Level of Measurement
Level of Measurement
Contents
[hide]
1Stevens's typology
o 1.1Overview
1.1.1Comparison
o 1.2Nominal level
1.2.1Mathematical operations
1.2.2Central tendency
o 1.3Ordinal scale
o 1.4Interval scale
1.4.1Central tendency and statistical dispersion
o 1.5Ratio scale
2Debate on Stevens's typology
o 2.1Other proposed typologies
2.1.1Mosteller and Tukey's typology (1977)
2.1.2Chrisman's typology (1998)
o 2.2Scale types and Stevens's "operational theory of measurement"
2.2.1Same variable may be different scale type depending on context
3See also
4References
5Further reading
6External links
Stevens's typology[edit]
Overview[edit]
Stevens proposed his typology in a 1946 Science article titled "On the theory of scales of
measurement".[2] In that article, Stevens claimed that all measurement in science was conducted
using four different types of scales that he called "nominal," "ordinal," "interval," and "ratio," unifying
both "qualitative" (which are described by his "nominal" type) and "quantitative" (to a different
degree, all the rest of his scales). The concept of scale types later received the mathematical rigour
that it lacked at its inception with the work of mathematical psychologists Theodore Alper (1985,
1987), Louis Narens (1981a, b), and R. Duncan Luce (1986, 1987, 2001). As Luce (1997, p. 395)
wrote:
S. S. Stevens (1946, 1951, 1975) claimed that what counted was having an interval or ratio scale.
Subsequent research has given meaning to this assertion, but given his attempts to invoke scale
type ideas it is doubtful if he understood it himself ... no measurement theorist I know accepts
Stevens's broad definition of measurement ... in our view, the only sensible meaning for 'rule' is
empirically testable laws about the attribute.
Comparison[edit]
Incrementa Advanced
Mathematical Central
l Measure Property Operation
Operators Tendency
s
Progress
Geometric Mean,
Ratio Magnitude, Amount *, / Ratio
Coeff. of Variation
Nominal level[edit]
The nominal type differentiates between items or subjects based only on their names or
(meta-)categories and other qualitative classifications they belong to; thus dichotomous data
involves the construction of classifications as well as the classification of items. Discovery of an
exception to a classification can be viewed as progress. Numbers may be used to represent the
variables but the numbers do not have numerical value or relationship: for example, a Globally
unique identifier.
Examples of these classifications include gender, nationality, ethnicity, language, genre, style,
biological species, and form.[6][7] In a university one could also use hall of affiliation as an example.
Other concrete examples are
Interval scale[edit]
The interval type allows for the degree of difference between items, but not the ratio between them.
Examples include temperature with the Celsius scale, which has two defined points (the freezing and
boiling point of water at specific conditions) and then separated into 100 intervals, date when
measured from an arbitrary epoch (such as AD), percentage such as a percentage return on a stock,
[16]
location in Cartesian coordinates, and direction measured in degrees from true or magnetic north.
Ratios are not meaningful since 20 °C cannot be said to be "twice as hot" as 10 °C, nor can
multiplication/division be carried out between any two dates directly. However, ratios of
differences can be expressed; for example, one difference can be twice another. Interval type
variables are sometimes also called "scaled variables", but the formal mathematical term is an affine
space (in this case an affine line).
Central tendency and statistical dispersion[edit]
The mode, median, and arithmetic mean are allowed to measure central tendency of interval
variables, while measures of statistical dispersion include range and standard deviation. Since one
can only divide by differences, one cannot define measures that require some ratios, such as
the coefficient of variation. More subtly, while one can define moments about the origin, only central
moments are meaningful, since the choice of origin is arbitrary. One can define standardized
moments, since ratios of differences are meaningful, but one cannot define the coefficient of
variation, since the mean is a moment about the origin, unlike the standard deviation, which is (the
square root of) a central moment.
Ratio scale[edit]
The ratio type takes its name from the fact that measurement is the estimation of the ratio between a
magnitude of a continuous quantity and a unit magnitude of the same kind (Michell, 1997, 1999). A
ratio scale possesses a meaningful (unique and non-arbitrary) zero value. Most measurement in the
physical sciences and engineering is done on ratio scales. Examples
include mass, length, duration, plane angle, energy and electric charge. In contrast to interval
scales, ratios are now meaningful because having a non-arbitrary zero point makes it meaningful to
say, for example, that one object has "twice the length" of another (= is "twice as long"). Very
informally, many ratio scales can be described as specifying "how much" of something (i.e. an
amount or magnitude) or "how many" (a count). The Kelvin temperature scale is a ratio scale
because it has a unique, non-arbitrary zero point called absolute zero.
Central tendency and statistical dispersion
The geometric mean and the harmonic mean are allowed to measure the central tendency, in
addition to the mode, median, and arithmetic mean. The studentized range and the coefficient of
variationare allowed to measure statistical dispersion. All statistical measures are allowed because
all necessary mathematical operations are defined for the ratio scale.
1. Names
2. Grades (e.g. freshmen, sophomores etc.)
3. Counted fractions bound by 0 and 1
4. Counts (non-negative integers)
5. Amounts (non-negative real numbers)
6. Balances (any real number)
For example, percentages (a variation on fractions in the Mosteller-Tukey framework) do not fit well
into Stevens’s framework: No transformation is fully admissible. [17]
Chrisman's typology (1998)[edit]
Nicholas R. Chrisman [5] introduced an expanded list of levels of measurement to account for various
measurements that do not necessarily fit with the traditional notions of levels of measurement.
Measurements bound to a range and repeating (like degrees in a circle, clock time, etc.), graded
membership categories, and other types of measurement do not fit to Stevens' original work, leading
to the introduction of six new levels of measurement, for a total of ten:
1. Nominal
2. Graded membership
3. Ordinal
4. Interval
5. Log-Interval
6. Extensive Ratio
7. Cyclical Ratio
8. Derived Ratio
9. Counts
10. Absolute
While some claim that the extended levels of measurement are rarely used outside of academic
geography [21], graded membership is central to fuzzy set theory, while absolute measurements
include probabilities and the plausibility and ignorance in Dempster-Shafer theory. Cyclical ratio
measurements include angles and times. Counts appear to be ratio measurements, but the scale is
not arbitrary and fractional counts are commonly meaningless. Log-interval measurements are
commonly displayed in stock market graphics. All these types of measurements are commonly used
outside academic geography, and do not fit well to Stevens' original work.
Scale types and Stevens's "operational theory of measurement" [edit]
The theory of scale types is the intellectual handmaiden to Stevens's "operational theory of
measurement", which was to become definitive within psychology and the behavioral sciences,[citation
needed]
despite Michell's characterization as its being quite at odds with measurement in the natural
sciences (Michell, 1999). Essentially, the operational theory of measurement was a reaction to the
conclusions of a committee established in 1932 by the British Association for the Advancement of
Science to investigate the possibility of genuine scientific measurement in the psychological and
behavioral sciences. This committee, which became known as the Ferguson committee, published a
Final Report (Ferguson, et al., 1940, p. 245) in which Stevens's sone scale (Stevens & Davis, 1938)
was an object of criticism:
…any law purporting to express a quantitative relation between sensation intensity and stimulus
intensity is not merely false but is in fact meaningless unless and until a meaning can be given to the
concept of addition as applied to sensation.
That is, if Stevens's sone scale genuinely measured the intensity of auditory sensations, then
evidence for such sensations as being quantitative attributes needed to be produced. The evidence
needed was the presence of additive structure – a concept comprehensively treated by the German
mathematician Otto Hölder (Hölder, 1901). Given that the physicist and measurement
theorist Norman Robert Campbell dominated the Ferguson committee's deliberations, the committee
concluded that measurement in the social sciences was impossible due to the lack
of concatenationoperations. This conclusion was later rendered false by the discovery of the theory
of conjoint measurement by Debreu (1960) and independently by Luce & Tukey (1964). However,
Stevens's reaction was not to conduct experiments to test for the presence of additive structure in
sensations, but instead to render the conclusions of the Ferguson committee null and void by
proposing a new theory of measurement:
Paraphrasing N.R. Campbell (Final Report, p.340), we may say that measurement, in the broadest
sense, is defined as the assignment of numerals to objects and events according to rules (Stevens,
1946, p.677).
Stevens was greatly influenced by the ideas of another Harvard academic, the Nobel
laureate physicist Percy Bridgman (1927), whose doctrine of operationism Stevens used to define
measurement. In Stevens's definition, for example, it is the use of a tape measure that defines length
(the object of measurement) as being measurable (and so by implication quantitative). Critics of
operationism object that it confuses the relations between two objects or events for properties of one
of those of objects or events (Hardcastle, 1995; Michell, 1999; Moyer, 1981a,b; Rogers, 1989).
The Canadian measurement theorist William Rozeboom (1966) was an early and trenchant critic of
Stevens's theory of scale types.
Same variable may be different scale type depending on context [edit]
Another issue is that the same variable may be a different scale type depending on how it is
measured and on the goals of the analysis. For example, hair color is usually thought of as a
nominal variable, since it has no apparent ordering. [22] However, it is possible to order colors
(including hair colors) in various ways, including by hue; this is known as colorimetry. Hue is an
interval level variable.
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Level_of_measurement