Catholic Bioethics: Dobbs Jackson Women'S Health, Inc

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 7

Catholic Bioethics

DOBBS V. JACKSON WOMEN’S HEALTH, INC


___ U.S. ___ (2022)

The opinion should be read in full to appreciate its intellectual and logical force, which is
considerable. Nonetheless, substantial excerpts are provided below to show the power and
intellectual integrity of its logic. A substantial step has been taken to restore and preserve legitimate
constitutional order.

Abridged Opinion of the Court


Americans continue to hold passionate and widely divergent views on abortion, and state
legislatures have acted accordingly. Some have recently enacted laws allowing abortion, with few
re- strictions, at all stages of pregnancy. Others have tightly restricted abortion beginning well
before viability. And in this case, 26 States have expressly asked this Court to over- rule Roe and
Casey and allow the States to regulate or prohibit pre-viability abortions.

Before us now is one such state law. The State of Mississippi asks us to uphold the constitutionality
of a law that generally prohibits an abortion after the 15th week of pregnancy—several weeks
before the point at which a fetus is now regarded as “viable” outside the womb. In defending this
law, the State’s primary argument is that we should reconsider and overrule Roe and Casey and
once again allow each State to regulate abortion as its citizens wish. On the other side, respondents

reaffirm Roe and Casey, and they contend that the Mississippi law cannot stand if we do so.
Allowing Mississippi to prohibit abortions after 15 weeks of pregnancy, they argue, “would be no
different than overruling Casey and Roe entirely.” Brief for Respondents 43. They contend that
“no half- measures” are available and that we must either reaf- firm or overrule Roe and Casey.
Brief for Respondents 50.

We hold that Roe and Casey must be overruled. The Constitution makes no reference to abortion,
and no such right is implicitly protected by any constitutional provision, including the one on
which the defenders of Roe and Casey now chiefly rely - the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment. That provision has been held to guarantee some rights that are not mentioned in the
Constitution, but any such right must be “deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition” and
“implicit in the concept of ordered liberty.” Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U. S. 702, 721 (1997)
(internal quotation marks omitted).
The right to abortion does not fall within this category. Until the latter part of the 20th century,
such a right was entirely unknown in American law. Indeed, when the Fourteenth Amendment was
adopted, three quarters of the States made abortion a crime at all stages of pregnancy. The abortion
right is also critically different from any other right that this Court has held to fall within the
Fourteenth Amendment’s protection of “liberty.” Roe’s defenders characterize the abortion right
as similar to the rights recognized in past decisions involving matters such as intimate sexual
relations, contraception, and marriage, but abortion is fundamentally different, as both Roe and
Casey acknowledged, because it destroys what those decisions called “fetal life” and what the law
now before us describes as an “un- born human being.”

...

The Constitution makes no express reference to a right to obtain an abortion, and therefore those
who claim that it protects such a right must show that the right is somehow implicit in the
constitutional text.

Roe, however, was remarkably loose in its treatment of the constitutional text. It held that the
abortion right, which is not mentioned in the Constitution, is part of a right to privacy, which is
also not mentioned. See 410 U. S., at 152–153. And that privacy right, Roe observed, had been
found to spring from no fewer than five different constitutional provisions—the First, Fourth,
Fifth, Ninth, and Fourteenth Amendments.

...

Roe expressed the “feel[ing]” that the Fourteenth Amendment was the pro- vision that did the
work, but its message seemed to be that the abortion right could be found somewhere in the
Constitution and that specifying its exact location was not of paramount importance. The Casey
Court did not defend this unfocused analysis and instead grounded its decision solely on the theory
that the right to obtain an abortion is part of the “liberty” protected by the Fourteenth Amendment’s
Due Process Clause.

...

The underlying theory on which this argument rests - that the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due
Process Clause provides substantive, as well as procedural, protection for “liberty” - has long been
controversial. But our decisions have held that the Due Process Clause protects two categories of
substantive rights.

The first consists of rights guaranteed by the first eight Amendments. Those Amendments
originally applied only to the Federal Government, Barron ex rel. Tiernan v. Mayor of Baltimore,
7 Pet. 243, 247–251 (1833) (opinion for the Court by Marshall, C. J.), but this Court has held that
the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment “incorporates” the great majority of those
rights and thus makes them equally applicable to the States. See McDonald, 561 U. S., at 763–
767, and nn. 12–13. The second category - which is the one in question here - comprises a select
list of fundamental rights that are not mentioned anywhere in the Constitution.
In deciding whether a right falls into either of these categories, the Court has long asked whether
the right is “deeply rooted in [our] history and tradition” and whether it is essential to our Nation’s
“scheme of ordered liberty.” Timbs v. Indiana, 586 U. S. ___, ___ (2019) (slip op., at 3) (internal
quotation marks omitted); McDonald, 561 U. S., at 764, 767 (internal quotation marks omitted);
Glucksberg, 521 U. S., at 721 (internal quotation marks omitted). And in conducting this inquiry,
we have engaged in a careful analysis of the history of the right at issue.

...

Historical inquiries of this nature are essential whenever we are asked to recognize a new
component of the “liberty” protected by the Due Process Clause because the term “liberty” alone
provides little guidance. “Liberty” is a capacious term. As Lincoln once said: “We all declare for
Liberty; but in using the same word we do not all mean the same thing.” In a well-known essay,
Isaiah Berlin reported that “[h]istorians of ideas” had cataloged more than 200 different senses in
which the term had been used.

In interpreting what is meant by the Fourteenth Amendment’s reference to “liberty,” we must


guard against the natural human tendency to confuse what that Amendment protects with our own
ardent views about the liberty that Americans should enjoy. That is why the Court has long been
“reluctant” to recognize rights that are not mentioned in the Constitution. Collins v. Harker
Heights, 503 U. S. 115, 125 (1992). “Substantive due process has at times been a treacherous field
for this Court,” Moore v. East Cleveland, 431 U. S. 494, 503 (1977) (plurality opinion), and it has
sometimes led the Court to usurp authority that the Constitution entrusts to the people’s elected
representatives. See Regents of Univ. of Mich. v. Ewing, 474 U. S. 214, 225-226 (1985). As the
Court cautioned in Glucksberg, “[w]e must . . . exercise the utmost care whenever we are asked to
break new ground in this field, lest the liberty protected by the Due Process Clause be subtly
transformed into the policy preferences of the Members of this Court.” 521 U. S., at 720 (internal
quotation marks and citation omitted).

On occasion, when the Court has ignored the “[a]ppropriate limits” imposed by “‘respect for the
teachings of history,’ ” Moore, 431 U. S., at 503 (plurality opinion), it has fallen into the
freewheeling judicial policymaking that characterized discredited decisions such as Lochner v.
New York, 198 U. S. 45 (1905). The Court must not fall prey to such an unprincipled approach.
Instead, guided by the history and tradition that map the essential components of our Nation’s
concept of ordered liberty, we must ask what the Fourteenth Amendment means by the term
“liberty.” When we engage in that inquiry in the present case, the clear answer is that the
Fourteenth Amendment does not protect

...

Until the latter part of the 20th century, there was no support in American law for a constitutional
right to obtain an abortion. No state constitutional provision had recognized such a right. Until a
few years before Roe was handed down, no federal or state court had recognized such a right.
...

Not only was there no support for such a constitutional right until shortly before Roe, but abortion
had long been a crime in every single State. At common law, abortion was criminal in at least
some stages of pregnancy and was regarded as unlawful and could have very serious consequences
at all stages. American law followed the common law until a wave of statutory restrictions in the
1800s expanded criminal liability for abortions. By the time of the adoption of the Fourteenth
Amendment, three-quarters of the States had made abortion a crime at any stage of pregnancy, and
the remaining States would soon follow.

Roe either ignored or misstated this history, and Casey declined to reconsider Roe’s faulty
historical analysis. It is therefore important to set the record straight.

...

The inescapable conclusion is that a right to abortion is not deeply rooted in the Nation’s history
and traditions. On the contrary, an unbroken tradition of prohibiting abortion on pain of criminal
punishment persisted from the earliest days of the common law until 1973. The Court in Roe could
have said of abortion exactly what Glucksberg said of assisted suicide: “Attitudes toward
[abortion] have changed since Bracton, but our laws have consistently condemned, and continue
to prohibit, [that practice].”

...

Instead of seriously pressing the argument that the abortion right itself has deep roots, supporters
of Roe and Casey contend that the abortion right is an integral part of a broader entrenched right.
Roe termed this a right to privacy, 410 U. S., at 154, and Casey described it as the freedom to make
“intimate and personal choices” that are “central to personal dignity and autonomy,” 505 U. S., at
851. Casey elaborated: “At the heart of liberty is the right to de- fine one’s own concept of
existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life.” Ibid.

The Court did not claim that this broadly framed right is absolute, and no such claim would be
plausible. While individuals are certainly free to think and to say what they wish about “existence,”
“meaning,” the “universe,” and “the mystery of human life,” they are not always free to act in
accordance with those thoughts. License to act on the basis of such beliefs may correspond to one
of the many understandings of “liberty,” but it is certainly not “ordered liberty.”

Ordered liberty sets limits and defines the boundary between competing interests. Roe and Casey
each struck a particular balance between the interests of a woman who wants an abortion and the
interests of what they termed “potential life.” Roe, 410 U. S., at 150 (emphasis deleted); Casey,
505 U. S., at 852. But the people of the various States may evaluate those interests differently. In
some States, voters may believe that the abortion right should be even more extensive than the
right that Roe and Casey recognized. Voters in other States may wish to impose tight restrictions
based on their belief that abortion destroys an “unborn human being.” Miss. Code Ann. §41–41–
191(4)(b). Our Nation’s historical understanding of ordered liberty does not prevent the people’s
elected representatives from deciding how abortion should be regulated.
Nor does the right to obtain an abortion have a sound basis in precedent. Casey relied on cases
involving the right to marry a person of a different race, Loving v. Virginia, 388 U. S. 1 (1967);
the right to marry while in prison, Turner v. Safley, 482 U. S. 78 (1987); the right to obtain
contracep- tives, Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U. S. 479 (1965), Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U. S.
438 (1972), Carey v. Population Services Int’l, 431 U. S. 678 (1977); the right to reside with
relatives, Moore v. East Cleveland, 431 U. S. 494 (1977); the right to make decisions about the
education of one’s children, Pierce v. Society of Sisters, 268 U. S. 510 (1925), Meyer v. Nebraska,
262 U. S. 390 (1923); the right not to be sterilized without consent, Skinner v. Oklahoma ex rel.
Williamson, 316 U. S. 535 (1942); and the right in certain circumstances not to undergo involuntary
surgery, forced administration of drugs, or other substantially similar procedures, Winston v. Lee,
470 U. S. 753 (1985), Washington v. Harper, 494 U. S. 210 (1990), Rochin v. California, 342 U.
S. 165 (1952). Respondents and the Solicitor General also rely on post-Casey decisions like
Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U. S. 558 (2003) (right to engage in private, consensual sexual acts), and
Obergefell v. Hodges, 576 U. S. 644 (2015) (right to marry a person of the same sex). See Brief
for Respondents 18; Brief for United States 23–24.

These attempts to justify abortion through appeals to a broader right to autonomy and to define
one’s “concept of existence” prove too much. Casey, 505 U. S., at 851. Those criteria, at a high
level of generality, could license fundamental rights to illicit drug use, prostitution, and the like.
See Compassion in Dying v. Washington, 85 F. 3d 1440, 1444 (CA9 1996) (O’Scannlain, J.,
dissenting from denial of rehearing en banc). None of these rights has any claim to being deeply
rooted in history. Id., at 1440, 1445.

What sharply distinguishes the abortion right from the rights recognized in the cases on which Roe
and Casey rely is something that both those decisions acknowledged: Abortion destroys what those
decisions call “potential life” and what the law at issue in this case regards as the life of an “unborn
human being.” See Roe, 410 U. S., at 159 (abortion is “inherently different”); Casey, 505 U. S., at
852 (abortion is “a unique act”). None of the other decisions cited by Roe and Casey involved the
critical moral question posed by abortion. They are therefore inapposite. They do not sup- port the
right to obtain an abortion, and by the same token, our conclusion that the Constitution does not
confer such a right does not undermine them in any way.

...

The dissent is very candid that it cannot show that a constitutional right to abortion has any
foundation, let alone a “‘deeply rooted’” one, “‘in this Nation’s history and tradition.’ ”
Glucksberg, 521 U. S., at 721; see post, at 12–14 (joint opinion of BREYER, SOTOMAYOR, and
KAGAN, JJ.). The dissent does not identify any pre-Roe authority that supports such a right - no
state constitutional provision or statute, no federal or state judicial precedent, not even a scholarly
treatise. Compare post, at 12–14, n. 2, with supra, at 15–16, and n. 23. Nor does the dissent dispute
the fact that abortion was illegal at common law at least after quickening; that the 19th century
saw a trend toward criminalization of pre-quickening abortions; that by 1868, a supermajority of
States (at least 26 of 37) had enacted statutes criminalizing abortion at all stages of pregnancy; that
by the late 1950s at least 46 States prohibited abortion “however and whenever performed” except
if necessary to save “the life of the mother,” Roe, 410 U. S., at 139; and that when Roe was decided
in 1973 similar statutes were still in effect in 30 States. Compare post, at 12–14, nn. 2-3, with
supra, at 23-25, and nn. 33–34.

The dissent’s failure to engage with this long tradition is devastating to its position. We have held
that the “established method of substantive-due- process analysis” requires that an unenumerated
right be “‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition’ ” before it can be recognized as a
component of the “liberty” protected in the Due Process Clause. Glucksberg, 521 U. S., at 721; cf.
Timbs, 586 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 7). But despite the dissent’s professed fidelity to stare decisis,
it fails to seriously engage with that important precedent - which it cannot possibly satisfy.

...

Roe was also egregiously wrong and deeply damaging. For reasons already explained, Roe’s
constitutional analysis was far outside the bounds of any reasonable interpretation of the various
constitutional provisions to which it vaguely pointed.

Roe was on a collision course with the Constitution from the day it was decided, Casey perpetuated
its errors, and those errors do not concern some arcane corner of the law of little importance to the
American people. Rather, wielding nothing but “raw judicial power,” Roe, 410 U. S., at 222
(White, J., dissenting), the Court usurped the power to address a question of profound moral and
social importance that the Constitution unequivocally leaves for the people.

...

Roe found that the Constitution implicitly conferred a right to obtain an abortion, but it failed to
ground its decision in text, history, or precedent. It relied on an erroneous historical narrative; it
devoted great attention to and presumably relied on matters that have no bearing on the meaning
of the Constitution; it disregarded the fundamental difference between the precedents on which it
relied and the question before the Court; it concocted an elaborate set of rules, with different
restrictions for each trimester of pregnancy, but it did not explain how this veritable code could be
teased out of anything in the Constitution, the history of abortion laws, prior precedent, or any
other cited source; and its most important rule (that States cannot protect fetal life prior to
“viability”) was never raised by any party and has never been plausibly explained. Roe’s reasoning
quickly drew scathing scholarly criticism, even from supporters of broad access to abortion.

...

All in all, Roe’s reasoning was exceedingly weak, and academic commentators, including those
who agreed with the decision as a matter of policy, were unsparing in their criticism. John Hart
Ely famously wrote that Roe was “not constitutional law and g[ave] almost no sense of an
obligation to try to be.” Ely 947 (emphasis deleted).

...

We must now decide what standard will govern if state abortion regulations undergo constitutional
challenge and whether the law before us satisfies the appropriate standard.
Under our precedents, rational-basis review is the appropriate standard for such challenges. As we
have explained, procuring an abortion is not a fundamental constitutional right because such a right
has no basis in the Constitution’s text or in our Nation’s history. See supra, at 8–39.

It follows that the States may regulate abortion for legitimate reasons, and when such regulations
are challenged under the Constitution, courts cannot “substitute their social and economic beliefs
for the judgment of legislative bodies.” Ferguson, 372 U. S., at 729–730; see also Dandridge v.
Williams, 397 U. S. 471, 484–486 (1970); United States v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U. S. 144,
152 (1938). That respect for a legislature’s judgment applies even when the laws at issue concern
matters of great social significance and moral substance. See, e.g., Board of Trustees of Univ. of
Ala. v. Garrett, 531 U. S. 356, 365–368 (2001) (“treatment of the disabled”); Glucksberg, 521 U.
S., at 728 (“assisted suicide”); San Antonio Independent School Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U. S. 1,
32–35, 55 (1973) (“financing public education”).

A law regulating abortion, like other health and welfare laws, is entitled to a “strong presumption
of validity.” Heller v. Doe, 509 U. S. 312, 319 (1993). It must be sustained if there is a rational
basis on which the legislature could have thought that it would serve legitimate state interests. Id.,
at 320; FCC v. Beach Communications, Inc., 508 U. S. 307, 313 (1993); New Orleans v. Dukes,
427 U. S. 297, 303 (1976) (per curiam); Williamson v. Lee Optical of Okla., Inc., 348 U. S. 483,
491 (1955). These legitimate interests include respect for and preservation of prenatal life at all
stages of development, Gonzales, 550 U. S., at 157-158; the protection of maternal health and
safety; the elimination of particularly gruesome or barbaric medical procedures; the preservation
of the integrity of the medical profession; the mitigation of fetal pain; and the prevention of
discrimination on the basis of race, sex, or disability. See id., at 156– 157; Roe, 410 U. S., at 150;
cf. Glucksberg, 521 U. S., at 728– 731 (identifying similar interests).

These legitimate interests justify Mississippi’s Gestational Age Act. Except “in a medical
emergency or in the case of a severe fetal abnormality,” the statute prohibits abortion “if the
probable gestational age of the unborn human being has been determined to be greater than fifteen
(15) weeks.” Miss. Code Ann. §41–41–191(4)(b). The Mississippi Legislature’s findings recount
the stages of “human prenatal development” and assert the State’s interest in “protecting the life
of the unborn.” §2(b)(i). The legislature also found that abortions performed after 15 weeks
typically use the dilation and evacuation procedure, and the legislature found the use of this
procedure “for nontherapeutic or elective reasons [to be] a barbaric practice, dangerous for the
maternal patient, and demeaning to the medical profession.” §2(b)(i)(8); see also Gonzales, 550
U. S., at 135–143 (describing such procedures). These legitimate interests provide a rational basis
for the Gestational Age Act, and it follows that respondents’ constitutional challenge must fail.

We end this opinion where we began. Abortion presents a profound moral question. The
Constitution does not prohibit the citizens of each State from regulating or prohibiting abortion.
Roe and Casey arrogated that authority. We now overrule those decisions and return that authority
to the people and their elected representatives.

You might also like