Disappearing Agent
Disappearing Agent
Disappearing Agent
➔ “In Springs of Action (1992: 158–159), he writes: ‘in deciding to A, one settles upon
A-ing (or upon trying to A), and one enters a state—a decision state—of being settled
upon A-ing (or upon trying to A)’” (PEREBOOM, 2017, p. 630)
➔ “To settle which action to perform is to determine, not necessarily causally,
which of one’s options for action to perform. And now, as Mele’s exposition
specifies, one settles (or at least one can settle) whether the decision to A
(conceived of as a decision state) occurs by settling or determining whether to A
or not-A. This is at least typically the case: one settles whether a decision to A
occurs by settling upon A” (PEREBOOM, 2017, p. 630);
➔ “An agent settles which of one’s options for action occurs just in case she determines,
not necessarily causally, which action occurs, and she makes the difference as to
which action occurs” (PEREBOOM, 2017, p. 630);
◆ This is possible in Frankfurt Cases: “causes of action in Frankfurt cases,
despite the agent being unable to do otherwise, still make a difference to their
effects in that the effects wouldn’t have been caused by the absence of their
causes” (PEREBOOM, 2017, p. 630);
● “An agent settles whether an action occurs if it is caused by certain
reasons of hers, where the absence of those reasons would not have
caused that action” (PEREBOOM, 2017, p. 631).
➔ Should the relevant sort of settling or control in decision be interpreted as involving
complete control? (PEREBOOM, 2017, p. 631);
◆ “A smallish probability of such a failure is consistent with settling, and
with the control in deciding that’s at issue in this debate—in my view, the
control required for the agent’s basic-desert moral responsibility for the
decision” (PEREBOOM, 2017, p. 631);
◆ “But suppose I also maintained that a 50% probability of such a failure
renders the agent’s control insufficient. Do we now have in place a barrier
to whether the notion of settling in play can be understood? An analogous
concern has familiarly been raised for the notion of knowledge. Just as one
might propose that settling involves complete control, one might propose that
knowledge involves certainty” (PEREBOOM, 2017, p. 631).
● It’s an imprecise term.
➔ “On my construal of event-causal libertarianism, control is a causal matter; since
settling which decision occurs would be the key control relation for securing
moral responsibility in paradigmatic cases, such settling must be a causal matter.
In addition, the event-causal libertarian claims that all causation is causation by
events. My claim is that, given these commitment of event-causal libertarianism,
the theory lacks the resources to explain how the agent can settle which decision
occurs in the equipoise situation. I contend that we understand what it means to
make such a claim about settling, and that Mele himself provides us with an account
that provides us with this understanding. It may be that in certain cases in which
what the agent does to settle which decision occurs is compatible with a smallish
probability that it does not occur, the agent nevertheless settles that the decision
occurs as required by moral responsibility for it in the basic-desert sense. I claim
that the relevant antecedently occurring agent-involving events don’t settle which
decision occurs in cases in which the probabilities are not in equipoise but are
significant on both sides, where the relevant boundary between smallish and
significant is vague” (PEREBOOM, 2017, p. 632);
➔ “At this point, the event-causal libertarian might contend that causation by appropriate
agent-involving events in the equipoise case is sufficient for settling which decision
occurs. After all, the agent is involved in each of the two competing sets of
antecedent events, so, no matter which decision results, she herself will have
settled which one occurs. Mele would agree that which decision occurs is a matter of
luck, but would question the claim that the action is not free in the sense required for
attribution of basic-desert responsibility. Just as for the hard line response against
the manipulation argument, I doubt that there is a rationally coercive response
to this line. Like the manipulation argument, the disappearing agent argument
involves fishing for an intuition. In the manipulation argument, it’s for the
intuition of non-responsibility in a manipulation case; in the disappearing agent
argument, it’s for the intuition that the agent does not settle which decision
occurs in the equipoise case, supposing that settling is a causal matter, and thus
the agent is not morally responsible in the basic-desert sense. If the opponent
does not have this intuition, then the argument fails as a way to engage her, and
another medium for negotiating the dispute would have to be found. Mele may
be in this camp, and, if so, I have no rationally coercive way of showing him that
he’s mistaken. Still, others have the non-settling intuition, as I do, and this is
required for the argument to engage them” (PEREBOOM, 2017, p. 632)
➔ “Mele intimates that it is mistaken to contend that the event-causal libertarian can
allow only events antecedent to a decision to settle whether a decision occurs. He
objects to my formulation of the concern insofar as it employs the future tense ‘will
occur’” (PEREBOOM, 2017, p. 632)
◆ “This formulation suggests that settling would result from events that occur at
least in part antecedently to the decision, and not by events that occur only
simultaneously with the decision, which Mele thinks should be permitted for
the event-causal libertarian. As I said, in my discussion of event-causal
libertarians, I’m assuming that they are committed to the claim that
control in action is a causal matter. It’s the non-causalists who hold that
control in action is non-causal. If the locus of moral responsibility is an
agent’s decision, and if control is a causal matter, then it would seem that
control in settling which decision occurs would be a function of how the
decision is caused. On event-causal libertarianism, only events can be
causes, so control in settling which decision occurs would, then, be a
matter of the causing of the decision by events, and some of these would
be agent-involving events. The agent-involving events would at least
typically be belief-events and desire-events. And, in the usual case, if a
decision is caused by beliefs and desires, the beliefs and the desires would
exist for at least a short time prior to the decision. Thus it would make
sense to describe such a case as one in which the occurrence of such events
do or do not settle whether the decision will occur. At the same time, I have
no convincing argument against the claim that it’s possible for a decision to be
caused by belief-events and desire-events that occur precisely at the time of
the decision and not at earlier times. Such simultaneous event causation is
controversial but sometimes endorsed. But I’m happy to accommodate Mele’s
recommendation and eliminate the apparent futurity requirement”
(PEREBOOM, 2017, p. 633).
➔ Talking about Agent’s in ECL: “On the assumption that event-causal libertarianism is
committed to a broadly causal theory of action, and to the claim that all causes of
actions are events, this position is committed to the thesis that all causal
influences on action are most fundamentally event causal, and thus explicable in
exclusively event-causal terms. So what is Mele claiming when he says that Sam’s
‘intentions, beliefs, skills, and the like do not sink free throws’? He can’t mean that in
the sinking of a free throw Sam is a causal influence distinct from Sam-involving
events and states. It of course sounds odd to say that a collection of events or states
sinks a free throw, and we don’t talk this way. But the event-causal libertarian must
affirm that what grounds the truth of the claim ‘Sam sank the free throw’ is that a
collection of events, a number of them Sam-involving, caused a further event, the
ball’s going through the hoop. What’s at issue here isn’t how we’re used to
speaking, but the metaphysical commitments of an event-causal theory of action”
(PEREBOOM, 2017, p. 634)
➔ “I maintain that the disappearing agent argument successfully targets the semantic
position according to which claims such as ‘‘Sam sank the free throw’’ are true, but
the causal relations that make them true are solely event-causal relations. I also
believe that it is successful against the metaphysical position that all substance-causal
relations reduce to event-causal relations. But let me note that I do not claim that the
argument successfully targets a position according to which agents as substances are
causes, and such substance causation does not reduce to causation by events, but is
instead (non-reductively) constituted by or grounded in causation solely by events at
more basic levels. (I tentatively affirm a deterministic version of an agent-causal
picture of this non-reductive sort (2015)). Such a view endorses the metaphysical
thesis that there is unreduced causation by agents fundamentally as substances, and
thus denies that all causation is event-causation, a claim essential to the views the
disappearing agent argument is designed to undercut” (PEREBOOM, 2017, p. 634)
Deflationary Responses
➔ Balaguer: it is the agent who does the choosing - consciously, intentionally and
purposefully. It is she who does the just-choosing (PEREBOOM, 2017);
◆ Balaguer 2010, 2014.
➔ Clarke:
◆ Pereboom: “on an event-causal libertarian picture, the relevant causal
conditions antecedent to the decision, i.e., the occurrence of certain
agent-involving events, do not settle whether the decision will occur
(Pereboom 2014, 32)” (PEREBOOM, 2017);
◆ Clarke → “The Rejoinder: the making of the decision by S at t to A settles
whether the decision is made then” (PEREBOOM, 2017);
● “Settling happens exactly when the decision is made” (PEREBOOM,
2017) → Franklin 2014, Clarke 2017.
● “After all, that matter is not settled by anything prior to t (for the
decision is not determined by anything prior to t); and nothing more
than the making of the decision at t is needed to settle the matter
then. Further, since it is S who makes the decision, S, in making that
decision, settles at t whether that decision is made then. For given
that nothing prior to t settles whether that decision is made then, S
need not do anything more than decide at t to A in order to settle
at t whether that decision is made then. An event-causal libertarian
theory, then, has the resources to satisfy the settling requirement SR”
(PEREBOOM, 2017).
○ “(SR) If an agent S freely decides at time t to A, then S settles
at t whether that decision is made then” (PEREBOOM, 2017)
● “To clarify, by ‘the making of the decision’, what is meant is simply
the occurrence of the mental action of deciding. If such a mental
action occurs, then a making of a decision takes place; the latter is
nothing more and nothing less than—it is—the former. (Clarke 2017)”
(PEREBOOM, 2017)
◆ Pereboom:
● Confusion between the meanings of settling:
○ Clarke: “the occurrence of the mental action of deciding settles
which decision occurs in the sense of making a certain
proposition about the decision true” (PEREBOOM, 2017);
○ This is not what Pereboom means by settling: “settling, as I
use the term in the context of the disappearing agent argument,
is an exercise of control, and the event-causal libertarian is
committed to this exercise of control being a causal matter”
(PEREBOOM, 2017);
● What does it mean to say “the making of the decision by S at t to
A”?
○ “The making of the decision by S would consist in the causing
of the event S’s deciding to A at t by S-involving events, say
(desire) E1 and (belief) E2. In Balaguer’s example, Ralph’s
just-deciding is caused by, say, his desiring to star on Broadway
and his believing that moving to New York will facilitate this
aim. But given indeterminism and equipoise, there will be
other events, E3 and E4, set to cause the alternative
action-event, S’s deciding to B at t, in Ralph’s case, deciding to
stay in Mayberry, with the same antecedent probability.
However, at this point there is nothing left to settle whether
S’s deciding to A at t by contrast with S’s deciding to B at t
occurs. Only E1-E2 and E3-E4 are candidates for this role,
but they don’t settle which decision-event occurs. This is the
disappearing agent argument, and so far we’ve encountered no
convincing event-causal libertarian response.” (PEREBOOM,
2017);
➔ Different Directions:
◆ Reinterpreting Agent-Causality:
● Part 1:
● “On one variety of the agent-causal view, decisions are
agent-causings, which in turn might be analyzed as activations
of an agent-causal power” (PEREBOOM, 2017);
● “On this picture, which decision occurs is not settled by the
agent causing it, but instead by virtue of its being an
agent-causing” (PEREBOOM, 2017);
● Adapting to Event-Causality: “the decision is an event-causing,
and we can plausibly claim that its occurrence is settled by
virtue of its being identical to the event-causing”
(PEREBOOM, 2017);
● Problem: these views are non-causal;
◆ “His conception of the agent-causal position doesn’t
really preserve the specification that control is a causal
matter. In this conception, the agent does not cause her
causings, and thus the relation between the agent and
the decision is in fact non-causal” (PEREBOOM, 2017)
● Part 2:
○ “In agent causing my raising my arm at t1 I also bring about the
event my agent-causing my raising my arm at ti - that is, I also
bring about my deciding to raise my arm at t1. Since bring
about just is causing, I thus also cause my decision”
(PEREBOOM, 2017);
○ Event Causalism: “S can exercise control over action A by
virtue of S-involving events causing A. S’s deciding to A at t1
would in such cases be identical to the complex event
S-involving events causing A at t1. In causing A at t1, the
S-involving events bring about, and thus cause, the event
S-involving events causing A at t1, which is S’s deciding to
A at t1” (PEREBOOM, 2017)
◆ Problem: “Given motivational equipoise, the
S-involving events don’t settle whether A occurs,
and thus don’t settle whether the decision to A
occurs. In this analogy, the causes of the decision are
inherited from the action, and since the causes of the
action don’t settle whether the action occurs, they don’t
settle whether the decision occurs either”
(PEREBOOM, 2017).
◆ Non-Causalism: one might just specify that “the making of the decision by S
at t to A” is to be interpreted non-causally;
● Problem: “This option might be considered on its own merits, but it is
at odds with the view that control exercised in settling is a causal
matter, a commitment of event-causal libertarianism, at least as it’s
usually set out.” (PEREBOOM, 2017).
➔ Pereboom is open to the claim that the disappearing agent argument extends to a
successful objection to event-causal theories of actions generally;
➔ This event-causal accounts “cannot account for the settling role in action that the
agent intuitively can have in situations of rational equipoise” (PEREBOOM, 2017)
➔ “If agent causation is required to solve the disappearing agent problem for
event-causal libertarianism, now it appears to be required to solve a disappearing
agent problem that arises for the event-causal theory of agency more generally”
(PEREBOOM, 2017);
➔ Pereboom can adopt a deterministic account of agent causation: “As on the libertarian
version, agency (or at least full-blooded agency) is accounted for by the existence of
agents who as substances have the power to cause actions. But by contrast with the
libertarian counterpart, in the exercise of their agent-causal power agents are in
general causally determined by factors beyond their control” (PEREBOOM, 2017)
➔ “I don’t believe, however, that the disappearing agent argument that aims at
event-causal theories of action generally is as strong as the one that targets only
event-causal libertarianism. This is because the more general argument requires
an equipoise situation, while the less general one does not. Event-causal
libertarians agree that agents have freedom of choice in non-equipoise situations,
and the settling problem arises in such cases as well.” (PEREBOOM, 2017)
➔ Pereboom: “If factors beyond the agent’s control, rather than determining a single
decision, instead simply leave open which decision will occur, and the agent has no
greater role in the production of the decision than she does in the deterministic
context, then there is no more reason to think that she is morally responsible than
there is in the deterministic context. So it appears that the event-causal libertarian can
supplement the deterministic context only with the relaxation of the causal net.
(Pereboom 2007, 195)” (PEREBOOM, 2017);
➔ Pereboom changed his mind: “Given that I allow for deterministic agent causation,
and that I am open to the possibility that indeterministic agent causation does secure
the sort of free will required for moral responsibility, then relative to deterministic
agent causation mere relaxing of the causal net may indeed precipitate the sort of
control required for moral responsibility. So I cannot accept the general principle that
mere relaxation of the causal net cannot enhance control in the relevant way, a
principle essential to the “no enhanced control” objection.” (PEREBOOM, 2017)
➔ “Given exactly the same conditions antecedent to t1 as those that precede S’s decision
in the actual world, S’s deciding to A at t1 might not have occurred” (PEREBOOM,
2017)
➔ Problem: “As Mele (1999, 2006) and Haji (2004) emphasize, given the same history
antecedent to t1 as those that precede G, and given the indeterminism of the
agent-causal libertarian view, G might not have occurred. Thus there is a non-actual
possible world, W*, that shares a history up to t1 with the actual world, W, but while
G occurs in W, it fails to occur in W*. But is the fact that G occurred merely a matter
of responsibility-undermining luck?” (PEREBOOM, 2017);
◆ But, in agent-causal libertarianism: “If in addition to the events that precede G
we hold fixed in W and W* the agent-as-substance’s exercise of her
agent-causal power, G will occur in W and not in W*, but only because the
agent-as-substance causes the action A in W but not in W*. For this reason, it
isn’t a matter of responsibility-undermining luck that G occurs in W.”
(PEREBOOM, 2017)
● “This last claim is indeed controversial (Clarke 2010), but I find it
compelling. Thus in my view, present luck does not, in general,
preclude the control required for moral responsibility.” (PEREBOOM,
2017)
➔ “But event-causal determinists can hold that situations in which motivating reasons
don’t causally determine scarcely ever arise, if at all, and if they do, the agent can
deploy a psychological device functionally similar to the throw of the dice, instead of
settling by just choosing. Thus event-causal determinism remains a viable option”
(PEREBOOM, 2017)
Pereboom, D. 2001. Living without Free Will, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. P. 81
Pereboom, D. 2017. “A Defense of Free Will Skepticism: Replies to Victor Tadros, Saul Smilansky, Michael
McKenna, and Alfred Mele on my Free Will, Agency, and Meaning in Life,” Criminal Law and Philosophy,
DOI:10.1007/s11572-017-9412-2.
➔ “The objection is not that agents have no causal role in producing decisions, but that
agents have insufficient causal role for the control that moral responsibility
demands” (PEREBOOM, 2014, p. 61);
◆ “What needs to be added to the event-causal libertarian account is
involvement of the agent in the production of her decisions that would
enhance her control so that she can settle which decision occurs, and thereby
be the source of her decisions in a way that allows for moral responsibility.
The agent-causal libertarian’s proposal is to reintroduce the agent as a
cause, not merely as involved in events, but rather fundamentally as a
substance. If the agent were reintroduced merely as involved in events,
the DA argument could be reiterated with undiminished effect”
(PEREBOOM, 2014, p. 61).
➔ Pereboom attacks Balaguer’s View (PEREBOOM, 2014, pp. 62-63):
◆ Given that the account is event-causal libertarian, it’s crucial to see how this
story is to be told in event-causal terms. Reference to agents being causally
influenced by reasons, or agents causing decisions, is to be recast in terms of
causation among events.
◆ Here are the relevant events:
● E1: Ralph’s desiring at t1–tn to play for the Giants,
● E2: Ralph’s desiring at t1–tn to star on Broadway,
● E3: Ralph’s desiring at t1–tn to marry Robbi Anna,
● E4: Ralph’s desiring at t1–tn to manage the local Der Wienerschnitzel,
● E5: Ralph’s deciding at tn to move to New York,
● E6: Ralph’s deciding at tn to stay in Mayberry. In the actual situation,
● E1 and E2 probabilistically cause E5.
◆ The DA objection counts against the supposition that this account secures the
control required for moral responsibility. Intuitively, this sort of control
requires the agent to settle which of the options for decision actually occurs,
and the event-causal libertarian view does not seem to allow for this in the
case of torn decisions. For on this picture, given the causal influence of
E1–E4, nothing settles whether it will be E5 or E6 that occurs. Thus the
agent does not settle whether E5 or E6 occurs. The objection concludes that
event-causal torn decisions cannot, in Balaguer’s terminology, be
appropriately nonrandom, and the indeterminacy in question cannot
increase or procure the appropriate nonrandomness, for the reason that
appropriate control is missing: Ralph does not control which option is
chosen (2009, p. 83). Moreover, authorship is missing if this sort of control
is required for authorship.
➔ Balaguer’s Response: it is Ralph who decides;
◆ Two Ways to Construct the Claim:
● Pure-Event Causal: ‘Ralph decides to move to New York is to be
analyzed as: Ralph-involving events E1-E2 probabilistically cause
Ralph-involving event E5.” (PEREBOOM, 2014, p. 64);
○ “On this option, the objection that Ralph has insufficient
control over which decision is made retains all of its original
force. Balaguer claims: ‘‘if the just-choosing were done by
anything other than the agent, the she would lose authorship
and control.’’ (2007, p. 97). But the concern is that if the
just-choosing is what gets Ralph the control, and, in the
spirit of event-causal libertarianism, control is a causal
matter, then it seems that what is being specified is that a
causal relation obtains between Ralph himself and the
decision. However, the event-causal libertarian allows only
causal relations among events, and not a fundamental
causal relation between agent and event.” (PEREBOOM,
2014, p. 64)
● Non-Causal: “Ralph decides to move to New York specifies a
non-causal relation between Ralph and a decision, perhaps the relation
of being-the-subject-of.” (PEREBOOM, 2014, p. 64).
➔ Kane focusing on the phenomenology of the decision making process: “But any
incompatibilist has reason to be wary of this response, since a compatibilist could as
easily appeal to this same sort of phenomenological consideration in response to the
objection that agents cannot be responsible for causally determined actions (Pereboom
2001, 2007). A compatibilist might argue that if an agent experienced her causally
determined decision as resulting from an outside determining force, she would have
good reason to believe that she was not making choice for which she was morally
responsible. If, by contrast, a causally determined decision were experienced as
voluntary and resulting from the agent’s effort of will, she would have a strong reason
to believe she was morally responsible for it.” (PEREBOOM, 2014, p. 65)
PEREBOOM - Is Our Conception of Agent-Causation Coherent? (2004)
➔ “What is required for settling which decision one makes?” (FRANKLIN, 2014, p.
424);
➔ “The agent’s contribution in virtue of which he settles which decision is made occurs
simultaneous with his making the decision” (FRANKLIN, 2014, p. 425);
➔ “Why not just think that the agent’s making the decision suffices for his settling which
decision he makes?” (FRANKLIN, 2014, p. 425);
◆ “What makes it the case that the agent fails to settle which decision will occur
is a combination of two factors: that the decision is undetermined and that the
agent’s causal role is exhausted by the agent’s antecedent states and events. It
is this second feature that differentiates event-causal from agent-causal
accounts, and it is this second feature that renders event-causal libertarianism
susceptible to the disappearing agent argument” (FRANKLIN, 2014, p. 426).
➔ “But by enriching event-causal libertarianism with a reductive theory of
selfdetermination, we acquire the needed resources to respond to Pereboom’s
objection. For, on the account I developed above, it is false that the agent’s specific
desires and beliefs for action exhaust his causal contribution. In addition, the agent
himself intervenes, or could have intervened, in virtue of the causal power of his
desire to act in accordance with what he takes to be the best reasons—a desire with
which he is identified. Consider again the story of the thief and let us suppose that his
decision to refrain from stealing was self-determined. On my account, his desire to act
in accordance with the strongest reasons combined with, and supplemented the
motivational force of, his desires and beliefs that favored this action to jointly cause
his decision to refrain from stealing. In this way, the agent does play an additional
causal role in settling on what to do. Now suppose that although the decision to
refrain was free, it was not self-determined (suppose in this case the thief judged that
it was best to steal). In that case the thief did not play an additional causal role
(although he could have), but instead let his motivational factors sort themselves out,
perhaps doing whatever he felt like at the moment of action. But even agentcausal
libertarians should not require that every instance of free action be selfdetermined. It
should be enough to require that every instance of free action is one in which the
agent could have brought his power of self-determination to bear. So the thief did play
an additional causal role beyond that of his specific desires and beliefs for action: he
also determined (or could have determined) which set of desires and beliefs he acted
on. This determination does not require the agent, qua substance, to cause his action,
but rather that a state that is functionally identical to him and with which he is
identified plays the relevant causal role” (FRANKLIN, 2014, p. 426)
➔ “The problem with traditional event-causal libertarians is not that they reduce the role
of the self-determining agent to states and events; the problem is with the specific
states and events they attempt to reduce his role to. Once we enrich the reductive base
to include a state with which the agent is identified and that plays his functional role,
such as the desire to act in accordance with the strongest reasons, we provide all the
resources needed to furnish the agent with the power to settle which decision he
makes. Therefore, premise (1) is false” (FRANKLIN, 2014, p. 427).
➔ “If the agent’s decision was solely caused by the agent’s desires and beliefs for one of
the two decisions, then there was indeed an important role that the agent failed to
play: he failed to intervene between his reasons and the making of his decision. I then
explained that this is not the story I offer. On my account, in addition to the desires
and beliefs for action playing a causal role, the desire to act in accordance with the
strongest reasons—a desire that is functionally identical to the agent and with which
he is identified—also plays, or could have played, a causal role. It is in light of this
additional causal role that the agent determines, or could have determined, and thus
settled, what he would do.” (FRANKLIN, 2014, p. 427);
➔ “The desire to act in accordance with the strongest reasons does not introduce a new
decision in the action-sequence, but introduces a new causal antecedent to decision.
On the account I am espousing, the agent’s desire to act for reasons combines with
one set of desires and beliefs for action to jointly cause the decision. The decision is
undetermined and so it was possible that the agent’s other set of desires and beliefs for
action, without the additional force of his desire to act in accordance with the
strongest reasons, caused him to make a different decision. My introducing this desire
does not introduce a new and earlier decision in the action-sequence and so I am not
guilty of endlessly positing earlier decisions to forestall the original query”
(FRANKLIN, 2014, p. 428)
➔ Self-Determination does not need determination:
◆ “The notion of ‘determination’ in ‘self-determination’ is the notion of ‘settling
or resolving some issue’, such as what to do” (FRANKLIN, 2014, p. 429);
● “When deliberating about what to do I determine my action by causing
my choice to pursue a course of action—I settle what to do by causing
my choice. This is the sense of self-determination that seems required
for free will” (FRANKLIN, 2014, p. 429)
◆ The second instance trades on the meaning of ‘determination’: here
‘determination’ means something like ‘deterministically caused’. It is only this
second sense of ‘determined’ that is contrary to ‘undetermined’ (which I
assume is being used univocally to mean ‘not deterministically caused’).
➔ “On my account, the agent is robustly present during the moment of self-determined
action and makes his distinctive contribution by having his desire to act in accordance
with the strongest reasons add force to the desires and beliefs that favor the decision
he makes” (FRANKLIN, 2014, p. 429)
➔ “By reducing the role of the agent in action to a state with which the agent is
identified and that plays his functional role, we preserve the presence of the agent at
the moment of decision. In addition to all the motivational states that do not play the
role of the self-determining agent in action, such as beliefs and desires for particular
actions, the agent himself contributes to his decision in virtue of the desire to act for
best reasons causally contributing to his decision.” (FRANKLIN, 2014, p. 430)
Introduction
➔ “In each of these quotations, the future tense is used. So, as Pereboom understands
agent causation, are agents who decide to A supposed to settle what they will decide
(or whether they will decide to A) before they decide to A? If so, how would they do
that? Would they agent-cause a decision (or intention) to make another decision a bit
later— a decision to A? (The former decision is a second- order decision.) Would they
agent- cause some process or other that issues a bit later in their deciding to A? I
doubt this is the kind of thing Pereboom has in mind” (MELE, 2015, p. 569; MELE,
2017a, p. 162)
➔ “In the absence of substantial guidance about what it is for an agent to settle at t what
he decides at t, how should one proceed?” (MELE, 2015, p. 569; MELE, 2017a, p.
162)
Other
➔ “If the same readers assume that settling whether one decides to A depends on
agent-causal power because such settling requires exercising complete control over
what one decides” (MELE, 2015, p. 571; MELE, 2017a, p. 167);
➔ Is Settling Necessary to Moral Responsibility? → “A key claim in Pereboom’s
disappearing agent objection is that, if neither the agent nor ‘‘anything about the agent
settles whether the decision will occur,’’ the agent lacks ‘‘the control required for
basic desert moral responsibility for it’’ (p. 32). I do not understand this claim well
enough to assess it, because, despite my efforts, I do not have a good grip on what
is meant by settling whether a decision will occur” (MELE, 2015, p. 572; MELE,
2017a, p. 167)
◆ “Depending on how settling what one decides (or will decide) is supposed to
be understood, Eve’s decision being partly a matter of luck may preclude her
having settled what she decided (or what she would decide). But does it
preclude her having decided freely and her having basic desert moral
responsibility for her decision?” (MELE, 2015, p. 572; MELE, 2017a, p.
177).
● “There was some chance that Eve would decide at t to reject the job
and some chance that she would decide then to accept it. It is likely
that there was also a chance that Eve would, at t, continue to be
unsettled about what to do and continue deliberating about the job
offer, and there might have been a chance of her mind beginning to
wander at t (among other things). Consider these chances— or
antecedent probabilities— very shortly before t. If they came out of the
blue, wholly as a matter of luck, that would be cause for worry about
Eve. But they did not. They were shaped in significant part by Eve’s
evidence gathering and her deliberation. These antecedent probabilities
were also shaped partly by Eve’s long- term preferences and values,
and these preferences and values were in turn shaped by past decisions
Eve made, by what she learned from past successes and mistakes in
decision- making, and so on.” (MELE, 2015, p. 572; MELE, 2017a, p.
177)
○ “Imagine that we are like Eve in that, sometimes, the processes
that issue in our decisions are such that it is at no time
determined what we will decide. Even so, our values,
preferences, learning history, information gathering,
deliberation, and so on constrain the physically and
psychologically possible outcomes and shape the antecedent
probabilities of the outcomes. If we come to know that we are
like Eve in this respect and the indeterminism worries us, we
should do our best to minimize our chances of making poor
decisions by working on developing good habits of decision-
making and good habits in general. If we learn that we are like
Eve in the respect at issue, should we also infer that we never
act freely? It may be said that someone like me who believes
that Eve may decide freely and have basic desert moral
responsibility for her decision sets the bar for free action and
this sort of moral responsibility very close to where a
compatibilist sets it. This might make me worry, if there were
an argument that convinced me that compatibilism is false. But
there is no such argument.” (MELE, 2015, pp. 572-573; MELE,
2017a, p. 178)
➔ “Owing to my inadequate grip on what Pereboom means by an agent’s settling
whether a decision will occur (and on what it is to exercise complete control over
what one will decide, if that is what he means), I am not in a position to assess the
proposal that the problem posed by his disappearing agent objection is deeper
than, for example, what I called ‘‘the problem of present luck’’ (Mele 2006, p.
69). An ideal, reader-friendly version of Pereboom’s presentation of his disappearing
agent objection would include substantial guidance on what it is for an agent to
settle whether a decision will (or does) occur. Ideally, the reader would get an initial
sketch of an account of this settling that does not refer to agent causation and
then an explanation of why it is that “event- causal” libertarian agents” cannot
do anything that satisfies the account. If no sketch of decision settling is even
intelligible without reference to agent causation, a reader- friendly version of the
presentation would explain why that is so. Also if the guidance provided on settling
does not render it obvious that basic desert moral responsibility for a decision
one made depends on one’s having settled whether that decision would (or did)
occur, a reader-friendly version of the presentation would include an argument
for this thesis about settling and responsibility” (MELE, 2015, p. 573; MELE.
2017, pp. 178-179);
➔ “An account of what it is to settle whether one will (or does) decide to A may
prove illuminating. Possibly, with an account of such settling in place, we will be
able to ascertain, among other things, whether settling whether one will (or does)
decide to A is required for freely deciding to A and for basic desert moral
responsibility for one’s decision” (MELE, 2015, pp. 573-574; MELE, 2017a, p. 179)
➔ “Commenting on Griffith: “Taking our lead from this, we have an answer to my
questions about the alleged power to “determine the decision.” It is the power to
completely control which decision one makes.” (MELE, 2017a, p. 169)
➔ “In my view, even if the difference between what an agent does at t in one world and
what he does at t in another world with the same past up to t and the same laws of
nature is just a matter of luck, the agent may perform a directly free action at t in both
worlds (Mele 2006, chap. 5). This is the thesis I labeled LDF in chapter 6.” (MELE,
2017a, p. 169)
➔ “Now, anyone can say that something or other is the power to completely control
which decision one makes. An event- causal libertarian can say this about some non-
agent- causal decision- making power, and so can a noncausalist libertarian. One thing
I would like to know is how replacing event- caused decisions or uncaused decisions
with agent- caused decisions (or intentions) is supposed to make true something that
would otherwise supposedly be false— namely, that the decisions are made by
someone who exercised the power to completely control which decision he made (or
which intention he came to have). (On this sort of thing, see Mele 2006, chap. 3.)”
(MELE, 2017a, pp. 172-173)
➔ “What is complete control? And what is it for an agent to determine something?”
(MELE, 2017a, p. 173)
◆ “Suppose that the keyboard Sol is using has a randomizer on it that ensures
that there is always a small chance that a key he is trying to press will stick
and fail to make contact with the switch under it. (Recall the definition of a
key press above.) Then Sol never has complete control over whether he
presses the Q key or the P key. Suppose now that a randomizer has been
installed in Sol’s brain that ensures that there is always a small chance that his
proximal decisions to press a key— his decisions to press a specific key
straightaway— will not be followed by a corresponding attempt. Then Sol
never has complete control over whether he tries to press the Q key or tries to
press the P key (at least when no alternative route to attempt- production is in
use— that is, no route that does not include decisions). These observations
prompt the following two questions: Might Sol nevertheless freely have
pressed the Q key the last time he pressed it? Does a satisfactory account of a
person’s having complete control over whether he decides to A or decides to B
have a “no chance” clause? The correct answer to the first question, I believe,
is yes, provided that free actions are common in Sol’s world and it is possible
for agents to act freely when their options are of the kind featured in Buridan’s
ass scenarios” (MELE, 2017a, pp. 174-175)
◆ “What about the second question? According to a standard libertarian view, if
a person’s deciding to A is to be a directly free action, there was a chance,
right up to the time at which the decision was made, that he would not decide
then to A. But this alone does not obviously commit a proponent of this view
to claiming that no satisfactory account of a person’s having complete control
over whether he decides to A or decides to B can have a “no chance” clause.
One reason is that the following option is not obviously a nonstarter: having
complete control over whether one decides to A or decides to B is not
required for a directly free decision in favor of one or the other of these
courses of action.” (MELE, 2017a, p. 175)
● What is complete control?
○ “It can be said that having the kind of control at issue it a
matter of its being entirely up to the agent whether he decides
to A or decides to B or a matter of the agent’s having the power
to determine whether he decides (or intends) to A or decides (or
intends) to B” (MELE, 2017a, p. 175)
◆ “I would like to be told what it is for it to be entirely
up to an agent whether he decides to A or decides to
B and what it is to have the determining power at
issue” (MELE, 2017a, p. 175)
MALE, A. R. Free Will and Luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
➔ “Not every bit of luck that an agent has in a causal stream leading to an action
precludes moral responsibility for that action” (MELE, 2006, p. 108);
➔ Modest Libertarianism: indeterministic selection of what comes to an agent’s mind
before the deterministic choice;
➔ Mele argues that, even though the difference of the actual world and a possible world
is just a matter of luck, luck does not undermine Modest Libertarianism.
◆ “Does all agent-internal psychological luck in a causal stream leading to
action preclude moral responsibility for that action? No. Today, Bill luckily
remembers where he hid a treasure map years ago: he was indeterministically
caused to remember. Bill was arrested shortly after he hid it, and he has just
completed a twenty-year prison sentence. After he retrieves and sells the
treasure, Bill gives 25 percent of the proceeds to charity” (MELE, 2006, p.
109)
◆ “In Wn, because T unluckily fails to come to mind, Beth fails to gather
additional relevant information about the small town. But it is generally
granted that very few free decisions are made in the light of complete relevant
information. So, just as it is difficult to see why T’s unluckily not coming to
mind should be believed to preclude Beth’s being morally responsible for
accepting the job, it is difficult to see why it should be believed to preclude her
freely accepting the job. Furthermore, just as Bill’s luckily remembering
where he hid the map is not at odds with his freely making the donation he
makes, T’s luckily coming to mind in the actual world is not at odds with
Beth’s freely rejecting the job offer” (MELE, 2006, p. 112)
➔ “How should DSLs respond to the claim that the influence of agents’ actions on their
present probabilities of action is of no use to DSLs because an agent’s being subject to
cross-world luck at the time of action precludes his acting freely and morally
responsibly at that time, no matter how the pertinent practical probabilities came to be
as they are?” (MELE, 2006, p. 123)
➔ “It may be objected that DSLs are not entitled to make any claims about the
influence of past basically* free actions on present probabilities of action until
they have shown that there is good reason to believe that basically* free actions
are possible. However, DSLs should reply that the point they have made thus far in
that connection is simply that we should not believe that basically* free action is
impossible on the grounds that, necessarily, indeterministic agents’ probabilities
of action are externally imposed or that indeterministic agents necessarily are
related to their present probabilities of action roughly as dice are related to
present probabilities about how they will land if tossed” (MELE, 2006, pp. 125);
➔ “Can DSL accommodate basically* free akratic actions? If indeterministically caused
actions contrary to the agent’s CB were like outcomes of tosses of dice, they might
plausibly be deemed to be only apparently akratic and actually unfree. If agents were
to house neural randomizers with unchanging probabilities of continent and
akratic action or with probabilities that change independently of what agents
learn from their mistakes and successes, they would be subject to luck in a way
that seems to preclude their being basically* morally responsible for actions
contrary to their CB-s and to preclude their performing basically* free akratic
actions. But DSLs postulate neural equipment of a kind that agents are capable
of molding through, for example, reflection and efforts of self-control. They
contend that morally responsible agency is possible and that, over time, agents can
take on increased moral responsibility for their probabilities of action in the sphere in
which CB-s clash with temptation, probabilities that evolve in ways sensitive to what
agents have learned and their efforts at self-control” (MELE, 2006, p. 125);
➔ “How does an agent come to be morally responsible for anything? This is a question
for any theorist who believes that at least some human beings are morally responsible
agents. More fully, how do we get from being neonates who are not morally
responsible for anything to being the free, morally responsible agents we are now, if
we are indeed free and morally responsible agents? I return to this question in section
6 and point out now that one thing that is required is an S-ability to adjust our
behavior in light of what we learn from our past behavior. DSLs are claiming that this
ability includes an S-ability to mold our probabilities of akratic and continent action.”
(MELE, 2006, p. 125)
➔ If someone only acted in a way to diminish the probability of doing X, but, thanks to
present luck, does X, how can we say that this person is responsible?
Little Agents
➔ “The main question for DSL in this connection is whether it can accommodate the
possibility of a neonate’s developing into an agent capable of performing basically*
free actions for which he is basically* morally responsible” (MELE, 2006, p. 129);
➔ Degrees of Responsibility: “when normal four-year-olds snatch an appealing toy
from a younger sibling’s hands, most people take them to be morally responsible and
blameworthy for that, but not as responsible and not as blameworthy as their normal
eight-year-old siblings are for doing the same thing” (MELE, 2006, p. 129);
➔ “When he saw Tony move away from his sister and pick up something else to
play with, he praised him for his good behavior. The father was not simply trying
to reinforce the good behavior; he believed that Tony really deserved some credit
for it. Suppose now that owing to Tony’s being an indeterministic decision maker
and to his being tempted to take the toy, there was a significant chance at the
time that he would decide to take it. In another world with the same past and laws
of nature, that is what he decides to do, and he proceeds to grab the toy (with
predictable results). Does that entail that Tony has no moral responsibility at all for
deciding not to take the toy? Well, he is only a child, and if he can be morally
responsible for anything, he can be so only in ways appropriate for young
children, if moral responsibility is possible for young children. It does not seem
at all outlandish to believe that Tony would deserve, from a moral point of view,
some blame in the world in which he decides to snatch the toy and acts
accordingly—but blame appropriate to his age and the nature of his offense, of
course. If he does deserve some such blame, he has some moral responsibility for
the decision. Similarly, the father’s belief that Tony deserves some moral credit for
his good decision is far from outlandish. If he does deserve such credit, it is of a kind
appropriate to his age and the nature of his action, and he has some moral
responsibility for the decision. The difference at t (the time of Tony’s decision)
between the actual world and a world with the same past and laws in which Tony
decides at t to snatch the toy is just a matter of luck. That should be taken into account
when asking about Tony’s moral responsibility for deciding not to take the toy. Only
a relatively modest degree of moral responsibility is at issue, and the question is
whether the cross-world luck—or the luck together with other facts about the
case—entails that the degree is zero. I doubt that the knowledge that all actual
decision-making children are indeterministic decision makers like Tony would
lead us to believe that no children are morally responsible at all for any of their
decisions. Views according to which agents’ past decisions can contribute to their
moral responsibility for their present decisions naturally lead us to wonder about the
earliest decisions for which agents are morally responsible. When we do wonder
about that, we need to keep firmly in mind how young these agents may be and
how trivial their good and bad deeds may be by comparison with the full range
of good and bad adult deeds. Tony’s making the right or the wrong decision
about the toy is not that big a deal, and that is something for theorists to bear in
mind when trying to come to a judgment about whether Tony is morally responsible
for his decision. If, when pondering whether an indeterministic decision maker
can make a first decision for which he is morally responsible, a theorist is
focusing on scenarios in which adults make decisions about important moral
matters, cross-world luck at the time of decision should strike the theorist as at
least seriously problematic on grounds associated with the worries presented in
chapter 3. But this focus is very wide of the mark” (MELE, 2006, pp. 130-131);
➔ “Tony might occasionally deserve some unpleasant words or some pleasant praise;
and, to use Strawson’s expression, ‘‘it makes sense to propose’’ that Tony has, for
some of his decisions, a degree of moral responsibility that would contribute to the
justification of these mild punishments and rewards—even if those decisions are
made at times at which the past and the laws leave open alternative courses of action,
owing to Tony’s being an indeterministic decision maker” (MELE, 2006, p. 131);
➔ “But if people are morally responsible for some things, they have to develop from
neonates into morally responsible agents, and Tony’s decision not to take the toy is a
reasonable candidate for an action for which this young agent is morally responsible”
(MELE, 2006, p. 131);
➔ “Moral responsibility is very commonly and very plausibly regarded as a matter of
degree. If young children and adults are morally responsible for some of what they do,
it is plausible, on grounds of the sort I mentioned, that young children are not nearly
as morally responsible for any of their deeds as some adults are for some of their adult
deeds. When we combine our recognition of that point with the observation that the
good and bad deeds of young children are relatively trivial in themselves, we should
be struck by the implausibility of stringent standards for deserved moral praise and
blame of young children—including standards the satisfaction of which requires the
absence of present luck. And once even a very modest degree of moral responsibility
is in the picture, DSLs can begin putting their ideas about the shaping of practical
probabilities to work” (MELE, 2006, pp. 131-132)
➔ “What DSLs say about agents’ shaping of their practical probabilities is meant to help
us understand, among other things, how we get from being little free agents like Tony
to being the mature free agents we are, if, in fact, we are free agents. The free agency
at issue is an incompatibilist kind, not a compatibilist kind to which DSLs are open,
given their softness. The process, if it is real, would seem to be very gradual, and I
will not try to trace it. DSLs claim that, other things being equal, as the frequency
of the indeterministically caused free actions of little agents increases and as the
range of kinds of situations evoking such free actions expands, the agents take on
greater moral responsibility for associated practical probabilities of theirs and
for their morally significant free actions. This, DSLs say, helps to account for the
fact that the moral credit and blame that little free agents deserve for their
indeterministically caused free actions tend to increase over time” (MELE, 2006, p.
132)
◆ How are they responsible for the first lucky decision?
➔ “Now, given that Bob does have a history of the right sort, DSLs maintain that what
probabilities of action obtain at the time is not just a matter of luck. But probabilities
of action are one kind of thing, and the difference at noon between Bob’s cheating
then in W1 and his flipping the coin then in W2 is another. Suppose that if Bob had
performed different free actions in the past, as he could have, his probabilities of
action at noon would have been different and that, at one time, a history was open to
Bob—one including his performing relevant character-influencing basically free
actions—such that, if that history had been actual, it would have resulted in Bob’s
having, at the time, a probability of 0 of very high probability of tossing the coin, as
promised” (MELE, 2006, p. 133)
◆ “The supposition would reveal something about Bob, but it is irrelevant to the
question whether, holding fixed the actual past and the laws of nature, the
difference at noon between Bob’s cheating then, as he does in W1, and Bob’s
flipping the coin then, as he does in W2, is just a matter of luck. And again,
the actual past and the laws are held fixed when testing for basically (and
basically*) free and morally responsible action. Even if the practical
accessibility of the worlds open to Bob at the pertinent time is partly explained
by basically free actions he performed at earlier times, the cross-world
difference in Bob’s noontime actions in W1 and W2 is just a matter of luck”
(MELE, 2006, p. 133)
➔ “DSLs grant that if, in the actual world, an agent decides at t to A, whereas in
another possible world with the same laws of nature and the same past he
decides at t not to A, then the cross-world difference at t is just a matter of luck.
But they hold that the fact that the difference is just a matter of luck is
compatible with its being true that the agent decided freely and morally
responsibly at t. To be sure, hard eventcausal libertarians and agent-causationists can
make this compatibility claim, too. According to DSLs, the main problem with the
most detailed event-causal libertarian view on offer, Kane’s, is not that it is subject to
the problem of present luck but rather that its account of what agents do in cases of
basically free action for which they are basically morally responsible is
unsatisfactory” (MELE, 2006, pp. 133-134)
➔ “Modest libertarians hold that if (ML1) an agent’s A-ing satisfies a set of alleged
sufficient conditions for free action that a sophisticated compatibilist would endorse
and that many sophisticated folks who have no commitment to incompatibilism would
find very attractive, including the condition that the agent A-s on the basis of a
rational deliberative judgment that it would be best to A, and (ML2) while the agent
was deliberating, it was causally open that he would not come to the conclusion that it
would be best to A, then (ML3) the agent freely A-s. (The specific compatibilist
proposal that I offered [Mele 1995, p. 193] is summarized in ch. 7, sec. 1.) Modest
libertarianism does not include a position on the possibility of free actions that are not
performed on the basis of a judgment about what it would be best to do. Proponents of
daring soft libertarianism substitute the following for ML2 : (DSL2) the agent’s
A-ing is a decision the proximate causes of which do not deterministically cause
it. They maintain that the combination of ML1 and DSL2 is conceptually
sufficient for the agent’s decision’s being basically* free. They maintain, as well,
that there are basically* free akratic decisions.” (MELE, 2006, p. 134)
➔ Libertarianism:
◆ It’s a “necessary condition for a directly free action that there is no time at
which it is determined (in the ‘deterministic causation’ sense of determined)
that the action will occur” (MELE, 2017b, p. 59);
◆ Positive Side: free will is actual and actually exercised by real people”
(MELE, 2017b, p. 59);
◆ Both Thesis imply that: “at least some of sometimes perform actions that are
deterministically caused by their proximal causes” (MELE, 2017b, pp. 59-60)
➔ Event-Causal: “appeal to indeterministic causation by events and states” (MELE,
2017b, p. 49);
◆ Event-Causal Libertarian Views hold “that although directly free actions are
caused, they are not deterministically caused by their proximal causes”
(MELE, 2017b, p. 59)
➔ Mele is not a libertarian, because he does not endorse incompatibilism (MELE,
2017b, p. 49);
➔ Soft Libertarian: asserts that free action and moral responsibility may be compatible
with determinism (MELE, 2017b, p. 50);
➔ Daring Libertarian: “maintains that there are free actions such a kind that it is at no
time determined that the action will occur” (MELE, 2017b, p. 50);
◆ A Daring Libertarian may or may not be a Soft Libertarian (MELE,
2017b, p. 50);
● If she is a Soft Libertarian, she adopts Daring Soft Libertarianism.
➔ Basically Free Actions: “free A-ings that occur at times at which the past (up to
those times) and the laws of nature are consistent with the agent’s not A-ing” (MELE,
2017b, pp. 50-51).
◆ “An agent performs a basically free action A at a time only if there is another
possible world with the same past up to t and the same laws of nature in which
he does not do A at t” (MELE, 2017b, p. 51).
● Problem of Present Luck: “the cross-world difference in decisions at
t is just a matter of luck” (MELE, 2017b, p. 51).
➔ "Whether an action is self-forming or not depends on its effects on the agent’s
‘will’” (MELE, 2017b, p. 51).
Commentaries on Kane
➔ Dual efforts seem remote from ordinary experience (MELE, 2017b, p. 53);
➔ Kane’s Theory is a victim of the Problem of Present Luck: in different possible worlds
with the same laws of nature and the same past right up to the choice, different
outcomes happen - there is no difference in the efforts. The difference between both
worlds is just a matter of luck (MELE, 2017b, p. 57)
➔ “We can say, if we like, that in fully depressing the cat key, Donna made her reasons
to help cats prevail. And this claim can be counted as true, if we do not read too much
into it. But the truth of the claim is utterly compatible with the difference in the two
worlds at the time at issue being just a matter of luck” (MELE, 2017b, p. 63);
◆ “Which reasons prevail is up for grabs until he makes his choice, and the
prevailing of a collection of reasons is precisely a matter of Bob’s choosing for
those reasons – that is, his choosing for reasons RC to cheat or his choosing
for reasons RT to do the right thing. Again, in one world one set of reasons
prevails at t, and in another world a competing set of reasons prevails at t –
and there is no cross-world difference in the reasons, Bob’s efforts, or
anything else before t” (MELE, 2017b, pp. 63-64).
➔ He could not say that the agent is responsible for the contrastive fact: X is not
responsible for the fact that she Y-ed rather than Z-ed.
Daring Libertarianism
➔ Mele’s solution to the worry of Present Luck “acknowledges the presence of luck at
the time of action” (MELE, 2017b, p. 51)
➔ To assert that the difference between two worlds with the same laws of nature and the
same past right up to the choice is just a matter of luck is not the same as asserting
that the agent’s decision is not a basically free action for which the agent is morally
responsible (MELE, 2017b, p. 57);
➔ LD: “Even if the difference between what an agent decides at t in one possible world
and what he decides at t in another possible world with the same past up to t and the
same laws of nature is just a matter of luck, the agent may make a basically free
decision at t in both worlds” (MELE, 2017b, p. 58);
➔ Only One Effort: “where Kane postulates concurrent competing indeterministic
efforts to choose, I postulate an indeterministic effort to decide (or choose) what to
do. That effort can result in different decisions, holding the past and the laws of
nature fixed” (MELE, 2017b, p. 60)
◆ Decision Voluntary and Rational: “There is a possible world in which Bob’s
effort to decide what to do about the coin toss issues at t in a decision to cheat,
and in another world with the same past up to t and the same laws of nature,
that effort issues at t in a decision to toss the coin right then. Bob has
competing reasons at the time, and the decision he makes – whether it is to
cheat or to do the right thing – is made for the reasons that favor it” (MELE,
2017b, p. 60).
● The agent has Plural Voluntary Control: the choice of Bob in one
world is voluntary (uncoerced) and intentional (knowingly and
purposefully made) - and the same is true for the choice in the other
possible world (MELE, 2017b, p. 61);
○ The choice is up to the agent: “If, as Kane says, plural
voluntary control in this connection is sufficient for the choice
the agent makes to be up to the agent, then DLV also
accommodates it sometimes being up to agents what they
choose in scenarios of the sort at issue” (MELE, 2017b, p. 61).
○ Isn’t there an additional requirement for choosing freely
that the agent was trying specifically to choose what he
chose?
◆ Choosing to A is essentially intentional. “Agents do not
need to try to choose to A nor to try to bring it about
that they choose to A in order to choose to A; and the
nature of choosing is such that, whenever they choose to
A, they intentionally do so: there are no
nonintentional choosings to A” (MALE, 2017b, p.
64).
◆ Reasons and Choices: “on DLV, agents have reasons or motives for two or
more competing choices and choose for reasons in cases of the kind at issue”
(MELE, 2017b, p. 66).
➔ The Cross World Difference is just a matter of luck: “The cross-world difference
at t in what Bob decides seems to be a matter of luck. But it does not seem to be
any more a matter of luck than a cross-world difference that I identified in a version
of Bob’s story in which he is trying to choose to cheat while also trying to choose to
do the right thing: namely, the difference between the former effort succeeding and
the latter effort succeeding” (MELE, 2017b, pp. 60-61);
◆ “When Bob’s choice-making occurs in a way that fits my DLV, the
cross-world difference in what he chooses is, in Kane’s words, ‘a matter of
luck or chance’” (MELE, 2017b, p. 61);
◆ “When an agent’s choice-making occurs in a way that fits my DLV, the
cross-world difference in what he chooses is, in Kane’s words, ‘a matter of
luck or chance’” (MELE, 2017b, p. 65).
◆ Why isn’t this a problem?
● We can look back in time - into the agent’s history (MELE, 2017b, p.
66);
● “My DLV finds in reflection on agents’ pasts a partial basis for an error
theory about why some people may view cross-world luck at the time
of decision as incompatible with making a basically free decision”
(MELE, 2017b, p. 66)
○ “My error theory is for a limited audience – people who are
attracted to libertarianism and reject agent-causal and
non-causal libertarianism. When some such people reflect on
stories like that of Bob and the coin, they may ignore the
sources of the antecedent probabilities of Bob’s choosing to
cheat and his choosing to do the right thing. If it is imagined
that these probabilities come out of the blue, Bob may seem to
be adrift in a wave of probabilities that were imposed on him,
and, accordingly, he may seem not to have sufficient control
over what he chooses to be morally responsible for his
choices. But, as I have explained elsewhere, it is a mistake to
assume that ‘indeterministic agents’ probabilities of action are
externally imposed’ or that such agents ‘are related to their
present probabilities of action roughly as dice are related to
present probabilities about how they will land if tossed’. If it is
known that Bob’s pertinent probabilities shortly before noon
are shaped by past intentional, uncompelled behavior of his,
one may take a less dim view of Bob’s prospects for being
morally responsible for the choice he makes and his
prospects for making it freely” (MELE, 2017b, p. 66)
◆ “This is a long story that carries us all the way back to
candidates for young agents’ earliest basically free
actions, and I cannot do justice to it here” (MELE,
2017b, p. 67).
➔ There must be no time at which it is determined that one choice will be made:
“Call Bob’s reasons for cheating RC and his reasons for tossing the coin at noon RT.
In the present context, what it is for RC to win out is for Bob to choose for those
reasons; and if that happens, then, of course, Bob chooses to cheat. Now, in order for
Bob’s choice to cheat to be basically free [...] there must be no time at which it is
determined that he will choose to cheat and so no time at which it is determined that
he will choose for RC” (MELE, 2017b, p. 62).
◆ “The prevailing of a collection of reasons is precisely a matter of Bob’s
choosing for those reasons” (MELE, 2017b, pp. 63-64);
● One set of reasons prevails in one world, another in another world and
there’s no cross-world difference in the reasons and the world before
the choice (MELE, 2017b, p. 64).
➔ Is the agent responsible for the contrasting choice?
◆ “If, past intentional, uncompelled behavior of his played a significant role in
shaping his character and the antecedent probability that he would decide to
cheat, and if better behavior was open to him on many relevant occasions in
the past, behavior that would have given him a much better chance of deciding
to do the right thing on this occasion, then maybe so. But this, as I say, is a
long story that I have spun elsewhere” (MELE, 2017b, p. 67).
MALE, A. R. Is What You Decide Ever Up to You? In: HAJI, I.; CAOUTTE, J. (Eds.) Free
Will and Moral Responsibility. Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2013, pp. 74-97.
NELKIN, D. K. Good Luck to Libertarians: Reflections on Al Mele’s Free Will and Luck.
Philosophical Explorations, v. 10, n. 2, pp. 173-184, 2007.
➔ “The view is a form of Daring Soft Libertarianism: ‘daring’ because it places a point
of indeterminism at the time of decision, and ‘soft’ because it does not require
indeterminism for freedom, but only for a kind of freedom particularly valuable (or
particularly valuable to some)” (NELKIN, 2007, p. 175);
➔ “It is unclear why the answer to the luck objection here is restricted to a soft variety”
(NELKIN, 2007, p. 176);
➔ “According to the Daring Soft Libertarian view developed by Mele, Drew acts freely
and is responsible for her actions, despite the existence of cross-world luck at the
moment of decision. In support of this idea, Mele reminds us that a key part of his
view is that the probabilities of Drew’s acting as she does, of her taking more time to
deliberate instead of acting when she does, and of her employing a strategy of
self-control, are themselves shaped by her own previous behaviors, her degree of
confidence in her best judgment which is itself based on her experience with her past
behaviors, and so on. In the view on offer, probability shaping ahead of time, and
learning lessons from our lucky successes and failures that can be employed to shape
future probabilities, are meant to soften worries about present luck” (NELKIN, 2007,
p. 177);
➔ Two Questions: “The first is whether we still face an objection to calling an agent’s
current actions free and responsible, no matter how the probabilities have been
shaped, if it is a matter of luck whether the agent acts in one way rather than another.
The second is whether this view has succeeded only in pushing back the problem of
present luck to the earlier probability-shaping actions of an agent” (NELKIN, 2007,
p. 177);
➔ First Question:
◆ “Here is one way of pressing this worry: consider a variant on the Drew case,
call it ‘Bad Luck Drew’. Suppose that Drew has chosen well, learned from
past experience, and she has reduced the probability of her acting akratically
to 1 percent. Still, she acts akratically, and we can give no explanation for why
she did that rather than the action she knew to be right. Why is this luck not
still troubling?” (NELKIN, 2007, p. 178)
● Two Ways Out:
○ Improbability is sufficient for absolving one of responsibility
(NELKIN, 2007, p. 178);
◆ Why would it be?
○ Improbability is not sufficient (NELKIN, 2007, p. 178).
➔ Second Question:
◆ “The question now is whether the existence of cross-world luck precludes
Tony’s being responsible to any degree. Mele answers: ‘I doubt that the
knowledge that all actual decision-making children are indeterministic
decision makers like Tony would lead us to believe that no children are
morally responsible at all for any of their decisions’ (p. 130). While this seems
right, the question is whether we should revise our views” (NELKIN, 2007, p.
179);
◆ “So while ‘cross-world luck at the time of decision should strike the theorist as
at least seriously problematic’ in adult cases, matters are different when we
also focus, as we should, on children. Responsibility then increases over time
as the frequency of indeterministically caused decisions and the range of
situations for choice increases. But by the time the degree of responsibility has
increased significantly, I gather, one can appeal to prior probability shaping to
justify the compatibility of cross-world luck and responsibility” (NELKIN,
2007, p. 179)
◆ “We might also ask whether Tony really is responsible if it is a matter of luck
that he acts in the way he does. Someone already worried about luck in the
adult cases would have reason to be equally worried here. Granted, the
sanctions are not as great; but in Mele’s view, sanctions are still deserved if
Tony acts badly. I wonder whether Mele’s conclusions about Tony don’t gain
in plausibility simply because we can all see the potential instrumental value
in praising and blaming Tony; but for someone who is really worried about
luck in the adult case, there would be good reason to resist the conclusion that
Tony is really deserving of blame if he acts badly” (NELKIN, 2007, p. 180)
FISCHER, J. M. Review: Alfred R. Mele: Free Will and Luck. Mind, v. 117, i. 465, pp.
195-201, 2008.
CLARKE, R. Free Will, Agent Causation, and “Disappearing Agents”. Noûs, v. 53, i. 1, pp.
1-21, 2017.
➔ “Pereboom argues that if actions are caused solely by events, then even if the causal
production of our behavior is indeterministic, this does not suffice for free will.
Event-causal libertarian theories are inadequate, then, even if the indeterminism that
they require exists. Pereboom’s argument for this claim is what he calls the
‘disappearing agent objection’” (CLARKE, 2017, pp. 5-6)
➔ “Be that as it may, a comment on Pereboom’s statement of the objection is in order
before I turn to an assessment. As he puts it, given the theory in question, nothing
settles whether the decision will occur. I do not think that he has any grounds for
rejecting a restatement in present tense: nothing settles whether the decision occurs.
Standard libertarian accounts—including standard event-causal libertarian views—
require that directly free decisions aren’t determined by anything that precedes them.
Proponents of such views, if they accept a settling requirement, will take it to require
that when an agent exercises free will in making a decision, the settling takes
place when the decision in question is made, not prior to that time. Thus, I’ll take
it that what is at issue in the objection is whether, given an event-causal libertarian
theory, the following settling requirement can be satisfied: (SR) If an agent S
freely decides at time t to A, then S settles at t whether that decision is made
then” (CLARKE, 2017, p. 7)
◆ “Freely deciding should be understood here, and in the subsequent
discussion, as exercising free will in deciding. If we construe the latter as
exercising the strongest sort of control, in the making of a decision, that is
required for basic-desert moral responsibility, then SR states the settling
requirement that Pereboom’s disappearing agent objection relies on.
Satisfaction of SR is said to be a necessary condition for exercising free will in
making a decision” (CLARKE, 2017, p. 7).
➔ “(The Rejoinder) The making of the decision by S at t to A settles at t whether
that decision is made then. After all, that matter is not settled by anything prior to t
(for the decision is not determined by anything prior to t); and nothing more than the
making of the decision at t is needed to settle the matter then. Further, since it is S
who makes the decision, S, in making that decision, settles at t whether that
decision is made then. For given that nothing prior to t settles whether that decision
is made then, S need not do anything more than decide at t to A in order to settle
at t whether that decision is made then. An event-causal libertarian theory, then,
has the resources to satisfy the settling requirement SR” (CLARKE, 2017, p. 7)
◆ “To clarify, by ‘the making of the decision’, what is meant is simply the
occurrence of the mental action of deciding. If such a mental action occurs,
then a making of a decision takes place; the latter is nothing more and nothing
less than—it is—the former. Similarly, by ‘S makes the decision to A’, what
is meant is simply that S decides to A. There is nothing fancy hidden in the
expressions that appear in The Rejoinder. In effect, what it claims is simply
that if it is granted that an event-causal libertarian theory provides what is
needed for there to be decisions—for the makings of decisions—then it
should be accepted that such a theory provides all that is needed to satisfy
SR” (CLARKE, 2017, p. 8)
◆ “(MS) If nothing prior to t settles whether S decides at t to A, and if S decides
at t to A, then the making of that decision by S at t settles at t whether that
decision is made then; and (AS) If nothing prior to t settles whether S decides
at t to A, and if S decides at t to A, then S, in making that decision, settles at t
whether that decision is made then. Reading settles whether as fixes or
resolves conclusively the question whether, these are certainly credible
claims” (CLARKE, 2017, p. 8)
➔ Defending (S-FAC): “(S-FAC) An agent settles whether an action occurs only if (i)
she agent-causes it for certain reasons, where the absence of her agent-causing the
action for those reasons would not have caused the action, and (ii) her agent-causing
her action for those reasons is ontologically fundamental” (CLARKE, 2017, p. 9).
◆ “P1) An agent’s settling whether a certain decision is made by her is a matter
of the agent’s causing something” (CLARKE, 2017, p. 9);
◆ “P2) If an agent’s causing something is non-fundamental, grounded in
causation by events or states, then in causing that thing the agent settles
whether a certain decision is made by her only if certain prior events or
states—those whose causing something grounds the agent’s causing
something—settle whether that decision is made” (CLARKE, 2017, p. 9);
◆ “P3) But in the cases under consideration, no prior events or states settle
whether the decision in question is made, since the pre-decision history leaves
open a significant probability that the agent not make that decision”
(CLARKE, 2017, p. 10);
◆ “C) Thus, in the cases under consideration, agent causation that is
non-fundamental, grounded in causation by events or states, does not yield the
agent’s settling whether a certain decision is made by her” (CLARKE, 2017,
p. 10).
➔ Questioning P2:
◆ Decision as a causing (fundamentally by mental events) of the acquisition
of an intention (CLARKE, 2017, p. 10):
● Agent-Causal View of O’Connor: actions are not events caused by
agents; rather, they are agent-causings of events;
● Event-Causal View: decision is not something caused (fundamentally)
by mental events of certain kinds; rather, they are a causing
(fundamentally be mental events) of the acquisition of an intention.
○ “A causing by an event e begins when e begins. In this case,
the event causes to which an event-causal theory of action
appeals will not all precede the actions in which they figure. It
is still the case that premise P3 is correct, for it concerns only
events that precede the decision in question. Further, the
causing events that are now included in the decision do not,
simply with their occurrence, settle whether the decision
occurs. For with their occurrence it remains open that the
decision not be made. The argument to follow thus goes
through on this alternative view of the matter” (CLARKE,
2017, p. 18)
◆ “(AS) If nothing prior to t settles whether S decides at t to A, and if S decides
at t to A, then S, in making that decision, settles at t whether that decision is
made then” (CLARKE, 2017, p. 8)
◆ 1- If a decision is an agent’s causing her coming to have a certain intention
and in making the decision the agent settles whether that decision is made, “it
may be said that the agent’s settling this question is a matter of her agent
causing something, viz., her coming to have the intention in question”
(CLARKE, 2017, p. 11)
◆ 2- “Even given the supposition that the agent-causing is reducible to or
realized in event-causings, the events in question do not themselves settle
whether the decision is made. Since (in the cases under consideration)
causation by these events is indeterministic, these events might occur then and
the causings not come about, the decision not be made. Thus the events in
question don’t settle whether the decision is made” (CLARKE, 2017, p. 11)
◆ 1 and 2 imply that P2 is false.
PALMER, D.. Event-Causal Libertarianism: Two Objections Reconsidered In: HAJI, I.;
CAOUTTE, J. (Eds.) Free Will and Moral Responsibility. Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars
Publishing, 2013, pp. 98-122.
Pereboom’s Argument
➔ “This objection rest on two crucial claims” (PALMER, 2013, p. 102):
◆ A (Power to Settle Claim)- “On event-causal libertarian views, agents lack the
‘power to settle’ whether or not their decisions occur” (PALMER, 2013, p.
107);
◆ B (Control Claim)- “If agents lack this power to settle whether or not their
decisions occur, then they do not have enough control over their decisions for
them to be free and for agents to be morally responsible for them” (PALMER,
2013, p. 107)
➔ “How should we understand the nature of this power [to settle]?” (PALMER, 2013, p.
107);
➔ Power to Settle: “An agent S ‘settles’ whether or not her decision D occurs if either:
(i) some prior event or state of which S is the subject causally determines (i.e.,
deterministically causes) D, or (ii) S causes D as a substance (where causation by a
substance is not reducible to, nor composed of, causation by prior events or states)”
(PALMER, 2013, p. 109);
➔ How should the Event-Causal Libertarian respond to the objection?
◆ Affirm A and deny B (PALMER, 2013, p. 110): “it is true that, on
event-causal libertarian views, agents lack the ‘power to settle’ whether or not
their decisions occur in the sense that, on these views, no prior events or states
causally determine whether or not the agents’ decisions occur and, on such
views, agents do not cause their decisions as substances. But having conceded
this, event-causal libertarians should insist that it is not true, as (B) says, that if
agents lack the power to settle in this sense, then they thereby do not have
enough control over their decisions for those decisions to be free and be
something for which agents can be morally responsible” (PALMER, 2013, p.
110).
➔ Pereboom and the Burden of Proof: “As I see it, the following question is what
separates the two parties (event-causal libertarians on the one hand and proponents of
the disappearing agent objection on the other): if agents lack the power to settle
whether or not their decisions occur in the sense we have specified, do they thereby
lack sufficient control over their decisions for those decisions to be free and
something for which agents can be morally responsible? Proponents of the objection
answer “yes” to this question; event-causal libertarians answer “no.” What would
break the deadlock here? In my view, what would break the deadlock is the
presentation of further considerations on both sides: further considerations to
answer “yes” in the case of proponents of the objection; and further
considerations to answer “no” in the case of event-causal libertarians. If further
considerations on both sides are what would break the deadlock, then who has
the burden of proof? As I see it, the burden of proof lies with the proponent of
the objection” (PALMER, 2013, p. 111).
➔ Isn’t the claim intuitive?
◆ “I think that event-causal libertarians should counter by asking people to
reflect on the following: assuming that (i) the agent’s decision was caused by
prior events or states of the right type, and (ii) there was appropriate
indeterminism in the causation of the decision by the antecedent events or
states, then the claim that (i) and (ii) are jointly sufficient for freedom and
responsibility (as the event-causal libertarian suggests) is not markedly less
intuitive than Pereboom’s claim that if agent’s lack the power to settle in his
specified sense, then they lack sufficient control for freedom and
responsibility. As I see it, agreement on this statement is all the event-causal
libertarian needs to respond to an argument from intuition from Pereboom”
(PALMER, 2013, p. 121)
KANE, R. Torn decisions, luck, and libertarian free will: comments on Balaguer’s free will as
an open scientific problem. Philosophical Studies, v 169, n. 1, pp. 51-58, 2012.
Pereboom’s Argument
➔ (1) ‘‘On the event-causal libertarian picture, the relevant causal conditions antecedent
to the decision—agent-involving events—…leave it open whether the decision will
[or will not] occur’’ (KANE, 2012, p. 57)
➔ (2) “The agent has no further causal role in determining whether it does [occur]”
(KANE, 2012, p. 57)
➔ (3) ‘‘Whether the decision occurs is thus not settled by any causal factor involving the
agent’’ and so ‘‘the agent lacks sufficient control over the decision for moral
responsibility’’ (KANE, 2012, p. 57).
Kane’s Response
➔ “On the view I have outlined, the conclusion (3) does not follow from the premises
(1) and (2)” (KANE, 2012, p. 57);
➔ The relevant causal conditions of (1) include, also, the agent’s efforts to bring about
each choice (KANE, 2012, p. 58);
◆ Because of this, from (1), it does not follow that ‘‘whether the decision occurs
is thus not settled by any causal factor involving the agent’’(3). “For whether
the decision occurs is settled at the moment of choice by the successful
completion of the agent’s effort to bring about that choice, which is a
‘causal factor involving the agent’” (KANE, 2012, p. 58).
➔ The agent has plural voluntary control and this is sufficient control for moral
responsibility (KANE, 2012, p. 58).
KANE - The Agent Causation Response (2021; 2022a)
KANE, R. Making Sense of Free Will that is Incompatible with Determinism: A Fourth Way
Forward. Journal of Philosophical Theological Research, v. 23, n. 89, pp. 5-28, 2021.
KANE, R. The Problem of Free Will: A Libertarian Perspective. In: KANE, R.; SARTORIO,
C. Do we have Free Will? Routledge, 2022a, pp. 3-67.
➔ “A continuing substance (such as an agent) does not absent the ontological stage
because we describe its continuing existence - its life, if it is a living thing - including
its capacities and their exercise, in terms of states, events, and processes involving it”
(KANE, 2021, p. 14; KANE, 2022a, p. 55);
➔ “One does not have to choose between agent (or substance) causation and event
causation in describing freedom of choice and action. One can afrim both” (KANE,
2021, p. 13; KANE, 2022a, p. 55);
➔ “In the case of self-forming choices or SFAs, for example, it is true to say both that
“the agent’s deliberative activity, including her efort, caused or brought about the
choice” and to say that “the agent caused or brought about the choice.” Indeed, the
first claim entails the second” (KANE, 2021, p. 14; KANE, 2022a, p. 55)
➔ Agents as Information-Responsive Complex Dynamical Systems (KANE, 2021, p.
14; KANE, 2022a, p. 55);
◆ ““An agent’s causing an action” is to be understood as “an agent, conceived as
such an information-responsive complex dynamical system, exercising
teleological guidance control, over some of its own processes” (KANE, 2021,
p. 14; KANE, 2022a, p. 55);
◆ Complex Dynamical Systems: “systems in which emergent capacities arise
as a result of greater complexity. When the emergent capacities arise, the
systems as a whole or various subsystems of them impose novel constraints on
the behavior of their parts” (KANE, 2021, p. 14; cf. KANE, 2022a, p. 56);
● These systems exhibit Teleological Guidance Control (TGC) “when
they tend through feedback loops and error correction mechanisms to
converge on a goal (called an attractor) in the face of perturbations”
(KANE, 2021, pp. 14-15; KANE, 2022a, p. 56);
○ This control is necessary for any voluntary activity (KANE,
2021, p. 15; KANE, 2022a, p. 56).
◆ “An important consequence of understanding the agent causation involved in
free agency and free will in this way is that the causal role of the agent in
intentional actions of the kind needed for free agency and will is not
reducible to causation by mental states of the agent alone. That would
leave out the added role of the agent, qua complex dynamical system,
exercising teleological guidance control over the processes causally linking
mental states and events to actions” (KANE, 2021, p. 15; KANE, 2022a, p.
56);
● The agent exercises TCG over the manner in which the mental states
cause the resulting events “by ‘guiding the flow of activity along
neural pathways that establish the proper mappings between inputs,
internal states, and outputs’ and being able to alter those pathways in
response to new information” (KANE, 2021, p. 15);
● Without this control, causation by mental states would be deviant
(KANE, 2021, p. 15; KANE, 2022a, p. 56).
➔ “The agent causation involved is not reducible to event causation by mental
states and events alone for the reasons given” (KANE, 2021, p. 16; KANE, 2022a, p.
57);
➔ The exercise of this notion of agent causation essentially involves causation by
states, processes and events (KANE, 2021, p. 18);
➔ This kind of agent causation is capable of being itself caused by prior events
(KANE, 2021, p. 18)
RUNYAN - Events, agents, and settling whether and how one intervenes
(2018)
RUNYAN, J. D. Events, agents, and settling whether and how one intervenes. Philosophical
Studies, v. 173, i. 6, pp. 1629-1646, 2016
➔ “While the agent can be said to cause the ‘action’ (see Pereboom 2007c, p. 194), she
seems not to have control over the crucial element for which she is responsible: that
she has decided to A rather than to B” (GRIFFITH, 2010, p. 50)
➔ “On an event-causal picture, the relevant causal conditions antecedent to a decision -
agent-involving events, or alternatively, states of the agent - would leave it open
whether this decision will occur, and the agent has no further causal role in
determining whether it does” (GRIFFITH, 2010, p. 51) → Quoting Pereboom, 2007b,
p. 102);
◆ “The problem is that the agent is not able to control which decision is made.
The extent to which the agent is causally involved leaves this open”
(GRIFFITH, 2010, p. 51).
➔ “So the agent is such a picture does disappear to an important extent. And this
problem is not constituted by the unavailability of an explanation. It is constituted by
a lack of control. It just happens to the agent that A occurs instead of B, since the
agent has no involvement beyond those states or events that leave it causally open. So
in the end, the event-causal libertarian cannot give the agent the control she needs”
(GRIFFITH, 2010, p. 51)
ČEČ, F. The Disappearing Agent In: BERČIĆ, B (Ed) Perspectives on The Self. Rijeka:
University of Rijeka, 2017, pp. 235-253.
➔ “The event causal libertarian should reject the objection as it rests on an unacceptable
ontology and that consequently, he should bite the bullet and admit that there is some
residual arbitrariness in torn decision making” (CEC, 2017, pp. 235-236);
➔ Torn Decision (CEC, 2017, p. 238):
◆ a) the agent has a feeling of being torn between two or more options;
◆ b) the outcome is not causally determined by influences of the past (it is not a
deterministically produced event);
◆ c) the decision is probabilistically caused by agent involving events;
◆ d) the indeterministic event is part of the decision itself, it does not happen
before the process of decision making;
◆ e) the options are in a motivational equipoise: if two options are open, option
A and option B, then there is 50% chance that the agent will choose option A
and 50% chance that he’ll choose option B.
◆ f) the act of deciding has to be analyzed on the basis of a causal theory of
action.
➔ Five Responses to the Objection (CEC, 2017, p. 242):
◆ 1. Formulate an answer that relies on specific events or states that fulfill the
functional role of the agent. Velleman (1992) and Franklin (2014) opt for this
solution.
● As Runyan points out, Velleman’s response cannot be applied to the
case of motivational equipoise (CEC, 2017, p. 243).
◆ 2. Appeal to phenomenology by claiming that the decision is attributable to
the agent because there is a special phenomenological feeling that only the one
who decides can have. Balaguer (2010) adopts this option and perhaps Kane
(2007) can be interpreted as appealing to it.
◆ 3. Devise an enriched event-causal account which will ultimately explain why
the agent has not lost control over the decision making process.
◆ 4. Discard the disappearing agent objection as it relies on a form of control of
the decision making process available only to agent causal theories, thus
making it (1) unacceptable because of the metaphysical burden it brings along,
(2) incompatible with the concept of torn decision making, (3) incompatible
with the concept of motivational equipoise.
◆ 5. Bite the bullet and stick to the idea that something gets lost if one adheres to
event causal libertarianism.
➔ “The disappearing agent objection must rely on a different, stronger conception of
control, a kind of control that can be secured only by agent causal theories” (CEC,
2017, p. 245)
➔ “The fourth option is grounded on the presumption that the disappearing agent
objection can be rejected as it relies on a form of control available only to agent
causal theories” (CEC, 2017, p. 246)
◆ Pereboom’s Settling is inconsistent with universal determinism. Quoting
Helen Steward: “For example, if an utterly deterministic process leads via a
successive chain of causes c1…cn to effect e, then cn cannot count as having
settled that an event of any of the types that e instantiates occurs, even though
cn is essential to the occurrence of e, since it was already settled at the time
of c1’s occurrence that e would occur. An event can only settle a matter at
the time at which it occurs, if that matter is not already settled before that
time. (…) If there is ever any settling of matters in time, then universal
determinism cannot be true, since according to universal determinism,
everything is already settled at the start (whatever exactly we are to
understand by “the start”). (Steward 2012: 40)” (CEC, 2017, pp. 246-247);
◆ “The notion of settling is libertarian in its core because it requires open
futures” (CEC, 2017, p. 247);
◆ Pereboom’s and Steward’s concept of settling presuppose some kind of agent
causation, because: “… one cannot hope to analyse what it is for an agent to
act in terms merely of the causation of her bodily movements by various of her
mental states, because her action has to be a part of this story, the part that
connects those non active mental antecedents to her bodily movements. It is
the agent who has to settle the question whether those mental antecedents will
result in a movement or not. That is the way commonsense psychology tells
the story of action, and it cannot be retold at this level of ontology without her
participation. (Steward 2012: 65)” (CEC, 2017, p. 247);
◆ “The self that is compatible with the notion of settling, the self that can settle
must be one of a non-reductive cast similar to the ones presupposed by agent
causal theories: a mover unmoved, an agent-as-substance” (CEC, 2017, p.
247)
◆ The concept of torn decision is incompatible with the concept of settling:
● In ECL, “there is no ‘I’ who does the settling” (CEC, 2017, p. 248) -
agents qua substances are inexistent;
● The concept of settling contradicts the concept of torn decisions
making: “One important characteristic of settling is that nothing
prior to the settling itself suffices for the production of the action.
Nothing prior to the raising of my arm suffices for the raising of my
arm, as Clarke invites us to think in his example. However, the
concept of torn decision making implies that the situation of
motivational equipoise is sufficient for the production of a decision.
Nothing more can be added to the picture. Therefore we have two
concepts that do not combine: according to the concept of settling
nothing prior to the act of the agent suffices for the act, while
according to the concept of torn decision making the situation of
motivational equipoise suffices for the act” (CEC, 2017, p. 248);
● Problem: how can agent-causal libertarianism save libertarianism.
ACL fails to resolve the problem of luck (CEC, 2017, p. 249).
➔ “As exposed in the previous section of the paper adhering to the standards imposed by
the concept of settling is not something that can be achieved in an event causal
ontology. Therefore the answer to the question “Should an event causal libertarian
settle?” is simple: no. An event causal libertarian should explain how a free decision
looks like, why it is attributable to an agent, explain the functional role of the agent’s
in it, how it is incorporated in other parts of his mental life, etc. He has to do so in
order to demonstrate that the residual arbitrariness isn’t an obstacle in the production
of free decisions and attribution of moral responsibility” (CEC, 2017, pp. 250-251)
◆ “He should admit if a decision making process is grounded on
probabilistically caused agent involving events then there will be some
residual arbitrariness present in the decision making process” (CEC, 2017, p.
251);
◆ “What can an indeterministic world offer? One obvious answer is that such a
world provides open futures in which an agent can create or follow novel
causal pathways. But as already seen indeterminism is a dangerous toy to play
with. Following that path does not mean that the journey will be without
perils. No wonder that Randolph Clarke spoke of it as a of horror story.
(Clarke 2011: 331” (CEC, 2017, p. 251);
◆ “There is no settling, at least not as demanding as the disappearing agent
objection requires. Consequently some residual arbitrariness will be present in
the decision making process because it rests on the idea of motivational
equipoise which gets resolved by an agent involving indeterministic event.
The indeterminism is here to stay but to implement Balaguer’s term it will be
appropriately non-random. (Balaguer 2010: 66) It will be the agent’s own
doing” (CEC, 2017, p. 251)
● “Toying with indeterminism demands a price to be paid” (CEC, 2017,
p. 251).
➔ Torn Decision: “a decision in which the person in question has reasons for multiple
options, feels torn as to which option is best, and decides without resolving the
conflict, i.e., decides while feeling torn” (BALAGUER, 2014, p. 79);
◆ Torn Decision Wholly Undetermined (TDW-undetermined): “the actual,
objective moment-of-choice probabilities of the various reasons-based
tied-for-best options being chosen match the reasons-based probabilities (or
the phenomenological probabilities), so that these moment-of-choice
probabilities are all roughly even, given the complete state of the world and all
the laws of nature, and the choice occurs without any further causal input,
i.e., without anything else being significantly causally relevant to which option
is chosen” (BALAGUER, 2014, p. 80)
➔ If Ralph’s decision is a TDW-undetermined, we get the following results
(BALAGUER, 2014, p. 80):
◆ (A) Ralph’s choice was conscious, intentional, and purposeful, with an
actish phenomenology—in short, it was a Ralph-consciously-choosing event,
or a Ralph-consciously-doing event (we actually know all of this
independently of whether the choice was TDW-undetermined); and
◆ (B) the choice flowed out of Ralph’s conscious reasons and thought in a
nondeterministically event-causal way; and
◆ (C) nothing external to Ralph’s conscious reasons and thought had any
significant causal influence (after he moved into a torn state and was about to
make his decision) over how he chose, so that the conscious choice itself was
the event that settled which option was chosen. (If you like, we can put it
this way: The conscious choice itself was the undetermined physical event that
settled which option was chosen).
◆ “My claim is that given (A)–(C), it makes good sense to say that Ralph
authored and controlled the decision. It seems to make sense in this scenario to
say that (i) Ralph did it, and (ii) nothing made him do it. And, intuitively, this
seems to be sufficient for authorship and control” (BALAGUER, 2014, pp.
80-81).
➔ Two Kinds of Control:
◆ DP-Control
◆ MB-Control: control applied to TDW-undetermined (BALAGUER, 2021, p.
81);
● Balaguer does not need to argue that MB-control provides a correct
analysis of the concept of control. All he needs is this: “(*) If our torn
decisions are TDW-undetermined, then they’re authored and controlled
by us and appropriately non-random and L-free in interesting and
important ways that are worth wanting and worth arguing for and that
libertarians can hold up and say, ‘‘This gives us a noteworthy kind of
libertarian free will.’’ (Actually, what I really need here is a bit weaker
than this; all I really need is that if our torn decisions are
TDW-undetermined, then we ‘‘author’’ and ‘‘control’’ them and so on
in ways that are interesting, important, and so on; for on the view I’m
suggesting, it doesn’t matter whether MB-authorship and MB-control
provide correct analyses of the concepts of authorship and control, and
so it wouldn’t matter if they failed to be genuine referents of the
English terms ‘authorship’ and ‘control’. But I won’t bother with this
complication here.)” (BALAGUER, 2014, pp. 82-83).
○ (A)-(C) motivates (*) - “they are clearly enough to give us one
important kind of L-freedom (...) in this scenario, the event that
settles which option is chosen is the conscious decision (...) But
it seems to me that if the event that settles the matter is the
agent’s conscious decision, then, at the very least, there is a
sense in which the agent does settle it. There might be other
senses—most notably, agent causal senses—in which the agent
does not settle it; but, again, all I need is that there is one
interesting, important sense in which the agent does settle it.
And it seems to me that if the event that settles which option is
chosen is the agent’s conscious choice, then that clearly gives
us a sense in which the agent settles it” (BALAGUER, 2014, p.
83)
➔ “So that’s my main response to Pereboom: I do not need to argue that MB-control
gives us a correct analysis of the concept of control, or that the kind of L-freedom I
describe in my book is the only kind of L-freedom that anyone might care about; all I
need to argue is that if our torn decisions are TDW-undetermined, then they are L-free
and appropriately non-random and authored and controlled by us (or ‘‘authored’’ and
‘‘controlled’’ by us, as the case may be) in ways that are interesting and important and
worth wanting and that libertarians can hold up and say, ‘‘This gives us a noteworthy
kind of libertarian free will.’’ That’s all I need, and I think I have delivered it”
(BALAGUER, 2014, p. 84).
FRANKLIN - A Minimal Libertarianism (2018)
In addition, neither can she be responsible for the effort that is explained by
the character, whether this explanation is deterministic or indeterministic. If
the explanation is deterministic, then there will be factors beyond the agent’s
control that determine the effort, and the agent will thereby lack moral
responsibility for the effort. If the explanation is indeterministic, given that the
agent’s free choice plays no role in producing the character, and nothing
besides the character explains the effort, there will be factors beyond the
agent’s control that make a causal contribution to the production of this effort
without determining it, while nothing supplements the contribution of these
factors to produce the effort. Then again, the agent will not be morally
responsible for the effort. (PEREBOOM, 2088 [FOUR VIEWS]