, such as Michael Fried, T.
J. Clark, Rosalind Krauss, Linda Nochlin and Griselda Pollock among others. Though
only originally intended as a way of understanding a specific set of artists,
Greenberg's definition of modern art is important to many of the ideas of art
within the various art movements of the 20th century and early 21st century.[123]
[124]
Pop artists like Andy Warhol became both noteworthy and influential through work
including and possibly critiquing popular culture, as well as the art world.
Artists of the 1980s, 1990s, and 2000s expanded this technique of self-criticism
beyond high art to all cultural image-making, including fashion images, comics,
billboards and pornography.[125][126]
Duchamp once proposed that art is any activity of any kind-everything. However, the
way that only certain activities are classified today as art is a social
construction.[127] There is evidence that there may be an element of truth to this.
In The Invention of Art: A Cultural History, Larry Shiner examines the construction
of the modern system of the arts, i.e. fine art. He finds evidence that the older
system of the arts before our modern system (fine art) held art to be any skilled
human activity; for example, Ancient Greek society did not possess the term art,
but techne. Techne can be understood neither as art or craft, the reason being that
the distinctions of art and craft are historical products that came later on in
human history. Techne included painting, sculpting and music, but also cooking,
medicine, horsemanship, geometry, carpentry, prophecy, and farming, etc.[128]
In another essay, "The Affective Fallacy", which served as a kind of sister essay
to "The Intentional Fallacy" Wimsatt and Beardsley also discounted the reader's
personal/emotional reaction to a literary work as a valid means of analyzing a
text. This fallacy would later be repudiated by theorists from the reader-response
school of literary theory. Ironically, one of the leading theorists from this
school, Stanley Fish, was himself trained by New Critics. Fish criticizes Wimsatt
and Beardsley in his 1970 essay "Literature in the Reader".[133][134]
Gaut and Livingston define the intentionalists as distinct from formalists stating
that: "Intentionalists, unlike formalists, hold that reference to intentions is
essential in fixing the correct interpretation of works." They quote Richard
Wollheim as stating that, "The task of criticism is the reconstruction of the
creative process, where the creative process must in turn be thought of as
something not stopping short of, but terminating on, the work of art itself."[136]
Classification disputes
Main article: Classificatory disputes about art
Architecture is often included as one of the visual arts; however, like the
decorative arts, or advertising, it involves the creation of objects where the
practical considerations of use are essential in a way that they usually are not in
a painting, for example.[151]
Value judgment
The assumption of new values or the rebellion against accepted notions of what is
aesthetically superior need not occur concurrently with a complete abandonment of
the pursuit of what is aesthetically appealing. Indeed, the reverse is often true,
that the revision of what is popularly conceived of as being aesthetically
appealing allows for a re-invigoration of aesthetic sensibility, and a new
appreciation for the standards of art itself. Countless schools have proposed their
own ways to define quality, yet they all seem to agree in at least one point: once
their aesthetic choices are accepted, the value of the work of art is determined by
its capacity to transcend the limits of its chosen medium to strike some universal
chord by the rarity of the skill of the artist or in its accurate reflection in
what is termed the zeitgeist. Art is often intended to appeal to and connect with
human emotion. It can arouse aesthetic or moral feelings, and can be understood as
a way of communicating these feelings. Artists express something so that their
audience is aroused to some extent, but they do not have to do so consciously. Art
may be considered an exploration of the human condition; that is, what it is to be
human.[155] By extension, it has been argued by Emily L. Spratt that the
development of artificial intelligence, especially in regard to its uses with
images, necessitates a re-evaluation of aesthetic theory in art history today and a
reconsideration of the limits of human creativity.[156][157]
The trade in works of art or the export from a country may be subject to legal
regulations. Internationally there are also extensive efforts to protect the works
of art created. The UN, UNESCO and Blue Shield International try to ensure
effective protection at the national level and to intervene directly in the event
of armed conflicts or disasters. This can particularly affect museums, archives,
art collections and excavation sites. This should also secure the economic basis of
a country, especially because works of art are often of tourist importance. The
founding president of Blue Shield International, Karl von Habsburg, explained an
additional connection between the destruction of cultural property and the cause of
flight during a mission in Lebanon in April 2019: “Cultural goods are part of the
identity of the people who live in a certain place. If you destroy their culture,
you also destroy their identity. Many people are uprooted, often no longer have any
prospects and as a result flee from their homeland.”[158][159][160][161][162][163]
See also
icon Arts portal
icon Visual arts portal
Applied arts
Art movement
Artist in residence
Artistic freedom
Cultural tourism
Craftivism
Formal analysis
History of art
List of artistic media
List of art techniques
Mathematics and art
Street art (or "independent public art")
Outline of the visual arts, a guide to the subject of art presented as a tree
structured list of its subtopics.
Visual impairment in art
Notes
"Art: definition". Oxford Dictionaries. Archived from the original on 1 September
2016. Retrieved 25 December 2015.
"art". Merriam-Websters Dictionary. Archived from the original on 30 August 2019.
Retrieved 25 December 2015.
"Conceptual Art | Definition of Conceptual Art by Oxford Dictionary on Lexico.com
also meaning of Conceptual Art". Lexico Dictionaries | English. Archived from the
original on 14 April 2021. Retrieved 18 March 2021.
Stephen Davies (1991). Definitions of Art. Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-0-
8014-9794-0.
Robert Stecker (1997). Artworks: Definition, Meaning, Value. Pennsylvania State
University Press. ISBN 978-0-271-01596-5.
Noël Carroll, ed. (2000). Theories of Art Today. University of Wisconsin Press.
ISBN 978-0-299-16354-9.
Vasari, Giorgio (18 December 2007). The Lives of the Most Excellent Painters,
Sculptors, and Architects. Random House Publishing Group. ISBN 9780307432391.
Archived from the original on 14 April 2021. Retrieved 8 November 2020.
"Art, n. 1". OED Online. December 2011. Oxford University Press.
https://www.oed.com Archived 11 January 2008 at the Wayback Machine. (Accessed 26
February 2012.)
Kennick, W. E. (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics. New York (NY):
St. Martin's Press. pp. xi–xiii. ISBN 978-0-312-05391-8. OCLC 1064878696.
"Art". Encyclopædia Britannica. Archived from the original on 11 March 2009.
Retrieved 6 July 2012.
Elkins, James (December 1995). "Art History and Images That Are Not Art (with
previous bibliography)". The Art Bulletin. 77 (4): 553–571. doi:10.2307/3046136.
ISSN 0004-3079. JSTOR 3046136. Archived from the original on 18 August 2021. Non-
Western images are not well described in terms of art, and neither are medieval
paintings that were made in the absence of humanist ideas of artistic value
Gilbert, Kuhn pp. 73–96
Gilbert, Kuhn pp. 40–72
Aristotle, Poetics I 1447a
Aristotle, Poetics III
Aristotle, Poetics IV
Languages, Oxford (20 September 2007). Shorter Oxford English Dictionary (6th
ed.). Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 119–121. ISBN 978-0-19-920687-
2. OCLC 170973920. Archived from the original on 3 March 2022.
Gilbert, Kuhn pp. 287–326
David Novitz, The Boundaries of Art, 1992
Richard Wollheim, Art and its objects, p. 1, 2nd ed., 1980, Cambridge University
Press, ISBN 0-521-29706-0
Jerrold Levinson, The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics, Oxford University Press,
2003, p. 5. ISBN 0-19-927945-4
Jerrold Levinson, The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics, Oxford University Press,
2003, p. 16. ISBN 0-19-927945-4
R.G. Collingwood's view, expressed in The Principles of Art, is considered in
Wollheim, op. cit. 1980 pp. 36–43
Martin Heidegger, "The Origin of the Work of Art", in Poetry, Language, Thought,
(Harper Perennial, 2001). See also Maurice Merleau-Ponty, "Cézanne's Doubt" in The
Merleau-Ponty Aesthetics Reader, Galen Johnson and Michael Smith (eds),
(Northwestern University Press, 1994) and John Russon, Bearing Witness to Epiphany,
(State University of New York Press, 2009).
W. E. Kennick, Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics. New York: St. Martin's
Press, 1979, p. 89. ISBN 0-312-05391-6.
Shiner 2003. The Invention of Art: A Cultural History. The University of Chicago
Press Books. p. 3. ISBN 978-0-226-75342-3
Gombrich, Ernst. (2005). "Press statement on The Story of Art". The Gombrich
Archive. Archived from the original on 6 October 2008.
"Shell 'Art' Made 300,000 Years Before Humans Evolved". New Scientist. Reed
Business Information Ltd. 3 December 2014. Archived from the original on 6 June
2015. Retrieved 24 August 2017.
"130,000-Year-Old Neanderthal 'Eagle Claw Necklace' Found in Croatia". Sci-
News.com. 11 March 2015. Archived from the original on 14 April 2021. Retrieved 7
May 2021.
Radford, Tim. ""World's Oldest Jewellery Found in Cave"". 16 April 2004. Archived
from the original on 8 February 2008. Retrieved 18 January 2008.. Guardian
Unlimited, 16 April 2004. Retrieved on 18 January 2008.
"African Cave Yields Evidence of a Prehistoric Paint Factory". The New York Times.
13 October 2011. Archived from the original on 1 January 2022.
Cyranoski, David (8 October 2014). "World's oldest art found in Indonesian cave".
Nature. doi:10.1038/nature.2014.16100. S2CID 189968118. Archived from the original
on 11 October 2014. Retrieved 12 October 2014.
Gombrich, p.83, pp.75–115 pp.132–141, pp.147–155, p.163, p.627.
Gombrich, pp. 86–89, pp. 135–141, p. 143, p. 179, p. 185.
Tom Nichols (1 December 2012). Renaissance Art: A Beginner's Guide. Oneworld
Publications. ISBN 978-1-78074-178-9. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019.
Retrieved 26 May 2018.
The Genius of Arab Civilization: Source of Renaissance. MIT Press. 1 January 1983.
ISBN 9780262081368. Archived from the original on 23 November 2015. Retrieved 20
June 2015.
Gombrich, pp. 127-128
Gombrich, pp. 634–635
William Watson (1995). The Arts of China 900–1620. Yale University Press. ISBN
978-0-300-09835-8. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 26 May
2018.
Gombrich, p. 155, p. 530.
Colin Moore (6 August 2010). Propaganda Prints: A History of Art in the Service of
Social and Political Change. A&C Black. p. 76. ISBN 978-1-4081-0591-7. Archived
from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 26 May 2018.
Gombrich, pp.394–395, pp.519–527, pp. 573–575.
"The Age of Enlightenment An Anthology Prepared for the Enlightenment Book Club"
(PDF). pp. 1–45. Archived (PDF) from the original on 27 May 2018. Retrieved 26 May
2018.
The New York Times Book Review. Vol. 1, 84. The New York Times Company. 1979. p.
30. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 26 May 2018.
Adorno, Theodor W., Aesthetic Theory, (1970 in German)
Dr. Sangeeta (2017). Development of Modern Art Criticism in India after
Independence: Post Independence Indian Art Criticism. Notion Press. ISBN 978-1-
947697-31-7. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 26 May 2018.
Liu, Xinru "The Silk Road in World History" (New York 2010), pp 21.
Veronika Eckl "Vom Leben in Cafés und zwischen Buchdeckeln" In: Frankfurter
Allgemeine Zeitung 17.01.2008; Angelo Ara, Claudio Magris "Triest Eine literarische
Hauptstadt Mitteleuropas (Trieste: un’identità di frontiera)" (1987).
"How did New York City become the centre of the western art world?". 26 September
2016. Archived from the original on 21 January 2021. Retrieved 15 January 2021.
Walton, Kendall L. (1 January 1970). "Categories of Art". The Philosophical
Review. 79 (3): 334–67. doi:10.2307/2183933. JSTOR 2183933.
Monelle, Raymond (3 January 1992). Linguistics and Semiotics in Music. Routledge.
p. 202. ISBN 978-3718652099. Archived from the original on 14 April 2021. Retrieved
8 November 2020.
Belton, Dr. Robert J. (1996). "The Elements of Art". Art History: A Preliminary
Handbook. Archived from the original on 27 February 2017. Retrieved 26 February
2017.
Xu, Min; Deng, Guifang (2 December 2014). "Against Zangwill's Extreme Formalism
About Inorganic Nature" (PDF). Philosophia. 43 (1): 249–57. doi:10.1007/s11406-014-
9575-1. S2CID 55901464. Archived (PDF) from the original on 27 February 2017.
Retrieved 26 February 2017.
Livingston, Paisley (1998). "Intentionalism in Aesthetics". New Literary History.
29 (4): 831–46. doi:10.1353/nlh.1998.0042. S2CID 53618673. Archived from the
original on 31 August 2017.
Munk, Eduard; Beck, Charles; Felton, Cornelius Conway (1844). The Metres of the
Greeks and Romans. p. 1. Retrieved 26 February 2017.
Tolstoy, Leo (1899). What is Art?. Crowell. p. 24.
Emiroğlu, Melahat Küçükarslan; Koş, Fitnat Cimşit (16–20 September 2014). Design
Semiotics and Post-Structuralism. 12th World Congress of Semiotics. New Bulgarian
University. Archived from the original on 17 February 2017. Retrieved 26 February
2017.
Breskin, Vladimir, ""Triad: Method for studying the core of the semiotic parity of
language and art"" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 1 September 2011.,
Signs – International Journal of Semiotics 3, pp. 1–28, 2010. ISSN 1902-8822
The Illustrated London News. Illustrated London News & Sketch Limited. 1872. p.
502. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 26 May 2018.
Eric Newton; William Neil (1966). 2000 Years of Christian Art. Harper & Row. p.
184. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 26 May 2018.
Kirk Richards; Stephen Gjertson (2002). For glory and for beauty: practical
perspectives on Christianity and the visual arts. American Society of Classical
Realism. ISBN 978-0-9636180-4-7. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019.
Retrieved 26 May 2018.
Richard Leslie (30 December 2005). Pablo Picasso: A Modern Master. New Line Books.
p. 7. ISBN 978-1-59764-094-7. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019.
Retrieved 26 May 2018.
Jane Dillenberger; John Handley (17 April 2014). The Religious Art of Pablo
Picasso. Univ of California Press. p. 26. ISBN 978-0-520-27629-1. Archived from the
original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 26 May 2018.
Fred S. Kleiner (2009). Gardner's Art through the Ages: The Western Perspective.
Cengage Learning. pp. 24–27. ISBN 978-0-495-57364-7. Archived from the original on
5 August 2019. Retrieved 26 May 2018.
White, Luke (1 January 2013). Damien Hirst's Shark: Nature, Capitalism and the
Sublime. Tate. ISBN 9781849763875. Archived from the original on 17 April 2021.
Retrieved 26 May 2018.
La Belle Assemblée. Vol. V. J. Bell. 1808. p. 8. Archived from the original on 5
August 2019. Retrieved 26 May 2018.
Giovanni Schiuma (19 May 2011). The Value of Arts for Business. Cambridge
University Press. p. 37. ISBN 978-1-139-49665-0. Archived from the original on 5
August 2019. Retrieved 26 May 2018.
Aristotle. "[Book 10:] The Poetics". Republic. www.authorama.com. Note: Although
speaking mostly of poetry here, the Ancient Greeks often speak of the arts
collectively. Archived from the original on 8 May 2008. Retrieved 28 June 2008.
Einstein, Albert. "The World as I See It".
https://www.aip.org/history/einstein/essay.htm Archived 8 June 2008 at the Wayback
Machine
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Aesthetic Judgement (1790).
Silvia Tomaskova, Places of Art: Art and Archaeology in Context: (1997)
Constantine Stephanidis (24 June 2011). HCI International 2011 Posters' Extended
Abstracts: International Conference, HCI International 2011, Orlando, FL, USA, July
9–14, 2011, Proceedings. Springer Science & Business Media. pp. 529–533. ISBN 978-
3-642-22094-4. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 26 May 2018.
Steve Mithen. The Prehistory of the Mind: The Cognitive Origins of Art, Religion
and Science. 1999
Information Resources Management Association (30 June 2014). Digital Arts and
Entertainment: Concepts, Methodologies, Tools, and Applications. USA: IGI Global.
p. 976. ISBN 978-1-4666-6115-8. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019.
Retrieved 26 May 2018.
"André Breton, Manifesto of Surrealism (1924)". Archived from the original on 25
May 2020. Retrieved 24 May 2020.
According to Maurizio Bolognini this is not only associated with the postmodern
rejection of all canons but with a process of secularization of art, which is
finally considered as "a mere (albeit essential) convention, sustained and
reproduced by the art system (artists, galleries, critics, collectors), providing a
free zone, that is, a more open place for experimentation, removed from the
constraints of the practical sphere.": see Maurizio Bolognini (2008). Postdigitale.
Rome: Carocci. ISBN 978-88-430-4739-0. Archived from the original on 18 January
2011. Retrieved 2 August 2013., "chap. 3". Archived from the original on 18 January
2011. Retrieved 2 August 2013..
Trotter, Jeramia (15 February 2011). "RiverKings raising autism awareness with
art". WMC tv. Archived from the original on 22 February 2011.
"Art exhibit aims to raise awareness of autism". Daily News-Miner. 4 April 2012.
Archived from the original on 9 October 2019. Retrieved 22 January 2015.
"Anchorage art exhibit to raise awareness about autism" (PDF). Alaska Department
of Health and Social Services. Archived (PDF) from the original on 30 March 2013.
Retrieved 22 January 2015.
Ruhl, Ashleigh (18 February 2013). "Photographer Seeks Subjects To Help Raise
Cancer Awareness". Gazettes. Archived from the original on 21 February 2013.
Retrieved 22 January 2015.
"Bra art raising awareness for breast cancer". The Palm Beach Post. n.d. Archived
from the original on 9 October 2019. Retrieved 22 January 2015.
Flynn, Marella (10 January 2007). "October art walk aims to raise money, awareness
for breast cancer". Flagler College Gargoyle. Archived from the original on 20
February 2013. Retrieved 22 January 2015.
"Students get creative in the fight against human trafficking". WDTN Channel 2
News. 26 November 2012. Archived from the original on 30 June 2013.
"Looking to raise awareness at ArtPrize". WWMT, Newschannel 3. 10 January 2012.
Archived from the original on 6 October 2012.
"SciCafe – Art/Sci Collision: Raising Ocean Conservation Awareness". American
Museum of Natural History. Archived from the original on 3 July 2013. Retrieved 21
February 2013.
"SMU students raise awareness with 'Art for Darfur'". SMU News Release. 4 March
2008. Archived from the original on 3 April 2013. Retrieved 3 March 2022.
Donnelly, Greg (3 May 2012). "Red dress art project to raise awareness of murdered
and missing Aboriginal women". Global News. Archived from the original on 18 May
2020. Retrieved 2 May 2020.
"Raising elder abuse awareness through intergenerational art". Human Resources and
Skills Development Canada. Archived from the original on 22 January 2013. Retrieved
21 February 2013.
Mathema, Paavan (16 January 2013). "Trash to treasure: Turning Mt. Everest waste
into art". CNN. Archived from the original on 9 October 2019. Retrieved 22 February
2013.
Susan Hogan (2001). Healing Arts: The History of Art Therapy. Jessica Kingsley
Publishers. ISBN 978-1-85302-799-4. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019.
Retrieved 26 May 2018.
Roland Barthes, Mythologies
Dutton, Denis. 2003. "Aesthetics and Evolutionary Psychology" in The Oxford
Handbook for Aesthetics. Oxford University Press.
Gilbert, Kuhn pp. 161–165
"Ceramics of the Indigenous Peoples of South America: Studies of Production and
Exchange using INAA". core.tdar.org. Archived from the original on 28 May 2018.
Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Barbara Ann Kipfer (30 April 2000). Encyclopedic Dictionary of Archaeology.
Springer Science & Business Media. p. 264. ISBN 978-0-306-46158-3. Archived from
the original on 10 May 2016. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Ancient Coins as Works of Art. Museum Haaretz. 1960. Archived from the original on
5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
George Hugo Tucker (2000). Forms of the "medieval" in the "Renaissance": A
Multidisciplinary Exploration of a Cultural Continuum. Rookwood Press. p. 148. ISBN
978-1-886365-20-9. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May
2018.
Antony Griffiths (1996). Prints and Printmaking: An Introduction to the History
and Techniques. University of California Press. p. 149. ISBN 978-0-520-20714-1.
"550 Jahre Universität Basel". Archived from the original on 24 September 2017.
Retrieved 4 July 2020.
Győző Vörös (2007). Egyptian Temple Architecture: 100 Years of Hungarian
Excavations in Egypt, 1907–2007. American Univ in Cairo Press. p. 140. ISBN 978-
963-662-084-4. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Adam Waldie (1839). The Select Circulating Library. A. Waldie. p. 367. Archived
from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Andrea Meyer; Benedicte Savoy (2014). The Museum Is Open: Towards a Transnational
History of Museums 1750–1940. De Gruyter. p. 66. ISBN 978-3-11-029882-6. Archived
from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Gloria Fossi (1999). The Uffizi: The Official Guide : All of the Works. Giunti
Editore. pp. 8–11. ISBN 978-88-09-01487-9. Archived from the original on 5 August
2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Berger, Robert W. (1999). Public Access to Art in Paris: A Documentary History
from the Middle Ages to 1800. Penn State Press. pp. 281–283. ISBN 978-0-271-04434-
7. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Susanne Grüner; Eva Specker & Helmut Leder (2019). "Effects of Context and
Genuineness in the Experience of Art". Empirical Studies of the Arts. 37 (2): 138–
152. doi:10.1177/0276237418822896. S2CID 150115587. Archived from the original on
24 January 2020. Retrieved 26 August 2021.
Michael Findlay (2012). The Value of Art. Prestel Verlag. ISBN 978-3-641-08342-7.
Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Sharp, Willoughby (December 1969). "An Interview with Joseph Beuys". ArtForum. 8
(4): 45.
Rorimer, Anne: New Art in the 60s and 70s Redefining Reality, p. 35. Thames and
Hudson, 2001.
Fineman, Mia (21 March 2007). "YouTube for Artists The best places to find video
art online". Slate. Archived from the original on 7 September 2011. Retrieved 3
August 2007.
Robertson, Jean and Craig McDaniel: Themes of Contemporary Art, Visual Art after
1980, p. 16. Oxford University Press, 2005.
Maureen McCue (2016). British Romanticism and the Reception of Italian Old Master
Art, 1793–1840. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-317-17148-5. Archived from the
original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Angela K. Nickerson (2010). A Journey into Michelangelo's Rome.
ReadHowYouWant.com. p. 182. ISBN 978-1-4587-8547-3. Archived from the original on 5
August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Alvina Ruprecht; Cecilia Taiana (1995). Reordering of Culture: Latin America, the
Caribbean and Canada in the Hood. McGill-Queen's Press – MQUP. p. 256. ISBN 978-0-
88629-269-0. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
John C. Stout (2018). Objects Observed: The Poetry of Things in Twentieth-Century
France and America. University of Toronto Press. p. 50. ISBN 978-1-4875-0157-0.
Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Claude J. Summers (2004). The Queer Encyclopedia of the Visual Arts. Cleis Press.
ISBN 978-1-57344-191-9. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28
May 2018.
Narim Bender (2014). John Sargent: 121 Drawings. Osmora Incorporated. ISBN 978-2-
7659-0006-1. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Roger Chapman; James Ciment (2015). Culture Wars: An Encyclopedia of Issues,
Viewpoints and Voices. Routledge. p. 594. ISBN 978-1-317-47351-0. Archived from the
original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Brian Arthur Brown (2008). Noah's Other Son: Bridging the Gap Between the Bible
and the Qur'an. A&C Black. p. 210. ISBN 978-0-8264-2996-4. Archived from the
original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
"go to nature in all singleness of heart, rejecting nothing and selecting nothing,
and scorning nothing, believing all things are right and good, and rejoicing always
in the truth". Ruskin, John. Modern Painters, Volume I, 1843. London: Smith, Elder
and Co.
Wollheim 1980, Essay VI. pp. 231–39.
Griselda Pollock, Differencing the Canon. Routledge, London & New York, 1999. ISBN
0-415-06700-6
Modern Art and Modernism: A Critical Anthology. ed. Francis Frascina and Charles
Harrison, 1982.
Jonathan P. Harris (2005). Writing Back to Modern Art: After Greenberg, Fried, and
Clark. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0-415-32429-8. Archived from the original on 5
August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
David Kenneth Holt (2001). The Search for Aesthetic Meaning in the Visual Arts:
The Need for the Aesthetic Tradition in Contemporary Art Theory and Education.
Greenwood Publishing Group. ISBN 978-0-89789-773-0. Archived from the original on 5
August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Gerd Gemünden (1998). Framed Visions: Popular Culture, Americanization, and the
Contemporary German and Austrian Imagination. University of Michigan Press. p. 43.
ISBN 978-0-472-08560-6. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28
May 2018.
The New Yorker. F-R Publishing Corporation. 2004. p. 84. Archived from the
original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Duchamp Two Statements on YouTube[dead link]
Maria Burguete; Lui Lam (2011). Arts: A Science Matter. World Scientific. p. 74.
ISBN 978-981-4324-93-9. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28
May 2018.
Patricia Waugh (2006). Literary Theory and Criticism: An Oxford Guide. Oxford
University Press. p. 171. ISBN 978-0-19-929133-5. Archived from the original on 5
August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Claire Colebrook (1997). New Literary Histories: New Historicism and Contemporary
Criticism. Manchester University Press. p. 221. ISBN 978-0-7190-4987-3. Archived
from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Tiger C. Roholt (2013). Key Terms in Philosophy of Art. Bloomsbury Publishing. p.
161. ISBN 978-1-4411-3246-8. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved
28 May 2018.
Darren Hudson Hick (2017). Introducing Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art.
Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-350-00691-1. Archived from the original on 5
August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Leitch, Vincent B., et al., eds. The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism. New
York: W. W. Norton & Company, 2001.
Fish, Stanley (Autumn 1970). "Literature in the Reader: Affective Stylistics". New
Literary History. 2 (1): 123–162. doi:10.2307/468593. JSTOR 468593.
Gaut and Livingston, The Creation of Art, p. 3.
Gaut and Livingston, p. 6.
Philosophy for Architecture, Branco Mitrovic, 2012.
Introduction to Structuralism, Michael Lane, Basic Books University of Michigan,
1970.
Languages of Art: An Approach to a Theory of Symbols. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill,
1968. 2nd ed. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1976. Based on his 1960–61 John Locke
lectures.
Nick Zangwill, "Feasible Aesthetic Formalism", Nous, December 1999, pp. 610–29.
Tomkins, Duchamp: A Biography, p. 186.
Deborah Solomon (14 December 2003). "2003: the 3rd Annual Year in Ideas: Video
Game Art". The New York Times Magazine. Archived from the original on 1 April 2017.
Retrieved 18 February 2017.
Novitz, David (1996). "Disputes about Art". The Journal of Aesthetics and Art
Criticism. 54 (2): 153–163. doi:10.2307/431087. ISSN 0021-8529. JSTOR 431087.
Painter, Colin. Contemporary Art and the Home. Berg Publishers, 2002. p. 12. ISBN
1-85973-661-0
Dutton, Denis ""Tribal Art"". Archived from the original on 17 May 2020. Retrieved
27 January 2008. in Encyclopedia of Aesthetics, edited by Michael Kelly (New York:
Oxford University Press, 1998).
Danto, Arthur. "Artifact and Art" in Art/Artifact, edited by Susan Vogel. New
York, 1988.
""Glossary: Anti-art"". Archived from the original on 10 September 2009. Retrieved
23 January 2010., Tate. Retrieved 23 January 2010.
Schneider, Caroline. ""Asger Jorn"". Archived from the original on 13 May 2011.
Retrieved 24 January 2010., Artforum, 1 September 2001. Retrieved from
encyclopedia.com, 24 January 2010.
Ferguson, Euan. ""In bed with Tracey, Sarah ... and Ron"". TheGuardian.com. 20
April 2003. Archived from the original on 21 December 2016. Retrieved 11 December
2016., The Observer, 20 April 2003. Retrieved on 2 May 2009.
""Stuck on the Turner Prize"". Archived from the original on 21 June 2017.
Retrieved 22 January 2010., artnet, 27 October 2000. Retrieved on 2 May 2009.
Glancey, Jonathan (26 July 1995). "Is advertising art?". The Independent. Archived
from the original on 30 August 2017. Retrieved 18 August 2017.
Joe Potts (2011). The Kahuna Kit. AuthorHouse. p. 72. ISBN 978-1-4567-8689-2.
Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Nicholas Addison; Lesley Burgess (2012). Debates in Art and Design Education.
Routledge. p. 97. ISBN 978-0-415-61887-8. Archived from the original on 5 August
2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Yale H. Ferguson; Richard W. Mansbach (2008). A World of Polities: Essays on
Global Politics. Routledge. pp. 38–39. ISBN 978-1-135-98149-5. Archived from the
original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 28 May 2018.
Graham, Gordon (2005). Philosophy of the arts: an introduction to aesthetics.
Taylor & Francis.
Spratt, Emily L. (3 April 2018). "Computers and art in the age of machine
learning". XRDS: Crossroads. ACM: Association for Computing Machinery. 24 (3): 8–
20. doi:10.1145/3186697. S2CID 4714734. Archived from the original on 25 February
2022. Retrieved 12 November 2019.
Spratt, Emily L.; Elgammal, Ahmed (29 September 2014). "Computational Beauty:
Aesthetic Judgment at the Intersection of Art and Science". arXiv:1410.2488
[cs.CV].
"UNESCO Legal Instruments: Second Protocol to the Hague Convention of 1954 for the
Protection of Cultural Property in the Event of Armed Conflict 1999". Archived from
the original on 25 August 2021. Retrieved 25 February 2022.
Roger O’Keefe, Camille Péron, Tofig Musayev, Gianluca Ferrari: Protection of
Cultural Property. Military Manual. UNESCO, 2016.
"UNIFIL - Action plan to preserve heritage sites during conflict, 12 Apr 2019". 12
April 2019. Archived from the original on 26 July 2020. Retrieved 19 December 2020.
Friedrich Schipper: "Bildersturm: Die globalen Normen zum Schutz von Kulturgut
greifen nicht" (German - The global norms for the protection of cultural property
do not apply), In: Der Standard, 6 March 2015.
Corine Wegener, Marjan Otter: Cultural Property at War: Protecting Heritage during
Armed Conflict. In: The Getty Conservation Institute, Newsletter 23.1, Spring 2008.
Matzl, Christoph (28 April 2019). "Austrian Armed Forces Mission in Lebanon" (in
German). Archived from the original on 26 May 2020. Retrieved 19 December 2020.
Bibliography
Oscar Wilde, Intentions, 1891
Stephen Davies, Definitions of Art, 1991
Nina Felshin, ed. But is it Art?, 1995
Catherine de Zegher (ed.). Inside the Visible. MIT Press, 1996
Evelyn Hatcher, ed. Art as Culture: An Introduction to the Anthropology of Art,
1999
Noel Carroll, Theories of Art Today, 2000
John Whitehead. Grasping for the Wind, 2001
Michael Ann Holly and Keith Moxey (eds.) Art History Aesthetics Visual Studies. New
Haven: Yale University Press, 2002. ISBN 0300097891
Shiner, Larry. The Invention of Art: A Cultural History. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 2003. ISBN 978-0-226-75342-3
Arthur Danto, The Abuse of Beauty: Aesthetics and the Concept of Art. 2003
Dana Arnold and Margaret Iversen, eds. Art and Thought. London: Blackwell, 2003.
ISBN 0631227156
Jean Robertson and Craig McDaniel, Themes of Contemporary Art, Visual Art after
1980, 2005