WILSON John Cook Statement and Inference
WILSON John Cook Statement and Inference
INFERENCE
Oxford University Press
London Edtnbu,gh Glasgow Copt'1'hagen
New rork 'Toronto Mel.bourne Cape Town
Bombay Calcutta MaJra1 Shanghai
Humphrey Milford Publisher to the UNIVtRSITY
STATEMENT
.. AND
INFERENCE· )
BY
A. S. L. ~~RQUHARSON)
Fl;LLOW OJ' UNIVERSITY COLLEGE
IN TWO VOLUMES
VOL. I '
-
OXFORD
AT THE CLARENDON PRESS
1926
Pnnld ,,. E11gl&ttd
Al Ille OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS
Ily John J olm.,,,.
/'mlU, lo tlle Unwe,isly
TO
MY MOTHER AND MY FATHER'S MEMORY
PART I. INTRODUCTORY
I. The Definition of Logic 24
II. The Relation of Knowmg to Thmkmg . 34
III. Logic and Cognate Studies. General and Special
Logic 48
IV. Logic and Theones of Knowledge and Reahty 60
CONTENTS OF VOLUME II
PART III. INFERENCE
I. The General Nature of Inference 412
LIST OF ILLUSTRATIONS
John Cook Wilson. From a photograph by Elliot and Fry
(see Letter No. 70, p. clxii) . Frontispiece
J. C. Wilson playing with Mr. Prichard's sons
(see Letter No. 31) • To face p. cxvii
TO THE READER
THESE volumes embrace what seemed most valuable and
best suited to publication of the late Professor John Cook
Wilson's philosophical lectures and speculations. His reputa-
tion for Greek scholarship stood so high with his contemporaries
that a strong desire was expressed that his best work in this
field also should be colJected under one view. Expense and
the inchoate condition of his unpublished critical studies have
prevented this. Two important sets of lectures were accessible
in pupils' note-books and were put generously at my service,
To fit them however for the learned public would have
demanded laborious recasting, while the student has easy
access to invaluable work in English on both these topics,
Plato's Republic and Aristotle's Theory of Demonstrative
Science.
His collections upon the Greek Scriptores Musici and Tactici
and his careful studies in Plato's later dialogues only Wilson
himself ccmld have arranged.
It seemed therefore best simply to make a list of his published
works, with a note of the places where tbey are to be found
and an indication of their nature. This I have done
His logic lectures, on the other hand, could be presented in
a form which does not indeed do justice to his powers but
will, it is hoped, be of assistance to the philosophical student.
Moreover, he had himself clearly contemplated their publica-
tion. They are supplemented by two special courses, by
selected passages from his memoranda-especially a paper
which he was preparing to read to the British Academy-and
by his philosophic correspondence. The latter has, it will be
viii To THE READER
seen, the imprimatur of no less an authority than Bernard
Bosanquet.1
The sources of this work I have indicated in a Postscript,
where I have also set out the approximate dates of the several
constituent parts. This will explain and perhaps justify in-
equalities and inconsistencies of expression and even, at times,
of doctrine. These could hardly be removed without serious
danger of misrepresentation. Some recompense will be found
in the light thrown on the path which led Wilson to his goal.
I desire here to thank those gentlemen who so freely put their
lecture notes at my disposal. In the end I had an embarras
de choix.
My little Memoir is written dehberately from the point of
view of a single observer. To correct its deficiencies or
partiality I have added a selection from Wilson's familiar
letters. These are meant to give ' some idea of what was in
the man's mind in its original unmitigated form, without
apology or attempt to soften it down '. 2 I might add ' what
was in his heart ' also. The series covers, so far as was possible,
his hfe from childhood to age. I have had no thought by my
choice to idealize the writer or to disguise his amiable weak-
nesses. Wherever I could I have given the letters entire.
Part of Boswell's secret lies in the scrupulous setting-down
even of the trivial and commonplace. In these things we
want a man, not a hero or a lay figure. My only omissions
have been made to avoid giving pain to relatives or to living
writers. I have left out some characteristically intemperate
outbursts provoked by differences of opinion on philosophic
themes, not because I desire to represent a passionless sage
but because they would not be understood. Otherwise the
1 Part V, x, xiv, esp. p. 826.
1 R. L. Nettlesh1p of his own account of Plato.
To THE READER ix
letters are nearly exactly as they were written, punctuation,
spelling and all. The more scientific letters are in Part V ;
their length and the care given to their composition display
very successfully the immense time and ardour Wilson lavished
in his friends' assistance and in the attempt to win converts
to his way of thinking. To illustrate his singular generosity
m this regard I have been old-fashioned enough to include
a selection of Testimonia.
The work has cost me most of my leisure hours in the past
four years. That the result is very imperfect I do not need
to be told, but I was anxious not to delay the book too long.
For obvious reasons and others which do not concern the
public I could not get to work until the Easter of r92r. It
will be recalled that Green's Remains took a long time pre-
paring and other examples will readily occur. Yet Nettleship
found Green's works either already printed or in their manu-
script form ' in general, contmuous and coherent '. Tins was
not my good fortune. Wilson left a great mass of material.
He himself called hts handwnting ' impressionist '. Thus the
mere ocular labour of reading the manuscnpts through has
been most exacting. Moreover some parts, and those impor-
tant, were in great disorder, and age increased his inveterate
tendency to discursiveness and prolixity. In editing an intri-
cate and abstract discussion it is very hard, I have found, to
be always certain where one's author is repeatmg htmself and
where he is merely making one more parallel in his laborious
advance. To o:nut or to rearrange may involve serious mis-
representation. Mr. J.C. B. Gamlen however, my co--executor,
desired me to use my judgement in all these matters, and I am
in consequence entirely responsible for any changes made in
the order and expression. Certainly the book appears to m~
to give a sufficiently exact view of Wilson's faith.
X To THE READER
• Lett.er of J. C. W , 10.111.84.
• Letter of Mr J W. Sharpe, sometime Fellow of Gonville and Cams,
25.v 16, to H. W B. J.
MEMOIR xxiu
the custom of the Methodists, was never more than three years
on one station ; and his son once or twice told me that they
were twice reduced to dire straits, i.e. on two stations, because
his father would not model his teaching on the opinions of some
powerful deacon or other, who thereupon took care that the
teachings of poverty should be inflicted upon the recalcitrant
and stiff-necked minister. Wilson's stores of energy, both
physical and mental, were to me always astonishmg, at all
times of my life. Nothing depressed him, and no prospect of
work appalled him, and hardly ever indeed proved too much
for him.' 1
Professor Hobson says : ' Wilson was, when at school, much
interested in the drilling of Volunteers. One day when the Drill
Sergeant was absent, Wilson was set to dnll us small boys. We
imagined we were gomg to have an easy time, but we found we
were quite mistaken, as Wilson turned out to be quite a martinet
who compelled us to do everything with extreme care. I have
a vision of seeing Wilson m the Entrance Hall of the School
busily turning over the leaves of an immense Dictionary (prob-
ably Liddell and Scott), when I was told he was preparing for
the Oxford Semor Local Exammat1ons. I remember the feclmg
of awe with which the sight msp1red me.' 2
It was T H. Green's reputation and m part Green's initiative
that brought lum to Oxford. Desiring to bridge the gulf which
separated the poorer classes and the less privileged schools from
the Universities, Green had earnestly supported a favourite
scheme of Jowelt's by which boys who had done well m examma•
t10ns hke the Oxford Local might, provided they had offered
Latm and Greek, be elected to an exhibition at Balhol. 3 Wilson
profited by this He came up with one of these exhibitions in
January 1868, assisted also, I believe, by his head master's
generosity. 4 The College had instituted a hostel in St. Giles',
1
' J W. S to H W. B. J , 21 v 16
Letter of Mr E W Hobson, Sc D , LLD , F RS , Fellow of Christ's,
Sadleirian Profeb'!or of Pure Mathematics, Cambridge, to H. W B J ,
15 V 16
• For Green's interest in the scheme see Worhs, vol 111, p. cv11 (Bradley's
memoir)
• • In several instances, to my knowledge, he generously helped those
who had difficulty 1n meetmg the expenses of a University education' :
Letter of J C W., 10,111.84.
xxiv MEMOIR
where poorer men might lodge and board at less cost than in
college. Green himself hved there both before and after his
marriage m 1871 to John Addington Symonds's sister. Here
Wilson read for both mathematical and classical honours.1 He
had few friends, lived to himself and was happy enough, studying
very hard, rismg rarly and s1ttmg up late. In November 1869
he was raised to the status of mathematical scholar and resided
continuously until the summer term of 1873, never moving mto
college 2 Thus he missed one of the happiest and best of
influences, the society of young men congregated within the
walls of a college. At Balhol Green's influence was strong upon
him; he followed his courses upon St. Paul's epistles as well as
his ordinary instruction. He attended Chandler, a very learned
Greek scholar, and an early course by Wilham Wallace on the
Politics of Aristotle. He heard Mr. Case too and his hfe-long
friendship with him depended largely on their common friend
Aristotle One thing he would say he learnt from Green, to
divide his own lectures into paragraphs. This has left its mark
on the present lectures. When he began to teach, he imitated
too Green's patient method of wcighmg every detail of an author
he was cnticizmg, spending an mordmate labour on minuter
issues, which the advance or change of ideas has itself anti·
quated Both Wilson and his master thus often seem unable
to discern any good in the author they are handling, m this the
very opposite of Wallace. This tendency has a bad effect on
the bcgmner, rousmg his natural sense of fair play and thereby
producmg the reverse of what is mtended, or else makmg him
run off with the notion that philosophy preserves the errors of
the past in order to refute them, while science quickly leaves
mistaken theories behind.
His mathematical teacher was Henry Smith, 8 a fascinating
and richly endowed character for whom Wtlson had an undying
admiration. Menttonmg Chandler, Green and Smith in his
' ISt Math. Mods 69: 1st Classical Mods 70; ISt Math. Finals 71 ;
1st Lit Hum 72.
1
The late Rev F H. Hall, Fellow and Dean of Oriel, told me that the
night of his election at Oriel was the first Wilson had spent w1thm the
walls of a College
1
H. J. S. Smith, F.R S., Ireland Scholar 48 ; Fellow of Balhol 49 •
SaVJhan Professor of Mathemabci, 6o-83; Fellow of C.C C. 73-83 •
MEMOIR XXV
17-18)
MEMOIR lxiii
we drove to Islip, where he was laid to rest beside his wife and
parents and sister in the churchyard which commands the
valleys of the Ray and Cherwell. A month later I was standing
on the bttle eminence, called Mont Rouge, watching our English
shrapnel bursting over the grim lines of the enemy front, and
only with difficulty could I free myself of the notion that my
old company commander in the 1st Volunteer battalion of the
Oxfordshire Light Infantry was at my side So strong was his
vitality that, for the first time in the presence of actual warfare,
I turned involuntarily as if to hear his appreciation of the
features of the ground. That closing scene was appropriately
set amid the beauty of the College which endows the chair he
held ; the broken sunlight seemed to speak of the intense
pleasure he took in the glory of the physical Universe and m
the power of mmds hke Newton's; an English churchyard 1 is
a good resting-place for the son of a minister of the Methodist
New Connexion, who with a full measure of the polemical temper
of that sect loved well the order and dignity of the Nat10nal
Church; finally, the stern struggle m Flanders seemed no
mappropnate background to the close of a hfe dedicated m so
much of its rare le1o;ure to training a succe . . sion of scholars m
the rudiments of military science.
Remarkable though these fragments of Wilson's higher thmk-
mg may appear and highly characteristic of his fearless and
uncompromising mmd, they do not exlubit, save dimly, the
power of his confident and passionate assertion of a hardly won
philosophic creed Except m their literary form they cannot
present the unaffected simphc1ty of their auth'>r, nor the almost
excessive devotion to detail that was his characteristic in small
thmgs as well as great. No words of mme will convey a true
notion of the exuberant and boyish happiness which triumphed
for so long over domestic anxiety and sorrow, the entire absence
of a scholar's self-consciousness and timidity, the affection for
friends and the love for parents and little children, winch m his
nature ran so strong and deep
1
In his account in German of Mrs Wilson's funeral he says of what was
to be his own resting-place ' The grave itself, adorned with a celtic cross
of white marble, occupies the highest point of the lovely churchyard, with
an extensive view of a pretty landscape.'
MEMOIR
We shall always regret that the necessity of a long absence
prevented most of us from waiting upon Wilson's declming days.
His loss makes a greater gap than we expected in the circle that
enjoyed his friendship and profited by his words. When we
returned, Oxford, swollen by the unexpected volume of maturer
students, was only gradually resuming her normal channels,
had hardly subsided within her banks. She was recruiting her
heavy losses, restoring and remaking her studies, discussing how
best to commemorate her dead, ambitious of a future worthy
of her past Oxford the same no doubt in essence, yet how
changed for the men of my generation ! In the tyranny of war,
manhood had slipped into middle age ; our own ranks were
thinned, and we marked for the first time that the majority of
those who taught us were no more Without the familiar faces
Oxford 1s strangely unfamiliar; but of all that is gone, more than
my gay company of the Trammg Corps , 1 the happy careless
friends, my pupils , more tl1an the cheerful and witty Charles
Fisher, 2 or Foster Cunhffc's 3 curious melancholy, even more
perhaps than the gentle and cxqu1s1te irony of Reginald T1ddy,'
I miss the little figure, the hght quick step, the good grey head,
the secure affection, the profound plulosoph1c ardour of Wdson
himself. A. S. L. F.
March 1921.
1
E Company, 0 U O T.C, was handed over by me tn 1913-14 to J L
Johnston, formerly Junior Demy and afterwards Fellow of Magdalen and
then Fellow of New College He se1ved with the 52nd m France and fell
at Festubert 12 v 15 He would certamly bave r1ben 1n Church or State
I wish specially to mention two of my Colour-Sergeants, both of New
College H T Culhs of Alleyne•~ College of God's gift at Dulw1ch, Scholar
of New College m 1899, wa& on leave from India when war began He
fell at Armentillres 10 xii 1 'i, servmg m the 12th (Service) Bn Rifle Bde
The other 1s Geoffrey W Polson, lulled at the Aisne, dunng the first allied
counter-stroke, 15 ~x 14 He wai, a subaltern in the zst Bn Royal High-
landers There were no better NCO 'sin the old Volunteer Bn. and the
new Tr0.1mng Corps Of the cadets who attended my lectures m nuhtary
sub1ects 111 May and June 1914, sixteen out of forty-four fell in the war
• Charles D Fisher, Scholar of New College, Semor Student and Censor
of Cbnst Church, lost m the foundering of HMS In111ne1ble 1n the action
off Jutland, p v 16
• Sir Foster C H Cunliffe, Hart, of New College, Fellow of All Souls,
formerly Colour-Sergeant of E Company, 0 UR V Bn., lolled serv1ng with
the 13th (Service} Bn Rifle Bde. on 10 v1116 at the battle of the Somme.
' Reginald /· '.E T1ddy, f,cholar and Fellow of University, .Fellow of
Tnwty, one o Wilson's cychsts Killed 1n the trenches when commanding
the men of his village in Oxfordshire m the 2nd Terntonal Bn Oxf. &
Bucks. LI. on 11.vm.16.
ELENCHVS OPERVM
TESTIMONIA
LIST OF PUBLISHED WORKS AND
CONTRIBUTIONS TO REVIEWS
[The articles m German penod1cals are wntten in that languagt' The
following abbreviations are used ·
0. P. S. =- Transactions (or Proceedings} of the Oxford PbilologJcal Society.
J of P = The Journal of Philology
Cl R = The Classical Rev1l'W
Cl Q = The Classical Quarterly
The remark.c; m square brackets are to indicate the character of the arbclec;
and 'IOml't1mt's to c;how add1tional content~ ]
1873.
Chancellor\, Latin Es~ay, Quaenam fuent rei•era Epicureorum
philosophia, recited m the Shcldonian Theatre, Oxford, 18 June,
:\-IDCCCLXXIII, by John fook Wilson, B.A , Mathematical Scholar
of Balliol. (Oxford)
1879
On rearrangements of the Fifth Book of the Ethics
0 P S , No 83, 14 March.
Aristotelian Studies, I On the structure of the Seventh Book
of the Nicomachcan Ethics, ch 1-x. (Oxford )
0 P S, ~o 8,+, 9 ~fay
1880
J Cook Wilson, An~toklic1.n Stud1cc., I, \'om Verfasst-r
Gotting1sche gel Anzc1gen, St 15, 14 April
[An account of his book, with d1scm.,ion of interpolations m
Eth E11d, Cat and An Pr]
Prof Suscm1hl's Ed1t1on of thl" l\'1comachea1i Eth1cs
The Academy, 26 Jun<'
1881.
Aristote, Morale a Nicomaque (8me hvre) Par L Levy.
Phil Rundschau, i 39.
(Review of the book, with suggestions as to the text-structure
and the existence of parallel version,; here and elsewhere.]
Notes on some passages in the Politics
J of P. x, pp So-6. ..
[Stmcture of text, Bks IV. 3; III. 10-n; V 1-3; VII. 1-3
and 12-13 (13-15) and 1260a 22, 1298a I, 1342b 23,l
ELENCHVS 0PERV1\I Jxvii
1882.
(i) Zcllcr's interpretation of Xen. Mein. iv. 2, 34 and iii. 2, 4.
[Socrates' eudaemonism.]
(ii) Plato, Phil. 3I A.
(iii) Aristotle's criticism of the definition of pleasure in the Philebus.
(iv) Theophrastus, De Sensu, § 90. [emendns. of Plato, Tim.
66 D ; Arist. 443a 2I, 359b 32,]
0. P. S. 1881-2, pp. IO-I3, IO Feb.
Conjectural emendations in the text of Aristotle and Theophrastus.
J. of P. xi, pp II9-24.
[Aristotle, 443a 6, 444 8 16, 11 2, 453a 27, 457" 31, II34a. 1, 056•
29, and Thcoph De Smsu, § 90 j
Stud1en zu Arh,totcles Politik von H Bucl1-.rnschutz
Phil Rund~chau, ii 39
[Attempts to prove that ordu of books in tlw Aristotelian
vulgate 1s as old as Anus D1dymt1'>' t-pitom(' ]
The interpretation of certain passages of the De .lmm,i in the
editions of Trcnddcnburg and Ton,tnk
0 P. S. 1882-3, pp 5-13, 17 NoY.
'ApttTToT,.>..71s Tl'Ep2 iftvxijs by E. Wallacr, :\I A.
Phil Rundschau, ii. 47.
1884
The gemunencss of An~totl(', Rheforir, ii 25-6 [also text of
14020. 29 and b 19l
The poss1btl1ty of a conc<'pt10n of the Enthymcmc earher than
that found m the H.lwtonc and th<' Pnor Analytics
0 P S 1883-4, pp. 4-6, 22 FPb. and 7 :March.
1885.
De Amma, 431" 24-6
Meteorologica, 1v, ch. 8-9 [on TEyi.ro, = soaking].
Nie. Eth. 1097b 8 [cf 1887].
0. P. S. 1884-5, pp. n-13, 6 March
A recent emendation of Aristotle [Metaph. 1035a 14].
The Academy, 2 May
1886.
Nie. Eth. n33a 14-16
Platc4IR, 330 E.
Nie. Eth. iii. t. 17.
0 P. S. 1886-7, pp. 2-4, 5 Nov.
e2
Jxvib ELENCHVS 0PERVl\-f
1887.
The sphere of Corrective Justice in Nie. Eth. v.
Nie. Eth. 1143b 5,
On Trendelenburg, Eletnenla Log. Anst., § z.
[Doctrine of truth and falsehood in de bit. and de An.
Simple notions.]
· 0. P. S. 1887-8, pp. 2-6, 4 Nov.
Recent emendations of the Aristotelian text.
The Academy, 3 Dec.
f\'inchcates, against H Jackson, MS. readings of Etlt. Nie.
I. vii 7-8 ; VII xm 2 , II vu 14 ; \'I v 4 and 6 ; JI.
\'JI I ' \' Vil l ' I \'l, I ]
18t(8.
Xie Eth 1097h 8, 1145h 23-4
0 J> S 1887-8, pp. 20-1, 3 Feb
~ome recent t'lll<'ndabons of Aristotle and Plato
fVmdicat<'s MS rt'admg-. of Eth l\"1c u45a 27, b 30, 1147b 31,
n77a12,n7<J'1 1fi,IX x §3,andPlatoR .n8E,andillnstrate.::
A 'i, tendency to dhphcal langua!?c ]
A recent emendation of SophocJt>1,
!Vind1catei. MS reading of AJax,646-9,against van Leeuwen.]
The Academy, 18 and 25 Feb.
Lange's theory of thl' cond1t10nal sentence m Greek
[E: originally a relative and (probably) a temporal pronoun.]
0 P S 1887-8, p 22 (for brief account see ib 1889-
90, pp 54-5], 8 June.
1889
Some recent t'mcndat10ns m the text of Plato
[Vindicates the MS. readings in R 537 c and 402 A.]
The Academy, 23 Feb
The Timaeus of Plato, cd R Archer-Hind
[Rev1ew1, m] 1 The Clas-.1cal Review, iii, pp. 114-23, 183-4.
11 The Oxford Magazine, 13 March.
Mr. Archer-Hind's 'Last Word'.
The Academy, 8 June
On an Evolutionist theory of Axioms, an Inaugural lectun-.
Oxford.
On the interpretation of Plato's Timaeus. Critical st$es with
reference to a recent edition. London (D. Nutt).
Manual of Cyclist Drill for the use of the Cyclist Section of the
O.U.R.V.f Oxford.
ELENCHVS OPEK\rM
1890.
Military Cycling, or Amenities of Controversy. Oxford
On some apparent anomalies in the use of p:,j.
0. P S. 1889-90, pp. 23-56, 13 June.
1892-3
A point of Infantry drill.
A. and N. Gazette, 16 Jan 1892
The pseudo-Aristotelian treatise<;, De JI,,/ elisso, Xc1topl1anc, <,,wgia
Cl. R. ,·ols. v1 and vii
[Six articles on Apelt'i. edition, containi. incidentally many
suggested emendations ]
1894
Ani.totlc, Sopli. El. 166b 32, 171b 37, 172a 25 and Top. 1621! I.
0. P S. 1894, 12 May
1895
lcsllmonia for the tc:xt of Arbtotlc's Etli. Sic, Mctap!i. and
An. Po
[From Ptolemy, Theon, &c J
CI R. ix, pp. 1-4
1890.
Am,totle'i. ClaSblfication of the arts of ,1cqui&1tion.
rscc 1902 J
Cl R. :x, pp 184-9, l\lay
1900
Suggestions for Cyclist Road Practice in Skirmi:.hing and
Patrolling. Oxford.
Inverse or" posterior, Probability.
[A proof of the principle and an explanation of the philo-
sophical meaning of probability.)
Nature, 13 Dec.
lxx ELENCBVS 0PERVM
1901.
1902.
F..dward Postc
Obit. notice in The Oxford l\lagazinr, 4 June.
Eth. Nie. VII. xiv. 2 and xii 2.
[Correction of articles dated 1896, 7 and 8 ]
Alrya.\mrpi71'E&a and Mrya.'A.Dlfvxla. in Aristotle.
On the u-rr~1~p.a.Ta of Greek ships. [Cf J. Adam, 1'he Republic
of Plato, h, p 44-5 ]
Plato, R. 616 E Lagainst Kron•~ ed. of Proclus in Rep.; astronomy
of the myth of Er, the Armenian]
Cl. R xv1, pp. 23-8, 203,234 and 29.?-3, 0. P. S., 31 Jan.
The astronomical concephom, m Plato, R , Bk X
[V1dc J Adam, I c , 11, App VI, pp. 470-9 J
1903
l\1emo1r of the Rev T. W Fowle, 1\1.A , 1.tte Rector of fabp,
Oxfordshire Oxford
On the g<•om<>trical prohl<'m 111 Plato'& l\Jeuo, 86 :E.
Note on LAnstotk] de lw 111,ec CJ70 8 5
J of P , , ol ,._ '\ vm, pp. 222-40
Eliz Ni, u35b 19
Cl R XVll, pp 384-5
1904.
Pseudo-Euclid, I ntroductio Harmonica [text on Concord!, emended].
On tbe Platonist doctrine of the d.crvp.PA.,,,.o, d.pi8p.o{.
The problem of the Greek modes [criticism of D. B. Monro].
Musici Scrit,tores Graeci, Emendations and discussions.
Cl. R. xviii, pp 150-1, 247-60, 278; 0. P. S., 12 Feb.,
and 387-gr
ELENCHVS 0PERVM lxxi
1905.
On the Traversing of Geometrical Figures. Oxford.
Addendum to the above. Oxford.
Homer, Od. xxiv. 336 seq [vindication of the MSS.]
The idea of tcd.Oa.po-,,;; in Aristotle's definition of Tragedy.
Cl. R. xix, pp 144-7 and 321-2 (0 P. S , 2 June).
Lewis Carroll's Logical Parc1.dox [signed W.]
Mind, N S , No 54, pp. 292-3
19o6.
On a supposed solution of the '!•our-Colour Problem ' [against
Archbishop Temple]
The l\lath<'matlcal Gc1.zctk, in, No. 58, pp 338-40.
1907
(1) :\Iemonal Notice of D. B l\Ionro
Burs1an's Jahresbc•richt, xxxu B, pp 30-40.
(n) David Binnmg 'Monro, a short :\lcmoir Oxford
[Translated, with alterations, from (1) ]
(m) David Bmmng :\lonro, 1836-1905.
Proceedmgc; of th<' B A. 1907 [ (ii) abbreviated].
Plato, R. 442 B
Et/1 Nie 114811. 23 [emrndation]
Cl R X'\.1, p 106
1908
Clement Ale:<.. Stromateis, 1 158 [emendation].
Cl Q. ii, p 293
1909
On the use of d.U' .;; m Aristotle
Plato, Pliil , 31 c.
Clement Alex , Stroni iv. 23 [emendation].
Cl Q ih, pp. 121-6, 216-17
1910.
Natural anomalies in original compo&ition.
[Refers to a paper to 0. P S , 1909, on The Similes of Homer.)
Eth. Nie. IV. iu. 15
Cl. R. x.uv, pp. u8 and 144-5.
lxxii ELENCHVS 0PERV:M
19n.
Eth. Nie. n23b 31.
Cl. R. XXV, pp. 132-5.
1912.
Aristotelian Studies, I {1879), Reissue of, with additions. Oxford.
[A Postscript on the authorship of the parallel versions and
supplem. index.]
Inaugural lecture {1889), Reissue with mtrod. sect. omitted.
Oxford.
Syllogism of the Abbe and the penitent.
The Athenacum, 10 Aug.
1913
A metapby&1cal problem written in Greek in mutation o! the
&tyk of Aristotle
The o~f. Mag xxxi 16, 6 ::\larch.
Plato, Soph., 244 c LCnticism of H. Jackson J
Cl. Q vb, pp 52-3.
De Motu A nim 69Ba 16-24
Rh. 1403b 21 Sl'q , Po 1449a 2J !:-Cq
Phy. 231b 21.
Eth. Nie. n22b n-18.
Plato, Tim. 37 c.
Catullus, lxili. 31
Metaph. 1048• 30 seq.
J. of P. xxxu, pp. u3-4, 137-65, 166, 167-g, 300-1.
Po. 1451• 22, 1447b 13-16.
On the meaning of M.,..os m certain pasi.agcs m Anstotlc'& Nico-
HUJClsetan Ethics.
[.\o-yos to be tram,lated by' reason'.]
Cl R xxvii, pp 7-9, n3-17.
TESTIMONIA
'To Professor J Cook Wdson, of New College, Oxford, I owe
a special debt of gratitude for undertaking in response to my appeal
an exhaustive discussion of the astronomical difficulties m Book X
and unreservedJy placing at my disposal the full results of his
investigations '-J Adam, The Republ,c of Plato (1902), vol. i,
pp. ix, x (Cambndge)
' It is only through the kmd co-operation of Professor Cook
Wilson that I have at last been able to form a definite view as to
the meaning and '>0lution of this e,.tremely complicated problem.
From 616 B to the middle- of 617 B, my commentary is mainly
based on the exham,t1vc criticisms and mvest1gatlons which he has
sent tom<' '-lb, vol ii, p 441
'Thii. Appendix 1s the result of prolonged d1scusr;ions with Pro-
fessor Cook Wil'ion and frc·ely r<'produccs nearly all his most
important argument1, '-lb, vol. 11, App. VI to Book X, p. 470.
' [The Editor] has to thank Mr J. C. Wdo,on ... for the most
cordial and ample as'iistance in dealing with the numerous passage&
in which mathematical knowledge was required. It is believed that
the translation of these passages will, owing mainly to his help, be
found on the whole correct and mtelligible '-Lotze, Logic• (Eng.
Trans.), ed. by B Bosanquet (Oxford, 1888), vol. 1, p. vi.
' The Editor has to thank Mr. J C. Wilson . for ample and
ready assistance when consulted on passagrs involving the technical
language of Mathematics or Physics, 1f the Author'& meaning in
such places has been intelligibly conV<'yed, this result is wholly due
to Mr. Wilson'i. hclp.'-Lotze, Metaphysic (Eng Trans.), ed. by
B. Bosanquet (Oxford, 1884), p. v1
'Line of treatment [of Plato's Parmemdesj suggested by Pro-
fessor Cook Wtlson.'-B. Bosanquet, Plato's Theory of Forms
(Oxford, 1903), p. 14
' Sed est cui prae ommbus grates agam atquc habeam, VIrum
dico si quis alius 'Apt.cr,w~TOv, I. C. Wilson: quem ut
socium mihi in hac editione paranda futurum speraveram, ita post•
quatn instantiora eum negotia alio averterant, alienum opus adiuvare
ct, quantum potuit, amico suppetiari non recusavit ; haud exiguam
Jxxiv TESTIHONJA
enim libri partem una relegimus, crebrisque colloqaiis collato studio
diflicillima quaeque excussimus.'-AristoteUs Eflffca N-ico,nacllea,
I. Bywater (Oxford, 1890), p. vii.
' The essential symmetry of the inverse and the direct methods
... is shown by an elegant proof which Professor Cook Wilson has
given for the received rules of inverse probability.'-F. Y. E.,
Encycl. Brit., x1, p. 378b, note Io
'To Professor Cook Wilson in particular, who read over the
whole of the proof pnnts of the work and made a number of acute
criticisms, I am much indebted '-Trichotomy in Roman Law,
H. Goudy (Oxford, 1910), preface. (German translation Dreiteilig-
keit im 1innische1i Recht, E Ehrlich, 1914.)
' ... the debt wluch I owe, in common with so many of his older
or younger pup1b, to Prof J Cook Wilson, whose death occurred
while these sheets were pas::.mg through the pres!> Various foot-
notes will show the~ that I haw made of his unpublished teach-
ing; but hi:. tllness prevented me from subm1tt1ng to him what
I have written, and h1:. authority mu!>t be made responsible for no
errors that I have made. His few and scattered publications can do
little to convey to strangers the power and stimulus of his personal
teaching. And there are subject!> on which, by his combination of
scholarly and mathematical with philosophic insight, he was quahfted
as few have been to produce new work of real value.'-Anlntro-
duction to Logic 2, H. W. B. Joseph (Oxford, 1916), pp. vi and vii.
' My obligations arc many and great . . . to Professor Cook
Wilson, to have been whose pupil I count the greatest of philo-
sophical good fortunes Some years ago 1t was my privilege to be
a member of a class with which Profeso;or Cook Wilson read a por-
tion of Kant's Critrquc of Pure Reason and subsequently I have
had the advantage of discussing with him several of the more
unportant passages. I am especially indebted to lum m my dis-
cussion of the following topics . the d1Stinction between the Sensi-
bility and the Understanding, the term "form of perception", the
Maaphysical Exposition of Space, Inner Sense, the Maaphysical
Deduction of the Categories, Kant's account of "the reference of
representations to an object ", an implication of perspective, the
impossibility of a " theory " of knowledge and the points con-
sidered, pp 200 med.-202 med., 214 med.-215 med. and 218. The
views expressed in the pages referred to originated from Professor
Cook Wilson.'-Kant's Theory of KMWledge, H A. Prichard
(O.xford, 1909), pp. ui-iv.
T.ESTIMONIA bav
' Throughout this Essay I am deeply indebted to the critic:isms
and suggestions of Professor Cook Wilson. In particular, I h&ve
substantially adopted his account of the distinction between abstract
terms and adjectives, in place of a less satisfactory view of my
own.'-Personalldealism, ed H. Sturt (1902). Note I to Professor
G. F. Stout's essay on E,-,,o,,,
' I owe to conversation with Prof Cook Wilson the first suggestion
that this view is one for serious consideration, but for nothing in
my working out of it can I claim his authority.'-Problems in lhe
relations of God and Man, C C J Webb (London, Nisbet, 1911).
' Dedicated in affectionate gratitude to the memory of a great
thinker and a great teacher, John Cook Wilson, sometime Wykeham
Professor of Logic in the University of Oxford.'-Dedication of God
and Personality, C. C. J Webb, Fellow of St. Mary Magdalen
College, Oxford. (London, Allen & Unwin, 1918 )
' ... as my lamented and honoured teacher, the late Professor
Cook Wilson, did in a paper of marked originality, which made
a great impression on those who heard it read at Oxford, and which
I hope may hereafter be made pubhc, when the return of peace
shall have set his literary executors free to carry out the pious task
of giving to the world what he has left behind him '-lb., p. n9,
foot-note 6.
Referring to Martineau's works on Ethics and Religion, Professor
C. C. J. Webb says: 'In later years I have re-read them with
greatly mcreased admiration and have seen how well this writer
deserved the commendation which I recollect my lamented teacher,
Professor Cook Wilson, long ago bestowing on him for his bold
faithfulness to the facts of our common moral expcrience.'-Divbre
Personality and Huttian Life (London, Allen & Unwin, 1920).
'So ist das Verhiiltniss schon nchtig \-On Herrn John Cook
Wilson, dem Ari!.totelesfon,cher, beurthellt, der auf gutige Ver-
wendung des Herrn Prof. 0. Francke . die drei Hss , wie ich
sagen darf, mit ausserordentlicher Genauigkeit collationirte.'-
Awaoi M-yoi, Ernst Weber, Phil -Hist. Beitr. (p 35).
' In the attempt to interpret this difficult passage I owe much
to the late Professor Cook Wilson, who discussed it with me.'-
Aristotle's Metaphysics, W. D. Ross (Oxford, 1924), vol. il, p. 268.
'I am indebted to my friend, Mr. J. Cook Wilson, Fellow and
Tutor of Oriel College, for many valuable hint-. in connection with
the Introduction.'-A.ristotle's Psychology, Edwin Wallace (Cam-
bridge, 1882), p. vii.
lxxvi TESTIMONIA
See the following notices ·
S. Ball in The Oriel Record, Sept. 1915, pp 246-8, Oxford Mag•-
zint, :z:z Oct. 1915.
The late Rev. F. H. Hall in The Onel Record, Sept. 1915, p 245,
' Peace and fresh service to that imperious spirit '.
Mr. H W. B Joseph, Proceedings of the B. Academy, vol. vii,
pp. I-II.
Mr. H. A. Pnchard, Mtnd, N S., ;,.;,.nu, No. III, pp. 297-318.
FAMILIAR LETTERS
1859-1914
(Numbered 1-72 indusive)
The following letters were addressed :
To Mrs. W1lc:;on senior ~0<1 1-6, and 8-12.
To I. Bywater. ~o 7.
To Mr. J W "harp N'o 13 (from Wilson's own copy).
To Rev. S C Parm1ter. ~o. q.
To B. Bosanquet Nos. 17, 24-6, and 59.
To a Schoolmaster. No 27 (from Wilson's own copy}.
To Mr. H. A. Prichard. Noc:;. 28, 30, 31, 34, 39, 6o, and 61.
To Sir W. Henry Hadow. No. 58.
To Mr. Colin Gilray. Nos. 62 1 63 1 and 70.
To C. Cannan. Nos. 64 and 67-9.
To Lieut -General H. D. Farquharson. No. 71.
The remainder were to myself or my wife. They are often
undated but I have indicated "hat I believe to be the dates.
I have to thank those ladies and gentlemen who have per-
mitted me to use this material
1
[Shireland Hall, Birmingham.]
Wednesday aftnoon
[? 10th August 1 1859.]
MY VERY DEAR MAMMA,
I received your dear letter this morning, the reason that
I wrote my letter so bad was I couldnt keep from crying. I hope
that all are well give my love to dear little Maggie, many kisses
for you. I have written this very badly as the other and for
the same reason. Miss Simmonds does not know the reason my
collars were iron moulded, she says I shall not want the 2 collars,
she sends her very kind regards to you, I hope that Grand•
mamma is better give her my love and lots of kisses. Your
letters make me cry so, your ever
affectionate son
JOHNNY,
The first page 1s to h1, mother, the letter to his Fathe-r takes page z and
part of page 3.
1
The next letter gives 49 as the number The preceding letter says, ' When
we eot near Bl1'Illlngham John McKenzie took mv umbcrclla and had a ,;cuffle
with James Wright and the:1- broke the handle of'
lxxx FAMILIAR LETTERS
I shall try to get into Astronomy. The drawing master thought
that I should win the prize in this half. Dear Papa I cannot
live away from home. If you want me to die send me to this
place or away from home. I do not say anything of this to
anybody. Lots of kisses. Your affectionate son
JOHNNY.
P.S. I will try to write well.
2
Shireland Hall,
Birmingham,
December 1st, 1859.
}fy DEAR PARE!l<TS,
It is with great pleasure that I inform you that the
vacation will commence on the 16th inst. The school will be
reopened on the 1st of January. Please to send the money for
my travelling expenses as soon as possible and give me all
needful instruction~ for my journey. Please to give my love to
all at home. llopmg that you are quite well,
I remain,
Your affectionate son,
JonN COOK WILSON,
3
The Rectory,
Grasmere.
July 19 [? 1872].
Mv DEAR MAMMA,
J am much obliged to you for enclosing Mr. Case's letter.
I am much amused at your apologising for opening it seeing
that you appear to have read it. I am glad to hear the touching
account of Puss : you don't say whether he gets his lights very
regularly. You needn't envy my staying here. It rains with
few intermissions in bucketfuls. The most useful of all garments
is a mackintosh : moreover I find it an awful grind to keep
these men going: but I don't give them more than 3 hours
a day among them. Consequently I would much prefer to be
like you, at home : than hke me, here. . • . Today was the
festival or ceremony of ' rush-bearing ' at Grasmere Church,
F AMILi AR LETTERS Ixxxi
All round the churchyard wall inside and I think on the top
stood children with wooden frames covered with flowers and
devices made of flowers and rushes. I don't know what it all
means.•.•
Papa need not put B A on my letters any more :-once was
enough (July 20).
4
Gottingcn June 16
f? 1875].
~l y DEAR MAM MA
2773•1 f
lxxxii FAMILIAR LETTERS
5
Sept. 13 [1882].
Mv DEAR MAMMA,
Y csterday I went with Shadwell to see our Littleworth
estate. I walked about a mile and a half to Bessclsleigh where
Shadwell, dnvmg from Oxford, picked me up. The road, the
one I hope to traverse when I bicycle to Clanfield, is a beautiful
one We had a splendid day and I looked down upon you with
the opera glass from the lull, Clanfield church being visible
among the trees Of this attention you "ere of course uncon•
scious, We found everything going on well The estate is
a beautiful one and extensive, comprising a fine manor house
with a small park (for a park) at Wadley.
(The rest is an account of the fascinating ways of his baby
son, including ' the way the sly dog hints what he wants is
amusing. "Dat Father's cake, poo Father wants it", as though
his own anxiety "as that I should cat my own cake This
transparent hypocrisy 1s a" ful at such tender years.'] Best love
to all, your affectionate son
According to this evening's Echo, the great stronghold Tel·
el-Kebir was taken this morning by our troops
6
August 7th, I 888.
Hotel de la Marine
Arromanches par Bayeux.
Mv DEAR MoTUER,
I was glad to get your letter. I tried today to get
a photograph for you with a peasant woman m the cap of the
country but was unsuccessful. They wear a u•hite cap with
a white starched band bound over it something like this only
the effect, as you will believe, is much prettier [pen-and-ink
drawing]. I have been twice to see the beautiful cathedral of
Bayeux-architecture nth (one of the towers), 12th, 13th and
15th century. In the nave are fine Norman arches, with the
genuine Norman Byzantine decorations, especially the zigzag
round the arches [sketch) but the greater part-of the architecture
is much later especially in the chancel or choir, which looks like
FAMILIAR LETTERS lxxxiii
our Early English decorated. The central tower of the catbedral
1s I think of 15th century (time of wars of Roses) and is very
beautiful, the tracery of the windows in it (open without glass
like those in tower of St. Mary's, Oxford) is very light and
elegant. Ralph and I went up into tbe lantern (300 feet and
over high). I also saw all the famous Bayeux tapestry, attributed
to Matilda, wife of Wm. Conqueror, with the history of expedi-
tion to England ending in Battle of Hastmgs. Bayeux is
a picturesque medieval town. There arc shops "1th old China
-French mainly &c-1 tried one of them but find it dear and
only bought a few trifles. . . I took Ralph to Bayeux on the
tncyclc The people thought it so charming to see him sitting
behind. Today we made a short expedition and Ralph had
the- pleaE-ure of examining a ship wrecked m February last on
the sands.
7
Hotel de la Marine
Arromanchcs
To I BYWATER, 93 Onslow Sq London. par Bayeux.
Aug. I 6, I 888.
As you may suppose I don't get much time for work here.
I have however got far enough m A.-H. to be able to form an
opinion on his capacity for the non-scholarship part of the
T1m(aeus). It took a ternble long time to make sure about the
mathu~ and music, with his authont1es. As to math. I find he
has but little knowledge of Gk mathuc and writes authonta·
t1vely, as usual, making all kmds of inaccurate statements.
Nearly evcrythmg 1s straight out of Martin and Stallbaum and
tlungs thdt ought to be noted are not because he knows nothing
beyond what is ms1de these sources The music is straight out
of Mart. and Stallb: and no acknowledge' beyond his preface,
even where quite necessary. He doesn't know the subject well
enough to reproduce these authorities properly or to distinguish
between what ought to be given in full and \\ hat can be abbre•
viated. (Often like the schoolboy who, havmg cribbed the
answer, is unable to shew the working or doesn't know it matters.)
As to the philosophy he doesn't understand the elements of his
business. I draw your attention to the pretentious note on
P• I06, which is utter nonsense, as a te11t passage.
f2
fxxxiv FAMILIAR LETTERS
8 Arromanches
Bayeux.
Aug. 24 (Friday) 1888.
Mv DEAR MOTHER,
The above little map shews the places which I visited
lately-Caen, st Lo, Coutances, Avranches. Caen contains fine
specimens of the early Norman Churches, one built it is said by
wm Conqueror and another by his wife. But perhaps one of
the most beautiful was at Coutances. Town set high on hHl,
abt 6 miles from sea. The Cathedral spire serves as a sea mark.
I was at a part of the Sunday morning mass there and the
architectural effect was much enhanced by the imposing cere·
monial. I think of all the cathedrals and churches I have seen
that of Bayeux ha,:; the most beautiful exterior on the whole,
I shall probably go there agam tomorrow on my tricycle and
take Ralph who enJoys 1t all very much .
. . . We went along the coa,;t the other day to sec an isolated
rock standing in the sea, 1 a<'ccssiblc at low tide. A striking
object. I made a sketch of it which I will shew you. Such
things rare on tlus coast. On the Cornwall coast they are
common enough.
9
Dec. 4. I 889.
26 Winchester Rd. Oxford.
Mv DEAR MoTnER,
•.. My article promises to be successful. It appeared
yesterday and the same evening I had a note from a Professor
here congratulatmg me on having completely smashed my
Cambridge opponent. I have had great luck in Kriegspiel (the
Wargame) and lately completely defeated our best player, or at
least one of the best. He had however the great disadvantage
of having (through an accident) httle time to prepare his plans,
whereas I had a long time. We had a game last week in which
a real military man (a retired Colonel) commanded the opposite
side to that in which I served as a subordinate (this time). He
suffered a tremendous defeat, lost a whole battery and a third
of his infantry.... Your affectionate son, J. C. W.
• {La demo1selle de Fontenable<1 1
FAMILIAR LETTERS lxxxv
'S Gravenhage.
Wednesday, June 29, 189:?.
Mv DEAR MoTHER,
Tomorrow (30th) is dear Meggy's birthday as you re•
minded me in your Jetter. There wdl be fresh flowers on her
grave and fresh remembrances of her in all our hearts. You
would be glad to hear that I had such a good passage. We do
not go to Amsterdam after all until tomorrow (30th) [after all]:
i,,o perhaps I may find a letter from you there. We shall take
Haarlem-the tulip place-on the way, principally to look at
some pictures. Of course the tulips have Jong been over. I shall
be thinking of you and dear Meggy. Mr. Shadwell is as pleasant
a travelling companion as can be imagmed. The hotel is a very
nice one indeed-a sort of picturesquenesc; and · magnificence
about 1t. It is lighted throughout, bedrooms and all, with
electric light. The I Iague is a beautiful place with its canals
J.lld parks We have been to Delft from here, where the famous
pottery used to be made. Yery httle made there now. We have
also been to the famous Dutch watering place called Scheven•
ingen, near here. To it and in many other directions there are
trams, steam, electric and horse power. Everything in Holland
seems as neat and clean and polished as possibly can be. With
bei,,t love to both, yr. affectionate son,
]. C. W.
11
Hawthorn Cottag~
West Malvern.
August 29, 1892.
Mv DEAR MoTHJ:R, •
I wonder "hether you have seen the sad news from
~w1tzerland in the paper. I first saw a paper m which it was
reported that Professor H. NettJeship had died from cold and
exposure on the Alps, he and his guides being overtaken by bad
weather as he was going up Mont Blanc and losmg their way
1n the snow storms. It would have been a terrible thing as he
was just going away from Oxford for a term to be with his son
who is to commence a musical education in Berlin in the autumn,
lxxxvi F AMILi AR LETTERS
However the Pall Mall Gasette said that it was R. L. Nettleship,
the unmarried brother at Balhol. This I expect is the true
version for he usually went to Switzerland in the summer.
I have also a letter from Bodmgton th1s morning who speaks
of R. L. Nettleship and says he met him last year in Switzerland
with his t,vo guides and that he seemed to be undertaking then
expeditions which were rather beyond his strength. You will
remember that he hved with h1s mother an invalid almost
entirely confined to her bed, to wlu>m he showed every attention.
No doubt when he "ent away some of the family would come
and stay with her, probably the wife and children of her painter
son, so she would not be alone. It \\lll be a most terrible blow
to the poor old lady.... The loss "dl be much felt at Balbol.
He was Green's successor and their prmcipal philosophic tutor
there. . . . The men "ere very much attached to him for he
had a certam nobleness of character. One of his most intimate
friends was Mr. Warde Fowler of Lmcoln College, the man who
is such a good musician and slightly deaf. He will be much
missed m the University too He was certamly one of our very
best men. He was so gifted and could write and speak so well.
He was a brilliant scholar and I thmk one of our ablest n1en
m philosophy.
12
Oriel College
Wednesday.
p 18921
Mv or:AR l\loTHl!.R,
... I am to stay m and take care of myself I thought
however I would send you a letter by tram as I can't come
myself. I haven't eaten or drunk anything apparently to upset
me. Perhaps I have been thinkmg too much I am nearly all
right again. I wanted to tell you that I asked the doctor to
visit you a httle often er, because I thought it prevented you
from getting too nervous m the intervals. He wrote in his reply
an encouraging account of you. Although you have felt so
depressed the action of the heart is steadier and also the other
matter which teases you seems to present no disquieting symp·
toms at all. I am so glad and so grateful. I expect you are
F AHILIAR LETTERS Jxxxvii
depressed by this uncommon bad weather like everybody but
more in proportion as you are so poorly. I have explained to
the Cook about the brawn. He quite understands what you
mean and will be glad to prepare it. Shall I let him do some
for Saturday? To dinner tomorrow we have Mr. Heberden of
Brasenose and sister, Mr. Warde Fowler of Lincoln College,
Mr. and Mrs. Madan, Bodleian Library, Mr. and Mrs. Warner
for whom the party 1s given, MISS Wordsworth, Principal of
Lady Margaret Hall and two others whose names I forget.
With best love, yr: affectionate son,
J.C. W.
The Clarendon Press present to me has come at last. 3 folio
volumes, handsomely bound in half-morocco. You perhaps
remember they gave it me for crit1ci&mg a book for them.
13
[posterior to Nov. 1900.]
When you say you occupy the • common mathematical posi•
tion about the relation of the geometrical diagram to geometrical
thought ' I have a remark to offer which I thmk may interest
you and make you thmk twice about the meaning and value of
the common mathematical position . . . when we mean real
mathematical thought I should say it was pretty fatal to disagree
with the common mathematical position But the 'position of
a mathematician ' on a given question 1s not necessarily • a
mathematical position ' ; he may not be Judging qua mathemU,
nor usmg his mathematical faculty at all, though mathematical
matter m.r1y be mvolvcd. For mstance, he may conduct a process
quite nghtly m mathematics; but there ts a certain reflection
on the process, philosophical, logical, whatever you like, which
1s certainly not mathematical, but the exercise of a totally
different faculty. And it is a great mistake of a man to suppose
that because he is (humanly speaking) mfalltble in the one
process (math0 ' ) he is equally successful m the other. Thus,
e.g., there are people with a perfect knack of doing certain
physical things, but either utterly unable to say how they do
them, or, if trusting to their perfect practice they imagine they
must have the right theory of them, give [sic] a most incorrect
account.
lxxxviii FAMILIAR LETTE~S
We graduate our vocal apparatus with marvellous accuracy
when we smg a melody, but this power does not help us in the
least to say how we do it. That belongs to the physiologist and
psychologist, so far as anything is known of it,
Suppose a gemus among vocalists-a Patti or a Reeves-
presumed to dictate on the question of how it was done, the
scientific investigator of the larynx &c. wouldn't trouble himself
much about that. He would admit that a musical ear was
necessary to conduct the investigation and concede readily that
the great singer or mus1c1an had a better musical ear than
himself, but he couldn't affect, even for courtesy's sake, to
pretend to care about their op1mon on his subject. The' common
position' of musicians would be authoritative to him upon
a. really musical question, but he would be foolish to defer to
their common pos1t10n on the phys1ological question, if they
had one. One can imagmc how Plato might have worked out
the point in a dialogue
Now there is the same kmd of difference between conducting
a math1 process and nfl,ecting (in certain ways) upon the method
and presuppos1t1ons of the math1 process and faculty. A man
may conduct other processes of reasoning too, not mathematical,
and fail utterly m the analysis of what he is doing.
For centuries mathemat1c1ans were content with the view
that geometry had axioms, def111 &c, for its principles and given
premisses, and got the rest by sytlog1sm, a view originated, as
far as records go, by Ar1stotlc In which they shewed they
didn't understand processes which they conducted so rightly
that 1t seems a paradox to say they didn't understand them.
Of course they understood them in one way but not in another.
The common mathematical position here was wrong and it was
reserved for Kant, both a real mathematician and a philosopher,
to free our minds from this illusion.
Now emphatically the question of the use of the figure in
relation to geometrical thought belongs not at all to the sphere
of mathematicians as such. One must know a certam amount
of Geometry to be able to handle the question, just as a man
must have some musical ear to study the larynx &c in relation
to sound, but that is not enough nor even to be a very accom•
plished geometrician. The common mathematical position in
FAMILIAR LETTERS lxxxix
t/zis-quption must be carefully distinguished from [the] common
mathematical position, when mathematical is used in it~ true
sense : it is really a position or attitude of mathematicians, but
it is not a mathematical position : and therefore, while I abso-
lutely defer to the (common) mathematical positmn, I haven't
the slightest respect for the common position of mathematicians
10 this question. As they were wrong 10 a body about the
syllogism, so the maJority (I suspect) are wrong in the modern
question and indeed the error 1s a consequence of the older one.
So if all the mathematicians took off their coats to me (to parody
Plato) I shouldn't run away.
There is however a natural reason wJ1y mathematicians should
have been misled so far as to thmk this a part of their own
subject and therefore one on which they arc particularly com•
petent to pronounce The speculations, which produced hyper•
bolical and elliptical geometry and the theory of (3 +n)•
dimensional space, seem math 1 and purely mathematical, but
they are not. They mvolve mathematics together with phdo•
sophical or metaphysical reflection on mathematical processes :
for they arc only possible by a theory (and a false one) of the
use of the figure in ordinary Geometry. The mathematician is
thus unconsciously conducting processes \\ luch belong to that
reflection which I have characterised as not an exercise of the
mathematical faculty at all and he, supposing that be is but
acting as a mathematician, 1s proportionately confident and of ten
contemptuous of phdosopluc questioning and doubt. The mathe·
mat1cal investigations here can only be called ' geometrical ', or
relating to some thinkable 'space', through a nustaken theory
of the position of the figure in ordmary geometrical (or Euchdean)
reasoning: a theory wlurh is not a mistake in mathematics but
a mistake in the phJlosophy of mathematics ; but, through the
unfortunate confusio11 of the two processes and faculties m the
same subject, it is presented as a necessary development of
mathematics and therefore 1s bound up mistakenly with the
honour of mathematics as such. We therefore who study
philosophy and presume to form an opinion on what is a phdo·
sophic and not a mathematical problem are put in a false
position .•.• Fortunately I can claim to be what perhaps no
living mathematician can claim, one of the inventors of hyper•
XC FAMILIAR LETTERS
bohc geometry. For I discovered the main features and theorems
of the subject for myself years ago before I knew that mathe-
maticians had done it already and I cannot therefore be treated
exactly as an outsider.
As I have said the people who invented the new Geometry
were mixmg geometrical and philosophic thinking, invading
a sphere of which they knew next to nothmg-unconsciously-
and they she" themselves extraordmanly incompetent in it.
I refer especially to the Pohsh geometricians who started it, who
talked the greatest nonsense when (necessarily) touching on the
metaphysical question which seemed to them mathematical.
These good people take an authoritative tone to such as myself
as if we "ere mterfermg "1th their proper province ; whereas
it is they who have made mroads mto ours and while they
thmk that \\e raw and untrained ones are presuming to judge
in their subject : 1t is they who raw and untrained are presummg
to judge m ours I recall an amusing instance. A man {now
dead) considered one of the greatest hvmg authont1es on hyper-
bolic geometry, with a great assumption of superiority, brought
agamst me m a debate (London Mathematical Society) as
a crushing obJection that to every theorem in the supersensible
geometry corresponded one in the Euclidean ( I knew the
commonplace argument) and gravely argued (as 1s customary)
that this was a strong proof of the validity of hyperbohc geo•
metry 1 The pnnc1plc involved m the argument ts such <1. ridi-
culous fallacy and so easdy seen to be so by anybody accustomed
to ordinary logic that I hardly knew how to preserve the outward
appearance of good behaviour And to have this infanttle non·
sense gravely and authoritatively put before one as an important
piece of instruction. There 1s nothmg so irritating as when
a man who 1s really a great authority m his own subject pro·
nounces on another of which he hardly knows the elements-
not indeed from conceit but simply because, through a confusion,
he thinks it within his own.
1
Infr.i., I 3.20
FAMILIAR LETTERS xci
14
Fyfi.eld Road
I2
Oxford.
22 Sept. 1901.
Since IV.Tote to you I have been to Glasgow as representative
of the Oxford Philological Society-of whJch I am this year
President-and I saw some very distinguished people, among
them Lord Kelvin. I was mterested to notice that his face
confirmed my Jmpress1on of him as a man devoted in the most
smglehearted way to his subject, mathematical physics, and
utterly unable to see beyond it. It is amusmg to see how the
matha• bow down to him and attend seriously to the extra-
ordinarily naive utterances he dehvers on the philosophical side
of his subject. He seems to me a mere child m such matters.
Have you noticed the worship of the ' mighty atom ' in the
British Assoc•. Rucker (I suppose 1t ts the same man) delivered
once a lecture m Oxford on ' Action at a distance '. It was
mdescr1bably funny-such elementary ignorance about the
nature of the quec;t10n he was dealmg with One could have
reduced him to the most artless contradictions (w1thm his own
lmuts) and I was strongly moved to do so but hadn't quite the
courage. It was some years ago. If it happened agam I think
I skould have the courage now I was glad also to see and
speak to Professor J. B. Mayor of Cambridge, who is one of the
most learned and accurate men of his generation and I think
one of the most honest.
So from the end of June till now I have worked at the Greek
tacticians hke-the best bishop-you know what I mean. . . .
I wanted to get my work into <the) shape of a treatise before
the vac• is out I daresay I shan't do that especially as the
continuous application JS begmnmg to take it out of me. But
I hope certainly to publish my results rec1.sonably soon. The
thing was really too tempting to neglect. I hope my friends
won't despair of me when they hear that the promised i,ray(l)y,j
is not ready for I think scholars will think the work I turned
aside for worth domg.... I haven't published my address 1 on
the nature of one's conviction of the existence of God: and
I have generally thought it best not to lend the MS. because
1 Infra., H 505-8:z,
xcii F AMILi AR LETTERS
it is not adequate to what I actually said. It 's too much of
the nature of notes for an address. If you are very anxious to
see it however perhaps I had better let you have it-that is
when you have really time to read it-you would be more
sympathetic than a stranger and perhaps know what I was
driving at even when only indicated. But then I am afraid it
would be necessary for me to make additions to the last part
or even rewrite 1t to make 1t clear, for being pressed much for
time I couldn't write out at all properly the very end of it but
that didn't matter for my address, for it "'as the most important
thing I had to say and I was m no danger of forgetting it. But
I haven't seen it for a long time and I don't know how much
I should have to do at it. If it was fairly much I could with
the present preoccupation of my ' pint of brams ' (would it were
at least a quart I) hardly put myself back in the right position
just now at least. As a matter of fact I should bke you to see
the argument (though I should mfimtely prefer that you had
heard it-' the letter kdleth ') and so later on I shall sec if
r couldn't make the l.ittcr part fairly intclhgible to a reader.
I trust everything 1s prospermg with you. I am very glad to
say that the place I was at in Yorkslure (Ravenscar) suited my
wife better than most places we've tried. For which I am very
thankful. •.. We were counting up to-day the number of
eminent specialists she has been to and found them nine at least.
But I am beginnmg to hope that she really will get much better.
She can tricycle a httlc, rt suits her better than walking.
With kind regards, yours truly.
15
si Edward'~
Islip, Oxon.
t May 1902.
It 1s perfectly splendid. I can't tell you how glad I am.
Your cup of happiness is getting pretty full and I congratulate
you with all my heart. I wish I had a daughter myself, I should
have adored her : and 1t 's a blessing to a boy to have a sister.
My own sister whom I lost when she was 30 was the light and
blessing of our household. She was sweet and adorable beyond
words.
FAMILIAR LETTERS xciii
My mother says it is so nice to have a little girl first and
I am to tell you that. But I expect these things are relative.,
that most mothers prefer a son, if the idea of preference is
allowable, and most fathers (apart from the artificial prejudice
in favour of a son and heir to maintain the family succession)
prefer a daughter.
I always thought it so touching that Victor Hugo should
present his bttle grand daughter with the words 'c'est ma petite
grand'fille que j'adore '. I can so enter mto his feelings ...•
How very good of you to write to me at once about your
good fortune. I am afraid, by the by, that you will have been
pursued by a letter from me about defaulting Cyc-hsts. I didn't
know you were off. To-day (Friday) I am in lsLIP and sleep
also, as my mother's condition has begun to give cause for
anxiety. With very kind regards to you both and hearty good
wishes.
Yours truly.
I'll tell you about my interview with old Poste when I sec
you. He was calm and cheerful. Did I tell you I tried diameter
myself at first as ao8Eia-a ypaµ.µ.~. Thanks for date of Butcher's
solution Bywater with whom I spenl yesterday evening is
rather epns of my solution and wants it published 1
16
Recluse Lodge
Freshwater, I.W.
8 Aug. 1902.
We are truly sorry to hear that you have lost that noble dog 2
It h, well that he did not have a longer 11lncss-poor fellow....
I do trust the httle daughter is getting on better and that you
have no anxiety about her. I didn't deduct anything from the
account you sent for I do not know what the ' At Home ' cost.
We can settle that next term. We are resting here, only my
friend is very fond of discussions and, as he is an invalid and
doesn't often get such a chance, I have to humour him. But
it is tiring sometimes and I shall try to keep the thing within
1 Plato, .lleno, S6 F, f, of Plulolog,•, XX\'ui, pp 222--40 (1903)
• llafe Bernard, one of the noble<it of a. noble breed. Buried, by kind
pernw1s1on of His Grace the Duke of Bedford, on his estate at Aspley Guise.
xctv FAMILIAR LETTERS
limits. You will miss Rafe sadly, but it is well that the little
daughter had arrived and with her and with music and gardening
(which I think delightful) you and Mrs. - - should have
a pleasant summer. I have brought here my Vergil and my
In Memoriam with Bradley's commentary, which I shall greatly
enjoy. I had already read some of it. The weather has been
deplorable but our friends are charming. My friend's daughter
is a good musician and plays the 'cello wdl. I may confess
I never felt so old, but I trust the feeling will pass--it is
depressing. With very kind regards from us to you both,
yours truly.
17
To BERNARD BosANQUET.
22 June 1903 .
. . . The reason I did not publish '\\ as that tho' Boole is the
fountam there- has been a good deal of development of the thing
m Germany and I thought one must attack the thing as a whole.
Consequently I got Schroder's book- a frightful tlung to tackle
and there I stuck because I was obliged at the time to turn to
something else and I have never had the time since to read
Schroder. I contented myself with giving a public lecture 1 in
which I endeavoured to show. (1) that merely as a calculus it
went on a wrong principle, not recognizing that a symbolic
calculus must be developed from the particular matter it relates
to i (whereas 2) they are forcing the matter into algebraic
symbolism, as 1f the latter were the only possible ; (2) I shewed
that as a cakulus it was involved m a contradiction which
mathematicians as such must admit to be such-violating the
principle of algebraic calculus as such ; (3) I shewed this latter
not merely verbal or formal, but that by it the identity of the
extension of any class could be proved with that of any other,
e.g. if A and B are class symbols, as they are, then the equation
A=B can be established K•hatei,er A and B represent; (4) I
pointed out some minor fallacies ; (5) taking the calculus on 1ts
own merits (as (intended) to solve certain kinds of problems)
I can verify my first point, about fitting the form and the
matter, by producing a calculus of my own of exceedingly simple
1
See ff 371-400 1 ' when ', original
FAMILIAR LETTERS XCV
18
Fyfield Road,
I2
Oxford
30 June 1903.
I do hope you are better of that touch of sun. For your very
kmd letter very many thanks. I was so glad to hear the field
day on Monday was such a success. By a happy chance the
problem was the same that the Colonel himself set upon Satur-
day : so our men would have the advantage of that day's
experience on the same ground and with same obJect. I con·
gratulate you also on managmg so well with the faithful few.
Kindly remember me to all who care for the message and you
may go down as low as beutenants for the sake of B--.
Mrs. C. W. is engaged m the arduous toil of getting me into
the right clothes to see the Major 1 married this morning. Wir
smd beide sonst etwas medergedruckt.
19
Kurhotel-Schbnwald.
Schonwald be1 Triberg, Baden.
29 July 1903.
I cannot remember whether I wrote to you or not, but give
you the benefit of the doubt. This place 1s really capital and
I could recommend it if I were sure the rainy weather we have
been having was exceptional and not normal. The hotel is
quiet, comfortable and quite moderate in charges. Actual
1 Now the Right Rev the Lord Bishop of St Albans
g2
C FAMILIAR LETTERS
locality not striking, but good centre and fine views within
about a mile. Between two centres of the clock industry,
Furtwangen and Tr1berg. Tr1berg is very fine in its scenery.
It doesn't suit my wife as well as I could wish. She misses the
tricycle very much, as I feared she would. I hired her a bath
chair from Fre1burg, which has extended her radius a good deal.
Yesterday I pushed her up a road with frightful gradient (45°
as Dodgson might say) in a pelting storm of rain {which over-
took us) for a frightful way. Thought I should be stiff all over
this morning but am not stiff at all.
20
Hannover.
Sat. 29 Aug. [1903].
. . . I do hope you are better Perhaps what you want is
a fortnight {say) of mere physical exercise and enjoyment of
open air, carefully avoiding any ph1losoph1cal or Academic work.
I believe this absolute laying aside of work is often imperative
m such a condition as you seem to be (m). It 's difficult, I dare-
say, but 1t pays We wmd up our holtday to-night by going
to Fidelio and expect a great treat We start home to-morrow.
We wonder what the surprise 1s and hope it may be that you
and Mrs. - - are coming to hve m or near Oxford. Kmd
regards from us to both.
21
Oxford.
7 Sept. 1903.
We have just been having a hohtary tea m our little garden
which looks perfectly lovely. Oxford 1s now m the throes of
St. Giles' Fair My wife was noticing the other day how
many suicides there are m the papers. For myself I am suffering
from such acute nervous depression that I might think it
alarming if I had not had it before now. We spent our last
fortnight m Hannover : it 's a place which always has a most
dismal effect on me (tho' such a beautiful town) .... I suspect
the strange weather has helped, it was simply stifling at first
jn Oxford I have got what I suppose to be the male equivalent
for hystena-somet1mes badly. It makes me understand the
FAMILIAR LETTERS ci
queer things that sane people sometimes surprise one with, for
I expect they get into this extraordinary nervous phase. I may
however myself count on being preserved from them, because
I am conscious of the situation. It helps me also to understand
hysteria in general. I am doubtful sometimes whether there is
anything properly insane about it ; whether 1t 1s not that one
feels and realises things clearly and acutely, for instance, one's
utter powerlessness and insignificance, also the loss and absence
of friends and relatives,-too clearly for one's proper balance
which is cond1t1oned by a certain callousness But when it's
pretty bad I do thmk it 1s something hke a conscious msamty.
The feeling is, I thmk, the mental analogue of the misery {even
agony) of sea-sickness. It's worse than any mere physical
illness and the effect of 1t I dread is mabihty to do any real
thmkmg or reading. . . . I even seem to dread tlus mechanical
work coming to an end, when I must face real work. As
a matter of fact I have now-being the next thing promised-
to wnte out my article on the points you wot of m the trireme,
not a great mental task, the material all ready in the shape of
notes, but I shrmk from it. Also I have to keep up my study
of Dedekind and Cantor, which I broke Wl'll during my stay m
the Schwarzwald (that was splendid) but scarcely was able to
touch m Hannover ...
My wife has been also very depressed m Oxford (of course
I can't confide my real cond1t1on to her ...) ...
22
Oxford.
17 Sept. 1903 .
. . . I am glad to say I am distinctly better. I feel the worst
is over and I am able to do some work.... One feels so much
coming back to Oxford and not being able to go and recount
one's experiences of travel to one's parents It 's my tirst
summer without one of them and till last Easter 1 I had both
of them My wife feels our loneliness in this respect very much,
tho' of course 1t doesn't concern her anything like so nearly....
1 [vu:. Easter IQO:Z]
cii FAMILIAR LETTERS
23
[June 1905]
I wish you had been at my paper on Friday or that I had
been at your Inspection.... Fortunately I. B. was there him-
self. He was much pleased with my paper and said he (had)
never seen the point put properly before. We made a night of
it together after in the Randolph.... It wouldn't do for them
of Ascalon to know the rifts m the philosophic lute and don't
repeat to the philosophers either
24
12 Fyfield Road,
Oxford.
I I May 1904.
l trust that you have had a refreshing Easter holiday, and
are now able to devote yourself to your studies agam I want
to report progress on some of the subjects on which we have
corresponded. I am always moved by what Locke calls ' the
most pressing uneasiness ' and have had to deviate more than
once from my study of Dedekind. However, one of my devia-
tions has brought me to it again m, I hope, a useful way.
The ' Greek M us1c ' earned me off first, for the tlung seemed
to work out so well and to be confirmed by further examination
of ancient classical and post-classical authorities. I read a paper
on it here which was attended by the Provost of Oriel and the
Principal of Brasenose · and was greatly confirmed by the
result. I told the Provost beforehand the new passage in
Aristotle. I understand he came thinking he could dispose of
it, though how he could I can't imagine, as it certainly is obviously
fatal to his own view. However, I revised all the classical
evidence, without the Aristotle, and I think satisfied my audience
that the modes differed both in interval and pitch. I then
showed that the Aristotelian passage confirmed this, and from
it alone one could get the kmd of theory I advocated. Monro
hardly made a crit1C1sm. Heberden thinks he realized the
Aristotelian passage couldn't be got over, and indeed I had led
up to 1t by showing that there were other important passages
which couldn't be got over and had been misinterpreted by the
Provost and others. It was a feature of my theory that one
FAMILIAR LETTERS ciii
recovered a quite simple and natural interpretation of such
places. I was told afterwards, that the Provost had been
greatly impressed. Well I started to get this ready for the
press, when I read an article upon Eth. I. vi, in connection
with the Idea Number theory by one R. G. Bury in the February
Classical Review, which turned out a still more pressing uneasi-
ness for it gave me a great opportunity of saying something on
the d.rruµ.PA.f/T'O& ,lp,6µ.ol, upon the Idea-Number theory, and on
Plato's philosophy of Mathematics-things (some of them) which
I have given in lectures I had by me for years, but had no
occasion to publish. The article in question showed that there
was really need to say something. So after patenting the
'Music' by a short abstract of my paper in the Classical Review
(it will appear either in May or June) I gave myself to the new
work This took up a good part of my energies in the Easter
Vacation. I have written and indeed printed, for the proofs
are finally corrected, a long article entitled auvp.f3>..f/T'O& a.p,8µ.of.
for the Class. Review. This will probably, or a first instalment
of it, appear m the June Class. Review. I used the opportunity
to give two ' Pubhc Lectures ' m Oxford on the subject, and
am glad to know that I gamed the adherence to my views on
the Platomc and Aristotchan questions involved (mamly in
Aristotle, Metaphysics, Plato, Republic; lhavoia, et id genus omne)
of the kmd of people here one wishes to convince. The reason
why I may suppose this to interest you at all is that d.rrvµ.~. ap.
led me to give a deliverance on Dedekind which I have put
in a foot-note. It relates not to the book 'Was sind und
was sollen die Zahlen ' but to ' Stetigkeit und die irrationale
Zahlen '. I am clear now that the attempt to introduce con-
tinuity into ' number ' itself comes from a fairly ghastly mistake
as to the meaning of ' the number two ', ' the number three '
etc. etc. that I am sure about, but I think that I have made
it very probable that it was from a very accurate understanding
of what these expressions do mean, that Plato or a Platonist
got the conception of d.rr11µ.fiA.11T'ot ap,6µ.ol, This I have put
forward in my article, and have chaffed the modern metaphysico-
mathematician for a mare's nest constructed from fallacies the
Platonist saw through long ago. I have through the comparison
of ' parallel versions ' in the Metaphysics shown, I think, that
civ FAMILIAR LETTERS
one writer in the Metaphysics particularly wished to dissociate
Plato's name from the later' Idea-Number' theory. This same
writer does associate Plato with the o.rrvfJ,~"'1/To, aµ,8µ.ol, and it'
is one of my points that it arises out of the earlier Platonism
and has nothing to do with the later Idea-Number theory as
such. I have also given an explanation of the Ta ,,.ua'6 for
Mathematics, which I dare bet you will approve, and I think
I have shown 1t a great mistake of interpretation to think any
such doctrine m the Republic. This I thmk inter alia disposes
of some of the great nonsense H. Jackson talks about Plato,
but I had no occasion to name him, as the essentials of the view
I traverse are a mistake at least as old as Ueberweg.
I will send you a 'deprmt' of the whole thmg when I get
some. I might have got on to my • music ' m the vacation but
was interrupted by two claims on me. Lady Welby insisted on
my g1vmg a set opinion on her book, and I had to read it nearly
through I knew already enough of it to sec 1t wouldn't do,
despite her cleverness, and would gladly have declined the task
but she wouldn't let me off. I broke the result gently to her
and had a very charming reply. Agam a friend bringing out
a rather good analysis of the Ethics for pass men {the pass
part) submitted 1t to me and I spent a good shce of my time
in writing and argufymg about that. So you see I haven't been
able to help myself (' bin wirkhch sehr unschuldig ', what you
once kmdly quoted) One absolutely can't avoid these thmgs,
and 1t ts only now that I am gomg to begin to get the Greek
Modes ready for press Fortunately now it is simply a matter
of straightforward work and can be got through almost mechani-
cally. I don't thmk I can mterlard Dedekmd with 1t (much
as I wish) because I have got with help of notes of pupils to
rewrite my commentary on the Posterior Analytics (delivered
about one and a half years ago) as some of the tutors are good
enough to desire very much that this should be done, and I must
use these notes while I can keep them. Meanwhile I itch to go
for the other Dedekind books, I really believe I can do for 1t,
but I know I must get the ' music ' out of the way first. I saw
with mterest your review of Moore's Ethics m ' Mind '. As
I haven't read Moore and am httle hkely to, I have no right
to opmion but you seemed to me to say Just the nght thing,
FAMILIAR LETTERS CV
and what is perhaps a good deal harder to do, just in the right
way. I asked a very capable Oxford tutor if he had seen it
and what he thought of it, and I found he was very pleased
with it and thought it remarkable that you could manage it at
all, considering the amount of your lecturing work.
I have not been afraid of writing about my own work, not
only because I know you are so sympathetic, but because I want
you to understand I have not let go the investigation which
you think [it] rather a duty for me, though I haven't been able
to give it first attention, and also by explaining what has
hindered me, to show that I was really justified in leaving it
for a time.
You yourself have no need I expect for any such ' apologia',
you manage to go straight forward and finish off important
pieces of work.
I do trust you are all right and vigorous. For my own part
I seldom had such a good Easter vacation.
I was at a lovely Sussex village standing on the Downs four
miles from Arundel and within easy ride of a very dear friend,
an old Oriel pupil, a most interesting young artist with such
splendid ideals. He lives on other side of Downs near Amberley
at a place called Bury-if you happen to know the neighbour-
hood. My friend's name 1s Wethered. Ile has now a picture
m the New Gallery-if you go tell me what you think of 1t,
I haven't seen 1t. Some of his work 1s very successful (I think)
and certamly 1s all very imaginative--some of 1t I don't like,
but he's uncompromising and sticks to his prmc1ples. He 's gone
on landscape but can draw figures wonderfully. He made
a pastel of me, which I think 1s very fine vigorous drawing,
and the critics here agree. There 's a good show of portraits
from the Colleges here now. You may see an account of it m
the Burlington Magazine by Blakaston.
cvi FAMnIAR LETTERS
25 22 May 1904.
12 Fyfield Road,
Oxford.
(1} o.rruµ.{JJ1.11ror means 'not add1ble' as is abundantly proved
by Aristotle's d1scuss1on in the Metaphysics. I suspect you
were thinking of o.rrvp.p.Erpor.
(ii) You say on the universal of number ' It is clear ... that
twoness cannot be added to twoness and make fourness ; but
twoness must involve some sort of structural relation to fourness,
I should have thought '
I don't follow the ' but'. What it introduces 1s no objection
whatever to what precedes it. Don't you rather mean that you
are accustomed (or perhaps we are all when not reflecting) to
think of the structural relation of two to four as the construc-
tion of Four by the addition of two Twos, and that as this
clearly wont do (for you agree I have shown that) since by Four
the number Four 1s meant, a new question arises What is the
structural relation of Two to Four, if any ? How ought their
relation to be represented ? What 1s there m the relation in
virtue of which three comes m the serial order between two and
four ? If I have got the real meamng of your difficulty clear,
I think the answer 1s also clear.
I have pomted out that the proposition ' two and two make
four ' means that any particular two added to any particular
two makes a particular four, or two particulars added to two
make four particulars. Two means always two of, twoness 1s
twoness of (cf. Aristotle's defimtion of o.pLfJfJ,or as 1rAijfJor
µEµup71µl1 1ov-which 1s very suggestive, as all his say10gs about
number and magnitude are).
Now that any particular two added to another makes a par-
ticular four hes m the nature of Twoness and Fourness. This
seems to me the simple answer to the question about structural
relation I imagine proposed. You may say that if one group
of elements has twoness and the other also twoness, they con-
stitute a group which has fourness, but I think the more natural
language the best. So agam as to the serial order :-The serial
order 2, 31 4, corresponds simply to the fact that the nature of
Twoness and Threeness and Fourness 1s such that a particular
FAMILIAR LETTERS cvii
three consists of a particular two with a particular one added
to it, and that to get a particular four another particular one
must be added to the particular three.
Thus it takes two steps of the same kind to produce a four
by addition to a two, only one such step to produce a three by
addition to a two and only one such to produce a four by addition
to a three. These productions accordingly form a series : and
in the serial order the production of the particular three comes
'between '-in the sense explained-the production of the
particular four and the two (or the product10n of the two).
This is the simple meaning of the order of ' the series of
natural numbers '. The order 2, 3, 4 does not mean that the
numbers 3 and 4 arc formed successively (one before the other)
by the addition of the number one (=oneness) to the number
2( = twoness), and of the number one again to the number 3,
which is mere nonsense, but that a particular three and a par-
ticular four are produced successively by the addition of a
particular one to a particular two and the addition to them
again of a particular one.
May one not compress the principle which explains all these
things into this statement?-' Just as squareness has not got
four equal sides etc. but is the having of four equal sides, so
twoness is not made up of two umts, but means the being made
up of two umts.' I think the key to all the fallacies and con-
fusion can be got from this.
By the way, you would, I suppose, agree with my criticism
of Dedekind, for his theory of Continuity depends precisely on
the fallacy that the number four 1s a magniJude differing from
the number three as another magnitude by one unit.
(ui) As to BLavoLa-1 mtended to write but think it best to
take one thmg at a time, so will put off till I hear from you
about the above. I will only say that I feel pretty sure that
when you have reconsidered what I have said with Plato's text
before you at leisure you will agree with me I can't pretend
that I think there can be really two opinions. The objection
you make seems so directly dealt with in what I submitted to
you that I think it might be merely enough to ask you to look
at my argument agam when I can send you a deprint.
I am sorry you didn't agree at once (the criticism I should
cviii FAMILIAR LETTERS
have rather expected was that it was not at all new to you)
but am not exactly surprised : for my· experience has shown
me that it 1s often more difficult to convmce acute people about
something very simple than on a difficult pomt, especially when
they have got biased by some current view. You quote our
friend Stout as apparently agreeing with you in doubting my
interpretation. I might also quote my Oxford audience 1£ we
are to count heads (as' heads'), Some of them, of co\:lrse, have
given very special attention to the question, and I felt sure they
were (some of them) in favour of some such interpretation as
Ueberweg's. There was a moment when I saw I had captured
them-one notices these things m an attentive audience-and
it was when I challenged any one to say whether they could
make anything of aui,-..ETp05' avT~ and TfTpO:ywvov aw~assigned
m the most defimte way by Plato as the object of lluivo10-
except the ll1'a1 of these geometrical elements.
And I saw also the pomt fully taken and appreciated that
the origin of the fallacious mterprctatlon was the confusion of
lluivo,a '\\Ith the faculty of mathematical mvestlgat10n-whereas
p.a871p.a.Tuc~ hke a,aAo:nK~ wac:; a process 'outside' the four
farultu.•s I found out after people were convinced.
I will only ask you for the moment to try a method which
I find it useful to fall back upon when I can't make headway
with what I beheve the simple, obvious, and necessary meaning
of a passage in Plato or Aristotle.
I ask those who, I believe, are mamtammg an unnatural and
artificial view to try the experiment of puttmg what they believe
the meanmg of the text into the Greek wluch they think would
best and most clearly convey it. The comparison of the result
with the text tells its own story , and 1t becomes evident that
Plato, humanly speaking, couldn't possibly express himself as
he has done if he had mtended what was attributed to him-
especially when as m the present case the expression he actually
uses would convey naturally the very opposite of the supposed
meaning.
I pointed it out in my lecture that when we satisfied ourselves
of the absolutely necessary meaning of Plato's making the objects
of a,&vo,a the ' originals of which the phenomena arc copies ' and
the awcl TtTpdywvo11 etc., that point of mterpretat1on was irre•
fragably fixed and we must not mind what difficulties PJato got
F A'MILIAR LETTERS cix
himself into afterwards by his distinction e.g. of a,,h,o,a and
voiis, It would be a great mistake to alter the necessary
meanmg of the Greek because of any such considerations-the
confusion if any would be Plato's look-out. But I contended,
and satisfied people, there was no such confusion and Plato said
something perfectly intelligible
The fact is the distinction Plato makes between the• obJect
of a,&vota and voii~ 1s one which in essence appears within
mathematics, and no doubt was suggested to him by mathe-
matics 1t is simple and not difficult and nobody really following
the text and undcrstandmg the thing 10 question in mathe-
matics, and not confused by the Aristotelian passage, could have
two minds about 1t.
I will explain this later and put the answer to your objection
again and more at large than in the printed article when I next
write, unless you prefer merely to wait and take another look
at the article.
Joachim has been givmg me an amusmg account of a debate
with Stout at St Andrews. From what he said I have a sus-
p1c1on I should have been m essentials with Stout Some things
Joachim said seemed right, but I can't help thmkmg that 1£ he
had put them properly they would be found m agreement with
Stout's view. But I may be qmte out of it.
Yours truly,
J. CooK WILSON.
PS. I hear Stout 1s not brmgmg his little boy when he comes
to Oxford, that seems rather mean.
26
13 November 1904.
Oxford
' An anxious mqu1rer ' this Sabbath mornmg who, though
a young student (a BA) and not an 'expert' in mathematics,
though he knows a decent modicum, 1s convmced of the non•
sensical character of the construction of space out of an aggregate
of points and has been attacking this effut1t1on as represented
by B. Russell (m a College Society), has brought back to my
mind a matter which I ought to have wntten to you about
long ago
You will remember my writmg to you about that (tn my
ex FAMILIAR LETTERS
opinion) rather foolish fallacy of B. Russell's about a class being
a member of itself. I showed by an artifice how the game
could be played with any class, and emphasised the fact that
it was a mere fallacy of language. You weren't altogether
happy, because you didn't, I think, altogether see what I was
driving at. But later I put the theory on what I must think
a sound basis 10 writ10g to Stout. There remained, however,
one difficulty 10 Stout's m10d 1 which roughly came to his
accepting a very fallacious verbal mistake of Russell's, in fact
that a class as many could be dist10guished from a class as one
and (ultimately) represented as a member of itself.
These things provoke me for, though they depend on fallacies
of mere language which I am obliged to think very childish,
they are insidious if people aren't accustomed to analyse forms
of expression-and so many, even logicians, are not I therefore
sat down to a determined effort to dnve the hobgoblin out of
Stout's mind, and took great pa10s to get all clear. Stout had
fought determinedly but this final effort conv10ced him abso-
lutely (that was long vacation 1903, I thmk) I should bke you
to know this in case you had thought there was anything in
the thmg · and 1t drives me wild that these mere muddles of
language which annoyed Plato and Anstotlc so much in the
petty and trivially clever debaters of their day, should reappear
at (all), after all philosophy has done, d.Od actually be mistaken
for somethmg the least worth having.
Russell's fallacy may be refuted m a hne or two, thus·-
A class 1s a unified manifold of elements A member of
a class is one of the elements so unified To say, then, that a
class is a member of itself is to say that a unified manifold of
elements is an element in the same unified manifold of elements.
(The peculiar way in which the members (elements) of a class
are unified doesn't matter, one only need use the part of the
conception which 1s sufficient to show the fallacy ) This being
so the fallacy can only be due to some verbal error and the
remainder of one's work 1s to show what the verbal error is,
which has made it seem plausible. I think I did that, but for
mere refutation('s) sake the above 1s enough.
Yours truly,
J. COOK WILSON.
FAMILIAR LETTERS cxi
'Zl
rTo a schoobnaster 1n reply to the words ' 1-rners generally find a difficulty
1n Tngonometry from the fact that a revolvtng hne only baa a BlgD 1n 4 definite
pos1tions and 1s regarded as having no sign 1n all other positions There
seems no way (1n elementary Tngonometry) out of this ddliculty except
co1111ent1011 ' ]
(? 10 Feb. 1905.J
(Such an answer would never do, for the following reasons :-)
Nothing in the way of truth can ever be settled by' convention',
though all the elementary books speak as if the use of + and
- for direction was, as you said, JUSt a convention. All con•
vention can do is to settle what symbols sha)) be used for a given
idea, we can mvent the symbol and ' agree ' (convention) to use
1t, we cannot mvent the idea. For instance we may have the
convention that + shall represent division That is absolutely
an convention can do. This as a general principle 1s quite
self-evident, but we can bring it to the reductio ad absurdum
test, in a particular mstance, easily. For instance, if we tell
the boy the use of + and - for two opposite directions is
arbitrary and a convention, he might reasonably say: 'Well,
1f + doesn't itself mean direction, what right have you to use
1t for d1rect1on ? It 1s a sign of a certam meaning or idea,
viz. addition, how can you make 1t the sign of another meaning
or idea without confusion ? Either you are usmg 1t as having
a different meaning from add1t1on or you are not. In the first
case, why on earth don't you use a different sign as the meaning
1s different? In the second case (i e. 1f you don't use it as
having a different meaning) you are obviously makmg a mis-
take.' And he might involve you in the reauctio ad absurdum
by saying ' Good I If 1t 1s mere convention, we might just as
well use the sign of multiplication for one direction and the sign
of d1vis1on for the opposite direction ( x and +) ' There could
be no answer to this upon the convention principle and you will
find at once, if you try and in the ordinary co-ordmate system
substitute x for + as a sign of direction and + for - , that
it won't work the least bit, but you will get quite ridiculous
results. Try it : I have. I am not saying what the true answer
is but only pointing out the futility of the convention answer,
which we all ahke have been taught.
cxii FAMILIAR LETTERS
May I add to the support of my imaginary schoolboy that,
after he says + must mean one thing or another, he might go
on to remark that he actually finds in trigonometrical examples
before htm + used in the same example both for sign of direc•
tion and sign of addition. Heaven save you for the present
from the imaginary boy I
Note agam that m co-ordmate geometry you may see no
difficulty in an equation hke y = mx + c. You will substitute
for y, as representing a co-ordinate, -b, say, and calculate the
-b-c
value - - for x as a co-ordinate. But what happens when
m
you have a product xy,. To begm with, this represents no
co-ordinate with direction at all, but a rectangle. How can it
hJ.ve a sign at all ? And suppose we give x the value -a, and
y the value -b · then xy = ( -a) ( -b). How can we say that
the two minus signs of direction can produce a plus sign. How
could they be multiplied " And are we to say that the resulting
+ sign (1f we take the algebraic rule) 1s a sign of direction?
(To consider now, so-called imaginary quantities). The mis-
take m people like De Morgan ts to suppose they have to look
for an •interpretation' of ✓-1, where it does not (or could not)
represent an 1mpossib1hty, misled by the analogy (not rightly
understood) of those problems which give - I (or some number
with - sign) simply m the answer and thus shew the question
of the problem has to be answered m the negative, while the
same - quantity m another reference would give a positive
answer and express a possibility. For instance, 1£ you ask what
will be a man's gain under certain condrttons and working the
equation find 1t == - 3£1 the simple meaning is that he gains
nothing at all and further that his failure to reach gain is
measured by 3£. If now you ask what he loses, you get the
answer 3£. The first answer shows it 1s impossible he should
gain and how far he falls : the second shows that he actually
loses and how much.
Now we want ✓ -=--i" explained, so far as it represents an
1mposs1bihty. Any interpretation.· of it as representing some-
thing possible and founded on a really different calculus and
symbolism 1s quite irrelevant and a false use of the loss analogy.
The true parallel is that the ✓ -=-i answer, hke the - 1 answer,
FAMILIAR LETTERS cxiii
gives a definite measure of the impossibility. In the profit
question, -3 shews, so to say, how far the transaction fails of
being possibly gain. The ✓--:::j_ answer shews also a measure
of how far the thing fails of possibihty. For in an instance (of)
it, a difference like a• -b1, which ought to be positive to give
possibility, and the magnitude of its negative value, 1.e. of the
value under the root m ✓a• - b1 = ✓ -c•
shews how far it is
off possibibty. In the case of a circle for instance 1t shews how
far a circle comes off reaching a given hne which 1t does not
reach, as can be easily seen from a figure. If r is the radius
and d the distance of the line from the centre, then the y
,a
co-ordinate of (the) point of intersection = ✓ -d2• And r• -d,1
gives the exact measure of the 1mposs1b1lity, when it is negative,
and accordingly gives a distmct1on between one circle and
another (e g. of same centre)-the very (definite) measure of the
1mposs1b1hty, varymg from one circle to another, actually seems
to define and detcrmme each circle. It 1s quite simple d bemg
constant, the value m question of the 'degree' (shall I say) of
the impossibility determmes the correspondmg value of r and
so the circle 1
28
[Oxford]
20 June, 1905.
You asked me what Bywater thought of my views on
Kd8apcr,,. 2 I have been to see him to-day with a result both
amusing and unexpected. As l anticipated he does not think
of giving up the ' purgation ' interpretation of the passage and
apparently does not dispute my analysis of the metaphor of
purgation so applied I should have thoiight that nothmg
remained but to admit Aristotle was wrong, and badly. But
Bywater seriously holds that Anstotle 1s right because this 1s
all that can be said to excuse tragic representation on the stage.
Plato was right, he says, it 1s wrong to have tragic representation
at all. From the point of view of the moralist and the politician
this titillation of the emotions ought not to be permitted (these
are Bywater's exact words), Plato's view bemg right, the only
possible excuse for performance at all is that given by Aristotle,
says Bywater, to let off, purge off these undesirable feelings.
• Cf t 116, p 268 • Seep lxx1, O P S, under 1905.
2 773 l h
cxiv FAMILIAR LETTERS
From further conversation, after this remarkable deliverance,
I gathered Bywater thought that tragedy only gratified (from
the ideal point of view) a morbid liking for seeing and hearing
horrors. ldeaJly it shouldn't be gratified at all (so Plato), but,
if at all, only by way of harmless outlet and purgation (Aristotle}.
I feel the wirked mirthfulness of the slave in Plautus (or is
it Terence?) who' mixed things'. I have driven some into bad
translations or fantastic creations quite away from anything in
the Poetics, or into that confusion of metaphors I prophesied,
and Bywater I have driven into the arms of Plato. He certainly
developed his adhesion to Plato's view of the drama after my
criticism for, when I first told him my difficulties, such a solution
had not occurred to him. I thmk I may leave the people who
disagree with me to deal with one another. I have got views
written down for me by various people and J. A. S. has ex·
pounded viva voce the positive side of his view (he agrees, you
know, with me on the negative side) to me lucidly and ener•
getlcally. I have not had time to study thoroughly the written
papers, I have been too unavoidably busy with other things:
but everything I have yet seen or heard, whether by itself, or
setting opposites against one another, confirms me in the view
I advocated m my paper and m my impression that there was
a deplorable confusion of ideas on the subject You said you
had heard some things which seemed to shake my position.
I wanted to ask you what they were but haven't had the chance.
Don't write, I'll wait till I see you.
N.B. Miss Gwyer, for whom I wrote the essay out of which
I developed my paper, is very properly delighted at the rumpus.
Yours
29
5 Granvdle Place,
Portman Sq.
w.
3 Jan 1906.
The Morals of Marcus makes a good play, 1£ well acted and
it was well acted. Carlotta was played wonderfully well by
Miss Carlisle. . . . I had read the novel but had forgotten even
that I had read it. Of course it came back to me as the piece
developed. If I had known, I hardly think I should have gone.
F AMILi AR LETTERS CXV
PS. I simply can't come to teas this term-at least not yet.
I am bothered about my lectures next term bacause 1t is exactly
the time when I ought to letture on a number of difficulties left
over in the Poster1.or Analytics and I am not ready. I have
continually yielded to the ' more pressing uneasiness ' and so
put it off. I can't risk advertismg 1t because 1t 1s quite possible
cxviii FAMILIAR LETTERS
I may not find time m the Easter vacation As I have to go
to Scotland for the degree on April 3d I may take my wife to
see Edinburgh and stay a short time with a friend in Glasgow,
who has sent a pressing invitation, and this doesn't look hke
time for woz'k. I am very unhappy about it, because the
Summer term is JUSt the one in which I ought to give this
lerture
32
[Oxford, ? June 06.]
. . . I am grateful both to you on whom far more. work
devolved than upon the men and to the men themselves who
certainly worked under great difficulties and drawbacks. 1 Well,
give them a jolly good dmner on my part on Monday and say
how much I wished I could be among them. They are stunning
chaps even if they haven't won....
He 1s perfectly and exceptionally capable of doing the work
but apparently has some sort of kmk in ]us mmd and just
' bucks ' as some of these clever people will. What a lot of
good it would do such creatures (God's creatures after all) to
come into camp-just a httle ragging, for which we could acquit
everybody all nght, would be most salutary. Figure me gomg
to-morrow and trying to coax this fractious ass of a gemus with
p.uA.1xto,r i1r,fcraw when I should hke to - -....
Really I am a person of little readiness of mmd, the Col.
presented me with a cucumber (or lone) as field-marshal's staff
at luncheon. What an ass I was not to put 1t in my pocket I
He would, in common honour, have had to pay and my wife
would have been most pleased with me, as economical Hausfrau,
for cucumbers are dearish this year.
33
Redfern House, Bosham.
[19 Apnl ? 1905.]
Utmam me una tandem re nunquam im1tatus esses, dico
,ca,coypa</>(av. Litterae tuae nov1ss1mae v1x legi possunt. You
might have kept (the) Bradley letter till term. 1 There is much
• Extract from a long letter about a competit,on (Wolseley Cup) at Bisley.
1
A letter from me on Mr A C Bradley's cntiC1Sm of Shakespeare Wilson
thought at this time that he had improved on Mr Bradley's theory of the
l'ragedies Letter to A C.F., 27 m 05 (notprmted) Tlusletterisoutof order
FAMILIAR LETTERS cxix
force in what you object but there are reasons why I did not take
the obvious and simple interpretation : and as I am sworn foe
to interpretations which are too subtle and ingenious you may
suppose I have special reasons. These are best not detailed in
a letter, we will talk them over. You perhaps do not remember
enough that Hamlet is an inhabitant of the same kind of world
as Ophelia, when you talk of a 'sterner' age than ours. Valde
dolemus quod uxor tua, nobis con1unct1ssima, Justo tardius con-
valescit. My article on Odyssey XXIV has appeared m Clam.cal
Review. 1 Prmters made awful hash of my article in Mind. 1
Stout is penitent-not my fault.
34
Bad Kreuth,
Bavaria.
13 July [19()6) .
. . . My wife is disgusted with Kreuth. We began with sultry
thundery weather which is for her the most trymg thmg of all.
Then suddenly mist and ram and cold November weather.
To-day we are Just sh1vermg about. . . . Fortunately for me
there 's a mce young fellow here named Franz who was about
IO years ago learning English m poor Abbott's house m Oxford.
He went an expedition with me the other day mvolving a climb
to the saddle of the Plauberg (otherwise Blauberg). The climb
turned out extremely steep and m one place where we had to
scramble over a scarp of naked rock the track practically dis-
appeared. There was a glorious crop of gentians at the top.
I read m the guide book (afterwards) the path was called ' uber
den Fels ' and was ' nur fur schwindelfreie ' Fortunately I am
' schwindelfrei ' m a most desirable degree. There can't be
much the matter with me for my young companion was much
more pumped by the ascent and begged me to stop and give
him breathing space. He remarked that I was evidently ' very
well trained ' (he meant ' m good training '} and expressed his
surprise, when we got back, to my sister-in-law on my walking
and climbing powers. I attach importance to this incident
1
The Classical Review, xix, pp 144-7.
• On the strength of tins and of internal evidence I have included the
artlcle 1n Mind, N. S,, No 54, Signed W., 1n Wilson's works
CXX F AKILIAR LETTERS
because through my other ' Beschwerden ' I had begun to fear
that I had entered a period of permanently diminished vigour,
which considering the work I have before me had been causing
me some anxiety .1
Today I have got the proofs of my Monro memoir from
Berlin.
Kindest regards from us both to you both.
35
New College.
28 Feb. 1907.
I understand the difficulty. It looks as though one ought to
try to do some recrmting in some of the Colleges. We can talk
about that when we meet. We might have a short pow-wow
in certain selected Colleges. It's a pity the Cyclists are not
better supported and it's rather hard upon you because in the
last two years the work of the Cyclists has been on a much
higher level than it ever has reached before . . If you like
I could draw up with you a short statement of the nature of
the work of the Cyclists which could be seht to captains of
compames or other persons mfluential m the matter of volun-
teering. It 1s clear to me that the difficulties of recruiting have
increased a good deal from the causes you mention smce I left
the Corps (except that cause which 1s among what you mention,
courteously, but really 1t isn't that I). Of course I was not
finding fault with you, I am not so blackly ungrateful.
36
Monday.
[20 May, 1907.]
The letter . . . proved to be of the d1stressmg kind I feared.
. . . I should like to come and talk to you about 1t, for though
no very decisive step need be taken at the moment I feel as
though I should break down if I couldn't confide the main
things to somebody....
If you happened to come here and there was some one else
in the room you could say you wanted to talk to me about
something and when we were alone you could say first some-
' Part of this letter 2s pnnted 1n Part V.
FAMILIAR LETTERS cxm
thing about the Cyclists or any other subject. If I don't see
you before I should like to see you Wednesday, I suppose my
best chance to see you (or Tuesday) would be after 4, but it
may be very difficult for me to get away. My wife will want
me to tea and be afraid of my being out too late. Would there
be any chance of finding you in about 2.30 ?
Bywater's pubhc lecture is 2.15 {I think) to-day. 1 I am afraid
no chance of my going. By irony of fate, another of my letters
was to say I was recommended for election to the British
Academy : but I am in such trouble I can't appreciate it.
Please do not say a word about the Brit. Acad. to an;yone
(except of course Mrs.--).
Many, many thanks.
37
Villa Taunus, Ems.
4 June {and after I) 1907.
. At Cologne where we spent the night. . . I thought
it best to go and have a restful time in the Cathedral and was
glad I did. I found it had lost none of the charm it had for
me when I was younger. It is wonderful what an effect such
architecture can have upon one, it is so calming. Such lofty
vaultmg as that of the aisle and choir at Cologne, with such
light and graceful forms, is subhme without being oppressive,
it is the subhm1ty which encourages and lifts one up in a manner
sympathetically to itself. A service was just concludmg without
music, but the responses of the congregation had a very beautiful
effect : the vast echoing spaces transmuted the sound till it was
no longer like human voices but bke the breakmg of waves
heard at a distance. One was far enough from the congregation
(Defense de circuler pendant l'office I) to get this effect. I wanted
to renew my acquamtance with the choir chapels, partly to see
some beautifully carved woodwork figures in high relief on (the)
altar-piece and partly, as I thought, to see some Flemish pictures
by Memling and Kranach. But my memory played me false in
both respects. I suspect I was thmking of some other church
seen since-possibly at Bruges, for though I found a magnificent
carved-wood altar-piece, 1t was not in the choir but on the east
• Tiu Er1Um111" Pf'otJWtJ&1f1110Jt of Greelt ""d ii, prec-ursors (pubhahed 1908),
cxxii FAMILIAR LETTERS
wall of the S. transept and the figures were not what I had in
memory, really far better. [Here follows praise of the altar-piece
in Radley School Chapel.] ... I doubt whether you would find
anythmg better in any continental church and it will transport
you m imagination to Flemish and German medieval churches.
. . . In the ' Three Holy Kmgs ' Chapel there were some very
beautiful figures of the 14th century (the above is dated 1520)
but they were ordmary detached images (the three' kmgs' and
I thmk two other images) and apparently they had been put
into the altar-piece m modern times-the altar-piece itself bemg
by a modern Dutchman (and excellent). The aforesaid very
large altar-piece-sort of big triptych or tetraptych-in the tran•
sept came out of a destroyed church.
As for the pa10tings there was no Memling or Kranach but
to compensate, the famous picture of the Adoration of the Magi
(not 10 their chapel however) by Stephan Lochner, 15th century.
It is triptychal, the colourmg is very beautiful and the faces
and figures are quite out of medieval stiffness and almost
modern. It is in wonderful preservation and 1s said to be the
picture mentioned by Albrecht Durer 10 his journal of his visit
to the Netherlands. How thankful one must be for these great
painters and one is so glad to thmk the names of the quite early
people are not forgotten (Lochner was from Switzerland but had
settled m Cologne) and also that the names of the first architect
of Cologne cathedral and of his successors are also preserved.
It is delightful too that the orig10al sketch of the towers and
W. fa1;ade has been recovered (they say part of it was in Darm-
stadt and the rest in Paris) and is to be seen in the Cathedral
June 9th. I mtended to send this off days ago but my time
is taken up by my medical exercises and restmg after them and
writing necessary letters (I wrote 7 postcards yesterday and
I write every day to Mrs. Wilson, she is often so lonely especially
as her knee prevents her from walking). 1 I must also count the
music which is my principal resource. I listen to that from
4 to 5.30 every day and generally take a good walk between
that and supper. After supper there is another concert, generally
the best in the day.... I chose a train which gave me a little
more than two hours in Cassel, for I wanted to renew my
• He had left Mrs Wilson at GOtbngen.
FAMILIAR LETTERS cxxiii
acquaintance with the picture gallery there. 1 It contains some
fine Rembrandts. One of these is the celebrated picture of his
wife Saskia. . . . The picture is fine enough but what he saw in
Saskia I don't know. Even he has not succeeded in making her
look interesting.... Much more interesting are several portraits
of himself, one very fine. The most celebrated is, I believe, a large
picture 'Jacob blessing the sons of Joseph. It 1s a fine thing but
rather monotonous m colour for Rembrandt. There are also
some splendid portraits of various people by him. I was happy
to find quite a nice landscape, The shore of Scheveningen by
Adrian van der Velde. That's the man of whom I have an
original landscape drawing over the mantelpiece in my study.
His metier was to put the cattle in other people's pictures,
e.g. Hobbema's, and so one doesn't often see a whole picture by
him. There is also a splendid and well-known Van Dyck, The
painter Snyders and his wife . . . also some gems by Metso and
Ter Borch.... Cassel itself is worth a visit ; it is ideally situated
and has a delightful old-world look, Just an ideal of the old·
fashioned capital of a German principality. There is at least
one fine Titian and I was much struck by a small cattle piece
by Paul Potter, it seems a sort of preparation for the famous
Bull. 11 There 1s the same wondedul rendering of the glossy hides
of the cows and of their horns but still 1t is far behind the
famous bull, the cows are more hke single studies beautifully
detailed just put on the same canvas, whereas the Bull is a fine
composition. By the way there 1s a curious picture of Rem•
brandt's, celebrated and I daresay you know it but I had
forgotten it. It is called The Woodcutter's family and 1s supposed
to be a Holy Family. It seems an absolutely Dutch interior,
very delightful are the mother and child ; the father is dimly
seen a little distance off, perhaps through a door into a shed,
chopping wood. . . . I came by chance on quite a beautiful
picture by Antony More : perhaps you remember that one of
his was about the finest in one (the first I thmk) of the exhibi•
tions of College pictures m the schools. It would delight the
heart of Woods, and doubtless has delighted it for he is sure to
• He had VlSlted it in 187 s m company with Miss Margaret Wilson and
probably later.
• He had adnured tlus when v1SJtJng Holland with Dr. C. L. Shadwell in 189:z.
CX.XJV F AHILIAR LETTERS
know the Cassel gallery. The amiable custodian, who was with
me, told me there were other Mores but I hadn't time to look
them up. The line hither passes Marburg . . when I first
went to Gottmgen 1874 I went that way-ils situation is most
romantic, the bmldmgs delightfully quamt and medieval. The
town seems to pour down the semicircular side of a high hill
into the Lahn. The configuration of the hill occasions the most
picturesque situation for the buildmgs. I always think it one
of the sights of the world and compare it to Innsbruck, which
also is built high and low on a hill-but it is rather at the foot
of a mountam. I fancy Marburg must be an excellent place to
philosophize m. Leyden I always thmk another, Leyden so
wonderfully still and remote from the world. You can imagine
people there wrapped up m classical scholarship or philosophy,
as mdeed its great men were, a place from which physical
science would be bamshed as mere ' stinks ' Gottmgen was,
but Gottmgen, I feel, fuit. It has grown tremendously. The
suburb where my wife 1s m a nursmg home was utterly unrecog-
msable, fine handsome houses grossstaedhsch [sic] m fact and
the idylhc countnfiedness of Gottmgen seems gone for ever.
It seems only appropriate that the prmc1pal philosopher should
be a psychophysic1st. Nevertheless the old town w1thm its
'Wall '(the latter, which used to surround 1t and was a favourite
walk of mme, 1s levelled now m many places but the site of it
remains as a sort of boulevard}, not so very much altered, is
now a kmd of kernel of old-fashioned med1eval-hke bu1ldmgs,
surrounded by large suburbs with modern bmldings. It makes
a sad 1mpress1on on one, the simple charm of the old place is
gone, the time when 1t seemed all Umversity. By the way on
one house outside the 'Wall' I saw a tablet with the names of
Brahms and Joachim. Ask Joachim if that was h1s uncle.
I certamly don't remember to have seen 1t there ' m my time '.
This place (Ems) 1s delightful. ... The position, on the Lahn,
is just wonder£ul, steep rocky hills go sheer up from the river
which has delightful wmdmgs. These hills are well wooded and
there are delightful walks to the tops of them .... One of my
greatest delights 1s the fine band. It plays to us from 7 to 8.30
wlule we are drinkmg our waters, but I don't get much out of
it then. There's a fine concert in the afternoon 4 to 5.30 when
FAMILIAR LETTERS CXXV
39
Sunday July 7 [1907].
Johannser Kurhaus bei
Zellerfeld (Harz).
Though I owe J - - a letter a long time I must wnte to you
first, for I am not comfortable about your work It seems
obvious you should not have begun on the Kant so soon after
term. I know the importance of sticking to a piece of work
hke that, if 1t is to be got through-and the work of a tutor
1s so entirely engrossing during term, that in the vacation one
must stick steadily to a thing even agamst the grain sometimes,
remembering that the ' term cometh when no man can work '.
But 1t was clearly imprudent, considering what you did at
Easter, to start on such a hard subject as Kant when term was
hardly over. As I said I suppose it means you must in con-
sequence of other vacation arrangements take the time for work.
Of course 1t 's better to arrange to have two or three clear weeks
of rest and recreation after term. But if you had to take your
main holiday later, then nevertheless you ought to have had at
least a clear week after term and then only done routine work,
FAMILIAR LETTERS cxxxi
such as College business or lecture work or reading. You really
must believe me about this. You will do your work all the
better if you wait till really fresh for it and certainly get more
done too, if you have the self-restraint to wait a fairly good time
after term. If you're at the Kant still, I should venture to take
the risk of advising you to stop it.
As to your experience now, undoubtedly if you take the kind
of view we seem agreed upon (at least m essentials) of the
original source of confusion in Kant, the more his theory is
carried into details the more confusion it will naturally shew,-
that is only to be expected. As to style, I trust you will take
to heart what I said on my postcard. In order to be qmte
clear m your thmkmg, your expression at first must be just what
1s natural to you, or you won't really say what you mean. Of
course what you don't hke is the labour of writing the thing
twice over. Now I will confess to you. I generally write first
a rough draft, then I begm to write out as for prmt . but
presently I begm to think or rethink and sometimes seriously
alter, and then there has to be a second rough draft. Then
I try to make certain that the third (is final) and 1t often is not.
Lookmg back on the various articles &c. I have prmted, I came
to the conclusion that I generally write a thmg four times by
or before the last version ,-a thmg wluch would frighten me
1£ I realised before it was to be so. Each time I try of course
lo have fewer rev1c;;als but generally 1t comes to the same thing.
For you (as for anybody) I am sure the first one or two \.ers10ns
&hould be in the words and forms of sentence most natural to
you. Don't be afraid of repetition. IF you mean the same
thmg, say the same thing or you will really get altering your
argument. In the final form you can use literary devices lo-
overcome the verbal repetition. I am fairly sure Aristotle wrote
m this kmd of way-more especially that 1f a word was the
right and natural word in the present context, he kept 1t though
he had used (it) just before m a different sense appropriate to
the previous context. Of course a mathematician never thinks
of varying the phrase, because he wishes to be absolutely
accurate. I repeat that you should certainly not look at the
MS on Universals if the thing is at present off your mind.
I only left it with you because at one time it was worrying you
l 2
cxxxii FAMILIAR LETTERS
40
Hannover. Ellernstr. 2.
I Aug. 1907.
It was so kind of you to send me a card here. We leave
Monday Aug. 5 and hope to be in Oxford on Aug. 7. My wife
picked up a good deal in the last ten days in the Harz in general
health and her knee at last gets distinctly better. The gout in
her fingers got very bad indeed and she is here trying a new
electric treatment which has certainly had remarkable successes.
I take her twice a day for the treatment, which may be described
as getting certain gout remedies directly into the fingers from
the outside (instead of through the stomach) by means of
electricity. The inventor was confident he could cure my wife's
fingers in IO sittings (for which we JUSt have 5 days), but so far
his ant1C1pations have not been realised as to rate of progress
and a good deal of pain is caused. The treatment is fairly
expensive and I confess to some anxiety now about its success.
Weather bad again after one or two fine days, on one of which
we left Gaslar [sic]. I renewed my acquaintance with Gaslar on
the way. The last Harz week I made (the) acquamtance of (a)
delightful German officer on the General Staff who had spent
the last month in England with Sir John French, &c. I had
rousing good walks with him. I must tell you about him later.
In the Harz the birds suffer from the multitudinous squirrels.
As to cows, distribution of their breeds follows d1stribullon of
races (Fick told me), e g. m Tyrol, the Slaves, the Germans,
Italians &c have their original breeds of cows. You will enJOY
the famous beauty of the Italian lakes
te, Lan maxumc, teque,
fluctibus et fremitu surgens, Benace, marino.
Let me have a card again soon ; affectionate remembrances
to both.
41 Hannover.
Aug. 3 [1907].
I was very glad to get another card from you here-I needed
it. The gout treatment seems a failure and therefore also
a serious waste of money. I am so sorry, for I had hoped my
wife had at last found something to give her relief. Yesterday
cxxxiv FAMILIAR LETTERS
came the very sad news that her only surviving brother, the
pamter, who had been for years in America was dead. It was
a shock to her.... I forget the Wages of Sin, tho' it interested
me much at the time. But I do trust you don't read English
books when abroad I L. M. always struck me as an effective
writer.
42
Hannover, Ellernstr. 2.
7 August [1907].
My wife has had to go into Hospital w1th diphtheria and we
may be delayed a week or ten days. She is gomg on all right.
I have written to ask Mrs. - - if she would look m at our
house as the house-parlourmaid (good hearted but headless} is
there with a new cook and a new boy I I She might kindly help
the headless one, 1£ m difficulty .... If you are not at Oxford
it does not matter.
43
Hannover. Ellernstr. 2.
7 August [1907].
There 1s no end to our troubles. My wife's expensive 'gout
cure' seems absolutely to have failed. Moreover we were to
have left yesterday (Tuesday), delaying a day on account of the
cure, but my wife got an attack which the doctor pronounced
diphtheria on Tuesday and the same night she had to be removed
to the hospital. I was in an agony of fear because the doctor
said it was rather advanced or, at all events, the white ' skm '
in the throat was extensive and he was clearly anxious. We
ought to have sent to him sooner but it seemed a mere infiam•
mation of the uvula at first. However she is doing well, the
serum was inJected last night and this morning she was, rather
to the surprise of the doctor, without fever and apparently the
wlute membrane has disappeared (two doctors testified to its
existence last night). I was the more frightened because she
always takes the worst possible view of herself-this of course
impedes recovery and is serious in such a dangerous matter.
She was quite overcome when she went away and said she knew
she should never come back. But that is all different to-day.
'Joy cometh in the morning.' I have been to see her twice and
the second time took joyfully a scolding for having bought her
FAMILIAR LETTERS CXXXV
44
Ellernstrasse2. Hannover.
22Aug. [1907].
Your kind letter has cheered us. I regret to say that there
is no immediate chance of our travelling. My wife came out
of hospital on the 13th, but soon developed after-effects (appa-
rently) of the moculation and has taken to her bed. She had
such pam in all her limbs. Now it seems to have settled m the
knee which was bad originally. She suffers such pam when she
stands that, after frmtless efforts to be up and use the limb,
she has had to go back to bed and wait to see what complete
rest will do. Of course she is in the doctor's hands. We are
m a pitiable plight. I had hoped to settle to steady work m
Oxford by the second week m August and I really can't do
here the philosophical work which I am upon, One is so dread-
fully unsettled. I long too to be back to our house and garden,
1t is Just the time of year for it. We are much m the way here,
for my sister-in-law was preparing to go to America and she
sailed on Tuesday I On the Ist of September a young lady
returns who occupies one of the rooms we have and a deplorable
hugger-mugger must result if we arc still here, for if my wife
had to go to a Chnik again, I think she'd go out of her mind.
They are touchingly kind to us m the house and do all they
can for us. Another trouble 1s that the Kai~er comes next week
cxxxvi FAMILIAR LETTERS
and so, if my wife 1s not well enough to travel before, we should
be delayed, for the trams will be too crowded for us. Please
ask Spenser to let me know when the Hertford fellowship is, as
I have promised to examine. Hannover disagrees with us both,
so our enforced stay 1s the more tantalising It was so kind of
you to go to our house so soon. Kindest regards.
45
Ellernstrasse 2. Hannover.
28 August [1907] .
. . . Many thanks for your very kind letter. I hoped to start
on Friday or Saturday, but my wife is now suffering with
a floating kidney trouble wluch comes and goes intermittently
and she 1s afraid about starting We all here have no doubt
she ought to make up her mind to start: 1t 's a good deal
a matter of courage and nerves but we don't like to tell her.
It 1s just about the last straw to me and I don't know what'll
happen, if we don't get off tlus week It's all I can do to bear
up at all, and I have begun to suffer from (a) very disquieting
feelmg of pressure on the brain, hkc what I had after strychnine
p01soning. Perhaps I'll write you a letter, but I want to get
off this because of the question about (the) Hertford fellowship.
46 [Oxford]
13 Nov. 1907.
We will consider the return of my MS. after the turmoil of
term is over. Perhaps you won't forget about 1t even if I do .
. . . I was sorry to nuss you but sec no prospect for the present
of havmg time for a talk. I am examining for the John Locke
and for B.Sc. I do hope Mrs Cook Wilson will let you examine
for me in the former next year. Many thanks for the kind
message from your wife. One of the compensations of age 1s
that one's lady friends send their love to one. Some of mine
are quite reckless m the way they transmit such messages. I will
tell you an amusmg example when I see you.
I have thoroughly sifted --'s case, interviewing all kinds
of people . . I will tell you all about it when we meet. It
was an interesting study of evidence. Everything proved accord-
mg to my view, before I got the unexpected ear-witness....
FAMILIAR LETTERS cxxxvi1
47
[5 Granville Place, Portman Sq. W.]
26 Dec. 07.
It was one of your kind thoughts to send me a letter of good-
will this Xmas. These things are a great help ' m dieses Lebens
Jammerthal '. Your letter suggests a delightful picture of
domestic happiness which you and your wife so well deserve.
But I miss one thing-you haven't told us about little Jane's
Xmas pleasures, and what she said and did.
In the doubts and difficulties about good and evil m our lives,
there is one thmg which is most comforting and encouragmg to
me and that 1s that m so many young cluldren tender and
affectionate and even unselfish feeling ts so soon developed. It
does not come as the slow result of a long experience m which
by repeated and painful effort a ' natural ' selfishness 1s gradually
ovcrcome-somethmg which needs much reasoning and reflec-
tion : but it is there almost at once-like a revelation. The
fcelmg of gratitude for services rendered seems to us, by habit,
so obvious as to need no explanation and it docs not surprise
us even in the animals. But how much reason it implies-the
realisation of the existence of another personality, the attribu-
tion to it of agency, rcahsmg that some one else has done this
for us and has caused 1t as willing it-and that this person also
1s well disposed to us. All this seems to me implied m gratitude
for benefits received and yet qu1te tmy chlldren are grateful.
Besides, at a lower level, they arc not merely pleased with what
they get but they are quite obviously pleased (even 1f the feclmg
1s not developed enough for gratitude) with those who have
given them a pleasure.
It is a most encouraging thmg for our view of humamty that
quite the highest and best feelings and the amount of intelligence
that they imply arc found quite at the bcgmnmg and not as
the result of careful thmkmg about experience-as a slowly
learned lesson.
Of course the familiar rubbish about ' instinct ' is no help and
1s a sort of irreverence to the human spmt. So far as there is
any truth m it, it is an imperfect recognition of the fact that
affection for others is primitive in the sense that 1t is underived
cxxxvih F A:MILIAR LETTERS
from anything else. It is indeed a rational emotion, reason's
own immediate activity and undesired possession. You might
just as well call the highest thinking possible 'instinctive', and
it is ' instmctive ' in the same sense. So you see the immense
importance of httle Jane-that mighty atom. We saw Marie
Tempest m - - , a poor play but she was as excellent as ever.
We dmed with the C-s on Xmas day. Mrs. C - and her
two daughters arc daughters of Anak. ... Friday and Saturday
we arc hearing Wyndham and James Welch. Next week
Charley's Aunt. . . . I hope little Jane got her doll all right (from
Mrs Wilson) as well as the mechamcal toy, which does she hke
best? I have no poetry for Jane this time (J01ccy p) calls it
' rhymes ' I) for I have exhausted my vein in writing German
verses to a delightful httle girl in the Harz to whom I'm Onkel
John. {I have brought Caird's addresses with me, you and your
wife would greatly enjoy them) A pamtcr friend of a Jewish
lady friend of mme, who has long wanted me to sit for my
portrait, has collared me at last and I am to begin sitting
to-morrow (Friday) I The painter is first rate. My wife much
plagued with gout. Both of us join m kmdest wishes to you
both, yours affectionately.
48
S Granville Place, Portman Sq. W.
31 Dec. 1907.
It was so kmd of you to write to both of us but one envelope
and one stamp would have done-youth is so reckless. We arc
so sorry to hear that little Jane was so unwell, but it often
happens after parties to children otherwise healthy enough.
Please give her our love. We both send our hearty good wishes
to you all for the New Year. Please tell Jane I was delighted
with her pretty little letter and wish her a Happy New Year.
She doesn't say what the castle was budt of m which I was
imagined to be.
The drier air in London is doing my wife good. She is dis-
tinctly better than when we came. I take care to wrap up well
after the theatre-this is in reply to your husband's kind moni-
tion. This morning I took Miss C - and Miss G-- to look
FAMILIAR LETTERS cxxxix
at the Rembrandts and other Dutch pictures in the National
Gallery. The arrangement has been much changed in the last
year {' hew management ') and I think for the better. E.g. three
pictures of De Hoogh's, which I always used to compare w1th one
another-two hanging apart in (the) same room and another in
a different room, are all hung together. Artistically they are
best in 3 different rooms and I think the artist would have
preferred that : but for purposes of study one wants them side
by side. But perhaps after all this is wrong as a principle of
arrangement in a gallery, m fact on 2nd thoughts it seems
possibly horribly wrong. However pictures of Ver Meer (or
Van der Meer), Maes, Metsu, Ter Borch &c. are now brought into
the same room, which seems both convenient and right. I sup•
pose Jane would say it was no use putting good wishes at the
end of the letter as they have been already expressed in the
letter I Yours truly.
49
[Oxford] 29 Jan. 1908.
µ711l/ µ' lpv,u µ&x11s t/n'll.Jwv 'ITEp"ovlil JJ,E 'ITfl(JUS, 1
50
[Oxford] 8 Feb. 1908.
Confidential
The teichomachy 8 has an amusing sequel. You r<"member
Murray abandoned the Jones, Brown, Robinson passage, though
it is the one he quoted for (the) 1st year of War in his book
and the only one. He told me he really meant to quote .S 32,
not M 1-32. I had considered the passage myself and never
imagined tt contained any reference to the first year of the war,
but I did not feel competent to deal with rt decisively last night
on such short notice. I have looked it up in Monro's notes
{xili-xxiv) Monro's explanation (wluch excludes (the) idea of
• Iliad, xvm. 126, with </>l'-lo11aa ,rrp, of course Achilles to his mother,
'Hold me not back from battle, though you love me I will not obey.'
' The ' fight at the wall • was a debate on the 7 Feb at the Oxford Plulo-
logical Society upon part of a paper called On the Suniles of Homer read by
Wilson to refute Professor G. Murray's ' advanced• views m Homenc cnticism.
It was a field-day with he.,,vy guns ; Sir Arthur Evans, among others, being
present at lea9t for part of the ti.me.
cxl FAMILIAR LETTERS
1st year of war though he doesn't say so) is obviously right and
entirely convmcing. It explains also the point of the passage,
which the mterpretabon of Murray's friends does no~ in the
least. In fact the 'advanced' ones have misconstrued and
badly. Just look at Monro's note. Godley agrees, he tells me,
entirely with me about the Wall. He thmks, as I do, the sup-
posed d1fficult1es about its occasional absence purely imaginary.
The whole wall argument, I think, mcludmg these precious
construes, rs a heartless hoax, due to a lying dream sent by
Zeus to the advanced ones.
From a remark of Murray's to me after, I gather he was
under some illusion about your remark to him about the way
Mill's contradiction could be explained. I suppose in such
circumstances a man naturally thmks hastily a new pomt hasn't
been noticed by his opponent and therefore is m his own favour.
Of course the contradiction can be explained-I thought I had
given the explanation myself-and I did, only I didn't dwell on
1t. I thought of workmg it out quite clearly last night but
didn't want to waste time, as 1t didn't matter.
Obviously all these contradictions have an explanation. 1 The
first thing 1s to establish their existence cmpmcally : one then
explains them, and not by the rational workmgs of consciousness
as I abundantly indicated. So m the 'first over the wall',
I offered an explanation as to how the poet could get confused
over it. In fact this is the 'fightmg m the dark ' which the
advanced school do not understand You were doing this when
you offered an explanation of Mill's contradiction to Murray,
but he didn't realise that.
The valentines haven't appeared in the shops yet.
Yours truly.
PS. Godley said he thought I ' had ' Murray generally,
because he (and even more the school he follows) depends upon
contrad1ctions, despite what he said-indeed he shifted ground
(gracefully), for the view specially criticized depended wholly on
contrad1ct1ons.
1
See 'Natural anomalies in original composition', The Classacril Revi,w,
vol. xxiv, p u8.
FAMILIAR LETTERS cxli
51
Oxford.
7 April 1908.
It was very kind of you to write, for I felt when you left that
two guardian angels had gone off duty. I saw Jane in the
street the day you left but haven't yet paid her a call ...
Thank you for the view of Wells. I have never been, and
always hope to go there and to Glastonbury. It looks very
attractive in the picture. I go in to sec Caird sometimes : he
came here this afternoon-a lovely day 1t has been and the
buildings looked wonderful in Oxford. My head is distinctly
better. Yesterday I had headache until about tea-time but
to-day there was none and the oppression was very much less.
I could have done some work I am sure this morning, only I had
a good deal of business out of doors which I naturally put into
the morning. Indeed I have idled all day, for I mowed the
lawn this afternoon (1t was very nice to do m the sun, I delight
m the smell of the cut grass too, it 's refreshing) and after the
Cauds were gone, I had to go out with my wife on business
(to look at kitchen ranges, as we have succeeded m getting our
landlord to contemplate a new one for us). Joseph 1s here for
a few days. In the latter half of the day, 1 e after tea, I have
been able to work fairly , but it 's frightfully hard stuff I am
thinking out. I have been ' stuck up ' nearly a week on one
point, but I have at last got hght, I think. ... My wife also is
gettmg dreadfully nervous about the trouble of going away the
last week to Woburn Sands. If however she gives it up, I must
go away a few days myself-probably to my friend in Sussex.
I do hope you are thoroughly resting, both of you, and enjoying
yourselves. I am fully content here when able to work. It 1s
really very nice here. Mrs. Case has lent me Sir Sterndale
Bennett's 1 Life. It is so mce-you ought to look at it. I am
solving a ' logical ' conundrum sent me by a man in Kentucky,
US A. I have to do these things sometimes. It's an [sic]
awful piffle and he ought to have done it himself or got help
easily at home, but then his institution 1s ' The Potter Bible
College'. Very kmd regards to both from both, yours truly.
1 Mrs T Case's father.
cxlii FAMILIAR LETTERS
52
Villa Taunus, Ems. June I, 1908.
Herc 's a geometrical problem for you suggested by Roman•
esque architecture. Suppose a tower 1 has a square section and
each wall terminates in a gable as at A and D. Let AB be the
height of the gable. Then if the planes of all such triangles as
ACD arc continued so as to cut in such lines as AE, DE, four
4-sided figures such as ACDE will be formed. Prove that, what-
ever the length of AB may be, these figures are true rhombuses :
so that AE, ED, DC, AC are equal. The same is true if the
section of the tower is a rhombus and not a square. The proof
is delightfully simple.
I had a dehghtful journey here The Surrey landscape was
golden with a splendour of broom and gorse. (Read a man's
dissertation for B.Sc. before leaving and this is the effect, for
he couldn't say anything simply. Lud I I let him have it.)
Dover, where (via Reading) I had five hours, was en fete for
the French President. The promenade pier was outlined in
electric lamps. So were the promenades on sea front and
another pier (not the Admiralty), and the scene lovely beyond
description at night. There were about 30 Torpedo boats in
harbour and from 9 to 9.30 they gave a display with their search
hghts-prmcipally by dluminatmg the chalk chffs. I had a
capital passage and a most comfortable coupe to myself all
night. Arriving at Cologne at midday, I was able to start by
the one o'clock boat to Coblenz. It was a perfect day for the
Rhme. It has rained for me on most previous occasions. The
view of Bonn and the Siebengebirge was very fine as we came
up the river The S1ebengebirge was very imposing and looked
the ideal home of Saga. I had forgotten how very wide the
Rhme is about there-the width of the river adds much to the
effect. Had a most amusing experience of the dependence of
' apprehension ' of objects on physical conditions. As we got
abreast of the Siebengebirge near Konigswinter and it was
opening out fully, something got in my eye, I believe an eyelash,
and you want another Johnny to get out an eyelash for you.
1 This JS Jllustrated by a drawmg of a typical German pyramidal roof,
53
12 Fyfield Road. II July, 1908.
Louis Dyer had, it was supposed, very painful neuritis m (the)
left arm. He went to Matlock for a fortnight-suffered agonies
and they idiotically dosed him with opmm, which the doctors
here had to try to get out of his system. The symptoms how•
ever soon made them suspect grave m1sch1ef, malignant disease
of the bone. It was thought that 1t might be enough to remove
the top part of the arm near the 'ihoulder, just as in Strachan-
D,1V1dson's case, the bone gradually forming a new surface for
the JOmt. But 1t was feared the arm might have to be ampu•
tated. This alas proved necessary: 1t was mahgnant, but the
tlung had spread to shoulder and (the) shoulder had to be taken
off too (done m London). He seemed makmg a good recovery
when a clot of blood got on (the) bram and caused paralysis
from which he died very soon. J saw the poor fellow a day or
two before he went to London. He was so brave and even
cheerful. I was filled with admiration of him.
The doctors said his case was anyhow hopeless. If he recovered
for a bit, he would have got bad agam for his system was per-
meated with cancer. I didn't know he was such a friend of
yours. I have known him for more than thirty years. Poor
W--, I wrote to him. They sent round a prmted acknow•
ledgement to their numerous sympathisers .... It's capital m
Oxford now. I take a header at our boathouse at 7.30 unless
(the) mornmg happens to be too v.mdy (tho' entre nous I thmk
that's all fudge as we have the boathouse to dress m) I can't
help thinkmg they made a mistake about Grenstcd. If you write
to him convey my sympathy. I have been greatly interrupted
in my work since we are back-can't be helped; but we have
JUSt secured Mrs. --'s cook, who seems to be a treasure. She
will come after we return (Sept. I 5, circa) and I trust hfc will
become easier. You can't conceive how my wife worries over
housekeeping and she has indeed had baddish luck since we
returned. However we have got what seems a capital new boy.
We seem as if we should have some peace at last. Of course
I have had so much bother with the house and getting the new
cook (advts. and letters) and my wife also bemg so poorly, that
FAMILIAR LETTERS cxlvii
the work has (been) very sadly interrupted. At Llandrindod
I shall have very much fewer duties and (I trust) fewer worries,
and I hope, tho' in a boarding house, really to get some work
done. I have, I confess, spent some time with Bywater-that's
natural. I do feel so sad sometimes about his going. (N.B. clrco.A•
aa"Tor is, on account of privat:, proparoxytone.) How sweet
of dear little Jane remembering us m her prayers Little Alan
Stout does the same for Prof. Bosanquet and for me. I must
write and tell Mrs Stout I hope he keeps 1t up, for we both
need it. (You remember my addition to the usual health at
mess, ' The King, God bless him I ') How you must have been
delighting m httle Jane Yes, we just miss We depart Tues·
day. Bywater has given me some more books, the photograv.
of his picture and a photog of the Ba.le picture of Erasmus.
J - - was here a day and gave me Nicholson's 'etching' of
Oriel. Much love to Jane. Our very kmd regards to you both.
Yrs truly.
54
Montrose, Aspley Heath,
Woburn Sands
[last week of July 19081
It is so kind of you to renew your offer to take me into
your party m Cornwall. I.can conceive nothmg more delightful
than to stay quietly m your happy family circle, with little
Jane as the centre thereof. It is so kmd of you to be willing
to extend the radius of 1t to mclude me (Postulate Let 1t
be granted that the family circle may be described with Jane
as centre and of such radms as to mclude C. W.) But 1t isn't
really possible. I doubt whether it would be advisable to leave
Mrs. Wilson alone in Oxford till the 18th when we go to Lian·
drindod. She has been hysterical lately and has no friend to look
after her there Moreover she is nervous about her fingers, which
are very bad, and wants to have them examined by the Rontgen
rays. I think it might have been a good thing if she could go
to Llandrindod alone or be there alone, if she could have been
with a friend there (Mrs. D-) but that plan has broken
down ; Mrs. D-- will be there but can't be in the same
boarding-house. I could then have gone somewhere myself and
177,1•1 k2
cxlviii FAMILIAR LETTERS
got some work done. It wd. have been nice to come to you
then but I shd have had to work a good deal and it would be
too late for you (latter half of August). Meanwhile don't worry
about me. I am much better, have done some satisfactory
work, if no great quantity One of my speculat10ns seemed to
go so easily into Aristotelian Greek that I wrote it 10 that
tongue 1 Tl seemed really clearer and more adequate to the
subject than English. I tried it on Gilbert Murray (with whom
I had previously discoursed on the adequacy of Gk as a philo-
soph1cal language), I sent him no English as the thing won't do,
unless it tells its own story He was delighted and said he
thought it couldn't be so clearly said m English Love to Jane.
Kindest regards to Mrs - - and yourself With much gratitude
for yr kmd help and kmd mvitatlon.
Yours truly.
55
Oxford 7 Aug 1908
We returned here July 31st The last week .tt Woburn Sands
was very hot and my wife was murh tried It was difficult to
get a cool place When the sun went down, however hot the
day, it was usually too damp (at once) to sit out. [There follows
a long and distressing account of the radiography of Mrs Wilson's
hands and of the defcct1on of the new boy He was followed
by a 'motherless' boy, a great relief] ..
Bywater 1s here from time to time I am to dine with him
on Sunday. I was so sorry to see Grenstcd 10 the 2nd class
Perhaps I made him too clear and all he said was mtelhg1ble,
or perhaps he failed m history . . We go to Llandrmdod on
the I 8th and stay 4 weeks I am qmte hopeful that I shall
get some work done at Llandrmdod. What I have done has
been pretty satisfactory and I am not troubled by that dis-
tressing oppression in the head . . I hope you have a piano
I am looking forward with horror to 'Kurkapelle' at LI It's
awful. ... Our garden and verandah are JUSt delightful now-
bkfast on verandah difficult to beat anywhere 10 Europe More
kmd regards, yrs truly
1 Published 1n the O!11/ortl Macaz1ne, vol. xxXJ., No. 16, 1n 1913.
F AIIILIAR LETTERS cxlix
56
Oxford.
Sunday 16 Aug. [1go8].
I have left the keys of our boat (' Witch '} m College lodge
for you. . . . I went first to your house but nobody there to
take the keys. I cut off the dead flowers (a quantity} from the
httle standard which flowered so freely, so that you may have
a chance of seeing it do 1t again, for which I claim a place m
your ' spiritual exercises '. Been seemg a good deal of Bywater,
last glimpses of him m Oxford. He 1s so pleased with Raleigh's
lecture on Johnson and wished me to tell him so. Look up
Bywater yourself, he's here the weekends till about end of
August. Much love to Jane W1r haben schon eme Kochm,
cm Schatz I
57
5 Granville Place W
3 I Dec [19081.
This is to wish you a Happy New Yt'ar all of you, and to
thank you for another kmd letter describing your Xmas festi-
vities which mterested me I suspect little Jane didn't get the
mechamcal toy (' galloping maJor ') which was to have been
sent on 23d If not, wd. you mmd applymg at the shop which
rails itself • Sports Club', or some such name, opposite the
Town Hall m St Aldate's and wd. you mmd at same time
askmg 1f they sent a toy from me to the Carntts (mcchamc.i.l
swan) in Holywell. Yrs
58
[To 1llustrat«- his theory of the genesis of the Anstoteban text, Wilson had
~ent a correspondent the shp proofs of the b'lt of contents of hu, book On
llie Traversing of Geometncal Figures. These showed a very considerable change
and growth 1n the book after the first proofs had been pnnted and m the
process of proof correction This letter was m consequence l
59
Wed. 7th April, 1909.
12Fyfield Road, Oxford.
We got back on Monday. The time was rather unprofitable
because the whole fortmght had scarcely a warm or sunny day.
This made a great difference to my wife, who couldn't get out
much, and she returned both unwell and dispirited. Unfor•
F AKILIAR LETTERS cli
tunately a change of domestics has turned out badly, or partly
so, for though we have a very nice woman as cook, a young
German house-parlourmaid very specially recommended to my
wife turns out to be a minx and we must be rid of her as soon
as may be. This sort of thing affects my wife very much and
has caused a return of hysteria, her condition having been lately
very neurotic. These things affect my stupid head also. Besides,
I have had to be constantly employed as errand hoy during the
uncomfortable transition period. and have besides to go with
my wife sometimes on her necessary errands, because it isn't
quite safe for her to be alone. It is hard on her for she suffers
otherwise enough from painful ai thntis 10 the finger Joints, for
which we have tned much in the way of remedies and in vain.
So I haven't been able to get to our suh1ect till this afternoon,
and as my head isn't very well I will confine myself to the first
point. If I don't do more it is quite good for me : indeed it
is a kind of welcome anodyne. 1
60
The Boar's Hill Hydro, near Oxford.
16 June Thursday 1910.
Your question was as usual qmte relevant but when developing
a contmuous argument, as opposed to discussing, I find it difficult
to switch my mind off to another question however germane.
And so I forgot that at the beginning of my paper I said not
that we thought of hving as = growing but that growing was
the fundamental conception we had about the hvmg thing, and
I gave as an mstance that we thought of a seed like a bean (not
as something growing but) as something which could grow,
whereas a pebble could not. This 1s an mstance of somethmg
we contemplate as belongmg to livmg matter as against dead,
though we don't think of it as actually growing, and our idea
of it as such, i. e. as living and not dead matter like the stone,
depends on the idea of growth. Later on in the sequel (unread)
of my paper I have pomted out that m the more scientific con•
cep~ion of the hvmg thmg as feedmg, growing, reproducing (and
moving otherwise) one sees that the bottom of the thought is
that life, as the hving quality of the hvmg thing, is the principle
1 The remainder of this lettel' ,s 1n Part V, xiv.
clii FAMILIAR LETTERS
which makes 1t have the actav1t1es of growth, movement, &c.
though it is only thought of defimtely through these observable
activities, in which (according to a familiar usage"of speech in
such cases) we should say 1t 1s 'mamfested '. These two parts
of my paper (if I had only thought of it) give the answer to
your question and objection so far as it implies 'alive'=
' growing', in the sense of giving what I think about it, at any
rate, and had expressed I had begun to think about ' decay '
but, partly m (the) hurry to get it done and partly through
much preoccupation, qmte forgot to develop it in the written
paper As to the plant at the stage when it perhaps 1s growing
no more, we, I thmk, clearly regard 1t as ahve, as long as the
sap rises and is absorbed, 1. e. as long as it is ' feeding ' : which
really involves (1f we reflect so far) that, if then not growing
absolutely, 1t 1s losing matter (wasting) which is replaced by the
feeding, and thm, 'growing' relatively is going on. The dying
plant I suspect we thmk of as having parts of it dead, parts
which no longer feed, m which the sap doesn't rise, and are just
dead matter as lifeless as what never hved, as the w1thermg bp
of a blade of grass or the husk of wheat: ' dying ' meaning then
havmg more and more parts dead, and also probably as having
less and less sap nsmg m the parts we still think ahve. They
feed less and less until unable to feed at all and cease not only
to grow but to be able to grow
The more difficult case however seems to me to be the one
which I mentioned at the begmnmg of my paper, viz. that of
the seed. For, whether 1t be really growmg or feeding m any
sense or not, we don't th111k of 1t (normally) as domg either.
But ~e do think of it as something which can feed and can
grow : whereas the dead parts of the plant which have ceased
to feed cannot feed or grow again. I suspect that m practice,
while we certamly don't think of the seed as dead, hke the
husk, we don't naturally think of 1t as (actively) ahve or strictly
speaking (as) · ahve' at all, simply because of its quiescence.
While we don't think of the :;eed as dead (wh· N.B. ts obviously
not the same thmg as thinkmg that 1t is not dead) I suspect
we only come to reahse that 1t is in some sense ' alive ', when
we find certam seeds won't grow any more than a pebble--then
we naturally come to think of those which do germinate as
FAMILIAR LETTERS cliii
having been ' alive ' tn some sense when not germinating.
Growth is therefore exactly the test used to decide even here,
in what is not actually growing, whether it 's ' ahve ' or not.
Not only, then, that which 1s growing but also that which has
the potentiality of growmg is considered by us (as) alive. Our
thoughts are so filled by the idea of growth, the actuality by
which we test the potentiality, that we don't reflect on what
the seed actually is as opposed to its potentiality-but N.B. that
tf the question occurred to us at all we shouldn't answer ' 1t is
a dead thmg but one with the potentiality of hfe '. Probably
we thmk of it m a way which corresponds to the formula
'suspended animation', even if we don't use this phrase. For
I suppose this formula 1s itself the result of the observation
that somethmg which doesn't manifest the ' activity of life '
nevertheless can't have been dead, because it afterwards shows
such activity. It 1s Just the kmd of uncritical formula which
belongs to imperfect reflection-or reflection m 1ts first stage.
We are probably helped by the analogy of sleep m the eonsc1ous
Irving thing, and mdeed the word ' dormant ' 1s what we are
likely to use
Yours truly.
61
The Boar's Hill Hydro, near Oxford.
21 June 1910.
Your letter gave me great pleasure. I am glad to thmk that
I have been of some use to you , such generous acknowledge•
ments as yol.V's are a great encouragement. And it was a no
small encouragement to have a few men hke yourself who never,
or ' hardly ever ', missed the weekly two hours' talk for the
whole year and who showed such unwearied attention as you
did. I always greatly enJOY the informal class myself and it is
very mce to find from ttme to time that my pupils enjoy it
also. Not long ago a young American professor writing to me
said our conversations in the informal instruction class were
such a pleasant memory to him, and your own kmd expressions
brought back his words to me
I trust that if I can be of any use to you m the future you
will not scruple to write to me
Owing to domestic troubles, which quite prostrated my invalid
cliv FAMILIAR LETTERS
wife, we fled up here before the end of term and my last informal
class was held here. With kind regards and best wishes, yrs.
truly.
PS. I should have rephed sooner to your letter but didn't
get 1t until to-day when I went down to College.
62
[Shap, (? July), 1910.]
My remarks on the teaching of mathematics concerned the
teacher's own method rather than the text-books . . . The
defect of method m the qmte elementary teaching of Geometry
1s that boys are usually given Eucbd or some other geometrical
treatise to learn the demonstration of propositions. This, I
thmk, should not be done. The teacher should propose each
propos1tton to the pupils as a problem to solve. Let them try
first For instance, ask them how they would describe an
equilateral triangle, 1f they were c1llowed a pair of compasses
and a ruler. If the boys :find a solution of their own, it may
be right, even 1f not the orthodox and, 1f 1t really assumes too
much, this can be pointed out, and the pupil should try to prove
the assumptions he makes, which will often be quite right. If
they cannot find the solution, they will often become far more
able to appreciate the proof when 1t 1s given to them by the
teacher. And sometimes 1t will be possible to lead them on
from the pomt they have go(t) to. If possible, I should do this
from the very begmmng. E. g , tell a boy what you mean by
an isosceles tnangle and then ask him to find out how to make
one. Then you can lead lum on to an eqmlateral. But in a boys'
class this may not be always thought possible. I shouldn't agree
with that view-or else the boys may have so bttle idea of the
subject that you can't quite begm this way Then I should
teach them by gomg through the steps of the discovery myself :
getting them, when they understand it, to help by finding or
suggesting the next step after you have given them the start.
The boys will get much sooner a real interest m the subject m
this way. Moreover every proposition will be to them a 'rider',
and a class taught in this way will find ' riders ' far easier than
those taught in the ordmary way Boys who can follow and
reproduce rightly and intelbgently demonstrations in a given
FAMILIAR LETTERS cJv
text-book are often very bad at riders and are afraid of the
'problems' in the Geometry paper, because their minds have
never been accustomed to originate thinking, but only to under·
stand the given argument ready worked-out. In the case of
those theorems which require a construction, it is the construe•
tion which is the important thing and the text-book, such as
Euclid, n8Ve1' shews how the construction is found.
It is absolutely necessary that the teacher should try to show
how the construction may be arrived at. The whole difficulty
in many riders depends on finding the right construction. No
wonder then the boy as ordinarily taught finds difficulty, because
he has never learned from the text-book how the construction
1s found in the various theorems. He is accustomed to have
the hard part done for him, that 1s to say to have the construc•
tion given to him, whereas he ought to see how every step in
1t 1s suggested by a consideration of the problem.
The real difficulty, as regards time, 1s that it means so much
extra work for the teacher. You must yourself study the given
demonstration beforehand and try to see how the discovery of
the various steps m it is suggested. This is not always easy :
but I can make a suggestion which may be of use. A theorem
may be quite evident m some special symmetrical case and this
may suggest what to do, when the symmetry is disturbed. For
instance, I suspect that the theorem of Euclid 1 47 (Pythagoras'
theorem of the square on the hypotenuse) was first suggested
by the case where the right-angled triangle 1s isosceles. This is
the case worked out m the Meno (of Plato).
As a matter of fact a theorem and its construction are not
infrequently discovered without looking for them, m the course
of some other investigation. So that, m such a case, it is not
true that the construction was discovered by considering the
needs of the problem, because the problem itself had not occurred.
Some other problem was before us and, in making our con•
structions and seeing what followed from them, we observe
something that part of our construction necessitates and then
this can be turned into a separate problem, the construction for
it being what we have accidentally discovered. I daresay if you
find yourself sometimes hard up to see how a construction or
demonstration was discovered, I could help you.
clvi FAMILIAR LETTERS
As you reahse, the work of the teacher is at first increased,
but the class will make far greater progress, though they may
have, say, only done half a book of Euclid while another has
done two books. But your class wtll know and wdl not easily
forget, whereas the other may have to go over the ground again.
One very important and usually neglected thmg is to have
the figure drawn on the board as correctly as possible. Let the
straight lmc be ruled, and the circle described by a pair of large
wooden compasses, \\-luch you can easily get. When I was
a boy, I first got to understand Geometry through a teacher
who used wooden compasses. I remember I first realised what
an angle meant and what equal angles were, when he drew an
angle by ruhng along ms1dc the legs of the compass-the com·
pass bemg put flat on the (black)board-and then carrymg the
compass to another part of the board and makmg an equal angle
by rulmg ms1de the legs of the compass agam, the mchnatlon
of the legs not havmg been varied When I went to a higher
school and there wasn't such apparatus, I made a pair of wooden
compasses and used 1t in class with the approval and apprec1a•
t1on of my class master
In teaclung Algebra and Arithmetic you should treat the
' book work ' m a s1m1lar manner, letting the boys thmk 1t out
as far as possible themselves and only helping them when
they fad.
A second thing I am very anxious about 1s that the teaching
of elementary mechanics, mcludmg hydrostatics, should begm
as soon as possible In many schools the boys are kept working
at Geometry, Algebra and Trigonometry long before they begm
Mechanics As soon as a boy knows the elements of Tngo·
nometry he 1s able to do Mechanics and should begm at once.
The more abstract studies arc so wearying, and the apphcat1on
of Geometry and Trigonometry to Mechanics gives them quite
a new interest-the sooner therefore Mechanics are introduced
the better. The ordinary practice, which I have described, tends
to kill interest in the subject It 1s as 1£ you kept a boy grmdmg
always at Grammar and exercises m Latin, until he had got
through all the exercise books, before allowing him to translate
a Latin author and giving him that mterest.
There is another very important point and that is the teaching
F AKILIAR LETTERS clvii
as regards the use of signs of direction, i. e. plus ( +) and (minus)
(- ), used as signs of direction in Trigonometry and afterwards
m algebraical Geometry, or analytical Geometry as it is called.
But now I admit this is a very difficult matter, because mathe-
maticians, even the best books, are in the dark about it. The
usual thing to say 1s that it is a ' convention ' to represent
direction by the signs plus ( +) and minus (- ). This 1s sheer
nonsense. You could never get the mathematical results (and
they are marvellous) out of a mere convention. If it were mere
convention one might ask why should not the signs of multi-
pbcabon ( x ) and division (+) be used as signs of direction ?
And to this question the ' conventioners' have no answer. It
is possible however that you mayn't have to teach Trigonometry
and we may let the sleeping dog he for the present.
In Algebra and Arithmetic you should take every trouble to
make boys understand proportion and mcommensurability.
Nixon's 'Euchd revised' has a capital treatment of the incom·
mensurabihty of the side and diagonal of the square-Euclid's
own, if I remember right, but I haven't the book before me--
which makes the mcommensurability clear without the help of
algebra or square roots. The only books I have ever seen
myself which treat the elements in the right kmd of way are
those by De Morgan There is an Anthmetic and, 1f I remember
rightly, an Algebra. As regards Algebra, a title I am sure of
is De Morgan's Trigonometry and Double Algebra, but that is too
advanced. 1 think there is an elementary Algebra I do not
always agree with him, especially m the Double Algebra (which
wouldn't concern you), but he goes the right way about it and
is suggestive and sbmulatmg [1t]. For instance, his remarks on
Concrete and Abstract number, upon the meamng of the minus
sign m the answer to a problem (even though this latter may
not be altogether right).
Another thmg you will have to be careful about 1s the meanmg
of an answer with ,/ =- I, m an algebraical problem : and here
I am afraid you would find no help whatever from mathematical
books. Suppose the problem is what is the value of x when it
satisfies certain conditions, the boy must be taught the difference
between the answers x =o and x = ,/--::::X. You see I have sent
you a fairly lengthy reply instead of ' merely mentioning
clv1ii FAMILIAR LETTERS
literature', but the reason 1s that I know of no satisfactory
literature on the subJect.... With kind regards, yrs. truly.
[The Elemetds of Ardhmetie •, A. De Morgan, 1835, 5th ed. 1848 (see
especially the Prefa~. London (Taylor & Walton)
T/,e Elements of Algebra, A De Morgan, 1835.
Tngonomet,,y and Double Alg,bra, A De Morgan, 1849
The Conntnon of Number and Magndude, A De Morgan, 1836, 18 probably
the book to wluch the letter refers for the d1stmct1on between abstraet number
and tlungs counted or repeated
De Morgan's Differential and Intelf'al Calculus, 1842, 1s the forerunner of
certa.Jn modem books which endeavour to make the Calculus 1ntelbgible to
a reasomng mmd, not gifted mathematically It 1s still worth perusal by
plulosoplucal studentci ]
63
South View House, Shap,
Westmoreland. 18 Aug. 1910
My friend 1 recommends as about the best guide to modern
method in teaching mathematics A school course of Mathematics,
by David Mair. Clarendon Press
He says that Mair has done more to improve mathematical
teachmg than anyone else in England He (Mair) is the senior
exammer of the C1v1l Service Commission From what he says
I thmk Mair's book would give you very valuable suggestions.
My friend thmks the books by Hall and Knight are probably
the best among ordmary text-books. These authors sometimes
wrote Jomtly and sometimes with other authors. But he says
he won't venture to recommend them as sound m principles,
though they have much merit as simple guides I should thmk
probably you would have to have Mair for your own guidance
and possibly have to give the boys Hall and Knight's books.
By the WclY, when you do teach geometry and are trying to
interest the boys m the ' thmkmg ' method, you would probably
gain their confidence 1f you let them have the usual proofs of
the Pons Asinorum and then gave them, after they had studied
these, the simple demonstration without construction which
I think I gave to you. Of course I would Jet them try them-
selves first before shewmg them the usual proofs, some boy
might well hit upon the proof I gave you. Yours truly.
PS. I regret I have mislaid your letter, so this must go
round by Umversity College.
1
[The late Mr. J. W. Russell, lecturer of Balhol College ]
FAMILIAR LETTERS clix
64
7th May, 1912.
You formerly spoke feelingly of my aspersions upon the intro-
duction to Post. Analytics, 1 1. I, and, as these were only made
in lecture, I concluded you had become acquainted with them
either by seeing a copy of my notes or hearmg of 1t from a pupil.
My reasons were stated in lecture thus : ' The passage profes_ses
to sketch the subject but it 1s a mere analysis of the first chapter
though it has one line to the effect that the u,c/1/m is 'llEp'i.
411'oouf,v and 1s of ,m<TT~JJ.71 a,roou,cTmj, and there is the
farther difficulty that J. d.. is properly the subject of the Posterior
Analytics' I added that the Post. An. began with a general
statement, hke the Ethics, which wasn't a sketch of the subject
and that that was the Aristotelian manner. It has occurred to
me since that this kmd of thing is not likely to have been done
by a Peripatetic philosopher. He wd know that i,r. clvoo, was
the proper subject of the Post. An. No reason why he should
go out of his way to make that kmd of mistake. On the other
hand when wntmg Pr. An mtrod0 Aristotle may well not as yet
have conceived the special log. treatment of science as in Post. An
In fact m wntmg on syllog demonstration a:. opposed to mere
dialectic he thought he was writmg on Ell'. a.ll'oo. Afterwards
he felt the Pr. An. was too general and somethmg more special
required on the sciences and so he wrote the Post An -and
as to the analysis bemg of the 1st ch: 1t 's hkely enough Arist.
might have written so, mtendmg, after the part to which the
analysis referred, to go on with another introduction to the next
part, but as a matter of fact he went straight on without doing
1t. This 1s the kmd of mistake an author might make, but not
at all so likely a mistake for an mterpolator who wanted to
write an introduction. He'd be likely to give something general
covering the whole treatise. The origin of my note I on Tim. 37 c
was this :-Somebody, who had before him Archer-Hind's
foolish note on the place, prepared a juggling emendation in
which i.olwv was somehow got out of ,holc,w, really supposing
the interpr0 of the kind A. H. had in view. The editors of the
periodical in which the article with the emendation was offered
1 A abp for Pnor Analytics, ste the author's words, p. 31 • See p. lxxai.
clx F AM:ILIAR LETTERS
sought advice. J. A. S. told me of it and I wrote this paper
which the editors communicated (typewritten) to the would-be
emender. Afterwards I sent my paper to the Journal of Philo•
logy. I enclose my article from Cl Journ ... Yours truly
j. COOK WILSON.
In same no. of Cl. Journal (April) <J of P. )xiii, p. I 36)
Henry Jackson has come a cropper in trymg to emend punctua-
tion of Soph. 244 c.
65
New College. 31st May 1912 .
• . . By the way as I was gomg at a fair pace to-day, bemg late
for lecture, on my bicycle I passed M. I column and I heard
one of the men r1dmg at the head call out ' There 's that old
man agam I' How smoothly the waters close over us!
Yours truly.
66
12 Fyfield Road 2nd June 1912 .
. . • the matt<-r of the accouut of the pleasures of knowledge
m the Republic. Plato describes these as mcident to the filling
of the soul, leavmg one m the difficulty that they then seem to
be mixed pleasures at least and perhaps wholly pleasures of
relief of pam The difficulty 1s directly met m the Philebus, for
Plato there expressly lays down that the pleasures of learning
are not the removal of (the) pam of want, because the absence
of knowledge 1s not felt as a pam otherwise, as Plato says
acutely, we should not forget (or we shd be conscious of the
pam of the losing of knowledge, etc ) ... [he contmues about the
Sophist and the Parmenides] for 1t consists m what I confess 1t
has taken me some time to arrive at, trymg to appreciate the
quite plam meaning of the dialogues apart from the pre-
suppos1t1ons wJ11ch encumber us so much m our study of
him....
67
15 Dec 1912. Oxford.
I regret that owing to the great demands on my time through
the disquieting and distressmg change in my wife'b condition
{she has been getting worse smce beginnmg of August con•
FAMILIAR LETTERS clxi
tinuously) that I haven't time to write to you as I should like
about the Arist8 question. But I think I can in a few words
perhaps comfort you. (I) The IT'tp&v ,., 811 business is very
fully dealt with m my ordinary Aristotle lectures. (2) It is not
really relevant to the particular question before me-the con·
fusion about the use of the word predicate in both ancient and
modern times. Whereas the remarks in Post. An. (are) relevant.
You would realrsc this if you could see the long discussion I have
on the distinction of subject and predicate, which perhaps I may
some day put before you. Indeed I mtend to do so. (3) The
kmd of diff. Aristotle gets mto (as I suppose) on the occasion
when he had ttme (?) to reflect on the nature of predication was
important to me, ~nd he's not the least excused by the fact
that he wanted to meet a special difficulty. It's a bad look-out
1f he had to make a lot of mistakes to do 1t (4) There may
be a 'higher synthesis' which JUsttfies a circular defimtion, but
this is JUSt the place at any rate where 1t won't do (5) Don't
misunderstand these ' extracts of Logic ' I They are merely
printed because, owmg to a dra~t1c rewntmg of my lectures
under great difficulties, I can't give the men anything hke
a complete course without prmtmg pieces for them to read
which I shan't have ttme to lecture on I send them to you
because some of them are likely (I imagine) to interest you.
I thmk, e g , what I have written on' Modahty' and on Bradley's
' Ultimate Reahty ' might be of the kmd I intend this vacn.
lo prmt a good btt more (e g. on subj and pred. in the smtence
of the form A 1s B) and on the negative Judgement .... Yrs truly.
68
I2Fyfield Road, Oxford.
22 May 1913.
The enclosed contam extracts from my lectures which I was
obliged to omit 111 delivery. I make a pomt of letting my
hearers have a fairly full course, covering the usual main topics
and latterly I have helped myse\i out in. this way. Don't ti:oub\e
to study it. I shall never ask you even 1{ you nave rcaa' any
of it. If you have any leisure and interest you might look at
the §§ on the Categorical and Hypothetical propos1ttons as these
clxii FAMILIAR LETTERS
contain a covert polemic against Bradley. If you have any
further curiosity you might look at the §§ on the Negative
conceptian. Yours truly.
69
New College. 27 Dec. 1913.
I send you of my Logic Extracts Pt. II §§ 26-60 (with excep•
tion of § 57). I thmk I sent you §§ 61 seqq. before (didn't I)
but a better print. Part one 1s m the press and will follow.
Yrs. truly.
70
12Fyficld Road. Oxford.
Oct. 22, 1913.
I was greatly pleased to get your letter. I have a very vivid
and pleasant recollection of you. I am much mterested m your
present candidature for a lectureship in Otago University.
I resolved to write you a testimonial though you did not ask
for it. But soon after I had a request for one through Mr. Wylie
and have sent it through him. Your degree m Greats is quite
good enough because you were considerably handicapped at the
start, and I daresay with the same advantages as people here
you would have secured a' First' comfortably
It was very considerate of you not to call m January but the
fact is that m that month at the begmning my wife had a sudden
and decisive change for the better. I thmk you rather overdid
it m courteous consideration, for when a man is going so far one
can always spare a little time for him. I regret much I have
no photograph I could send you. Elliott & Fry photographed
me some few years ago, but I was far from well and the result
1s most melancholly [szc] I shouldn't hke anybody to have it.
But I must think of having some made and will remember you.
However I don't think it will be yet awhile, for unfortunately
either in consequence of over-exercise in the autumn-grubbing
up trees, the hardest work I ever did-, or of an unrecognised
influenza attack, the doctor doesn't know which, I have got,
the doctor says, a weakness of the heart (I suppose so-called
'athlete's heart') which he takes so seriously as to prescribe as
much rest as possible for the present. He allows my morning
lectures but I have not been permitted informal instruction this
FAMILIAR LETTERS clxili
week. The last years I have had 2 delightful classes, one of
men and one of women. The women were good, and one .got
a ut and another a 2nd. This year also I have a good women's
class and the new men's class seems promising.
This Summer was the best holiday we have had for years-
in Westmoreland near the scene of the Aisgill railway disaster.
The air did my wife an extraordinary amount of good. The
• squires ' m the neighbourhood were extraordinarily hospitable
to us. One of them housed my motor-car m a lordly stable.
I have acquired a car and the art of dnvmg it and am glad that
my wife was able to go about with me, though the country was
too hilly for her. She never quite hked coming down a steep
hill though I always went slowly. The car of course contributed
much to the pleasure of our holiday. I have a very good friend
in N.Z., Bevan Brown, Headmaster of the Christchurch School,
and Professor Macmillan Brown. With kindest regards from
Mrs. Wilson and myself, Yours truly.
71
I2 Fyfield Rd. Oxford.
November 9, 1914.
To L1EuT.-Cot. H. D. FARQUHARSON.
DEAR SIR,
The enclosed letter from my friend your brother Spenser
must serve as my mtroduct1on and commendation to your kind
services.
In view of the difficulties caused by submarines and floating
mines I have some suggestions which I should hke to put before
the naval experts of the Admiralty. I want to secure that they
shall be attended to merely, and if they seem of no use, I don't
want the Office to trouble to do more than send me a line to
say that this is so. I had intended to send them now, but in
the meantime an urgent matter has come to my knowledge
which I must write about at once.
From an absolutely reliable Danish source I hear it is believed
in Denmark that the German fleet is only being held back until
certain new guns are ready which will out-range our guns by
a matter of two miles. If this is so, it accounts for Admiral
Tirpitz's boast that he would surprise the British Admiralty
about this very date.
clxiv FAMILIAR LETTERS
I daresay the Admiralty know all about this but it is welt
to make sure. Yours truly,
J. CooK WILSON.
PS. My suggestions 1 will follow in another letter.
72
MILITARY CYCLING
To the Editor of 'The Times'.*
SIR,-The letter of mme on military cycling which you were
good enough to publish has not only evoked a very kind notice
from the Manchester Guardian but has brought me a com•
munication from a d1stingu1shed cyclist officer which I trust the
War Office may thmk worthy of very serious attention. It
seems that we have no cyclist battalions with our Army in
Belgium, although the country in which it is operating is specially
suited to the operations of cyclist forces. Now we have at home
quite a considerable number of cyclist battalions, smart, well
trained, and enthusiastic, and each with its machine-gun detach•
ment. Their ranks, I beheve, are full, and their reserves, in
some cases at least, of equal number. It seems that these are
being kept in this country to perform a service which could be
rendered by much less valuable troops, to their exceedmg regret.
If the commanding officers of these battalions are anything like
as good soldiers as the one who wrote to me, we might expect
quite remarkable results 1£ they were given their chance in the
present war.
Such men naturally burn to be at the front, where I have no
doubt they would give a brilliant demonstration of the special
value of cyclists as fighting troops. I may repeat that I hope
the War Office may give this matter their earnest consideration.
I have the honour to be yours, &c ,
J. COOK WILSON.
1 They were sent on the 10th Nov They concerned (1) the destruction of
submannes, (11) the closmg to submarines of a passage through a maned area,
and (in) the destruction of contact mine&
• Pubbshed II Nov 1914. The article in 1.hf' Manchester Guard,an wa.'I
under date the 30th Oct 1914, and referred to a letter from Wilson in The
Times of the 29th October The Manchtslef' Guardian said, 'All honour to
those who have the capacity to thank for themselves an a science which of
all others most needs onganabty and independence of thought, the courage
to give their View'! to the world and the pat1'11ce to wait for thE'lr acceptance.•
STATEMENT AND INFERENCE
21731 B
ANALYSIS OF CONTENTS
PART I. INTRODUCTORY
I. THE DEFINITION OF LOGIC PAG'B
§ I. Logic, hke the sciences, begins with special problems, not with
a general definition of its nature and province 24
§ 2, One scientific problem suggesting another, cognate questions get
grouped together Reflection on such organic groups is a new
land of thmkmg 25
§ 3. This generahzmg tendency is due neither to logiccu thought nor
to the impulse towards definition Definition is the search for
a universal to cover a whole subJect and thus to permit its
differentiation . , 26
§ 4 Coherent problems do not necessarily belong to the same science.
Ancillary sciences 27
§ 5. The true nature of abstraction, a gradual realization of a common
universal . 27
§ 6 The ideal of definition. Definition and classification cannot even
m a priori ,;c1ences precede their development Logic 1s no
exception 28
§ 7 No defirutton of logic nor explicit recognition of it as a special
department m Anstotle's works 30
§ 8 Modem attempts to define logic Prov1Siona.lly it may be called
some kmd of study of thought m d1stmctton from a study of
things 32
XVII DE:FlNlTION
§ 173 Dehmt1on 8b (a) bearch for the esi,ence, (b) proceedmg byget1u~
and dijferent,a • 377
§ 174 The object of defimt1on. Artifi.ciality'IOf Anstotle'b acwu11t 378
§ 175. Definition applied to moral notions 379
§ 176. Definition 8b of esi,ence m opposition to property Anstotle's
account of essence ,• 380
§ 177 Two grave difficultie& mvolved in the idea of defi.mbon of essence 381
§ 178. Div1S1on and defi.mtlon The relation of definition by essence to
defimbon by genus ,1.nd dsffiwen#ia 382
5 179 By definition, bC1ence gaim1 both m cleames~ ,1.nd 111 extent.
True scienbhc propositions are convertible lhe search for
analogous elements arises from the di!:ttmcbon of genus and
d1Jferent,a 'lhe progress of science 383
I 18o The reason why science prefers one kmd of clas!:t1fi.ca.t1on to
another 384
VOLUME II
PART III. INFERENCE
I. THE GENERAL NATURE OF INFERENCE
I 208 Inference regarded as the study ot certain ways of reaching
op1mons and Judgements Concl•n and proof are words of
ordinary speech, not technical logic:tJ terms • 412
f 209. Inference d1Stmgu1Shed from e:r.perl.ence. Ongmatlve and recep-
tive activity. Denvation of one fact-from other facts. MntJ
inference and direct apprehens10n • . • 413
I 210. Dlssatzsfact1on m regard to inferred laiowledge, Intr1ns1c and
e:xtnns1c evidence There may be different lands of inference 414
§ 21·1. Provisional account of inference Difficulties in the Vle'WII of
formal logicians Pure thought, imagination and experience • 41 s
I 212. The d1Stinction between prem1'ls and conclu'11on Novelty of the
conclusion • 416
14 TABLE OF CONTENTS
PAGB
1213. Mediate and immecba.te inference • • 417
1214 All inference is strictly speaking 11nmedia.te • 418
1215. Limitation of the idea of immediate inference in the ordmary
syllogistic logic. Form and matter of inference , 419
I a 16 Im.mediate mfereru:e Relation of the conclusion to the premiss 42 J
f 217. The mconceivab1hty of the opposite as a cntenon of truth • 424
f 218. Reality of the advance in knowledge made in an immediate
inference 42 S
f 219 Certain proces,es which seem hke a repetition of the premJ.SSeS
but which simulate the verbal form of inference 42 S
I 220. Distinctions prerequisite to a theory of inference 426
f 22 J. Solution of the prccecbng d1fliculbes 427
1222. Inference in general is the apprehension of one fact as necessitated
by a different fact or facts • 429
§ 223 Immediate inference and the syllogism The conclus10n of an
inference, whether syllogi'!bC or not, is always immediate • 430
§ 224 The relation of apptthen,1on to proof 431
I 225 An instance of apparent dtfforonce between conclusion and
premisse'I . , 43 I
f 226 Sub1ectiv1ty of the idea of inference a.,; a connexion of 'Judge-
ments• 431
f 227. Prov1S1onal recogrut1on of the universal character of inference • 433
II SYLLOGISM
§ 228. Problem of the ~yllogisbc logic 435
S229. Limitation m the form of the solution proposed by the syllog1Stic
logic Two particular premisses can give a conclusion. Un-
d1str1buted middle 435
§ 230. The method of syllog1sbc logic 1s a priori and not analytical. It
1S not a branch of logic but a science hke mathematics • , 436
§ 211, The syllog1Sbc method does not proceed by' pure' thinking alone 437
§ 23z Formal logic 1s not an cwganon. The syllog1sbc 'rules• are
nugatory , • 438
t 233. A further bm1tabon of the syllogistic logic It 1s unsuitable m
form for quite simple arguments • . 438
§ 234 The syllogistic form is not the general form of demonstrative
reasoning. • •
I 23.5 The syllog1stic form 1s a species co-ordinate with other forms of
inference . • 441
1236. The middle term Syllogistic reasoning does not succeed in
abstracting all matter from its argument • • 441
f 237. The fallacious reduction of arguments to a syllog1'!bC form The
rule (ax1om) of syllogism fallaciously made a premiss . • 443
f 238. Relation of the conclusion of an mference from two premisses to
either premiss taken smgly 446
f 239 Apphcat1on of the preceding cons1derabons to the syllogism • 441
I 240. Relation of the conclusion to both premisses taken together.
The cohefttlce theory of truth • •, 449
124t. The reduction of one form of argument to another. Anstotehan
reduct10n. • 452
TABLE OF CONTENTS :r:5
III. PRINCIPLES AND METHOD OF PURE DEMON-
STRATIVE SCIENCE
PAGB
5242. Attempted use of the syllogism m demonstrative science. Geo-
metry is not syllogistic m method 454
5 243. Actual procedure m geometncal reasoning 455
§ 244 The imperfection of the geometncal figure. A new d1stmction in
our apprehendmg faculty • 456
§ 245. The apparent place of the syllogism in geometrical reasomng 457
§ 246 Geometrical advance 11l1Srepresented as the subsumpbon of a
particular case under a universal The true process is the
d1Scovery of the umversal m the particular instance 458
§ 247. The syllogism of proof 1s in fact only recognized by reason of the
analytical process of discovery. Memory of by-gone proof 459
f 248, Application of the preceding investigation to a.II demonstrative
syllogisms. Extension of Kant's principle m regard to mathe-
matical inference • 461
I 249. The particular <1yllogism regarded as a genera.l1zat1on of some-
thing apprehended m the particular instance 462
S2 50. The application of the universal to the particular 464
f 251, The fir,t principles of geometry, The postulates are theoretic
constructions 464
§ 252, The axioms are incorrectly d1stmguished from demonstrations.
Both are based upon mtu1bon 465
I 253 Nommal and non-nominal definition m Euclid's geometry 466
I 254 M1Sconceptlon-; m regard to the nature of defin1t1on m science • 467
f 255. False d1Stmcttons between conceptions and Judgements that such
conceptions arc vahd for their obJects • • 468
f .l56 The difference between defimbon m mathematic~ and 1n the
empmcal sciences 46g
f 257 Essence and property Aristotle's d1stmction between them • 470
f 258 Essence m mathematical science 471
f 259. Rec1proc1ty of e~sence and property Condition and condit10ned.
Direct and md1rect proof in geometry A thmg may be both
self-evident and demonstrable 47 3
f 26o. Algebra and the science of pure quantity depend on perception
or 1magmabon for their reasoning 476
§ 261. The three uses of symbols or perceptual units. The processes
symbolized are not merely analytical • 477
VI SYMBOLIC LOGIC
§ 371 Symbolic logic conducts formal inferences by the aid of an
algebraic calculus • 635
§ 372 Though tlus logic pretends to be mathematical 1t must be studied
by the logician • • 636
§ -~73 The method of logic cannot be mathematical, because mathe-
matics 1s a special science and the methods of the sciences are
a part of logic's object matter 636
TABLE or CONTENTS
l'AG:S
I 374, TJus logic liOlves partu:ular scientdic problems and ignores the
real problems al logic 637
§ 375 Its general problem JS bllllphc1ty 1Wllf, 1ts 1,pecral problems may
be 111m11tely 111tr1cate b37
§ J76 Ongin of the &tudy Analogy of Iormd.l log1c to the science of
pure quantity Unw1,e choice of algebnuc symbols by thu,
logic C139
§ 377. The unllkehhood of the symbol!, oI one bClt.nce bemg &uited to
another. The danger that th1~ logic may confound terms w1th
units of quantity 640
§ 378 A and B representing classe&, AB &tand~ for what lb both A .and
B. MeanmgofA+BandA-B (4o
§ 379 Multlphcation of the ,;ymbols Boole's fundamental rule of
thought~=~ • 641
§ 38o. Symbolb of operation 1n mc1.illematiu, and m logic Un1ty
unfortunately chosen to -,ymbohze Rf'al1ty. Any empty
clasb =o • <>42
~ 381. If x 1 =not x, x+.!-'= 1 lb the fnndament"-1 cquct.bon Equations
of dichotomy 043
§ 38.1 A= B to be mterpreted oI the l.lasse-, m exten'i1on, not. m mtcru,1on 043
§ 383 '!he vital quest.ion for the calculu& 1s to expre&s all A 11, B m an
equation. The form A=vB, (where v=' -,ome ') 11, .i. bogu'i
equation 644
§ 384 Boolt.'s equation X\: '=o depends upon conceivmg all X 11, Y d.b
hypothetical, viz as conveymg no defirutc statement ~ to the
existence of X lhls fundamental equation i'i an 1l1U&1on 644
§ 385 Elimination 1n the calculu& Particular propo&1tion1, are sc1.1d to
unply the ex1Stence of their &ubJeCtb, raibe equivalence of
All X 1s Y to No XY 1 e'l:1-,tq lhe true contradictory of All
~~y 045
§ 386 D~proo{ by red ad abs of the above equ1vcllence <>47
§ 387 lhe true mferenl.e from AU X 1'1 Y 1'> all XY 1 1., YY 1, but lhlb
g1veb no equation 648
I 388. 1he attempted mathemat.u,al mtcrpretatmn of XY•=o Equa-
tion of 1mpos:,1bleb to zero • 649
I 389 x+ a-1 = I fal5ely mc1.kes reahty ml.lude unrcal1tlcs (1) All 1mpo&•
s1b1htles are equated to the same and therefore to one c1.nother,
(11) each unposs1b1hty 1s equated to zero 649
I 390. (1) and (11) above would be fallacies 1ll algebra lmagmary
quantities 1n modem mathematic'! The equation of 1mpos-
s1bles or 1mc1.gU1c1nes to one another 111volveb the equation of
c1.ll real quantities to one another 650
§ 391 Illu&tration from geometry. The equation of 1mpos1>1bleb mvolves
the equation of all realities to one another . 651
§ 392. Reasons why tlus paradonccl.l equating 111 adopted • 652
I 393 By the rules of the calculus we can show by red ad abs that
the equation of all unpob&lbles mvolves the equation of all real1, 653
It
§ 394. Meanmg m the calcalus of the mverse operation y . Proof by
the calculus that a real class JS part of unreality , • 654
I 395. All clilbliCs morcove1 can be.. proved to be pred1c..c1.ble oI one d.llothcr 656
TABLE OF CONTENTS
PAGS
f 396, True c:oncluaions may be drawn from fal.'le prenussea , 656
I 397, Why the trr0neous representation of Barbara JD the calcul\18 GOii
not influence the conclu&1on • • • 657
I 398. The equation of dichotomy. The cond1tlonal statement which
the equatJou includes lb employed and the erroneous add1t1on
which 1s necessary to make an equation 1S ignored 658
1399 The equational element 1S m fact never used m this logic, The
truth of its conclusions depends wholly upon the element of
predication 659
f 400. Distinction between categorical and hypothetical btatement.
Imposs1bilibes arc but the reverse of Necesi.ities That every
frue statement would involve every other must not be con-
sidered a fatal obJection to the calculus 659
Notes to Chapter 6 • 6oo
[• Derived from Ueberweg, Log,,;, I 51, and Lotze, Log,,;, t123, 121 and 1.57,
but the pomt goes back to Kant (Logu;, 1. 1, I 6 ct al.).]
Ths Dlfinitlrw,. of Logic
objects which is not attainable without definition, We want to
know not only the solution of problems, or how one necessitates
another : we also seek for their general connexion under some
unifying universal or characteristic. Our impulse is not satisfied
till we get a conception, the articulation of which we suppose
will cover the whole of the science or department of study.
The ideal of the definition of an inquiry is that while it covers
the whole subJect it should be such as to indicate within itself,
by its own differentiations, the total divisions of the subject.
It may then, by its very generality, indicate special fields which
ought to be, but have not at present been, mvestigated. For,
when we have the universal, we may discover species implicit
in it which may not as yet have been approached in the course
of the actual solution of the problems of the science in question.
This ideal definition cannot be obtained in every science because
we cannot always differentiate a priori the genus given by the
definition, and so determine a priori the species and the depart•
men ts thereof. For these latter may depend upon experience
to reveal their subject-matter. Yet the more the empirical
sciences advance, the more they progress to the unification of
their theorems on the one hand and to their ideal definition on
the other. They endeavour to systematize the knowledge which
they have, though clearly such systematization must always be
provisional.
In the exact sciences, where the method is a priori (what this
precisely means we shall determine later), 1 it might seem at first
sight that, after definition of the whole, the determination of
the subordmate definitions ef the parts mdicated by the general
definition might be possible by simple successive differentiation
a priori. For m such sciences we ran differentiate universals
into their species a priori and know that our classification is
exhaustive. Thus we may divide geometry into plane and solid
geometry. Then the study of plane figures may be divided into
that of rectilinear figures, curvilinear figures, and the combina•
tion of the two, and so on.
Yet this kind of differentiation is but of a limited character.
The actual working of a science, in the solution of its particular
problems, leads to departments of investigation and so to
I II 16, 243.
30 INTttODUCTORY
principles of classification, which we can arrive at in no other
way. Hence, these important differentiations of the province
of the science cannot possibly precede its actual development,
and the field cannot be mapped out at the beginning, a priori,
u a mere consequence of the general definition of the science.
Thus it turns out that not only in the empirical but also in the
exact or a priori sciences, we have to wait for the progress of
the science, in the solution of its problems as they occur, in
order to effect the successive differentiations of the general
notion of the science and to articulate its departments. To
take a simple instance, the division of triangles mto right-angled,
acute-angled and obtuse-angled depends upon the proof of
Euclid, Elements, i. 32. One example among many in a higher
department is the discovery of the Cartesian method of co-
ordinates, which brought with it classifications of geometrical
subject-matter unsuspected before. The reason of this will
appear hereafter when we have seen what the method of the
mathematical sciences really is.
It is important therefore to observe that the differentiation
of the definition of an mquiry depends upon the particular
subject-matter and can therefore only be effected by scientific
thinking proper, not by philosophic or logical reflection. In
logic, too, we must expect that the differentiation of the depart•
ments to be investigated will depend mainly upon the develop•
ment and discussion of particular problems, and that 1t would
be as futile here as m science to try and formulate a complete
scheme of its subjects beforehand.
§ 7. Logic, as the history of Greek philosophy shows, is no
exception to the rule which has governed the development of
the sciences. It began without any definition of itself. Even
after logical inquiry had become more or less independent and
methodical, it remained without any such defi.mtion. In Plato's
case this is not surprising, for, though he made some contribu-
tions to logic proper, these are not advanced so far as to make
it obvious that they form a separate provmce of philosophical
investigation. Aristotle however has become conscious of the
separate nature of the subject, for he thinks of it as a whole
and has devoted special treatises to it. Yet he neither gives
a definition of it nor has he anywhere a discussion of the sphere
The D,ji,MM of Logic
peculiar to logic, Of the inquiriet grouped together at the head
of his works and commonly styled the Organon, the Categoriu
has not even the pretence of an introduction. The Prior
Analyacs opens with a few lines which profess to sketch the
subject but, with the exception of one line, we find merely
a summary of the first chapter. The subject is said to be
• proof ',1 properly the subject of the Posterior Analytics, This
book (one of the author's most mature works) begins in truly
Aristotelian fashion with a general proposition, ' all teaching
and learning of an intellectual kind arises from previously
existent knowledge '. 11 This is not a definition of the subject
he is about to mvestigate ; it suggests however what is more
clearly expressed in the opening of the Prior Analytics, that his
main intention is to discuss inference. If so, the discussion of
propositions, for example, might have come in as subordinate
to the general purpose. The De lnterpretatione has a more
systematic opening than any other of these treatises. It dis•
tmguishes thought from things and language from thought.
But, though enumerating particular topics to be discussed, it
has no general account of the subject as a whole. Moreover, its
style is scholastic and it is a bare analysis of the early part only
of the De lnterpretatione itself. Nor is there in the body of the
Organon any attempt at a definition, and the only thing like
a general name for logic m Aristotle is Analytics ; 8 even that
is not intended by him to designate all the treatises in the
Organon.
We should naturally look for some definition of logic in
a passage of the De AnimtJ 4 where he classifies the various
forms of knowledge. But, though he is there speaking of philo•
sophy as well as of the sciences, he does not mention logic even
indirectly. We may conjecture a reason for this. He is thinking
of the processes of the attainment of truth and may very well
have thought of logic not as a process of this kind; that is,
not as a study by which we add to our positive knowledge but
rather as an analysis of the mental forms and processes which
1 D•,2 drilr,£11,, 1111E ,.,~IA'I' dwoh11rT1djr. See however my A nstotelian Sluds,s,
D
II
THE RELATION OF KNOWING TO THINKING
§ 9. THE descnptton of logic as bemg some kmd of investiga•
tion of thought m d1stmctton from things may seem a ~e
enough generahzatton, yet we shall see that it involves certain
difficulties. Before cons1dermg the d1sttnctton we may naturally
ask for a definition of the word thought itself. The thought with
which logic has to do seems obviously connected with knowledge,
and, 1£ we examine the normal usage of the word in English,
we shall be led to the view that this connexion of th10king with
know10g 1s a universal charactensttc of the word. We shall also
see that we can give no defi01t1on, 10 the ordmary sense of that
term, either of thmkmg or of knowmg or 10deed of certam words
cognate with these.
In exam10mg the meanmg of a word such as ' thought ' in
philosophy, we must remember that it 1s a term of ordinary
language. It may have acquired, rightly or wrongly, some
different mean10g 10 philosophical wnt10gs and we must be
careful not to confuse the two. Thus 111 the philosophy of
Berkeley thought comes to be used in the general sense of
consciousness. Tlus is ahen to the normal use of language ; but
the philosophy of Berkeley and the alhed systems have come
so murh into vogue, that we are m danger of forgetting this
and falling into confusions. 1
Let us then first endeavour to follow actual linguistic usage
and take for granted the application of the name thinking to
certa10 kinds of consciousness and its exclusion from certain
other kinds. We shall then ask what is common to the things
1 So also Locke's use of the word ' idea • • was aben and still remains ahen
to the normal usage of ordinary English And the vogue of the phdosophy
of Locke has popularized a confusion
[• 'Some immediate obJect of the mind which 1t perceives and has before
1t' Epistle to Reader in An Essay, &c , cf Letter I to Stlllm.gfleet. The
word 11 used by Hobbes, but witltout emphas1S, m this aense, e.g. Lo11e, i 5,
§18and9]
The Relation of Knowing to Thinking 35
to which the name is applied. Thinking then, in its normal
use, always has something to do with knowing.
There is some knowing, viz. the process of reasoning, to which
the name ' thinking ' is applied without any doubt. It is true
that, according to an idiom of our language, when we prove by
reasoning that the angles at the base of an isosceles triangle are
equal we should not be said to think that the angles are equal,
but to know that they are. We might therefore vaguely suppose
that perhaps the process of reasoning is to be called thinking
and that knowing 1s the result of such a process. This would be
a mistake ; for the process of reasoning is precisely the activity
of knowing, as will become obvious when we discuss inference,
and here, therefore, the ordinary idiom encourages a fallacy.
Thus then there is a certain kind of knowmg, which must be
called thmking 1f anything is.
But, on the other hand, there are activities, often, at least,
called knowing, which would not be called thmkmg. If every
apprehension of the nature of an object is taken to be knowledge,
then perception (or at least some perception) and the appre-
hension 1 of a feelmg would be knowledge ; yet, according to
the natural usage of language, they would not be called thinkmg.
This is probably because we regard thmkmg as an originative
activity of our own (not that we have clear ideas either of activity
or of origination), whereas we regard neither our perceptions nor
our apprehension of feelings as originated by ourselves. On the
other hand, the comparison of feelings, or of perceptions in
general, we do regard as thinking, because we seem to ongmate
these processes of comparison ourselves. Thus the apprehension
of relations, either of some or of all of them, is accounted
thinking, and probably the apprehension of universals 1s similarly
always taken to be thinking, as depending on acts of comparison.
If then some perception I is knowing, there 1s some knowing,
i.e. the experience of perceiving and feeling, which is not
accounted thinking.
1
Having a mental state, for instance a feeling, whether 1nvolvmg our
apprehe11S1on of 1t or not, 1s not, as such, to be 1dentmed with the appre-
he11S10n of the state For the mental state of desmng, e g , 1S not an apprehen•
sion of desinng, nor 1s 1t any kind of apprehension
• On perception .&nd thmking, cf. H 13, 4S, 146, 209, 263
D2
INTllODUCTORY
Again, as not all that might be called knowing is thinking
so also not all thinking is knowing.
The formation of opinion is undoubtedly called thinking ; but,
though based on knowledge, it 1s not knowing. Indeed, according
to the English idiom already referred to, if we say we ' think '
A is B, it is understood that we are not prepared to say we
• know ' A 1s B. We are accustomed to say ' I don't know but
think so '. Opm1on, in fact, is a dec1s1on that something is
probable and, though not a decision of knowledge, is based upon
~ ur knowledge of the evidence available.
Further, there is something still more remote than opinion
from knowing which would be called thinking, viz. questioning
or wondermg. •
When we have not got to the truth which we happen to be
seeking, nor formed an opinion about it, but are wondering what
is true and putting questions to ourselves about it, we should
be said to be thinking. This certainly is the ordinary view, and
it seems natural enough when we reflect that this wonder is the
force which brings mto play that thinking which is the invest1ga•
tion of a given problem.
In an inquiry, first comes this questioning activity when we
set a problem to ourselves This implies that we know some-
thing of a given subject but are ignorant of some aspect of it
which interests us. We put to ourselves questions. our attitude
1is obviously not that of knowing, nor even of having an opinion,
c• Ultimately from Anatotle, ' Mal id, afdarrN& ,..1. "" .,,.. lunar
t r .r.,,,.., mllllldAov lnw, ol'w M,--, ', An. Po. 1ooa 16 Wilson is
doubtleu ftfernng to the current Oldord ideahsm. • The sunplest act of
pm:eption is a judgement• was almost a commonplace then, cf. T. H. Green,
Wora, u, pp. 170-2; and • In all human perceptaon thought is pre&ent, 10
too thought 1s the 111Uversal in all acts of conception, recollection, &c.', and
again • Man therefore is always thinking, even in lus perceptions ; if he
obeervea anything, he always obeerves 1t as a 111Uversal ', Hegel, I. c., f 24 (r).J
46 INTRODUCTORY
of the element in it which we seem in no way to originate ; an
element also which seems to be what is mainly important in the
matter.
Consider a sensation and our knowledge of it. The mere
having a sensation, though 1t is consciousness, is not knowledge
and must be d1stmguished from apprehension. To know what
a sensation is I must recognize 10 it a definite character which
dist10guishes it, e g, from other sensations. I recognize, let us
say, thc1,t 1t is a pam, and then agam a burn10g, or a prfcking,
pain, as the CJ.se may be. But this implies comparison of pain
with other sensations and other pams; and thus by the activity
of comparing we go beyond the mere passive state of being
pained, and this activity we are sure, ex hypothesi, is thinking.
Thus though the sensation is not orig10ated by us we require
an originative act of consciousness to apprehend it.
The same is true of other obJects of consciousness 10 percep-
tion, which we do not ordinarily suppose to be sensations,
e g. objects seen as extended m space. Whatever passive
element there 1s (and we certainly do not suppose ourselves to
origmate the shape and colourmg of thmgs) the apprehension
of the characteristics of what we perceive mvolves a comparison ;
and comparison we take to be thinking. If this ts so, the knowing
part of perception would after all be thmking and the distinction
whereby the knowmg 10 perceptmn was excluded from thinking,
would only be a popular inaccuracy.
Yet here we must be careful to avoid an overstatement. It
is not fair to condemn the ordmary view wholly, nor 1s it safe :
for, if we do, we may lose sight of something important behind it.
Distinctions current m language can never be safely neglected.
In what we ordinarily recogmze as comparison we have before
us two obJects at least and apprehend each of them distinctly.
As we should say, we are thinking of the nature of both. But,
in the apprehension of the definite quality of a given sensation,
we are as a rule not consciously comparing it with the quality
of another sensation which we distinctly remember and so have
before us. We are not concerned primarily with the qualities
of other things, but only with the quality of the object before
us : our interest is 10 it and not in them and the fact seems to
be that we have a consciousness of 1t as havmg a quality differing
The Reltition of Knowing to Thinki,ig 47
from that of other objects in general, but not a consciousness of
other objects in detail. The particular qualities then of other
things being in abeyance m this way and our interest being in
the distinctive quality recognized in the object, we can under-
stand how the fact that there is a comparison comes to be
overlooked and how we seem to be merely appreciatmg the
quality of the object by itself In short, we are really comparing
but do not recognize that we are. This then shows that the
comparison in this case (though obviously necessary to recog-
nizing the quality of the obJect as something distmct m itself
and not just to be confused with anything at all) is different
from ordmary comparison, and requires special recognition.1
• The sub1ect of the d1&tmct10n of thought from perception will be resumed
later m the discussion of universals, § 146.
LOGIC A~D COGNATE STUDIES GE.SERAL
A~D SPECIAL LOGIC
[• No reference given Perhaps he was thinking of• II est vra1 qu'd ne faut
point s'1magmer qu'on pu1s,e bre dans l'Ame ces etemelle& 101s de la ralSOn
a\ bvre ouvert ma1s c•e~t assez qu'on le~ pu1S&e tlecouvnr en nous a\ force
d'attention a quo1 le~ occasions sont foum1es par IC'! sens', Introd, and the
passage about the Chmese language ending, • c•c~t ams1 qu'on pos~de b1en
des choses sans le savo1r • Book I,§ 21 Cf Lotze, Logic,§ 358)
3 773 I E
50 INTRODUCTORY
that the forms of thmkmg might necessitate something m the
object to be thought about. Now, 1f that were really possible,
we could not intelhg1bly represent any object as contradicting
them, for to do so we must thmk abo1:1t 1t and, tf 1t possessed
attributes contradictory to what the forms of thmkmg demand
m 1t, 1t simply could not be the obJect of thought. S1mdar
cons1derat1ons apply to the forms of apprchens10n m general.)
Not only arc the formc, a priori m this sense, but so also 1s the
method of their mvest1gat1on For, though first recogmzed in
particular inc,tanccs of their use, they are at once seen to be
mdependent of them, smce otherwise we could not go beyond
the mstr1nces analysed, except by way of conJecture Now we
have a ccrtamty of their umvcr,;ahty wluch 1s mcompat1ble with
.m a postertort ongm Thought can recog01.:e 1ts own laws by
rcflectmg upon itself
~ 17 Grammar cannot be simply d1-;tmgmshcd from logic on
the ground thc1t 1t dral., \\1th lr1nguage wlule logic deals with
thought Grammar deal~ with lang•uge only as the symbol of
thought, a,; enahlmg us to understand thought when expressed
in words Thus 1t '>l'ck-; for general formc;; of cxpress10n which
have the same kmd of rnd11Terencc .is log1rnl form!> to the c;pcc1fic
cont mt rxpres!><:d, and c,omettml's thc&e general forms comc1de
with the log1ral forms Their prmc1pal difference 1s that logic
deals with thought qmlc generally and m absturt10n from any
particular hngu1c;t1c mode of expression (though 1t 1s true that
log1c1anc, may be greatly 111fluenced by the form'> of expression
111 their own languagt·) , gramm,tr treats of forms of thought so
far as they h.i,·e bernmc recognized 111 hngu1st1c formc; Forms
of thought get direct rcrog01tlon m grammar ""hen in the
language studied there happen,;; to be a general word-form
correspondmg to them or some kind of general rule For
example, noun~ have not all the ~.1me termmat1on m a given
language, yet tlwy all ~tand under the same set of rules m
relation to verb-; Forms of thought get also an indirect recogm-
t1on \\ hen the different species mto which the form subd1v1des
have special word-form'l corresponding, though the general form
itself which comprises them all has not Clearly then logic and
grammar so far agree 111 that both involve a study of forms of
thought applicable to all kinds of obJects. Grammar however
Logic and its Cognate Studies 51
is the more hmited in scope, because it studies them primarily
only so far as they have received expression in the general
word-forms of a given language.
§ 18. If psychology meant the study of mmd in general, logic
would only be a part of 1t, but then the same would be true
of ethics, politics, aesthetic, the philosophy of history and the
theory of literature In practice psychology has not this general
scope; 1t has become a special study of a scientific character,
and in some ways 1s experimental and empmcal like the empirical
sciences Psychology 10 this narrower sense of the \\<Ord differs
from logic by mcludmg subjects which logic exdudes, for example
the practical and emotional aspects of consciou,;ness and ques·
tlons about the physical cond1t1ons of consc1ou,;ncss The real
difficulty m d1o;tJngmshmg the two comes m those departments
10 which they have m some sense a common ohJert, for psycho·
logy generally mrludes some study of the mental processes
connected with knowmg and behevmg, processe,; such as havmg
apprehensions or forming Judgements and opm10ns. It must be
confessed that the attempts often made to define the province
of psychology 10 d1,;t10ct1on from logic and other wgnate sub·
Jects arc vr1.guc and unsat1-,factory, for the truth 1,;1 success
depend,; upon ,;omc knowledge of logic and metaphysics, 10
wluch !.UbJcrts p,;ycholog1sts are not ..t.lway'> at home
In every ,Ht of thought we must recognize a twofold aspect.
In the first pl.tee, it appe,us a,; an event, when regarded as the
activity of J. particular thinker bccau,;c 1t happen,; at .• parti-
cul.ir time, and m a particular time-order with reference to other
events Agam 1t 1s connclted 10 th1,; time-order with all those
occurrences, physical or mental, which may be ,;aid to con·
tribute m any way to the fact that the per,;on thmkmg thinks
a particular thought at that particular time, for example the
thmkmg suggested by the sight of some memorandum we have
made. But there 1s another and a totally d1stmct a&pect 10
every thought , <tins aspect 1s <;imply the tl11nk1pg a:. thmkmg
about somethmg, an apprehension of somethmg, whether accom•
pamed or not by a conJccturc or a question about 1t.) This
aspect 1s the Sdme whenever the thought occur<; and is wholly
unaffected by that other aspect of the thought as an event. It
rs somethmg complete m itself, wholly mdepcndent of the time•
E 2
52 INTRODUCTORY
order as such and of anything which conditions that time-order
as a mere time-order.
It is quite true that (this aspect of the thought as apprehension
of a fact connects 1t with other thoughts as also being appre•
hens1ons, and through the nature of the facts apprehended ; it
is true also that) this very connexion (which we may convemently
describe as a connexion of the contents of the thought) may
cond1t1on the occurrence of a given thought as a subjective
act1v1ty at a given time. Nevertheless this connexion of the
thoughts (m respect of what 1s apprehended in them) 1s not
such temporal connexion at all. It may 10fluence but it cannot
be mfluenccd by the temporal order To take an example, we
may have the thought of a triangle. Now the content of that
thought necessitates a property of the triangle and we, appre-
hending the first content, may apprehend afterwards that 1t
neress1tates the &erond The reason of that hes m the objective
relation 1b,df Tlus, though appn,hended m time, 1s not a tem•
poral relation, and m it the two clements <l1stmgmshed as
corre.,pondmg to the two acts of thought arr not related as
before and after Tins d1stmct1on appears m every process of
learmng or mventmg a proof ; the various &teps are apprehended
by a particular lhmker m a certain order m time , 1t • takes
tum time' as we say to discover the argument, the amount of
time bemg conditioned by his mental capacity and his physical
state Here then the acts of thought seem to present them-
selves as events bearmg an essential relation to time, and even
camally connected with other events, (they may possibly even
havl' the appearance (though that 1s a m1smterpretation) of
bemg connected "11th one another m the temporal way of cause
and effect) Nov.. though this may be so, yet what the thinker
m this process understands, the meamng of the argument, does
not as such enter mto anv of these temporal relations That
meanmg obviously hes m the apprehension of the premisses and
of their connexion with the conrlus1on. The apprehension of
a premiss is something complete m itself and, whatever the
temporal occasion of the apprehension, what 1s apprehended is,
e:xcept m a sense to be presently explamed, entirely free from
temporal connexion and its temporal character may therefore
be ignored. S1mtlarly the connexion of the premisses with one
Logic and its Cognate Studies 53
another and with the conclusion is not temporal in the sense
that it has anything to do with the time taken to apprehend
it The relation of premisses and conclusion (as thoughts about
something,) is not that of cause and effect, nor even a relation
of succession in time The premiss is not an event preceding
the conclusion, for then it would be over and gone when we
reach the conclusion, whereas 1t 1s the presence of the premiss
which 1s the cond1t1on of our having the conclusion at all.
Premisses and conclusion are, m their essence, m no time relation
and, 1£ we tried to represent them as m time at all, we should
have to represent the various apprehensions as completely
synchronous in an mdiv1S1ble time
Now logic 1s concerned with our thoughts not as events but
with that side of them which 1s not event , 1 1t 1s concerned
with (their character as apprehensions of ob1ects, or as con-
Jectures and op1mons added to those appreheno;1ons; that is,
1t is concerned with) the truth or falsehood of what we thmk
Logic never considers the way in which we come to thmk a given
thought at a given time, except so far as the process is entirely
withm (the activity of apprehension as such,) and dependent
therefore on relations, which are entirely non-temporal, (between
the thoughts, apprehens10ns and so forth concerning a given
object matter), and not upon anything belonging to their
character as events It is true that we may trace such con-
nexions between the contents of our thought man order of time
m our own mmds, but m our apprehension of them the idea of
(this sub1ect1ve) time and everything temporal (wluch does not
belong to the nature of the obJect thought about) 1s abolished.
This gives us a distinction between logic and psychology in
so far as both deal with thought II Psychology treats thoughts
as events and, qua psychology, is mainly concerned with their
time-order , often indeed 1t has to regard the merely temporal
conditions under which the content of a given thought becomes
a matter of consciousness to a given thmker at a given time.
1
Mr Bradley gets mto great confusion about this charac.ter of thought.
Cf f 122
• The word psychological 1s too often used m a vague and confusing manner
even 111 logical treatises See, for example, S1gwart's Log1k, vol 1, § 32 (p 203,
bne g of German text 1873) [' No Judgement JS uttered without a psycho•
logical ground for its certamty ']
54 INTRODUCTORY
Moreover, (besides certam physiological conditions which are
absolutely nothing to logic,) psychology 1s occupied with (the
temporal conditions of) such phenomena as memory, association
of ideas, 1magmat1on m general, (treating a side of them which·
doe!> not belong to logic) and with processes necessary to per-
cept1on, (which logic as such does not consider. Nor, finally, 1s
logic concerned with what 1s paradoxically called the uncon-
scious mechanism of consciousness )
§ 19 It mu!>t not be suppo-,ed however that all consideration
of the subJective time-order 1s nece!>sanly excluded from logic.
Logic ongmated in the reflection of the mmd on its own sub-
jective arhv1ty, and 1s essentially concerned for example with
inference as a subjective act As such, mfcrence repre!>ents an
advance m knowledge 1mplymg a contrast with a prev&0us state of
mmd, before that realization of thought wluch 1s the result of the
process In the statement, too, with 1t., <l1stmctton of subJert and
predicate, a tnnr-order 1s, we !>hall see, mvolveci Tins cons1dera-
tion of the ttmc-ordt•r 1s ueces!>ary for log1c, \\ hatrver p!>ychology
may from 1t., pomt of view ha.ve to say, and nothmg whatever
1s here borrowed from p!>ychology a!> a science. But the d1s-
tmction of before and ,liter 1s treated quite differently m logic
and 111 psyd10logy. (In the d1-,tmct1011, for mstancc, of subject
and predicate, logic 1s concerned with the mere fact that the
apprehension correspondmg to the one precedes that which
corresponds to the other but not with anythmg else rel,Ltlng to
the tune; not with .my reason for the fact and ccrtamly not
with any temporal rea!>on for 1t nor, 111 general, with anything
cond1t10111ng the temporai sencs, qua temporal) In the case of
mference logic 1<; concl·rncd only with !>uch reasons for the time•
order a!> he 111 (the nature of the apprehension itself) If we
ask whether the concept1011 of a figure whose mtenor angles are
together equal to two nght angles could precede the conception
of a three-sided rect1hncar figure, the answer depends entirely
on the matter of the conceptions themselves, 111 other words on
the relations of what 1s apprehended
§ 20 (Though metaphysics has no generally accepted defim-
tion, the word 1s m frequent use and this 1s so far Justified
masmuch as 1t corresponds to a certam affinity, felt rather than
clearly understood, m the subjects to which 1t 1s applied Thus
Logic and its Cognate Stu.dies 5S
we feel that certam problems are rightly called metaphysical,
though we may be at a loss to define metaphysics ; Just as we
are sure that a certain act ts generous, though we might find
it difficult to define generosity so as to draw the lme between
it and justice. This 1s why philosophers are more likely to agree
as to what questions should be called metaphysical than upon
::my defimt1on of metaphysics. The vague popular conception
of it seems to be that it H, not science but philosophy ; and
further, not any philosophy but some lughcr kmd of plulosophy.
Logic, m a strict acceptation, and etlucs and politics may all
seem not to be metaphysics, yet we find questions occurrmg
m logic and also m ethics wluch we should naturally call meta·
physical. Examples of such questions arc, the reality of uni-
versals, the nature of causation, the problem of freedom and
necessity. The word metaphysic origmated m the name given,
by some unknown arranger of Aristotle's works, to the treatise
which Aristotle himself spoke of as concerned w1th First Philo·
sophy 1 and the name only means that the treat 1sc m the order
of his system was c011S1dere<l to come '.1fter The Physics',
although Aristotle's Physics would itself accordmg to our modern
usage be said to be mamly metaphysical
The popular idea of metaphys1cc; correi,ponds so far with the
contents of the Aristotehan treallse, masmuch as he thought
tlus first philosophy 1 to uc a higher km<l of study lo wluch his
Analytics was a prl'hmmary, and as moreover he does not mclude
etluci, w1th111 1t He also d1st111gu1sl,cd it from the sciences, as
treating of Bemg m general while they each consider some
special part of Bemg. Thuc; Aristotle's metaphysics mvest1gates
the elementary or fundamental prmciplcs, 2 and God as the
supreme and most perfect Bemg ) If we now try to formulate
what 1s essential m the affinity we feel between metaphysical
problems, perhaps it 1s truest to say that metaphysics ha!> for
its ultimate object and ideal a complete understanding of reality,
and that not as opposed to the thmkmg subJect but as mcludmg
the subject. It seeks at all events a completer understanding
than 1s contamed m the sciences and so 1t is bound to let no
assumption or presupposition pass unexamined. The sciences
are also mqumes mto the nature of reality, for they assume
I dpxal.
INTRODUCTORY
conceptions and statements which they use and develop, but
which, as sciences, they neither examme nor cnt1c1ze. Geometry,
for instance, assumes space, but, as geometry, does not criticize
it. Generally, scie11ce assumes the reality of ob1ects of a knowmg
or perce1vmg subJect and accepts a certain oppos1tion between
the two ; these presuppositions metaphysics cxammes. Logic,
such as Aristotle origmated, studies thought and brings to hght
its presuppositions, but still it makes assumptions which, as
logic, 1t does not investigate. Exammmg thought as the sub-
Jective element m apprehension and so assummg the difference
of subject and object, it assumes that m experience the subJeCt
can know (that the object is there and also) something about it,
it assumes m short the workings of thought as data and arranges
them. The criticism of these assumptions, (whether explicitly
faced m logical treatises or not,) 1s metaphysics Metaphysics
1s bound to raise the whole question of the nature of the relation
of thought to reality and therefore an ideahsllc theory of reality
such as Berkeley's belongs to metaphysics and not to logic
Similarly with subJects usually included under the title of theory
of knowledge We may l>ay then shortly · <science studies the
obJect1ve side of thought, logic the subJcct1Vl'), metaphysics
studies both and the relation between them But tlus 1s not
enough; metaphysics btudies them m a manner d1ffcrcnt from
that m wluch they are studied by logic and the sciences Meta-
physics (does not propose to add to the sciences w1thm their
own hm1ts ; for example 1t docs not study geometry m order
to develop new geometrical the,orems it tries to complete the
sciences m another \\ay, a way m ,,luch they cannot help them-
selves), by understanding both their prel>uppos1t1ons and the
orgamc connexion of the <.hffcrent parts of rcah t y "Inch are
severally studied by them
§ 21 'We can no\\ see how the 1,tudy of thmkmg, of the bemg
of the apprehending thought, may go beyond a strictly logical
activity and comprise subjects usually contamed under the term
theory of knowledge, for example, the vahd1ty of thought in
relation to reality {a problem wluch involves metaphysical
questions proper) or the reclhty of the umversal, and the pos•
sibihty of gcttmg knowledge from percept10n 1 two problems
which have also some relation to psychology. The association
General and Special Logic 57
of ideas seems to belong peculiarly to psychology, yet it comes
naturally into any discussion of knowledge. All such subjects
are united by the desire to mvest1gate thought as true,-this is
what relates them to logic , and though not parts of logic
proper, they are so connected with it that the logician is obliged
to consider them, JUst as the geometrician must study the theory
of proportion, though it belongs to the province of pure quantity.
On this account we must never· put aside a question on the
mere ground that it 1s metaphysical. It may be as necessary
to logic as the theorems of one science sometimes are to those
of another 1
§ 22 • A d1stmct1on 1s sometimes made between ' pure ' and
'applied' logic, which seems to be partly a legacy from an old
mistake about the theory of the syllogism and partly due to an
maccuratc d1stmct1on made m the sciences The terminology
1s borrowed from the d1v1s1on of mathematical science mto pure
and applied mathematics This agam 1s grounded on the fact
that the theorems of geometry and of the calculus of pure
quantity arc applied to the geometrical and quantitative rela·
twm, of bodies m movement or m eqmhbrmm 2
Now the old view of syllog1sttc inference was that 1t formed
the general method of all demonstrative mfercnce whatever, so
that the methods of the demonstrative sciences would be merely
an apphcat1on of the rules of the syllog1st1c theory ; they were
accordmgly called deductive sciences. Hence, perhaps, may have
arisen the idea that the logic of a particular deductlvt: science,
1 e the logical theory of it!> method, would be the application
of the general theory of demonstrative mference to its special
case. Similarly, when the theory of mduct10n began to have
I (,f § 4
[• Wilson frlt the difficulty of the metaphor of• grasping• Fmdmg a remark
on 1t m a pupil's note-book, he wrote a Ion~ note on the question wluch I do
not reproduce. An~totle used 9,-,Ei" (to touch), Metaph w51b 24. Cf Reid's
Inq1my (ed Hamilton), 2, § 3 note, and note to § 34 infra]
Theories of Knowledge and Reality 67
an object to grasp, we not only distinguish the object from the
grasping of it, but we never think of calling 1t a part of the
whole fact or activity of grasping. Nor do we represent 1ts
being as wholly comprised in that of grasping. Is then ' what
we think ' to be called ' thought ' in the ordinary sense, which
means ' content of thought · and 1s 1dent1cal with actualized
thought? In favour of this 1t may be said that 1t seems hkcly
to be right, because 1t is the natural and universal mode of
expression m ordmary untechmcal language, ancient and modern.
Tlus seems evidence that the distinction is not artificial, as the
mclusion of the grasped obJcct m the grasping ccrtamly would
seem to be.
!wen m the case of graspmg 1t might be said that though the
body grasped 1s not a part of the whole actuality of grasping,
yet its resistance to the pressure 1s inseparable from the
grasping and only comes mto existence when the object is
grasped
But the strongest argument m favour of what appear to be
the impltcat10ns of the ordmary use of language seems to be this.
If we say that thought proper (m the case of knowledge) is
nothmg but the apprehension of the obJcct, 1 e. the apprehension
of • what 1s thought', and that • what 1s thought' (i.e. the
nature of the obJcct) is not of the nature of thought or apprc•
hens10n itself, tlus abstraction of what 1s apprehended from the
apprehension of it, of what 1s thought from the thmking of 1t,
seems to make the act of thmkmg or apprehension en1pty and
meaningless. This argument is perhaps more convincing 111 the
case of a umvcrc;al proposthon, where we are not so much
influenced by the customary oppos1t10n between the mihvidual
tlung perceived and our perception or thought of tt. We apprc•
bend that the product of two odd numbers 1s odd. If now we
abstract what we apprehend here, the essence of the act of
apprehending seems to be gone. Hence the nature of \\-hat we
thmk seems m this instance to belong essentially to the nature
of thinkmg. There 1s a kmd of parallel to this in feeling ; there
is no feelmg apart from the defimte quality of what 1s felt-say
heat or cold-the idea of feeling seems altogether empty if we
abstract what is felt, the quality of what 1s felt ; and here, at
any rate, our ordmary attitude, whether nght or not, is to make
F2
68 INTRODUCTORY
the quality a part of the whole reality of feeling, and without
any hesitation.
Of these three considerations, the second appears to be of no
value, because this property of the object, viz. its resistance,
only gets reahzcd in the fact of its being grasped. The corre-
sponding feature in apprehension, if the argument is to be
relevant at all, would have to be that the properties of the
ob1ect known should only come mto ex1:;tcnce m the sub1cct1ve
act of apprchenclmg them That however would be m plain
contrad1ct1on not only to the ordinary view, with the language
of \\ luch wc arc at present concerned, but to the nature of
sc1cnt1fic knowledge. We have, therefore, to turn our attention
to the first and tlurd cons1dcrat1ons
§ 30. To hegm with the firr;t cons1dcrat1on, derived from the
natural moJc of lingu1st1c cxprcss10n It "111 prove in the end
that the phrase ',,hat we thmk about a tlung' is ambiguous.
There 1s a sense m which ' v. hat WL tlunk ' must be a part of
the activity of thinking and entirely '"1thin the being of thmking.
Let us see what is charartcn-;tic of the c-.1sc where it is so
natural to call' "hat \\e tlunk ', thought That seems to come
out mol:,t dearly Ill the kmd of thmkmg wluch 1s called opinion.
Suppose v. c arc of op1111011 that A is B, and it turns out we are
wrong. It would be said, m the natur..il use of words, that what
we thought was untrue · or, agam, that what we thought about
A was untrue Herc ' what we think ' cannot be the nature of
A, for the nature of A cannot be wrong or untrue. So far then
we have a fairly ckar distinction to JUsllfy the contrast between
'thinking about the tlung' and • thinking the thmg ', and
between' what we thmk about the thmg' and 'the tlung '.
We should say that '"hat v.-c thought' was untrue 1f the
opinion was wrong But then, if tins 1,; so, there must after all
be included m ' \\ hat we think ' the thmkmg, because 1t 1s only
the thinking that can be wrong ; and the fact 1s that what 1s
here termed 'what we thought', and said to be untrue, is a
particular act of thmkmg, in ,vh1ch the thinking is inseparably
included. It differs from thmkmg if thinking stands for a uni-
versal : for it differs from thinking 111 general as being a particular
realization of thmking. In the case then of opinion, it is easy
to understand how ' what is thought ' 1s included in the activity
Theories of Knowledge and Reality 69
of thinking in a way in which what is grasped is not included
m the activity of grasping.
The case where thmkmg means knowledge is obviously the
most important, for, as we have already seen, whatever is
mcluded under thinking depends entirely upon the notion of
knowmg. In this case also when we say that 'what we think'
is • thought ', or ' what we tlunk about anythmg ' 1s ' thought ',
we mtend, of course, not merely that the thinking of it 1s
thought, but that ' what we thmk ' is ' thought' m the sense
of that which makes the thought a real indiviclual thought as
opposed to the empty form of thmkmg m general. We should
also say that tlus thought ( :s what we thmk) is true masmuch
as it is knowledge, and consequently, as before, whether the
thmkmg 1s knowmg or opm1on, it follows that it necessarily
includes our subJectlve act.
It makes ~o difference, then, '" hether the thinkmg 1s knowing
or opm1on: the whole point 1s that we do attach these epithets
' true ' or ' false ' to ' what we thmk '.
Now, whether we know that A 1s B or form the opinion that
A is B, what Is the accurate answer to the quest10n ' What 1s
It we thmk about A? ' The accurate answer 1s, 'That A is
B '. With regard to the expression (observe) we can rightly
say ' that A 1s B is false', or ' that A is D is true'. This shows
that the expression ' that A is B ' 1s not equivalent to ' A's being
B' : for A's bemg l3 represents a fact which cannot be true or
false, so that when the tlunkmg 1s knowledge, and therefore
thmkmg A 1s B is true and is knowmg that A is B, the expres-
sion ' that A is B ' is still not equivalent to ' A's bcmg B ',
or 'the B-nec;s of A'. What we thmk about A 1s, m fact,
properly understood, always ' that A 1s B '. This, then, seems
to be the accurate expression for th.:it upon which so much
depends-' what we thmk about A'.
Our previous difficulty arose from makmg what we thmk of
A equivalent to the obJcct1ve B-ness or the ol>Jectlve ' A's
bemg B '. Can we say m any sense that m thmkmg A 1s B
(whether the thmkmg 1s opmion or knowledge) B-ness or A's
bemg B 1s what we tlunk of A ? The answer seems to be that
. we can and do, and yet that m truth the expression 1s not
accurate but abbreviated and idiomatic. It has mdeed, in the
INTRODUCTORY
last resort, to be explained as just meaning that we think that
A has B-ness or that A 1s B ; and consequently, when accurately
expressed, this explanation 1s precisely the same as the one
already given.
So far, m examining the identification of ' what we think '
with ' thought ', ' thinking ' has been used m the widest sense.
Dut our invest1gat1on of the various uses of the word thinking
has shown the importance of asking m every given case what
kind of tl11nki 11g 1s meant, when any such quest10n as the one
before us 1s raised about thmking In the case of op1111on, we
got our answer by considering precisely the kmd of thmkmg
meant-viz. opinion. In the case of knowing that A is B, our
thinking is the apprchcnc;1on of A's bcmg 13, or of the B-ness
10 A; and' what we thmk' of a tlung wluch we know 1s what
we apprehend m it and muc;t be part of its nature 1 If what
we thmk were accounted to be thought and mrludcd in thinking,
this would have to mean that what wc apprehend, the fact
of A's bcmg D, or the D-ncss of A, 1s mcludcd in the apprehension
as a part of the activity or reality of apprehcndmg. Obv10usly
this bst statement woul<l be quite ag,unst the usage of language :
and 1t is the usage of language that we arc cxammmg.
This shows that the use of language when properly understood
implies an 1dcnttficat1on of ' what we thmk ' with ' thought '
only when 'wh.i.t we thmk' 1s taken in the general sense m
wluch 1t mcludcs opmion, and 1s not the nature of the object
thought. Accurately, then, the ' what we tlunk' 1dcnttficd by
implication with thought m ordinary language 1s not a 'what
we think' abc;tr.t( tL·d from the tlunkmg of 1t, but mcludcs
mscparably our su1i1cctivc act of tlunkmg- 1t
§ 31. \\'e come now tu the tlurd conc;1<lcrat1on, for the pre-
ceding has by no mean,;; d1o;;poscd of that.
In kno\\ mg the n.iture of A as B, wc arc apprehending an
obJcct, ,md ' 'i.£ 1/iat we apprehend ' 1s an obJcct, and the apprc-
hcns1011 seems empty and no apprehension at all, 1£ we abstract
from 1t \\ hat 1s apprehended. Take that a\\ ay and what 1s left ?
Tins naturally mclmcs us to tlunk of what is apprehended as of
the bemg of the apprchendmg This time, undoubtedly, what
is apprehended 1s the nature of the thmg.
' § 27
Theories of Knowledge and Reality 71
Nor is this a mere theoretical development, for, as a matter
of fact, people do vaguely thmk of the • content ' of thought or
apprehension as being the main part of the reality of the apprc•
hcnsion itself: and persistently, m consequence, distinguish this
from the thing. To solve this problem then we shall have to
appeal to cons1deratlons of a more general kind, which are not
confined to the relation of thmkmg and its obJect, but apply
m general to things which arc related.
In popular thmkmg, at all times, there 1s a tendency to treat
individual existences as independent rcaht1cs and, though the
fact that they enter mto relations is recogni1,ed clearly enough,
to regard their rclat10ns as something external to the nature of
the things rcttterl, not as bclongmg to their own bemg. Tlus
which 1s 1mphc1t m the ordmary consc10usncss becomes explicit
m the bcgmnmg of philosophy, and it 1s what we find m
Aristotle a Rclallons arc d1stmguishcd from tlungs and are
excluded from the bcmg or essence of the individual thmg. In
many ways Locke in modern times remmds us of the position
of Aristotle m relation to his own day. For Locke may be
described as a plulosopher who makes explicit the tendencies
and 1mphcat10ns of ordmary popular thmkmg. It seems fair to
say of him that he treats the md1vidual substance as thus remote
from relations There 1s, m fact, a somewhat sharp distinction
between substances and relat10ns both m Locke and m Aristotle.
Modern metaphysics u has revised tlus view as 1t has become
clearer about the connex10n of tlus supposed md1fferent relation
\\ith what 1s called the essence of the thmg, and has come to the
conclusion that the severance of the two 1s artificial But, in
so domg, 1t has tended to advance to the extreme opposite of
the view it crit1c1zecl and more or less consc1ously to break down
the <l1stmct1on bet,-.ccn tlung'> related altogether.
It seems quite wrong lo exclude from the being of a tlung
anythmg wluch 1s necessitated by what we have t..ikcn to be
its bcmg, anythmg from which that is in">eparable For the
latter 1s a ncccsc:;ary clement 111 the complete ..iccount of the
[• In earlier lectures ' Plato and Aristotle '
b 'The general metaphysical theory • • overstatement•, p 72, refers to
Green, e g Wllf'ks, 11 170-2 Hts reaction against this view was fundamental
but he d1d not emphasize it in reference to Green. Cf. Part V, I 564.J
INTRODUCTORY
thing's being, though it may be different from that aspect of
the thing's being which we first had before us. Suppose A and
B are in a relation R. R is nothing without the special nature
of A and B, and th11s, 1f we follow the tendency above described,
we should say that 111 the being of R, in its completeness, must
be included that of A and B, and similarly B would be included
in the bemg of A TIHS would have to be the case even if R
were a temporary relation Suppose two bodies come into
collision ; the colhs1on 1s nothing "1thout the bodies of which
1t 11:, the colhs1on, and its special n.iture as th1s collision depends
on the special nature of these bodies On the other hand,
R itself similarly belongs to the special nature of A and B, so
that the nature of A or B in tlus way would be made to include
that of R
The apphcat10n of th15 lo the relation of the apprehending
and apprehended 1,; obvious We should be obliged to say that
the bemg of the tlung ".l!> included in the bemg of the relation,
the bemg of the t hmg apprehended somehow mcluded in the
being of the ,tpprchcns1on. We shall find that the general
mclaphys1cal theory wluch would lead to such a result 1s an
over:.ta.tement
If A stands 111 a relation R to B, even 1f R be temporary,
the bcmg of A 1s not mdependent of the bemg of B That 1s
true and accurate. Again the complete account of the being
of A must include the relation to B. That again 1s true and
accurate. But must we, therefore, include the being of B m
A, as seems the tendency m some modern metaphys1cians, and
would the use of ' include' here be accurate ~
The key to the ans\\cr 1s the fact that A and B, however
closely rcl.itcd, arc different and not to be entirely identified
with one another. The dependence of the one on the other,
however absolute, cannot destroy this difference. If now 111clu-
s1on 1s taken in a strict sense, as 1t ought to be, and the being
of B 1s to be mclude<l 111 that of A, for the same reason we
!.hould have to include the being of A in that of B This would
result in a contrad1ctlon, which would only be avoided 1f A and
D were ind1stingu1shably the same
Again, 1f "c take the ' bemg of A ' 111 the Jense of what A is,
then what is part of the being of A must be a part of what
Theories of Knowledge and Reality 73
A is. So we say 'heavy' is a part of what lead is, since lead
is heavy. Now, if this 1s a particular quality or kmd of thing,
X-ness, we must be able to say that A is X or A is an X, where
X is an adjective or a common term. If, however, X is a parti-
cular hke A itself, we must be able to say simply A 1s X, e g. that
flower is the one I bought yesterday. But if A is related to B,
we cannot therefore say that A 1s B, or A is /3 where /3 1s an
adjective or common term corrcspondmg to B. It 1s not accurate,
then, to say the bcmg of B 1s mcludccl m that of A, or the bemg
of A m that of B. On the contrary, m so far as we say A 1s
m the relation R to D, and m so far as it is the nature of A to
stand in this relation, A's bemg m the relation to B may be
said to be a part of the bemg of A. But A may have a being
other than this relation, a bemg not mcludmg it ; c g. if we
say A is near to B, this implies that A and 13 arc something,
have some nature, wlnch 1s other than this rclat10n, for mstance,
that A 1s a tree and B a house. Moreover, 1t 1s this nature,
other than the relation and not mcludmg it, which is what we
mean by A or B, and 1f we were asked what A and D were, our
answer would be a descnpt1on of JUSt tins nature In short, the
relation only obtams between terms winch arc different from one
another and as havmg natures wluch do not mcludc the relation.
Consider now the bcmg of R, the relation between A and B.
Tlns is relevant to our 1mmcd1atc prol,lcm, smce the appre•
hendmg of the obJcct may be said to be a relation between the
thmkmg subject and the object.
Our difficulty was that 1f we abstract what 1s apprehended
from the apprehens10n of 1t, apprehension seems empty and
meamnglcss. We saw, for instance, that 1f we abstracted a uni-
versal proposition apprehended from the apprehension of 1t, the
essence of the apprehcndmg itself seemed gone Thus the nature
of what we thmk or apprehend might seem to belong to the
nature of thmkmg or apprehendmg. Now, 1t 1s true of a relation
m general that 1t is inseparable from the terms rcl..i.tcd and that
1t seems empty and meaningless 1£ we abstract these terms from
it. Equality is essentially the equality of two tlnngs and we
cannot leave out the things. But docs 1t follow that we should
therefore regard terms related as havmg their l>emg mcluded m
that of the relation ?
74 INTRODUCTORY
Let us consider the example of a collision. This is nothing
apart from the bodies which come into collision : it is inseparable
from them. Abstract the bodies and the collision is gone also.
However, the very nature of the collision between two bodies,
A and B, ncccss1tates itself that A and B should be different
from one another It also necessitates that A should have
a being other than bcmg in colhs1on \\ 1th B, and 1t 1s only as
havmg c;uch bemg that 1t can enter mto the given relation with
B. Agam, while the bcmg of A is not mclu<lcd m and is not
part of the rolhs10n, on the other hand (m that wider sense in
which the bcmg of A is made lo include everything which
happens to A) the colhs10n would be part of A's bemg. But
1t 1s no part of that bcmg of A which 1s 1<lent1cal m all that
happenc; to 1t, and wluch would be called what A 1s ' m itself' .1
And the latter bcmg, wl11ch excludes the given temporary rela-
t10n, is the being already spoken of a,; necessary for A's entermg
mto the relation
We have, then, here a case \\<here n relation, though empty
and mcanmglcsg 1£ we abstract from 1t the terms related, 1s so
far from neccss1tatmg their mclus1on in itself that 1t necessitates
the contrary ; for 1t ncccss1tatcs that these terms must have
a bemg of their own which 1s not included m the bcmg of the
relation.
§ 32. This 1llustration seems enough to show that the insepar-
ableness of the apprchcm,10n from what 1s apprehended docs not
warrant the co11clus1on v. luch 1t seemed to suggest The truth
is, that Just as the coll1,;1011 with I3 1s only possible through
a bemg of 13 other than 1t!., rommg mto colh-.1on, and 1t is with
B as h,wmg sue h hl'mg that the colhs1on t..1.kcc; place, so also
the apprchcn<,1011 of an oh Jct t ,.., only poc:;c:;1blc through a bcmg
of the obJcct other I han its hcmg ,tpprchcn<lccl, and 1t 1s tl11s
bcmg, no part 1t 5clf of the apprchcn<lrng thought, winch 1s what
is ,tpprchcndcd.
Thus, 1f an obJcct 1!. apprehended, 1t does not follow that
merely because 1t 1s apprehended 1t must be a part of the nature
of the apprehension, that 1s part of the apprehcndmg conscious-
ness If that ,,ere so 1t would be entirely mental or, m general,
a state of consc10usncss. \\•hat 1s apprehended, or the obJect
I H 70, 71.
Theories of Knowledge and Reality 75
apprehended, may be a state of consciousness, yet even then-
it would not be a part of the apprehending consciousness ; or
agam it may not be a state of consciousness. VVhich 1t 1s can
only be determined by an examination of the nature of the
object in question itself and certamly not from the mere con-
s1dcrat1on that 1t 1s apprehended in general, or is an obJccl of
thought. Y ct it 1s this consideration wluch 1s the sole basis of
such 1dcahsm as Berkeley's, and, one may ask, 1s there as yet
any system of idealism of wluch this 1s not true?
§ 33. We have seen m what sense the habit of making ' what
we tlunk ' belong to the nature of thought itself may be JUStlficd.
On the other hand, when' ,,hat we Lhink' means what 1s appre-
hcncled, what 1s thus thought or apprehended is an obJect wluch
1s not to be reduced to J. part of the bemg of tlic apprchendmg
thought Yet tlus 1s actually donl' by 1mplicallon when the
idcnt1ficabon with thought of 'what we tlunk' (or the so-called
content of thought) 1s applied to the apprehension of the nature
of the obJect. For the only thmg that c-an be found as' content'
of the apprehcndmg thought 1s the nature of the obJcct appre-
hended. The mistake however is not noticed because thinking
is still supposed to be tlunking something about the tlung and
not thinking the tlung, whereas, if the act1v1ty of consc10usness
1s to be called 111 tlm, case tlunkmg at all, it must be tlunkmg
the thmg
But now, m discussing the d1ffirulty about the belong"ing of
the ob3cct to the being of the apprehending thought, we have
been led to sec th.it conversely, m the wider sense of the being
of the obJcct, there belongc, to tlus bcmg the fact of its being
apprehended, and therefore the apprehension. As the way m
which the obJect bdong'l to the being of the apprchenswn docs
not rc<lurc the obJcct to terms of the apprehending thought, so
also th1'l bclongmg of the apprehension to the bcmg of the obJcct
does not warrant our reducing the bemg of the apprehenswn to
terms of the ob1cct nor make 1t of the same kmd Neverthcle'>s,
this latter is Just what 1s 1mphc1tly done m the old theory of
knowledge of thmgs through idcas-wl11d1 really still mfluenccs
people who would unhcs1tatmgly rcJect it when put to them
explicitly-for the idea in quest10n 1s notlung but a sort of
mental replica or reproduction of the obJect, sometimes called
INTRODUCTORY
a copy, and the apprehending of the object is reduced really
to having such an idea; that is to say, is reduced to the existence
of such an idea in the mmd.
• Theories of kr.owledge and reality, in the futile attempt to
explain apprehension (1 e. to explam the absolute presupposition
of any explanation), have been much affected by these two con·
trary and one-sided tendencies, earh of them an overstatement
of the mterconnexion of the bemg of the obJrct and the being
of the apprehending thought ; the tendency to reduce the obJeCt
apprehended to terms of the apprehension of 1t, and the tendency
to reduce the apprehension to terms of the object. Now neither
can be reduced to the other ; neither expressed or explained
in terms of the other.
[• Cf Part V, §§ 54r-52 ]
PART II
[• The last paragraph 1s exaggeratedly put ' rulu, • m tins sense Logic 1s
called an Organon, see§ 232)
2773•1 G
82 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
that the kind of questions to be asked about verbal statement
and the nature of its analysis were suggested by the interest in
discovering the general forms of inference. Inference, m its
verbal cxprc,;sion, bcmg made up of statements, the search for
a general form of inference leads to a determmatlon of the
general form of 1,t,1temcnt, with its cl1v1S1on mto species. And
the clement!> wluch arc d1'>tmgu1shccl w1tlun the form arc of
a kmcl suggtsted by the contemplat1on of a syllog1st1c argumcnt. 1
Nc,w the <l1stmct1on w1thm the verbal form of statement
arrived at with such an mterest m mm<l-a d1stmct1on sub-
servient to the ana]y1,1s of the syllog1sm-1s one which belongs
to the being of the object and not to our apprehension of it,
and so 1s not logical Tbat a distmctlon wluch belongs to tlungs
should be discovered through the medmm of the statement is
not surpnsmg, for the statement dec;rnhes the nature of the
thmg, and to the ohJcehvc d1stmrt10n m question corresponds
a verbal d1,;t mrtion ,, 1thm the gener.tl form of the statement.
It 1s quite nght that the d1..,tmc.t1on arrived at should be, not
a logical one, but \\1lhm the nature of the ohJcct, because it 1s
such a d1c;t111ct10n \\ Juch is nccc•c;c;ary for the purposes of syllo-
g1st1c mfcrcncc, a,; "ill .tppC'ar on e::,.,.an11nat1011 Y ct, though
not a log1cal but a mct..iphys1ral conception, 1t has a true place
111 logic because' 1t 1c:; the result of a log1r.il mqu1ry and 1s mtro-
duccd as ncc.cc;sary to the solut10n of a logical problem
But, though 1t 1s an ob1cct1w <l1stmct1on which 1s made and
used, the ordinary logic docs not realize thnt 1t 1s so and actuaJly
confuses 1t in tcrmmology with a truly log1cal d11,ttnction, that
of subJcct and prcchcah' Y ct the t\, o arc so chfTerrnt that
\\ luk the d1stmct1on m quc,;t1011 1s m <'l''-'mry to syllog1o;t1c theory,
the du,tmc t10n of suhJeC.t ,111<1 prc1h<'ate 1s ah<:olutdy useless to
th,\t theory. l'ar,ulox1ully t·nc,ugh t hL· tc-rm111ology of suh1cct
and pn•chratl' 1s ah, a) s used m the prc..,l·nta t10n of the syllog1stic
theory, "1thoul ho\\cvcr producmg conf u!>1on The reason is
that the erroneous termc:; ,\re Ile.\ er usC'd 111 that theory m their
proper senc;;c, but arc confined to the ohJcct1ve <l1stmct1on, and
what 1s really me.mt 1s made rk.1r C'nough for practical working
by the symbolism adopted. ~ot uncommonly those who apply
a pnnc1plc rightly 111 particular cases arc unable to give a correct
• Thi~ pomt 1i, rC'i,umcd m §§ 61-2
A pprekension in General 83
account of its general character. The confusion in this case
comes from a mistake about the meaning of verbal forms m
relation to 'predication', and the exact nature of the objective
d1stmct1on of wluch we have been speaking will have to be
reserved for a special 111,·cst1gat1on, where \\ e shall show how
the confus10n makes itself felt m a noteworthy utterance of
Aristotle's upon predication 1
It 1s mdeed possible that the idea of a general form of state-
ment and of its analysis mto such ekments may have been
growmg up already through the interest taken by Greek thmkers
m the metaphys1c..il questions of the umty of a thing m its
attributes and the umty of the universal m its particulars. To
the former correc:;pond:, Ill statement, as Plato says m the Sophist,
the calling of one thmg by many names; to the latter corre-
spondc; the callmg of many tlungs by the s.1me name. Never-
theless the analysis of the syllogism probably brought with 1t
the precise formulation and actual symbolism, for v,e do not
find this before tl,e '"ork of Aristotle, and it is connected with
the characteristics of the syllogism m a i:.trikingly direct manner.
How far the analyi:.1s arrived at m logic was promoted by tlw
contemporary progress of grammar v,e cannot say, for we know
so little about the l.ttkr Grammar doec:; presuppose that the
.1b~tract10n of a general form of statement- the sentence-has
been arrived at, and that would facilitate and perhaps influence
such a treatment of the propoi;1t1on as \\ e find m the logic of
Aristotle On the other hand, the analysis which he reached 1s
not a grammatical one; 1t docs not coincide with the distinct10n
grammar proper makes w1thm the sentence, either of clauses
(for these arc altogether 1gnore<l) or of parts of speech. The
,tnalys1s however, "Im h the syllog1~m would n.tturally i-.uggei:.t,
hes to hand, the '-'Cry name mdcc<l under winch state-
ment 1,; invest1g,LI c<l 111 this loe;1c 1s not a gr.Lmmatiral one, but
derived from argument m debate For propo1>1t10n 2 me.1nt
1 § ;z
G2
84 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
originally a premiss put forward in discussion, to be accepted
and argued from, or to be questioned and argued against.
§ 38. Logic, m some· rc<'ent books, has followed the ancient
trad1t1011 111 Legu,mng "1th "liat 1s m fact the !i>tatcmcnt and
its analysis Tl11c; 1c;; trul ,1l'>o of the more .idvanccd and ph1lo-
supl11c modern log1r, though 1t profec;c;cs to ch.,cuc;s a mental act
called JU<lguncnt an<l not the verbal cxprcsc;1on of that act a
Thus, m llm more advanrl·<l modern lo~1c, we find the term
JU<lgl·ment .,nb!'itltuted for the propoc:;1t1on an~l the enunciat10n
of the olcl logw Tim, no doubt ,trosc be.cause the older tcrmmo-
logy sterned to the more plulosoplll( pornt of view madequate
to log1t rcgar<lc<l as the !>Ludy of thmkmg 1 he propos1t10n
wac; -.o 11,1mul ongm,illv on ,1crou11t of 11!> rclatwn to debate,
and cnunn,tt1on too refn., to the verbal cxprc.s..,1oll A!> 1t, \\as
hd<l tli,tt I he mtentwn of logic\\ ,ts prmwnly to cxamme thmkrng,
and verbal t''("prc~c..wn only c..o f.1r a-. c..u!J<,1dury to th1::, ob3ect,
the word Judgement c;tcmul more arrurate ,rnd w,ic; ac.cordmgly
c;ubc;t 1tut ct! for the tl rm pir,poqt1011 Tl11s, ho,\ cvrr, \\ ac; done
without a full .ipprct 1,1!1011 of thl ronseqm llCL'> ,llld the result
h,1-. been a Ll'Ttam ,111101111! of c ontuc:;1011 'J he11· 1~ " furthc.r
eonfu,1011 111 the cli,-,t m, l 1011, uc..u.1! 111 tlrn, ach .imed logic, bet,, ccn
.l tl1eory of mkrcntl' .ind a thl·ory of J11dgcnwnt, and about the
true n,1tun· of tJu.., ~croncl rnqu1ry and its relation to mference.
I lo,, then doc., the 1h~t1nct 1011 bl t \\ cen the~ci\\ o mqumcs naturally
ansc and \\lut I'> the confusion that rec;ults fromfalc;eabstrac.t10n ~
§ 39 The f.tn11li.1r concc.pt1011 of a theory of JUdgemeut as
cl1stmgu1sl,ed from a theory of rnfrrencc sremc; lo ongmatc thus
The proc.css of rnfr1 encc 1s seen to prc-suppo..,e knowledge already
ga1tll'd or ornmon., ,1lrL,Hly formed The process itself 1s con-
Cl'l\l'd, m l'ilect, ac; the apprd1lntl111~ of \\hat thu,c prc\.lOUS
apprl'hcnswn., or op1111onc; rn·ress1tate m the \\ ay of other kn<)\\ -
ktlgl' or opm1on I knee 1l Leconws C\ Hknt that there must
be apprchens!\>nc; not got by mfcrcnrt or n·a,omng Tlus appcars
m the f,u111lt,1r statunent tl1,1t till re mmt be undemonr,trated
prcnu::,ses or there \\ ould l>c .t Ill'\ Lr•emlmg process I b
J § ,~<I
(• Ifrfrrrmg to Ho~anquct':, I ,,i:1c a11,I F H Ilra<llcy•~ The I'rrnc1ples of
I o.~u (181:q)
1• Inf,·rcnLc us{'(] to bC' ba1d to l><'gm ' rx f>rnecogmhs ct f'rarronce5s1s • The
\'IC\\ 1~ 111 An~totlc, .4.11 l'o 7~• 7 an<l b 18, Metaph 1006• 8]
Apprehension in General 85
Certain apprehensions, then, are recognized as not bcmg
inferences, and also as being material of inference. These arc
called propositions or Judgements (not that these terms arc con•
fined to them alone), the name 'judgement' being preferred to
proposition rn modern logic, because the word ' propos1t1on ' 1s
associated with the verbal statement rather than with the mental
al.t1v1ty. The study of such apprehension<; would be necessary
to the 'itudy of mfcrcncc, as it 1s here conce1vcd, smce they arc
1tc; material, but d1stmct from the study of mfcrcnce smce they
arc not mfcrences.
Thus, 1f the namec, ' propos1t10n' and 'Judgement' were
confined to apprehcns10ns winch "ere not mfcrence<; and 1£ the
theory of the propos1hon or Judgement meant the c;tudy of them
a<; such, the d1v1s10n mto the theory of Judgement and the
theory of inference \\ ould be JUSt1fiable and the nomenclature
c,o far correct But the study 1s not so concc1vcd nor 1<; the
termmology thu<; restnrted , for the clcc;1gn.ttlon 'Judgement '
1c; not confmcd to \\ hat 1s not mfcrrcd, but mrludes what 1s
mkrrccl, whether knO\\ lcclge or op11110n
§ 40. Tim, secmc; to come <1bout ,1.., follo\\;; The knowledge
,, l' get l,y 1nfc1 encc Ill the sc1cnccs 1s stated m a verbal form
,,. l11ch sr~rnfic<; the ll,ttun of the tlung known and that only,
i•ot the nature of our apprehcns10n of 1t , and the i,tatcmeut
of the fart, onuttmg, as it uftt11 docs, the grounds of it discovered
Ill the mfrrencc, supprcs&c<; d!l trace& of the existence of the
pro<.css. For lll<;tance, ' the square on the hypotenuse of a right-
<tngled triangle 1s cqudl to the sum of the squ.ircs on the other
t\\o 1,1des' ii, a dcscnpt10n of the obJcl.t1ve f..ict, without any
rcfcrcn<.e to our suLJcct1ve state Such a statement preceded
by the \\ ord ' therefore ' H, the last statement lll the verbal
expression of an mfcrencc But without th1<, word, wluch con·
ncl.ls it \\ 1th the proce&&, 1t 1s given as the so-called concluci10n
of the mfcrence 1 he form of the conc.lu;,10n, not cont..immg
the grounds on \\ h1ch \\ c based it, promote~ the h,tl lit of rcprc•
c;ent111g the mental activrty v.lu<.h corresponds to rt (the appre-
hension of the fact) as a rei,ull d1c;t111ct £10111 the reasoning
protcs& by v. luch it 1s got, and the fall.icy of regarding it as
something in itself apart from the process and po&sessed some·
hov. alone v.1thout the process; whereas the possession of 1t ii:.
36 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
JUSt the inferring procesb itself The mental activity corre-
sponding to 1t, the having or posses!>mg it, wluch 'having' can
only be the apprehl'ns1on of the fact expressed by the statement,
or the belief m 1t, tl1Uc; , irtually becomes a result of the infernng
process and 110 somethmg chffcrent from 111fcrnng or reasoning.
Like the apprehrm,10ns \\ h1ch arc not mfcrcnccs, 1t 1s called
Judgement. ltc, wrhnl fmm 1s tal,cn to be the statement of
a Judgement as d1'itmgu1shcd from the statement of an inference
that 1s to c;ay, the statement of sometlung Judged as opposed
to the c,tatemcnt of c;onu thing mfcrred. Tlus carries with it
111ev1tably the <l1stmet1on of Judging from mfrrrmg and thus the
fiction nf a kmd of mental act1v1ty called 3uclgcment or Judgmg,
as somethmg d1stmct from mference, comes mto existence. The
truth however 1s that 1£ \\ e allow ' Judgement ' the meaning
necessary for the view under cons1derat1011, viz the havmg any
knowledge, behcf, or op1mon, the Judgement called the con-
clus1on 1s not anytlung apart from the process of inference by
which 1t 1s att:.11nc-cl, and the 1IH ntal ,u ti\ 1ty of J1tdg111g tlus
judgement-the ' havmg' of 1t spoken of aboYe- 10:, prcc1.:;ely
the process calkcl 'att.11mng' 1t, y1z the mkrrmg of 1t, and
mfcrnng 1s merely a part 1cular wny of 1uclgrn~.
Dut more than tlus, 1f "e take 3udgmg m its moo;t correct
and natural i;ensc, that ,., as dec1s1011 on evidence after dehbera-
twn, then mfcrnng 1s Just one of those forms of apprehending
lo "lurh the "orcls 3udpng and Judgement most properly
apply. 1
§ 41. The fam1h.1r d1strnct10n then of Judgement from inference
m\.olvcs a confus10n of thou({ht. Kno,, ledge, op1111on and behef
arc regarde<l as fe>rms of the s,imc sort of mental activity, termed
;udgcmeut, and tins actIY1ty, called Judgement, 1s made the
subJcrt of ,i Sl'pnratc 111q111ry Just bccam,e 1t 1s regarded as
• Thl' acti, c "urkmg of tlw fal,t- cli-t1m hon between a JnrlgC'mC'nt m gcnl'ral
and the procc-',< b} "ha h 1t 1, ,lttatnC'd is su•n rn the trad1t1011al doctrme uf
rrduct1on (of tlw l mfcrmr IH{llrl'' to thL Fir&t) Tlu, rC'ductton 1s crroneou~.
though appan•ntl} qmh. um.h,1llt•ngul a, and it depends on the fallacy c-xposcd
above Cf §; 11
l" The &t.ilL111c11t u, too gC'neral, d (l' g ) 'The first three figure, are the
l'lt)pcs of threl' real and c-sst-11t1.1lh d1tfcrl'nt operations of thought•. Schopen•
hancr, I he ll'orld as H 1/l a11d ldca, Bk I, t-h ,.. • Tu bomc people this
,1 e n•duct1011 to the 1st Figure) has seemed &upcdluous,' Lotze, Logic, § 91 J
Apprehension in General
somethmg different from inference. This fictitious severance of
Judgement from mfcrence results from ,L false abstraction. The
rn11clus10n of an mfcrence 1s really the verbal st.ttcmcnt of
a fact, the eAi,,tence of wluch is inferred. Tins statement,
,lbstracted from the mfcrnng process, 1s treated as 1f it could
be conceived ,, 1thout the mfcrrmg activity. The supposed
activity of 'havmg' or apprehcndmg 1s called JUclgmg or Judge•
ment and the statement itself 1s called a Ju<lgcment, or more
accur..1.tcly the express10n of a judgement.
Tlus act1v1ty, then, called Judgement, as ch:,tmgu1shed from
mfcrcncc, 1s a fiction, there ts no such tlung Judgement m
tins fictitious sense, besides mcluc1mg non-mfcrrcd knowledge
and knowlcdgr said to be the result of mfcrencr, mcludes also
op1111on and behd, for the s1111ple rcac;on that what 1s known,
pcrcr1vccl, suppoc,rd, or believed may Le expressed 111 an identical
verbal form. The man who knows that A 1s n, whether as
perce1v111g tlus or not, whether as mfcrnng 1t or not, and the
man \\ ho holds the opm1011 or be!tef that A 1s n, may equally
use the form of statement that A 1s B, and under ordmary
un-umstances do &o use iL
Now, 1f this common form ,,ere an cxprcss10n of the mental
,1ll1tude of the pc1s011 us111g 1t, 1t woul<l be reasonable to expect
to fm<l a common and Ct>'>l,lltial c..lcmcnt 111 the mental attitude
corresponding to the verb.ti form But the form merely slates
thP uaturc of \\hat \\C know to be, or tlunk to be, existent,
\\1th complete ab<;tract1011 of the fact that 1t 1s for m, matter
of knowledge, conJccturc, or behcf. So far from bcmg an expres•
!:>Ion of our mental attitude, 1t says notlung about 1t whatever.
A is B means th,tt a cerlam ov3ect has a c<-rtam nature or
quality, 1t Jocsn't matter \\hethcr the statement 1s true or
not, that 1s what 1t me.am,
§ 42. The trad1t1onal d1v1sion of logic, therefore, rnlo the
theory of Judgement and the theory of mkrcncc rcc,t<; upon an
erroneous pn11c1ple Strictly !:>peakmg, the llung- called Juclgc•
mcnt, wluch shoulcl be the sub1ect of wh,tt 1!:> CJlh J the theory
of Judgement, 1s fict1llous but the confus1011 1s concealed by
the fact that the verbal cxpress10n common to matter of know•
ledge, both 111fcrrcd and not mferrecl, ancl maller of opmion or
belief, and mistakenly supposed to be the expression of a mental
88 STATEXJ'tNT, THINKING, AND APP RB BENSIOlf
activity called judging, does duty for this activity in this part
of logic and forms the real object of study. Indeed, the logic
which in modern phrase is to be a logic of judgement is, quite
unconsciously, a.logic of statement.
If this is so, what should we expect? We should expect the
inquiry to be directed sometimes to what the verbal form
signifies and sometimes to the verbal form itself. If the inquiry
is into what the given verbal form signifies, since that is the
nature of the object only, with no reference to our thought
about it, we should expect the result to be abstractions which
belong to the objective reality and not to the apprehension of
it, nor to our thought about it m general ; objective forms,
that is, not forms of the subjective.
And this is what has actually happened. We do find in this
part of logic abstractions which are of what belongs to the
nature of the object (objective forms of the kind called meta•
physical, not true logical forms at all) and, further, metaphysical
forms may be confused with logical, as we shall see m the case
of the familiar d1stmction of subject and predicate, where
a logical and a metaphysical d1stmction are unconsciously
combined m the same designation. No wonder that in some
modern ph1losoph1cs logic is md1stinguishable from meta-
physic.
On the other hand, if the inquiry is really directed to the
verbal form, we should expect to find abstractions which belong
to grammar and to bngu1stic form in general, associated with
the logical and metaphysical abstractions. And this, again, has
actually happened. Many of the mqumes in medieval logic are
of this kmd. In modern logic an mstance of it 1s the theory
of the connotation and denotation of terms-" hich, indeed, has
a medieval source 1 This instance 1s mterestmg because the
subject has proved so confused and puzzling. One must venture
to thmk the secret of the confusion to be that the d1stmcbons
attempted concern the grammatical functions of certam word
forms, a fact which has not been realizcd. 2 Another instance
is the theory that all universal propositions arc hypothetical,
a fallacy which has arisen because the logicians who hold the
view do not realize that they have before them the question of
• Part II, ch. 18.
8g
the meaning of certain forms of speech, a purely linguistic
question. 1
In general, when the logical, grammatical and metaphysical
notions are not confused with one another, there is a tendency
to pass from one to the other without a clear consciousness of
the transition and to associate them as if they were of the same
kind.
But though the general character of this part of logic may
have been misconceived, that need not prevent the presence of
true logical mquiries in the traditional theory of judgement and,
indeed, of grammatical and metaphysical mqu1ries which belong
to the subJect because they subserve the logical. If there are
such logical mquiries and such justifiable metaphysical inquiries
in this traditional part of logic (and there seem to be), we have
to ask what the rationale of their grouping as a special part of
logic is. If they differ, and they do seem to differ, from what
belongs to the theory of inference, how should the part of logic
to which they belong be characterized ? From the point of
view of the wrong distinction of inference from something called
judgement, the difference between the two parts of logic would
have to be characterized thus :-the theory of inference studies
the subjective side of thought in the reasoning process by which
we attain a thought consisting m knowledge or opinion ; the
theory of Judgement studies the subjective side of thought in
the form of knowledge or opinion, considered in itself and apart
from any process by which it may be attained.
After what has been said, it will be evident that the formula
betrays its own mcoherence.• The subjective side in question,
when the thought attamed is knowledge, is the apprehension of
the fact and, m the case of what would be called the Judgement
attained by inference, the apprehension is the inferential process
itself. Thus, according to the above formula, we should, in the
theory of Judgement, be studying {m the case of a judgement
which was the conclusion of an inference) the apprehension of
something, considered entirely apart from its apprehension.
1
H 98, 103, and 312 [Ueberweg, Logia•, § 94]
[• Tlus, as so often in Wilson, 1s self-polemic. He states his own old attempt
to 110lve the problem and condemns it, as he would have said, unc;ompro-
m1smgly]
go STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
And, in general, we have found the whole basis of the view
which would result in such a formula untenable.
§ 43. What then have we to substitute? For we shall not
necessarily reject the whole of an inquiry because it has been
conducted under a m1sconccpt1on. We have seen that the idea
of logic as a study of thinking in its various kinds led to the
consideration of apprehension m general as the primary subject
of investigation in logic Starting now from the form of appre-
hension \\h1ch is reasoning, that is from our interest in the
subJective side of thought as 1t appears in reasoning, we observe
that inference or reasoning depends upon apprehensions which
arc not inferring. We arc then naturally led to the idea of
some study of apprehension m general as apprehension, whether
inferential or not. This would be a preliminary to the study
of inference and so far accord with a feature of a traditional
part of general logic, namely that part wluch, though sometimes
entitled the theory of conception, 1s nowadays usually embraced
under the title, the theory of judgement. Apprehension being
properly restricted to knowledge and opinion bemg formed in
the effort to get knowledge, we might further mquire into what
is common to the attamment of knowledge and the formation
or opinion, more especially as what would be called the state-
ment of an opinion and the statement of knowledge are so often
{indeed commonly) the same in form.
Such an investigation, agam, we should expect to lead naturally
to an examination of the verbal form of statement, not merely
because of this formal sameness in the verbal expression of
opinion and knowledge, but m order to see what light the form
of expression might throw upon problems about the mental
state. But then we should clearly recognize that it is the verbal
form which we are exammmg and how such examination 1s
relevant to our purpose. This, again, would correspond to
a feature of the theory of judgement, for example the classifica-
tion of the various forms of propos1t1ons, though the inquiry
would be conducted in a different way and with a better chance
of avoiding confusions.
Again, metaphysical conceptions such as substance and attri•
bute might have to be recognized and considered in so far as
they, m turn, may assist m the understanding of subJects con•
A pp,ehension in Gene,al 9:r
nected with apprehension or thinking in general. But here,
again, we should avoid confusion by recognizing that they are
of what belongs to the object and not to the apprehension of 1t
and so should not confuse them with logical forms. In this way
we might expect to mclude those parts of the traditional theory
of Judgement which can be v111dicated as having a place in logic
and to understand their relation to one another and to the
general scope of the mquiry. This part of logic then we may
describe as concerned with statement and its relation to thmking
and apprehension.
II
THE USE OF THE TERM 'JUDGEMENT' IN
MODERN LOGIC
H
Ill
OPINION, CONVICTION, BELIEF AND
COGNATE STATES
to the obJect as, for example, • being concerned with the apprehension of the
obJect' For the apprehemaon of the ob1ect 15 knowledge , thus we should
be merely definmg knowledge as an activity concerned with knowledge.
H2
100 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
nized to be insufficient, nor to come to any decision except that
the grounds are insufficient ; for it is here that in the"'tnowing
activity we stop. In knowing, we can have nothing to do with
the so-called ' greater strength ' of the evidence on which the
opinion is grounded ; simply because we know that this ' greater
strength ' of evidence of A's being B is compatible with A's not
being B after all. Beyond then the bare abstraction of conscious
activity, there 1s no general -fharacter or quality-of which the
essential natures of both knowledge and opinion are d1fferentia-
tions, or of which we could say in ordinary language that each
was a kind. One need hardly add that there 1s no verbal form
corresponding to any such fiction as a mental activity mani•
festeq in a common mental attitude to the obJect about which
we l&ow or about which we have an opimon. Moreover it is
vam to seek such a common quabty in belief, on the ground
that the man who knows that A 1s B and the man who has
that opinion both believe that A 1s B. Bebe£ is not knowledge
and the man who knows does not bf'lieve at all what he knows i
he knows 1t. We might as well say at once that knowledge is
a kind of op1mon as that it 1s a kind of belief.
§ 50. We have spoken of op1mon such as is consciously formed
and recogmzed as an opm1on and not .as knowledge by the
person who forms 1t; and, however determined we may be in
such a case to act as if the op1mon were knowledge, our expres-
sion of it shows that we do not confound it with knowledge,
and hence follows what has been said about the distinction of
judgement which is decision from opinion. There is here a cer•
tam simulation of an act of Judgmg which, however, ought not
to mislead us For, though I am not sure that A 1s B {and
therefore, though inclined to 1t as probable, I have not decided),
I may decide to act as if A were B I may have to make up
my mind between two alternative courses of action and, knowing
neither, I may choose all A is B as the more probable and the
one therefore that I shall act upon (although probability is not
the sole ground of such decision). There is then a mental
decision, which may be said to be in favour of all A is B,
a practical decision, getting it is true greater definiteness by the
fact that we act upon 1t, but not the Judgement (or decision)
1/wA is B.
Of,imon, Conviction, Belief , 101
• Doubtlt•s., v.c do not take ~l"r10u~tv Plato'" account of thought ac; the
dialogue of the ~oul wtth 1t!.elf for a true dt hmhon of thought . nevertheless.
v.hen 1t 1s a q11est10n whether we v.ere thmkmg or not, it 1s often useful to
ask,' Did I say &0 and so to myself~' [R 437c, Tht 189e, Sp/, .163e J
Opinion, Conviction, Belief HI
§ 55 Tm~ ' propos1t10n ' m the older, ' Judgement ' m the
modern tcnmnology, 1., said to be analy<;ed mto subject and
pred1c..ik, or, agam, mto subject, predicate and copula If this
&ccond analysis be .tdopted, propos1t10ns are supposed to be
resolved, for logac1I purposes, mto the form symbohzcd by S 1s
P , where S 1s said to be the subJect and P the predicate, while
the verh ' 1c, ' 1c. called the copula, ,1c; connectmg the predicate
v.1th the bUhJcct
Now, l.lc<..ordmg to the trad1t1on.1I defimt1onc; • of subject and
pred1catt-, thl' &ubJcLt 1s what m tht:: propo::.1tion or statement
we .ire speakmg about, .rnd the pn·chr.-tle ts what we say of
the subJell or. m a f,umh.ir forni, thr i,ubJect 15 th,tt about
v.h1ch ~omethmg ,., asc;ertl'd, .ind the predtcJte 1c; thctt which
1
1s asserted .1bout 11 Tim, agrt'c::. v.1th the derivation of the
v.ord · predic..tte' irom the Latin term prrduatum, a translation
of Anstotll",; Knn,ro1>01ip.wo1• An.,totlc d1stmgu1shc::, v.1thm the
propos1t1on, r,'i rnr,.,yopovµEZ•or .ind ru ,:;a(J' ov ,:;ar11yopE'irai, what
1s said of somethmg and th.It about \\-htd1 it JI'> ::,aid He never
defint•s the d1::.t111rt10n, anc.l gets mto d1ffirult1es m consequence.
The earhest kno" n formul..1.t1on b of the c.l1stmction, amount mg
to a dcfimt1on of 1t, i.l e1nc; to be that given by Boethms He
1 H \\' B Jo~eph, ll1trod11ct1on to Log,c, pp vu, 145
[• ( f '"""!(t 111.111 d,,., ~11h1u t 1-,t d,,.,, wovon t twa, ,1.11,g<•,agt uud das
Pr.id1k,1t 1,t d,1-, \ufi;<•,.11,:h, .,., 1-,t dtl''- ct\\a.o Tnv1dlt'o (u,mmonplac.e) und
llldll erl,,hrt tl,1durd1 Ill< ht, N.,Ju n, ub, 1 den l·11terotJ111 <l d1cscr be1dc11 '
Hegel, H "~"'"/1<1/I drr I oi:rk,, ,,,., (lr,r/.1, 11>40, vu, p 130)
b \\• l,lll, I thmJ.. tr,LLC llu:, l,uhc-r, 01Taii8a -,a,, ll c 'l!o,1<paT11s >r<puraT<i) Tr)
,.,,., ~. i rrmt1i/JfJ10S Vpui A.i11. ra,, 7~ , ; 11Ep,11aT,; 1tar-rryopo'Up.12 os, &Ur, ,,,. ff'tlYTl
1 1
llO.Tf/'Yap&ll9' >.o-y91 'fC) µii' lart ..,pl uli cl >.t-yo1, T<l a• • ,,,i ••• ,, ov >.1-yuµEIIOI', /tl1i TO ,.,.,
'lllpl o1i ,I Au-yOi, i11ro,n/µ1vov At}fTGI 0/5 11,xi.µoor, Ta.s 1to.T' o.vroii nnrroplo.s, TO
a•• ,pl 0.UTOii >.11uµ1ro11 • KO.T'/")Oput;µ,,,,,,, 0/S 1<0.7' (KEi11011 d-yopn,oµFlfOfl ml Af-yv-
,.,.,011, Ammomu~ 111 .I" Dr l11terprrtatr011r, pp 711-8• The copula 1, called
"poaicGT'l'Yopoi,.., w \ <on temporary c>f Hocthm~. he profes5cs to give the
doctrme of l'rodu, (.po 85 A D ) I llf' d(•hmttou or1gmated probably m the
gr:i.mmanans, e g ' alt(•rum (~c verbum) l'~t quod loqmmur, alterum (bC
nomen) de quo loqu1mur' Vumhha.n. Insl 1 4)
Subject and P,edicate II5
says·-' The parts of simple enunciation are subject and pre•
dicate : the subject is what supports the predicate locution, ..
the predicate is what is said concerning the sub1ect.' 1 Herc
we at once observe a certain awkwardness in usmg the concep-
tion of the predicate m the definition of the subject, and the
conception of the subject in the definition of the predicate.
This 1s clearly the forerunner of the modern formulae that we
arc cons1dermg These formulae are both inaccurate and
ambiguous For, in the first place, 1£ we consider the part of
the sentence to which the term ' predicate ' is applied, we shall
find that the above definition docs not accurately dct.cnbc 1t.
It 1s inaccurate to say that P 1s what 1s ac;serted or c;aid of S.
In th£' normal and non-teduucal use of language, 1f we asked
what wac; asserted of S m this sentence, the answer would be
not simply P but that S 1c; P If some onr, for m,;tancc, said
Jones was a good <1rt1<;t, ,ind some one dsc, hearmg 1mperfcctly,
,1:,ked ' what w.is said of Jones ) ', the answer would not he
'a good artist', nor would any one reply "' a good artl<;t' was
&aid of Jones", but ' that he 1s a good artist'. The difficulty
makes itself very dearly felt if we attempt to ,tpply the given
dl'fi111t1on of predicate to the negative propos1t1on In ' S I!>
not P ', what 1s ,tated about the 50-c.illed suh1ec-t S 15 'tJul
1t 1s not P ' we t ,mnot !>ay thctt P 1s wh.1t 1c; .1ssertcd or st.tied
about S. Consistency with the procedure of r,tllmg P the prc-
d1cate, m the .iffirmativr c;tcttement S 1s P, can 011ly be preserved
either by confining the given definition of suhJect ,md pre 11cate
to the affirmative statement, or cl,e by the e1roneou, device of
reducmg the negative to the c1.ffirmatJve form through the '>Ub-
st1tut1on of ' S 1s a not-P' for ' S 1s not P ' The m1!>t.tke
which would be comm1tte<l 111 such a reduction will be cons1clcrcd
later, when "e come to treat of the negative <,l.11 c-ment But
the truth seems to be that the trad1llonal clcfi111t10n 1s usu.illy
given with the affirmative st..i.tement alone m vJCw, the negative
being forgotten a Till'; 1s but in consonance with the unc.ntlcal
1 S1mphc1um nem enunc1abonum parlt,b ~unt ~ubudum .. tquc prcd1catum,
were not for a study of the linguistic forms in which the sup-
posed Judgement is expressed. But we shall consider later the
so-called Judgement and concepts. We shall begin with some
metaphysical or obJcctive distmctions and follow this discussion
by an account of the doctrine of predication in Aristotle, which
it helps to elucidate. We shall then discuss the general relations
which the grammatical forms of the sentence express or imply.•
§ 70.b There are implied then in our thought certain distinc·
tions between clements in the object of a statement as elements
in the object, which arc therefore not distinctions between the
apprehensions of these ob1ects, and so not subjective m meaning.
These must not be confused with the subjective distinction of
logical subject and predicate and yet tend to be so confused.
Such distinctions arc the distinction of substance and attribute
and a more general one includmg this, which may perhaps best
be formulated as the distinction of sub1ect and attribute.
(In such mqumes as the present we have to keep apart two
different questions. The first, what the real nature of the facts
is to which a given word or notion refers, and the second, what
we exactly mean ourselves, whether our notion is adequate to
the facts or not. If we do not keep them apart, we may get
to doubt the existence of a notion, whereas what we ought to
be doubting 1s its adequacy to the facts, or we may be led to
confuse considerations which belong to the facts with those
which belong to the notion. The want of this precaution is one
of the chief causes of perplexity m such modern questions as,
What 1s hfe ? What is force ? and the hke. There will be
incurable confusion if we do not first ask what it is that we
ourselves exactly mean by the word ' hfo ' which we are using
in our problem. If we do ask the question, we are the more
likely to understand what it 1s we really want, and sometimes
our problem may take a new shape or disappear altogether.
The assumption of the d1stmct1ons before us as objective is
rooted m human thought and, in the first instance, we have
merely to try and find out what they are m our thought ; to
recognize them, not to vindicate them. After that we may
(• Cf. Locke, Essay II, xxxm, § 19
b I have marked later additions to tlus section by <) Sec analysis of
dates of fragments.)
I52 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
inquire into their rationale and their relation to the facts with
which they have to do.)
Ordinary and popular thinking, like the philosophies for
instance of Aristotle and Locke, which give expression to it, is
accustomed to regard certain existences or reahties as complete
and independent, others as dependent and existing only in
dependence upon the independent realities.
Thus we thmk of a body as an independent existence, whereas
its movement cannot exi5t independently but only as movement
of the body ; and so for its weight and surface, &c. Such
a supposed independent reality, which we call a thmg, m a special
sense, is m fact a unity of real clements (volume, weight,
shape, &c.) which cannot exist except m that unity, so that
the being of one clement seems to enter, in a way, into the
being of another. Moreover such 'thmgs' stand in relation to
one another, and the relations of a thmg to other things belong
to its bemg.
In philosophic thinkmg then we come to sec that things have
not an mdcpendent bemg but that the bemg of one enters
somehow mto the bemg of another Such reflections may cause
us difficulty as to the meaning and justification of a familiar
phrase, viz. '\\hat a tlung 1s m itself', which implies usually
an mdcpmdent bemg m the thmg, expressly contrasted with
its relations to others. But now every element of reality, how-
ever dependent, whether thing, or element m the being of
a thing, or a relation between such realities, must, smce it is
definite and different from other reahtics, have in some sense
a bcmg of its own, or it could not be distinct from other reahties.
It must be &omethmg which they arc not.
We thus get a 1ust1ficatlon for the phrase ' in itself '. We may
say that what a somethmg 1s, and other somethings are not, is
' what 1t 1s m itself '. The ordmary use of the phrase ' in itself '
is somewhat narrower. Suppose a thing T1 stands in a relation
R to a thmg T2 : standfog m this particular relation belongs
to the being of T 1 and to the bcmg of nothmg else, for nothing
else can stand m this relation accurately understood. Yet we
don't think of this as belonging to what T1 is m itself, or as
a part of what T1 ' is in itself '. In fact, 1f a given something
has a part of its nature not constituted, or supposed not to be
Predication and Objective Relations 153
constituted, by relation to anything else, 'what it is in itself,
is usually restricted to this, and what it is in relation to any·
thing else is excluded from it. Thus we should say that an
orange was in itself yellow and round, but its being on the table
we should not call ' what it is in itself '. This kind of limitation
cannot be made in the case of a reality whose being is entirely
constituted by relation to something else, e.g. the movement
of a body, for clearly such relations cannot be excluded from
what the given reality (e.g the movement) is m itself. Such
a movement stands in a relation to the movement of another
body, or to another movement of the same body, but 1s not con•
stituted by this relation. Accordingly this relation would be
excluded from what the first movement would be said to be ' in
itself'.
(While things or substances are treated as absolutely inde•
pendent realities, the dependent existences may, in their turn,
have other existences depending on them. The absolute or
relatively mdependent reality, considered in relation to what
depends upon 1t, 1s what 1s called in philosophic thinking ' sub-
ject of attributes '. The main idea which determines the use
of the word 'attribute' seems to be that of something which
' belongs ' to somcthmg else, and is thus dependent on that
somethmg. But the ordmary use of the word attribute seems
to, cover two different things, the distmction between which is
not provided for 1nph1losoph1c language. The one is the depen•
dent existence itself, e g. the pomt of a needle, the other is the
possession of it by its subject, e g. the pointedness of a. needle.
As will be seen 1 when the distmcbon is more fully discussed,
it is the latter which, accordmg to the usage of language, should
be called attribute. The former may be called clement, but for
clearness we might call it ' attribute-element ', since (awkward
as this expression is) it will prevent any doubt as to what is
intended. Such an account of the proper meanmg of attribute
involves difficulties m view of expressions current m plulosophic
language. But a reminder may again be given that we have
to recognize and describe actual facts m thought and language,
not to vindicate them. Moreover it is no reason against the
alleged existence of such mental facts that their implications,
I I 81,
154 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
if fully thought out, are fraught with difficulties. Ordinary, as
distinguished from philosophic speech, attests the distinction of
attribute and attribute-element m our thought, and provides for
it without confusion. For the latter it uses the verb ' to have',
e.g. ' a needle has a pomt ', and for the former the verb ' to
be', with the adjective corresponding to the name of the attri•
bute, e.g. 'a needle is pointed'. It is quite artificial, as we
know, to say that a needle has pointedness, and the natural
usage of speech docs not permit such an expression at all.)
The subject as thus d1stmgmshed from the attributes, m either
sense, might be supposed to be 'what the thmg is in itself', or
at least some special part of it, as opposed to an ' attribute•
element ' which 1t has, wh1£h also 1s not something which it is,
e.g. we can say a body has surface but we cannot say the body
is the surface. Yet we fincl, 1f we try to describe what this
subject is, that we can only do 1t m terms of some of the things
which we have been callmg attributes in one sense or the other.
For instance in the case of the spherical shape of a body we do
not, it is true, say that th9 body is its roundness or its round
surface, but we do say .it is round.• (Though then the word
'is' gets used with reference to every attribute, the tendency
is to restrict the bemg of the subject proper to what seems to
be permanent and identical m its temporal existence. Here the
subject agam is undoubtedly conceived as something which
possesses those ' attribute-elements' which are themselves
apparently permanent.
Yet, when reflective thought is turned on such 'subject', we
seem to find that nothing can be said of 1t except that it is
what has these attribute-clements. In consequence the concep•
tion of subject, whether substance or not (though it 1s substance
which is mainly in v1ew) 1 comes to be doubted, challenged as
a metaphysical mystery, and finally treated as an dlusion. Here
two mistakes are made. In the first place, we find that subject
(or substance) is merely omitted and the attributes retained,
sometimes with such a defimtc statement as that the subject
1s only the sum of its attributes. This leaves the difficulty just
where it was, because ' attribute ' is necessarily ' attribute of'
somethmg, and presupposes that of which it ts attribute. It is
[• This, llke the whole section, only holds within a certain group of languages.]
P,etlication and Objective Relations 155
easily seen in any example that this could not be the sum of
the attributes of which the given attribute was an item, and the
discarded conception of subject (or substance) inevitably re-
appears. Moreover, there 1s the familiar criticism that some-
thing is required besides the attributes (in whichever sense) to
hold them together in a whole. But the form of the criticism
seems unguarded and may lead to a umty external to what has
to be unified.
Secondly, it is a common fault in critical philosophy • to
think that to pronounce a notion an illusion 1s enough to
settle an issue, whereas it is imperative to go on to ask what is
meant by illusion in the given case and how the illusion could
come about. If this 1s done, it sometimes happens that the
true character of what has been rejected may be revealed for
the first time and vindicated, in essentials at least.)
§ 71. There 1s, however, somethmg to correspond to the dis-
tinction of 'subJect' and 'attribute', though imperfectly for-
mulated and understood, as indeed we might expect from the
fact that ordinary language has a special form for it. The
rationale of it seems to be not that the subJect is its attribute-
clements (language avoids any form which would mean that),
nor that 1t 1s the sum of such elements. A reality, whether
a thing or not, may be a umty which unites in itself different
aspects or clements : not something over and above them, which
has them, but their unified existence. They cannot exist except
in this umty with one another, and they, in their unified existence,
constitute the one thmg or one element of reality in general
whether thmg or not.
(The difficulty we raise about the notion of' subject' is really
a difficulty about this umty and we are puzzled merely because
we think of the unity in the abstract.) How a diversity can
form a unity, or how a unity must be the unity of diverse
elements in one whole, depends on the particular mstance and
we understand it in the particular instance. Thus we see that
a volume must have a surface and that a surface can only exist
[• Not, of course, referring to Kant. ' To trace any error to its source
will often throw more bght on the subJect m hand than can be obtained if
we rest satisfied with merely detectmg and refuting 1t '-Whately, Log,c, iv.
4, I I, • -,a, lwr,pov •ilropla Ail0'1r TOIII ffp/,npov d.'6opovp.4nn, lO'-rt, M11r, r ot. IO'TW
il-yr,ooiivTas T~v IEul'O"• Ar, Melaph., 995• 28.]
156 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
as the surface of a volume ; we seem also to see exactly what
the nature of their unity is, and that no mysterious something
outside the elements themselves is required to unify them. Such
unity of diversity 1s not merely found in what we call things
but also in what are elements of the existence of thmgs. Thus
a movement unites in itself direction and velocity, and we
understand again exactly how it does unite them.
The umty of 3. mind m its attributes, in whichever sense, and
whether conceived as temporal or not, 1s quite different from that
of a material body, and this again we see by considering particular
mstanccs. 1
Now, what have been called ' attribute-elements ' are the
clements m such a whole, and the ' subJect' of them, as it is
called, 1s this whole itself, as a umty. In this wide sense 'attri•
bute '; as ' attribute-element ', would include relations, which
belong to the thing or other given reality. But this would not
agree with the commoner usage of language. Attribute 1s often
confined to the l'lements of 'what the tlung, &c., is in itself',
taken m the restricted sense explained above, so that relations
would be cxduded from them.
If the subJcct of an attnbute 1s a thing, it 1s called a substance
and the d1shnct1on becomes that of substance and attribute.
(As far as language goes, a mind 1s treated m no way as 1f 1t
were different from a thing. For 1t, and what belongs to it,
there is the same grammatical apparatus as for a substance and
attribute, when the substance 1s a thing. We .find this coming
into recognition in Locke when the mind ts spoken of as thinking
substance.•
The question now arises inasmuch as some attribute-elements
1 A notable example of loose tlunlong about umty in diversity 1s the
modem rcprese11tat1on of the 1nd1vidual as a universal because it 1s a u111ty
Jll the d1vcr,,1ty of its quahbcs, &c Thu, doctnnc, which 1S taken as advanced
metaphysics, is nothmg but a d<.plorablt• confusion, due to a. mere verbal
analogy helped out by the metaphy!,tCian's mchnation to paradox, and
absurdest results may be developed from it The umty of the universal 111
its particulars 1s totally different from the umty of the 1nd1vidual substance
as a. umty of its a.ttnbutes (or attnbute-elcmenti.) The pa.rt1culaIS of a. um-
versa.l are not elements m its umty Whether the universal can be the umty
of any elements at all is touched on later (§§ 78 and 8.2).
[• Essay, 11. 23, 122 ; 1v. 3, § 6 Letters to Sbllmgfieet, p. 293 (Worh,
vul 111, 1824).]
Predication and Objective Relations :r57
at least are themselves unities of elements, as in the instance of
movement given above, how such a umty of diversity differs
from a thing which is also a unity of elements. The answer
implied in our ordinary conception 1s quite clear. The attribute-
element (it would be said) is always a dependent reahty, existing
only as an element in a thing and not conceivable otherwise :
a thing or substance is a reahty not dependent on any other as
element in the existence of that other , or, as Aristotle would
say, the substance 1s a 'subJect' 1 of which itself there is no
other ' subject '. But then it may seem at first that this
answer cannot be vindicated. For we come to see that things
are not absolutely independent. They enter into relations with
one another, and thereby become clements in a wider reality
which comprehends them. In ordmary hfe we freely recognize
that thmgs or substances are related to one another ; we do
not realize how this affects their independence and we still think
of them as the independent realities on which the relations
themselves depend. It is philosophic reflection which seems to
make this idea untenable.
Yet it is not a mere fallacy. We feel that there is a very
real difference between a thing and what we have called attribute-
clements, and that, somehow or another, the thmg or substance
has a higher degree of independence than the element. This
feeling is justifiable, and precise expression can be found for it.
The attribute-element has no nature of its own apart from its
existence m the umty of the thing to whieh it belongs, and we
can form no idea of it without taking account of the nature of
the thing. On the other hand, the thmg or substance, though
as related to other thmgs it may rightly be held an element in
a wider reality which would be the 'one absolutely independent',
has, nevertheless, a nature of 1ts own, not at all constituted by
1ts standing in relations to other substances, and so not con-
stituted by 1ts bemg an clement in the larger umty to which
these telations conduct. We recover thus the true independence
of the thmg as against the overstatement of its dependence.
Language is faithful to the d1stmct1on. Whereas an attribute
is always an attribute of, a thing, in respect of this independent
nature, has a name which cannot be followed by the preposition
1 Sub1ect (substance) iJKcmdp,-,,011,
1~8 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
' of ', and, in respect of its dependence in the way of relations,
has another name, a relative noun which can be followed by
' of ', as ' captain of '. This is in strict accordance with the
nature of a relation between two somethings m the proper sense
of this expression. Each of the somethings has, in the cases to
which this expression applies, a nature not constituted by their.
relation at all, and therefore not at all constituted by being
a member of the system which the given relation necessitates.)
The distinction before us, whether m the general form of
sub1ect and attribute, or in the special one of substance and
attribute, 1s a d1stmctlon in the obJects of our apprehension or
thinkmg and not in the order of our apprehensions or thoughts
about them ; 1t 1s, therefore, wholly different from the distmc-
t1on of logical subject and predicate, with which it sometimes gets
confounded. The subject in this objective sense we may con-
veniently term the ' metaphysical' subject, but 1t 1s best defined
as the correlate of 'attribute' (in either sense of that word}.
The d1stmction of subject from attribute is not only not that
of logical subject from predicate, but a subject of attributes in
a statement 1s not necessarily the logical subject. Thus m 'that
buildmg 1s the Bodleian ', 'that buildmg' 1s a subject of attri-
butes and also appears as such m the statement , but it 1s not
the logical subject of the statement. ( A statement can have
only one logical subject, but 1t may contain several subjects of
attributes) Indeed, every element of reality to which the state-
ment refers may be a subject of attributes, and may sometimes,
though not always, be represented in the statement, at least
imphc1tly, as such Thus in ' A walks fast ', A's walking, as
well as A, is a subject of attributes, and one of these is stated,
viz. its havmg a certain speed. In 'the earth moves', on the
other hand, the earth's movement, though a subject of attributes,
1s not represented as such m the statement.
The relat10n of subject and predicate is, as we have seen, in
a certain sense reciprocal, for what is subject of a predicate in
a statement in one context may be predicate of that predicate,
as subJect, in another, and what is predicate may become sub-
ject. But the relation of a subject to its attributes is not
reciprocal. The subJcct cannot be an attribute of one of its
own attributes.
P,etlication antl Objective Relations 159
The distinction we have here discussed of subject and attri•
butes and relation concerns only particular existence-particular
thing and particular attribute and particular relation. It is of
this usage that we have been trying to find the rationale. How
far a similar distinction may apply to universals we need not
consider at present.•
§ 72. It is instructive now to turn to a doctrine of Aristotle's
which illustrates the confusion resulting from neglect of this
essential difference, the distinction of subJect and attribute
which is objective, and that of subject and predicate which, in
any reasonable account of the meaning of predication, depends
upon a subjective principle. We find m his writings the dis•
tinction of 'what is predicated' 1 and the {subject) 'of which
this is predicated ' 11 established and used for some time before
reflection upon the distinction appears.
In the Posterior Analytics he has at last occasion to stop to
consider 1t and we shall see the difficulties he gets mto ; diffi-
culties which seem to arise from the fact that he has long been
using the d1stmction, without having attempted to define exactly
what it should mean.
With him substance is subject m the sense m which subJect
as the correlate of attribute is 'substrate '. 8 'Accident','
which includes what he calls property as well as accident, comes
nearest the word attribute, m English, but in the Posterior
Analytics he appears, in one place at least, to limit accident to
that which is not in the ' essence '. 6 The elem1mts of the
essence arc 'the (attributes) predicated, or stated, in the what
a thing is '. 6 In the Metaphysics he defines the 'substrate'
as what cannot itself be predicated, whtle everything else is
predicated of it Thus : ' now the substrate is that of which
the rest are affirmed, while itself is said of no other.' 7 ••• 'not
affirmed of a substrate but the rest affirmed of 1t '. 8 So too in
the Categories.-' further first substances, because they are sub-
1 T3 l«JTf/'YOpo!JµEl'OII, I Ta 1ta6' oli traTff"(OpEITOl, • Tel lnr01tdt,1flfOI'.
1
• Tu 1TVµ/31/Jf/trol. ofJula•
• Ta'" T4i Tl lur, 1ta"7-yopovp1r,a An Po 83& 30.
7 T.l 3' brro1t1lpEvl,,, lt1T1 1t11,6' oli rd llAll.a 11.l-yerm, l1tEi110 ll' aim) Jjf/itln itar' 4ll.ll.ov,
Muaph. 1028b 36.
• µ~ d ' lnroitflµlvou clAAd PB' oi TG 4ll.ll.a, ib. 102g& 8.
(• Yule Ockham, m Prantl, u1, p. 368, note 851.J
I6o STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
strate to all else and all else is affirmed of them, or inheres in
them, are therefore termed substances par excellence.' 1 • • •
'for of first substance (primary essence) there is no predicating;
for it is said of no substrate '. 2 In the Posterior Analytics 8 he
maintains that the substrate cannot properly stand m the pre•
d1cate, but must be the subject of which predicates are affirmed.
Comparmg 'that white obJeCt 1s a piece of wood' 4 with
• the piece of wood is white', 6 he says that the latter is pre•
dicat1on proper, 8 where white 1s predicate and the substrate 7
is subject, whereas the former, m which the piece of wood, the
substrate, appears as predicate, is either not to be called predica-
tion at all, or else is ' improper ' and ' accidental ' predication. 8
What he says then here, m accordance with the other passages,
is that substrate must properly, i e. in proper predication, be
subject: he doesn't say explicitly that the (logical) subJect of
predication must always be a substrate. Nevertheless, that
would be the natural implication and, if this is not intended,
the language is unguarded. But a passage which follows, if
strictly interpreted, would seem to necessitate such an 1mplica-
tion. 8 He says, apparently, that an accident must be predicated
of a substrate (and cannot itself be a substrate) and cannot be
predicated of an accident. From this 1t would seem that an
accident could not be a subject for, if it were, it must have as
predicate either a substrate, which would be impossible, or an
accident, which, by the passage, is also impossible.
But whether we suppose him to mean that the subject of
predication proper is always a substrate, or only that the sub-
strate must always be a subject and never a predicate, the
doctrine 1s full of confusion and quite untenable.
Whatever definition may be given of predicate and subject-
and Aristotle never gave any clefimtion of them, probably
1 IT1 al wpiimJ, ovala1 llui Tl. Tots ci>.Ao,s 11.waau, lnro«<ia8a1 im2 1ravTa Td 4AAa mTd
ToilTow KaT'lf'tOpEia9111 I) ,,, TaVTair rlva1, &d TOVTo l'aA1aTa ova(111 A4'Yol'T111, Cat 2b 15.
1 ...,,a µ~v -ydp Tijs ,rpjJr71s uvaias oilllfµla laTI ltGTf/YOpla, ltQT ol,llu,os -,dp btro1tfl1'4"ou
Al-,«Ta&, Cat 3" 36 • An Po 83" 1.
' Tel AcU#OI' l1tci'vcl lll'TI {vAor,, • Ti) {vAol' AfU/tul' IO'Tlv
1 &wA&is 1taT,r,opeii,, • Til b1ro1tdµrvoi,, 1b 83• 17
1 d ll,) ll,i lfopo817itra,, lno, Til o/$ro, Al-y11" ltllTf/'Y"Pfi", rl, ll' l1e,(vo,s #fTn, µqllapGn
KaT'lf'tOpEil' I) ltGTf/"fOpEIII l'i" I',) c\rrA&is, mTd au1'fJ•fJ71«ds ll~ mT,r,op,iv, ib 83" 14
• bn1telalo, Bi} Tel ltaT'lf'topovµww 1taT,r,opriuBa, ,M, o; 1t1J"7'Yop<iTa11 c\wA&is dAAd
irat'il n/Afl•fl'11t6s. oflT111-ydp Al ,hrolld(11s dwoll1&1tvvovu,,,, ib, 83" 18,
I'•
Predication and ObjectiTJe Relations 161
thinking the words tell their own story-' predicating ' is the
-subjective act of statement, and so the distinction of subject
and predicate ts a subjective one, a distinction in statement as
statement, and not a distinction in objects. We cannot, there•
fore, suppose that Aristotle would consciously identify the
objective relation of substance and attribute with this relation
of the parts of a statement to one another, though his language
may tend to such confusion. In fairness he may be interpreted
to mean that while the subjective distinction of subject and
predicate is different from that of subject and attribute (an
objective distinction) the substrate shou]d a]ways be made the
subject of a statement and never the predicate.
But then it is a serious defect to define the objective relation
as he repeatedly does through the subjective one. It is a greater
defect that he mvolves himself m a circular definition. He
de.fines the substrate {'subject') through the notion of predica-
tion on the one hand, and on the other hand he defines predication
by the notion of the • subject '. For in order to distinguish
proper from improper predication, he either defines proper pre•
dication as that m which a substrate 1s the subject, or at least
defines improper predication as that which has a substrate as
its predicate.
li we put the best, or most favourable, interpretation on
Aristotle's doctrine, 1t would come, accurately put, to this :-in
predication proper that which 1s the predicate, or the object
s1gmfied by the predicate words, must stand m a c-ertam objective
relation to that which 1s made the subject of the statement.
~hat is to say, the prcd1cat1onal form itself, in the verbal state-
ment, properly implies that the object which the predicate words
signify must stand m the given objective relation to the object
which is signified by the subject words. ~
To maintam such a doctrme 1t would 'be absolutely necessary
to define subject and predicate, and subject and {say) attribute
apart, and then to show from their defimt10ns that a substrate-
a substance-could only be a subject Aristotle-a sign of his
confusion here-makes no attempt to do tlus.
If he supposed that • prcd1catmg' (or 'statmg ') had an
obvious meaning and required no explanation, and 1£ we take
him to imply this definition-' that about which a statement is
2773•1 M
I62 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
made 1s the subject and what is stated about it is the predicate',
-then the doctrine is quite obviously false. For anything may
have a statement made about it, and anything may appear as
what is stated or as an element in what is stated. In default
again of a definition we may take the form of verbal expression
and consider what Aristotle suppose& to be subJect and predicate
in that. In the form all A is B, he takes A for subJect and B for
predicate. But, in this form, a substrate, 1.e. an mdividual sub-
stance, may clearly t.ike the place of either A or B, and that
form of statement would be perfectly normal and correct.
If the predicational form agam as such implies that what
stands m the subject and what stands m the predicate must be
in a certain obJective relation, improper predication would be
that in which the objects denoted by the subject and predicate
did not stand in the relation.
It follows that improper predication \\<ould have to be called
either false, or unmtelhg1ble nonsense, as the verbal form would,
ex hypothesi, contradict the matter. But then neither Aristotle's
formula nor his examples arc right. In the formula. ' not to be
called predicating at all, or else improper predkatmn ', ' not at
all ' might correspond to ' nonsensical ', as the nonsensical might
fairly be said to be no predication at all. But the alternative
'improper' (lit. by accident) is incorrect, for this does not
correspond to ' false '. As an analogy to the manner in which
the contradiction of a verbal form produces falsity or nonsense
we may take an mstance m which the implications of a more
concrete formula are contradicted ; m ' A weighs twice as much
as B ', the words necessitate that m the given verbal form A
and B can only apply to bodies. Hence, 1f we put for A some-
thing not a body, e g. 'the rule of three weighs twice as much
as that chair ', we get a statement which must either be called
false or nonsense; but 'that white object is a piece of wood'
is not nonsense, and is not necessarily false. Aristotle himself
says it may be true-' we may say truly ... that big (thing)
is a piece of wood (or wood) '. 1
Again, according to Anstotle, predication would have to imply
in its very form that the predicate was attribute, in the wider
sense, of the subject-as that on which it depended. In improper
1 lorr1 -,dp fl••i• clAPJl&r •• TC) pl-y,,. lir1wo £•Ao,, eT11111. 1b. 83• 1.
P1edicatio,i and Objective Relations 163
predication, therefore, where the substrate is made predicate,
the mistake or defect should be that the substrate was then
represented as ' accident ', or attribute in general, of something
else as the subject. But this is not so in the instance which
Aristotle gives of improper predication,' the white thing 1s wood•.
The substance called wood 1s not here represented as treated as
the attribute of anything. What, according to Aristotle, would
be the logical subJect 1s the wlutc (thing), which is not white-
ness 1 but the white object, and the proposition does not mean
that wood is an attribute of this On the contrary, the wood
1s identified in the statement with the substrate which has the
attribute of wluteness It 1s therefore not treated as an attribute
of anytlung else, but as a substrate. This appears even in
Aristotle's own account of it : ' when I say the white thing is
wood, I say that what has the attribute " being white " is
wood '. 2 Thus, on lus own showmg, the statement has not that
kind of fault which alone seems to make !11s d1stmction of proper
and improper predication mtellig1ble. Possibly he intends that,
though m saying the white thmg 1s wood we mean that the
object which 1s wlute 1s also a piece of wood, not that the
white object as such, 1 e. as white, 1s the subJect of which wood 1s
attribute, 3 the form of the expression nevertheless 1s only appro-
priate to, and only naturally has the latter mea01ng.' But, 1£ the
form of express10n meant naturally somethmg so contrary to
what we really mean, we should not use it A!'. a fact it does
naturally mean what he says we mean by 1t, so much so that
sometimes it is the only correct form of expression, and the form
he approves would be entirely incorrect. If the question 1s
' what is that white thmg yonder ? ', a correct form of answer
and the natural one would be, ' That white thing yonder 1s
a piece of wood '. ' That piece of wood is white ' would be
absurdly wrong in form and no one would speak thus.
If Aristotle had asked himself how the form he considers not
true predication could arise, he would doubtless have seen that
so far from being a form which was either not to be called
1 ' the white ' 1n Greek may mean white in the abstract, 1 e whiteness.
,.i., "'(dp TO Afu..a., flPa, ,t,G, £uA,w, T6Tf At'r"' 11-r, ~ ,,..,./JI/J.,.., An,..,ji .1....,
• /l.,..,,
EilAw lt1Tlv.
I cwx cl,s .,.,) inratrflJ,lfl'OP .... £ull.q, Til AfUKOP IITTUI.
' After n,.S,s.,..,,,, then m 82• 8, we should supply tra.iTo& 13., ... a 1-tx•i·
'"1/MUftlP'rOVl'O,
11 2
164 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
predication at all or else not ' proper ' but only ' accidental '
predication, it was in a certain context the correct one, while
the form he called ' proper ' was quite inadmissible.
We must now ask what considerations led him to the mistake,
and naturally look for an answer to what he says of the difference
between the two forms of expression. The characteristic which
he finds m the statement 'the white (thmg) is wood' seems to
be this. Wht:rea& the subject of the statement is designated
and defined by a certain ' accident ', it is not as having this
' accident ' that it gets the predicate attached to it. But the
predicating a predicate of a subJect only designated by one of
its accidents, and not as havmg that accident, is not on that
account accidental pred1cat1on. To make 1t so would be down-
right confusion of an objective quality of the object matter with
a quality belonging to our subjective statement. There is
another sense which might possibly be given to the accidental-
ness. It might be said that m proper predication the attribute
or attributes by wluch the subject is designated is what makes
the subject the substrate which 1t is 1, and the substrate to which
the predicate attaches In the 'improper' (it might be said)
this is not so, the ' white ' which designates the subject is not
that aspect of 1t to which the predicate directly attaches , the
predicate (it might be said) is only connected with the attribute
which designates the sub1ect by the fact that they both belong
to the same substrate. This, accordmg to Aristotle's own usage,
might be called an ' accidental ' connexion But this interpreta•
tton can hardly be allowed, because Aristotle would not say that
the only ground of connexion between the two different thmgs
was inherence m the same subJect, but that white attached
directly to wood as to its substrate. They would not be treated
in Aristotle as merely both in the same substrate, but wood
would actually be the substrate of white. And, even if this
interpretation were allowed, we must repeat the previous objec•
tion, that a predication which relates to an accidental connexion
is not on that account itself 'accidental ', for, 1£ so, ' the wood
is white ' ought to be accidental predication, whereas, according
to Aristotle, it is predication proper. And, if we consider the
1 lr,p i,al 1-rl•tTo. Tills seems to be the right way to translate thul
difficult clause
Predication and Objecti'IJe Relations 165
predication itself, we see that it is in no sense accidental, for
what he calls, the predicate is not attached to the white as white
but to the substrate which has the white, i.e. 1t is attached to
its proper substrate, m the sense of being identified with it.
Thus according to his own view it would have to be ' properly '
predicated. 1
Aristotle's statement that 'the white (thmg) is wood' ought
either not to be called predication at all, or else improper and
accidental predication, could be justified only if the phrase in
question was asserted to be predicating wood of the attribute
white (i.e. of whiteness, really) in the object, that is to say of
the object's whiteness For to this (1 e. to the view that wood
was predicated of white) 1t would rightly be replied either that
the relation of the two in the statement is not to be called
predication at all, which would be a correct alternative ; or
that, if it was to be called pred1cat1on, it would not be predica-
tion in the proper sense, for 1t would only mean that the one,
the predicate (wood), was predicated of a subject of which the
other was predicated, and, as we shall see, this 1s so far incorrect
that white is not predicated at all in the sentence. But then
no one does take such a view (1 e. that wood is predicated of
the attribute whiteness), so that Aristotle's supposed cr1t1cism
would not be true of the form itself, but merely of a wrong
representation of it.
The characteristic, however, which Aristotle appears to find
in the form he considers improper predication and the kind of
difficulty he founds upon 1t would not lead naturally to the
exclusion of the substrate from the predicate position ; it would
only necessitate that the subject should be designated by that
which made it the subject to which the predicate belonged,
i.e. by that aspect of 1t which necessitates the predicate. Indeed,
he has quite overlooked that here he is contradicting his own
principles. Socrates is animal I he would regard as quite a proper
form of predication. But in this sentence an ammal means
a substrate (substance), and a substrate as a substrate.
In his doctrine, m this and the other passage, that substrate
cannot properly be a predicate, he seems obviously affected by
a form of language which we shall have presently to discuss.
166 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
It is the rule in the earlier stage of language both m the race
and in the individual, the tendency also in the simpler speech
at all times, to make the thing the noun and the grammatical
subject of the sentence (the nominative to the principal verb),
and to express its attributes m their relation to 1t by verbs, or
adjectives in combination with verbs. And it is not natural to
represent the attributes by noun forms. Thus the realities
which are considered as dependent are associated with these
non-nominal forms, as the ones proper to them. Even in the
advanced stage, when attributes have nouns to denote them,
the adjectival forms, &c., remain peculiar to them, for ' things '
cannot be put into such forms
Now Aristotle treats the grammatical subJect (meaning by
this the nommat1ve to the verb} as the subject of statement
and the rest of the sentence as what is stated of it, 1.e as the
predicate. In this way dependence upon some thmg as sub-
strate (subject) of which 1t was attribute, might be associated
in his mmd with the nature of a predicate Thus in chapter 2
of the Categories we find him confusing ' that which 1s said '
with the attribute or attributive.
Fmally, we may say that when Aristotle defines the substrate
or metaphysical subject as that which 1s subject and never predi-
cate he 1s confusing an objective with a subJect1ve distinction.
§ 73. The confusions m the Organon which we have been
investigating appear in a new dress m a modern doctrine to
the effect that the true sub1ect of every ' existential ' Judgement
is the ' ultimate reality ' 1 We may here examine this view in
order to elucidate further the position we have been led to adopt.
What we have said 1mphes so far that all statements or
propositions are about reahty-1 e. some sort of being. Now
the doctrine before us is not that all propositions are about
reality, but that ' ex1stent1al ' propositions II are about reahty
and, further, have the ' ultimate reality' for their subject. The
'existential' propositions are, in general, singular propositions
as distinguished from universal and hypothetical propositions;
the universal categoricals m this theory bemg erroneously
reduced to hypotheticals.
• F H Bradley's Log,c•, Bk. I, ch 11, f 42 (p So).
• The word actually used 1s • Judgements ', an inaccuracy already cnticJ.Zed.
Predication and Objective Rel«tions rlY'J
The question as to whether the subject of such propositions
is the ultimate reality cannot be profitably discussed unless we
clearly define to ourselves what we mean by the subject of
a judgement, and what by ' the ultimate reality '. When we
have done this, we shall find that the doctrine and the importance
attached to it depend on a mere confusion of analysis, and that,
instead of being a bit of new metaphysics, it is only an ancient
fallacy in a modern dress.
First as to the meaning of ' ultimate reality'. There seems
here to be a special use of the word 'real'. It means the self-
existent and that, agam, apparently means the complete reality
of the world, as bemg the only self-existent, m distinction from
its partial manifestations. The theory must be tested by possible
meanings of the word 'subject' m relation to 'Judgement' or
to statement.
It need hardly be said that in ' existential Judgements ' the
ultimate reality is not what is sometimes called the grammatical
subject. A second meaning of subject which we have distin-
guished is any element m the statement considered as what we
called ' subject of statement (representing knowledge or opinion)
in general '. This we have seen to be entirely relative, every
element being subJect in turn in this sense. Since this kind of
subject necessarily means some element of reality as related to
other elements, 1t cannot be the ultimate reality, as here under•
stood.
But when, m logic-, we speak of 'the subject of a judgement'
simpliciter, we ought to mean what we have called the' logical'
✓
[• ' The extreme case of 1dentmcation 18 that whl"re the attribute :is indi•
w:lual •.-MS. note Cf. pp. 194, 208, a.nd 349.]
188 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
of universals, that is without nouns which mean universals.
And it is worthy of remark that even the most developed stage
of language both of ordmary hfe and of science does not evolve
names for universals of substances or individual things. Such
a word as ' horseness ' or ' animalness ' appears only in the
artificial language of philosophical mvestigations. In ordinary
speech we should use a circumlocution such as 'being a horse'
or ' being a horse in general '. But the simpler language can
dispense with umversal names There, though the umversal
proposition expresses a connexion of umversals (as even Locke
saw), this 1s by various devices expressed m grammatical forms
which belong to particulars.
The most defimtc and adequate method is to take for the
nommative the plural of a particular noun preceded by such
a word as 'all': 'all crabs walk sideways', 'all eqmangular
triangles are equilateral '. The grammatical form 1s that which
attaches a particular case of the attributive to each of the total
of particulars of the universal signified by the nommabve phrase.
Next the quahfymg words, such as 'each', 'all', may be
omitted and the indefimte plural used . -• crabs walk sideways ',
' equiangular triangles are equilateral '. The meanmg of the
grammatical form 1s the same as before.
Agam the singular, with the word 'any' or 'every', or the
singular mdefimte (as in English with the mdefimte article)
may be used ' a crab walks sideways ', ' every circle has
umform curvature '.
These are methods of general application. There are others
which are not. The defimte article may be used with the
singular of the particular noun . ' the crab walks sideways ',
'the circle meets its tangent m one pomt only', 'the vulture is
carnivorous'; but we shouldn't say. 'the man is carnivorous',
' the man is mortal '. An mterestmg idiom is illustrated in :
'lead is heavy', 'man is mortal', 'man 1s endowed with
speech'. But we shouldn't say· 'crab walks sideways', or
' man 1s endowed with speech but fish 1s speechless ', though
we should say : ' fish, when not fresh, is poisonous '. Since
' lead ' is a word applied to every piece of lead, the particular
being denoted by phrases hke 'this piece of lead' {and similarly
for ' man '), it might perhaps be thought that the words ' lead '
The Meaning of Grammatical Fo,ms z8g
and ' man ' actually denote universals. But this is disproved
by the verbal or grammatical form. For the grammatical form
is that which attributes something to an individual subject and
we cannot in the sentence substitute nouns which clearly mean
universals for lead and man. We cannot say 'manness is
mortal', it is only the individual man who is mortal; nor can
we say ' manness is endowed with speech ', or ' leadness is
heavy '. The true account seems to be that lead is a sort of
collective and represents, so to say, the whole stock of lead.
But when those nouns appear which are the names of uni-
versals, whether substances or attributes or relations, can they
be treated grammatically hke the nouns which represent or are
names of particulars ?
A particular substance uniting elements m itself, such as
weight and a certain shape, has these attached to it in the
sentence by the corresponding adJectlve, cg. 'it is heavy', 'It
is round '. Similarly for an attribute , to express the fact that
a movement has swiftness and straight direction we say 'this
movement is swift and rectilinear '. To these attributes corre-
spond universals, and so we may say that the universal of the
given movement involves m Itself the universals of swiftness
and recblinearity and that 1t is mseparable from them. The
universal itself 1s ' swift rectilinear motion '.
Now, though a particular has certam particular elements, the
universal of that particular has not necessarily the universals of
those elements a.s elements of itself. Thus the universal ' swift-
ness' cannot be an element of swift, rectilinear motion ; for,
if it were, its bemg would be comprised entirely in the being
of ' swift recbhnear motion ', and then a swift motion would
be necessarily rectilinear. Similarly for rectibneanty. Thus,
though the universal ' swift rectilinear motion ' appears as one,
and as a complex mvolvmg the universals of swiftness and
rectilinearity, it is not a complex of which these umversals
are elements or members. Nor is swiftness an element of the
universal ' motion ', for then all motions would have to be
swift. The universal of an emerald, to take a substance, is of
something transparent, green, heavy, and of a certain shape.
As before, transparency, greenness, weight cannot be regarded
as elements of the universal ' emeraldness '. Thus, if a particular
Igo STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
is a unity of elements or attributes, the universal of that par-
ticular is not necessarily a universal of which the universals of
the given attributes are elements or attributes.
These objections do not apply to such a relation as that of
velocity to movement in general. The being of velocity is com-
prised in that of movement, and movement cannot be without
velocity. The universal of velocity may be said then to belong
to the univers.il of movement. So also the being of volume and
surface is comprised in that of body, and the actual being of
body must always be accompanied by surface and volume.
Suppose then we allow them to be elements in the universals
of movement and body respectively, as universals which belong
to those universals. Whether the universals which a given
universal involves can be said to be elements in the latter or
not, the noun which is the name of the given universal cannot
appear as the nominative to the verb which corresponds to one
of those other umversals, nor as nommative to the verb ' to be '
with the adJectives correspondmg to the other universals, nor
can we employ the circumlocution with 'have'. Thus the
analogy of the case where we are sure that the elements are
elements in the particular thing cannot hf' followed here.
For instance we cannot say ' starness twinkles ', but only
'a particular star twinkles'. Or, to take a universal which
might be considered an element m another (sentiency in animal-
ness, rationality in manness), we cannot say ' animalness is
sentient', but only 'a particular animal is sentient'. We can•
not say ' bodmess is heavy ' or ' bodmess is extended ', for only
a particular body 1s heavy. We cannot say 'bodiness has
surface', nor 'motion in general has velocity'. The ordinary
adjectives and verbs then will not do, and there is no special
set of verbs or adjectives analogous to the ordinary ones to
express the connexion of such a universal as velocity with such
a one as motion. Even when we say ' velocity is an attnbute
of motion ', we mean that a particular movement has velocity
(a particular velocity) as attribute, and not that the universal
of motion has.
Nevertheless we are not at a loss to express the true relation
of universals. We can use the grammatical forms for particulars
with the devices already explained, e g. ' a movement must have
Tiu MeanlH-g of GraffUMllcal For,ns 191
Y are compatible ' ; ' things equal to the same thing are equal
to one another '. The adjective refers to something which
belongs indeed to each of the subjects denoted by the associated
nominatives, yet only in relation to the others. Now m the
ordinary formula 'all A is B ', the adjective or noun denoted
by B belongs to each A separately, independently of any rela-
tion it may have to the rest, so that of each A we can say it
is B, and the sentence is equivalent to ' each of the A's is B '.
But the adjective which forms part of the attributive in the
case before us 1s not of any kmd which B can represent, since
it does not apply to each of the associated nommabves by itself
but only as in relation to the others Consequently also, such
a sentence cannot be reduced to a form m which the adjective
1s attached to each member of the set singly. We cannot say
in the above mstances ' X is equal ', or ' X is compatible ', or
' each of these thmgs equal to the same thmg is equal to one
another'. It 1s obv10us therefore that these cases are qmte
unprovided for m the traditional form 'all A is B ', which is
given as the general form of all propositions with the verb ' to
be ' On the other hand, the fact they express must be put into
language quite different grammatically 1f the ' all A is B ' form
is to be possible How this can be done will be considered later.
As already explamed, 1 when either elements or attributes
come to have names denoting them, as umting elements within
themselves, these also enter mto the same lmgmstic forms as
substances and attributes Thus a movem,.nt unites in itself
velocity and direction For the velocity there are adjectives
such as ' swift ', correspondmg to A, and the attributive noun
sw1ftness, correspondmg to Aness ; for the direction, such
adjectives as ' straight ' or ' circular'. It must be remembered
that it 1s as a particular movement that the noun for it can
have these adjectives attaching to it. 2
It remams to symbolize the analysis of the sentence mto the
subject of attribution and the attributive To av01d confusion
with the symbolism above used for the grammatical distinctions
letters from another alphabet may be used, say Gothic, and the
sentence with the verb ' to be ' may be represented by S is a.
P2
X
THE COPULA AND THE MODALITY OF STATEMENTS
§ 84 THE mistake of confusing the distinction of subject and
predicate with an objective distinction culminates in an account
of the i:;o-called copula which is often associated with 1t. This
appears in a common doctrmc that the word ' 1s ' does not
signify reality but 1s merely a sign of predication. Thus the
members of the symbolic form, all A 1s B, are familiarly termed
subject, copula and predicate, where the very name 'copula '
implies that the verb ' to be ' is a mere link, properly under-
stood, a sign of the connexion of A and B m the sentence , for
the termmology 1s justifiable only 1f 1t characterizes what 1s
essential m that of which 1t is used. This doctrine 1s entirely
opposed to the view we have mamtamed ; namt'iy, that, in the
form in question, the vrrb 'to be' refers to the being of the
object which 1s denoted by the nommat1ve to the verb
Now we might reasonably suspect the poss1b1hty of such
a change m the meaning of '1s '. It 1s a paradox that such a
simple word should lose the very essence of its meaning, and
still more so when 1t keeps that meaning m ordmary speech.
Ag,un, as a matter of logical formulation, 1£ the copula has
nothmg to do with bemg and is only a sign of ' predication ',
surely 1t would be better to avoid the word ' 1s ' altogether and
to put a symbol for it, jUSt as we put A and B for the (so-called)
subjl•ct and predicate. This bemg so, 1t 1s remarkable that the
verb ' to be' should be employed so commonly and in so many
languages to express this relation and that its use should not
only be allowed but be universal in logical treatises. There
must have been good reason for choosing, consciously or uncon-
sciously, this word in particular. The reason appears to be that
the symbolic formula contaming 1t 1s not merely artificial, but
generalizes ordmary usage, that, m that formula, as we have
tried to show, 1 the verb 'to be' retains its ordmary meaning.
How then could the contrary view have arisen ? Here agam
I§ 79
The Copula .a,ul Modality 213
we feel that there must have been some ground for accepting
a theory so much opposed to the common uses of language.
The doctrine seems to have arisen m the following way. In
the form 'all (some, this) A is B ', A being called the subject
and B the predicate, as ' what is stated of A ', 1t remained to
find a function for 'is' in relation to the 'predication'. Now
there can be no statement and so no ' predication ' m the given
form without the verb '1s' (or 'are'), and 1t was on this ground,
probably, that the verb ' to be ' was taken erroneously to be
the sign of predication. Thus though Aristotle's analysis 1s mto
sub1ect and predicate merely, we find the copula recogmzed as
a distinct member already by Abelard, 1 who says, ' the members
out of which categorical propos1t1ons are combmed are predicate,
subject and their copula (hnk). The reason 1s that we separate
the verbal notion from the predicate and take 1t by itself .
the interposed verb lmks the predicate to the subJert '.
There 1s somcthmg prima facie hke this m Aristotle's De
/nterpretatione, 2 where 1t 1s said that the verb 'to be' by itself
means no ex1stmg reality, and so m itself 1s nothing, but 1mphcs
a certam con1unction (1 e. of realities) which cannot be under-
stood apart from what is conjomed This however is not part
of a discussion of the analysis of the sentence mto subJert
and predicate, but comes m merely to tllustrate the doctrme
that words m isolation from the sentence, though they have
a meanmg, do not mean that anytlung corresponding exist&.
It is in this connexion that Aristotle says it 1s not even true
that the word for existence, or bemg, itself, when put apart from
any context or sentence, means that anythmg exists. This then
1s so far from bemg a deliberate analysis of the sentence mto
subject, predicate and copula that there 1s no ment10n m it of
predicate or sub1ect and the question of such an analysis 1s not
before Aristotle at all. Conceivably, 1£ Aristotle had h.i.ppened
to reflect upon the connexion of this with the analysis of the
1
Sunt autem membra [videlicet propoi.1bonum categoncarum] ex qu1bu,;
coniunctae sunt praed1catum ac 1,ub1ectum atque 1psorum copula, secundum
hoc sclhcet quod verbum a praed1cato seorsum per i.e acc1p1mus Verbum
vero 1nterpos1tum praedlcatum sub1ecto copulat Abelard, Dialectica, Cousin,
P 246 (Prantl, I c , vol 11, p 196, note 370 , cf id, p 206, note 11 )
AilTI) ,.~,, -ydp oua,,, ltrTI, 'llpG17U7//IIJ'"" 3, u(,116•11/11 T111a, ,Ov dv•u TiiJII avy•••I'•"°'"
1
[• The Form des Satzes w1derspncht 1hm c,chon o;elbst, dd em Satz auch
emen Unterschled zwischen SubJekt und Pmd1kat verbpr1cht Hegel, Wet'ke
(113.to), v1, § u5 (Wallace, Eng Tr, pp. 213-14)]
218 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
X ' has in a way the verbal form of a judgement or opinion, but
a matter which cannot be the matter of a Judgement or opmion.
Difference then bemg necessary, the solution 1s that Bness 1s
not really different from the bemg of the subject of attribution,
(s)iA, but only different from that aspect of its bemg which is
conveyed in that subject Thus, m 'this A 1s B ', Bncss and
Aness are both parts of the bemg of the same subject, each
identified with a part of its bemg, and each different from the
other. Tlus involves identity and difference, an 1dent1ty wluch
without losing its umty ha,; these different forms of bemg.
We thus get away from that false vie"' of identity or umty, as
mere sclf-1dent1ty without difference, which was the fallacy of
the Cymcs and apparently of Lycophron, to the true identity
wluch as identity 1s identity m difference and as umty 1s a unity
of differences, a umty, that 1s to say, such that the elements
which we call different have existence or reality only m unity
with one another; and, v.lulc each of these has m a true sense
a bemg of its own whereby 1t 1s d1stmct from the others, yet
at the sam<.• ttme each hy its own bcmg neccc;s1tatcs the bemg
of those others a
Tlus 1s the general conception of umty and difference covering
every case of statement, but we cannot a priori say anythmg
more about 1t ; its peculiar character can only be seen m
particular 1m,tanrcs, as when, m the statement 'this piece of
chalk 1s round ', I d1stmguish chalk from roundness and under·
stand their umty with one another Or agam take ' this blue
1s a dark blue' The generic notion of blue lhikrs from the
notion of dark and hght which we apply to colours m general ;
nevertheless blue cannot exist except as havmg one of these
shades Here we have another kmd of umty 111 difference
Thus in every statement two apprehensions are given of the
reality of one and the same obJect, on one side m the nominative
and on the other m the attributive Neither, m the normal
case, 1s of the whole bemg of this ob1ect1 but each 1s an appre-
hension of some aspect or part of its being. We see then what
constitutes the umty m d1fference of what 1s stated. The
difference is between two aspects of the obJect, and the umty
[• necessitates v I '1s m necessary relation to the being of those others•
(1907) The 1904 text seems to have got into the pnnted copy by DllStake]
The Copula and Modality 219
§ 95.b THE doctrme that in 1ts proper logical sense the pre-
dicate m a given Judgement or opimon 1s a new determination
of the sub1ect1 as previously conceived by the person Judging,
leads us to consider a trad1t10nal distinction in modern logic to
which 1t seems opposed, the d1stinct10n of analytical and syn•
thctical judgements tAn analytical Judgement is generally
defined as one m winch the conception of the ' predicate' is
already contained in the conception of the 'subJect ':'} A syn-
thetical Judgement 1s one in winch the conception of the
'subJcct' docs not contain the conception of the 'predicate'.
Now 1£ predicate is taken in what seems its proper sense m
logic, 1t would follow that there could be no such thing as an
analytical judgement
It must be admitted that m a sense the conception of the
sub1ect always rnvolvcs that of tht• predicate, m so far as a thmg
necessarily has of 1lo;; own nature the properties which we rightly
a.!i!i1gn to 1t But that 1s not what 1s meant by an analytical
judgement m the view \vC arc to examine, and for accuracy the
dcfimt10n !ihould be restated as follows . ' an analytical Judge•
ment 1s one of which the predicate 1s contamc<l cxphc1tly in the
subject as the subject 1s conceived by the person Judgmg; m
a synthebcal judgement the predicate 1s new at least to the
person Judging.' If then 1t 1s the essence of a ' Judgement '
(" From tlus point onwards 1t has been difficult to make the termmology
con!.1stcnt Th1!. chapter, for instance, was complet<•d fairly early and I have
left the language ~ubstanbally as 1t stood m the prmted ver~mn of 1913.
The author, 1f ht. h,ul uhted 1t, would have tri<'d to avoid txpreS&10ns hke
' conception of the predicate ' and the use of the word ' Judgement ' m 1ts
current sen&e, not h1i. own He had however usually substituted the word
' statement ' for the verbal exprei.s1on wluch would ordmanly be called
'propos1t10n • Seep 235, note 1
b Cf Lotze, Logic, m 5, t§ 363-4]
232 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
which has a logical subject and predicate to give a new deter•
mination of its subject in the predicate, an analytical Judgement
as just defined is a contradiction in terms. It has however been
gravely maintained that every synthctical judgement inevitably
becomes analytical. In a synthetical Judgement of the form
(s)iAB is C, C is the new clement and therefore the Judgement
is synthet1cal ; but it 1s mamtamed that, after the act of judge•
ment, C becomes an element m (s) 1 or rather an clement in the
concept1cn of (s) 1 for us. Thus ' (s)i 1s C' 1s now analytical, is
in fact equivalent to ' (s)iABC is C '.
Now, m the first place, even ,vere this so, the analytical
Judgement would seem to be postenor to the synthetical m
order of thought, for it depends entirely on the synthesis which
precedes 1t. There cannot be analysis unless there has been
synthesis. Secondly, we can show that 1t is an 1llus1on to
suppose that a synthctical Judgement can ever lose its character
of synthesis and pass mto the analyt1..:al m the way supposed.
When would the synthet1cal Judgement c:,,.1st at all ~ It would
follow that the predicate the moment 1t was assigned to the sub-
ject became part of the subJcct, and the Judgement would be
mstantaneously analytical Let us however waive the difficulty
and suppm,c, for argument's sake, that the synthesis takes place
first, and th,1t the Judgement becomes analytical on repet1t1on,
tlus 1s probably \\hat 1s mtcndcd, the temporal d1fiiculty havmg
escaped notice altogether. Now under v. hat c1rcumstanccs 1s
such a judgement repeated ? One obvious reason 1s to mform
some one else, who only knows that (s) 1 1s AB. For him the
Judgement (s)iAil 1s C 1s clearly synthet1cal But "hat of the
origmal author "hen he repeats (s)i 1s C ? Ile docs not mean
that the Judgement 1s vahd because of the identity bet\\een the
C m the predicate and the C he has already thought of as in
the subJect. On the contrary the statement 1s of no mterest
except as a repetlt10n of the ongmal ' synthesis '. It 1s not
mdeed a new truth to the person so Judging, but that does not
make 1t analytical ; and thus he \\ ould give as the reason
why (sh 1s C, not that (sh already contams C but whatever
reason had been found before for Jommg C to something
different from itself m (sh, viz AB. The importance then
of the l>tJ.tcmcnt "hen repeated hes Just m this synthesis
Synthetical and Analytical Statements 233
of C with elements different from itself, not in an equation of
C to itself.
If we msist on our previous obJection that a Judgement, if
it could become analytical at all, must do that mstantaneously,
then we could not really say it became analytical, but that it
always was both ; we could not say that the judgement had
lost its original synthctical character, but rather that it never
had a purely synthetical character. But such a change of state-
ment would be met precisely as before , for it would still be
true to say that the meaning of the Judgement as such lies in
the associat10n of C with elements other than itself, and never
m an analysis
§ 96. A difficulty may arise from the fact that when we repeat
' (sh 1s C ' we do not always think of the nature of the synthesis
of C with A and D. We seem at times only to remember that
(sh is C, and this may have the appearance of a mere analysis
of a conception m our mmds of (sh as ABC. This difficulty
1s unreal ; what we arc domg m such a case is not to make an
analysis, but to remember that there was a synthesis, though
for the moment we are not attendmg to its nature or may have
forgotten it. In a mathematical demonstration, for mstance, we
often use a formula without rcmembermg the process by which
1t was reached But the use of 1t 1s entirely due to its synthetical
character, and 1t 1s only thus that 1t can be any help 111 our
demonstration No one can get anythmg out of a statement
of the form C 1s C. Suppose that we wanted to prove (s) 1ABC
1s D, • and that we established tlus by showmg that D attaches
to C. Then the last stage of our argument has the form C 1s
D, but (s) 1 1s C, therefore (sh 1s D. Now as the conception of
(sh, as ABC, 1s presupposed, the premiss (~h is C may look like
a mere analyi,1s, but what we really do in tlus proof is to pick
out the attribute Cness from among the other known attnbutes
of (s)i as the one which 1s responsible for D. This shows the
truly synthet1cal character of the premiss we were usmg. We
should not have picked out this attribute at all unless it was
to be distinguished from the others, and that shows we were
thmking of (sh as somcthmg else besides C; (sh 1s not only
[• In the lectures the dlustrallon U&ed here wai. from ' the opposite angles
of a quadnlateral mscnbed m a circle are together equal to two right angles • ]
234 STATEMENT, TIIINKING, AND APPREHENSION
AB, but also C. Thus the interest of the ' judgement ' lies in
the synthesis of the different elements A, B, C. This comes out
clearly if, in that last stage of the argument (C is D, but (s) 1 is
C, therefore (sh is D), we replace the statement (sh is C, by
C is C. This shows us at once that the mterest of repeating
(sh 1s C hes not in any identity between C and (sh, but m some
d1fference. What we really want to say 1s that that which is
AB as well as C 1s also D, because Cncss involves Dness. This
1s equally true whether the presupposed conception (s)iABC is
the rcs•Jlt of a demonstrat10n that Ail necessitates C, or JS an
und1.,monstrated defimtion with which m a particular science
we begm. For the dcfimt1on itr,clf has only mc.inmg, interest,
and use because 1t 1s itself a synthesis of d1fTcrcnt elements.
§ 97. There 1s one general consideration which covers all cases.
If ' (sh JS C ', when repeated, were really an analytical Judge•
ment, 1t would be of the form (s) 1ABC 1s C, where C 1s exphe1t
both m subject ,.ind predicate, the truth of the Judgement would
then he 111 the Jclent1fic,it10n of C w1U1 1tc;clf, 111 other words,
the valt<l1ty of the Jt1<lgemrnt would be clc11ved entirely from
the Jdcnt1ra.l Judgement 'C 1s C '. Dut 1t 1s evident that the
so-called identical Judgement v10latcs the very idea of Judging.
There 1s no such thmg except as a verbal form It JS nothing
for thought, and, inasmuch as the analyt1cal thus rea11y
resolves itself mto an Jdcnt1cal Judgement, we may sc1y of Jt
.\h,o that 1t exists only as a form of wor<lr, and 1s nothing for
thought.
If now \\C give to 'r,ubJCl.t' ..md 'predicate' the mcanmg they
un<loubte<lly h.1, c 111 the or<lmary trc.itmcnt of the syllog1sm,
the subJcct bcmg \\hat 1s denoted by the nominative case to
the verb ' to be', au<l the prc<l1cate the adJcct1val phrase or
noun phr.ise winch follo\\s 1t (.1 <l1stmct10n we have designated
as that of subject and .1ttnbut1vc), the same general argument
"ill apply. For 1t ,viii be evident from what has been said of
the d1stmctlon that the purpoc;e of the attnbutivc 1s to express
for the subject an aspect of 1ls bC"mg chffl·rcnt from that expressed
m the nomm.itivc case The same agam holds m sentences
where the prmc1p.1l verb 1s not the verb 'to be', 1f the term
' predicate ' stands for the attnbutivc, and the attributive con•
sJsts of the verb or verb phrase attached to the nommative.
Synthetical and Analytical Statements 235
In conclusion then, the repetition of a synthetical judgement
has its meaning and value as recalling an original synthesis: its
meaning never is that the predicate is attached to the subject
because it 1s already there. The doctrine that a synthetical
passes mto an analytical Judgement is a mere confusion, and
strictly speaking there 1s no such thing as an analytical judge-
ment.
§ 98 • So far we have implied as the general form of every
affirmative statement, what 1s commonly calkd the categorical
form (m the ordmary notation, S 1s P), where a so-called pre-
dicate 1 P 1s absolutely affirmed of a subject S, and 1t has been
mamtamed that tlus uncond1t10nal affirmat10n is the necessary
characteristic of statement as such D1stmgmshed however from
the categorical we find m logic another form recogmzed, the
hypothetical, and 1t would of ten be said that by this 1s meant
a form in which the predicate 1s not absolutely affirmed of the
subject, but only under a ccrtam cond1t1on. If so, there would
be a form of statement m which the true predicate was not
absolutely affirmed of the true subject Tlus would seem to
contradict the account we have given, and we must therefore
consider the value of tlus currrnt d1stmct10n and ask whether
we must revise our account of statement so as to make the
hypothetical form co-ordmatc with the categorical.
We may take as the general form of an hypothetical propos1-
tl(m, m,mg the ordmary notation, 'S 1s P, if a certam cond1t10n
1s n·<th.ted ', or ' S 1~ P, 1f X 1s Y ', \\ her<' S 1s P I'> called the
wnscquent ,Llld the ' 1f ' cl..iusc the ..intcxcdcnt Now 1f we
confine our~dves to the idea of a cond1t10n, 1t 1s not necessary
to express a cond1t10n m an hypothetical form at all, for the
ordmary categorical statement of the form S ( =ABC) 1s P, really
' In the ordinary dt•fimtious of the catcgoncal and hypothetical proposi-
tions, the terms 'bUbJect • ,md •predicate• always have the meaning they
h.i.vc in the theory of the 1,yllog1sm, and denote not the logical 1,ub1ect and
predicate, but what we have called • i.ub1cct • and ' attributive • In the
following discussion the terms •subject• and •predicate' will be retained on
the underi,tandmg that tht.y h.i.vc Uub me.i.mng, because the theones examined
arc expressed m thu, terminology For the same reason the oi-dmary sym-
bohsm for the propob1bon will be used
categorical form is intelligible in itself and does not for its employ-
ment presuppose that we already understand the hypothetical.
Does the hypothetical statement then not only presuppose
the categorical by its very form but itself also contain a cate-
gorical element ;, If 1t docs not, how can we call it a statement,
for it will not satisfy the cond1t1on which we have hitherto
assumed as obvious, namely, that there 1s no statement or pro-
position unkc;s c;omcthing 1s defimtely stated of something else.
Now in the form ' 1£ A 1s B, C 1s D ', B 1s not assigned dcfimtely
as the predicate of A, nor D of C Neither of these pairs then
constitutes the true subJcct and prechcatc which make these
clauses together one statement correspondmg to one Judgement,
opmion, &c. W c must ask what 1s decided m the act of thought
wluch corresponds to such a statement In all hypothetical
affirmative statl'ments the affirmation which must be there to
make a statement at all 1s that the consequent 1s the necessary
result of the antecedent. This 1s a categorical statement, one
in which the prechcatc 1s attached to the subJect without any
condition. Tlus 1s offcred not as an arbitrary or possible reduc-
tion of the hypothetical form, but as the statement of what it
is m the complex hypothetical sentence \\ luch really makes 1t
into one statement, rC'prcscntatlve of one Judgement, opmion, &c.
The hypothetical form then cannot claim to be a d1stmct form
co-ordmate \\1th the categoncal m an ultimate logical analysis.
The supposed ddicrcncc between them, as represented m that
dcfimtron of them with wluch we started, 1s due to a comparison
of hypothetical and categorical forms in which the subject and
predicate arc only m appearance the same. Just so the modal
distinction of propositions was, we saw, due to a comparison of
statements \\ hose subJcct and predicate were only m appearance
the same.
We may also sec that tlus 1s true by various modes of logical
analysis, if we take prcd1ratc m the sense of 'logical ' predicate.
Thus 1f our qucst10n had been about the nature of C, C would
be the logical subJect m the statement 'C 1s D if A is B ',
and we should affirm that C 1s such as to be D 1f the condition
holds that A is B; that is, we attach a complex predicate (m the
logical sense of predicate) uncond1t1onally to C. Or suppose the
context were such that the antecedent itself was the subject.
Categorical and Hypothetical Statements a41
If the question were : ' what follows if A is B ? ', we should
m ' C is D, if A is B ' attach the consequent unconditionally
to the antecedent A is B, and the tone in which we pronounce
the clause 'C 1s D ', as contrasted with that in which we say
• A 1s B ', md1cates that 'C 1s D ' is the predicate.
§ 102. Hitherto we have for convenience described the ele•
mcnts m the hypothetical statement, which arc conceived as
necessarily connected, by help of the' grammatical forms wluch
rorrespond to them witlun the sentence, that is the antecedent
and the consequent But what do these exactly represent?
A common view is that m the statement, ' if A is D, C 1s D ',
a relat10n between two 'judgements' 1s affirmed, viz. that the
Judgement A 1s B ncccss1tates the Judgement C 1s D, and indeed
that 1s one way m which the hypothetical judgement is supposed
to be reduced to the categorical. This 1s entirely erroneous.
In the given form, A is B and C 1s D do not represent judge-
ments, simply because they arc not judged. We are uncertam
whether A 1s B, provided the particle ' 1£ ' is used in its normal
and proper meaning ; that is, when the statement 1s a true
hypothetical. So we do not Judge that A 1s B, and the words
'A ic; D ' (wlurh occur WC' observe not inclepC'ndcntly but
only m connexion with the ' 1£ ') do not represent a Judgement
at all Bemg uncertam then whether A 1s B, we are so far
uncertam whether C 1s D, and so the words ' C 1s D ' do not
represent a judgement either. If ' A 1s B ' really represented
a Judgement, we should be able to say, ex hypothesi, ' because
A is B, C 1s D '.
It 1s a quest10n or a problem to us whether A 1s B, and
a qucst10n whether C 1s D, and the hypothetical sentence states
a relat10n of a certam kmd between these problems, grounded
on our knowledge of the realities to which they relate The
statement 1s that the question whether A 1s B 1s a case of the
question whether C 1s D, and 1t may easily be shown that tlus
entirely accounts for the mfcrence which can be made from such
a statement. Or, to put 1t m a manner which accords more with
the actual cxpress10n, the form of statement (not the statement)
A 1s B necessitates the form C 1s D 1
1 This sub1ect, as well as that of the D1~1uncbve statement, 1s discussed
• It 1s not d1fhl.ult to show that the mam fallacy of• non-Euchdean space '
1s a complete m1bunderstandmg of h)pothcbcal tlunJ..mg and more especially
of the h)l>0thct1l.il • conccphon • Vidc Part III, ch 7 Another fallacy m
It I!> IIOli<-cd lll § J:?U,
Categorical and Hypothetical Statements 243
already made 1t is not a conception m the proper sense, but
a problem or question, and the very result of our argument (the
reductio ad absurdum) 1s to show not merely that such a concep-
tion is obJectively mvahd but that we cannot have the conception
at all, since the supposed connexion 1s shown to be unthinkable.
Now we obv10usly cannot argue from what we have not got.
The hypothetical statement then 1s an mfcrcnce, and an
mfercncc m non-hypothetical argument."
§ 103. Our general conclusion then 1s that the categorical
statement cannot possibly constitute a species of statement,
because all statement as such ts categorical. The expression of
every dcfimte judgement, or opinton, &c , is a categorical state-
ment m the sense that a connex10n between two sometlungs is
affirmed absolutely and uncond1ttonally The categorical state-
ment which expresses an hypothetical Judgement, or opmion,
states absolutely a connexion between two problems or questions
about reality. The categoncal statement which expresses a non-
hypothellcal Judgement or opm10n states absolutely a connexion
!Jetween realities.
The doctrmc then that the categorical statement cannot be
reduced to the hypothetical stnctly means that a given non-
hypothetical statement cannot be reduced to an hypothetical.
And we may obt.1111 another proof of this doctrmc from the
account we have given of the nature of hypothetical statement.
For obviously the statement of the connexion between realities
cannot be reduced to a statement of the connex10n between
problems. We must also withdraw the concess10n that the
hypothetical statement (e g 1f anything 1s A, it is B) can be
derived from the non-hypothet1cal, all A 1s B, for this 1s mac-
curate. All that 1s true m the supposed dcnvation or reduction
1s that 1£ the non-hypothetical 1s true, the hypothetical 1s true
also. The one cannot properly be said to be denved from the other
because the hypothetical 1mphes the uncertamty whether there
is such a tlung as A, wherec1.s the categorical 1mphes that this
is not uncertam but ccrtam, and obviously we cannot clcnve the
uncertainty of a thmg from its ccrtamty.
§ 104. The non-hypothetical statement ' all AB 1s C' only
entitles us to attribute Cncss to A under the condition Bness ;
[• 'The hypothetical Judgement 1s always an 10ference.' Bradley,
1 p 407]
C, 11,
R 2
244 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
it does not convey the information whether or not Bness is
a necessary condition, and therefore is so far compatible with all
A is C. The same 1s true of the hypothetical form, if A is B,
A is C. For this docs not exclude the poss1b1hty that A may
be C, even if A 1s not B. In both therefore there seems to be
the same ambiguity, and tlus remark applies also to the con-
ditional form (whenever A 1s B, A ,s C), which as such assumes
that thr cond1t1on exists It may reasonably be obJcctcd that
we must here attend to the normal use of language and that
the intention of an hypothetical proposition n, to state that an
A requires, as far as we know, to be under the cond1t1on of
bemg B, in order to be C. And so m the non-hypothetical form
all AB is C , for here again, the normal meaning 1s that we
cannot attach Cness to A without the cond1t1on Bness; other-
w1sc wc should c;ay A ts C. It nevertheless remains true that
even in tlus normal use of language there may be an ambiguity.
When a man says all AB 1s C, he ought to mean that, so far
as he knows, A 1s C not szmpl1C1tcr, but under the cond1t10n B.
But now B may contam more than the necessary c-ond1t1on and
therefore 1t docs not follow that the A which 1s C must neces-
s:mly be D Tlus kmd of amb1gu1ty may correspond to the
speaker's own unccrtamty ; for mstancc, m experimental science,
we may find that an A \\h1ch was without the attribute Cncss
gets that attribute when we mtroduce the cond1t1on Bness We
arc therefore entitled so far to say AB 1s C; but yet we may
be unaware how much of B 1s necessary and may have to
proceed to new experiments m order to eliminate everything
except the true cond1t1on.
Curiously enough,• this amb1gu1ty is found m the exact
demonstrations of mathemat1cc1.l science. It might seem that
this was not possible , that 1f we demonstrated the property D of
ABC, where D depends on A alone, we should derive D from
A. But tlus 1s by no means ah, ays the case. A mathemallcal
proof often enough derives D from the "hole nature of its sub-
JCCt as cxpref:>sed m its dcfimt10n, or at least from more than
the element A. The reasoner 1s not aware that he has introduced
[• ' Matht'mabc1ans do not st'em to l1avc noticed tlus and 1t came as
to B B, when I mentioned 1t to lum."-MS. note Cf Part V, xiv,
a bUT'pn'le
toD.B 71vo9;fromB B.101vo9}
Categorical and Hypothetical Statements 245
anything superfluous, while the examination of the argument
will not always show the superfluity. For instance, the harmonic
properties of the circle, for the demonstration of which its whole
definition is used, yet follow from a generic clement which
1t has in common with other come sections, a fact which can
be established by a different method of proof; but, though this
is so, the generic element formmg the definition of a conic section
cannot be discerned m the defimt10n of the circle used m the
given proof, nor anywhere m the proof itself.
§ 105. The hypothetical statement, as a general form, just hke
the universal cakgor1cal, cannot be converted simply. From
' all AB is C ' we cannot mfcr that ' all C is AB ', nor can we
from ' 1f A is B, A is C ' mfcr that ' 1f A 1s C, A 1s B '. We
shall show hereafter m dealing with mfcrence that the reason
hes Just m the amb1gmty with wluch the condition is expressed. 1
When the true or exact condition 1s stated, whether in the
categorical form or the hypothetical, either can be converted
simply. Thus ' all All 1s C ' can be converted into ' all C is
AB ', provided that AB is the sufficient and necessary condition
of C. Now, 1f this be true, smce an accurate scientific propos1-
tlon should state the cond1t1011 without the amb1gu1ty, should
give, that is to say, the sufficient and necessary condition, 1t
follows that a scientific propos1t10n, though 1t may be true, 1s
not perfectly accurate m form, unless 1t can be converted simply.
This may be at first unexpected, but mathematical demonstra-
t10ns present contmual examples of it, and it is a tes!. which
every perfectly accurate proof• must satisfy, that we should be
able to convert the conclusion. And if m any case we are unable
to convert the conclus1on, this 1s proof that the conclusion has
not been drawn from the accurate condition, m other words that
the condition states more than is necessary. A consequence of
this prmciple would be the dental of the 'plurality of causes '. 2
The vmdication of the prmc1ple itself will be reserved for the
theory of Inference.
NoTE. The treatment of hypothetical statement in these
sections requires to be supplemented by the lectures specially
devoted to hypothetical thought ; 3 but on reflection I must
1
if 352-3. 8
Part III, chs. 5-7.
[• Cf. § 259. Tlus 1s true only w1t.h the proviso 'sufficient and necessary'.
246 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
admit it to be a defect that only that sense of hypothesis is
di~cusscd here which corresponds to the ordinary meaning of
the term ' scientific hypothesis ', and no notice 1s taken of the
case where we know or believe that the condit10n stated in
the hypothetical clause 1s not reahzed-e g. 'if he had known
wha.t would be the consequence of consenting, he would not
have done 1t '. This case 1s directly but not sufficiently con-
sidered m the other set of lectures, a defect I mtcud to remedy.
I shl)ul<l hkc here to explam that the omission docs not mean
accept-inre of the doctrine held by some thmkers that the state-
ments m qucst10n arc not true hypothct1cals. At present I must
he content to say that such a view does not realize the full
difficulty caused by the fart that the only natural way of
expressing them 1s m the hypothetical form, with the particle
' 1£' expressed or understood, cg '1f A were B (as 1t is not),
C would be D '. Any other mode of exprcss10n would be very
difficult, and would stnke us at oncl, as art1fir1al. It seems also
to be qmte forgotten that a reductw ad absurdum proof 1s often
an mst,mce of the h.md, because the condition introduced by
the word ' 1£ ' t!> not conce1vcd and cannot be conceived as
possible , and yet from Am,totlc onwards these statements with
such clauses have been held as promment types of the merely
hypothettcJ.I Fmally the form '1£ A 1s 13, C is D ', which is
the proper form for the case where we arc unccrtam whether
A 1s B, and the form '1£ A were B {as 1t 1s not), C would be
D ', have tlus essential m common that m both cases A's bemg
D would be held to be somethmg conceived merely and not
represented as knov.n to be rc,tl though what this exactly
means requires careful d1scuss1on, and ought already to have
been taken account of 111 the present 10vest1gabon.
XII
NEGATION OR TUE QUALITY OF PROPOSITIONS •
' TI1c5e fall,tcu '> an- '>otm tlml'<, t,tk<'n very ,cr10u'>ly Thu, ma W< J1-known
book the general m1,tnk<• about n•l,ttlon (wluc.h can he c.,t,1ly <'XJ'll>'>t.d) 1'1
m..ide part of the h,:1<,1~ of a ml'taphy,1cal theory, and the muc tangle• of
a verb.ii fallac.y 1s quamtly taken to be a 5ort of '>Clf-wntrad1cbon m the
nature of Thought 1t,clf LV1dc Part V, §§ 433-7)
• Th1!> latter apprch<'n~1on 1~ a part of the forml'r, and not <,omcthmg added
to 1t For Bness bemg d1flcrcnt from Anc55 we nccl'&5anly apprehend this
"'hen we apprehend both Ancss and Bness, otherwise we should confuse 1t with
256 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
It may be objected that though not-Aness, or difference from
Aness, can only be apprehended in the apprehension of An•ess
and Bncss, and of Ancss and Cness, &c , yet the apprehension
of it may be d1stmgmshcd from the apprehension of them, and
1t can be appreh:.-nded as a umty m the difference of Bness from
Ancss, and the difference of Cnesc; from Aness, &c. ; m short
that a rclat1on, e g equality, can m general only be apprehended
along with the apprehension of tli.e terms related, and yet that
this docs not prevent our abstracting 1t from them, and appre-
hending 1t m abstraction as a umty m the different instances.
But surh abstraction 1s not always possible. One quality may
so depend upon and presuppose another that 1t cannot possibly
be separated from that other by any kind of abstraction For
mstancc, straightness can only be straightness of a hnc and
cannot be apprehended apart from lmeanty or in any abstrac•
tlon from lmearity Thus there 1s not, properly speaking, any
' conception ' of straightness in abstraction from lmearity. So
also oddnrss prcc;upposec; number. There 1s no conception of
oddncsci in itself, in abstraction from numbrr Such an abstrac-
tion could not be performed Similarly the negation of Ancss
can on the one hand only be apprehended as the difference from
Aness of some positive quality, say Bncss, and on the other
cannot po.,s1bly be abstracted from such pos1t1vc quality, Just
because negation is d1fTercncc of posillvcs. 1 Thus of not-Aness
in the abstract, or of difference from Aness in the abstract, there
is no apprehension or 'conception' whatever, any more than
there could be of oddness or straightness m abstraction from
lmc or number.
Further, "1th regard to the rase first alleged (the abstraction
of a rdatwn like equality), 1t 1s obvious" c cannot m our thought
abstract the concept10n of any rclat10n from the conception of
the kmd of terms it n.·latl's Of tluc; general principle negation
1s a particular case But JUSt as 111 the case of oddness \\C get
a true umvcrsal and true conception by takm~ m the nature
of number to wluch oddness belongs and which 1t presupposes,
Ancss Thus there 1s no app1ehens1on of the difference of Aness and Bness
other than the apprehension of both Aness and Bnc~s together
1 This 1s m effect the I'latomc doctrme, m the Sophist, that negation 1S
• othemess •, but with the add1tJon that there can be no conceptmn of other-
ness m abstraction from poS1bves whJ~h are 'other· than one another
Negation or Quality of Statements 257
could we not similarly in the case of not-Aness, by taking in
the nature of the positive being to which not-Aness belongs and
which it presupposes, get a true universal and a something
which could be apprehended in abstraction ? Is there not an
abstract unity in fact, apprehensible as such, which could be
called 'positive bemg m general which 1s not Aness'? We
shall find that the analogy does not hold, and that there is
again no reality to correspond to this verbal form of a universal.
We have to abstract from the not-Aness of special forms of
being, such as Bness, Cnesc:;, &c , determined Ill each case by
a positive character such as Bness and as inseparable from it
as oddness from odd number, and h.1.vc ex hypothesi to include
abstraction from the pos1t1ve natures of Bness, Cncss, Dness, &c.
Moreover this positive something, which 1s abstracted along with
the not-Aness, must be one and the c:;ame in all the mstances
Bncss, Cness, &c.
What will this abc:;tract1on be ? The pos1t1ve clement cannot
be positive bcmg in general, for that would mcludc Aness. It
must be a kmd of positive being somehow specially dcfin<'d.
But, as we have seen, there 1s no c:;pecial kmd of being common
to all that wluch is not-A, nothing, that ts, common to sound,
triangle, theft and so on by wlm.h these are all not-circular.
Thus the required abstract10n cannot be found.
The matter may be put also m tlus v. ay. The positive clement
which must be included in the proposed abstraction, as mdicated
m the verbal form, would have to be the special kmd ot positive
being which differs from Aness. Now difference from a given
somethmg Aness can only exist as caused by the positive
character of what 1s d1stmguished from the given somethmg.
Thus the distinction of the kmd of bemg to be abstracted as
being different from Ancss must depend on some positive quality
which 1t has Thus a positive quality must be common to all
the bemg which 1s not-Aness, which however 1s 1mposs1ble
This makes 1t evident what the fallacy of such an abstraction
consists in. It 1s the endeavour to define a special kmd of being
by the mere fact of its distinction from something else, which
is an inversion of the relation between defimtion and distinction.
For it is pos1t1ve definition (including the recognition of a positive
quality which 1s sui generis) which alone makes possible a dis•
s
258 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
tmction of the thing defined from other things. Such distinction
therefore presupposes a definition to explain it. The conclusion
arrived at is attested by the fact that every one would think
it absurd to institute any sort of inquiry into the nature of
not-Aness as something common to everything distinguished
from Aness, into the nature, say, of non-circularity as something
common to a triangle and a theft For this fact would be
unaccountable 1£ not•Aness were a true umversal,-were any-
thing of wlu<'h we could seriously be c;a1d to have any concept
or roncept10l'l, or wluch could itself be called in the ordinary
confused phraseology a ' concept '.
The mere verbal fallacy of bemg misled by the artificial form
' not-Am·ss • into supposing that there as a universal not-Aness,
or that there 1s a concept not-Ancsc;, or that there 1c; a concep•
tlou or ronrept of 1t, ha'l led to unworthy puzzles which have
been gravely taken for plulosopluc truths It 1s excusable to
find difficulty 111 getting at the exact nature of the mistakes 111
verbal fall,tc•1ec;, muced 1t 1c; often really difficult, but 1t 1s quite
inexcusable not to 5ee that they mu,;t be nonsense, and actually
to mistake !-Uch mfinmtics of mtellcct for subtleties of meta-
physic.
§ I 10. Smee not-Bnec;s does not represent a umvcrsal, or kmd
of bemg ,the reduction of (s) 1A 1s not 13 to the verbal form (s) 1A is
a not-B rannut c;cn e to reduce the negative statement to a true
affirmative form llo,,ever, 1t nught be contendrd that the
statement (s)iA 1s not I3 puts (s) 1A 111c;1de thl' sphere of reality
which 1s outside what 1s B, and that tlus gets ,·erbal expression
in fact m the form of statement (s) 1A 1s a not-B. Now it is
quite possible th.1t i,omc c,nc who chooses tlus latter form
deliberately does mtend that (s)i has some other place in the
reality outside B and that may bl· precisely has reason for
choosing it. Tlus would at once suggest that he chooses this
form because the usual negatav<:> c;tatement has not naturally
that imphcataon That 1t has not got this 1mphcatlon 1s indeed
the truth, the intention of the form b<'mg normally only to
exclude (s)iA from "hat 1c; B and not at all to assign (s}i a place
m reality. But more than tlus. It 1s not true that the negative
statement as such, (s) 1A 1s not B, necessarily implies that (s)i
has a position m that other sphere of reality at all ; it is com-
Negation <W Quality of Statements 259
patible with the statement that (s)iA as (s)iA has no being
whatever. If I find that this page is not in my book, it does
not follow that the page, as a page, 1s anywhere. The page
may have been burnt, and, as a page, have absolutely no
existence. ' The pam 1s not in my head now ' means that the
pain has no existence, not that it exists somewhere else. To
avoid misunderstanding, we shall return to this sort of example
in the discussion of statements wh1rh assert complete non-
existence
To return, (s)iA 1s a not-B al all events gives us no mformation
about the pos1t1011 of (s) 1 m the 111fi111tc sphere of reality outside
what is B Whatever (s) 1 may be pos1tivcly remams unknown,
since merely to put (s) 1 in this mfimte unknown (for we are here
to omit the only thmg by wluch 1t can be known, namely, its
exclusion from what 1s B), is to give it no positive determination
of being whatever. We have already seen, m the example of
'five is not an even number', that when such a positive deter-
mination seems possible, 1t 1s only because wr have combined
with the negative statement a d1sJunct1ve affirmative which
confines not-B to one or more defimte positive realizations,
thereby really lumtmg the sphere of not-B to a portion of the
infinite not-B This 1s what 1s done mall ehmmative arguments.
In them we seem to arrive at a kno" ledge of what (s} 1 is by
'ltatcment'l of what 1t 1s not. Yet these ncgatJvrs only serve to
give (sh a positive detcrmmat1011 because they cancel certain
pos1t1ve alternatives wlurh are given to (..,) 1 111 a disJunctlve
statement. Thus, 1f (s)i 1s either B or C or D, the negatives,
(s) 1 is not C and (s) 1 ts not D, m rombmat1011 with this dis-
Junction, give us finally (s) 1 ts B. This 1s an ehmmative argument
and is the analys1c; of what Bacon and Jue; modern followers
understand by mductlon
Finally, then, the negative statement taken by itself cannot
give pos1t1vc detcrmmabon as the affirmative docs. It remains
essentially different m spite of the apparent reduction, which is
merely verbal Moreover, although 1t l'l true that ordinary
negative statements (cg. nobody m the next room can read
Greek), hke ordmary affirmative ones, normally presuppose the
existence of their subJects of attribution, this existence is not
asserted by the negative statement as such.
82
260 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
§ I I I. It will save fruitless effort if we recogniz~ at this point
that we cannot profess to explain negation and its correlative
affirmation. Negation and affirmation may be contrasted, but
they cannot be explained or derived from one another, nor
understood through anythmg but themselves. Anything given
as the basis of such an explanation, to be mtelhgible, would
have to presuppose the thing explained They are not in fact
among the things to "luch thl' idea of explanation can have
any application
• The most direct and adl'quatc tlung we can say 1£ we wish
to dr-sa1be the chffrrcncC' bet WC'C'll affirmative and negative
statcmentc; secmr;; to be tlus. An affirmative (s)iA ic; B giver;; m
its attributive a kind of bemg wluch the subJect of attribution
has, while the' negative gives a kind of bemg which this subJect
has not Further, a negative cannot give a kind of being which
the subject has without presupposing a strictly affirmative state•
ment. Conversely, the affirmative cannot perform the func•
t1on of a negative, and tl'II us wh:1.t sort of being a subJect has
not, except by the assumpt10n of ncgat1vr statements. If
I know (s) 1A 1c; B, I do not know (s) 1 1s not r, unless I have
the negative :-tatement 'what 1s B 1s not C '. Now both
statements do somcl10\\ advance our knowledge and make our
conceptions more dcterminate.b If then we merely define the
affirmative statement as one "hich gives a further determination
to the conception we have of the subJect, that might be under-
stood of the negative statement also Suppose I know (s) 1 as
A, and \\tshmg to extend my knowledge ask v.hl'ther (sh 1s B,
or C, or D, so that (s) 1 1s the logical subJect The question
1mphcs that for me the' conccpt10n of (s) 1 1c; indeterminate with
respect to B, C, :mrl n, and thus my concept10n of (s)i includes
an unknown fidd of pos..,1h1ht1C's, bemg mdccd so far problematic.
Now when I arrive at (s) 1 1s not B (m \\ h1ch logical subJect and
subject of attribution eomc1de) my conception of (s) 1 is more
determinate on the one hand than 1t was, because a certain
field of possibility is definitely excluded On the other hand it
is more adequate to reahty, for I no longer thmk it possible
[• 211d para ' Rephrase all through \\here the word " conception " occurs •
MS not, The reason for this will appear from Part II, ch xiv
b 'Alter dre,,,m1nt11,11n language', MS notr, repeated at§ 112)
N egatioti or Quality of Statements 261
signa. But this way is not open since both cunning and foxness
are considered as part of the content of fox. And of course it
is absurd to suppose that the image of the particular fox either
• means ' or ' symbolizes ' or is ' a sign of ' either cunning or
foxness.
The final classification appears to be :
sign
(a) natural sign (b) conventional or arbitrary
sign
(a,) secondary
-----~ ----
-=sign which has not a natural
meaning.
standing viz. symbol (no indication whether to be
directly standing subdivided into primary
for its indirectly and secondary)
meaning, for its
meaning,
e.g. fox e.g. fox
symbolizing symbobzmg
foxness cunning
But what possible sense could be assigned to standmg ' m•
directly ' for 1ts meaning ~ ' Direct ' and ' mdirect ' are here as
impossible of application as straight and crooked, and the use of
such terms betrays an extraordinary confusion
The only chance of getting any meaning into such an expression
seems to be to make the sign, which 1s nothing but a sign, stand
' directly ' for its meaning For instance + stands for division
and is nothing but a sign of div1S1on, while fox is something in
itself, besides being taken as a symbol of cunning, and so by an
abuse of language might be said not to stand directly for cunning.
But then it would be the arbitrary sign alone which could be caUed
direct and all the natural ones would have to be called indirect.
This account of sign and symbol and meaning is in fact utter
confusion
f 125. It has been pointed out above that strictly things can•
not mean anything, that it is we who ' mean ', and we mean
something by some sign or symbol which we use for the purpo,e.
There are two such uses .
I. We use a symbol, e g a word, for communication of our
U2
292 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
thought to others. But of course no such use can be made of
our mental images, which can only be in our own consciousness
and not in that of others.
II. (i) We use symbols for the operations of our own thinking
as in algebra. :But clearly there is no use of mental images
analogous to this.
(ii) We usc language 111 our own med1tat1on and thinking and
certainly thmk by help of 1t The symbol 1s here merely con-
\"entional and so far there 1s no analogy between 1t and the
mental images :'.\or <lo they (the mental images) enter mto any
system of constructc·d rcJatwns like the symbols of algebra, or
\\ ords m their grammatical construct1on.
There is howe\ er a certain analogy In thmking by means
of ·words, we use "ords and we are not thinking of them but
of things, of tlungs or m1httes meant by these words. In
thmkmg about realities, md1v1duals not present to us, we use
mental images and we are not thmkmg about the images but
1:1bout those reabtles But there 1s this great difference, that we
do not use the images as signs or symbols of the realities; on
the c-ontrary they are our imagination of "hat the reality really
looks hke Wt> might rightly say 'that 1s how we suppose the
reahty looks ' and tlas 1s language wluch \\ c would never apply
to a symbol.
Besides there 1s an important use made of mental images
when we thmk of um versa ls. Agam 1t may be said "e use the
mental images Mr liradley mdced 1s stnctly hardly entitled
even to the help, i,uch as 1t 1s, of tlw, fact, for lie says 1t 1s the
mental image as suc-h \\luch \\l' do not use. We are not thmkmg
of the 1ma~cs but t'{ the umversals. But here agam they arc
not used ai. S) mbols of the um\'crsals. On the contrary, we can
only thmk of the Ulll\ ersal as realized m a particular and the
mental image 1s of use only as the image of such a particular.
We imagme ourselves to be actually contemplatmg a particular
m which the universal 1s realized
To put 1t in the simplest language When we are thinking
of particulars absent from perception, "e are imagining the
object itself thought about (the obJect we are thinking about),
not imagining a symbol of 1t : in thinking of a universal we
Attempts to Define 'J1«Jgement ' :z93
imagme a particular realization of the universal, we do not
imagine a symbol of it.
There is a grain of truth m what Mr Bradley says in so far
as the analogies above pointed out obtain, but they do not
conduct to symbolism and he has almost entirely mistaken the
real condition of the facts and the function of the mental image.
He speaks as 1£ the mental image were for purposes of thought
related only to a universal wluch is 1ts meaning. The mental
image of a horse has to do "1th Judgement only as havmg the
universal horseness for its' meaning'. We' use' only the mean-
mgs and the meaning is for him (as shown m his dlustrat1on of
the horse image) a part of the content, namely 1s a universal.
We think, he says, or rather assert the fact the image stands
for, not the image In that case ,, e should make assertions only
about universals and our mental images would relate only to
these. But ob'\iously our mental images constantly relate to
md1v1duals, and c1.rc not there merely to help us thmk umversals,
but constantly to help us tlunk particulars He says, indeed,
"e always predicate the ' logical idea ', which strictly implies
that the predicate 1s always universal. Tlus 1s not true, the
predicate (the true Iog1cal predicate) may be particular. There
1s in this connexion an important difficulty, which 1s not pro•
v1ded for m his imperfect analysis. It does not however affect
the present cr1tJC1sm. We thmk of the 1mage as hke the object
and we say that the obJect looks hkc what we are imagining.
But an image 1s not like an obJecl as an obJeCt 1s hkc an object.
One horse 1s hke another m the real umversal ' horseness ' both
are mamfestat1ons or reah,mt1ons of ' horscness ' and that 1s why
they are ahke But an 1magmary horse 1s not a realization or
mamfestatlon of real horseness, it 1s simply (and the language
1s accurate and can hardly be improved) the 1magmat1on of
such a reahzat1on Thus the 11nagmary horse 1s uot like the real
horse m the real umvcrsal horsencss: its bkeness to the real
horse does not consist m its bemg, hke that, a reah.tat1on of
horseness.
Now when the author treats ' horseness ', which is what we
assert and so is the real (what the mental image of the horse
stands for), as a part of the content of the mental imaie of
294 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREBiNSION
a horse, he baa implicitly made horseness equivalent to real
horseness, present in or realized in the mental horse-image.
Thus he can in no way distinguish the imagination from the
experience of a horse. The truth perhaps is that he has not
reflected enough on the matter to be fully conscious of what he
is doing. It 1s perhaps significant that, in his account of the
Association of ideas, he commits himself to an explanation which
confounds experience with imagination.
XIV•
APPREHENSION, CONCEPTION, AND STATEMENT
§ 126. THE subjects to be considered, according to the ordina,ry
phraseology, m this chapter would be described as the relation
of Conception and Judgement; more particularly (1) the differ-
ence between Conception and Judgement, and the questions
whether (i1) Conception precedes Judgement and (iii) truth and
falsehood belong to Judgements only and not to conceptions.
But the very form in which these problems are raised implies
the acceptance of certam distmctions without critical examina·
tion, which must first be disputed. The questions themselves
cannot be clearly proposed untll the presuppositions of their
ordinary formulation have been weighed.
In the judgement of knowledge and the act of knowledge, we
do not combme our apprehensions but apprehend a combina•
tion. That 1s, while we apprehend (s) 1A and Bness (that is, have
our conceptions of them), we also apprehend their relation and
unity. Now obviously the conceptions themselves are not the
given judgement nor are the apprehensions of them the appre•
hension which constitutes the Judgement. The question then
naturally arises as to the difference, 1£ any, between concr.ption
and Judgement. In our account "e have used the term appre•
hension sometimes for one and sometimes for the other. Are
then the apprehensions of (s)iA and of B or Bness themselves
judgements ? The question 1s of importance and applies to judge•
ment m its strict sense as well as m the erroneous sense which
we have criticized Let us first consider how 1t has been treated
m modern logic and in some early writers, ancient and modern.
In the modern substitution of terms of thought for terms of
language, judgement tends to be represented as a synthesis of
conceptions. The verbal form 1s considered to be the expression
of a subjective act of thought called Judgement, and the single
[• II 126-141 (except 138-g) were revised m 1914-15 The tenmnology,
however, especially the vexed word' Judgement', was not alt~red consistently.]
2g6 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
1775•1 Aa
XVI•
CLASSIFICATION
§ I 5I. THE recognition of the universal has given rise to
important questions "luch conrcrn metaphysic and psychology
ct<, well as logic The contrast between the universal and the
particular presents certain difficulties to thought. Real existence
seems all particular, although the universal is necessary even to
a smgle statement or apprehension Hence there is a tendency
to represent the umversal as a subjective product, as a mere
idea. T}u., leads to a further difficulty because 1t is found that
the universal as such cannot be presented to imagination any
more than to perception. Thus ongmated the well-known con•
troversy between conccptuah-,m, realism, and nommahsm, a sub-
ject which belongs to metaphysics and psychology rather than
to logic To tl11c;, though properly metaphysical, we shall
return , at present we shall concern ourselves only with classi-
fication and the cognate subJect defimtion, recognized parts of
the traditional log1r.
§ I 52. Clasc;1ficahon 1s an activity of the human mind m
knowing obJcctc; ; an act1v1ty which logic does not create but
can only reflect upon. Formal logic has in tlus branch of the
study made the same mistake as m the case of the syllogism ;
1t has tned to gmde the mmd by warning 1t against fallacies
which 11 could not possibly commit. Thus 1t has enunciated
the grave dictum that 111 dividing a class we must not pass from
one fundamentum divisioms to another, but must divide by one
surh principle only. The reflectivt' consc10usncss which is logic
assmulates itself in fact too closely to the scientific consciousness
which 1s not reflective but directs itself to obJccts. As that
consciousness lays down rules, so logic tends mistakenly to
[• See notes 011 the 'IOurccs • fh1~ requires to be entirely rewntten and
the word roncept everywhere taken out ' MS ,iott He had intended to
embody also H 46o-76 in the course The foot-note references are D10Stly
.upplied conJecturally )
Classification 355
regard itself as testing the value of the rules which it examines
and even as producing correctness in them. Now what it is
examining are just the rules of thinking, rules therefore that
cannot be broken. Thought cannot justify its own rules or even
criticize them.
§ 153. The study of classification comes quite at the beginnings
of logic, implicitly in Plato,• explicitly in Aristotle.b This is
natural ; for the most elementary act of knowledge must involve
classification, and reflection upon that knowledge is logic Our
knowledge begins, doubtless, by attention to particulars m
experience and 1s stimulated by practical needs, not originally
by a desire for knowledge for its own sake. Mankmd, faced by
practical needs, seeks practical rules so as to know how to deal
with nature ; frames principles to go by m action. Such a rule
or principle is a universal We seek something which we can
count on at all times and m all the variety of the different
cases, and this is a umty by contrast with such variety. Even
if the knowledge be of a particular object, what is sought is
knowledge of the behaviour of that obJrct not at one time only
but at all times, and so 1s universal as compared with the different
times in which the behaviour ic, manifested The interest of
knowledge, whether theoretical or practical, will go further and
ask for a reason, and a reason or an explanation 1s, m the nature
of the case, umversal. Indeed even the attempt to represent
ourselves as knowmg one mdividual by itself inevitably involves
the universal. To know an obJect as something defimte, it must
be distinguished from other objects and is tl1us necessarily
related to them, must have something m common with them.
To distinguish 1s also to umfy. The characteristics we assign
to the individual have also a universal character as we recognize
something in it which might be applicable to other individuals. 1
1 Cf §§ 141 and 145 on thought as always umversabzmg 1ts ob3ect, and
Anstotle's generahzabon of the fact oi perception, d "14P _, l,nw ,t ala"1t11r ,-oij
'l"OCoiia• .nl pt} ,-oual .,.,,,o,, l'Ven 1f sense perception 1s of the ' so and so ' and not
of some particular ' t!J1s ' An Po 87b 28, cf 100a 16
[• ti o~i, n) -,,.,or 1.lirAws "~ l11T1 mpa T4 tlir .,,.,011, .ra,, • d ln1 pir, ells llA,, ,,. i11Tl11
(t l'i" -,np ct,a,i,q -,1..os iral iiA'I •••) 1038& 5, cf. 1058• 23]
Classification
call the species a determination or "differentiation of the genus;
for although this explains nothing, it may guard against a
misunderstanding of that peculiar relation which we have been
trying to recognize. We recognize rather than explain it, for
explanation usually means the reference of the thmg to be
explained to something similar to but not identical with itself.
This relation is sui generis and therefore defies explanation, is
not expressible in terms of anything but itself.
f 16o. We have then two kinds of classes. Symbolizing the
elements by AB , m the one kmd, A, though it may involve
B, is not a determination of B, nor B of A, though it may
involve A , 10 the second kind, one of these elements is a deter-
mination of the other. It 1s this difference that really determines
the usage of langu.1ge. In the first case it is neither natural nor
normal usage to represent AB as a kind or species of A or of B.
No doubt it is somehow felt that sphere, for example, does not
include, in its own nature, golden sphere On the other hand
we have no difficulty 10 speakmg of red as a kmd of colour, or
of triangle as a k10d of figure The tendency of language then
1s in favour of recogmzmg the second .is tJ1c true application
of these kinds of words The obv10us mark of the distinction
between the two ktnds of class 1i. the md1fference with wl1ich
in the one case either may be taken as genus or d1fferentia,
whereas 10 the other 1t 1s 1mposs1ble to reverse the order. The
ultimate agreement between them is the contrast between the
wider and the narrower class, where wider ~nd narrower refer
to the extension. The class A mcludes the md1v1duals of
the species AB, whether B 1s or 1s not a true d1fferentia
of A.
§ 161. The logical theory of d1v1s1011 originates m the fact that
the genus includes its species ac; a plurality and thl' species its
sub-species. This suggests the question whether any general
rule can be laid down a priori for the subd1vis1on of a genus.
Let A and B be the elements of a given general conception.
One may be either a differentiation of the other or not. In the
latter, case we may further distinguish two kinds. First that
in which A and B seem indifferent to each other, and secondly
that in which A involves B, but not m the way of differentiation.
Thus m three-sided (closed) rectihnear figure the possession of
362 STATEMEN:f, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
three sides involves the possession of three angles, but neither
of these two attributes 1s a differentiation of the other.
In the d1vis1on of a class then we have these three cases to
consider. The data of the division are, first the differentiation
to which each of the elements A and B 1s hable in itself, and
secondly the fact that A and B are not alone but in combination.
Case I. Take the case where neither of the elements A and B
necessitates the other. Let the d1ffercnt1ations of A be a1 a11
a 3 , &c., and of B, b1 b2 b3 , &c Though the nature of the one
element does not necessitate the other we cannot assume that
any member of the series a 1 a 2 &c can be combmed with any
member of b1 b2, for A and B are m combination and this may
hmit the possibihttes of combmat1011 of their respective differ-
cntiae. Thus we have prima facie two cases that m which
the d1fferentlat1on rcmams free m spite of the combination
of A and B, and that m which the combmation of A and B
prescribes certain limits to the combmat1on of their differentiae.
Case II. Let A and B mvolvc one another Herc 1t might be
supposed that the poss1b1htlc!, of combm,ttlon were limited,
inasmuch as the elements involve one another. For instance,
the possession of three sides by every triangle necessitates the
possession of three angles, and the differentiations of the sides
in respect of ratio cond1t1on the d1fferentic:Ltlon of the angles,
i e. their magnitude. The d1fferent1c:Ltlons of the one then are
not free from influence by the d1ffcrent1at1ons of the other. Bul
this is not umversally Lhc ca!,C A certain closed surface neces-
sitates a certain enclosed volume, but the various ddferentia-
t1ons of the surface may be combmed indifferently with any
differentiation of volume m respect of quantity. Thus a given
volume may be enclosed by a surface of any shape whatever.
But, in this case, there is nevertheless a limitation of the freedom
of diff erent1at1on 1£ we choose a dtff erent prmctple of division.
Although it is true that the magnitude of a given volume cannot
determine the shape of the surface which encloses it, yet, if the
shape be given 10 kmd, the volume does determine the differentia•
tion of certain of the elements of the shape. If, for instance,
the shape is to be spherical, spheres are d1fferent1ated by the
length of their radii, but a given volume determines one radius
only. Or, if the shape is to be a parallelepiped, the magnitude
Classification
of the volume enclosed does not indeed fix any of the dimensions
of the enclosing surface but it does determine their differentia•
tions taken all together. If we choose arbitrarily a certain
length and breadth, we cannot choose any height we please.
The three dimensions together are controlled by the rule that
their product must be equal to a constant. In certain directions
then the differentiation of the two elements is independent, and
so again the differentiation of the body enclosed is independent
m respect of quabty of all differentiations of the surface whether
of kind or magmtude.
In each then of these two prmc1pal cc:l.ses we have a priori
the alternative poss1bd1tics of a free or a determinate differentia-
tion. The information necessary to settle what 1s actually true
of any particular class, whether the d1fferent1ations are free or
not, and, if so, by what law they are controlled, cannot be supplied
by logic but must be got by experience and from the special
sciences Logic c.i.n only formulate a priori the different general
cases and the two possib1htics of free or hnuted differentiation.
Case Ill. Fmally, where B 1s a true d1ffcrentiatton of A, we
have only to do with the free differentiations of the one cle•
ment A.
§ 162. In the precedmg we hc:l.ve stated the data for dividing
a class. If we wish to d1stmguish the species, we must do it by
cons1dermg the various d1fferenttattons of the elements m a given
umversal and the law of their combmatlon as affectmg in them
the combination of these different d1fferenhae... D1v1sion of
a class, however, is not necessarily understood to be an enumera-
tion of all possible species Sometimes "e only seek fur a division
which may exhaust the species m this sense, that the classes we
assign, while mutually exclusive, contam all other possible
species under them. Such a div1s1011 mc:l.y be reached by
differenbatmg one element only of the general conception, for
clearly the species formed by combmmg the other elements of
the original notion with a complete set of differentlae of the one
chosen must be exhaustive By a complete set of d1fferentiae
is here meant not all differentiations of A but the complete set
[• A species m modem botany includes ' all md1v1duals winch resemble
each other sufficiently to make us conclude that they are all, or may have
been all, descended from a. common plant ', British Flor11, •, Bentham &
Hooker, p. xi Cf. Essay II 1n Dr. Poulton's Essays 011 Evolution (Oxford, 1908) ]
364 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
allowable to it when combined with B and C. For instance, if
ABC is the original notion and a 1 a1 a3 are the complete diif~-
entiations of A for this purpose, an exhaustive and exclusive
division of ABC is clearly a 1 BC, a 11BC, a 3BC. The element thus
selected is the so-called fundamentum divisionis. The ordinary
rules about the fallacies to be avoided in division need not be
here discussed. It is obvious that a complete differentiation of
the class proceeds by differentiating simultaneously all the
elements and takmg such combmattons of them as the rule of
the original combination permits, and it is here that the idea
of co-ordination arises. Let the elements of the genus be A and
B. Suppose the first determmations of A are a1, a 1, 4 8 ; these
are said to be co-ordinate as bemg 1mmed1ate differentiations
of A. Let the immediate differentiations of a 1 be a11, a11, a18 i
these a.lso are co-ordinate with each other but are not co-ordinate
with 4 1, a2, or a 3• Thus co-ordmat1on 1s the relation of certain
species to one another, as being aU ahke members of one
differentiation of a common element They are said to be
subordinate to the common element ddforentiatcd If now we
have species of the form a1 b1 and a 2 b2 (where b1 and b8 are
co-ordinate d1ff crentiations of B), since these two complexes
result by immediate diffcrent1at1on of A and B are they also
co-ordinate ? The answer accordmg to the normal use of the
word co-ordinate would seem to be ' No '. Co-ordmation appears
normally to refer to the differentiation of one single element.
Thus a 1 b1 and a2 b2 would be co-ordinate only as subordinate to
A and through the co-ordmate differentiation of A mto a 1 and a 1•
§ 163. There 1s another relat1011 usually recogmzed between
these immediate d1fferent1ations of a common element. They are
somet1mes sa1d to be opposed So Aristotle defines opposites •
as the members of the same genus wluch arc at the farthest
distance from one another But m some genera we do not find
it natural to speak of the species as opposed to one another at
all. We do not, for instance, naturally ask what 1s the opposite
of a square. Agam it is often impossible to determine what
t• Cf besides Caugories 61- 1'l, p 366, note r, TA '" mw,jl 'ffllfl W'AltrrOP
3'11fP'P""Tfl illflll'ria, Metaph. 1055• 28, al. We cannot translate ' ccmtranea •
tbough that is nearer to wbat Wllson means than the genenc word • opposrtel •.
He wrote ,,,_;a m his MS ]
Classification
members of a classification, even if we do not actually use the
word opposition, have the maximum difference from one another.
The species sometimes form a series which either terminates in
neither direction or only in one. Of the former kind is a series
of differences in intensity ; 1 of the latter kind is the infinite
series of rectilineal figures beginning with triangle. It must be
noticed that we are dealing with a question partly linguistic and
partly technical and the difficulties which concern the use of the
word • opposite ' apply also to its Greek correlate.
We also d1stmguish opposition and contradiction. Contra•
diction is the mere negation of a given species and the con-
tradictory therefore mcludes all the species co-ordinate w1th the
given one. The opposite falls within the contradictory, and is
considered, m some sense, as the extreme of difference within
the given genus. What does this exactly mean and to what
kinds of classes 1s it applicable ? If in a given classification we
cannot get extremes of which we can definitely say that they
have the maximum difference, it does not follow that we cannot
distinguish degrees of difference. We may still be able to say
that the species A is more opposed to the species B than to the
species C. Perhaps it might be said that the meaning of opposi-
tion is that the opposed species are entirely incompatible and
cannot coexist m the unity of the same subject For instance,
moral good and moral evil might be opposite, m this sense. But
this is obviously true of all co-ordinate species ; each one
excludes every other Isosceles triangle 1s clearly more akin to
equilateral than to scalene triangle, yet properly understood the
isosceles triangle cannot be equilateral. Orange is more akin to
red than to green, but the same colour cannot be both orange
and red ; and so of the notes of a musical scale This therefore
will not do for a defimtlon of opposition
Perhaps the true account of what 1s implied m the normal
use of opposition m reference to species of the same genus may
be as follows. Suppose the generic clement is differentiated
.according to a principle which produces a series of species in
1 Cf. Plato, Phslebus, [24 n,•) quahtJ.es hke hot and cold.
[• The reference seems to be that given in the foot-note "P"X°'fM' .,dp iral
.... ,.,_ ff Tf lrpplrr,po,, dtl iral Tl> ,fn,xp/,Ttpol' cliaumr , , , l.-.11pov "l('Y"O'T" 4,, N
fJ,pplrr,po,, •2 TOWIIJ'Tiov 4114 ]
366 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
a certain order. (We may leave the kind of order undetermined,
provided only that it be an order ) Then one species as a member
of this order, if not the first or last in order, will have one before
it in the order and one after it It will be nearer to these, in
the sense of the particular order, than to any other member of
the series. Thus in the series of natural members 4 is nearer
to 3 and to 5 than to any other number. And in general, in
the order ABC, we may c;ay there is a greater difference between
A and C than between B and A or B and C This seems to be
what is meant by comparative opposition, when we say one
species is more opposed to another than 1t 1s to a third. If
there is a definite beginning and end to the series, the beginning
species and the end species arc clearly farther from one another
than are any other pair. 1 a Tlus corresponds to the idea of
absolute opposition, Aristotle's ' opposites'. 2
§ 164. But it does not follow that relative or absolute opposi-
tion should be found 111 every class. Neither will be found in
the division of a genus unless the prmciple of differentiation is
one which produces an order. Thus m certain divisions of plants
and animals we do not thmk of usmg the term opposition. If
there is an order, but the series hac; not a definite end and
beginning, there 1s only relative and not absolute opposition.
Thus the series of integers has a begmmng but no end and there
1s no absolute opposition. Again, any geometrical series may
progress ad infinitum m both directionc; from a given member,
and the series of finite portions of a straight hne is infinite in
a positive and m a negative direction from a given finite portion.
The subJect is well illustrated by observing that 1f we differentiate
a genus by two different prmc1ples, producing two different
orders of the same species, we shall have different ideas of
opposition. If we d1fferent1ate ' come section ' by the angle
which the cuttmg plane makes with the axis of a circular
cone, we shall have the hyperbola, the parabola and the ellipse,
as the angle is less than, equal to, or greater than, half the
vertical angle. Here hyperbola and ellipse are most opposed.
1 -rd wAE&ffov d.\,\17.wr llfltT'7ltOTa , , •• lvavTla 6pl,011Ta& Cal, 6& I 7.
1 ia,a.,.•r'a
C- Rather • any other two opposed species'. On the general subJect see
Hegel, Logic, (Encyc ) f r 19.]
Classification
If we differentiate however by the distinction between central
and non•central curves, ellipse and hyperbola will be grouped
together and opposed to the parabola.
In the mathematical illustrations the order is definite in such
a way that we can state definitely the difference between the
species ; but we may be able to place the members of a genus
in a certain order and to recognize a greater affimty between
one pair than between another and yet have no definite state•
ment of the nature of the difference between them. Thus in
the order of colours, \\e rccogmze that orange comes between
red and yellow There is an affimty between red and orange
and between orange and yellow and more in each case than
between red and yellow Thi,;; re,;ults from an immediate per•
ception of colour, not reducible to terms of anything else. So
with the order of musical notes in c1. d1atomc scale. We recog•
nize an order of pitch and are certain that in that order the
mediant, for instance, hes between the tome and the dominant,
and that the sub-med1ant follows the dominant, in the ascending
order. We can say no more of 1t and need to say no more than
that it is an order of pitch "h1ch we recognize as certainly as
an order m space.
§ 165. There remains the method of dichotomy. This takes
one differentla and divides the whole field of a class into the
members which have this and those wluch have not. Thi,;
method, as Aristotle says, 1s exhaustive ; but then the negative
class as such admits of no further divu,1on or, as he puts it,
' there are no d1ff erences of negation, merely as negation ' ; 1
mere negation contains no principle of differentiation and there-
fore there 1s no real gain m the apparent exhaustiveness.
§ 166. It follows from what has been said that the complete
and true method of dividing the universal 1s by co-ordinate
positive diffcrentiae. 2 But now the question arises how we are
in practice to effect such an exhaustive division. If we suppose
(as the common logic seems often to do) that we begin with the
perfectly determined mdividuals (with the maximum, that is, of
intension) and then proceed by abstraction to universals and
1 -ETI 11Tfp{/rff& ,.i., <Wa-ywoi, &,u,-ii, #tu &a,paiia"' ol a,xoTOfll)iii,Ttr, 0(,11 ' " ' Ii
&a,t,opd. 11Tff"l/lfO,S, ; 11Tlflll111S' davl'UTOI' -,a.p .ra., ,r.a, Toii ,.~ iwTOS De PMt. A,mn.
64:zb Zl, [Cf. II 460-476)
1 r!.rr,ll&vpr,,.la,a, &a,t,upnf, Top 141• 36
368 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
thus to complete classification, division will appear merely as
the inverse of that process, implying the previous process to
give it its material. This however does not correspond to the
actual process of thought. We are presupposing that which is
wanted as already done, and all we should be doing would be
a mere matter of arranging species in an order of subordination
and co-ordination This we could not fail to do, provided we
had them at all. Classification and division are not a mere
fom1al, or so-called logical, operation performed on a given
matter. The process is not formal at all but has to be effected
in the sciences as distmguished from logic and depends entirely
on the particular subject-matter. Thus the differentiation of
plane triangle mto acute, right-angled, and obtuse depends in
Euclid on many propositions which terminate with the con-
clusion necessary to the classification, namcJy a proof that the
three interior angles of any plane rcctdineal triangle are equal
to two right angles The species of triangle then are necessarily,
one with three acute angles, one with a right angle and two
acute angles, one with an obtuse angle (an angle greater than
one right angle) and two acute angles. Similarly, elsewhere, no
a priori rule can be given to determine the classification of
a given subject-matter. It is, however, possible to lay down
one general prmciple. Exhaustive division, not m the sense of
complete enumeration of every possible species but in that of
a division mto classes winch mclude all, is not attainable in the
case of objects so far as they are known only a posteriori. We
can never assure ourselves from mere observation that the list
of species of a given genus is complete. Completeness is
possible only m the case of universals which we can deal with
a priori, where the mind so far sees into the nature of the
universal that it can discern the determinations which it involves.
This may be immediate, as where we divide lines into curved
and straight, or may be reached immediately by a proof or
series of proofs, as where we divide plane triangles into three
species. This is possible in (pure) mathematics. The process
by which the differentiation 1s then carried on is nothing less
than the mathematical demonstration itself and thus dependent
on the particular character of the science. Empirical science
can only ain 1 at this as an ideal and can only classify such
Classification
material as it has got. It must always have before it the
possibility of the discovery of new differentiae and can never
regard its division as exhaustive save in the barren way of
dichotomy.
f r67. We have seen that the word' kind' seems linguistically
more appropriate to those species in a classification which are
true differentiations of a genus. This seems to be the simplest
distinction of kind, as when we say blue and red agree m kind
because they are both colours, whereas heavy, blue, cold, double,
crooked, quick is a group lacking a common basis of classifica•
tion. These adjectives, we should say, differ m kind and our
meaning would seem to be that there is no common element of
which they can be regarded as determinations except the entirely
empty notion of ' being ', which is common to all notions what•
soever. But language often opposes a difference in degree to
a difference in kmd, and here the word kind has not quite the
same signification. In this use universals are said to differ in
degree or quantity when they are determinations of some
common element in respect of the more or less ; whether this
variation is measurable as m geometrical quantity, or whether
it is a mere more or less, not admitting of definite measurement,
as in the intensity of our sensations. A difference m kind or
quality opposed to this does not mean the absence of a common
element but only that the determinations of the common element
are not deterrmnat1ons of degree, that is, m respect of the more
and the less. In this sense red and blue would be said to differ
in kind, because the differentiations of their common element
colour are not in respect of quantity or degree A brighter and
a fainter red on the other hand would usually be said to differ
in degree ~nd not m kmd.
§ 168. In this connexion we meet the paradox that a difference
of degree may sometimes amount lo a difference in kind. The
statement is paradoxical because it seems to identify two sorts
of difference ; yet we observe that the phrase stops short of
absolute identification. For ' is ' we have ' amounts to '. We
shall find in the cases to which this paradox is apphed that it
is not true that as one element varies in degree there comes a
point in the variation at which a difference of kind appears in that
same element. Sometimes two elements are concerned which
~UI Bb
37" STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
are somehow connected with one another and, while one varies
in degree, there is a corresponding series of changes in kind in
the other. The paradox comes from a confusion of the one with
the other. To variations in degree, for instance, in the physical
occasions of our sensations there may correspond differences in
kind in the sensations themselves. Thus, in the theory of colour,
the wave length vanes quantitatively and the corresponding
colour varies m kind. But the variation in degree is confined
to the physical causes and docs not enter into the colour series
at all. What 1s of mterest m such a case is that variations of
degree in a cause may determine not variations in degree but
variations in kind m the effect. Again, 1f the difference in
curvature between a closed and an open curve be considered
a difference in kind, the change m kmd of curvature of the
conic sections as the position of the cuttmg plane varies in degree
of angle, a variation of kind accompanying a variation in degree,
belongs to this head. We have already noticed this case and
the analogous case of the change from a curve of two branches
to a curve with one branch. 1
There is another group of cases where there do not appear to
be two but only one element with changes thus corresponding.
In the case of a sensation of warmth, as the degree of tern·
perature-the physical condition of the feehng-d1minishes, it
may be thought correct to say that the feeling is approaching
the sensation of cold. The feeling diminishes m degree until the
zero point of warmth 1s reached. As the physical conditions
continue their variations in degree, we may gradually begin to
feel cold and the sensation of coolness may increase in degree of
intensity. The truth here seems to be that in the variations
of the sensation of warmth, there is a common element in respect
of which the sensations may be said to differ in degree. But
the series of decreasing sensations of warmth do not pass into
the series of increasing sensations of cold, for these two have
no common element, except sensitiveness to heat and cold.
The diminishing series ends in an absence of the sensation of
warmth, that is there is no sensitive feeling at all, either of
warmth or of cold. Thus the state arrived at is not in an
identical series at all and so is not a sensation which belongs to
l I 164.
Classification 371
and connects both series. When we enter the series of sensations
of cold, we enter a new series and not a continuation of the old
one. This new series consists of variations in degree of a common
element of cold, which is different in kind from the element
common to the first series. These two common elements cannot
be regarded as varieties in degree of one and the same element.
They are species of sensitiveness to heat and cold and differ in
kind, not in degree. The thing left out of account which contri-
butes to a confused view of the question is that the physical con-
ditions on which the continual change of sensation depends have
varied all the time m the degree of one common element while the
two series of sensations were varying in the degree of two suc-
cessive elements. The termination m zero of one series no more
leads to, or begins, a new series of sensations of cold as such than
it leads to, or begins, a series of sensations of pain, hke a smart
or a toothache.
§ I 69. • From an early period in the history of logic distinc•
tions have been made between different sorts of classification.
There has been a tendency to regard some classifications as
truer, or more important, or more natural, than others and to
deem some genera as of lugher rank than others and as more
natural kinds. Thus 111 Aristotle there are genera and species
which seem to have a special cJa1m to be so called. They are
thought of as the truest genera and species and the tendency
seems to find something bke formulation m the phrase 'secondary
essences' as used m the Categories. 1 There hac;, however, always
been great obscurity as to what this higher value or rank con•
sists in. In this spirit a distinction is sometimes made between
a natural and an artificial classification, m the writings of
Linnaeus for instance and in some more modern botanical and
biological authors 2 But we look in vain 111 such writers for any
clear idea of what they mean by a natural as distinguished from
1
Cf. fl 438-50.
1 See Whewell, History of tht Indm:twe Snencts (New Ed 1847), Bk. XVI,
c:hs. 1-5.
[• The author's cnticism here appears somewhat pedantic ; contrast I I So.
The greater naturalness of the later classdicabons, compared with the Llnnaean.
lies in the fact that the latter's arrangement was numerical The lnstory of
systems of botanical class.dication is very clearly set out in Tht Eletnents of
Botany, by Adrien de Jussieu (trans J H Wtlson, 1849), pp. 509-37]
Bb2
372 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
any other classification. It is impossible to construct a clear
idea from what they say and they seem never to realize clearly
what they want. Thus they tend to define the word natural by
itself. Whewell, for example, says that certain classes are natural
in~smuch as the division employed brings together those plants
which are naturally related,1 and Linnaeus' own confusion is
illµstrated in Whewell's History of the Inductive Sciences.•
We may find some help by cons1dermg a botanical system
presented to the world as a natural classification, that of the
two de Jussieus. 8 We see that one of the main characteristics
which determined the classification was the number of coty•
ledons. It 1s a fact that monocotyledonous plants agree with
one another m a vast number of details besides this character
and differ in the same particulars from dicotyledonous plants.
There 1s, however, no apparent connexion between these details
and the character chosen as a d1ffercnba.
§ I 70. This suggests the explanation that the principle which
appears more natural 1s one to the diffcrentiation of which
corresponds the greater number of other elements in the objects
to be classed Behind this 1s the idea of necessary connexion,
however dimly realized. Just as a variety in the general defini-
tion of a come section necessitates every other variety and
difference between the species, so the ideal principle which
modern scientific students are feeling after is that of a universal
which includes the whole nature, not merely a part, of the thing
classified, in the sense that the particular form which the
principle takes in a particular species determines necessarily
every particularity of that species. Clearly the secret and
imperfectly understood reason for prcferrmg one principle to
another in such cases 1s that one prmc1ple-the one which
seems natural-is in this way far more of an index into the
nature of the obJect than the other.
This difficulty which the empirical sciences have in deter•
mining what is a natural classification in a given department
is due to the fact that the advance of knowledge alone can show
that one principle is, at least as far as we have gone, of wider
embrace than another. The investigation being a posmiori
1 Whewell, Hiskw)' of tht Inductive Sciences (New Ed. 1847), XVl. 3, I 2
(vol. iu, p. 313).
1
1b XVI. 4, § S • 1b. XVI. 5, p. 369.
Classification 373
gives us no insight into the necessary connexion between the
variations of the given element by which we are classifying and
the concomitant variations of the other elements. As long as we
have no insight a priori into such connexion we cannot be sure
that the element chosen includes in the above sense the whole
nature of the thing which is to be divided. The ideal can only
be obtained in an a priori science where we can understand the
necessary connexion. In the empmcal sciences the ideal can be
only approximated to and the form of the supposed natural
classification m any such science is lic1.ble to continual modifica·
tion as the science advances
§ I 71. The tendency to look on some sorts of classification as
specially real, by comparison with others which are artificial,
has found expression in Mill's doctrine of recll kinds. There is
a great contrast, Mill thinks, between classifications of things
by such attributes as blue or heavy and those by such universals
as plant or animal. The former he thinks arbitrary or artificial,
the latter he names real kmds and he thmks it would not be
wrong to say that wlule real kmds are <1. d1stinct1on m nature
itself, the other kinds or classes arc made by us for our own
convenience. The d1st111ct1vc characteristic of a real kmd seems
to be that it comprehends an inexhaustible number of attributes,
so that the members of a real kmd agree with one another in
an infinite number of characteristics and differ also m the same
manner from the members of other kmds. The characteristic
of the kmd which is not real is that the attributes 011 which it
depends are easily exhausted. The class of blue things differs
from that of red only m the fimte attribute colour. We have
then to ask, is a mathematical notion hke triangle a real kind
or not? It would seem from the examples that Mill takes that
it ought not to be a real kmd because, although the attributes
of a triangle are inexhaustible, yet they are exhaustible in the
sense that they arc all derivable from a fimtc number of attributes
in the definition of a triangle. Thus infinity of attributes does
not constitute after all the nature of a real kmd, although it 1s
the characteristic Mill most insists on. We must have infinity
of attributes together with the impossib1bty of deriving that
infinity from a finite group of attributes.
Now, in the first place, we naturally ask what evidence an
374 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
empirical philosopher like Mill has of the existence of such kiads.
Observation could never show in regard to any supposed real
kind that its attributes were anything but finite. The reality
of an infinity can be known only a priori. Moreover, how could
we tell that the fact that a certain number of attributes had not
been derived from a given finite group was anything but an im•
perfection m our knowledge, and thus that, even assuming an
infinity of attributes, real kmds would not pass into artificial
kinds 1f we only knew enough ? This brmgs us to a second
difficulty and we ask what reason there 1s for the preference
shown to the real kinds. The infinite attributes of triangle, an
artificial kind, all follow from the fanuliar simple definition.
The real kind, w1th 1ts mfintte attributes, 1s a sort of chaotic
ununified infinity. For our purposes, at all events, the advantage
would seem to be altogether with the non-real kind. And how
does Mill know his real kmds ? He must assume that we assign
individuals to a definite kind on the ground of some attribute
or group of attributes, which is definitely determinable and is
the mark, as logicians term it, of the kind. But this mark is
useless unless its nature necessitates the presumed inexhaustible
number of attributes and, m consequence, that infinity would
be the consequence of this finite mark and the kind would cease
to be real. Mill's idea then seems altogether self-contradictory.
We may perhaps gather what was in his mind from the followmg
extract: 1
'A hundred generations have not exhausted the common pro•
pert1es of animals or of plants, of sulphur or of phosphorus . . .
while if any one were to propose for investigation the common
properties of all things which are of the same colour, the same
shape or the same specific gravity the absurdity would be
palpable.'
It may be replied that geometry undertakes to investigate
the properties of objects that have the same shape, and that in
one sense at least the investigation described as absurd is the
procedure of all those sciences which isolc1.tc certain attributes
of things for the purposes of study. Mill, however, clearly means
something of this sort. It would be absurd to form a class of
objects according to their shape and to propose to inquire into
1 MJJJ, Sysle#t of Loi'& •, I. vii, f 4.
Classification 375
their common properties in general, without any reference to
what depends on the shape, to ask for instance for the chemical
or physical properties of spheres. What however would the
investigator do who examined the common properties of sulphur?
He must classify pieces of sulphur by some common mark and,
by hypothesis, this common mark is not to necessitate the
presence of the other properties of sulphur or sulphur would
cease to be a real kind. He would, therefore, be examining
a class of things to find out common properties m them which
have no connexion with the mark or marks by which he classdies
them. This is the precise mistake which to his mind makes the
absurdity attaching to the non-real types of classdicat1on ;
classifymg things, that 1s, as blue and then askmg for the geo•
metrical properties of blue thmgs. It 1s clear that scientific
investigation is only Justified by the knowledge, or by the
suspicion, that the properties we are mvest1gatmg are necessarily
connected with the properties which serve as the basis of our
classification.
§ 172. We feel, however, that there is a difficulty, though we
cannot admit that Mill has succeeded m discovering its true
character. We may perhaps offer the following as an explana•
tion. In our ordmary experience, ,,hether rightly or not, we
distinguish things and attributes, things as independent realities
and their attributes as partial or dependent rcaht1es. Or the
attribute may be represented as a part of the existence of
a thing or, at least, as not exhausting the nature of the thing.
Corresponding to these we have two kmds 01 universals, for we
must avoid the mistake of supposmg that the attribute is
universal, and the thing itself particular The particular then
which corresponds to one kind of universal is the ind1v1dual
thing. To that corresponds the habit of language m which such
universals, as common terms, have a quasi-noun expression. The
other kind of universal has for its particular what seems only
a part of a complete reality, what is expressed m language by
an attributive term. Here then the universal 1s understood not
to comprise in itself the whole nature of a particular thing.
This is why what Mill calls real kinds seem, as the phrase is,
to go deeper into the nature of a thing, and this is really all that
he tries to express when he speaks of these kinds as in some
37'> STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
way specially real. This again accounts for a certain mystery
in his description of their inexhaustible number of attributes
and of how the attributes cannot be got at through one universal
from which they can be derived. Such universals of individual
things arc of a problematic nature : they contain this infinity
as the thought of a potentiality which may be developed without
limit. They do not m fact expre,s the nature of a thing ; they
are rather the idea that there is a particular thmg and that it
has within it this mfinitely developable nature. But Mill fails
continually through not distmguishmg the universal which is
definite from the problematic umversal which implies that there
is something definite without determining what it may be.
Such umversals, m one way, do not include and, in another, do
include the total nature of such a thmg. They do not include
it, in so far as they do not give a defi.mte universc1.l by differentia•
tlon of which one could arrive at the thmg itself. They do
include it problematically because they are the universals of
particular thmgs conceived as possible deternunations (1£ we
only knew how to conduct the process) of a umfied umversal.
The more artificial character, m Mill's view, of the other classi-
fication simply means that the umversals there arc abstractions
of particular aspects of the thmgs and artificial m the sense
that m Nature they arc not so separable. This view agrees so
far with what seems to have been the Aristotelian tendency.
In the Organon the secondary essences 1 are described as those
which arc the proper genera and species under which the primary
essences 2 arc found These essences then arc •animal' and
'man' on the one side, and Socrates and the md1v1dual animals
on the other. It 1s not to be understood that the Aristotelian
logic arrived at a quite dear idea of what the d1stmcbon meant,
but on the whole the d1stmcl1on really mtcnded seems to have
been between umversals hke ammal, wluch may be truly said
to include the whole thing under them, and universals like
whiteness,• which arc such that the thing is sometimes classed
under them, as when we say Socrates is a white (being), 1 yet
are understood not to include within themselves all that the
thing in its fullness means.
1
a,,.,,pai o6o'la.. • rrp&rra& oiHtla,, • S. ian Ae-S. f'I,
[& The word ' whiteness ' as sub&tdutcd for the neut. adJective AtlNM' whic;h
the a.uthor uaed,]
XVII
DEFINITION
§ 173. DEFINITION seems properly a subject belonging to logic
as a study of thought since it concerns a relation between things
and classes and their constituent elements, considered generally
and without reference to the particular nature of any individual
relation of the kind. In the majority of cases a given attrtbute
is recognized to belong to a subject and yet to express only
a partial determination of that to which 1t belongs. Hence we
are naturally led to ask whether a group of attributes can be
found which embraces the nature of a thing or of a class com•
pletely. To this search corresponds the statement of Aristotle
that definition 1s of essence or being. 1
Again, the attempt to distinguish one thing or kmd froqi
another involves the recognition first of some common element;,
and secondly of something m which the thing or kind differs ·
from other tlungs, somcthmg peculiar to the thing or kind.
Hence arises the question whether there is any attribute or group
of attributes wluch will serve to distinguish a given thing or
kind from certain others. The statement that defimtion is to
be by genus and differentiae 2 is the outcome of this second
question. The two questions correspond to the manner in which
the search for prmc1ples of defimbon developed in practice.
That the second probably attracted more attention at first we
may gather both from the derivation of the word definition,
which in Greek and Latin means fixing of boundaries, 8 and from
the fact that the Anstotehan dictum 4 that defimuon is to be
by genus and di.ffcrent1ae was accepted m the schools and from
them has passed into the traditional logic. The other impulse,
the search for a complete determination, does not so directly
suggest the distinction of genus and diffcrentia, but does in fact
lead to the same inquiry in the end. 6
1 A,u,p~s ,u11 ~ ~ ,.; IN, ""! wt1l11r. An Po. 90b 30.
1 & &f1U1,,J,.le 'fl11ow .au &atf,opG,,,, Top. 103b 15. Meltlj,h. 1024• 26, 1037b ag
,,,__,.., -y4.,.).
' ¥C•• &p,C4dm, definite.
• Nute :z (above). • S257.
378 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
I 174. The object of defimtion is sometimes said to be the
thing or objective reabty itself and sometimes our own concep•
tion, our subjective idea. The very idea of definition in the
second case seems difficult, if not paradoxical. It may seem
that we cannot seek to define our own conceptions because we
must know what they contain before we begm, or else what is
called the definition of a conception 1s either the definition of
a word, and nominal, or only the arrangement of elements,
already given and known, under the heads of genus and ddfer•
entiac. The latter process, at any rate, might seem to be merely
fonnal and of little interest or value. All th1s it may be seen
implies that the idea must be clearly, i.e. exphc1tly, before us.
Again there is a kmd of definition which seems to relate to
the obJect, for appeal is made to instances 10 experience. This,
however, seems to be equally trifhng ; the formation, that is,
of a definition by abstraction of a umversal from particulars.
This case 1s really the same as the one we have just been con•
sidering, because the end which is sought for is really the deter·
mination of a universal as such. This process is formulated by
Aristotle, 1 who represents 1t as starting from a set of similar
individuals and comparing them with a second set, distinct in
species but identical m genus, and so arriving at a genus by
successive ehminat1on of ddferentiae. Such a process seems to
be wholly artificial and to presuppose throughout what it seeks
to attain. In order to abstract magnammity, we must know
that the mdividuals taken arc examples of 1t, and how are we
to know th.1t without already knowing what magnanimity is?
Aristotle himself betrays the difficulty, for he says that, if we
abstract from the members of one species of magnanimous
persons and find a universal and then abstract from another
group of individuals m another species, we must again compare
these and abstract the common clement from them : and, if
there is one element common to all the species, this will be the
common definition, but, if we do not find anything in common,
we shall not end with one genus. 11 This of course implies that
the process may fail, and is an mherent contradiction, but
11713•t cc
XVIII
DENOTATION AND CONNOTATION
§ 181. MoRE than once I have referred to the confusion which,
I hold, besets the subJect of denotation and connotation. The
mischief seems to me to be due to a serious want of clearness
about the nature of meaning, some other results of which are
pointed out in my criticism of the doctrine that the true subject
of every existential judgement is the ultimate reality. In the
following investigation I shall devote myself to a search for
a positive answer to the general problem to which the theory
of denotation and connotation seems to belong This is a positive
supplement to negative crit1c1sm of traditional or current views
advanced by me elsewhere. I shall follow this by another
negative criticism which illustrates the method to be pursued
in examining any discussion of denotation and connotation
which may be found in the ordinary manuals.
In the case of any given writer one has to ask how he defines
these terms, or, failing an explicit definition, what definition he
really presupposes. One has then to inquire whether he is
consistent with the definition, 1f he gives one, and whether he
really employs more than one principle for the distinction he
makes or assumes. If he explains the distinction only by giving
instances of it or by describmg the general cases of its applica•
tion (and this is pretty much what Mill does), we must ask
whether the terms have any meaning except as labels for the
relations indicated If they are vindicated as simply meaning
those relations, we must insist on knowing why these terms
have been chosen as technical terms to designate the relations,
instead of words which have no significance otherwise. Again,
if they are mere labels, we can test their applicability in a given
[• This is redrafted from a manuscnpt note-book of uncertam date. The
chscussion 1s coloured by polemic against Mdl and the o,d,11417 logic. It
represents fairly the VJew which Wilson always maintained in informal
instruction Cf Part II, ch 8]
Denotation and Connotation
case only by substituting for them the account in ordinary
significant speech of the relation of which they are the labels.
The result of this will always, I think, be found disastrous. If,
however, the word denotation is used as m ordinary speech, we
shall find most extraordinary confusion to result. Any attempt
to give a significance to ' connote ' by making it equivalent to
' imply ', as Mill tends vaguely to do, leads also to confusion.
I 182. The distinction between denotation and connotation
has to do with the meaning of words and with the relations
which meaning bears to subjects and attributes, a grammatical
distinction which is presupposed; to put 1t more generally, it
has to do with the relation which a word may have to some
attribute or subject with which it may be concerned. In the
discussion of the distinction a word is sometimes said to be the
name of something, where ' name of ' has a sense which must
be nxed by ordinary usage. Again, words are said to mean or
to signify or to denote something, and here again we have non•
technical expressions, the sense of which is fixed by usage The
words connotation and connote are, however techmcal, employed
in a novel sense. 'They cannot therefore be presumed to be
equivalent to the words implication and imply, which are termc;
of ordinary speech. If they were, they would be superfluous,
there would be no need for them Now we arc entitled to use
technical grammatical expressions, hkc subject and attribute,
because it is precisely word-forms which we are to examine and
word-forms distinguished into nouns wluch are proper names,
nouns called abstract, nouns called concrete- general names, and
adjectives. But our question being what 1t 1s we must at first
use no other technical terms. For, in the first in-;tance, we have
simply to inquire what the linguistic facts arc and how these
word-forms are related as regards meaning to the distinction of
subject and attribute in their actual use We must not assume
and employ the words connote and connotat10n, which are
technical, because that would be to beg the question. The
question is the legitimacy of the distmction conveyed by these
words. as distinguished from denote and denotation, and it is
just because this is not realized that the d1scuss1onc; of the
question (so far as I know them) arc quite futile. The question
generally put as the problem is whether a given kind of word
CC2
388 STATEMENT, THINKING, AND APPREHENSION
has connotation or denotation, or both, and what is the denota·
tion and what the connotation of a given word. This pre•
supposes the legitimacy of the distinction (the very thing which
I call in question) and, if the distinction is in fact false and
illegitimate, attempts to answer such questions must result in
confusion. We might as well ask whether this quill pen can be
mended by kindness ao; well as by reproof, and, if so, by what
sort of kind treatment. Thus, it is usually, perhaps always,
taken for gr.intcd that every noun and adjective must have
either denotation or connotation, if not both It 1s at all events
assumed that every noun has denotation at least, the dispute
turning on whether all, or only some, have connotation. But
supposing it should in fact be true that some words of the above
kind have no denotation, how particularly puzzling and con-
£using must be the mqmry as to what 1s the connotation and
what the denotation of such words I
§ r83 We have therefore to inquire first mto the lmguistic
facts mvolved rn the problem before us and to abjure any new
technical \\ord until the facts compel its use, that is, until wc
come acroo;s some new relation for which ordinary speech has
no accepted word Moreover, wc must first consider words as
they actually are used and not in abstraction from the use made
of them in a particular sentence ; \!\'hen we do consider them
in the latter and abstract way we must expressly say so or
confusion will certainly arise. Indeed the confusion m the
doctrine of denotation and connotation is caused partly by
failure to remember this distinction. Now the relation of a word
or grammatical form to any subject or attribute with which it
is concerned is a matter of usage. It is not fixed by the gram•
marian or the logician, it depends on no logical or grammatical
theory. We ought then to be able to ascertain definitely the
relation as a mere fact of linguistic usage.
§ 184. Let us therefore first consider the use of ' name'. Mill
treats all nouns and adjectives as the names of something.
Consider then such nouns as John, man, stone; such adjectives
as virtuous, human, heavy ; and such nouns as humanity, virtw,
heaviness, weight. We will first ask whether these nouns and
adjectives are the ' names of ' subjects or attributes, according
to the normal meaning of ' name of ' in language. John as
Denotation and Connotation
used ordinarily in any given statement is the name of .a. parti•
cular individual,1 and we should say that this word John also
means the given individual whose name is John. It is the name
of an individual subject and not the name of any attribute of
his, as (for instance) his height, his weight, or his virtue. Singular
proper names then are in usage always the name of one person
and mean only one person.
§ 185. Consider now 'concrete general names' hke man. If
we suppose that a word has always, hke a proper name, to mean
that of which 1t 1s the name, of what 1s man the name, and of
what is stone the name ? Tree m a given sentence may refer
to a particular tree, but it does not follow that it 1s the name
of that tree. In ' this tree is hollow ', 1t 1s only the combination
'this tree' which means a particular tree. In this sentence then,
if anything could be the name of the tree meant, 1t would be
this tree. Yet 1t would be contrary to linguistic usage to call
such a combmatlon a name of the thmg meant, to say that ' this
tree' 1s the name of the obJect pomted at. The same holds of
the tree. If again we abs.tract stone and tree from their use m
given sentences, we cannot say that they are the names of
a given stone or tree, for they \\ould by hypothesis have then
to mean that stone or this tree and no other, and this they
certainly do not. Tree then 1s not the name of any particular
tree. Neither however is 1l the name of the umversal of tree,
for 1f that has any name it would be such a "ord as ' lree-ness '.
Neither therefore m use nor m abstraction could \\e say that
such common nouns or general names a& tree arc the names of
either subjects or attributes, 1£ a name has to mean that of
which Jt JS the name, nor the names of the umversals of subJects
or attributes. We may, however, note 1n passing c1.n ordinary
usage by which general names arc called names of somethmg ;
as, for example, when we say ' Gill JS the name of a certain
measure ', ' Ibis is the name of a certain kmd of bird '. This
has interesting 1mphcations which need not detain us now.
§ 186, We will next consider abstract nouns bke u1eight, heavi-
ness, virtue. Heaviness is naturally and rightly said to be the
name of the universal, and 1t means that of which 1t is the name
1 The pnmary appbcat1on, m the development of language, of the 'W01'd
u
I
THE GENERAL NATURE OF INFERENCE
§ 208 THE main ob1ect of the part of logic which precedes
Inference 1s to study the forms and characteristics of propos1•
t1onc; and terms (or, as i5 sometnnes said, of Judgements and
ronct>phonc;) \\hen they have been arrived at, rather than the
manner 111 which they arc attained, though the latter may
require some consideration as sub•nd1ary to the main mqmry.
Wl• have given rcasonc, for prcfcrrmg to speak of Judgement,
op1111on, and apprd1en!,10n in this connexion, and have main•
tamed that the d1~trnct1on between 3udgmg and mferring is false
alld, if assumed without srrutiny, lea<ls to difficulties 1 Logic
is, however, also roncernc<l with the way m "luch we arrive
at Judgements 2 ,111d op1mons, not w11h every way-not, for
instance, ,oth the processes of perception-but with that which
1s c-allcd mfcrrmg
Before we begin the ia1tudy of logic we arc familiar with the
idea of mfercnrc It 1s an operation we conduct in everyday
life and m the !>Ciencec; \Ve do not learn 1t from logic nor did
1 Sec the critic1~m of this doctrine 111 Part II, l-h r, §§ 39-41
• On the use and abuse of the word Judgement see Part II, ch 2
Chapters 1-4 were part of the Logic Lecture~. though from time to time
given a& a ~eparate conr~e \\1th the chapters on Induction This accounts
for some confusion m the opening which was never properly reconSidered
The chapters were continually revised 1n manuscnpt note-books of pupil~.
and new &ect1ons added The &tructure goes back, however, to an early
period and retain& marks of what may be called the Kantian penod of Wilson's
thought The cntic,~m of the syllog1sm and of modem mathemaneal theories
(Chapter 7) 1s, however, as Wilson would llave left 1t m pnnc1ple Chapters
s-7 are from a separ<Lte cour~e on Hypothetical Reasoning Substantial
,tdd1tions and mod1hcations were made m 1906, I have supplemented them
from the or1g111a.l manuscnpt
Wilson nearly always put the minor premiss of a syllogism before the
maJor I have altered 1t throughout as he nowhere Justifies the breach of
con,ention, and it 1s very confusmg where, as in tlus part, the argument 11
largely formal
The General Nature of Inference 4I3
logicians invent it, though they have often affected to teach it.
Words like conclude and conclusion, proof and prov~, are not
part of a technical vocabulary invented by philosophers ; they
belong to the inferences of ordinary life Although, then, some
of the technicalities of the schools do make their way into the
language of ordinary men, most of these terms are the familiar
product of a certain natural logic and come simply from the
fact that men have gradually been led to reflect upon the opera-
tions of their own thinkmg.
§ 209 If we consider imtanccs in which we should naturally
c;;peak of concludmg or mfcrrmg, we shall find that they are
not instances of expericncmg Our attitude in experience seemc;
to us to be mamly receptive, but in inference we appear to
exercise an originative activity either m the discovery of truth
or in probable conJecture It 1s tlus origmativc activity of ours,
as opposed to experience, which 1s one of the main charac-
teristics of inference
But we do not suppoc;e ourselves entirely originative. In the
first place, we do not tlunk that we originate truth but that we
discover 1L Secondly, we do not thmk that our method of
discovery, 111 the process of mferrmg, 1s entirely independent
and unassisted from without ; we thmk rat her that our activity
consistc; in denvmg the truth discovered from something already
known and ultunately from experience This brmgs us to
another main characteristic of mferring ; the knowledge it gets
1s derived from other knowledge. Jlence we again have the
idea that this kmd of kno\\ ledge ir;; m some way dependent.
Thus, from the c;ubjective c;;1de, inferred knowledge comes to be
looked upon as indirect, as not immediate knowledge but
mediated, while on the obJecttve side the inferred facts are
sometimes looked upon as dependent for their existence on those
from ,vh1ch they arc inferred We somet11ncs even tend to put
inferred knowledge on a lo" er level, somehow, than that from
wluch it 1s derived. Thrs 1s a natural outcome of the idea of
dependence. It happens that an inferred opmion may be called
a mere inference , and, with an imphcahon of defectiveness, we
may say of some kind of knowledge or opinion that it is only
inferential, implymg a want of something we think better and
should probably call direct apprehension of the subJect-matter.
B2
INFERENCE
Thus, it 1s often c;airl, whether rightly or not, that we can only
infer the existence of other people and do not directly apprehend
their being. And here 1t must be pointed out that the deprecia-
tion of an inference as a mere inference seems to be confined
to cases where the inference 1s not a certain one but a probabihty
because of the uncertainty of the matter, so that the defect is
not here caused solely by the injerential character of the process.
It is otherwise m cases like our belief m the existence of other
people, for there we do not doubt the truth which we say we
arrive at only by inference, and yet we do feel a "anl of direct
apprehrns1on.
§ 210. Now this Ycry dir,sati:.fact1on may so react upon us
when '\\e reflect upon 1t that we may rnchnc to thmk that the
inference m such a case 1!! after all not really certain. We may
reflect that it is somehow not hkc mathematical demonstration
and suppose that therefore 11 1s not certam. Yet, to take an
everyday dlustrat10n, we should under ordinary circumstances
be sure from the exprcsc;1on of a man's face that he was angry
and show thl' firmness of our conv1ct1on Ly actmg upon it,
lOmm1tting ourselves perhaps m consl•qucnce to some serious
line of conduct. Herc we should naturally call our thmkmg an
inference. We inforred his state of mmd, where \J,e could not
have the direct knowkdge "h1ch he himself has of his o" n
emot1oni.
On the other hand, we fincl no such deprcciat1011 as this in
the <;c1cnces There t lw h1ghl•c;t Yaluc 1s given to what claims
to be proof, that 1s, to "hat 1s rightly inferred. Nevertheless,
m reficct1on upon the method of !ic1cnce, though the inferred
knowledge 1s not depreciated as bcmg mkrred, the 1dea, never-
theless, of a dependent character m ,,hat 1s inferred often
persists, a<; wl.'11 as the 1dl.'a of a ccrtam 111d1rectness and want
of immediate apprd1ens1011 1
Whether all these 1deas and tendencies are Justified or not
we !!hall be better able to judgl' when we have advanced further
m our study of the subJcct. We must at the threshold be
prepared for the poss1bihty that the problems we have indicated
may involve different ktnds of inference, and that the answers
to them may therefore be divergent. It might be a question,
' This sub1ect 1s resumed m ch 4, infra
The General Nature of Inference 415
for example, whether there is the same directness, or even the
same sense of the word, in a probable inference about an object
of experience (say the inference that the pea 1s under the
thimble) as m certain geometrical proofs. The inference about
the pea and the thimble seems to point lo a real difference in
kmd between inferential opinion or Judgement and another
method of frammg a conclusion on the same subject-matter.
§ 2 I I. The most general account, then, of the problem of logic
111 Inference is perhaps this : to study the forms and the nature
of that act1v1ty of the nund by wluch we advance from given
Judgements or op1mons to new Judgements or opm1ons neces-
~1tated or made probable by the former, not by experience but
by some other operation of the mmd. Yet here also there are
d1fficult1cs Tlus operation "ould usually, perhaps always, be
c..illed tlunking as opposed to cxpencncmg ; yet there is often
co11s1dcral>lc vagueness ar, to what ' thought ' should precisely
mean, 1 and d1fficull1c-, .mc,c 1£ 1t 1s realized that percept1011 1s
somehow mt1matcly connected w1th what would 11c1.turally be
called thought, though the nature of that conncx10n has not yet
been cleared up or mvest1gated This at all events is true, thc1.t
the advance 111 knowledge wluch 1s meant 1s, as we saw, not
one made by getting some new perception to add to the given
statements from which in some sense the advance 1s made. For
when mfercncc 1s supposed to be clue lo the operation of thinking
\\<e find a tendency sharply to d1stmgmsh this thmkmg as pure
thought from both experience and 1magmation. Tlus is un·
doubtedly the c,isc \\-1th the formal log1crn.ns, who suppose that
formal rear.omng, which really means rcc1sonmg from the mere
forms of statement without any matter, proceeds entirely by
pure thmkmg.
Y ct imagination 1s ab~olutely necessary to the processes of
those sciences which seem to be the most perfect type of what
can be produced 111 the way of new and ccrtam Judgements by
inference. Geometrical thmkmg, ancl indeed all mathematical
inference, is impossible without 1magmation, and 1t is even true
that the abstract reasoning treated of in formal logic (which
consists of syllogisms m which the premisses r.eem to be mere
forms of statement and can therefore be expressedsymbohcally),
1 Pc1rt I, ch .l
416 INFERENCE
reasoning which is often taken as the type of pure thinking, is
quite impossible without the use of imagination. Again, imagina•
tion depends upon experience, and thus inference stands in
essential relation to cxpcnencc. But notwithstanding this con•
nexion with expcrwru e and imagmat1on, it still remains true
that what 1s really meant by inference 1s that the new knowledge
we reach '"c do not rcad1 simply by getting fresh experience.1
In view of these very real d1ffieult1es the best way to form
a corrcc.-t 1dt•,i of mfcrencc appears to be to study first those
inferences "luch arc certain and "hich constitute knowledge,
or wlm h at lea.st we suppose to be ccrtam, for it seems obvious
that "e can, in a given subject, only understand the imperfect
type from a cons1derat10n of the perfect We shall accordingly
bcg111 v. 1th a consideration of this kmd of mference
§ 212. It will be observed that the above general account, m
common with the m,ual defn11t10ns of mfercnce, has an important
presuppos1t1011 which 1s not alv. aye;, 5uffic1cntly reflected upon
Thought 111 I lus mfomng process 1s spoken of not as .,bsolutely
ongin,it111g truth,• but .1s !>tartmg from some truth, whether
that Is given m experience or not. I11 the tccluucal language
of logic the Judgements or optn10ns from ,, luch the thmkmg
process thus starts arc ralled premisses The Judgement or
op11110n to wluch thought advances by 1ts own operation is
called the co11clus1011 Now It 1s obvious that the concluston
must be different from the prcm1ssec; ctnd 111 some sense really
new Thr propo<;1tion" ' .111 A ts B ' and ' some A 1s B' arc
d1tforcnt, but the latter 1s not new 1£ \\e have the former. That
this should be so t'> self-ev1dcnt, but that it ts ctlso recognized
explic1tly m log1cal tre..1.t1scs 1~ shown, for mstancc, 111 the obJeC·
tton to the syllogism that 1t 1s a petitio prmcipii. For the
mcanmg of th.it t'> that the conclus10n docs not seem to be new
.is compared with tJ1c ma1or premiss. It should be observed
that tlus demand is made even in an empirical logic hkc that
of Md! b He will not allow an argument to be a true inductive
1
E, 1de11cc of the reallr distinct character of inference as a form of appre-
henb1on may be drawn from the hypothetical statement Tht-re we have at
an} rate knowledge or op1mo11 e"pressed which can be got only by mfcrence.
Cf, §§ 102 and 298
(& Cf Ill) note t~ § 39
b ' Coll>e:. of inference 111 the proper .i.cceptatiou of ihe term, ihoi.e m wh1U1
~ The General Nature of Inference 417
inference unless it contains more than is contained m any single
premiss. Now this involves a presupposition which he has not
reflected upon • it implies that the new knowledge is not the
result of experience and must therefore be due to the inferring
process itself. Thus, the conclusion is unavoidable that in some
important sense a mental process which ls not experience can
originate knowledge It is futile to object that the mmd merely
works on the material wluch 1s given m experience, for this
unphes that we are able m the process to get on to new know·
ledge not 111 the material. This then must be due to the mental
process which brmgs the new result. Such or1gi11at1on con·
trad1cts the very foundation of an empmcal philosophy hkc
that of Locke and 1\1111
Here we arc not so much concerned with this criticism as with
the hght "Inch 1l throws on the important principle presupposed
111 the ordmary idea of 111ference, m so far as we find that 1t
forces 1t5clf even upon those philosophers whose doctrines make
1t, one would have thought, 1mpos'l1blc to admit 1t.
§ 213 Inference 1s usually di\ 1ded mto mediate and unme•
<l1c1.te. To Judge from the mstancec; by which the d1stmct1on 1s
illustrated, the idea at bottom of 1t r,;ecms to be that in immediate
inference "e pa,;s directly from one prcmi~s, 1 e. from one given
judgement or op1mon, to the conclusion by a mere reflection on
the given premiss. In med1c1.te inference something comes
between a g1Yen prmuss ancl the conclus1on, that something
being another judgement or prenuss Thus, 1mmed1c1.le mfcrencc
has only one premiss, mediate has at least two We may
represent this mediation m another way. In a given premiss
1t would be said ordinarily that we have two concepltons in
a certain relation To be more accurate, the premiss states a
relation bet\\cen t,"o obJccts of apprchem,1011 1 The inference
is 1mmed1c1.tc 1f "e arnvc at some other rdation merely by
cous1dermg the given c.oncepbons themselves, by considering,
that is, what we apprehend in thc'>e two obJccts m the act of
apprehension rl!prescnted by the given premic;s. It 1s mediate
1£ we get a new relation by the help or mediat1011 of some new
' See Part II, ch. 14, on the use of the term conception
we set out from known truth, to arrive .i.l other~ really d1&tinct from them,
SJ,stem of Logic, II. 1, § J ]
INFERENCE
conception not contained in the premiss ; by the help, rather,
of the apprehension of something else not contained in our
previous apprehension.
Now clearly this latter can only be done by relating the given
conception (so called) to this other conception, and such acts
of relation are Judgcmenb or opmions, and hence we get more
than one prenus'>. We get exactly two 1£ we represent the
proce:,s as follows we find ourselves unable in a matter of two
concepl1ons, on the strength of the knowledge wluch makes
them what they arc for us c1.t the moment, to relate them m
some particular way. Thus (we should say), we cannot connect
them directly. We then mediate their connexion by a new
concepl1011 to which each 1s related . each relation 1s the matter
of a Judgement or op1mon, and thus we get l\'-O premisses.
§ 214 The above .H·counl of mediate and 11nmcd1atc 111fcrencc
1s not offered .t'> c1. <,at1:,factory definition of what such terms
ought lo mc..1.n, or even as 1mply1ng that mfcrcncc l'> properly
:.o di\ Hled It is mtcndcd rat her ,1,; ,111 e~planat1on of what the
lrad1l1011al d1stmet1011 amountl> lo Thub, if ,, c find 1t stated
t'iat an 11nmed1c1I c mfcrenec 1.., one m wluch a Judgement follo,,s
1mmedi,ttcly from another Judgement, 1t might well seem a more
natural construction to put upon the cbstmctlon of mediate and
1mmed1ate inference to say that 1£ a Judgement A necessitates
another judgement B directly, that 1s 1mmcd1ate mference , and
1f that Judgement B 10 turn neceso;1tatcs another Judgement C
directly, the mforence from A to C t!'> mediate, because the
connexion of A and C 1s only acquired through B. But that
1s nol the tra1ht1on,,l ..,em,1• of mctl1,Ltc mfcrenee, for, m the
ordinary deduct1,e logic, the '>yllog1sm 11, the m,L111 type of
mediate mfcrcncc, and such a. defu11t10n doer,, not sutl the r,,yl-
log1sm bcc,tusc m the i;,yllog1s111 the hrst prcnuss 1r,, not !'>upposed
to necessitate the second. In the end we shall depart so much
from trad1t1on as to show reason for calhng all mfercnce in an
important sense 1111med1ate. No doubt such a view seems at
first sight paradoxical, 1f we arc under the 1mprcss1on which the
account of 11nmcd1ate mference 111 formal logic naturally makes
upon us , for we !ihould not expect that such so-called mferencc
1s real mfcrencc <1.t all, but that immediate inference only gets
its 11.i.mc by c1. kmd of J.nalogy.
The General Nature of Inference 419
§ 215. The syllogistic logic in treating of inference has only
before 1t the general form S 1s P or S is not P, with the quanti•
tat1ve distinctions all S, no S, some S, and this S. What it does
m effect in the case of 1mmed1ate inference 1s to ask, given
a certain judgement or proposition tn one of these merely general
forms, what relation can be inferred between the subject and
predicate conceptions (more accurately, between what corrc·
sponds to them m rcahty) or their negations, & besides those
stated m the given proposition ? Further, 1t is an element in
the problem as usually conceived that the conclusion of the
inference should be restricted to the form tn which the so-called
ongmal subJect and predicate conccpt1011s and their negatives
,ire to make up the subJect and predicate conceptions m the
conclusion For example, from all A is B, we may tnfer some
B 1s A, or no A ts not·B, but not, for 1m,tance, that A and B
are compatible; for the predicate ' compatible' does not occur lll
the premisses. Agam, the mfcrencc from all A 1s B to some
B is all A is not recognized as an 1mmed1atc mforence, because
.t rcstnctlou 1s made that the so-called predicate 1s to have the
ongtnal adJectlval form, or at all events 1s not to be preceded
by a quantitative word like all, or some
Such restrictions .1re clearly artificial, but so, too, 1s the whole
.1ccount of 1mmed1.i,te mfcrcnce. It ,., not meant that these
restrictions arc formulated and consuously made , they arc at
first simply the result of .i.n uncritical tr,1d1tion '1 be mfcrence
B ts les,; than A from A 1!. greater th.an B conforms mdeed
entirely to what 1c; essential m the dcfimt1on of immediate
mferencc a!. 1t ~eems to be understood III syllogistic logic, and
we note al">o that 1t 1s this kmd of unmedutc mfcrcnce \\luch
1s most frequent ,ind unport,rnt m ordmary ltfc, and m the pro•
ccdure of the science<; Accordmg to the dot tnne of the syllo•
g1stic logic, 1t would be said that m such tcl.'~es thr 1mmcd1ate
mference 1s from the matter of the propos1t10n, not from the
form, whereas m the 1mmed1ate inferences treated of the mfer•
ence is from the form and not from the matter.
Now even if this were true, as 1t 1s not, 1t would not be any
reason for neglecting the ' material ' 1mmcd1ate mferenccs, unless
it could be shown that they are comprised under various ktnds
l" vu, what Ioimal lugn, name& their wnlraditlory term& J
420 INFERENCE
of immediate inference from the form merely. Now clearly they
are not so comprised; the relation of A to B in the proposition
all A is B is neither the same as A is greater than B nor does
it include this relation, for m 'A is greater than B ', A and B
cannot be represented as subJect and predicate respectively, nor
as subject and attribute, nor could the given inference from
A 1i; greater than B be derived from rt by any rule of immediate
mforencc given m the syllog1st1c logic
Nor, agam, can these material mferences be represented as
syllog1st1c ; the attempt to represent them as such would result
f,Olely m i,,t.1tmg as a premiss of the given inference that 1f A is
greater than B, then B 1s less than A, and next m subsuming
under rt a particular A and a particular B; \\hercas of course
tt 1s not the propos1llon that tlus B 1s less than this A which
we are concerned with. The mference rs the alleged premiss itself
The fallacy of such verbal reductions to the syllog1stic form
will become more apparent "hen we criticize the traditional
reduction of ..i.11 demon-.trat 1vc rc,i-.0111ng to the syllogistic form.
There 1t will be shown that tlw; torm 1s but one among many
of a cerlam class and thcJ.t the other members of the class cannot
be reduced to 1t
\Ve can now sec what the general notion 1s '"luch ts common
lo both of these kmds of 1mmed1ate mference, and we can see
that the type of 1mmed1c1.te mfcrence studied m formal logic is
but one among many. The general type 1s, that from some
given relation bet" ccn two dement!> X and Y \\ c mfer directly,
,ind without the adrht10n of .my other statement about them,
some other n•l,tt10n behH!en X .111d Y. Kow the :.yllog1st1c logic
wnfine-. 1tsrlf to one only out of 111.tny possible rcl,itiou!>, that
wluch l'i u:,ually expressed by the term pred1cJ.t1011 The term,
howc, er, 1s u.,cd uncnt1cally, for subJect and predicate do not
here mc,m log1ral '>UhJcct .111d logical pn·d1catc proper. In this
refereme, the propos1t1011 I!> &upposed to have the form S 1s P,
or Sis not P, J.nd 1t 1s meant that in this form P 1s the predicate.
Now the true relation of S and P (the rel<1.t1on which the syllo•
gisttc logic has here m view) 1s tlus: P-ness 1s a kmd of being
which S, the !>O·callcd subject, 1s stated to have or not to ha_ye.
The relation therefore 1s an obJcct1ve one. 1 But any other
1 P.Lrt 11, § 68.
The General Nat1,re of lnferc1tcc 4u
relation between two such obJects upon which an immediate
inference can be grounded 1s equally entitled to a place in any
theory of immediate inference.
To return now to a previous pomt, it might be said that our
ability to mfcr 11nmed1ately from the statement A is greater
than B that B is less than A depends, as it really docs, upon
our knowledge of the mailer of the relation, in other words, on
our knowledge of the special character of the relation greater
and less, whereas the other kind of inference depends upon the
general form of the Judgement or statement without any matter.
Now tlus would be a false d1stmctlon. The one kmd of inference is
as material as the other Just as from the statement A 1s greater
than B, our inference that B ts less than A depends upon our
knowledge of the relation of magnitude, so also our inference
&ome B 1s A from ' all A is B ' depends upon our knowledge of
the nature of the spccul obJcct1ve relation which has here,
through a confus1on, got the name of prcd1catlon (which pro•
perly drs1g11ate, ,t merely subJcct1vc rclal10n). Moreover,
.,., w<- shall sec hereafter, the rules of the ,yllog1stic logic
<lepend upon Lile special nature of till', rel,1t1011, and, m tlus
sense, arc as much material mfcrcucc as .i.ny other. The
'!UbJecl of 1mmcd1ale mfcrcncc 1c; treated m the ordmary
logic mo:1.nuals under such heads as conversion and opposition.
We ,trc not, ho\\ ever, here concerned to follow this in detail,
but only to consider 111 general the relation of the conclusion
to the prenusc; m ~urh 1mmed1atc mfercnccs, to ask how far
they constitute ..i real f>tcp m tlunkmg .i.nd what claims they
kL, c lo be c<illed mfcrcncc at all \Ve sllclll also have to
spl·.a.k of other kmtls of immediate mfcrence besides these so•
called ' formal ' ones
§ 216 The statement f>omc A,., B might be called an immediate
111fcrcnre from .i.11 A 1s B, but 1t doe'! not satisfy an essential
d1aracter1st1c of mfcrence 1t 1s lc'!s than \\-e knew m the
premiss. Consider, however, the relation of some B is A to all
A is B (the only form of immediate mference by conversion
from all A is B allowed 10 formal logic). The inference in the
form some B 1s A appears no longer to be, hke some A is B,
a mere part of what we knew before, in the sense of being less
than what we knew before, for the true full mfcrencc is some
INFERENCE
B is all A.• W c ask, then, the verbal form being different, is
there a difference of meaning such as we require for inference ?
In the facts exprec;sed by statements such as all A is B, or A is
equal to B, or A is a friend of B, the realities to which A and
B refer stand m a reciprocal relation to one another, and the
nature of each 1s affected by its relation to the other in the
obvious sense that the hemg of each mcludes the relation. But
the relations mcluded m the complex fact of the reciprocal
relation of A and B arc various. Sometimes they arc different
m species, and then the difference 1s seen at once, as in A 1s
the father of B and so B is the son of A. But the same is true
even when the relations arc the same m species ; if A and B
arc friends, A's fr1endsl11p for B is different from B's friendship
for A. Even U1 such an instance as A 1s equal to B the same
holds. Each of these d1ff erent relations 1s expressed by a separate
verbal form of statement, e. g by all A 1s B and some B con·
st1tutes all A. Even if we confine ourselves to the traditional
form some B is A, that expresses a reld.bon of J3 to A different
from the relation of A to B Such difference of relation we may
illustrate more concretely, thus: A 1s half B; in that way A 1s
related to B; an 1mmed1ate inference is that B 1s twice A,
representing the relation of B to A. These two relations arc
obviously different, the half and the double. But now the rela-
tion of A to B and the relation of B to A being d1fferent, they
nevertheless necessitate one another and the act of judgement
or opm1on involves m either cai.e, for the person forming it, the
other relation, though he docs not express 1t verbally. The
objective fact, indeed, to wluch the first statement relates is
d. unity, havmg two sides represented fully by two statements ;
the two sides arc not merely parts of an aggregate, but are
inseparable ; the complete fact to which the statements refer
being their umty. The expression, however, in either of the two
statements is as expression one-sided ; h which side 1t will happen
to take depends on what we have taken as our starting con•
ception or logical subJect.
We sec, then, that the so-called inference 1s in a sense not
[• Tiu11 1s to adopt the extreme view of one school of formal logiC111D11,
But then, in Wilson's sense, there 1s no inference smcc all A 1s some B and
some B 1s all A arc statements of 1dent1ty
b • Conwder the 1mpl&cauonb.' MS nole.]
The Gene,a/, Natu,e of Infwuice .f.23
new ; and this is what causes us our difficulty and makes us
doubt whether the inference should be called inference at all.
It is not uew ; the conclusion is involved in the act of thought
which makes the premiss ; the truth being that the premiss
brings out one side of the act of thinking, while the conclusion
brings out the other side. Yet we cannot call one of these
statements identical with the other, nor is one a part of the
other: each of them involves the whole, which gets its expression
verbally in both together. Now 1t 1s because of their difference,
which, as we have seen, is not that one 1s merely part of the
other but that they express two different relations, that such
inferences are entitled after all to the name of inference. They
satisfy this definition, that the one is different from the other
and necessitates the other. The process from the one to the
other is not on that account the less inferential that it is so
simple, and it wdl actually turn out in the end that this imme•
diate necessitation by one element, or complex of elements, in
a whole, of another element, or complex, in the same whole is
what always constitutes mferencc.
Inasmuch, however, as the simplicity of the process tends to
mislead us and to make us think that in the immediate inference
there is merely a repetition and at most only a change in the
verbal expression, 1t is useful to observe certain examples. Con•
sider the immediate inference a from all A is B to no A is not-B.
Suppose we start from all A is B : that necessitates no A is
not•B, and the latter states exphcitly an element in the whole
thought to which the first statement, as a partial statement,
corresponds. For we ask first whether A can, or cannot, be B,
and have before us the possibility both of all A is B and of some
A ts not-B. In deciding for the first we exclude the second.
The two, then, are inseparable aspects of the same truth, but
the difference between them appears at once when we consider
how each can be got. Though each ts necessary to the other,
they are not in our thinking co•ordmate, for we find we can
only possess the universal negative in the form of an immediate
inference from the affirmative. We might think at first that
we could get each independently ; that, while we get all A is
B by finding that the nature of A necessitates B, in getting the
[• • Rewrite this more clearly' MS. note. See Part II, ch. 12 ]
INFERENCE
negative we might, though ignorant of the reason why all A is
B., have arrived at no A is not-B simply by finding that there
wu no A outside B. But, as we have already seen, in many
instances (and indeed in every instance of a scientific universal),
this last process cannot be performed independently, because
the area of not-B is infinite, and hence we can only tell what
is in this sphere or not by considering positively the nature of
A and the nature of B. Jn the cases where we seem to form
no A is nol-B without the affirmative all A is B, we reany
depend entirely upon affirmations, which divide up exhaustively
the indefinite sphere of not-B. Thus, the exclusion of A from
not•B rould not be an mdependent act 111volving mere negation;
there 1s no ,vay of arriving al no A 1s not-B except by estab·
hshmg all A 1s B. Hence, we cannot arrive at the negative
statement m question at all except as an immediate inference
from all A is B. All A 1s B may be immediate m the sense
that I see immediately that A necessitates B, no A is not-B
cannot be itself an immediate apprehension, but can only be
acquired as an immediate inference
§ 217 a It is sometimes said that the inconceivability of the
contradictory of a statement 1s the test of its truth, and specially
that 1t 1s the test from which we really derive the certainty of
axiomatic truth Now the preceding discussion of the relation
of no A is not-B to all A 1s B gives us one criticism of this
theory. The theory at bottom a'lsumes that we can start with
the negative A cannot be not-B, and upon that are able to
ground the statement that A must be B ; for the assertion that
we cannot conceive the contradictory of A must be B really
means that we affirm that A cannot be not·B and that we
apprehend that directly, together with the implication that this
judgement is acquired 1mmed1ately. That is what is meant by
calling it the 11.lt1mate test. But, as we have seen, we can only
pronounce this negative Judgement because we have already
seen that A must be B. That is to say, this inconceivability
of the contradictory supposed to be a test of the axiom is only
the consequence of our already having apprehended the truth
of the axiom. All that is true in the doctrine is this : that, if
[• Referring to Mill's controversy with H Spencer SJ•stem of Logic, ii,
ch. ; ; cf. infra, I§ 355 seq]
The Gene,al NalUrt of I nje,ence 41S
we really see the necessity of a thing, we cannot conceive it
otherwise,
I 2 I 8. We may now give another kind of example of the
reality of the step made in immediate inference, In what is
called pure formal reasoning-the simplest of all-we sometimes
find it either necessary or convenient to draw an immediate
inference from one or more of the premisses in order to get our
conclusion. Now this shows the reality of the process that we
go through ; that 1t must be something more than a merely
verbal change. It will indeed sometimes be found that a com•
plex of formal premisses, though obviously dealing with the
simplest relations possible, causes us considerable difficulty, and
we see our way through a complicated system of premisses by
help of a number of mere immediate inferences. Indeed such
difficulty is sometimes found with quite a few premisses. For
instance, given that no AC is B, and no D which is not-B is A.
The solution becomes quite easy if we first transform by imme•
di ate inference the second premiss, and put it in the form
All A which is not-B is not-D ( = No A·not-B is D).
The original first premiss, then, being transformed into all AC
is A-not-B, we have a simple syllogism in Celarent with A-not-B
as the middle term, and the conclusion is that no AC is D.
Or, again, given that all AB is C, and all A-not-B is D. This
is solved simply by immediate inference from the first premiss
to all A-not-C 1s not-B, that 1s, all A-not-C 1s A-not-B. This
gives us with the second premiss as major a syllogism m Barbara
of which A•not-B 1s the middle term, and the conclusion is see'
to be that all A-not-C 1i,, D.
§ 219. There are certain processes which we ~hould on reflec- ·
bon not be inclined to call inference (nor are they usually
recognized as such m logic) which yet have the verbal form of
an inference and, if judged by the test which we have just
applied to immediate inference, appear entitled to be .,called
inferences because the argument seems to require the first st\
which· is preceded by the word ' therefore '. Moreover, they
seem sometimes to exhibit in the conclusion a real difference
from the sum of the premisses. For instance, if we know that
a.fl is C and find first that A 1s a. and then that A is /J, it follows
that A is C. This would usually and naturally be expressed as
INFERENCE
follows : A i'i II and A is /J, therefore A is 11/J. But o.fJ is C and
therefore A is C. Here, while the step A is o.fJ appears necessary,
it yet seems to be only the two premisses together. Again,
suppose AB exists, and we have A is II and B is P, therefor,
AB is o./J ; but we know 11/J is C, therefore AB is C. The step
AB is 11/J seems necessary. Further, it seems this time to differ
from the premisses, because from 1t given alone we could not
get the premisses. It 1s compatible, for mstance, with A is fJ
and B is a Euclid m the first proposition of his first book uses
an argument of the form A = B, and C = B : therefore A and
C = the same thmg B ; but things equal to the same thmg =
one another : therefore A -= C.
Herc the first inference seems a mere restatement of the
premisses, yet the step is in fact made and also seems necessary
to the complete argument.
Agam, 1t differs from the premisses either singly or together
because the term ' the same thing ' occurs in neither, and this
seems got by a comparison of the premisses. This again seems
a new act and not a mere restatement.
§ 220 To solve such d1fficult1es certain distinctions have to
be made which ought to be preliminary to any theory of
inference, and are yet commonly, perhaps always, neglected, to
the con!usion of certam parts of the subject.
We must distinguish first between the thought which the
verbal form given to a Judgement expresses and the whole
thought wluch produced the expression, for the former may not
be the whole of the latter As the Judgement really 1s the whole
thought which produces the imperfect expression, 1£ the latter
is taken as the true <"xpre,;sion of the Judgement, there arises
the fallacy, common m logic, of distmguishing the Judgement
as a result from the thought said to produce 1t ; an impossible
abstraction, for this thought is the full Judgement. What 1s
called the process of arriving at the Judgement 1s really the act
of judgmg. Thus, m B is C, A 1s B . therefore A is C, A is C 1s
represented as a Judgement resultmg by inference from the other
two. But tlus mference is exactly the Judging that A is C, and
thus A is C expresses only a part and not the full Judgement.
The full expression 1s A is C because B is C and A is B. This
solves the difficulty Just raised about the proposition AB is 11fJ1
The Gene,al Natu,e of Inference ~7
namely, that the premisses cannot be got out of it. AB is a.p is
only judged on the ground A 1s e1 and B is P, and so the full
expression of the judgement (that is, of the thought which is
necessary to make the verbal expression AB is e1/J possible) is
AB is aP because A is a. and B is {J. Thus the premisses must
appear in the only way m which AB is a.{J can really be a judge•
ment, and the difficulty raised is a fallacy caused by the false
abstraction of a judgement from the way 10 which it is judged.
We must again distinguish between the apprehension and the
fact which 1s apprehended. It will be found that much depends
upon the question whether the premisses are taken to represent
the one or the other.
Tlurdly, we must distinguish between our apprehension of
a fact and our memory that the fact was apprehended (which
1s not necessarily a memory of the apprehension itself). Observe
that if the apprehension was an expenence, the memory of the
experience (not the mere memory that it was experienced) is
not itself an experience and is not a repetition of the previous
experience. If, however, the apprehension was a process of
proof, the memory of the full proof 1s itself the process of proof,
or we may call 1t a repetition of the proof
By help of these distinctions we shall sec that in the cases
under consideration the fact represented by the conclusion is
equivalent to the facts represented by the premisses in conjunc-
tion and not something different from them necessitated by
their conjunction, and that m this sense the conclusions are not
inferences. On the other hand, we shall see that the appre•
hension represented by the conclus10n, or corresponding to it,
1s not the same as the apprehensions represented by the so-called
premisses, nor is it the same as thec;c m conjunction, and the
difference 1s not merely one of verbal expression
§ 221. The difficulties may be resolved m this way. Consider
first the premisses as representing the facts apprehended. The
fact of A's being a, and the fact of A's being /3, that 1s, the
co-existence of these facts, does not necessitate A's being e1/3 as
something different from itself. On the contrary, 1t 1s the fact
that A is both a and /3. And the other cases may be treated
similarly. Consider next the premisses• as representing acts of
(• 'Change the example, smce a here necessitates /J.' MS. note J
11773•a C
INFERENCE
apprehension. The facts A is ci and A is /J are in themselves
not separate, but the apprehensions of them may be separate
and, more than that, in some cases it may be impossible to have
these apprehensions together. For example, the triangle formed
by the diameter of a circle and by two straight lmes drawn from
its extremities to a pomt in the circumference 1s a right-angled
triangle. It 1s true ot the same triangle that the square on the
diameter 1s equal to the sum of the squares on the other two
sides. The apprehension of the first property is the proof given
by Euclid in Proposition 31 of his third book. The apprehension
of the second property 1s the proof given in the 47th Proposition
of the first book, and nothing shorter. Neither of these appre-
hens1om, contains the other, nor can we have them simul-
taneously, as we cannot conduct two proofs simultaneously.
Here then the judgement A 1s both a and /J, which we un•
doubtedly ground somehow on the apprehension of A as ci and
the apprehension of A as {J, is not the same as these apprehensions
nor the same as their conJunction. It 1s therefore m some sense
a Judgement which 1s different from them but which they neces•
sitate. It is on this account that the process has a resemblance
to mferencc, and on this account also 1t 1s natural in the state-
ment of the argument to add to A 1s a and A 1s {J the statement,
therefore A 1s a/J.
To see whether there really 1s an inference we must ask what
exactly the apparently new Judgement, A ts o. and {J, is. Suppose
we prove that A 1s o., and then prove that A 1s {J. It would
probably be said that m the proof that A Js {J, or at the end
of 1t, we remember the result of the proof that A is a, though
we have not the proof. The v.ord result JS somewhat mJsleadmg:
1t rather 1mphes that we remember the mere fact that A is a.
without reference to the proof, because 1t 1s somethmg different
and resulting from the proof. But this is qmte impossible; the
accurate expression 1s, that we remember neither the proof that
A is a nor the mere fact A 1s a, as a result, but the fact that we
proved A is ci. To put it otherwise, we are not really appre-
hending A's bcmg a but remembering that we once did apprehend
1t. 1 In the proof of A's bemg {J, if it is all before us, we have
the apprehension that A 1s {J. If we have this together with
1
Obspn•e, not remembering the apprehen1110n.
The General, Nattwe of Inference 429
the memory that A was proved to be a., this would be verbally
expressed in the two inadequate formulae of judgement, A is
a. and A is fl simply. And now is the judgement A is a.fl an
inference from the apprehension A is fl, and the mtmory that
we apprehended that 'A is a.' ? It is not such an inference, for
1t is obviously nothmg but having these two judgements together.
The same is true if the verbal form of judgement A is ft also
represented not the proof that A is fl but the memory that there
was a proof. But again we may ask, is it an inference from
the original apprehensions or apprehension ~ If 'A is fl ' happen9
to represent the second apprehens10n, and 'A is a' the memory
that we had the first, the difference is only in what 'A is a.' stands
for, and this 1s only the difference between apprehending that A is
a. and remembering that we once apprehended 1t. But now no
one would call the memory that somethmg happened in our
apprehension an inference from the apprehension of 1t, though
1t 1s true that the apprehension here conditions something
different from itself, that is, the memory that 1t happened. For
an mfercncc is always understood to be from what we have
before us, what we arc now apprehending. Now by hypothesis
the given apprehenc;ion 1s not before us. The same is obviously
true if both 'A is a.' and 'A is fl' represent memories that there
were proofs of them ; and 1f one or both of the original appre-
hensions was an experience and not a proof, exactly the same
treatment apphes Thus, finally, though 1t would follow that
the judgement 'A is a.{3' 1s not pi:operly called an inference from
'A io;; a' and 'A 1c; /J', we seem to have the explanat10n why it
1s natural to put in this step (therefore A ts a.fl) expressly. The
reason is that when 1t 1s naturally introduced 1t represents
a stage of consciouc;ness which 1s different from the apprehen-
sions (in the proper sense of the word) that A ts a. and A is /J,
1s indeed a step necessary to the proof
§ 222. The preceding mvec:;t1gat1on seems to bring out the
reason why we hesitate to call certam processes inferential even
when the step taken seems necessary, or at least natural, and
therefore not a mere restatement of what has preceded. In
the processes which we do not hesitate to call inferences the
facts or fact apprehended in the premisses necessitate the fact
apprehended in the conclusion as a fact different from t.hem-
c 2
430 INFERENCE
selves, and the latter fact is apprehended as thus necessitated.
Now we have seen that this definition at once decides the cases
under consideration not to be mferences. Again, it is these
processes (1.e such as correspond to this definition) which a.re
those actually recognized m logic as inferences, though without
a clear consc1ousnc,;s that this is so and of all that it implies,
Now a prmc1ple "h1ch ts correctly used in particular instances
is not al\\-ay,; rlearly recognized m the abstract or correctly
formulated. Tl11s has happened with regard to what seems the
true prmc1ple of inference ; the apprehension, one may repeat
shortly, 01 one fact as necessitated by a different fact or facts.
For inference m general is sometimes incorrectly represented as
the necessitation of one Judgement by another or others. If
this were so, a memory, as necessitated by a given apprehension,
should be regarded as an mferC'nc-e But, as we have seen,
nobody tlunks of mamtaming that; the real reason being that
we arc gmdcd m tlus particular mstanre by a sound instinct
and arc usmg the true prmc1ple For though m the given case
the memory 1,; neccss1tatc-d by the apprehension, the memory
1tc;elf 1s not an apprehension of this necessitation.
§ 223. The account given of the process A 1c; a. and B is /3 :
therefore AB 1s a./3 would, from one point of view, make an
inference in the third figure of the syllog1sm into an immediate
inference.
The- form of the figure 1c; M 1s P, M 1s S, t hcrcfore some S 1s P
(or some P 1s S).
The condus1on follows because the same thing M is both
S and P. We have then M ti. P, 1\1 1,; S, therefore M is both S
and P. The latter we have ruled not to be an inference from
the premisses, but merely a statement of them as both holding
together (which, we must notice, does not differ from the simple
statement of them), and the inferences from 1t of some S is P
and some P ts S arc unmediate. Thus there would be nothing
in the third figure but 1mmcd1ate mfcrence. The syllogistic
logic ts committed to this anyhow, if 'M 1s PS' is regarded as
one judgement, because that logic docs not recognize 'Mis both
S and P' as an inferenre. But now tlus analysis is not confined
to the third figure. Consider the first figure : all B is C, all
A is B, therefore all A 1s C. The premisses, all B 1s C and all A
The General Nature of Inference 43X
is B, may be combined in one statement, just as in the third
figure. Thus some B is all A and is at the same time C, or
some B is C and all A, and from this the inference to all A is C
is obviously immediate. This, however, 1s only an anticipation
of what will be maintained later, that the relation of the con·
clusion to the complex of premisses (whether syllogistic or not
makes no difference) is always immediate, is not mediated by
anything intervening.
§ 224. We have been led to recognize a principle which holds
not only in the non-inferential processes we have been con•
s1dcrmg but m inference proper What we have said of two
proofs each with a single conclus1on, that the app'rehensions
wluch they constitute may possibly not be present together,
may hold w1thm one of these proofs. For it may have parts
which cannot be had as simultaneous apprehensions. The verbal
form of a premiss A is B, used in drawing an mfcrence, may
correspond not to the apprehension of A's bemg B, but to our
memory that we have had such an apprehension, so that m
the strict sense we arc actually not Judging the judgement
'A 1s B '. This, though not the exception but the rule in the
vast maJonty of proofs, seems quite ignored m the usual treat•
ment of 111fcrencc. It has important consequences and, among
other tlungs, it seems to be a part at least of the key to the
poss1b11ity of a kmd of error m the exact sciences which is
a stumbling-block to theories of knowledge and error.
§ 225. We may return to the contention that the Judgement
A and C arc equal to the same thmg differs from the judgements
A = B and C = B, because the term ' the same thing ' does not
appear m either of these two latter, which 'may be accounted
premisses. It u. true that it does not appear m the verbal
expression, but 1t is contained m the thought which corresponds
to this expression. For m Judgmg C = B, we must recognize
B as the same B which = A or we should not use the common
term B at c1.ll. If we had forgotten the Judgement B = A this
would not be true, but by hypothesis we have not forgotten it.
The reason for mtroducmg the step m the verbal expression is
that which we have already given for the introduction of the
step A 1s a./J or AB is a./3.
§ 226. Inference is often spoken of as if 1t were essentially
INFERENCE
a connexion of judgements, as though the premisses were judge•
ments which necessitated our forming another judgement. Shall
we say simply that the Judgement of the premisses (that is,
the judging of them) necessitates the judgement of the con•
clusion? We have seen already that this, whether true or not,
is too wide to be taken for a dcfimt1on of inference, for it would
include memory.
Now first observe that "hether this is true or not 1t 1s in any
case not the mcamng of our verbal statement. If we say A is
C because B 1,; C and A 1s B, we do not mean that our Judge•
ments B 1s C and A 1s B necc!:is1tate our Judgement that A 1s C,
but \\C mean that the facts B 1s C and A 1s B necessitate the
fact 'A 1s C '. In science again the value of such inference 1s
not that somebody believes the conclusion because he believes
the premisses, but thc1.t ,u1 obJect1ve 11ecess1tatlon 1s actually
apprehended. Thus it 1s the connexion of the obJects appre•
bended \\ h1ch 1s meant, 1t 1s this which is apprehended m
mference and which is of mtercst and importance to science.
Secondly, we may truly say that I apprehend the conclusion,
or have the apprchcns10n represented by the conclusion, because
I have the apprehensions represented by the premisses In this
sense one apprl'hcns1011 m.t.y be said to necessitate another,
But, though true, tlm statement has a form which may mislead.
Apprchens1on, ,,e h.t.ve seen, cannot be abstracted from what
is ,lpprchendcd, and there is ..i. d.t.nger 111 scparatmg them, as we
have seen m d1scm,!:img the a priori view of knowledge .t.nd the
theory of the inconcc1vab1hty of the opposite as a tc5t of truth.
There we hc1.vc m.t.111l.i.1ncd that c1. ncccsbary apprchcnb1on 1s only
intclhg1blc as mcanmg an apprehension of an obJect1ve necessity.
We shall find this account verified in the case before us. How
1s 1t exactly that the apprehensions B is C aml A 1s B cc1.n be
truly bald to cc1.use or necessitate the apprehcns1011 A is C ? Only
li1 this \\ay. I apprehend the facts B 1s C and A 1s Band then
apprehend these facts as necessitating A 1s C Now that means
that the necess1tat1011 of the apprehension A is C by the appre•
hensions B 1s C c1.11d A is B 1s after all just the apprehension
of the necessitation of the fact A 1s C by the facts B 1s C and
A 1s B. Thus, as before, the necessary apprehension is only
11ccessc1.f) because 1t 1s an apprehension of a necessity, and the
The General Nrlture of Inference 433
question as to how necessity in the thinking can correspond
with necessity in the object cannot arise.
Finally, suppose that one or more of the premisses of an
inference is not an apprehension proper of the fact that B is
C or that A is B, but our memory that we apprehended the
fact (experienced it) or proved it. If ,ve remember proving that
B is C and A is B, even though it be said that memory is
uncertain, yet at least we know that, 1£ we remember rightly
that B is C and that A is B, the facts would necessitate A's
being C.
§ 227. The definition of mference that we have given docs not
&tate that the connexion on which 1t depends is always one of
universals, and yet we know that we always find 1t to be so."
Now this 1s not because we define inference beforehand as only
deahng with such connexion. We find m any instance where
we could be said at all reasonably to apprehend the necess1ta·
t1on of a particular fact by another particular or particulars,
that such necessitation 1s only a partlcularizat1on of a necessary
connexion of universals, and m tho inferences which we arc
about to examine we shall always find that we have to do with
this universal necessitation. Aristotle recognizes the universal
character of inference m so far as he makes the reason or
ground 1 to be universal, but he recognizes this fact as familiar
without reflecting on it and v.ithout reahzmg the necessity of
asking any questions about 1t, as is often the case v.1th facts
w1th which we are fam1har. Clearly the question must be asked
why mference should have tlus charctcter. There 1s a danger of
avo1dmg the difficulty by somehow mcludmg umversahty in our
definition of mfcrcnce, as some modem treatises do,b thus over·
1 nfTuw, irc6oA011. Cf, § 2 37
[• ' Con~ider and embody the tact that we ~ecm to 111£er i,ometimes from
what is peculiar lo the mdnidual · i\l~ note I have put in a foot-note
(p 434), from a hasty scribble, what wai, the difficulty Wilson felt. Cf p 481
b I am not sure of the reference ' The universal 111 its differences LS
then the basis of mediate Judgement or inference' Bosanquet, Logic, II 1 1.
' The general pnnciple on which the validity of every concluston rests may
be expressed by the formula . " What falls under the condition of a rule,
falls under this rule itself".' Kant, Logic,§ 57. Cf § 58, (See ali:10 infra,
§ 262,)
The statement about Aristotle 1s ob11Curc The general rc!crc11ce may be
lNFERENCE
looking an important point and evadmg a difficult investigation.
We may defer the quest1on untd '\\e have further examined the
nature of inference m sciencc.1
1 § 262 The nature of the umversabty 1s rv1dent when we argue {rom
a mark of what 1& of a certam kmd But there are lllStances where we argue
from what 1s c1. mark of a particular md1v1dual alone, so that if there 1s
a universal propos1bon 1riphed 1t 1& of c1. different sort from the other, and 1t
1& important to i.ec whether the ,1cw that mferencc 1s universal can here be
vmdu.ated
to ir &warm (uv>.>.o-y1up9i) 3,1 TU tta.8/,>.011 l11rapx~II' (An l'r I 24) Tlus l!I the
formal rule e'li mere parllc1uarib11s nrhil uguitur, but the reference to the
cause appears to relate to the doctrmc of the Posterior Analytics, that
thr aim of i11uT,jp1J lb to connect the predicate with the subJect through the
proxunatc 1.ause of tl1c predicate The maJor prcnuss, Aristotle therefore
m~1~ts, must be •al/,>.ov Moreover, &c1ence 1s the i.earch for pnmary, 1 e most
um\<ersal, caui.es (An l'o 72a 4-5) But, on the other hand, the J>ostmo,
An11lyt1es lb full of refled:mn on the quei.tmn whether demoni.trc1.tion 1s or
1~ not universal, and on the supenonty of true demonstration becau&c 1t 1s
universal (see cg An. Po 1 13 and 24) ln fcl.1.t the obiter dict11m would
perhaps have been reconb1dercd ]
II
THE SYLLOGISM
a real inference, not that there 1s no mference as to the relation of II and /J.
In fact II and 13 are related 1n the conclusions some 11 1s /J, or some /J IS a, m
consequence of their relation to A, as m the ordmary view of the third figure
of the syllogism What was pomted out about this was that the inference
is unmechate from A 1s both a and fJ. not that there 1s no inference at all.
• Cl the Aristotelian term Td artz.\1mn.
Syllogism 437
undoubtedly has. It might show by examples the evidence for
a form of argument, but its judgements would be empirical,
wanting m universality and necessity. Its actual method is as
much a priori and ' constructive ' as that of any pure mathe•
matical science. It starts with the general conception of a pro•
position, with a d1stmct1on of subject and predicate ; it then
distinguishes the possible varieties of proposition exhaustively
a pnori and not by any analysis or empirical examination of
actual propositions. Then, agam, 1l determjncs a priori all
possible combinations of two premisses and determines from
them a priori all possible varieties of conclusion of the bm1ted
kmd described This h, exactly parallel to the method of a
mathematical science, and 1t will become clear as we go on that
the determinatton of the rules, figures, and moods of the syl•
logism, which occupies so large a part of this logic, is no part
of true logic whatever, though vahd enough m itself, but 1s
.i. science m the same sense as pure mathematics.
§ 231. It must not, however, be supposed that this a priori
tlunking wluch we have been descnbmg can proceed by pure
abstraction only, although 1t docs deal with forms which to
a certain extent arc abstract, We may perhaps tlunk that m
this kind of logic we work with the general form of the syllogism
from the first and thc1.t we dcnvc from that any application to
pc1.rticular cases Now that 1s altogether impossible ; we cannot
understand these forms except by takmg dcfimte instances to
show what the symbols mean, that 1s by havmg matter as well
.i.s form. Take, for cxc:1.mplc, all M 1s P, all S 1s M, therefore
.i.11 S 1s P. To sec the vahd1ty of tlus we must take a parttculc:1.r
syllogism with actual propos1t1ons, and m that instanLe \\-C must
see directly the proper conclmwn, which is as specific and
definite as the premisses themselves. We must further see on
reflection how the general form of the conclus1011 depends on
the general charactenst1cs of the form of the premisses. The
first step, namely seemg the conclusion m a particular case, 1s
the condition of our bemg able to reason at all m the particular
way in question ; the second, namely the abstracting process,
is the condition of our being able to make the general logical
abstraction • of the syllogism It is also directly self-evident
L• ' "logical" reconsider.' :vIS, note.]
INFERENCE
to us that the form we are abstractmg is universally valid,
because we can sec that nothmg m 1t depends upon the matter
peculiar to the instance. Its method therefore is the appre•
hension of the universal 111 the particular, and we see how both
imagination and perception are necessary to that abstract
invest,gat1on, a priori a& 1t 1s, which determmes the syllogistic
rules. This proccdi.rc docs not mdced prove any rules of
inference ; 1t 1s simply the immediate recogmt1on of them.
§ 232. The syllog1st1c rules, being but abstractions from the
actual procedure of lhe human reason, cannot be described as
rulc,s discovered by the log1c1an and laid down for the guidance
of our reason : they tell us what reason necessarily is, m
.i. ccrt:\m hm1tcd department, and we cannot prescribe rules for
[• ' Darapti to Darn ' WJl~on nowhere explr1.m~ wh.it he mean& by tlui..
Pre&umably he mean& thc1t the minor prem11,1, 1s converted to Y and not to I,
I.,{ s 216]
III
PRI~CIPL~f:> A~D METHOD OF THE PURE
DEMO~STRATIVE SCIENCES
§ 242 a Ii wa!> long held from Aristotle onwards thJ.t the
syllogt!>m \\d.!> the method of cidvancc in geometry and mathe-
matics gencrc1.lly. These sciences were supposed to start from
certain gcncr..il prmc1plcs which they do not themselves demon·
strate, prmc1plc!> arrived c1t by 111tu1tion or induction, and the
progre!>s from the!>C prmciples was supposed to be made by
syllog1stlc infcrenLe Tlus theory i!> the direct consequence of
th.it. a priori theory of dcmon!>tr.i.tion wluch we have described.
It 1s owmg to such a view th.1.t we have c1t the bcgmmng of the
vcmouc:; book,; of Euchd'c; Elements a collect1011 of defin1t1om,1
axiom:., c1.11Cl post ulc.1.te ... , for these represent the effort to collect
.i.11 t.he supposed startmg prmciples or .issumptlom, We might
su&pect tlus theory on the ground that the advance in science
would then rest on no specific knowledge of the matter of the
science, beyond what was contained m the prefixed collection
of principles. It would depend solely on the use of syllogistic
forms supposed to be common to all demonstration. But this
we know is directly contrary to the fact. AgJ.m, the supposed
assumptions bemg taken to be !muted m number, their com•
binations in an argument mmt be hnutccl and so the conclusions
must be hnutecl 111 number. ln consequenLC geometry should
have been cxhc1ustcd long ago. The fact seems to be that those
[• \V1h.011 ai,i,ume, throughoul that Euclid develop:. h1., geometry syllo-
gu,ti.cally. Thu:. he :.peak-; repeatedly ai, 1£ the ax1om1> wluch Eucbd quotei.
1n h111 propo:.1tio111, were mtended to be prem1i.be, 'fh1:. 1:. a curious m11>take
It was much l<lter that Euchd'i, Elements were attempted to be set out syllo-
gist1cally An example 1s given 1n Manscl's edition of Aldrich, A,-t,s Logicae
Rudimenta, Appendix L Generally Wdo;on regarded lus own view as derived
from Kant (e g Jfritik, 1st ed. pp 707 et seq) It 1s m fact more hke
Schle1ermacher's (see e g Dialogues, § 327, quoted by Ueberweg, Logic, § 101).
Leibntz, Meditationes de cognitione (pp 540-1), puts the other view, • non
contemnenda ventat1s enunc1abonum cntena sunt regulae commums logicae,
qu1bus eti.am Geometrae utuntur firma autem demonstrati.o est quae
praescnptam a logica formam scrval • ]
P,inciples and Method of Science 455
who hold this doctrine of demonstration have not accurately
realized what their own doctrine should mean. It ought to
mean that the original principles or premisses being granted,
any further conclusions are got by combining them into syl-
logisms. That would be the whole operation of thought in the
way of discovery and inference. We may add accordingly that
this is refuted by a very simple experiment, for if we take the
definitions, postulatt"s, and ax10ms of Euclid and try to operate
upon them with the syllogistic forms, we shall make no discovery
at all; we shall not get one of Euclid's theorems; we shall get
no conclusion whatever worth having.
§ 243. If we examine any discovery in geometry and note
down everything that is necessary, we shall find that we can
do nothing at all unless we first draw a figure. The process
advances by making new constructions, the validity of such
constructions is a matter of immediate spatial intuition, and so
also are the consequences inferred from these constructions in
the way of other geometrical relations which they necessitate.
For the discovery of the right construction there cannot be
any rule , it depends upon the manner m which the particular
case suggests the steps we have to take. Thus the finding of
the construction is the real difficulty in the discovery, and there
is a great difference between one mind and another in the
capacity of seeing what the problem suggests. When the con•
struction is found the problem is solved and the proof also is
complete , we do not need to add to it a chain of argument
such as we find in Euclid, for though we can thus explain to
a learner the connt"xion of the premisses and the validity of the
conclus1on, the best way is to retrace the process of discovery.
Further, such procedure as that in Euclid may sometimes not
show at all how the construction is found. For instance, though
in Pythagoras' theorem (Elements, 1. 47) we see by means of
the argument both that the conclusion 1s justified and the use
of the construction, the real process by which thought advanced
in the discovery of this constructwn is kept out of sight. The
process of discovery then is not an analysis of propositions
already given us ; it does not consist in putting into syllogistic
form any given material of premisses. We add to the given
material by the constructive acts, through which we apprehend
INFERENCE
something other than the material, that is, something which
that material necessitates. We do this in geometry by con•
structing new spatial relations the validity of which we see in
the act of construction, and thus we apprehend the universal
in the particular.
Now, as these constructions are in the nature of the case
particular, how is the result universal ? The anc;wer lies in the
nature of our mathematical faculty itself In constructing the
particular we see immediately the universal validity of our con•
struct1on. The mam thought here, notwithstanding differences
of expos1t1on, 1s due to Kant 1 It seems clear that Kant thought
the method ronfined to mathematics, but that is not really so :
it is universally true that "c can only apprehend the relation
of universals m apprehending the corresponding particulars.
Though 1t may be difficult to understand this theory at first
owing to preconceptions derived from current theories of know•
ledge, 1t is nevertheless the fart, and can be dearly verified m
any actual demonstration m which we sec that we nowhere use
the particularity of the figure as such in our argument. The
ultimate fact therefore 1s that m geometry and mathematics
generally we are able to see the universal in the particular and
so to arrive at a umversal Judgement. It 1s this transcendence
~f he particular, though the particular must be used, which
rbi\ces mathematical method what is called a priori. In the
empirical sciences, on the other hand, we cannot thus see the
universal in the particular , m other words, given the connexion
of two elements m a particular experience we do not see the
universal connexion, that is, we do not apprehend the reason.
§ 244. A kmd of paradox remains to be considered : the figure
on v. hich everythmg depends may be imperfect and not an
adequate realization of the universal. It is on this acrount that
students of the subject have so often failed to recognize the
importance of the figure and have tended to suppose that the
reality of the process lay somehow in pure thought ac; opposed
to any particular and imperfect constructions. It is this fallacy
which 1s mainly responsible for the chimera of non-Eucltdean
spa<'e. The writers who mamtmn th1S do not realize the quite
1 1,,,.,,1, d , l"er,11111(1 (1~t ed, p j12; ~nd ed, p 740], Thel"E' 1s an
antic1patton, however, of the tntth in An'!totll', .11,fttaphysus, 1051• 22,
Principles antl Method of Science 457
fatal objection which lies in the impossibility of any construe•
tions to correspond to such space, This is because they do not
realize the place of the figure in Euclidean geometry. They do
not even suspect that it is precisely the construction of the
figure which is the true process of the advance of thought in
geometrical discovery. In truth a thing cannot be ' thinkable
but not representable '. The paradox we are now considering,
the possible imperfcctton of the figure, cannot really be removed
by supposing that we imagine a perfect figure. A figure in
experience might be m itself perfect. A falling rain-drop, for
instance, might be a perfect sphere or an accurate ellipsoid, yet
we should have no means of ascertaining that it was perfect,
and so its perfection would not be experienced by us. Now
there is exactly the same difficulty about any figure in our
imagination ; we may want it to be accurate but we can no
more be sure that it is so than if it were actually found in our
experience. We certainly must thmk of a perfect figure, for on
that our proof depends, but that is not the same thing as saying
that the figure in our imagination is perfect ; we apprehend,
that is to say, a particular, and in some sense we apprehend the
perfect particular. That apprehension is not an experience and
not an imagmat1on, but, nevertheless, it 1s an apprehension of
what the nature of the particular must be. This is undoubtedly
true, and 1t remains to attempt to characterize this kind of
apprehension. We seem to arrive at a new and important
distinction m our faculty of apprehension
We must clearly apprehend the nature of the perfect individual
figure, for on that our proof depends. But the apprehension,
as we have seen, is not an experience, because though a particular
given figure may mdeed be perfect we cannot apprehend 1t as
such with certainty in experience. Nor 1s 1t the apprehension
of an imagined particular, and for the same reason. It is an
apprehension which we have with such experience and with such
imagination. This peculiar kind of apprehension does not
appear to have been recognized in any theory of knowledge or
of inference. The fact 1s that the difficulty above described
has not been recognized and the solution of it has therefore not
been suggested.
§ 245. It may be objected that in actual geometry the axioms
INFERENCE
do appear as major premisses and that although we must admit
that the process of discovery is not syllogistic, in the strict sense,
yet when the theorem has been found and the connexion is
presented as something to be understood, it consists of syllogisms
as in the ordinary Euclid. We must distinguish two kmds of
major premisses. Axiomatic premisses, which are not demon·
strated, includmg defimtions, and premisses which are them•
selves products of demonstration.
To take the former first. Euclid shows (Elements, i. 1) that,
in the triangle ACB, AC and BC are- equal, each of them, to
AB, and being equal to the same thmg arc equal to one another,
because of the ax10m. Here the axiom appears in the last step
as the maJor premise;. This we have explained already. The
truth of th<' axiom is only apprehended m the individual instances
which we here pretend to derive from 1t. In the case before us
we see the truth directly m the particular mstance or we should
never see 1t at all, and therefore to represent 1t as deduced from
the axiom is an mvcrsion of the actual order of thought. We
recognize, however, that the truth we see has a universal
character, not depending on the particular magnitudes, and this
recognition of the umversal is prer1sely the axiom itself and
follows after that partJcutar act of thought which is wrongly
represented in the syllogistic procesc; as derived from it.
§ 246. We do, however, find m geometry cases where there
seems to be a real syllog1sttc process; where, as it would be
said, the result of a prev1ouc; proof 1c; applied to a particular
instance Consider the proof (Elements, 111. 31) that the tnanglc,
of which the bac;e 1s the diameter of a circle and the vertex
a point on the circumference, has a right angle at the vertex.
Jf this theorem ic; subsumed as a mmor premic;c; under the truth
of Pythagoras' theorem ac; a maJor premiss, we infer the same
property for this triangle. This may be put thus . If two
straight lines are drawn from a point m the circumference of
a circle to the extremities of a diameter, the sum of the squares
on the two lines is equal to the square on the diameter. The
act of thought, viz. the whole proof, which here gives us the
rnmor premiss, does not give us the major, we don't thereby
prove Pythagorac;' theorem. Again, the act of thought which
gives us the maJor premiss does not give us the minor, does
Principles and Method of Science 459
not, that is, prove Elements, iii. 31.1 The act of thought there-
fore which gives either premiss does not give the other and thus
a condition of valid syllogistic inference seems to be satisfied.
Here, then, there seems to be a syllogistic process. It is of the
simplest character, an operation found in all departments of
thinking, causmg no d1:fficulty, and not depending, be it observed,
on any knowledge of the special matter of geometry. On the
other hand, what is most valuable to the progress of the parti-
cular science as such is not this mere obvious subsumption of
the particular under the universal, but the process by which we
discover the universal in the particular which is subsumed under
1t. That depends not on the syllogism but on construction with
apprehension. Now when we examine more carefully the nature
of the major premic;s, we shall find that m the actual process
of thinking whereby we know 1t fully and do not merely
remember the result of the demonstration, m other words, in
the full apprehension of the Judgement represented by the
major premiss, the syllogistic subsumption disappears. Strictly
the maJor premiss, 1£ the Judgement expressed m that premiss
is properly Judged, can only be applied by our reproducing the
whole proof. If we do this, we find that m the case of the triangle
m the semicircle we first demonstrate by construction that the
vertical angle 1s a right angle and then go on by a system of
constructions (which is nothing but the proof of Pythagoras'
theorem) to prove that the square on the base is equal to the
sum of the squares on the sides In this complicated geometrical
proposition, JUSt as much as m any of the more primitive ones,
provided every judgement used 1s treated m the same way, we
shall find the whole process of thought consisting of these con·
structtons with the corresponding apprehensions. We shall find
no process of advance by syllogism here any more than there.
The syllogism also itself will agam have the same explanation,
as arising from the recogmt10n of the universal character of our
construction'> and their consequences.
§ 247. If, then, instead of conducting the proof in the particular
case that A 1s B and the proof in the particular case that Bis
C, we merely remember mther result or both, and so do not
fully apprehend the facts correspondmg to the premisses, we
1 The angle m a sem1c1rcle 1'1 a right angle.
qn~ E
INFERENCE
apparently have the syllogistic- form, all B is C, all A is B,
therefore all A is C ; and that is where the syllogistic form
would seem to come explicitly into geometry. But we must
not suppose that the syllog1stic form is related only to imperfect
apprehension and due only to that. It corresponds to some•
thing m the romplete proof, that is, in the complete act of
apprehension. Consider the complete proof when the syllogistic
form does not appear. In the case of a particular triangle in
a semicircle represented by the figure before me, where ABC
represents the triangle itself, I apprehend by Euclid's proof that
the triangle must have a right angle at the point represented
by B. Then adding the construction of Pythagoras' theorem,
I appr?hend by Euclid's proof that the right angle at B neces•
s1tates that AC1 = AB 2 + BC2• I thus apprehend that the
particular triangle m the partirular -;em1circle has this relation
be-tween the squares on its sides. Bui now the process is seen
not to depend upon the particularity of the figure, and thus we
apprehend the universal, namely, that any triangle m a sem1-
c1rcle has a nght angle at the vertex and, bcrause o{ that, the
relation bet\\ <"Cll th<" squares on its sides The verbal expression
of the generahzatmn \\hich we have thus apprehended m the
consideration of the particular 1s that any such triangle 111
a sem1c1rcle has a right angle; any triangle which has a right
angle has the Pythagorean property; t hcrefore any triangle m
a semicircle has the aforesaid property Thus m the properly
compl£>te apprehensmn we have this syllog1sm, not, however, as
the process by means of winch "e have discovered and inferred,
but a-, 'lomethmg the truth of "htch has only been fully appre-
hended 1n the precedent apprehensions concerned with the
particular figure In other words we only apprehend this
syllogism fully by the prorr'ls m question. Now suppose I have
neither proof before me. I remember that I proved that the
triangle in a semicircle has a right angle, and l remember that
I proved that a right-angled triangle bas the Pythagorean pro•
pcrty. Even 1f it 1s obJcctcd that memory 1s not trustworthy,
I know at least that 1f the facts are as I remember them, they
necessitate that any triangle m a semicircle has the property in
question Thus I have a true hypothetical judgement. But it
would be affectation to say that tl1erc are no cases m which
Princi,ples and MNhod of Sciencs .¢t
I do not absolutely trust my memory. I know, for instance,
that it was proved that the triangle in a semicircle has a right
angle ; then the facts represented by the premisses are known ;
each is apprehended, the apprehension consisting in a memory
that it was proved. But clearly the knowledge of the syllogism
is incomplete as compared with the knowledge of it in the
complete apprehension above described and depends in the last
rec;ort for its validity on the fact that we can replace the memory
of the proof by the proof itself. We thus see how the possession
of the syllogism in the one case differs from the possession of
it in the other, although the difference does not appear in the
verbal expression. It follows, then, that the syllogism is not
due merely to defective apprehension ; it exists anyhow but is
only fully comprehended in the case where we have the proofs
of which it is the generalization.
§ 248. The foregomg 1s not confined to geometry or mathe-
matics, but holds of any syllogism in which one or more of the
premic;ses 1s a universal proposition, the truth of which is known.
For such a universal, if really known and not merely probable
and based on mduchve evidence, can only be apprehended in
the particular; that 1s, we can only apprehend that all A is B
by apprehending m an instance A, that A 1s B as being A. This
dependence then upon the particular is not confined to mathe-
matics as Kant seems to have supposed.a
The conclusion to which we are led may be summed up as
follows. The true syllog1stic process in rcatfoning being the
possession of a major premiss followed or preceded by a minor
which is not included in 1t cxphc1tly ; the apl>rchension of the
minor again not including that of the maJor, and a conclusion
following which is necessitated for our thought by the possession
of the premisses, we never have such a process in mathematical
science, unless the major premic;s ic; possessed, not as the appre-
hension of the facts stated m "it, but as the memory merely that
1t has been apprehended. Thus the syllogistic form as a process
ra 'Nur die Mathematik mcht aus Begriffen, sondern der Konstruction
derselben . 1hr Erkenntmss able1tet . . Das philosoph1sche Erkenntniss
das Allgememe Jederze1t. rn abstl'aclo (durch Begriffe) betrachten 111uss,
indessen dass Mathematik das Allgemeine ita concreto (in der einzelnen
Anschauung) und doch durch reme Vorstellung II pnon erwtgen kann.'
I c, p 734 (762, 2nd ed ) ]
E2
INFERENCE
of thinking is followed in mathematics only when knowledge in
the most complete form is not present, that is, when the facts
stated in the maJor premiss arc not apprehended in the foll and
strict sense.
Such a syllogism 1s not complete in itself, because it depends
on the absent proof of the major premiss. Thus such a syllogism
could not be an absolute startmg-pomt in knowledge. Now 1t
can easily be shown that tlus must always be so in the case of
universal statementc; m matterc; of knowledge, not merely in
rt1athemat1cs, as Kant sel.'ms to have supposed. Obviously the
only rase we have to ronsidcr 1s that in which the major premiss
is not d<'monstrated. (Induction 1s excluded bcrause it cannot
give knowledge but only a high degree of probab1ltty. Even 1£
1t could give knowledge, that knowledge would be demonstrative
knowledge and th<' syllogic;m would depend upon it for 1ts major
premiss) The maJor then in question must be self-evident.
But the universal fart represented by the universal c;tatement
can only be matter of appr<'hens1on 111 a partirular, for we rannot
possibly apprcht>nd tht> nature of any umversal except by
thinking of a particular in which 1t 1s manifested. Now if the
universal 1c; sclf-ev1dent, it 1s seen in any partirular whatsoever,
and therefore our apprehension of the nature of any of its
particulars involves that of the universal. It cannot then be
preceded by the apprehenc;1on of the umversal so as to be sub•
sumed under 1t lf, for inc;tancc, the umversal 1s all B is C, and
the mmor all A is B, the A's arc particular mstanres of B; the
apprehension then of any of them involves the apprehension
that A as being B 1s C It 1s only after reflection on this that
we see that the thmg's being C depended only on its bemg B;
whirh 1s just what produres the universal statement represented
by the major premiss.
It 1s well to add here for clearnci:;s that the formula 'seeing
the universal in the particular ' means that m the case, for
example, of a particular A, though I am obliged to think of
a particular, I apprehend that 1t 1s B only as being A, or only
because it is A, and not through anything particular or confined
to itself.
f 249. The validity of the general form of the syllogism, that
is, of the syllogistic rule, is like any rule of inference recognized
Principles and Method of Science 463
in any particular syllogism, and the particular syllogism is, ae
we have seen, not deduced from it. The question then anSQli
whether every particular syllogism is not itself similarly the
generalization of a particular and the apprehension of a universal
m a particular. Suppose that tn the syllogism B is C, A is B,
therefore A is C, the statements BC and AB are full apprehen•
s1ons ; we have then a truly known universal and we can only
apprehend, as was said above, the universal all A 1s C because
r11l B 1s C and all A IS B, by considering a particular. The only
question is how this 1s done. Take the particular A1 . I appre-
hend that A1 as A must be B, and so 1s B1 (as m the geometrical
example). Agam, to get the universal ' all B 1s C ' when I can
really have such a statement as certarn, I apprehend m B1 that
.ts B it must be C. thus I apprehend A1 as being B because
1t is A, and as bemg C because it is B ; but to c1.pprchend A1 as
B because it is A, is to apprehend A1 to be B not as a particular
but only through its umversal ch,uacter A. Thus we apprehend
that all A is B or any A 1s B. The above apprehension then is
apprebendmg cl.ny A to be C because any A 1s B and any B is C,
which is the syllogism, and the syllogism therefore is a universal
apprehended thus 111 r1 particular.
Next, suppobe we only remember that c1.ll A is B was proved,
that is, w.is apprehended 111 c1. particular instance, and so for
all B 1s C It 1s not enough to say I think of c1. particular A,
and imagme 1t B, tor that is not the Judgement any A must
be B which 1s required for the syllogism I remember that A1
as A was shown to be B. This 1s an c1pprehcnsion through
memory tllclt A1 db A tb B (viz. B1) S1mtlarly we have an
apprehcnb1on through memory thc1t B1 as B lb C Thus though
the nature of the apprehension is d1fterent, the general form 1s
the same as in the prccedmg case c1.nd can be treated in the
same way. Thus \\C agam have the syllogism as a universal
apprehended m J. purt1cular case. Lastly, suppose I am uncer-
tain whether A 1s B and whether B fr, C, yet I know that 1£
A is B and 1£ B 1s C, then A is C. I tlunk of a particular A,
viz. A1 • Now this means that I apprehend the nature of an
A as particular, while 1magmmg a particular (1f I am not
experiendng or remembcrmg an actual particular), and I appre•
hend the fact that 1£ a particular A, ab A1, were B, and if as
INFERENCE
B it were C, A1 would be C, wluch 1s apprehending also that any
A, if it were B, would be C, if all B is C.
1250. We can now determine more precisely the nature of
what is called the application of the untvcrsal to the particular,
a phrase by which the syllogism is sometimes characterized, and
whether or not this 1s ever an inference. We shall be able at
the same t1me to see what 1s the ground and excuse for the
difficulty m.ide about a petitio principii in the major premiss.
Suppose, as m the example given from Euclid, we prove m the
instance B1 that all B 1s C, which is equivalent to saymg that
we apprehend that B1 1s C because it 1s B. Suppose we apply
this, let us say, to a new mstance Ba If now m so doing we
fully apprehend that all B 1s C, that means we apprehend that
B1 as B is C, and this will be a repetition of the former proof.
lfore there 1s no mfercnce that this B ( = B11) 1s C from all B 1s C.
But now suppose we do not thus prove that B 1s C but remember
that we proved it ; we might express the process thus all B
was proved to be C, therefore tlus B ( = B2) is C. This reasoning
has the verbal form of an mfercnce. In proving that B was C
wc- proved rcaJly that any particular D was C, for we found
a particular B1 "ai, C, only because 1t was B, and in tlus we
recognized that any B was C. Thub th<' rewgmt1on that tlus
B ( = B2) is C, bccam,e 1t H, B, 1s no new act of apprehension
but 1s truly comprised m the previous apprehension. Now this
1:. the true (though not understood) ground of the feeling that
the maJor premiss really contams the conclusion, for however
the Judgement all B 1s C 1s got, 1t is felt to mean that any B
whatever, as B, 11, C. Now the feeling would be right 1£ B1 was
apprehended merely as a particularization of B, but this is not
the case. B8 1s apprehended as a particularization of another
umvcrsal A, so that B2 1s also A2 , and A2 m fact 1s 1dcnt1cal
with Ba, The recogmt10n of that 1s the mmor prem1ss. Now
the apprehension that any B, ai. B, 1s C, represented by the
major premiss all B 1s C, did not m any way contam the appre•
hens1on th.it any B 1s A, and so not the apprehension that A11
is B, and consequently not the apprehension that Az, as B, is C,
which 1s the conclusion. We thus come back to our former
solution,
§ 251. The first prmc1plcs of geometry arc ui:.u.i.lly divided
Principles and Method of Science 465
into definitions, axioms, and postulates ; the last appearing as
practical rules stating what constructions are allowed. Properly
speaking, however, the science of geometry as such is not con•
cerned with the practical construction of geometrical figures. 1
The real value of the postulates is that they represent an imper•
feet recogmtion of the necessity of constructions, that is, of
particular figures, either m experience or m imagmation. They
should then be a classification of various kinds of theoretic
construction. The classification as given 1s by no means ex•
haustive. It does not even exhaust the constructions m the
Elements of Euclid ; nor 1s this surpnsmg, since the classification
was made without any consciousness of its real significance.
But, though it might have been exhaustive of what 1s actually
found m the Elements, it could not possibly be complete for
geometrical science. The various kmds of construction only
become known in the solution of various problems and they
cannot possibly be anticipated beforehand Thus there is no
prov1S1on m Euclid's Elements for the various fam1har construe•
hons of conic sect10ns.
§ 252. Whether m geometry or elsewhere, axioms are usually
regarded either as simple mtu,it1ve truths and contrasted as such
with truths which are mferrcd ; or as not intuitive mdeed but
the result of an mductive process. This second view 1s artdic1al,
ansmg solely m the interest of a given theory. Even m the
second altcrnallvc, ho"'cver, they arc still considered to be
sunplc by contrast with the complexity of demonstrated truths
and not mferred by a process of demons tr atlon strictly so
called. We shall mamtam that the axioms are, on the one hand,
not the result of induction, and, on the other, are, though
certainly intuitive, not to be distmgu1shed from demonstrations
as these arc usually regarded The demonstrat1011s themselves
are all mtuitively apprehended, and 1£ they arc got by some
construcllvc process, so cire the a..""-1oms Every axiom is syn•
thetic and not a mere 1dcnt1ty Thus it contains d1fferent
clements whose conncx1011 1s apprehended, and this apprehen•
s1on takes place m a -construction. We must, that is, have
a particular :figure imagined or perceived, and the umversal
validity of the axiom is seen 111 the particular construction
' V1de Plato, llepubhc, Bk. VI, 510 D.
INFERENCtt
because we there see that the connexion apprehended is inde•
pendent of the part1culanty of the instance chosen. But this
is exactly the process that we h.1.vc described already for
demonstration The construction for an axiom 1s simple; in
demonstration 1t 1c; more complicated. The usual d1stmction
then between ,txtom" .md dcmonc;trat1ons 1s quite unreal ; the
act of thought 111 ,duch we .tpprchcnd an axiom or a demonslra·
tion 1-, cxartly the !>.tmc m kmd m both cases. Agam in
dcmonstr,1t1on, the '>Uccess1vc constructions arc all mtmtive and
may all be t crmed axiomatic ; the mference from one end of
a ,;enc& of con'ltruc-t10n'i to another 1,:; 1 "hen generalized, an
.1.x1om lt'l meamng, hov.cver, 1& rccogmzed only 111 these very
acts ot con,,trurtJon .
§ 253 In E111'!1d we find two kmd& of dcfimt1on. Both refer
to rc,thty, but one kmd '\11,C mc1.y call nommal as m some sense
g1v111g the meaning of c1. name without the construction necessary
to decide "hether any re.ti obJcct corresponds to 1t or not.
Thus the defttution.., of obtu.,c•, acute-, c1.nd right-angled triangles
.i.rc .t.l fir&t 110111111.tl, hung only Jtl',l1ficd when Euclid has proved
th1.t the t hn·e mtcnor angle.., of ,1 t n.1.ngle are together equal
to t\\o n~ht angle'> Tluo; restricts the number of right or
obtus<· c1.ngk!> to one ,tnrl allows ,l tri,mgle to contam three acute
,tngJ<'.,, Tlrn!> dcfiml1011 1.., of no u,;e ltll 1t 1.., Jtl';t1ficd by construe·
t10n, m other ,,ord-,, by dcmon'>tr,tt10n There 1,:; .t scLond kmd
"Inch t!> not nomm,tl . for ex,.unplc, the defimt1ons oi a tri.i.nglc
or ,t urdl', bt•c.tU'>l' \\C sec the poss1b1hty of those figures at
onLe, ,m<l \\t' m,1v think ,,c <lo tlus befon· conducting .i process
ol micrcnce, !>UCh a"> 1s ncccs5,tr) 111 the former kmds of dcfimt1on.
But the truth t!> tlMt \\C sec tlm poss1b1hty only by a particular
conslrul't1011, "l11ch a-.sures U!> m the ca,:;e of a triangle, c;ay, that
&p,tcc l .in be cndm,cd by three .111d not by two straight Imes.
So for the definition of a circle We see that the revolving•
pomt, at a hxed radius, must return to the same pos1t1on and
so form a closed figure It 1s the ,;1mpltc1ty of these constructions
"Inch c.im,es them to be overlooked, and thus the fah,e idea
hc1s ,mscn that a dehmt1on 1s merely the description of a 'con•
cept1on' (.1.11 expression which will hardly bear exammatlon) and
distinct from the acts of thought which involve proof. The
necessity for a con!>tructivc process becomes obvious in the
p,-i,nciples and Method of Science 467
definitions which we have called nominal, and this helps
us to see that there is construction involved in the simpler
cases also.
§ 254. In the empirical as compared with the mathematical
sciences we observe a very important difference in the position
of definition. In an empincc1.l science we cannot start from
a definition and advance from it as we appear to do 10 mathe-
matics. The diffcrcncc cannot be accounted for by the ordinary
theory of definition, which 1mphC!, more or less unconsciously
that defuut1on only describes the content of conceptions ; a view
which depends on a false dntlthcs1s, a wrong distinction between
obJects and conceptions As to tlus ant1thes1s 1t is supposed,
for example, thdt w1th10 limits we can make conceptions at will
and so make definitions It 1s c1.dm1tted that there are elements
which we c.mnot mdke 10 thought but must accept from experi•
ence; given these, we arc still supposed to have a freedom of
combmat1on. Dcfimt1011 thus gets a subJectJvc arbitrary
character and cannot be treated as somethmg from which we
can derive mformatlon about reality If this were 10deed &o,
we could not underi,tand the posit10n of definition in mathc•
mat1cs. Tlus conceptualist1c view depends upon a m1sunder•
standing which may be illustrated trom Mill's Logic. Mill th10ks,
as we have seen, that "e cc1.n make a dcfimt10n of a dragon,
that this like dll dcfimtrnrn, 1& merely nommc1.l, thc1.t 1L only
cxpresi,c1., the meamng of a name, \\ luch he 1.,omet1mes appears
to distinguish even from an idea. It turns out, however, that
there 1s somethmg behmd the name. He means that to 'dragon'
corresponds an idea or tonccptJon so mdependent of reality that
we do not believe that a correspondmg obJect can exist. He
then seems driven to cxplam why the procedure of mathematics
results m no mere 1magmary theorem<;, by supposmg that to
a mathematical defimt1on 1s .tddcd a postulate of the reality of
its object. But, more than this, Mill's expressions would commit
lum to the view not merely that no deduction ' affecting matters
of fact' 1s possible from the dcfimtJon but that no deduction
at all is possible from the definition unless the postulate is
added.1 That he docs not realize this is probably due to the
strange confusion by which he d1stmgu1shes the view of defini•
1
.Mlll, A System uf L~gic, I. Vlll, §§ 5-0.
INFERENCE
tion as a • statement and analysis of the mere meaning of a word•
from definition as • the statement and analysis of the content
of an idea '. What from his pomt of view could ' meaning ' be
but idea ? In the second book, \\ here he is discussing mathe-
mat1cc1.l demonstrc1.t1ons, he has to assume that deduction can
be made from the content of the idea itself apart from the
postulate. 1 The former doctrme, however, 1s obviously absurd,
for ckarly the poss1b1hty of deducmg anythmg from a conception
hes m the 'content' of the conception itself, and, supposmg the
content (ac; 1s presupposed) were somethmg different from reality,
the postulate of existence could m no way fac1htate the process
of deduction The only effect it could have would be that,
while the mfcrent1c1.l process proceeded from a conception, exactly
as 1£ no postulate had been made, we should merely add at the
end of every deduced conception the words ' and this conception
correspond!> to a real obJect' The existence therefore of a
postulate would not explam the peculiar proce!>s of mathematics.
Mill's account I!> a part of the old nustake that mathematical
mference 1'> ml'rcly formal, cons1stmg of syllog1stic deduction
from g1vc11 prenw,i;e!>. It 1s amusmg to observe that Mill thus
mvolves l11mself m a characteristic cont_rad1ct1on, for in the next
chapter, 10 order to meet some difficulty about ma.thematics, he
m..i.mtams that re.ii obJccts do not correspond to mathematical
defuutious, !>O that thl· po!>tulc1.tc after all 1s false and mere
hypothc~n, ll
§ 255. We have seen that m the e,a!>e of the dcfimt1on of
a dr,1gon it has been m,\intamcd that \\e can h.i.ve an 1magmary
conccpt1011 to \\lmh no real C'bJel·t corrl'sponds. To that we
ans\\ er firbt th.it these rnnu.:pt10n!> turn out on analysis not to
be conceptions at all Ill the strict sense They have clement!>
supposed to correspond to parts of reahty and in thmkmg of
them \\C v10latc no rule necessary to reality. The dragon's body,
for mst.i.ncc, els c:.\.tended m space 1s never thought of as v10latmg
a gl·omctrical prmc1ple. But the wmbmat1on of these clements
(hvmg tisl>UC and fire) 1s not really performed m thought and
1t 1s quite untrue that "e have combmed or can combme m
I 1d , II v, §\ 1-.Z
1 It l'i trul' that he trn:~ (um,uctt.'l>li!ully) to p,n e the w.i.y for t1u11 by
a change of front 111 llook I, , 111, § 6.
Princi.f,les and Method of Science 469
thought what we know or believe cannot be combined in
reality.
Secondly, if the theory is put in the form that we can conceive
objects which we know cannot exist, it is easy to show that this
is self-contradictory. We can only know that these elements
are not combinable by our knowledge of what these elements
are, that is to say, by our ' conceptions ' of them. It is the
conceptions, therefore, which have this incompatibibty, and that
JS cqmvalent to saying that we cannot combme these elements
m conception.
The question also 1s easily settled as a corollary of the account
already given of the meamng of conception as properly appre•
hension of reahty. 1
§ 256. In empirical science there appear to be two courses
open to us, m the matter of definition, if we assume certain
clements as apprehended 111 experience.
We might define an ob3ect either .ts combuung certain of
these clements, without refcrrmg to experience to sec whether
the combmat1on occurred, or as combmmg clements which we
have observed combmed. In the first alternative there could
be 110 security that something real corresponded to our definition.
Yet, if a not uncommon view of dcfimtJon m mathematics were
right, we could sec no reason why we should not construct
a body of hypothetical physical science with the same prec1S1on
.t!:> m geometry. But we know that this 1s not possible The
second alternal1ve, where we at least know that a real object
corresponds, seems tl).crefore preferable But though this 1s real
knowledge, Jt would not enable us any better to draw conclusions
from the defimt1ons The reason 1s one which ts common to
both defimtions. As we have seen, a conception 1s not com·
pleted when we have stated the clements of it and added merely
the demand that they arc to be combmcd. It JS obviously not
completed until we know that they are combmed. This ts the
position in empirical definition. Even when we apprehend m
experience certam clements, we do not sec how they arc com•
bmed. In geometry, on the other hand, we not only apprehend
the elements but also how they arc put together ; we understand
the nature of their umty and we realize 1t to ourselves in an act
I Put 11, 1.h 14, Cl>J,JCI.Jally p. 315.
470 INFERENCE
of construction in which the unity of the elements is as much
apprehended as the elements themselves. We know exactly
how they go together Now this 1s jUSt what we cannot do with
the elements of J.n empmcal dcfi111t1on. There 1s something in
language wluch corresponds lo this. In a. statement of what
an empmcal object 1s, \\C find attributes m general only unified
by their refcrenle tu the r:,amc bUbject ; they appear as so
m.my beparJ.lc ,idjccllvc~, CJ.ch atlJ.chcd mdcpende11tly to a sub·
stanl1ve-· Um, body 1s h,ud and round and sweet', &c. In
a mathematical dcfin1t1011, on the other hand, the words form
an orga.mc grc:1mm,itu. al umty and not a mere aggregate of
clements Jomed by 'and'. We <lo not say a triangle has three·
foldnc:.s and sides c.1.nd lb rcctibnear and encloses a space.
Knowmg how these clements arc put together, we express their
umty thu& : ,t lnangle 1s a three-sided rect1hnec1r closed figure,
or (better), c1. triangle has three re1..l1lmear sides wluch enclor:.e
a. r:.pa1..e. 1
~ 257.• Tlll' usu..11 theory 4 that lhc exact r:,uenceb stc1.rt from
defimt1ons of their obJectb, ass1g01ng them crrtam c1.ttnbutes,
and then derive other facts about the objects from these defini•
t1ous, involves a sharp <l1stmct1on Lclwccn the attributes com·
prised in the dchmt1on, and those • derived ' from them by
demom,trJ.l1on. Tlus d1stmct1011 1s connected with a technical
distmct1on of ci,i,cnle from property , essence l>emg the attributes
constituting the dcfuut1011 A further d1stmcl1on 1s to be made;
not everythmg which 1s necesl>1t.i.tcd by the essence 1s property
m the stncl techmcal sem,e. A property 1s a necessary attribute
wluch 1s derived from the cr,r,enrc alone .i.nd not from anything
else. Thus, 111 tn,mglc, that the mtcnor angles are together
equ.tl to t\\ o nght .inglcs 1s a property, because 1t 1s derived
from nothmg ebe th.in the essence m the defimt1on. But that
the exterior angles formed by producmg the sides successively 111
the same d1rectio11 arc cquc.1.l lo t.\\o nght angles, though necesi,ary
to J. triangle, 1s not a property, because 1t follow& from some·
llung lesi, th,m the whole essence and 1s true of every rectilinear
1
U § z59 ad tin • Cf. §§ 17 3-4
r• Wilson alway~ maintamed that a direct proof of all theorems 111 possible.
11ua does not appear to be the case , see, for example-, Euchd, El.,,,mls, 11i, 1
(Heath, 1 c , vol. ii, p. 8), Wilson spent great energy over the attempted
conversion an the last part of tlus section. It IS clear from his manu9Cnpt
that he was not satisfied with the result reached in the text ]
2773°2 F
INFERENCE
the given property of the opposite angles bemg equal to two
right angles, and this 1s contrary to \\< hat was proved in the
original theorem In some cases then we fi.nd that we can make
a proof of A from B independently of the proof of B from A,
and that we can also have another proof m which we make the
demonstration of A from B depend upon and presuppose the
demonstr.1t1on of B from A But now let ui. take the proposition
that the 111ter1or ,tnglcs of a triangle are together equal to two
right angll!s and attempt to prove the converse, which 1s true.
We shall hnd that "e presuppo,;;c that there is such a figure as
a triangle and that we do not start from the mere conception
of a closed figure v. hose mtenor angles arc equal to two right.
.J.ngles For, 1f "c undertake the construction necessary to
vindicate that conception, we fi.nd we presuppose the possib1hty
of three straight Imes enclosing a space Any use of the axiom
of parallels involves this, because the axiom presupposes the
construction of a triangle What 1s the reason of this ? The
relation of the magmtude of the .ingles to the sules of a figure
{1f we do not introduce the cond1tion that the fi.gure 1s closed)
remains mdetermin.itc unless we hke to admit the hm1tat1on
that any one angle cannot exceed two right angles Thus, if
we fuc the magnitude of the sum of the angles of the figure
(estm1atcd on what might be called one ' side ' of the figure) to
be two nght angles, we shall detennme neither the number of
the sides nor v.hether the figure 1s dosed or not What effects
the determination 1s the closing of the figure ; that 1t 1s which
determmes the relations of the angles , that is, the various
determmat1ons of that closmg c1re due to the determination of
the magnitude of the mterior angles. It 1s on this account that
we find ourselves compelled to start from the determmatlon of
the closedness m respect to the number of sides.
§ 200 The science of pure quantity, though so abstract,
depends as much as geometry on a perception or 1magmat1on
of particular md1v1duals To prove the elementary propositions
which are the l>.is1s of this soence we do not thmk merely of
numbers in gcner .J.l but \\ e must represent defimte groups of
numbered tlungs For the theorems m ar1thmet1c we must count
definite md1v1dual instances, and for more general theorems, as
in algebra, ,, here we consider not merely the sums or multiples
Principles anti M ethotl of Science 4n
of definite numbers but sums and multiples in general, we still
require groups of units which are of definite number, though in
our argument we do not take into account the precise number
which they have. Our results are universal here as in geometry
because we see that they do not depend on the particularity
of the instances. Our attitude is the same as in geometry ; in
the individual instances which we construct empirically we see
the universality of the results. The latter are self-evident and
we never tlunk of appealmg for confirmation to new particular
mstances.
§ 261. In the case of the science of pure quantity the procedure
above described 1s supplemented by another process, that of
symbolic representation and symbolic operation, so that whereas
we start with defimte quantities and operate upon these, when
symbols are used we seem to operate on symbols. This is the
difference between algebra with its kmdred sciences and the
direct procedure of pure geometry, and requires special con·
sideration. Clearly nothmg can be effected through mere symbols
taken by themselves ; they depend always for their use on our
power of constructing or apprehendmg what they symbolize,
and thus we might mclme to underrate their importance, thinking
of them as a convenience rather than a necessity. But in truth
symbolism 1s the necessary rnstrument of the sciences to which
1t belongs and great advances are made by the discovery of new
symbols for new problems The first purpose of symbols m
algebra 1s to d1st111guish various quantities from one another as
merely distmct. quant1llcs without defimtc number. It ts 1mpos•
stble for us to work with the mere abstract notions of quantities,
conceived as merely different from one another, without some
perceptive or imaginative units representing them and so enablmg
us to keep them distinct and in our memory Such perceptive
units are supplied m algebra by the letters of the alphabet. By
their difference m form they represent the difference of the
abstract quantities and, as they are made to differ m a way
easily recognizable, they are not confused with one another.
Thus we remember what quantity had what operations per•
formed upon it. Secondly, a most important function of sym•
bolism 1s to represent conveniently not only the quantities but
the nature of the operation performed. They serve here the
F2
INFERENCE
important purpose of helping the memory and enabling us to
hold together with certainty a great variety of mental construe·
tions and operations which we should otherwise inevitably forget
or confuse Thus they render possible a train of argument
which would be quite impossible without them. Generally
speaking, any symbols will do, 1f sufficiently distinct in form ;
those being most suitable which, while simple, are sufficiently
distinct to prevent confusion A good deal again depends upon
convenience m wntmg or printing and representation to the
eye. If we must appeal to the touch, as "1th the bhnd, that
may produce a very important difference m the nature of the
symbols. Thirdly, the symbolism it5clf serves 111 a remarkable
manner to save the effort of the several mental constructions
which are necessary, because to each construction correspond
certain definite changes m the symbolism These changes are
easily remembered as valid, without the necessity each time of
going through the actual proce'>ses of thinking which make them
valid. Thus a rhfficult tram of argument is reduced in great
part to a number of merely mechanical chang<'s m our symbols
which we perform by rote, not apprehendmg their validity each
tim<' but rcmembermg that a proof has been given which estab•
lishes it 1 However, mcchamcal as tl11s process may seem, it
depends for its worth on the possibility of our making those
mental constructions,\ luch the chang<'s 111 the c;ymbols represent.
Fm,llly, the proc-c<;o;e<; thu,; symbolucd ,ire real constructions and
never have a merely an.ilyt1c.il character. They represent, even
the simplest of them, '>ynthct1c Judgements so called.
1
Compare what \\a& "aid m § 247 on the u~e of 1ememberecl theorems in
geometry,
[• § 263 to end of the chapter was never revised, nor apparently properly
reconsidered j
INFERENCE
comparison of a fact not got by inference with one derived from
the same fact by inference.
f 264. The judgement of inferiority arises in the case of
particular facts apprehended m experience, where inference
implies a kmd of knowledge different from that by which the same
facts are directly apprehended. The completest apprehension
of a particular fact m the present 1s perception ; the completest
apprehension of 1t as a past fact 1s our memory of the perception.
When we mfcr to a fact which belongs either to past or present,
though we 1magme at, we yet have not this completer kind of appre•
hens1on J Ierc abo our inference can at most be only probable,
based as 1t must be on particular observations about which we
cannot be certain; so that 1t does not constitute an apprehension
of the fact at all I may mfer, for instance, that another person
has a sensation of a certam kind ; but my mference is not
ccrtam \\htlc lus perceptive knowledge is certain.1 Agam, the
exact character of tus sensation he apprehends while I cannot
pos!>ihly apprehend it Here I am shut off from the only com•
pletc knowlcdg<', \\hu.h 1,; perception.
This uncertamt y, while often passed over in ordinary hfc-
so much so that we treat the highly probable as 1£ 1t were
certam-ic; yet forced upon us m cases of extreme practical
importc1.nc<', notably m \\ hat 1s called c1rrumstanhal evidence
m cnmmal trials Herc we become aware of the fact that our
most careful deductions from what 1s given m experience cannot
be equwalent to the Judg('ment of an eyewitness. In the sciences
again, surprise<; about opm10ns and theories wluch rested on
strong empmcal c, 1dcncc arc not mfrequcnt.
§ 265 In the dcmomtrattye sciences, whether or not inferred
knowledge t!> thought of c\!> mdcpcndent or md1rect, its certainty
1s not depreciated, but rlc<'m<'d equal to that of the premisses
themseh es. Here we arc not trying to apprehend particular
facts as particular facts, we are concerned only with the con•
nCX1on of umversals Yet the difference is not that there 1s no
consideration of universals m the former cases. We have already
tried to show 2 that 1t is only through universals that any
inference can be made, and this truth may be verified in any
instance whatever The distinction is that in these demon•
1 Compare what wa::, ::,d1d in ~ zo9
Injef'ence and Ifltfltelliau Apprehension 483
strative sciences we are not concerned with the nature of any
particular as that particular ; not therefore with singular judge-
ments but with the connexion of universals, and therefore only
with universal judgements.
Now the apprehension of the universal in this connexion
cannot be perception at all, though 1t takes place in perception
or imagination. And so we have not here the contrast of appre•
hending, or trying to apprehend, the same thing in two ways
which are so different m kmd as perception and a thinking
process which is not perception. And when we examined the
nature of geometrical argument we saw that all the apprehen·
s1ons, both of the premisses and of what they necessitate
inferentially, came m the same way, namely, in a geometrical
construction. Accordmgly what was apprehended as neces•
s1tated by a prem1ss or premisses was as certain as lhe premiss
or prem1sses apprehended That is why in geometry we do not
have the oppos1t1on of inferred knowledge to what 1s not inferred,
as of less certain to cerlam. The question before us therefore
concerns the dependence and mdirectness of mfcrred knowledge
and the sense m which these terms are rightly or wrongly
applied. Further, supposing the same fact to be apprehended
without mference, the question is whether there is any reason
for preferrmg the one kmd of apprehension to the other.
§ 266. We have mamtamed that mfcrence depends upon the
obJective fact that one element of reality, simple or complex,
may necessitate another d1stmgu1shablc from it, and we have
considered inference to be always the apprehens10n of one fact
as necessitated by another, though not assertmg that every such
apprehension 1s accounted an mfercnce m thll ordmary use of
language. The characteristic of the cases which arc not called
inference is lhat in them a relation between two elements of
reality is apprehended immediately from our expcricncc of them,
not by the help of rclatmg them to something else ; that is,
not by the help of additional knowledge consisting m the appre•
hension of their relation to somethmg else. But we shall see
that the converse 1s not true m the ordmary usage ; for not
every such apprehension is accounted non-inferential. Again,
if two distinguishable judgements necessitate a third; if, that is,
we apprehend that the two different facts apprehended in the
INFERENCE
two different judgements necessitate something else, this appre-
hension is usually accounted an mference. But to this also we
shall see there may be exceptions
Suppose we know one tlung as A and another as B and from
this do not see the relation r 3 bet\\een them. Suppose that,
when we gel the additional knowledge that A stands m a rela-
tion r 1 to M (Ar1M) and B m a relation r1 to M (Br1M), we see
that this of itself necesc;1tates that A stands m the relation r 8 to
B (Ar3 B) Tim \\ould be called an inference on both of the
above grounds, both because of the relation of A and B to the
third thmg and because of the two Judgements necess1tatmg
a third.
Here the fact Ar1M and Br2M, as a complex, necessitates
without anylhmg further (ex hypothesi) the fact Ar8B, and the
apprehension of tlus complex Ar1Mr 2B 1s enough (ex hypothesi)
to give at once the apprehension Ar3B. There 1s no md1rectness
or med1atenec;o; c1ther 111 the rclat 1011 of nece&c;1tat1on or m the
connexion of our knowledge of thl' one with our kno,\ledge of
the other ta pomt ,, h1ch has already bcen m:.untamed).
As to the dependence, ,ve have seen that m the mathematical
sciences the neccc;s1t,1t1on 1s reciprocal Tlus 1s evident enough
Ill a non·lemporal wnsequence, and \\e have &een thc1t m general,
when "e take the true cond1t1on, the existence of the cond1t1oned
necessitates that of the rond1tion Yet there may seem to be
m a true sense a certain dependence of an effect m time on
previous cond1t1ons bec,tuse they exist fin,t But an event and
its temporal cond1t1ons J.re part1culanzat10ns of umversals
(called, some of them at least, m such reference ' laws') whose
nature 1& not somet hmg wluch hJ.ppens m lime and whose con-
11ex1on also 1s somethmg non-temporal The propm,1ttons m
science concern these u111versab and their connexions. For
a scientdic propos1t1on 1s that surh and such a temporal con-
d1bon C has such a,id such an effect E, and \\C have seen that,
1£ C is the true cond1t1on, the umversal E necessitates the
umversal C Thus we can say briefly that 1£ X, as the true
cond1t1on, necessitates Y, whether temporally or not, neither
fact 1s mdependent of the other, for neither fact can exist save
in 1ts relation to the other There 1s, however, a dependence
of one of our apprehensions on .i.nother, 1£ we only know the
Infe,ence and Immedt.tde Apprehension .Ss
fact Y by knowing first the fact X and seeing that it necGSsitates
Y, and if we are not, at least at the time, able to apprehend Y
in any way which is independent of our apprehension of X.1 •
Whereas there is m one way a directness in our apprehension
of Ar8 B, as necessitated by Ar1Mr1B, there is in another sense
an indirectness, because the relation of A to B 1s not apprehended
by considering A and B alone, but by comparing each of them
with M.
Now, first, 1s the knowledge of the relation of A to B, when
derived from the apprehension of A and B alone, to be regarded
as direct and non-mfcrcnt1al ?
Secondly, 1£ Ar3 B 1s not derived from the conceptions of A and
B alone, but only by apprehending their relation to a third thing,
1s that knowledge always to be called md1rect and inferential ?
Neither principle 1s stnctly observed m practice.
In Euclid, Elements, i 4, the two triangles arc not related to
a third, but the process 1s undoubtedly looked on as inferential
and as a demonstration. But the truth 1s tlus · the magnitudes
compared, m tlus instance the bases of the triangles and the angles
at their bases, are produced by a construction wluch 1s one and
the same for both and can only yield one length for the lines
and one size for the angles. Consequently the magnitude must
be the same m the case of both triangles The relation between
the two tnanglcs 1s therefore got m the most direct manner
possible, got, that ts, from what we know of them, which is their
construction. The so-called demonstration by the application
of one triangle to the other 1s only a way of putting this (and
1s not always applicable m the case of sphencal tnangles).
Here, then, ,,c
have a case v.hcrc the immediate necessitation
of one fact by another 1s accounted an inference ; or, more
accurately, the apprehension that A and B stand in a relation
r 1s seen directly from A and B without reference to a third
somethmg and 1s yet c1.ccounted an mferencc.
This, however, 1s not done consciously, and so we cannot say
that the prmc1ple which we mamtam to be the ground of all
inference-viz. that one fact necessitates another different from
it-would always be held to make an apprehension an inference.
1 As e.g 1n Euclid, 1. 35. See below, p. 487.
L• • Expand th11,' .US. not,.]
INFERENCE
In ibe other case we might anticipate no exception. But
pouibly what "l\'e know of A and B may necessarily contain
a relation to M, and this may be inseparable from A and B in
our apprehension, i.e neither A nor B may be definable at all
without the relation, or, mother words, A as such may be Ar1M,
and B as such Br1M Now suppose 1t to be a consequence of
these relations to M that A stands in a relation r3 to B. Since
this, though 1t has the verbal form of what 1s called indirect or
inferential knowledge, is after all got immediately from the
knowledge "e have of A and B, can 1t rightly be called indirect
and inferential ~
In pr.l<:lice we find that 1t sometimes 1s and sometimes is not.
Thus in Euclid, Elements, 1. 1, AC and BC are only known as
each constructed cq ual to AB. Y ct we find that their consequent
equality to one another 1s looked on as an mfcrence. On the
other hand 1t 1s assumed "1thout proof m geometry m general 1
that the diagonals of a four-sided ' convex ' rcct1lme<tl figure
cut one another within the figure. Now each d1.tgonal 1s entirely
deternuned by 1t5, rdat1on to the given four-sided figure and can
only be apprehendt'd m that relation. Their mtersection a is
the immediate consc·quc·nre of this rcl.tt10n. Herc the propos1•
hon 1s taken as self-evident and not treated ,lb ,m mference
What is d1shnct1ve of such cases 1s that we do not ..tpprehend
A ab A and also as ArM W c can apprehend A only as ArM,
bccclu,;c objcct1vdy A lb only <h·fmcd a:. ArM And similarly
for B. The pos1t1011 ,rnd length of t hl- d1agonal, "h1rh are
required for its dcfuullon, arc only clctcrmmcd by 1b, bemg
,\ d1~1gonal, 1 t•, hy 1h Jommg t\\O oppo-,1tc angles of the quadn-
1.itcral S11111l,irly the hnc._ AC ,ind BC of Eurhd, i. 1, arc, as
we s.iw, constructed only ,is equal to AB. ln c.ises such ,ls
t hcse, then, the• kno\\ ledge must be c.i.lled dirert, for obviously
in the n.tt ure of the tlung there could not be any knowledge
more direct b
Herc an important d1stinctlon has to be made. Suppose that
' See e g Euch<l, ble111e11t~. 1v, 9, where the diagonals of a square are
assumed to cut one another w1tlu11 the square
[• The notion that the propo!i1t10111> arc connected by ,elation came into
common use from Kant Cf note to § 98 J
Simple and Comf,la I leas 497
§ 274. In the true hypothetical statement there is a kind of
paradox. It relates to something the reality of which is uncer•
tain and yet something definite 1s said about it-definite and
positive, not merely negative, for instance, not merely the
definite statement that 1t 1s uncertrun.
This uncertain something is the hypothetical element in the
hypothetical statement, and we must investigate its precise
nature. With the idea of the hypothetical we do not connect
merely uncertainty. To be uncertain about a. thing is not to
treat it as an hypothesis, nor as the hypothetical part of an hypo•
thetical statement. There 1s something apparently more positive
than mere uncertainty. Whether rightly or not, we often think
of the positive side as consisting in some fiction of ours. (Fiction
here is taken m the sense of conscious fiction, and not of an
unconscious mistake. A 'fictitious idea' sometimes means a
mistaken idea.) Or again 1t may be said that the hypothetical
element is a mere idea of ours, which really comes to the same
thmg.
Without analysing for the present (though 1t greatly needs
analysis) the idea of fiction, we can see that the hypothetical
element m a statement cannot be wholly fictitious and cannot
be merely uncertain. It must contain somcthmg known to be
real and something about which we are certain.
§ 275 If we examine any hypothetical propositions we make
m ordmary life or m science, as d1stmguished from phtlosophic
reflection, we find them to be of the type '1f A 1s B, C 1s D'
where A, B, C, and D are none of them regarded as fictions but
as realities. It would not even be correct to say that A, B, C,
and D are 'concepllons' , but, even 1f we do call them con•
ceptions, they arc supposed to be conceptions of realities and
so not fictitious. If there ts supposed to be any fiction in such
statements, 1t would probably be said that '1f A 1s B' represents
or is something fictitious, or mere idea , or that the hypothesis
that A is B (or the hypothetical case of A's bemg B) 1s a fiction.
But the important thmg 1s that A, B, C, and D are not thought
of as fictions.
It is, however, a current doctrine of popular philosophy that
the mind has a power of constructing fictions which are not
hypotheses in the above sense. It 1s supposed that the mmd
INFERENCE
cannot makt simple ideas, but that it can arbitranly makt
complex ones, because it can arbitrarily combine simple ones
into complex. This doctrine quite ignores a consideration which
should lead to c1. re-exammation of 1L and, mdeed, to its rejection,
that idea:, m.iy Just ab much be impossible to (..Ombine as to
make. We (.,.,innot, for mstancc, make the complex idea of
a closed rccl1lmc..1r 1igurc wluch hcts three s1del> .ind only two
interior ,.mgle&. If the dm,lrme ,,ere true 1l would imply that
we nught hJ.vc, m a st.itement, au clement AB (.is m '.ill AB
1s <.: ', or, •1f AB 1::, C, 1t 1s lJ '), which w.is a fictitious idea or
conception, beside:, &uch fiction as may be supposed to consist
m au hypothes1& If &o, the form of ,m hypothetical statement
would not necessarily be of the type '1£ A 1s B, C 1s D ', where
not one of the clements A, B, C, .ind D 1s a fiction. We have
therefore to consider" helher there really can be fictitious com·
plcx 1dc..1,; Tiu:, ag,un suggc:,t& the question, whether there can
be ,my 1it.L1t10uo:; &nnplc idem,
But the usual d1:,tmct1on bet" cen simple and complex 1dec1.&
1s not clear; indeed 11 1s o;ometlmcs confused and contradictory.
As a prehmmary therefore we must first discuss the distinction
itself.
§ 276. The locus classicus for the d1slmcl1on of •snnple' and
'complex· 1dec1s 1s Locke's Essay, Bk. 11, especially Chaps. 1i
c1.nd xu.
The ideas peculiar Lo e.it h of the five senses he calls simple,
Tac;tes (sweet, sour), Sounds (loud, Jo"), Sn1clls (sweet, stmkmg),
Colours (white), Touch (h..ird, sott, hot, cold). There are others
which we shall return lo presently, but those named arc such
as we should naturally takt' to be simple ideas, 1£ any are simple.
But this common-sense v1c\\ 1s threatened by a consideration
wluch had not occurred to Locke and 1s fam1har m modern
philosophy. The apprehension of red as a d1stmct colour,
different, say, from white and different from a sound, necessarily
involves the d1stmction of it from other colours and other objects
of the sensitive consciousness. The rccogn1t1on or apprehension
of •,-,d' as a d1stmct and definite colour 1s only possible for
a consciousness which has other objects to compare 1t with.
Thus every such 1dea as red, hot, sweet, loud, necessarily involves
a plurality to which it 1s related. Hence, if the involving thus
Simple and Complex I tleas
of a plurality made an idea complex, these simple ideas of
Locke's, which correspond to the objects peculiar to the five
senses, would all be complex.
Whether this is a real obJection to the distinction or not (and
we shall see that it is not), it docs hold against Locke's presenta•
t1on of 1t, and he can be sho\\ n to contradict it himself.
All ideas of relation he makes complex. So of course 'equal',
'greater', .i.nd 'less'. This, as his own language shows, is because
.i. relation involves the different obJects bet\\ ecn \\ hich it obtams
and thus mvolves a plurality 'The second (of the acts of the
mind wherein 1t exerts its po" er over its simple ideas) is bringing
two ideas, whether simple or complex, together and setting them
by one another so as to take a view of them at once, without
uniting them mto one ; by which way 1l gets all its ideas of
relations.' 1 It 1s clearly the presence of the t" o ideas thus
compared which makes Locke call the corresponding idea of
relation complex. He expresses hunsclf mdeed rather con•
f usedly : for the first of those acts of the mind is 'combining
several simple ideas mto one compound one and thus all complex
ideas are made' ; 2 whence of course the relations ought not to
be complex ! Yet elsewhere he says d1stmctly that relations arc
complex ideas.3 His account of the formation of the idea of
relation 1s obviously confused At .ill events he thus 1mplicitly
admits that an 1dra 1s complex 1f 1t involves a plurality of ideas
compared. He therefore contradicts himself, for the ideas of
red, &c., as we have seen, also involve a plurality.
The same thing results from his account of modes, and here
he cxpltc1tly contradicts him'>elf Thus he says that modes,
which include both 'simple' and •mixed' modes,' are complex
ideas; they arc 'such complex ideas wluch, however com·
pounded, contam not m them the supposition of subsisting by
themselves but arc considered as dependencies on, or affections
of, substances' 11 ( e g. triangle). That 1s because a mode as an
attribute of substance involves the reference to the substance,
the 'complex' clearly being itself and the substance (accordmg
1 Essay, II. Xll, § 1. • 1b
I 1b II. Xll, § 3 • 1b. II. Xll, §§ 3, 4
• ib. II xu, § 4 , cf xm, §§ I seq , ' 1111xed ' or ' compounded ' modes are
a species of the complex ideas called modes.
.500 INFERENCE
to Locke's way of thinking, that is, for he probably doesn't
think of its relation to its substance as an element in the com•
plex). Here again the unplymg of a plurality makes the idea
complex for Locke and he 1s involved in 1mplmt contradiction.
But the contradiction 1s also explicit because what he has called
simple ideas must have precisely this kind of plurality. Properly
speaking, colour must be a mode and therefore complex ; for
colour is the colour of an extended surface and so not 'subsisting
by itself'. Ile would, however, probably answer that colour is
not this but a mere sensation hke heat At least he would have
to admit, then, that no sensation can subsist of itself, but is an
'affection' of ourselves, 1 c affection of our spiritual substance.
He expressly makes solidity a simple idea ; but it does not
exist by itself . 1t 1s exactly an aff ect1on of a substance.1 There
are other explicit contrad1ct10ns, for he makes •succession' a.
simple idea, but 'succession' 1s obviously an idea. of relation
and therefore.-, accordmg to himself, should be a complex idea.
Again, •po,,cr' 1s a •sunple idea' ; 3 yet obviously it involves
relation and thmgs related, a.s much a.s any of what Locke calls
ideas of relation. It should therefore be an idea of relation and
•~omplcx'. Moreover, po,,cr, as an 'affection of substance'
and not subs1stmg by 1tscl!, should be a simple mode, if a sunple
anything, and therefore a complex idea 'Umty' 3 1s also a simple
idea, but umty 1s 'umty OF', and so m1phes plurahly.
§ 277. The reason of Locke's confusion 1s that he didn't see
the ncccss1ly of dctermmmg clearly whal he meant by s1mphc1ty
and complexity. Ile unconsciously used these distinctions some-
times m one sense, sometimes 111 ,mother.
By a complex 111 general 1s meant something which consists
in a unified mamfold, or m a umty of a. manifold or plurality.
But cverytlung depends on the kmd of plurality. We do not
as a rule mean that a thmg 1s a complex because it necessitates,
involves, or 1s connected "1th a plurality from which 1t can be
distinguished, but because 1t itself consists of a plurality which
1s umfied. Thus from complexity 111 a thing 1s excluded the
necessitation of plurality other than and distinguishable from
itself. (Examples will make this clear.) Locke's mistake is that
1
Essay, II w, § 1, where 1t is a. mode and therofore a. complex 1doa..
1
1b , II vu, §§ 1-8 a 1b., II vu, § 1.
Simple and Com1'J,x Ideas 501
he takes the latter for complexity, and hence relations and modes
are with him complex.
But sometimes he thinks of complexity in the true sense and
so makes succession, for example, though a relat1on, simple.
Power again, though both relation and mode (it never occurs
to Locke that a relation may be a mode), is also for him simple.
An example will make the issue plain. Consider equality.
Equality is a relation. It is complex, according to Locke,
because it is a relation between two magnitudes. It is certamly
true that in itself 1t 11eccss1tates two magnitudes and therefore
a plurality. But 1f equality itself 1s a complex, 1t must be
a unity of different elements m itself What makes it a complex
or plurality must be the plurality of elements or members which
constitute it. The two magmtudes, then, as making it a com•
plex, must be elements m 1t and it must be their unity, in the
sense of the whole system which they constitute. But the two
magnitudes are not parts or elements of the relation of equality
between them. A solid, we can say, consists as a complex of
surface and volume ; we cannot say c-quahty •consists' of the
two magnitudes which arc equals. The two magnitudes, as
1,tandmg m the relation of equality to one another (or in any
other relation), arc thereby umfied mto a system, i.e. a complex.
That is true enough. TIHS system 'consists' of the two magni-
tudes ; but this umficat1on of the two, i.e. this system which
they constitute, is obviously not their equahty. The plurality
of clements which makes a lhmg complex must be such that
those elements m their umty-of whatever kmd-are the thing
in question.
Thus, if the plurality of the two magmtudcs made their
equality complex, the two magnitudes m their unity must be
(or constitute) the relation of equality between them, wluch is
obviously absurd. The relation of equality, then, unifies them
but is not itself the umty of them, m the proper sense of 'unity
of them', 1.e. a umty of which they are elements, the magnitudes
themselves as unified.
The phrase •umty of' is ambiguous. That wluch gives a
plurality unity and systematizes 1t produces a system which is
a unity of the plurality, but the principle which gives it unity
is not itself the unified system ; it 1s distinguishable from it.
5oz INFERENCE
The children of the same parents are unified into a group, called
brothers and sisters, by their relation to the same pair of parents.
They form a umty of which they are the members ; but that
unity is not the relation v. luch unified them. They are members
of the family group, not members of their relation to their
parents
A complex 1r:, nol d1stmgu1shable from, and other than, the
totality of 1tr:. members So, ,my plurality from which it can
be d1stmgmshcd cannot be of members of itself, and so cannot
mdke 1t .i. comple:x But equality 1s obviously distinguishable
from and other th.i.n the magnitudes between which 1t obtams,
and so their plurality does not constitute 1t a plurality. Hence
equality is not mcide a complex for the reason which Locke
gives, and this applies, generally, to any other •idea of relation'
whatever.
We have then to ask whether equality in itself as distinct
from the plurc1ltty of the equc:tl magnitudes 1s a unity of elements.
If we take 1t 'm itself' 1t seems clear that "e cannot make it
a complex "luch 1s a umty of members; we could not assign
any members the umty of which constitute!> or makes up
equality. It 1s m this sense, therefore, simple. A sign of this
is that equality" ill not yield a complex attributive or a plurality
of attributives, as every true complex idea should. We say
of the magnitudes of two bodies that they are equal, and
the attributive 1s simple and will not yield several attribu-
tives. But 'ammal • yields both bvmg orgamsm and sentient
organism
It is because succession shows no such complexity within
itself, has no members, that Locke cc:tlls it simple. If consistent,
he would have seen that relation as such 1s not necessarily
complex.
§ 278. But there 1s another kmd of plurality or manifoldness
in 'ideas' which 1t is not natural to call 'complexity'.
Consider the particular red colour of tlus object. This is an
individualization of the species red colour, which again is a
differentiation of the genus colour. The genus is d1stingu1shable
from its differentia, and the species as umversal from the
individual. Hence there is plurality, whether red means the
species red colour in general or thlS red colour. This plurality,
Simple and Complex I fleas
however, is not one of what could be called elements or I members'
of some colour, while 'colour' and 'red colour' are not elements
of or members of this red colour.
Thus the equality of these two magnitudes is a particular case
of equality, which is a species of relation of magnitude, which
again is a species of the genus relation. Relation is then
differentiated into relation of magnitude, and this again into
relation of equality of magnitude.
Now in equality agam, the elements, relation in general,
relation of magnitude m general, and relation of equality of
magnitude, are not naturally called members ; the genus 'rela•
tion' is not a member of a relation of magmtude, nor are these
(i.e. 'relation' and 'relation of magmtude ') members of the
relation of equality of magnitude.
It is therefore also not natural to call 'the relation of equality
of magmtude' complex For the clements of a complex are
'members'. Members arc normally understood not as different
JO degree of umversahty, but as co-ordinate either as universals,
and of the same degree of umversahty, or as individuals.
Hence, whlle relation and relation of magnitude are not
members of that relation of magnitude which 1s equality, a
relation of magnitude m general and a relation of weight in
general are, as classes, members of the genus relation. The
species, equilateral, scalene, and isosceles triangle, are members
of the genus, but, even so, not of the genus or abstract universal
present JO them, but members of the group of classes which
constitute the whole of the species of the genus.
A complex is conceived as a unity of members which are
co-ordinate in universality, so that each member 1s a part of
the whole in the sense at least that the whole contains something
besides itself.
Now colour is not a member of red colour, for red colour is
not a whole of which colour is a part JO the sense that red
contains something besides colour. On the contrary, red con•
tains nothing except colour. Colour comprises everything in it.
Red is not colour together with something which is not colour.
In equilateral triangular figure, figure is not a member of equi-
lateral triangular figure as a complex. For everything in the
equilateral triangle comes under figure : it is altogether figure,
INFERENCE
and not figure together with something which is not figure. Nor
is triangle a member of equilateral triangle, for equilateral
triangle is altogether triangle, not tdangle and something else
besides triangle.
The plurality of manifoldness in red colour due to the distinc•
tion of genus and species in 1t 1s not such a manifold or plurality
as can make 1t a complex.
In this way, then, 1 e. in the accurate sense of 'complex',
equilateral three-,;idcd figure is not a complex idea, and, 1£ simple
means that which is not complex, what 1s not a unified system
of members, 1t is certainly simple If, however, we mean by
simple that in the nature of which no plurality is present, and
that which, if related to a plurality, 1s d1stingmshable therefrom,
then red and triangle are not simple. For red m itself has colour
and a d1fferentiat1on 'red', and tnanglc in itself involves the
plurality of figure and three-sided · ' m itself' because red in
itself is colour and can't be distinguished from colour, as some·
thing not colour, any more than three from number, whereas
surface can be d1st111gu1shed from volume as something not
volume. 1
On the other hand, the universal has plurality inherent in
itself, because 1t 1c; its nature to be necessarily chfferenilated into
species. It 1s not some one l111ng present m all the species along
with something else, viz a d1fferentia, constitutmg with 1t the
species. The d1fferent1a 1s entirely mcluded m the universal.
But this plurality 1s nevertheless not romplcx1ty. A universal
may have true comple'C1ty, 1£ 1t comprises elements which are
not differentiation!:. of one another. In the general idea of a 'red
and transparent body', redness and transparcncc are not related
as genus and species. Thus Locke's examples of equality and
succession are not complex but have this manifoldness of genus
and species. ' Equal in magmtudc and heavier in weight ' would
be a proper instance of a complex relation.
§ 279. There is a danger in some cases of putting complexity
into an 'idea' (so called) which relates to a complex, when the
[
4
The author wrote, ' Locke's callmg this a mixed mode amounts to
111akmg 1t complex '. See the passages m the foot-note. Locke calls numbers
simple modes, but all modes "" complex ideas. Three 1s called complex
because 1t ,s reac:hed by repeating the simple idea of unity (cf.§ 282),l
INFERENCE
nature of these three lines, as bounding this particular piece of
plane surface. The fact that they form a three-sided figure is
only an aspect of their nature, not the whole of it. They are
therefore not members of their triangularity. The same is true
for triangularity in general. Triangularity in general does not
consist of three Imes.
§ 280. Tlle foregoing distinction is not that between a complex
and the idea of a complex. Our idea of anything is our idea
of what it 1s m 1tsclf : 1t 1s what we think of it considered as
thought by us ; and what we think of it is what we know or
conJecture it to be. In the first case, then, our idea of a thing
is simply our apprehension of its nature or a part of its nature.
It is not an imaginary picture of the thing-'1dea' in that sense
-for that 1s not what we think the thmg 1s, nor 1s it the thinking
what the thmg 1s. In the second case, our idea of the thing is
our conJecture of what its nature really 1s. This, though helped
by imagination, is neither the mental image nor the imagining
of it.
We are here conrerned with the firc;t sense of idea of a thing
as our apprehension of its nature or of a part of its nature.
Our idea of a complex like the triangle or set of three is then
simply our apprehension of it. Our apprehension of a complex
involves apprehensions of the members of the complex and so
may be, m this sense, called complex apprehension.
In the case of the triangle we have distinguished between the
complex triangle and its attribute of triangularity. So we dis-
tinguish now between the idea of the complex (the triangle or
set of three), and lhe idea of its attribute (tnangulanty or threc-
ness) ; that is, between our apprehension (as subjective) of this
set of three and our apprehension of its threencss.
The distmction then of this three from its threeness is an
obJective distinction in the obJect apprehended, and not a dis•
tinction between something subjective (our apprehension of it)
and somethmg obJective (the object's nature), and is parallel to
a subjective distinction in the corresponding apprehensions.
§ 281. We have excluded from complexity the plurality of
genus and differentia in the species. This is not, however,
because the species necessitates the genus of which it must be
the determination. Elements in a manifold may necessitate
Simple and Complex Ideas
each other, not in the way of differentiation, and may constitute
a complex. A line has both length and direction (direction is
either constant, straight, or changing, curved or crooked) ; neither
of these is a differentiation of the other, though each necessitates
the other. Thus a line 1s complex.
A rectilinear boundary (i.e. of a finite plane space) must have
a number of straight Imes, not less than three. The attribute
of triangularity involves the attributes of linearity and recti•
linearity; but the threefoldness of the sides (though some
number or other 1s necessitated by rectilinear boundary) is not
a differentiation of boundary or of recttlinearity or of linearity,
and conversely. In this sense the attribute of triangularity,
whether universal or particular, 1s complex. We have seen
already in what sense 1t 1s not complex.
Contrast threeness. Threeness has no such complexity. The
plurality in it, number, odd number, number Three, is one of
differentiation only.
§ 282. If A necessitates B, the system AB is complex, sup•
posing A other than B. (This does not include differentiation ;
for the species necessitates the genus and is not something out•
side the genus, it is the genus m a certain form ) Now it may
be said that 1t is a part of the nature of A to necessitate B.
But this does not make the 'Aness' of A complex. For, by
hypothesis, the quality of A as A-its 'Aness '-is distinguishable
both from B and from the necess1tation of B. B is not a member
of the 'Aness' of A. The necessitation of B 1s not a member of
the 'Aness' of A. For A doesn't consist, in its nature as A, in
the necessitation of B, or rn B and the necessitation of B, for
that leaves out its quality of Aness. We should therefore have
to add this and say that the Aness of A consisted in the neces•
sitation of B together with Aness, which is absurd. Thus the
extension of a line necessitates pomts as its boundaries or
extremities. But the extens10n doesn't consist m the points
or in necessitating the pomts, nor m both, nor in both together
with extension.
The A quality in A, then, is not made complex because it
necessitates B which is not A.
We may apply this to show that an attribute is not complex
because it necessitates a subject : by substituting the attribute
H
508 INFERENCE
for A in the above proof and its subject for B. Surface is aa
attribute of a solid body. It does not consist in being the body, or
in body together with being an attribute of the body, or in the
latter. Any one of these leaves out its quality of being a surface,
And we cannot say surface consists in bemg an attribute of
a body and in bemg a surface.
This may be shown otherwise. Belonging to a subject is
undoubtedly of the nature of an attribute. Now 'belonging to
a subject' in general 1s not made complex by the reference
to a subJect-the subJect 1s not a member of 'belongmg to
a subJect' or of 'being an attribute '-and all that remains for
it is 'being an attribute', that is, an identity.
Thus 'being an attribute' is not complex because the plurality
it involves is not of clements which can be members of it. But
any particular attribute is merely a species of attribute in
general. Thus its mamfoldness is that of differt:ntiation and so
not complex. Surface, e. g., is a species of attribute. a
An attribute agam may necessitate other attributes, but this
does not make 1t complex. Surface necessitates another at•
tribute of a body, viz. volume, but, a!. surface, doesn't con•
sist in volume or m 'necess1tatmg volume', or in both ; and,
as before, not in necessitatmg volume and bemg a surface,
This is sufficient to disprove Locke's view that a mode is a
complex idea.
§ 283.b It 1s important to distinguish two kinds of complex
idea or complex conception For clearness we return to the
statement that the conception or idea of a complex is the appre•
hension of a complex ob.1ect, and that this 1s the only mtelhgible
sense of complex idea or complex conception. Observe that
apprehension does not here necessarily mean perception. What
is apprehended must be present to thought but it 1s not neces•
sarily present to perccpt10n. Ordinary accounts of memory tend
to confuse this. What we remember of a thing is certainly not
the memory image, 1t 1s something in the thmg. Thus what we
[• A lacuna 1s marked here in the manuscnpt
b The language here, as often above, 1s unnatural because the author has
mechanically substituted the words ' statement' and 'state' for ' Judgement •
and ' Judge ' m his old draft The act IS surely not an act of statement wlu.ch
is 'performed' but a companson which IS made, together with an 1dentification.
I have sometimes had to reintroduce the words • Judge ', &c ]
Simple anti ·Complex Ideas 509
apprehend in remembering is the nature of.the thing which is.
not present to us in perception.
Suppose I remember that certain words were spoken by
a certain man at a certain time. I may imagine myself hearing
them, but the fact which I say I remember, which therefore
I am thinking about and which I apprehend, is not these
imagined sounds. But it is just the apprehension of the fact
which is necessary to memory ; otherwise the mental images or
imaginations would occur as the images m a mere reverie. When
I say of them, in the case of memory, that they are like the
past experience, I am in some sense (other than havmg this
image) apprehending the past experience; I could not otherwise
perform this act of statement.
The complex concept10n, or idea, bring then the apprehension
of a complex object, the true conception, or the conception m
the most proper sense, is, obviously, the apprehcns10n both of
the members or elements of the complex and of the nature
of their unity. Now in the case of a given complex object we
may in perception apprehend its members or elements, and we
may apprehend the fact that they are a umty, but yet not
apprehend the nature of their unity because, as we say, we do
not understand how they arc unified In a solid, for instance,
we do apprehend both volume and surface, and their unity also,
for we see how one necessitates the other. So m ' triangle ' we
understand the unity of the three sides with the three angles,
for we see exactly how the possession of three sides necessitates
the possess1on of three angles. Suppose, however, that we
apprehend m perception the fact that m a crystal substance
a certain chemical quality is combined with a certain geometrical
form. This apprehension does not contam the reason why this
chemical substance crystallizes m this particular shape, and
accordingly we have not an apprehension of the precise nature
of the unity. There 1s therefore an undetermmed and mdefinite
element in our apprehension. Our attitude, then, 1s that we
apprehend the elements of the complex and the fact that they
are unified but are uncertain about the nature of the umty, If
we call this whole attitude 'conception', then, as contrasted
with the full and proper sense of conception, we may call it an
indefinite conception, or a partly determinate, partly. indeter!
H2
510 INFERENCE
minate, conception. Inasmuch as the nature of the unity is
a problem to us, this 'conception' might be called 'problematic',
though that word is more natural for a second case of indeter-
minateness.
In this second case certain elements are apprehended but not
even the fact of their unity ; on the contrary, we are uncertain
whether they can be unified in a given way. Here, then, the
possibility of the elements being unified at all in the given way
is a problem to us. If, then, this 1s to be called ' conception',
it may be called a problematic conception. Both kinds 0£
problematic conception have the verbal form of a definite con-
ception, i. c. conception in what seems the primary and proper
sense of the word. Thus in the statement 'a talking canary
would fetch an enormous price', 'talking canary', which may
be a problematic conception of the second kind, has exactly the
same kind of verbal form as 'tangent hne' or 'right-angled
triangle', which are definite conceptions.
It 1s true that m what we here call a definite conception (like
triangle) there may be said to be an indctermmatc element (and
indeed this is true of all 'definite' conceptions), because we do
not know many thmgs which triangle involves. For instance,
before we apprehend the proof, we do not know the magnitude
of the interior angles. But this indeterminateness is not relevant
to the present distinction. We do not indeed apprehend the
full nature of the three lines unified in a given triangle, or of
the corresponding universal, but we have apprehended some-
thing in them definitely, and we also apprehend definitely the
unity of these clements which we have apprehended. We
know, in short, how these elements are combined or put
together.
This distinction of problematic conceptions from others is
obscured by the verbal form, since this may be identical m
both cases. It 1s of the greatest importance for understanding
the nature of hypothetical thmkmg. The want of it causes
serious confusion in logic, as, e. g., m the theory of Definition.
A type of the ordinary confusions thus caused is Mill's account
of Definition. It is the same confusion which is at the bottom
of the somewhat naive illusion, which affects even distinguished
mathematicians, that it is possible to conceive a space other
Simple anrl Complex I tleas
than three-dimensional. 1 These problematic conceptions, jf con•
ceptions at all, must be classed as complex conceptions.
§ 284. The foregoing investigation was necessitated by the
common doctrine that simple ideas cannot be made at all by
us, whereas complex can, and that the latter may be fictions,
while the former cannot. Having discussed the meaning of the
distinction of simple and complex as applied to ideas or con·
ceptions, we can now begin discussing whether either kind can
be fictions.
The common doctrine above referred to, whether in popular
form or as held by philosophers such as Locke and Hume,
implies that the simple idea (or conception) is some mental and
subJective existence different from the thing to which it refers
and existing apart from 1t. This 1s treated as if it were somehow
a mental copy of the thing ; and, if we press for an exact
meamng, 1t reduces itself to the mental image m 1magination,
as it is explicitly in Hume. 2 This image, however, we have seen,
is not our 'idea of' or 'conception of' the thmg.
On this account the doctrine involves two thmgs which it
either implicitly or explicitly treats as different : first the
existence m the mmd of the mental copy or counterpart of
the thmg, and secondly its validity in relation to the object
or the reality, 'correspondence' or whatever else it may be
called. So when it is said that the simple ideas are not fictions, 3
or that we do not make them," it is meant that their existence
m our mmds is not our arbitrary creation. On the other hand,
the way m which they are caused in us, the source of what we
passively receive and do not make, guarantees their validity-
this source 1s experience. This is their only source, so that the
same cause makes them both not fictions and 'valid'. Con-
versely, as the idea 1s taken to be a mental something quite
apart from its object, or the real thing, so an idea arbitrarily
made by us would be, for these empirical thmkers, entirely
independent of any relation to an obJect in the way of 'validity'
or 'correspondence', and so with them fiction and invalidity go
I §§ 317-19,
• 'By iiuas I mean the faint images• Hume, T,-eRtise, I. i. 1. In Locke,
the pnmary qualities really come to tlus.
1
e g Locke, Essay, IV. iv 4.
• 1b,, II. 11. 2,
INFERENCE
together. This indeed is not the strict consequence of their
view ; it would only follow that such a fiction might not be
·'valid', not that it could not be. As to the 'source in experience'
there is much confusion. If pressed, the theory in its usual
form involves the tenet that the object not present to conscious-
ness ca.uses in us the idea of 1t which is present to consciousness,
whence a.rises the familiar difficulty that neither the validity of
the idea could be guaranteed nor even the existence of any
'object' of it. Or, as in one aspect of Hume's philosophy, the
object itself may be made mental, an 'impress10n' existing only
in the mmd hke the idea : the idea, then, becomes its fainter
copy; and certamly such famter copy, the same m kmd as the
impression, is not our conception of the ongmal or idea of the
original (which latter 1s itself, according to this theory, directly
apprehended). Even if we allow this 'idea' (1 e of Hume's) to
be true imagmahon and not a fainter mental slate of the same
kmd as the ob1ect or experience (which cannot possibly be
imagmat10n) the result is the same, this imagmat1on is not 'idea
of' or 'conception of' the thing or object. Smee, however,
experience naturally means direct apprehension of the object,
the above difficulties are often obscured or avoided by ambiguous
language such as 'got in experience', a 'got from experience',
'given m experience', and the hke: where advantage is uncon·
sciously taken of this natural meanmg of experience.
§ 285. The general statement of the doctrine is, then, that
experience is somehow the origin of the existence of the simple
ideas, as these are understood by empiricists (and generally in
the confused way which we have found m Locke), and also gives
them validity. Now whatever may be meant by this, whatever
'being given m experience' means, the facts which the Empiricist
refers to in this doctrme arc such as what we call the experiences
of an actual colour, of an actual sound, of an actual shape (with
some Empmcists). And they mean that everything of which
we have an 'idea' is experienced, in the sense in which colour,
sound, and (with some) shape arc experienced (seen, heard, &c.).
Now in this sense of 'origin in experience' there are 'ideas'
which do not thus originate in experience, because that of which
[& 'This relation (causation) arises entirely from expenence, when we find
that any particular ob1ects are constantly con1omed ' Hume, Enquiry, 1v. 1]
Simple .and Complex Ideas
they are said to be 'idea' 1s not experienced in this sense-as
not seen, felt, heard, smelt, or tasted ; nor are these ideas
combinations of such as are given in experience in this way.
This being so, whether they are simple in themselves or not does
not matter. Such ideas are, e.g., those of substance and attri•
bute, cause and effect, necessity m general. The development
of the empirical philosophy begun by Hume was due to a growing
consciousness of this fact. The development, however, failed to
explain the origin of such ideas, and only ended m self-contra-
diction. The association of ideas, for instance, the favourite
resource, either does not give any new ideas beside those found
in experience, which form its material (and this is indeed the
true alternative), or 1£ 1t 1s supposed to do so, the admission is
involved that the mmd can make new ideas which it has not
found in experience, and thus the premisses of the theory are
directly contradicted.
In view of the doctrme that 'experiencing' of the kind meant
(and best described by reference to the facts as above) 1s a source
of certain 'ideas' and guarantee of their validity (waiving for
the moment the question whether origm and validity can be
separated m the manner described), we have to ask how such
ideas as Substance, Power, &c., arc related to experience con•
ce1ved in tlus way.
§ 286. But it 1s useful first to consider a set of ideas of which
also 1t may be said that they arc not 'given' m this experience
although they arc not m the same relation to that experience as
substance, cause, necessity, &c. These latter (1. e. substance, &c.)
are what caused the first difficulty and misg1vmg to Empir1c1sts; 1
but there is an abundance of other ideas in ordinary thinking
about which there 1s a similar great difficulty, though the
Empiricists are either not conscious of it at all, or only very
imperfectly. As Plato pointed out, we do not, for example,
observe or perceive 'equality', because we do not perceive two
perfectly equal magnitudes. That 1s, m the language of these
Empmc1sts, we do not 'experience' equality, or perfect straight·
ness, or perfect circularity. Some Emp1ric1sts a have indeed
1 Cf Locke's controversy with Stilhngfleet, Hume on Ca.use.
[• e. g. • Since, then, neither in nature, nor m the human nund, do there
exist any obJects exactly correspondmg to the definitions of geometry.' Mill,
INFERENCE
so far realized this that they are driven to say, like Mill,1 that
there are no real objects possessed of the attributes studied in
geometry, which must involve for them the conclusion that there
are no ideas whatever corresponding to the words. This con-
clusion is actually admitted by Mill, but he conceals from him-
self the contradtctlon m which he is thus entangled by devices
of language and restores agam to the mind as 'hypothesis' what
he had banished from 1t as 'idea'.
But the usual answer (and the very one to which Mill himself
has recourse, 1mphc1tly, later on in his discussion) would be that
though we do not perceive perfect straight Imes, perfect equals,
&c., we do perceive the unequal and approximation to equality,
the curved and approximation to straightness, and the imperfect
suggests to us the perfect, 1.e. the equal and the straight. But
now suggest10n, understood as these Empiricists would have to
understand 1t (they have never really thought out what they
mean by 1t), could only mean that what was suggested had
been already experienced, and this 1s the real ground of Plato's
doctrine of Remm1scence, into which, or something essentially
like it, the Empme1st would be dnven
The true answer, which 1s 1mposs1ble from the point of view
of such empmc1sm, conducts us necessarily to the recognition
of a kmd of apprehension which 1s not perception and therefore
not 'experience' as understood in the view we are examining.
It 1s granted that we observe or expcnencc unequals and
inequality But, for tlus, we must apprehend the things so
observed to be unequal. Now mequahty 1s unintelhg1ble without
the idea of equality, and therefore m such statements we must
both have and use an '1<lea ', 1 c equality, which by hypothesis
we do not observe or experience, and 111 this sense do not find
m experience, 1 <' m whc1.t we experience. In this sense the idea
ts not given m experience. Now to have the idea of equality
m this active way 1s to know what equality 1s. This again does
not mean to have a mental picture or an imagination of equality
as d1stmgmshcd from apprehension of actual equality, for that
1 System of Lo~ic, 11, 5
System of Logic, 11. S, § 1 'It 1s customary to say that the pomts •.. ex1St
1n our conceptions merely,' 1d. 1b , and the note m the same section, • thlS
unreal exactitude might be called a fiction' (9th ed., vol. 1, p. 261),]
Simple antl Complex I tleas
is not equality itself. To know what equality is we must apprt•
hend equality itself ; and thus the idea of equality is simply
the apprehension of equality and nothing else but this appre•
hension. Thus the experience or perception of inequality itself
necessitates the apprehension of equality, which the experience
does not present. Further, if the experience guarantees the
validity of the 'idea of inequality' (using the language appro•
priate to the theory we are criticizing), it certainly guarantees
the validity of the idea of equality smce the former necessitates
the latter. And so for other 'ideas', such as 'straightness'.
The relation of such ideas to experience may be put also in
this way : the apprehension of the obJects of these ideas (1. e.
strictly the apprehension of them which constitutes what are
called the 'ideas' of them) 1s a necessary part of the whole
apprehension of which the apprehension called perception or
experience is the other part. Just on this account it is not in
any way necessary to assume that we have the ideas m question
before all experience, or that we could have them. They are no
more actively present to us without perception than are colour
and heat. If we like to call the whole act of apprehension above
referred to experience, then we experience the objects of these
ideas of cqua!Jty, straightness, &c, as much as the unequal,
crooked, &c. But this 1s not only not a fair use of the word
'experience' but tends to obscure an important distmction.
Wh~t, of course, 1s nght m the view of these Empmcists 1s their
feelmg that we have none of these ideas without experience, but
they entirely fad to understand their relation to experience.
§ 287. The ideas above considered, or rather their objects, have
corresponding to them m experience contranes to them more or
less remote, which may sometimes be accounted approximations
to them. But others, also not •given m experience' (such as
cause), have no such counterparts m 'experience', and this is
their distinction from the first set We do not, e g, experience
something approximatmg to causation or contrary to it. If we
keep the meaning of the expenenced which is proper to the
empirical theory before us, Time 1s as much an 'idea' of this
kind as is Cause. The Empiricists arc strangely unaware of this.
For instance, in the empiricist sensational Idealism, Time is
always presupposed and yet, on their account of the data of
INFERENCE
experience, it could not be among these data and would have
to be accounted for by the Association of Ideas. This difficulty,
however, never occurs to them. Time is not seen, felt, heard,
or experienced in general, in this sense of experience ; it 1s
apprehended along with the apprehension called experience, and
as apprehended 1t is an apprehension of particular time. Here
again, as m the case of the former set of 'ideas' or objects, we
cannot have the one apprehension without the other. Properly,
neither apprehension is more 'vahd' than the other, m the sense
that one 1s more certainly of a real object than the other. But
if 1t 1s held that the apprehension of experience 1s 'valid', or
guarantees the corresponding 'idea' as of a real object, then it
guarantees Time. For that which is necessitated by what is
taken to be real must itself be taken to be real. Now the objects
experienced necessitate Time. We, on the other hand, apprehend
this, and our apprehension 1s necessary as bemg of the necessary.
This proper account is inverted when we represent it as a neces•
sity of thinking as distmgu1shed from the obJcct, and so virtually
as primarily a subjecuve necessity. In recognizing or appre-
hending Time we are simply apprehending side by side with
experience a side or aspect of the object we are experiencing,
which aspect 1s not experienced. Time, then, is not an 'idea'
or 'conception' given in ~perience as simple ideas are supposed
to be, but must be as 'valid' as that which 1s given in experience.
Causality 1mphes Time and it is not mere necessitation of
events, or of their order, but implies the d1stmct1on of events
which happen from objects to which they belong and which do
not happen. The fact again of the existence of such objects,
identical in change, could not be experienced in the sense in
which we are now usmg 'experience' ; and this contention is
borne out by the failure of Locke to get the ideas, e.g. of
substance and power, out of experience as he understands it.
Some Empmc1sts might perhaps hold that we do experience
permanence, or identity in change, when we apprehend the
movement of a body. But, 1£ this is denied to be experience,
the events apprehended m experience at all events necessitate
this belonging to an object, and this, we contend, we do appre-
hend even if we do not experience 1t.
Causality will ultimately be found to mean that the events
Simple 11,n,J, Complex Ideas
belonging to an object, or to a system of objects, have a definite
order, that is, therefore, a necessary order. There is a reason
why a certain event happens in the particular order it does in
relation to the other events of the system. We apprehend this
necessity as belonging to the order of events : we apprehend it
as much as we do the events, though we do not apprehend it in
the way of experiencing it. And as before, therefore, experience
guarantees it, if it can guarantee anything. Here again the true
relation is inverted and the apprehension, because it is held not
to be experience, is represented as m the first place a necessity
of thinking (and hence arises a quite false problem as to how
reality has to agree with lhis necessity of thought).1 There is
in this case a special temptation to the fallacy, which we shall
come to presently. We repeat that our thought about the object
js necessary because it is the apprehension of something ncces•
sary. Necessity must he in the object apprehended: for appre•
hension as distinguished from that has no content whatever.
Whence necessary thought, as what we are obliged to think
about an object, can only be the apprehension of a necessity
in the object.
But, now, we neither apprehend m experience, nor do we
apprehend otherwise, the particular way in which a particular
event is caused : we apprehend a necessity in general, i. c. that
the event must have some cause or other This is a universal
and there is therefore a special temptation to make it subjective,
because of the common mistaken tendency to regard universals
as merely subjective existences. The example of the con·
trasted set of 'ideas', such as straightness and equality, shows
that there is nothmg strange m the statement that we can
apprehend something in an object of experience, which 'some·
thing' we do not experience, and that we can thus apprehend
a universal. Form the experience of two unequals we apprehend
their relation to equality ; this relation m them we do not, e,:
hypothesi, experience ; we must also apprehend equality which
we do not experience, and this 1s not a particular equality but
a universal.
1 A ialse problem is one 1n which we put as a question what cannot possibly
be a matter of question It therefore always admits a reduclio ad absurdum,
which could easily be given in the present case.
518 INFERENCE
If it be said that what we apprehend in the object of experience
must be a part of our experience of it, then inevitably it would
result that we experience time, the identity of a subject in its
changes, or of a system of subjects, and that we experience the
fact that events must be 'causally' connected. And if experience
is of the real, these will all be experienced realities. But as the
example of equality shows, we cannot properly call experience
all that we apprehend m an object of which some aspects are
'experienced '.
So far, then, from it being difficult to relate time, causality, &c.,
to objects of experience or to account for their vahd1ty1 they must
either be considered to be as direct obJects of experience as
anythmg else, or to have their validity guaranteed by that of
experience, if experience can guarantee anythmg
The real reason why people make experience the ground of
knowledge is that they think we directly apprehend in experience
real obJects, and this, as already noticed, 1s the natural meaning
of experience. But though this is the only thmg which makes
their appeal to experience mtelhgible, they often either obscure
1t, or are actually not entitled to hold 1t, because of their theories
of perception.
Our conclusion, then, is that if experience is o{ real obJects
and their properties, or if the obJccts of experience are real, it
inevitably follows that both these groups of ideas, equality,
perfect straightness, time, cause, &c , arc properties of real
objects.
It must be remembered that m any case the object cannot
apprehend itself : we must do that. Therefore such appeals to
experience, and indeed any appeal to experience, imply that our
apprehension of the obJcct 1s final and authoritative, in some
respect, whether 1t be of the quality or kind of quality of the
object or at the lowest of the existence of the objects. It follows
that our apprehension mu::,t also be authoritative m respect of
that which we apprehend as necessary to the objects of experience.
§ 288. We return now once more to the question whether
a simple idea can be made. A simple idea may, as we saw,
necessitate a complex idea, so that the one question involves
the other, whether, that is, the corresponding complex idea can
be made. The sense of 'making' which seems most intelligible
Simple and Comf>lex I leas
is that of composing something out of pre-existing materials
which are not made. But if ideas were so made they would be
complex, and thus we are anyhow, apart from the theory to
which we have been referring, led to consider whether we can
make new simple ideas.
For our purpose, which is to find whether there is any element
in an hypothetical statement which may properly be called a
fiction, or fictit1ous, we might be content with the fact that no
one believes it possible to make a simple idea, and that there is no
record of any one ever havmg made one. At first sight it might
seem enough to say that the absolute origination or making of
an idea out of nothing 1s mconceivable and unintelligible.
Yet it is worth while considermg the question for its own sake,
These are vague words. 'Inconce1vable' may mean that we
don't know how the thing could happen, or that we know it to be
unpossiblc as contrad1ctmg something known. 'Unmtelligible'
may mean that we do not understand it, or that it is contrary
to reason, which again means contradictory to something we
know to be true. There 1s always a danger of passing from one
of these meanings to another. As to' ongmation ', 1t 1s important
to remember that we arc accustomed to attribute origination to
ourselves, and yet the way m which this happens may be said
to be mconce1vable and umntelhg1ble m the first of the above
senses of these words We suppose ourselves to originate the
movements of our limbs ; but we do not understand how we
do it, nor can wc even form a conJecture. If this is immediate
origination, then at all events immediate or1gmation, 'out of
nothing' as the phrase 1s, would be a fact. But what is more
important and more to our purpose 1s that we certamly suppose
ourselves to origmate trains of imagination and trains of thinking,
where, again, there is immediate or1gmat1on or, if not, we at
least do not understand at all how they arc originated. It is
decisive to say that a thmg is mconcc1vable only if this means
we know it to be impossible because we know 1t contradicts
something that we know for certain. Thus m the case of this
example, if we are to pronounce 1t inconceivable, we ought to
know that the nature of the thing itself does not admit of
making or ongination.
If we consider some ideas that we have, we certainly do see
520 INFERENCE
that they are incapable of being made or originated at all in
time ; this is the ordinary way of speaking ; it is more accurate
to say that their objects are incapable of it, Unity, plurality,
the number three, &c., are universals which as such cannot have
any kind of beginning m time. In the nature of the case they
a.re unchangeable. And it might be contended that for any idea
whatever, supposed to be made, there must be a universal which
could not be made. But, for our present purpose, 1t is not
necessary to msist upon this. The question cannot be properly
discussed unless we get rid of the confusion caused by the false
representation of 'idea' as a mental existence which we can have
apart from any reference to or apprehension of an object,
A definite idea or conception being nothing but the apprehension
of a definite object, the question whether an idea can be made
arbitrarily is the question whether the apprehension of an ob3ect
can be made, :'l.nd this, agam, really means whether the object
apprehended can be made by the apprehending mind. Object m
the wider sense mcludes states of ourselves, feelings, emotions,
which can be apprehended, and objects not states of ourselves,
the latter, narrower, sense bemg the usual one. From these,
both of which arc called obJects of experience, arc distinguished
imaginations ; 1magmcd sensations, and imagined obJccts 1 in
the narrower sense. For clearness we may repeat that the
definite idea or conception of an object is not the 'imagination'
of it, but the apprehension of what it is itself
We may apprehend an 1magmat1on, or mental image, as an
imagination, and this apprehension of its nature is the 'idea' ot
conception of it. To make an idea, then, we must make 1ts
object, Suppose we could make an object in the narrower sense,
\t would of course be real and the idea of it, i. c, the apprehension
of it, the apprehension of somethmg real. If we could ongmate
a sensa.tion, the same would be true of its ' idea' or conception.
As to imagination we might here agam be content with the
universal adm1ss1on that we cannot imagine anything simple
except as the imagination of somethmg already experienced.
But suppose we could imagine something quite new, it would
be something existing as our imagination ; the idea of it would
be the apprehension of 1t as something ex:1stmg in our imagina-
• On the dulerence between imagmat10n and experience, cf § 137.
Simple and Complex Ideas
tion, By 'fiction' is usually meant something mental, not
corresponding to reality. In the first two cases the thing made
(an 'object' or a sensation, e. g.) would be a reality and there•
fore not a fiction and the idea of it (i.e. the apprehension of
it) would be in no sense a fiction. In the third case the imagina-
tion would not have any known reality ( = 'object' or sensation,
c. g.) corresponding to it and, in that sense, would be called
a fiction ; but it would certamly be an cx1stcncc, and the idea
of it, though not the apprehension of 'reality' m the above
sense, would be the apprehension of an existence, Thus even
here the 'idea' or 'conception' would not be either untrue or
without relation to truth (that 1s associated with fiction and
the fictitious), nor would it even be the conception or idea of
something untrue
Now that we see what 'making' an idea would have to mean,
it is clear that 1f a definite simple conception could be made-
and in the nature of the case all simple conceptions must be
definite-it could not be something false or even doubtful, or
a pretence that somethmg was real which was not. In short, it
would have none of the usual associations of the word fiction
and fictitious. This, then, is the important matter ; not whether
it can or cannot be made. Thus m an hypothetical statement,
or indeed m any statement, there can be no simple idea which
can be called false, or doubtful, or a fiction, in the sense of the
pretence that something exists which does not exist.
§ 289. We come now to the complex ideas. It is both popularly
and m some philosophical systems ta.ken for granted that the
mmd can •make' complex ideas, m the sense that it can arbi•
tranly con301n simple ideas, irrespectively of whether the cor.re•
sponding conjunction (to use the language of these systems) has
appeared m experience or not. It would follow m this case that
there could be uncertainty about any correspondence in reality
to these complex ideas. Such ideas, then, might be called
fictitious, as indeed they usually are.
We shall, however, find the truth to be that we have no
arbitrary power at all of thus making complex ideas, and that, in
the only sense in which we can be said to make them, the making
is necessary and the result not only not fictitious but necessarily
real. For 1f we really put together two or more simple con~
INFERENCE
ceptions into a conception which is truly one, the conceptions
must be put in organic connexion. But such organic connexion
depends on their own nature, and we manifestly could not put
them into a connexion of which their nature did not admit.
Observe that the connexion cannot be merely their being some-
how together ; 1£ we thmk the connexion at all (and we do not
put them into connexion unless we think the connexion} we
must think of it not as connexion in general, but as a particular
form of connexion. When, for instance, we connect the posses-
sion of three angles with the possession of three sides, we see
how the one fact is connected with the other. The connexion
of them will be one which their nature necessitates and therefore
as real as these elements themselves which are connected. This
is illustrated in geometrical demonstration. For in this we really
advance to new complex conceptions, not by experience but by
our own rcasonmg processes ; and, in this sense, viz. as not
merely takmg from experience but advancing to a new con•
nexion of elements by our own thought, we may be said to
make. Moreover, what we make is accepted without hesitation
as true and as real ; at all events, taken to be everyway as true
and real as the clements from which we start.
We have obviously, on the other hand, no power to put
elements together either in a way known to be contrary to their
nature or m a way about which we are uncertam whether it is
possible for them or not. For, in the first case, we should be
thinking the unthinkable ; and, m the second case, we have not
really put them together. In the second case, at the best, we
only know that we see nothing in the conception which prevents
the connexion, but we know no more. Our frame of mind is
not conception or statement, but mterrogatlon or wonder. We
merely wonder whether the connexion 1s possible. The second
case, then, 1s clearly that of conceptions which we have called
problematic: they have only the verbal form of a conception.
The common error 1s to take them for conceptions proper, which
involves considering them as fictions which we have made with-
out reference to reality. But it is now obvious that it 1s a mistake
to suppose them 'made' . they are not made at all and are
therefore not fictions. Instead of their representing a connexion
made between known conceptions, they merely represent the
Simple and Complex I leas
state of mind in which the connexion is problematic to us ;
a state of mind in which, on the one hand, we know nothing
against the connexion and, on the other, do not see its possibility
(i.e. necessity). We do not here 'make', we are only m doubt
whether the connexion can be made. Particular examples show
this at once. Thus in no case is it really possible for the mind
to produce a merely fictitious idea, whether simple or complex.
In the sense in which a complex idea can be made, the idea
cannot be a fiction but must be as real, or apply as much to
reality, as any other idea.
I 290. The preceding argument is expressed in the language
usual about conceptions and, as such, is of polemical use,•
because it does not involve an appeal to the doctrine about the
true nature of an idea or conception, which we ourselves main•
tain. It requires to be restated in the terms of this doctrine,
for the ordinary language is, in the end, likely to mislead by
suggesting the common confusion about the mental existence of
ideas and conceptions.
A complex conception or idea is nothing but the apprehension
of a complex object in which 'simple' elements A, B, C, &c.,
are united or unified m some particular way. The apprehensions
of A, B, C, &c., severally may be called simple ideas as appre•
hensions of simple elements whether umversal or mdiv1dual.
Obviously, then, the complex 'idea' is not properly speaking
a 'combination' or 'complex' of the simple ideas corresponding
to it, but rather the idea of the complex which the objects of
these simple ideas form; not, that is, a complex of these appre-
hensions of the simple elements but the apprehension of the
complex formed by these simple elements. At all events, to
call the complex idea a complex or combination of the simple
ones is, at best, an obscure and misleading way of saying that
the obJect of the complex idea (or apprehension) is a certain
kmd of complex of the objects of the simple ideas (or appre-
hensions).
Suppose, now, certain simple ideas a, /3, "I are given. These
are respectively apprehensions of objects A, B, C, &c. The
question, then, whether there can be a complex idea combined
[• In truth, I believe, an embodiment of his own ea.rher treatment of the
subJect. Seep 814 ]
2773•2 I
INFERENCE
of these simple ones is only intelligible as being the question
whether the objects A, B, and C form a complex m a certain
way, i. e. with a certain kind of umty, and whether we can
apprehend this as a definite conception , can, that is, both appre•
bend the elements and the nature of their umty. Can we see
how they form a unity of the given kind?
But whether A, B, and C form a complex of the given kind, or
can form it, depends entirely upon their own definite nature and
not on any act of the apprehending mind. The nature of the
clements themselves determines necessarily what unity they
have or can have, and thus the mind has no power whatever
arbitrarily to effect a combination of them (the necessary pre-
requisite of the complex idea), since that is only the apprehension
of such combmat1on. Thus the mmd has no power whatever
to make a complex idea, and therefore, in any intel11g1ble sense
of the words, no power whatever to make a complex idea out
of simple ones
As to the sense in which we may be said to make a conception
or a demonstration in the exact sc1ences, 1 thi'l agam is an
inaccurate and m1slcadmg use of words In the reasoning pro•
ccss, though as such 1t 1s not experience, wc are simply appre•
bending what the obJccts, with the apprehension of which we
start, necessitate through their own nature and we no more
'make' what they necessitate than we make them. If we do
not know the nature of the obJects sufficiently well to know
whether they can be umfied m a complex of the given kind, the
poss1b1hty of surh umficat1on of them is a problem to us and,
if our attitude 1s to be called idea or concept1on at all, our
conception must be what we have named problematic conception
or quest1on-coneeptton.
1
Compare § 289, p ;22, begmnmg ' ThlS 1s illustrated .
VI
HYPOTHETICAL STATEMENT AND
HYPOTHETICAL ARGUMENT
tnangles havmg their sides terminated at one extremity of the hne equal
to one another, and hkewlSe those termmated at ihe other extremity of the
line equal to one aDOther '
544 INFERENCE
we say we imagine a serpent breathing fire, all we imagine is
the colour and exterior appearance of a serpent and the same
for fire. We arc not 1magming the physical properties of fire,
and the biological properties of the serpent which make 'breath-
ing fire• impossible for the serpent.
§ 303. The mferencc '1£ A is B, A is C ; but A is not C,
therefore A is not B' arises m the following way. Being uncer•
tain whether the answer has the form 'A is B' which really,
since B is C, 1s equivalent to the form 'A 1s B, and therefore
A 1s C', or whether the form of the answer 1s 'A is not B ', we
afterwards find that a statement of the form A is C cannot be
made ; in other words, that A is not C. The answer therefore
cannot have the form mcludmg or nccess1tat10g the form 'A is
C'. It cannot therefore have the form 'A is B ', which (as we
have seen) mcludes or necessitates the form 'A is C' ; mother
words, it must be 'A 1s not B '.
This way of putting it explains most simply and clearly the
verbal parallelism between the hypothetical and non-hypothetical
arguments. We have simply to substitute, m fact, in the non•
hypothetical form of argument, the expree.sion 'the form of
statement A is B ', for 'the statement A is B •. Thus, e. g. :
Non-hypothetical argument. Ilypothetical argument.
the statement A is B ncces- the form of statement A is B
sitates the statement A 1s C, necessitates the form of state-
ment A 1s C,
the statement A is C ncccs- the form of statement A is C
sitates the statement A 1s D, necessitates the form of state·
mcnt A 1s D,
therefore the statement A 1s B therefore the form of statement
necessitates the statement A A is B necessitates the form
is D. of statement A is D.
The second (or hypothetical) argument 1s now rewritten, 'if
A is B, A is C ; 1f A 1s C, A is D ; therefore if A 1s B, A is D '.
We may also put the parallelism as follows:
A's being B necessitates C's bemg D. (This may be either
singular or universal in form ) The affirmative form of answer
to (AB~), viz. the form A 1s B, necessitates the form C is D.
In other words, 'if A 1s B, then C must be D '. If we put the
form '1£ A 1s B, C 1s D' m the following shape, 'the affirmative
Hypothetical Stalemenl and Argument 545
form A is B is a case of the affirmative form C is D', we have
language analogous to that used before about one problem being
a case of another, and the inference may be put similarly. In
the case where we know C is not D, the form C is D is impossible,
and therefore any case of it, as 'A is B ', is impossible. From
this pomt of view then we may say that the hypothetical stJte•
ment asserts something of one of those forms of statement, one
or other of which is the form which the answer to our problem
must take. The distmctlon on which everything turns in the
foregomg 1s that of the form A is B from an actual statement
of that general form.
In the hypothetical statement we assert nothing of a state•
ment, but we do assert something of a form of statement.
§ 304. The 'if' clause m an hypothetical statement may,
according to a familiar 1d1om, refer to something already decided
and thus appear not to embody a question. We say, for example,
'If A had been (or were) B, as we know 1t was (or is) not, A
would have been (or would be) C '. Such statements are, of
course, of frequent occurrence, e g. : 'If he had jumped out of
the carriage a mmute later he would have been killed.' Observe
that all such cases refer to the contradictory of what really
happened, 1. e , as would be said, to somethmg which did not
happen. It docs not follow that in such cases, or indeed in any
cases, the hypothetical statement 1s about a possibility which
is objective. For, as we have seen, there is no obJectlve pos-
s1b1hty of anything which 1s not nccessary. 1 The only other
possibd1ty, 1f 1t can be called one, 1s m our subjective uncertainty.
In such examples as the above the reference 1s to something
impossible and not to somethmg obJcctively possible. Nor is it
true that something is merely affirmed about an imaginary
existence. Somethmg true of reality is affirmed, as 1s easily
seen when we reflect that the example gives the information
that the man ;umped before a certam thing, incompatible with
the hfe of a man in the carriage, happened, e. g. before the
carriage fell over a precipice. The solution of the difficulty may
be got out of the case where there is a real question. Take
a case where we start with a real uncertainty as to whether
A is B but know that B is C; and suppose that we afterwards
l § g0,
find that A is not C. We say first, ' If A is B, A is C because
B is C', i.e. (AB?) 1s a case of (AC.?} since B is C. We add
afterwards, 'But A is not C', 1. e. (AC?) is answered in the
negative. •Therefore A 1s not B 'i i. e. (AB ?) is negatived,
But, when we have got so far, (AB ?} ceases to be a question,
for our uncertainty no longer exists. The proper expression of
our thought now is : '1f A were (or had been) B, A would be
(or would have been} C; but A 1s (or was) not C, therefore
A is (or was) not B.'
Now this 1s equivalent to the question (AB?) was a case of
the question (AC?), and as (AC?) was answered in the negative,
so also (AB ?) was answered m the negative
Thus the hypothetical form we now have before us, '1f A were
(or had been) B, &c. ', expresses a relation between what were
questions (AB ') and (AC '), as questions, and conveys also the
mformat1on as to how they were answered, viz. negatively.
The carriage accident 1s qmtc parallel to the above. The
question whether the man would Jump m time or not was a real
question before he Jumped, and the question whether he would
jump m time was a case of the question whether he would be
killed.
In the case of a.n ordinary reductio ad absurdum proof, it may
be said that the question (AB?) 1s known from the first to be
negatived; but this 1s not for the inquirer or learner, but only
for the teacher when he communicates 1t So in the mouth of
the teacher 'If A 1s B, A is C' means . 'the question for you
(i. e. the person learning) whether A 1s B 1s a case of the question
for you whether A 1s C ' Of course for the teacher himself at
one time (AB?) will have been a problem.
§ 305. The disJunctive statement 'A is either B or C' often,
not always, implies an uncertainty about some given subject
A, and accordmgly 1s akm to the hypothetical. It may mark
a stage m our inqumng attitude ; we may begm with uncertainty
as to whether A 1s B, but advance sufficiently m knowledge to
have the certainty that A is either B or C, or in general, either
B or C or D, &c. Moreover, it then gives rise to hypothetical
reasonmg, A is either B or C, B is X, C is Y, .·. if A is B, it
is X, 1f A 1s C, it is Y. But the statement 'A 1s either B or C'
nevertheless does not always imply an uncertamty, and is at
Hypothetical Statement tZnd A,gument 541
least not intended to express any. It may express the necessary
differentiation of a universal and contain nothing hypothetical
at all. For example, 'Lines are either straight or curved or
crooked'; 'number is either odd or even'. 'A triangle is (or
triangles are) either right-, obtuse-, or acute-angled.'
In reference, however, to a particular instance of the universal
such a statement has the dis1unctive form which expresses a
limited uncertainty. For of a given triangle we may know it
is a triangle because wc know 1t 1s a figure consisting of straight
lines joining three given points, each to each, without knowing
whether it is right-angled, obtuse-angled, or acute-angled. Thus
we know that the figure formed by joining any point in a cir-
cumference to the extremities of the diameter is a triangle,
before wc know its property.
But, m this case, we have the d1sJunctivc statement 'the
triangle X has either one right angle, or one obtuse angle, or
three acute angles' , which is based on the disjunctive non·
hypothetical statement, ' a triangle must have either one right
angle, or one obtuse angle, or three acute angles '. In fact
the disjunctive statement of uncertamty 'A1 1s either B or C'
(it is uncertain which) 1s always an mference from two state•
mcnts, v1z : {1) a d1s1unct1vc which is not problematic, or
expressive of uncertainty, i e. 'A (or all A) is either B or C ',
and (2) a statement neither hypothetical nor d1sjunct1ve 'A1 is
A'. In other words, m the problematic disjunctive statement
'A1 is either B or C ', A1 has the alternative attributes or pro•
perties B and C only because 1t has the characteristic A which
must differentiate mto B or C.
In this characteristic the problematic disjunctive 1s obviously
like the hypothetical, for this also must be an inference from
a non-hypothetical statement. But the non-problematic dis•
junctive statement is not necessarily an inference from another
statement. A d1s1unct1ve statement, however, of the form 'A is
either not B or not C ', suppose we start with A as subJect, can
only arise as an inference from A 1s not {BC), 1. e. from 'A is
either X or Y, and X is not B, and Y 1s not C ', for obviously
a universal A cannot be differentiated into negative classes
immediately.
§ 306. The disjunctive statement, whether problematic or not,
INFERENCE
is, like the hypothetical statement, as categorical as the statement
to which the word categorical is usually restricted.
The statement 'A1 is either B or C' (when not the differentia•
tion of a universal} implies the problems (A1B?} (A1C?) ; it
states that the problems are such that one of them has an
affirmative answer. But its meaning cannot be more simply
and directly expressed than by the use of the words 'either' and
'or', 1.c. 'A1 1s either B or C', supplemented by 'but 1t is not
known which'; for to say that one of two problems (A1B?) and
(A1C?} has an affirmative answer is to say either (A1B?} or
(A1C?) has an affirmative answer.
Or put 1t this way. the question 'what 1s A 1 ?' is such that
the answer must take one of the two forms 'A 1 1s B ', or' A 1 is
C' ; where, once more, 'A1 1s B' and 'A1 is C' are not statements
but forms of statement
Thus the problematic disjunctive statement does not affirm
a relation between statements ; it expresses a relation between
two problems, as above described, or (another aspect of the
same thing) 1t states a relation between two forms of state•
ment 'A1 1s B' and 'A 1 1s C ', that is, the statement which
answers the question about A1 must take one or other of these
forms.
§ 307. If we have the statement A1 is either B or C, it follows
that 1f A1 is not B, A1 1s C, and 1f A1 is not C, 1t 1s B. Thus
the problematic d1sJunct1ve statement gives rise to hypothetical
statements.
We may put the problematic disjunctive reasoning as follows:
the question whether A1 is not B 1s identical with the questions
whether A1 is not B and whether A1 1s C (A being either B or
C) ; or the question whether A1 1s not B 1s a case of the question
whether A1 1s C, 1 c. the / orm of the answer 'A1 1s not B'
necessarily includes the form A1 1s C. The ongmal disJunct10n,
as stated, is, however, compatible with A being both B and C.
We ought to add the caveat, if A 1s B, it docs not follow that
A is not C ; and where tlus 1s not the case, 1t ought to be
d1stmctly stated.
§ 308. The problematic disjunctive statement may by com-
bination with assertoric premisses lead to a conclusion which is
not problematic. For instance :
Hypothetical State,nenl antl A,gument 549
A1 is either B or C j B is D and C is D
••• if A1 is B, A1 is D
if A1 is C, A1 is D
••. A1 is D.
In other words, an attribute which belongs to A1 , if in the group
B and C, mvolves D.
Here it is not the disjunctive statement as such which leads
to a non-disjunctive conclusion. B and C must involve D in
consequence of something common to both, viz. A. We know
that A1 is B or C because A1 is A, and A is either B or C. Thus
we know already that A1 has the condition of D, viz. A, and
thus the argument accurately stated is A1 is A; A is D; .'. A1
is D. The disjunctive statement only arises from an imperfect
insight into A and D, on account of which we have not been
able to attach D directly to A. That 1s to say, the problematic
statement A1 1s either B or C follows from the non-problematic
disjunctive statements A is either B or C (where B and C are
differentiations of the universal A), and A1 1s an A.
But B (= AB) is D, and C (-AC) is D,
And AB and AC make up A (which statement implies that
AB is real and AC is real) .
. ·. all A 1s D, and A1 1s A,.·. A1 is D.
§ 309. Aristotle showed a right instinct in not proposing a
reduction of hypothetical argument to a non-hypothetical form.
He does not condemn it and probably 1t had never occurred to
him to consider its poss1b1bty. The ordmary method is to
substitute for the 1f clauses, in, for example, if A is B, C is D,
if C is D, E is F, therefore if A is B, E h, F, the apparently
non-hypothetical statements 'all cases of A being B are cases
of C being D '. But, as we have abundantly seen, the sub•
stituted and non-hypothetical form properly means that it is
not uncertain whether any A is B. In fact, to represent the
reasonmg m full, we should have to say all cases of A being B,
if there are any, &c. Thus we have not eliminated the' if' and
the supposed reduction is impossible.
Consider again, if all A is B, C is D ; but all A is B, ••. C is
D. Here, if we substituted 'all cases of A's bemg B are cases of
C's being D ', we should imply that all A is B and 'but all A is B 1
would be superfluous. In fact it 1s really unintelligible, in regard
IN.FERENCE
to such reasoning, to say all cases of A are cases of A being B 1
for ' if A is B ' contradicts the idea that all cases of A are B. If
it be said that reality necessitates A's being B, the first clause
must be A's being B necessitates C's being D, and this implies,
in ordmary usage, that A is B. The same difficulties occur in
the ordinary reduction of the d1sjunct1vc argument. Take, for
example,
either A is B or A is C,
A 1s not C . ·. A is B.
We are asked to represent this by the following reasoning:
Every case of A not C 1s a case of AB.
Every case of A 1s a case of A not C.
. ·. Every case of A is a case of AB.
But here, in the first statement, we have implied the reality of
the cases of A not C, whereas the obJect of our original statement
was to make these cases problematic. Moreover, the precedmg
criticism apphes to the way the second (so-called mmor) premiss
1s stated. Similarly we cannot reduce the argument A is either
DB or DC, . ·. A 1s D, to a non-dtsjunctivc form.
§ 310. We may now mqmre how hypothetical reasoning is best
represented so as to bring out its true form. It 1s uncertam
whether A is B , let C be A and B be D. Then if A ts B, inas-
much as C JS A and B is D, rt follows that C is D. Further,
we know that Jf C is D, E JS F. Therefore 1f A JS B, we know
that E 1s F.
The accurate way of stating this appears to be this. An
affirmative answer to the question whether A JS B necessitates an
affirmative answer to (CD?), an affirmative answer to the latter
necessitates an affirmative answer to (EF?), therefore an affirma•
t1ve answer to (AB~) necessitates an affirmative answer to (EF?).
But here we are m d1fficult1es again, because we can say that
the quest10n (AB?) 1s the same as the question (is CA-BD?)
but not that it is the same as (CD?). That 1s, we have to add
the reason for the dependence of C's bemg D on A's being B,
in order to express the hypothetical statement in terms of the
identity of one question with another. If, then, we only state
that C 1s D, 1£ A is B, without the connecting reason, we cannot
identify something relating solely to C and D with the question
whether A can be B.
Hypothetical State1Kefd and A,gument ssr
What is adequate, then, is to say that the form or answer
to the question (AB?) is identical with the question whether
A is B and C is D, owing to the real implication of the real
elements A, B, C, and D. This exactly covers the hypo•
thetical statement. For, if C is not D, the question whether
A is B and C is D has a negative answer and therefore the
question (AB?) has a negative answer, that is, 'if C is not D,
A is not B '. But if the answer to the question (CD?) is affirma•
tive, it does not follow that that to (whether A is B and C is
D?) is affirmative, and therefore not that the answer to (AB?)
is affirmative. This corresponds to the usual expression that if
C is D, it does not follow that A is B. Thus the hypothetical
argument, if A is B, C is D, and if C is D, E is F, &c., may be
correctly put in the form of the corresponding questions. We
may, however, ass1mrlate this to the usual form more closely if
for 'the question whether A 1s B 1s the same as the question
whether A is B and C is D' we substitute 'the question whether
A is B is the same as the question whether C is D and something
else is true', This exactly covers the usual hypothetical state•
ments, and the conclusion will be 'the question whether A is B
is true is identical with the question whether E is F and some•
thing else '. The argument, then, is a relative argument, that is,
the relation of two terms to one another by means of their
relation to a third. We can put it strictly as follows:
The problem whether A is B includes the problem whether
C is D.
Th!! problem whether C is D includes the problem whether
Eis F •
•·. The problem whether A is B includes the problem whether
Eis F.
And this form of argument cannot he reduced to a syllogism,
§ 311. We thus reach the conclusion that the assertion many
hypothetical statement is that one problem includes another or
that one question is identical with another and that the grounds
of this connexion or relation are based on non-problematic con•
siderations. These latter are implied but not stated explicitly
in the hypothetical statement. If A is B, C is D is grounded, for
example, on the non-hypothetical implication that C is A and
B is D, and means not that we imagine or suppose or assume
INFERENCE
that A is B i not that the supposition C is D follows from the
supposition A is B, but that the question whether A is B is
identical with the question whether A, which presupposes C, is B
which necess1tates D, or whether AC is BD, inasmuch as C is A,
and B is D. That is the full expression of our thought. If the
thought is not fully expressed (is expressed, that is, without the
ground of connexion, as '1f _A is B, C is D '), the adequate ex·
pression is 'the question or problem whether A is B is identical
with that whether C is D as well as A is B '. A relation, onC'C
more, of problems, not of statements.
VII
DIRECT AND INDIRECT ARGUMENT
THE FICTIONS OF MODERN MATHEMATICS
§ 312. As the forms of language encourage certain mistakes
about the nature of hypothetical thinking, the question arises
how far they are to be observed and whether they are capable
of modification. Ilypothet1cal thinking 1s so common in ordinary
life that there can be no idea of using a merely technical and
'artificial' set of expressions. But some of the misleading
expressions are unnecessary and the ordinary language provides
the right ones. Thus the causal form of the hypothetical which
sometimes occurs in a reductio ad absurdum proof is unnecessary
and can be discarded. We need not put '1f A is B, C is D' in
the erroneous forms 'since A 1s B, C is D' or 'because A is B,
C IS D'.
The case 1s somewhat different w1th such expressions as
'assume', 'suppose', '1magme'. We have already pointed out
the natural meamng of 'suppose'.
It clearly must have passed to a different meaning, if usable
at all, when applied to an hypothesis which we do not suppose
to be true, the consequence of which we are investigating. We
have not decided here either way. The same is true. of 'assume'.
There is a sense of 'assume' (as applied to a doubtful or hypo•
thetical matter) in which it 1mphes a dec1s1on ; and we must
be careful here to avoid a confusion. The same is true of
'suppose', but yet it is more usual with 'assume' than 'suppose'.
A man is uncertain which of two poss1b1hties for him is true
and they concern a matter in which action has to be taken.
He has to decide how to act, which means that he must act as
if one or other were true. If he decides to act m one way, he
acts and decides to act as if one or other of these alternatives
were the true one. In that sense he decides for one alternative,
and only in that sense. He does not decide that it is true ;
that is an impossible feat. He does not think that it is true ;
554 INFERENCE
that also we have seen to be an impossible feat. He may
suppose it to be the more probable alternative.
There is another case of decision which may seem rather
theoretical than practical. Of two alternatives a man may
choose one to argue from and to develop its consequences. For
example, in certain chemical or biological investigations where
a man may have to choose between conducting one set of experi•
ments and another, or between treating the living body in one
way and another. Slbch dec1S1ons, however, are clearly practical,
for theoretically he would conduct, 1f possible, alternative experi•
ments. Herc we may say that a man acts on the assumption
that one alternative is true rather than another.
Putting aside these uses of 'assume' and 'suppose' as obviously
inapplicable to the case where we say '1f A 1s B, C is D ', without
either decidmg practically in favour of the alternative that A is
B, or thinkmg 1t probable, we may ask what it is that corre•
sponds to the expression 'let us suppose (or ' suppose') A is B
and see what follows'. These words arc nothmg but a way of
proposing a problem for consideration ; they really mean 'let
us fix our attention upon the question whrther A 1s B, and ask
what follows if A is really B '. We shall then see that 'if ' mtrudes
itself and therefore can't possibly be replaced by 'suppose'.
This 'let us suppose' is, then, really a way of proposing some
definite problem ; m other words it is a kmd of decision, viz. to
consider one aspect of a problem. It is so much more convenient
to use the short than the long expression which appears to
be the legitimate one, and this m language is a scarcely
resistible consideration, and usage will be too much for us. For
ordinary purposes we may therefore retain such expressions as
'suppose', 'supposing that', 'let us suppose', 'let us assume', &c.,
remembermg of course what they really stand for ; but it will
be imperative in a philosophical investigation, or where there
is a possibility of confusion, to substitute the true equivalents.
The urgent necessity of the latter will appear m the subject we
are now approaching, the treatment of reductio ad absurdum
arguments. The confusion caused by not doing so is mainly
re!ponsible for the modern pseudo-mathematical monstrosity of
non-Euclidean space. There is no need in any scientific argu•
ment to use these somewhat misleading expressions 'assume' or
Di,ect and Indi,ect A,gument 555
'suppose'. Their legitimate use is really for the decisions we
have mentioned.
§ 313. The true view of hypothetical statement and reasoning
is obscured by a certain misleading use of language, which 1s
found in the ordinary scientific representations of a reductio ad
absurdum proof.
The reductio ad absurdum proof, stated in the way we criti-
cized above, usually begins thus, 'assume A is B ', then follows
'because A is B and B JS C, therefore A is C ; but A is not C,
therefore A is both C and not C '. Now we could not in fact
advance to the conclusion usually suhJomed, 1f the first premiss
really corresponded to the verbal forms in which it is put. We
have to restore the hypothetical form which we have verbally
suppressed before we can make another step; we have to say
'therefore if A is B, A JS both C and not C ; which latter is
impossible, therefore A is not B '. That is, we have to remember
that there was no real premiss 'because A is B ', and that what
we really meant was '1f A is B, then because B is C, A will
be C'. Now misleading expressions hke 'assume A is B',
which put quite a false complexion on thought, inclme people
to think they have 'supposed' A to be B, and hence that they
somehow start with a 'conception' of A's bemg B. To avoid
this danger the 'if ' should be restored throughout the reductio
ad absurdum argument.
§ 314. It must not be supposed that the form of the reductio
ad absurdum is peculiar to a particular kind of matter.
We can replace any reductio ad absurdum argument with its
hypothetical premisses and hypothetical inference by an argu•
ment entirely non-hypothetical 1 We infer 'if A is B, then in
general C is D ', and 'C is D' is known to be false Then it
follows unhypothetically from C is not D that A ts not B, and
the steps of the non-hypothetical proof can all be obtained by
a sort of inversion of the reductio ad absurdum proof. This
brings out its true characteristics. Starting with our question
I §§ IOS, 259 II
[ 11 Cf note to§ 259 If the matter 1s so simple, 1t may well be asked why
the incbrect argument should be used. On this, see § 316. In the author's
du-ect proof of Euclid 1 7, observe the last step, which certainly seems to be
indirect]
11773-a L
INFERENCE
whether A is B, we conduct an inquiry represented by a train
of hypothetical inferences till we arrive at a criterion which
decides the answer to our question. Now the reductio ad absur-
dum proof represents the process by the system of hypothetical
inference till it terminates in the hypothetical contradiction to
a known truth, which then serves as criterion. The non-
hypothetical proof consists m applying the criterion simply,
which of course is done in a system of non-hypothetical rcasonJng.
We may illustrate by a particular instance, drawn from the
Seventh Propos1t10n of Euclid's Elements, Book I. The truth
which it 1s desired to establish 1s that 'on the same base and
on the same side of 1t, there cannot be two triangles having their
sides which arc terminated at one extremity of the base equal,
and likewise those terminated at the other extremity, equal'.
The reductio ad absurdum proof given in Euclid runs as follows :
If A= B, then a+p = y.
But a+P > p.
Therefore y > {3.
Agam, 1f C = D, ,,+a= fJ.
Therefore, 1£ A = B and C = D,
fJ(= r+a) <r-
Therefore "Y > y+ a.
Thus the part would be greater than
the whole
Therefore A cannot - B, and C at the same time = D.
The corresponding non-hypothetical proof runs as follows :
Make A - B, and JOtn the cxtrem1ties of AB, by C and D,
to the other extremity of the base.
Take as before vertices external to each other's triangle.
Reqmred to prove that C cannot be equal to D.
Then, if A • B, a +{J = y.
But a+{J > {J,
Therefore "Y > {J.
But y+a > ,,, and,,> {J,
Therefore ,, +a > {J.
Therefore the sides of the triangle of which y + a and p are
base angles are unequal. Q. E. D.
The last step 1s that unequal angles at the base necessitate
Di,ect antl Indi,ect .A,gument 551
unequal sides. It is important to see that this last step is non•
hypothetical and is mistakenly represented as resting upon a
reductio ad ab1urdum proof.
It would be proved by a reductio ad absurdum proof as follows :
If the sides were equal, then the angles would be equal. But
the angles are not equal. Therefore if the sides were equal, the
angles would be both equal and not equal. But by the principle
of contradiction this is impossible. Therefore the sides are
unequal. This is a mere illusory and unnecessary transforma•
tion of argument. It is always futile to appeal to the principle
of contradiction as if it were a &pecial premiss to be used on
a special occasion. For, so far as any premiss depends on it,
every premiss depends on it equally, and every premiss would
fail, if the prmc1ple of contradiction were not observed.
The general form of the above argument is this. Let A be
a condition of B. If B 1s absent A 1s absent, because if B were
absent and A were present, B would be present and not present,
which by the prmc1ple of contradict10n 1s impossible. Now the
fact 1s that the thing to be proved 'if a thmg is absent, its con-
dition A 1s absent', 1s absolutely sclf-ev1dcnt. It is an inseparable
aspect of the fact that A 1s the cond1t10n of B · and a false
argument always arises when we try to prove the self-evident.
We really only base 1t on itself in the negative form and so
bring in the principle of contradiction. You can indeed only
argue from the pnnc1ple of contradiction as a premiss by usmg
the prmc1ple of contradiction and so ad infinitum. In the
present mstance, smce the angles at the base of an isosceles
triangle arc equal, 1t follows immediately that when the angles
are not equal the sides are not equal. The latter follows
directly : there 1s no hypothetical reasoning m the matter.
Thus what we have done in the non-hypothetical argument is
to use precisely the same material as we used before in the
hypothetical form of proof; inasmuch as the proposition that
unequal angles at the base necessitate unequal sides is simply
a necessary aspect of the truth contamed in the statement that
equal sides necessitate equal angles.
§ 315. The general proof that a reductio ad absurdum argument
may be always expressed without a reductio ad absurdum can
L2
558 INFERENCE
be put rigorously as follows. As a preliminary it is necessary
to prove the following theorem.
Suppose that we have the argument:
(I} If A is B, C 1s D ;
(2) But C is not D, therefore A is not B.
This argument is self-evident as it stands and is an ultimate
form, not requiring a reductio ad absurdum. In the reductio ad
absurdum form it would be
(3) If C is not D, and A is B, C is both D (from (1) above)
and not D.
(4) But C is both D and not D is not true ; therefore C is
not D and A 1s B is not true.
Here (1) and (2) have the form, 1£ P 1 is true P 1 is true; but
P 1 is untrue, therefore P 1 is untrue. But this is precisely the
form we have m (3) and (4) Thus, mstcad of provmg the form
represented m (1) and (2), we have merely repeated it in (3)
and (4). Thus we can't help makmg this form ultimate and
self-evident.
In any reductio ad absurdum proof the argument depends on
a proposition or system of propositions non-hypothetical in form
and given as true Let this propos1t1on or system be represented
by P 1 • Let Q1 be our question or problem. Let 1t follow from
P 1 that if Q1 1s affirmed (or true), R1 1s true. Let R 1 necessitate
P 2 as true. Then, if Qi is true, P 1 is true Let 1t be known
that Pa 1s untrue. Hence Q1 1s untrue. This may be reversed
as follows: P 1 is untrue, therefore R 1 is untrue, therefore Q1 is
untrue. By the theorem we have just proved none of these
reverse steps will involve a reductio ad absurdum proof. It is
important to point out that Q1 may itself be a system : and it
would be better to repeat the proof for this case.
Let P 1 be true. Let our problem or question be whether
Q1, Q1, Q8, &c., are to be affirmed. Let Q1, Q1, Q8, &c , in
virtue of P 1 , necessitate R 1 , R2 , R 3 , &c, i. e that 1f Q1 be true
it necessitates R 1 , that Q2 s1mtlarly necessitates R 1 , &c. Further
let R1, R1, R8 together necessitate P.11. Let P.11 be untrue, and
it follows that if Q1, Q2 , Q3 are affirmed together P 2 is true ;
but P 1 is not true; therefore Q1, Q1, Q3 can't all be true or
affirmed together.
This may now be put non-hypothetically. Pa is untrue,
Direct and Indirect Argument 559
therefore R 1, R 1, R 8 can't all be true: therefore Q1, Q1, Q1
can't all be true. Here as before the reverse steps don't imply
a reductio ad absurdum, '
We may apply this to Euclid's proposition, I. vii.
The angles at the base of an isosceles triangle are equal.
(Q1) therefore 1£ A - B, ,- =a.+ fJ (R1 ),
{R1) and 1£ C = D, fJ = y+ll (Q1).
Therefore, if A - Band C = D, a.+/J =rand fJ - r+a.
Therefore ,, > r + a.
Therefore 1f A= B and C .. D, r >,, +a.
But y is not greater than y +a.
Therefore A - B and C = D can't both be true.
To reverse this process we must begm by showing that from
r + 8 > y 1t follows that a.+ fJ = y and y + ll = fl can't both be true.
Now ,- +a> y, hence, 1£ y +ll - x, y cannot be equal to a
magnitude greater than x. Therefore 1t 1s impossible that
,-+a - fl and at the same time r = a.+fl. I e. from ,-+a >Y
follows 1mmed1atcly that r + 1l = fJ and ,- = a.+ fJ cannot both be
true. Therefore a condition of y + ll being equal to {J, and
a cond1t1on of y bcmg equal to a.+ fJ cannot be simultaneously
realized. Hence it follows that A - B and C - D cannot be
true together.
Now this has exactly the form y + a > y, •·• a.+ fJ = y and
f3 - y + ll arc not both true, wherefore A - B and C - D are
not both true; and thus 1t exactly reverses the steps of the
hypothetical reasomng.
§ 316. We observe Ill the first stage of this last argument
a certain art1fic1ahty, 1£ we suppose ourselves to start absolutely
with the non-hypothetical and not to have the hypothetical
argument before us. The statement that 1£ one magmtude is
greater than a second, &c., 1s of course true ; but the question
is, why should 1t occur to us and why should we know 1t to be
of any use? Secondly, even granted this statement, why should
we give x the value {J? For any magmtude whatever will do
for the purposes of the statement itself. Agam, why should we
take a.+ fJ for the magnitude greater than x?
It 1s here important to remark that this kind of difficulty as
to why we should select a particular premiss, the justification
of which 1s not seen till we have got the conclusion, is not at
560 INFERENCE
lJn IllIIII
A C B
rill 11 IIrrr.
A
02
III
THE AXIOMS OF MODERN INDUCTION
§ 346 A COMMON characteristic of all the current definitions
of Induction sccmc; to be the implication that the conclusion
must be wHIC'r than the premisses. It 1s easy to see, even from
the- adm1ss1on of such an mducttomst as M111, 1 that this is not
true of the so-called Experimental Methods. These imply certain
maJor premisses"' (clauses, so to speak, of the law of the uni-
formity of nature) far wider than the particular conclusions
drawn from tlwm Ly the help of the parllcular experiences used
in the mfcrenccc; It may seem at first sight that an inductive
clement 1s ldt 1n the cnumeratio simplex argument from which
these maJor premisses arc suppoc;cd to be derived. And if we
take the pomt of view of the mduct10nists themselves, they
would have on their own showmg to admit that the only
inductive part of the new methodc; is precisely that supposed
antiquated form of lncluct10n winch the<,e new methods are to
supplant. But \\e muc;t take away even tins last claim. It is
an 11lus1on to clcc;cribc the enumeratio simplex inference as a pro-
cess in wlnrh the conclusion 1c; an advance m generality upon
the premisses \Ve have srcn that such a statement is due to
an J.nalys1s "luch 1s not ultimate, and that ultimate analysis
involvcc; a UlllVl•r-,,11 axiom winch is parallel to the universal
axioms used for the experimental methods ; the latter axioms
being only cases of the former. But, apart from this, we can
show that the Inductive logic ic; not only mvolved m the
contradiction ,1bovc described, but also that 1t 1s involved m
more scriouc; contrad1ct1on by the manner m which the enu-
meratto simplex method 1s made to supplement the new methods.
On this pomt our obJections will not be merely formal m
character. We shall be able to show that the new methods
would have an uncertamty which the mductionists have not
suspected, and that actually they could not, on their own showing,
1 System of Logic, III. xxvn
["' Note a p 585 ]
Failu,e of Induction 6o7
be so trustworthy as the old method which they profess to
replace.
§ 347. Such inductionists as Mill admit that their induction
depends entirely upon the Axiom of Universal Causation. The
axiom bemg found by enum.eratio simplex, we ask how a process
described 1 as 'loose and uncertam' can prove the validity of
an axiom which 1s the foundation of processes supposed to be
methodical and satisfactory It 1s really clear that it could not
give a satisfactory proof and could not account for our convic-
tion that the necessary connexion of events is universal and
knows no exception. And 1t is a sign of the truth of this that
Mill 1s unable to mamtam this part of his theory without con-
tradiction. If we ask why a process wluch he condemns as
falhble should be admitted to prove tlus most important axiom,
his first reply is that the case 1s exceptional. This enumeratio
simplex can be rehed upon, because of the immense quantity
of the premisses We should naturally suppoc,e therefore that
Mill believed both that the principle of causation was universal1y
true and that this exceptional form of the ancient mductlon was
enough to establish 1t. Indeed he says 2 that 'the law of causa-
tion, for instance, and the principles of number and of geometry,
are duly and satisfa.ctonly proved by that method alone, nor
are they susceptible of any other proof'. Mill must mean by
'duly and sat1sfactonly proved' that the conclus1on, the law of
umversal causation, 1s absolutely true as a matter of fact and
that the proof of 1t 1s as vahd as a proof m geometry. Tlus
agrees so far as 1t relates to the mathematical axioms with what
he had said earlier : 8 'These arc rigorously true, even beyond
any possible experiences of ours.' a And so of the axiom of
causation (Jaw of universal causation) he says, 'we may . . •
1 Mill, 1 C • III XXl, §2 I 1b. § 3 • 1b , II v1 [see note a].
[" Th1s quotation, the reference for which 1s given m the author's typescnpt
and m the various lecture notes as Mill, System of Logic, II v1, I have not been
able to venfy. It was sometimes cited as' even beyond the lnwts of our
possible expenence •. The difficulty is that Mill's doctrmc m th.ls chapter
1s that axioms are dcnved from cxpencnce, and he 1s expressly speaking even
in regard to number of • all ob1ccts known to our expenence ' In III. v, § I,
1t 1s true, he says, ' In the laws of number, then, and m those of space, we
recognize . . the rigorous un1versahty of wluch we are m quest • ; but tlu.s
is consistent with his arguments elsewhere as to their ongm 1n experience 1
6o8 SPECIAL LOGIC
regard the certainty of that great induction as not merely com-
parative but, for all practical purposes, complete' .1 Yet at the
end of the chapter, m the course of which the uncertainty of
the method has been gradually growing upon him, he denies
that we may rely upon the law beyond the possible range of
our experience, c;aying 'In distant parts of the stellar regions,
where the phenomena may be entirely unhke those with which
we are acquainted, 1t would be folly to affirm confidently \hat
this general Ia.w prevails ' 2 Observe the contrast to his earlier
language in the same chapter . 'It is therefore an empirical law
coextensive with all human cxpcnence; at which point the
distinction between empirical laws and laws of nature vanishes.' 8
Clearly, m the later passage, he has become aware of the
untruth of what he said earlier, and rcahzed that all human
experience 1s not therefore coextensive with all nature. Again
in the cac;c of m.i.th<'mat1cs, the axioms of which he says are
duly and hahsfactonly proved by the same proof as the principle
of causation, he has affirmed 4 that we can rely upon them JUSt
in those chstant parts of the st cllar rrg10ns of which we can
have no experience "
Finally, m a note at the end of this same chapter, he rejects
his own doctrine m crit1r1zing Tame. Agamst Taine he says
that he can't sec how m 'interpreting in general language the
testimony of experience, the limitations of the testimony itself
can be cast off' ; though tlus 1s exactly what he himself did in
the carlrnr part of the chapter The contradiction is complete.
The truth seems to be that when Mdl has h1s attention fixed
on the obJcct1vc fart of causation he can't help feeling certain
about 1t, ancl t hcrcforc 1s obliged to think that the only method
wluch his ph1lobopl11c c;ystem allows him for estabhshmg 1t must
be satisfactory. On the other hand, when his attention is fixed
upon the mfcrcnt1al process, he sees that it is unsatisfactory
1 M11l, I c , III 'Uu, § 4, para 2 • 1b , last para. of ch. xxi.
1 1b , § 3, para 2, sub fin
• ' That a straight !me IS the shortest distance between two points, we do
not doubt to be true even m the region of the fixed stars.' 1 c, III. hi,
I 3, para 3
[& Notice, however, Mill's own caveat m the note to this section ]
Failure of Emf,iricism 6og
and so now, to save his philosophy, he has to throw doubt on
the conclusion of the process.
§ 348. To return to the exact form of the proof of the law of
causation by enumeratio simplex inference. First, what are the
premisses? In the nature of the case they must be of the form
'This A causes this a', 'This B causes this /J', &c. 1 with the
generalizations 'all events have effects'; and similarly, 'all
events have causes'. Now how can we get premisses of this
form? They can't be got by the four methods: for these methods
presuppose the axiom of all induction. They can't be given by
direct observation : for, as Hume contended and as empiricists
must and do admit, we can't observe causal connexion. Indeed
if we could observe A causmg a we should not need the methods :
for the meaning of these methods 1s that they arc to remedy
this defect of observation, and the analysis of the experimental
methods shows that the inductiomsts assume that we can observe
antecedents and consequents alone.
Where, then, do the premisses come from~ In this philosophy
there can be only one answer, from enumeratio simplex. This
is implicitly admitted 1 by Mill, though he seems 1,Lraightway
to forget the admission and its serious consequences. We notice
first, then, that this enumeratzo simplex, so far from being
founded on the facts observed, is founded upon premisses ;
premisses which are themselves not observed facts, but each of
them an inference from another enumeratio simplex. Enumeratio
simplex proof, then, of the law of the uniformity of Nature,
instead of being a peculiarly mfalhble form of enumeratio sim-
plex, is a specially fallible one. For, besides the uncertainty which
belongs to the final proof by enumeratio simplex, there is also
the uncertainty which attaches to each of its numerous apphca·
tions to prove the premisses. There is not one inference of this
nature concerned, but a great number ; and, unlike the ordmary
enumeratio simplex proof, there must be a doubt attaching to
each premiss, since 1t is got by an admittedly uncertain method.
But we see the fallibility to be still greater when we look at the
form of the various appbcations of this mode of proof to prove
the premisses. How are we to prove that A1 causes a1 ? Not
from the observation of A causing a at any time, but only from
• 1 c., III. xXJ, § a.
610 SPECIAL LOGIC
the observation of A followed by a, Thus the conclusion 'A
causes a' involves two processes, each inconclusive : first, the
inconclusive generalization from 'A preceded a on the occasions
observed• to •A is always followed by a' ; and secondly, by
the fallacious introduction of a new conception not contained
in the premisses, 1 e Lhe conception of causality. For whereas
the premisses mm,t uc 'A is followed by a', &c., the conclusion
is 'A causes a'. The falhbdity of the ordmary proof by 1nµ-
meratio simplex, 10stead of bcmg removed or mitigated, is, so
to speak, multrplred by itself.
§ 349. We can now tabulate the whole process:
(1) There is an experience of the type ' A preceded a, as often
as observed '.
(ii) There ts an enumeratio simplex 10fcrcncc from many such
10stances to the conclus1011 • A causes a ' ; and s1mdarly
'B cause,; /3 ', &c, &c
(111) The results of thu, unsr1cnttfic 10ductton give the premisses
for another 10durtron, ah,o an enumeraho simplex infer-
ence, winch has for its conclusion the axiom of the
umfornuty of 11.1ture or the bw of universal causation.
(iv) After tlus come the processes of the four experimental
methods, based upon the results of the second mduct1on ;
thcmi,elvcs, though deductive m form, ~lled 10ductions ;
and these constitute the supposed scientific lnduct10n.
Now these methods yield conclusions of exactly the same
form as those arrived at 10 the second stage by the
unscienllfic Induction. Modern Induction, then, claims
that the conclusions m tlus fourth stage are more trust-
worthy than those 10 the second i,tage. Thus 'C causes
'Y' 111 stage (1v) 1s more trustworthy than 'A causes a'
10 stage (11)
Now obviously the conclusion cannot be more certain than
its premisses ; and if the method is uncerta101 the conclusion
must be less certa10 than its premisses But the 10ference in
the experimental methods 1s not certa10, because we cannot be
certam of the facts of observation. Thus the conclusions of the
new induction are less certain than the axiom of Umformity.
This axiom again cannot be more certain than its premisses and,
the method of 1ts der1vat1on being admittedly not rigorous, must
Faitu,e of Emp;,ricism 6II
be less certain than its premisses ; but these premisses are just
the results of the unscientific induction. Thus a fortiori the
results of the scientific mduction are less certain than these last
premisses ; are less certain, that is, than the unscientific induc•
bon. Thus the conclusions of the new induction are two degrees
less reliable than those of the old. It follows that the only
rational procedure would be to abandon the methods, go straight
to experience, and use the unscientific induction.
§ 350. The question of the plurality of causes is part of a larger
question, the relation of the cond1t1on, whether temporal or not,
to what it conditions. We tend to assume a certain pnority of
cond1t1on over consequent and to look on the former as active
and the latter as passive. The cond1tton, then, seems to have
a complete hold over what 1t conditions, so that the result must
follow, whereas the result 1s not thought of as havmg the same
hold over the condition which precedes. A fact 1s not conceived
as compelling the existence of 1ts own condition in a particular
case, though appan:ntly it is concc1vcd as necess1tatmg some
condition or other, an adm1ss1on of the last importance. The
view is erroneous and probably clue mainly to tlus idea of
superior activity m the concl1tion which specially suggests itself
when the condition 1s temporal ; for, as such, 1t has apparently
a prerogative and superiority of existence over an as yet non·
existent result. Thus, when the relation is of sequence, il seems
a kind of paradox to represent the not yet existmg result as the
cond1t1on of what 1s ex1stmg There 1s a further corroboration
of the erroneous view in the doctrine of the plurality of causes,
which means that the same effect may at different times be
produced by different causes. Moreover, what is very important,
the view thus suggested by experience gets support from a general
a prion opinion about the rcla.tlon of the cond1tio11 to what 1t
conditions ; an opinion based on the fact that the hypothetical
proposition, as such, cannot be converted. From '1f A, then B'
we cannot infer '1f B, then A' , thus A seems to control the
existence of B but the converse does not seem to be true. Even
in this abstract form the condit1omng clause seems to have some
superior force.
§ 351. We shall try to show first that the relation of the
condition to the cond1tioncd 1s not one-sided ; and that the
61z SPECIAL LOGIC
conditioned has the same hold over the condition as the condi•
tion is usually thought to have over it; and, secondly, that the
illusion of a plurahty of causes is due to imperfect observation.
In such a question we must begin with something admitted
to be necessary. We shaJl therefore start from the fact that,
while it is thought that an effect may have different causes, the
ordmary observer is sure that the same cause cannot .h;we
different cffcctc;, or that the same cond1t1on, as essence say, will
necessitate the same result, say as property. In this lies the
key to our problem.
Suppose A rond1tions a : A docs that in virtue of its own
nature, 1 and the reason why B conditions fJ lies just in the
difference of the nature of B from the nature of A. It is self-
evidt"nt that the definite nature of A must, as definite, condition
not something mdcterminate, but a perfectly definite nature such
as a. We may get the same result negatively. If A conditions
now a, now /J, then there must be a reason for the difference
and that reac;on would constitute a difference between the two
<' u.ci. of A. Thus these two rnses were wrongly supposed to be
identical. Now tlus 1s doubtless the ground for the certainty
we assign to the propos1t1on that the same cause must have the
same effect. But exactly the same argument must necessitate
that a definite R determmes for itself a defimte C. • It is admitted
that a. must have !,0me condition, i.e. its nature necessitates
some cond1t1on 1 but necessity cannot possibly be indeterminate
and thu~ the detcrmmate nature of a. must necessitate a deter-
minate comhtlon. a as identical with itself and different from
fJ determmcs from its own nature a connexion with A, as dis-
tmguishc<l from any other clement such as B: and so with /l.
Again, ncgat1Vl'ly, 1£ this were not so, we should have to suppose
that the nature of a at least determined that it must have one
or other of a certain kmd of (."Ond1tions ; and, if we assume that
it docs not determmc a particular one, there wall be nothmg at
all to decide which shall cond1t10n 1t m a particular instance.
Further, if there were anything which did so decide, that would
constitute a difference between the two cases of a. Or to put
it otherwise ; 1f the given cond1t1ons were all equally indeter-
minate, a could not come about at all. We see in fact that,
I _, ai,,-6.
[• R = result, C = cause.)
Failure of Efflf>incism
just as the definiteness of the condition necessarily determines
a definite nature in the conditioned, so the definite nature of
the conditioned must determine a definite nature in the con•
ditioning. If the argument connecting the definite thing condi•
tioned with the definite condition is correct, so must the converse
be also, for the reasoning is exactly the same. Consequently,
when the contrary seems true, there must be some difference
in the conditioned or the difference in the condition is only
apparent. The instance of a conditioned by x cannot be the
same as the instance of a conditioned by y ; for otherwise it
would be true that the difference between x and y would have
nothmg to do with the identical part of a, and that which really
had to do with it must be identical in the apparently different
conditions x and y. Thus, either the cond1t1oned is not really
the same, or the cond1t1on was not different in the two cases,
so far as it was a cond1t1on m each. The argument is self·
evident and the difficulty would never have occurred but for
certain appearances which we must now consider.
§ 352. • Consider first the • condition ' in an hypothetical state•
ment. We have already seen that m geometrical science a pro·
perty of a figure is derived from its full essence or definition
and that, 1{ the proof has its completest form, the property can
always be shown to condition the essence. 1 In other words, the
hypothetical proposition in these cases 1s convertible. This is
important because in geometry we see into the necessity of the
connexion of the conditioning and the cond1t1oned. Thus, in
a case where we understand the connexion, there 1s no plurality
but the relation of condition and conditioned 1s reciprocal. It
1s significant that the case which causes our main difficulty
relates to that species of necessity where we do not understand
the nature of the connexion but only establish that there is a.
connexion. So too for the ' cond1t1on ' of an hypothetical state•
ment; we can easdyshowthat this 1s compatible with the doctrine
we have laid down and indeed follows from it, and that the pos•
sibility of conversion depends merely on sufficient knowledge.
Suppose A to be the true condition of C : then C conditions
A, as in the case of a reciprocal relation in geometry. Now
I § 258.
[• ' In re-wntmg this section, the sense of cause as not merely event (as in
Hume and Mill) but as comhtion must be discussed.' MS. not,.]
SPECIAL LOGIC
suppose that we have A and B connected together in experience
and let AB - %. Then 1t would be true that if x exists, C is
existing ; since x contams A, which conditions C ; but it will
not be true thJ.t, 1£ C exists, x exists. The reason is obvious.
Conly necessitates A and not B, which 1s also in x. This is why
the statement of the connexion 1s not convertible, i.e. because
the protasis of the conditional statement 1s not the truc.apd
accurate condition of the apodosis, but something more This
1s just what happens m a mathematical proof when a proposition
1s not convertible , more than the true condition has been
admitted into the protasis. Thus, when the cond1t1onal pro-
pos1tton expresses m 1ls protas1s the true condition of the
apodosis and no more, the proposition is always convertible. 1
§ 353. It 1s clear that the forcgomg investigation explams
many cases of the apparent plurality of causes : that so far as
tlie&e vanom, causes arc causes of somcthmg 1dent1cal, so far
they them,;elves are 1dent1cal. They differ only m what is
irrelevant to the effect, and 1t 1s the busme~s of science to
discover the 1dcnllty by clumnatmg the irrelevant, just as
mathematics discovers the true cond1t1on by chmmatmg the
irrelevant pa.rt~ of the protac;1s
There arc, however, othrr way'! m which the same false
appearance 1s produced. Suppose the condition of x (state,
process or event) 1s abed, where every clement is necessary to
x. Suppose only a portion of abed 1s realized, say bed : then x
will not Le there. Suppose now a 1s added· then x wdl be
there and 1t will seem as though a was the cause of x. S1mdarly,
1£ aed 1s realized, x appears when b is added, and thus x will
seem to have a or b or c or d as its causes. In fact the condition
was really always the same, 1. e. abed.
There 1s another case wluch 1s more important, because more
illusory. Suppose x 1s destroyed, not ongmated · now suppose
the condition of x 1s abed, each clement bcmg necessary ; then,
1f any one, e. g a, 1s removed, x disappears and similarly with
bed ; thui:, the d1s.ippearance of x may seem to have a plurality
of causes. Now, obviously, v. lule the cause of the existence of
x 1s always one and the same, the cause of its disappearance
1 In tlus section the term hypothetical statement has been employed in
accordance with ordinary usage Dut the more correct term here 1s c01tddt01fal
statement Cf § 293
Failu,e of Empi,icism 615
is one and the same ; it is always the destruction of abed as
a combination. The completion of abed the cause of .x, by
addmg a to bed or b to aed, &c., is exactly parallel to the process
of destroying the cause by taking away a or b or e or d. It
may seem, however, that, whereas m the first case the addition
of a is not the cause, because a by itself is not sufficient and
x only results because of the existence of the complete complex
of conditions abed, m the second case-the negative case-the
destruction of .x, the removal is rightly accounted the cause,
inasmuch as the removal of a is sufficient to destroy x, quite
irrespectively of the absence or presence of the other conditions
bed But tlus 1s untrue. If the other conditions, bed, were not
all present, x could not be m existence and so the destruction of
x would not take place as a result of the removal or destruction
of a. Thus the removal of a can only result m the destruction of
x, because of a'c; relation to the rcmammg cond1t1ons bed, and
therefore 1s not a sufficient cause m itself, irrespective of their
existence They must be m existence if the removal of a 1s to
result m the removal of x. The destruction of .x, when a is
removed, only takes place on the disc;olution of the relation
between a and bed, Just as the produc-tion of .x, when a is added,
only takes place through the establishment of the relation
between a and bed. Thus, as the true cause of the production
of x is always the organic complex abed and not any element
of the complex, so the dc&truct1on of .x has always for its cause
the destruction of the orgamc complex abed, as an organic
complex. This is the solution of the stock mstance of the
different causes of death. Life depends on the co-operation of
certain elements orgamcally connected, each necessary, none
sufficient. The complex bcmg necessary, the destruction of the
organic connexion causes death and is necessary as the condition
of death. The removal of any one of the clements of the complex
from its connexion with the rest is enough, obviously, to destroy
the organization of the complex. The account which assigns
a plurality of causes to death, then, is a confusion because
there is no consciousness of the distinction between the negative
and positive cases. For the kmd of mistaken consideration, due
to imperfect analysis, which gives rise to the illusion of a plurality
of causes in the negative mstance, the destruction of something,
cannot affect the positive mstance, the production of something.
rva
FAILURE OF EMPIRICISM TO EXPLAIN
THE LAWS OF THOUGHT
• ib., vol 11, § 3J!Z. • Spencer, ib., vol. 11, p. 195 (§ 332 fin ).
1 Spencer, ib , § 332.
618 SPECIAL LOGIC
impression to consciousness, the series of impressions produced
by the arc is felt as larger than the series produced by the
chord. This continues to hold however much the arc is flattened :
so long as 1t has any perceptible curvature at all, it is felt to
be longer than the chord umting its extremes. Parallel experi-
ences are derived from the ocular muscles. Carrying the eye
along the line of the curve yields to consciousness a greater
quantity of sensation than carrymg the eye along the chord
does. As the curve is flattened this difference dimmishes ; but
some of 1t contmues as long as the curve continues appreciable.
Thus the truth that a straight hne 1s the shortest hne between
two points, hes latent m the structures of the eyes and the
nervous centres which receive and co-ordmate visual impressions.
We cannot think otherwise because, during that adjustment
between the organism and the environment which evolution has
establtshed, the mner relations have been so moulded upon the
outer relations that they cannot by any effort be made not to
fit them. Just in the same way that an infant's hand, con•
structed so as to grasp by bendmg th<> fingers mward, implies
ancestral hands which have thus grasped, and 1mphes objects
m the environment to be thus grasped by this mfantme hand
when 1t 1s developed , so the various structures fittmg the mfant
for apprehensions of space-relations, imply such apprehensions
in the past by its ancestors and m the future by itself. And
just aS 1t has become 11nposs1ble for the hand to grasp by
bending the fingers outwards instead of mwarcls ; so has it
become impossible for those nervous actions by wluch we appre-
hend primary space-relations to be reversed so as to enable us
to thmk of these relations otherwise than we do.'
This theory, it may be remarked, does not necessarily imply
that the mmd 1s identical with physical organs, but 1t does
imply that the mind not only perceives by them, but can only
think and 1magme by their means, and 1s therefore restricted
by the functions of which they are capable. Divested of
technicalities unnecessary for our present purpose, it comes to
this. In its early experiences the mind was not obliged to think
the arc greater than its chord. But every arc presented to the
experience of every generation has been greater than its chord :
and the constant perception of this relation gradually modified
Failure of Empiricism 619
the perceiving and thinking organs, so that it became more and
more difficult to think arc and chord in any other relation. The
difficulty transmitted by inheritance became stronger by accu•
mulat1on in successive generations, till it became altogether
impossible to think the contradictory of the axiom. This is
how the individual's bchcf m the axiom is formed, and the
process secures that the subjective behef shall correspond to an
ob1ective fact.
This has an appearance of clearness and simplicity which
recommends it to many.
§ 357. Before asking if it is true, we may ask whether we
should hke 1t to be true. Such a qucsllon may seem unscientific,
but in philosophy at least we should clear our reasonings a good
deal 1£ we confessed to ourselves what we wanted to believe and
what we hoped was untrue.
Now at first sight the theory may well have attractions.
Many will feel that inducllon does not account for the con-
v1ct10n they have had, as far back as they can remember, in
the same strength about axioms · and yet they will feel on the
other hand the force of Mill's obJection-' I must protest', he
says, 'agamst adducing, as evidence of the truth of a fact in
external nature, the d1spos1t10n, however strong or however
general, of the human mmd to believe it.'
The evolutionist view seems to brmg a welcome help and to
show how the desired correspondence between subjective belief
and ob1ecttve fact has been brought about by the operation of
known causes.
No doubt, then, many may think it would at least be a good
thing if it were true. The evolutionist philosopher probably
believes that 1t is a beneficent result of the great law of Evolu-
t10n ; and there may be scientific evolutionists who feel at least
a prejudice in its favour. But let us look a httlc nearer to see
whether we should have cause to congratulate ourselves 1f the
evolutionist philosopher were nght.
The theory that the mmd has become modified by its environ•
ment, and that 1ts functions have become fixed, implies that at
first 1t was not modified and its functions not thus fixed. If
'Just as it has become impossible for the hand to grasp by
bending the fingers outwards instead of inwards ; so has it
!a773 !ii p
620 SPECIAL LOGIC
become impossible for those nervous actions by which we appre•
hend primary space-relations to be reversed so as to enable us
to think of these relations otherwise than we do', then it follows
that once it was poS!tblc that these nervous actions should be
reversed. And what does this mean? It means that the mind
and its organs were so constituted that they were capable of
thinking the contradictory of axioms, for instance, of conceiving
a chord equal to or greater than its arc, or two straight• lines
which enclosed a space, only that tlus capacity was never
developed.
To some this will appear a sufficient reductio ad absurdum,
but I do not propose to take that hne of argument. Let us
rather imagine that such a cond1t1on of the mind is possible.
It will follow that our minds have been deprived of half their
powers beyond recovery. The geometrician, for instance, is cut
off from a field of thought as large as the present science-a field
in which among many other things he would have developed
the properties of those straight Imes which are not the shortest
distance between any two pomts upon themselves.
In fact, in respect of all that is axiomatic, that 1s, of all that
appears self-evident, the whole human race is in the position of
that part of it wluch has lost or never had the use of a particular
sense-the deaf, the hlmd, or the colour-hhnd, or those who
have no ear for music. We are hke the Proteus which m dark
caves has gradually lost the eyes which would be useless to it:
except that we are worse off, for though an obJect for our lost
faculties may never come into our experience, we should
obviously have plenty of employment for them. The same
process has woven a falsehood mto our nervous tissues and so
into our minds: for the confidence we have in axioms is made
to come from our conviction that their contradictories are not
even thinkable, and yet it is shown at the same time that this
is an utter mistake, inasmuch as thought in itself, though not
as developed m us, is capable of thinking these contradictories.
The individual, then, at best has got a true belief at the expense
of entertaining a false behef, and at the expense of the loss of
half his mental powers.
Is this a result to be contemplated with satisfaction?
May one not look for sympathy 1f one confesses to the hope
Failure of Empi,ricism 62:I
that it is not true? Surely it would be one of those things for
which we could not honestly say we were thankful. At best it
would be a matter for resignation and not for gratitude. We
may bow to it as an inevitable decree of nature ; we deceive
ourselves if we say we can see it is good and desirable. The
pessimist would find another instance of Nature's unkindness.
Even where she seems to confer a benefit, she has done us a deep
injury. She has mutilated our mmds with a refinement of
cruelty. For instead of mercifully concealing a loss which could
only be deplored and never repaired, she has evolved the philo-
sophy which has betrayed the secret.
And is there really any compensation?
If we have gamed a behcf which happens to be true, can we
be said to understand it if we ground it on a falsehood. Can
we be said to 'know' at all in the proper sense of the word ?
Can a belief be even mtclbgent which is simply caused by the
want of a power to thmk otherwise, a power which might have
been developed and 1s lost to us by a process as unconscious
as that which deprives us of taste or smell when we have a cold?
In ordinary bfe, when we are not philosopluzmg, we have a great
contempt for beliefs which are merely the result of imperfect
mental development ; we expect them among savage tribes, the
prejudiced, and the uneducated.
§ 358. An attempt has been made to remove a bias in favour
of the evolution theory. If the attempt were successful, it must
be admitted that 1t would create a bias against the theory : and
there is all the more reason to try to take a purely scientific
attitude and ask whether we have to believe whether we hke
it or not.
In the first place attention must be expressly called to the
fact that this is a theory of knowledge. It does not explain
merely how we come by a belief, but how that belief is true ;
that is, how we have knowledge.
I will read a passage to make this clear : 1 ' Hence the incon-
ceivableness of its negation is that which shows a cognition to
possess the highest rank-is the criterion by which its unsur-
passable validity is known. If the negation of a cognition is
conceivable, the discovery of this amounts to the discovery that
1 Spencer, op cit., § 426
P2
SPECIAL LOGIC
we may or may not accept it. If its negation is inconceivable,
the discovery of this 1s the discovery that we are obliged to
accept it. And a cogmtion, which we arc thus obliged to accept,
is one which we class as having the highest possible certainty.
To assert the mconce1vableness of its negation is at the same
time to assert the psychological necessity we are under of
tlunking it, and to give our logical justification for holding it
to be unquestionable.' '
Other passages to the same effect might be quoted.
§ 359. I begin with an object10n, relating to a matter already
referred to, which perhaps concerns the form of the theory
rather than its essence. The evolutionist docs not seem suffi-
ciently to notice that, while seeming to make mconceivab1hty
an ultimate test or criter10n, he 1s really throwing entire d1scred1t
on the mind's power to conceive or not concmvc as such '
Men do indeed believe firmly when they tlunk the contra•
dictory of their belief mconcc1vable; not as bemg merely
inconceivable for them, but as berng mconrc1vablc for thought
.is SU(.h. For the moment a man is convmced th.it some one
else can conceive what he cannot, he ceases to suppose that his
own state of nund can determmc the truth m the particular
case. Thus a man v,1thout a mm,1cal car nevertheless may
believe th.i.t there 1s surh a tlung as a musical order. But the
supposed lustory of the mmd's mod1ficat10n 1mphes that, though
we are not able to conceive the contradictory of an axiom, we might
have been able, and our ancestors perhaps were able . and thus
the mmd's limitation m respect of the conceivable becomes as
such entirely md1ffcrcnt.
Any reliance placed on the inconceivableness of the contra-
dictory as a cntenon must he, and mdeed according to this
theory docs he, m the way in wluch tt has been produced, and
this 1s the essential thmg to be considered The criterion has
its value because it is the effect, as supposed, of an experience
infimtcly greater than that of one md1v1dual: and thus when
Mill obJectcd that 1£ the test got its value from expenence, we
had better appeal directly to experience, 1 it was replied that
the large experience represented by the test was inaccessible
to the md1v1dual. It is easy to see that the maximum logical
1 Mill, System of Logic, II vu, § 2.
Failu,e of Empi,icism
worth of the test would be that of an induction drawn from all
the instances which have occurred in the experience of the race,
supposing these could be presented to one mmd which would
draw the inference. The induction has registered its conclusion
automatically m the physical organism, and, through that, in
the mind. The race has come to believe that all A must be B,
because the constant experience through its history of instances
of A which were B has so modified the organs that they cannot
be used for thmking A except as B.
§ 36o. It has been madvertently assumed that in axioms such
a belief has been produced m one way only. From the very
assumptions about biological processes which tlus theory makes,
it is clear that the sufficient and necessary cond1t10n that the
belief 'all A must be B ' should be produced, is not that every
A should be B m the nature of thmgs, but only that those
mstanccs of A which have acted on the organs of perception
should have been B. And thus the conviction that A must be
B could be perfectly well produced m the automatic way sup•
posed, in a case where A was not necessarily B. The limitation
of our experience to a certam species of A which would be
necessary for this, would correspond to known facts. For
mstance, generation after generation of a particular race had
never seen swans which were not white. Countless generations
hving m certam parts of the earth have never seen water in
a sohd form.
Thus from the very manner of its formation our behef that
the arc must be greater than its chord is compatible with the
existence of arcs which arc not greater than the1r chords. There
are ways enough in which our hmitat10n to one kmd of arc may
have come about. For instance, naturalists expect to find new
forms of flora and fauna m regions which are being explored for
the first time. How do we know-not to speak of what may
be found m other planets and stars-that the polar regions have
not an abundance of that other kind of arc and chord? And
was it not as important scientifically that the naturahsts in the
Challenger should have dredged the deep seas for them as for
those objects in which they were immediately interested?
Or agam, allowing, what could not be known if the theory
we are examining were true, that all the arcs in the world now
SPECIAL LOGIC
are greater than their chords, how can the evolutionist know
that in early geological periods there were even any arcs at all
which were greater than their chords? For aught he can say
the arcs not greater than their chords may have been con-
temporary with the 'dragons of the prime' and have perished
with them. Why should he expect us to allow arbitrary assump-
tions here, which are allowed m no other empirical science?
It is quite remarkable to find the evolutionist confidently
makmg such statements as the following, without even askmg
himself how he could be entitled to them. 'Space-relations have
been the same not only for all ancestral men, all ancestral
primates, all ancestral orders of mammaba, but for all simpler
orders of creatures.'
But there 1s another and more serious form of the difficulty.
It is not even necessary that the experience of the race should
have been uniform. Arcs may have been seen equal to or less
than their chords, but 1f they only came seldom, or if in the
course of time their number much diminished, like that of an
expirmg race of animals, then according to the biological
prmc1ples presupposed, the infinitely greater accumula.,t:ion of
contrary experiences would m time wipe away all trace of them
from our organism.
Worse than th1s-owmg to the way m which Nature has fixed
our functions, we could not perceive arcs which were not greater
than their chords, even if there were plenty of them about us.
It is therefore useless to dredge the deep seas or to go to the
Poles, and mdeed we do not know whether in our own parts of
the world these arcs have not begun to exist. We could no
more sec them than a blmd man could. And thus the evolu-
tionist, professmg to have established the validity of the test of
inconceivableness, l1as unw1ttmgly shown it to be conSJstent
with the contradictory of what he supposes it to guarantee
absolutely. It follows 1rres1st1bly that all that seems to us
simplest, clearest, most self-evident, and more certain, according
to the evolutionist himself, than anything else we can believe,
may be an illusion.
The theory which was to hate reconciled great philosophies
has destroyed itself, and has ended m a scepticism which has
not even the merit of being self-conscious.
Failure of Empiricism
f 361. The contradiction cannot be avoided by dogmatically
affirming that the experience which has fixed our functions does,
as a matter of fact, correspond to a universal truth which has
no exceptions : for this involves, according as we look at it,
a new mconsistency or an argument in a circle.
(1} We are told that the ultimate and only criterion for the
individual who forms the last term of the series is the test of
inconceivableness, and yet on the other hand that the criterion
is trustworthy because an invariable experience has produced
it. To vindicate this position the cvolutlomst must know the
latter proposition to be true. But 1£ he does he has a higher
knowledge than the critenon itself, because it is knowledge from
which the criterion derives its value, and thus the criterion is
not the ultimate criterion for him. The evolutionist has fallen
into this contradiction apparently because he has forgotten that
he himself 1s one of the last terms of the series.
(1i) Or the difficulty may be put thus. The inconceivableness
of the contradictory of an axiom has been produced, it is said,
by a constant experience in the race, which again corresponds
to a universal truth without exception. How does the evolu-
tionist know that the experience of the race has been such, for
he cannot have had it ; and a fortiori how can he know the
umversahty of the corresponding fact m nature? Apparently
from what has been quoted he thinks he knows. Bemg the last
term of the series he can only know the fact by the incon-
ceivability which he supposes 1t has produced m himself : and
thus the invariable experience and the corresponding fact give
the criterion its value, and they themselves -are only known by
the criterion : wh1ch 1s arguing m a circle.
This may be shortly put by saying that the evolutionist
philosopher has cut himself off from the possibility of giving
the necessary evidence m favour of his own theory.
But it may be answered that though satisfactory evidence
for the theory cannot be given, it 1s a poss1ble hypothesis, and
though it may have to surrender all cla1ms to establish the
validity of our beliefs, 1t may be true, for constant experience
might produce such an effect on our organism. This of course
would be giving up a great part of the evolutionist position.
In the first place, it must be answered that according to
SPECIAL LOGIC
biological laws the loss of a function or of an organ may not
only be caused by want of a use for them, but also by the
operation of various processes, among which, for instance, are
diseases, and how can 1t be known that some such process has
not destroyed our capacity for thinking the contradictory of
axioms?
But the most important difficulty is this. The obJector can
hardly have reflected on the real consequence of his hypotl:ie~is.
It would throw a doubt, as we have seen, on every principle
however simple, self-evident, and certam it may appear, and
therefore it would leave nothmg even to found itself upon. It
would throw doubt also upon experience, which is supposed to
be our most direct access to reality, for owing to the hm1tation
of the nervous structures to one kmd of function, our mmds
may be m1sreprescntmg the obJect.
§ 362. How deep this unconsc10us scepticism has gone will
appear still better from another aspect of the theory.
• For logical mtuit1ons ', 1t is said, • there 1s no warrant assign·
able other than that assignable for all mtmtions accepted as
certam . namely, the imposs1bihty of thmkmg the opposite.
Unless 1t be alleged that the consc10usness of logical necessity
has a different ongm and a higher ongm, it must be admitted
that the consciousness of logical necessity 1s JUSt as much
a product of past experiences as 1s every other consciousness
of necessity.'
It follows, then, from what we have seen, that these logical
intuitions must share the uncertamty of axioms. But among
them we find included the prmc1ple of the syllog1sm, the law
of excluded middle, the principle of contrad1ct1on. They are in
fact those simple 'laws' or forms of thought to which thought
must conform to be thought at all. Thought therefore cannot
throw any doubt on them without committing smc1de. As
Aristotle has said .
6 IJ' a11a&p6111 T'GIJTr/11 ,-,}11 'lr&a'r'&II ol, 'trUIIV ,r&crro-r,pa lp,i.•
But there is one short general criticism which seems enough,
and would have explained beforehand without such an examina-
tion of details that the evolut10nist theory must end in self-
[• Now he who destroys tlus behef cannot expect lus own words to be
believed Eth Nie u7311 I ]
F ailu,e of Empiricism
contradiction. There is an elementary prmciple on which we
should expect all philosophies to agree, which is that thought
cannot question the vahd1ty of its own presuppositions or even
try to establish them without sclf-contrad1ction. Now 1t is
evident that the evolutionist theory violates this prmciple,
whether we consider the account given in it of the supposed
cnter1on of all truth, mconce1vableness of the opposite, or the
account of those primary laws of thought which have just been
spoken of.
§ 363. The mistake is of the more elementary character when
the attempt to establish the laws of thought, or a general
cnterion, is made by help of the reasonings of a special science,
for that of course must presuppose the general laws and the
criterion. But this 1s precisely the use here made of biology.
The reasonings of biology would collapse 1f it did not assume,
for instance, the principle of contradiction ; it 1s futile therefore
to prove its objective vabd1ty by biology.
As to the criterion itself, which 1s to show that a cognition
is of the highest rank (its 'unsurpassable vahd1ty', &c.), the
principles of biology cannot depend on 1t since biology has to
establish it. Hence, either they have not the highest rank,
which involves the absurdity that the criterion of cogmtions of
the highest rank 1s shown to be a valid criterion by appealing
to cogmt1ons which arc not of the highest rank : or else the
prmc1plcs of biology have the highest rank, and then 1t turns
out that there are some absolute truths which are not derived
from the criterion, and, what is still worse, that evolution has
altogether forgotten to explain their origin, thus leaving the old
problem so far from bcmg solved that 1t is not even attempted.
For instance, among these principles so entirely unaccounted for
is the axiom of umversal causat10n . for of course b10Jogy pre·
supposes this. It 1s true that in one place where Mill 1s criticized
1t seems as if the belief m the uniformity of nature (on which
biology depends) would be accounted for by the same biological
argument as the other axioms. If s01 confusion would be
confounded.
§ 364. May I say, in conclusion, that I venture to think there
is all the difference between evolution m science, and what 1s
known as the evolutionist philosophy ? It seems reasonable to
628 SPECIAL LOGIC
believe that there are many scientific evolutionists who will not
be led by a mistaken idea of the solidarity of the subject to
suppose themselves committed to the conclusions of the evolu-
tionist philosophers. 1 It is not the first time in history that
enthusiasts for a new and successful development of science have
tried to carry the science beyond its proper limits, and have
aspired to make it universal by making it what science never
can be-that is, philosophy. ' ·
§ 365. The futility of the inductive theory was seen by
Descartes long before the development of English empiricism,
and with his name and that of Leibniz is connected the theory
of Innate Ideas. This theory has often been misrepresented,
but the gist of it is that the truths m question are the mind's
own possession, developed somehow by its own activity and not
denved from experience--m the narrow sense-of the particular
facts.
The well-known criticisms of Locke on this theory are with
scarcely an exception an ignoratio elenchi. The answer to him
is obvious : Innate Ideas are intended to account for knowledge
where 1t is, not where it is not. It is as useful to allege against
it that plants have not these ideas as that children, idiots, and
savages have not. Locke was also under an illusion about the
presence of an idea which is implicit and not explicit. The time
at which an innate idea appears and the extent to which it is
defined are entirely irrelevant to the real issue. Locke was
answered by Leibniz m his Nouveaux Essais.
The real difficulty for the Cartesian school was to account
from their point of view for the validity of these beliefs which
the mind has on its own account. Why should this necessity
for thought be true of the objects of thinkmg? The theory of
the inconceivability of the opposite as the criterion of truth is
closely albed to that of Innate Ideas and may fairly be called
only a particular form of it. We may say that it is a test of
truth in this sense that, when the contradictory of a statement
1 The speculations of WelSSmann have made a diffenmce in the behefa of
(& Tlus chapter was unt.tl 1899 followed by sections, the mam purport of
which appears elsewhere in the book Of the rest I am not &urc how far the
wnter would have mamta.ined their tenets m later years Their contents were:
§ The conception of force m physics Further development of the relation
of pure mathematics to physic& We do not understand what Force means
§ On the axioms of physics Some great generalizations (e g. the mde•
structlb1hty of matter) are self-evident and a pnon, the experiments employed
bcmg suggested by our conv1ct10n of their truth
§ On the obJectiv-e v-alld1ty of our thought. The problem onginates in
difficulties felt about the axioms of formal logic [Dictum de omni, &c ),
§ The 1nduction1st theory of the ongm of axioms , Mill's theory of parallels ;
association of ideas explanation , H. Spencer's theory of inherited expenence
§ The Cartesian answer, The mconcotvab1Jity of the opposite as a cntenon
of truth Kant's solution (the last accepted broadly 1n 1899] J
SPECIAL LOGIC
physics depends ultimately on physical laws, which pure mathe-
matics cannot give. Thus in optics, as Aristotle knew them,
there were the laws of reflection and refraction, and it is odd
he did not see that in mathematical optics, as he knew them,
these were accepted as facts given by observation, together with
certain geometrical relations which they involved. Thus all
geometry did was to deduce certain geometrical consequences
from the geometrical part of the given premisses. •
§ 368. As may be seen in the instance of optics, mathematical
physics requires physical laws, which mathematics cannot supply.
About this we find in modern times a confusion like Aristotle's,
though not quite the same. The physical laws themselves
Involve certain mathematical relations both geometrical and of
pure quantity, and all mathematics can do is to develop the
consequences of these mathematical data. How, for example,
does mathematics deal with motion? Certain laws of movement
are given, i e. laws of the way in which a body changes its
distance from certain fixed points. Given such changes of geo-
metrical relations, geometry simply ralculates certain other
geometrical relations which follow from them. But it can say
nothmg whatever of the reason for the given laws of the changes.
To put it otherwise, if we think of force as the cause of move•
ment, it is with the effects of force, as changes in the geometrical
relations of bodies, that mathematics alone can deal. Given,
for instance, the force of attraction and given its operation or
effect, in the sense that a body revolving round the sun tends
to shorten its distance from the sun at a regular rate, 1 and given
tha.t it has at the same time a tendency to mov~ parallel to
a certain fixed hne at a certain rate, we find the body describes
an ellipse. This is only one geometrical fact deduced from
another. Given that a planet moves in an ellipse with a certain
varying velocity, we can prove that its distance from the sun
tends to shorten in the way attributed to attraction, and that
its tendency to move m the parallel direction is constant.
What is not supplied by geometry 1s assumed, i. e. the
parallelogram of forces.
§ 369. This (i e the mathematical work) is entirely misunder•
stood by Mill m his chapter on the Deductive method. He
1
The mverse square of the dJStance.
The Melhod of Physics
supposes that if the effects of the forces, operating singly, are
given, or the law of each force operating singly is given, ~he
combined effect, when the forces act together, can be found by
ratiocination, a mere name for the syllogism rejected in Book II.
He is thinking of course of mathematical physics and especially
of the example we gave in the last section. He supposes, given
the forces acting, given the operation of the law of attraction
on a body, and the operation of the original projection, that the
result, the path of the moving body, is got simply by deduction.
This is impossible and, given the laws operating singly, mathe•
matics as such is quite unable to discover their combined effect.
It cannot move a step without assuming a physical law of
combination, that is, how these forces will act in combination.
In the given problem mathematics solves a purely mathe•
matical question : 1t does not touch the conception of Force
as such at all. It deals only with the changes of geometrical
relations, assumed as the effects of the forces ; and it assumes
what 1t is supposed to prove, namely, certain laws of the com•
bined operation of physical forces. It is the easier for Mill to
make this mistake because he has so entirely mistaken the
nature of the geometrical method itself. He thinks of it in
general as a method of deduction. If he had realized that its
method 1s construction, he might have seen that the construe•
tion, being solely of mathematical quantities or relations, could
not possibly deal with the physical conception of force, which
is not 1dent1fiablc with such relations.
§ 370. In one department of these sciences, i. e. in dynamics
and statics, motions are considered without relation to their
effects on consciousness. But there is another department in
which motions are treated as causes of what are taken to be
sensations of ours-heat, light, and sound. Here we are concerned
with another set of causal laws, i. e. the effects in feeling-con•
sciousness of some action (in the way of movement) upon our
sense organs. Now here the mathematical part is concerned
solely with the movements of the material bodies. It cannot
deal with them as causes of sensation. Violet may be the colour
corresponding to a certain wave-length and the ordinary theory
is that it is a sensation of ours, like heat or cold, caused by the
impact of ether waves of a given wave-length on our retina.
SPECIAL LOGIC
But mathematics can only deal with the undulations : it cannot
say why violet corresponds to, or is the effect of, the undulatory
movement. That is learnt " posteriori from certain facts of
consciousness taken in connexion with the hypothesis of the
undulatory theory. Sometimes, again, it is supposed that the
concord between two musical notes 1s accounted for by the fact
that a certain number of vibrations of the air corresponding to
the one take place m the time occupied by an integral number
of the vibrations corresponding to the other. But this is an
illusion. It 1s merely an interesting fact that such commen-
surateness corresponds to our musical sense of concord. The
science fails to establish any connexion between the two. We
cannot possibly show why that numerical connexion should have
as its effect a musical concord The apprehension of the sensa·
tion, if it be such, 1s in no sense an apprehension of the vibrations
which arc its physical cause.
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
§ 37 I. THE term Symbolic Logic is taken in the following
sections m its current meaning. It denotes, that is, a theory
which, whether rightly called logic or not, proposes to conduct
operations of purely formal inference by the aid of an algebraic
calculus. Dodgson, bin calling his book Symbolic Logic, 1 departed
from what seems to be the common usage, for he did not employ
a mathematical calculus ; and how far he was from a mathe•
matical treatment is still more evident from the unpubbshed
second part, of which he, with his usual kindness, sent me the
most important of the proof sheets. I hke to think that my
main contention would probably have pleased him a good deal.
A common objection to Symbolic Logic, as thus defined, is
that it 1s mathematics and not logic, and so is not necessary to
the log1CJan. A lmc of defence taken by symbolic logicians 1s
that the subJect is not strictly mathemat1cal, the signs of multi•
pbcatlon and divis10n have not the mathematical meaning. But
while th1s could hardly be alleged in the case of the signs +
and -, there must be something essential, common to the use
in mathematics and symbolic logic of the signs of multi-
phcation and d1v1S1on, for otherwise the employment of these
signs m the latter would be ridiculous. The truth is, that
in symbolic logic these formulae follow the same laws of develop·
ment as the correspondmg formulae (or operations, rather) in
mathematics, notably in the matter of the multiphcation of the
signs + and -. 2 Besides, the idea of an equation, which is
• Symbolic Logic', Part I, Elementary, by Lewis Carroll London (Mac-
millan), 18g6. • See p 641, § Ji'9, infra
[& Redrafted from two manuscnpt lectures of Hilary Term, 1898, and
manuscnpt connected with the same subJect I have left the •propositional•
terminology
b The Rev C L Dodgson, the author of Alice in Wonderland, was lately
dead when the lectures were delivered, There 1s a kind of mathematical
calculus suggested m Dodgson's book as an alternative to the counter system,
which makes the easy part and the bulk of the treatise.]
2773"2 Q
SPECIAL LOGIC
fundamental to the subject, is obviously a mathematical idea..
Thus Boole entitled his earber investigation ' The mathematical
analysis of Logic ', and gave as a sub-title to his better-known
work 1 ' The mathematical theories of logic and probabilities ',
§ 372. A stronger hne of defence may be suggested. Suppose
it is mathematics ; provided only it is sound mathematics, it
is futile to object. We may not like mathematics, but that is
not an objection to the subject. And we may not like the extra
trouble ; but astronomers might as well agree to ignore the
planet Neptune, as a member of the Solar System, because it
gives them extra trouble. On the other hand 1t would be a most
interesting fact that mathematics could conduct logical pro-
cesses (as Boole's titles imply), and the logician would be bound
to study it as throwing light both on logic and mathematics.
Nor is it really enough to object that the inferences can be
conducted by ordinary methods, so that a calculus is not neces-
sary, or even that these ordinary methods are simpler, quicker,
and so better. The symbohc logicians would probably deny the
truth of both obJectlons and certainly they would deny the latter
with entire confidence. The answer should rather be that, even
if the calculus were more cumbrous, we should have to study
it or we should be cuttmg ourselves off from a most interesting
piece of knowledge. The objections clearly are only relevant to
any claims of superiority made for the calculus and not to the
questions of its right to exist and of its validity.
§ 373. The original objection, however, has a deeper basis
than mere prejudice and rests on a sound notion of logic, often
insufficiently realized, especially in Deductive Logic, but tending
to become conscious of itself, when such investigations as these
are presented seriously as logic. This sound notion is that, with
regard to inference, the methods of all the special sciences are
the object-matter of logic ; it neither makes them nor conducts
them, but studies them. It is thus, in a sense, more general
than any of them. This being so, 1t is incredible that any
particular scientific method, for example the mathematical,
should be the method of logic itself. We suspect somethmg
wrong and that the subject cannot be logic at all. That is an
1
A11 ltlflutigation of Ills La111s of TliougM, o,s Which a,e fON'#dlrl Che MtdM•
malscal Thlones of Logic anrl Probalnl1lses, George Boole, 1854.
Sy,nl,olic Logi,c
objection which is never even dreamed of by the symbolic
logicians, but the greatest danger usually comes from the quarter
which we least suspect. Indeed it would be a shock to their
feelings to have their title to be logicians disputed, for their
language is in no sense self-depreciatory and they openly profess
to make great improvements on the common or ' ordinary '
logic,• as they call it.
§ 374. The foreboding, however, of the 'common' logician is
Justified, for he will find that the symbolic logic as such consists
of the solution of particular problems, which are on the same
plane as the solution of geometrical or algebraic problems and,
though concerned with the abstract forms of subject and pre•
d1cate, as specially scientific as these mathematical processes--
no more logic than they are, and related to logic precisely as
they are. Incidentally there is a little elementary logic involved,
but the real and serious problems of logic proper do not appear,
nor is the symbolic logic able to touch them. In comparison
with the serious business of logic proper, the occupations of the
symbolic logician are merely trivial. I do not want, however,
at present to dwell either upon the comparative importance of
the ' logical ' calculus or on its relation to true logic, but to take
it rather at its own valuation, to inquire what its problem is,
and with what success the solution is attempted.
§ 37 5. The problem stated in most general terms is to find
what various inferences can be drawn from premisses btated in
the abstract symbolic form of the traditional syllogistic logic,
with no other quantitative notions than ' all ', ' some ', and
' none '. It might seem that in this comparatively humble
sphere there would be no difficulty, as every step of the argu-
ment is either immediate inference or needs no more than the
first figure and mood of the syllogism, than which nothing could
be simpler. But 1t should be remembered that, in the solution
of a difficult and complicated mathematical problem, every
single step, when the reasoning is fully expressed, may be very
simple. The difficulty consists in finding the right steps to take
and the right order of them. And so, in formal thinking, it is
possible to devise problems of such difficulty as would never be
[• The phrase goes back to Bacon. Here Wilson defends logms commrmu
polemically though he continually elsewhere speaks dlSl'eflpectfully of 1t ]
g2
SPECIAL LOGIC
anticipated by those who are only accustomed to such specimens
of formal argument as are given in the traditional logic.
If the premisses have compound subjects and predicates, as
all ABC is D, or DE, and if they are further perplexed by
a Judicious sprmkling of negatives (e.g. all A, not-B, C is not-D),
if further a considerable number of premisses be taken, a problem
may be invented which may take hours to solve, unless we have
some definite rule and method besides the mere possession of
the first syllogistic figure.
The followmg 1s an mstance of a formal problem devised
by Dodgson, who was clever in the construction of difficult
problems.
Given that-
(1) all active old Jews arc healthy,
(2) all mdolcnt magistrates arc unpopular,
(3) all nch snuff-takers arc unhealthy,
(4) all sarcw.t1c magistrates arc Jews,
(S) all young snuff-takers arc pale,
(6) all nch old men, who are unhealthy, arc sarcastic,
(7) all magistrates who are not poets arc studious,
(8) all rosy magistrates arc talented,
(9) all talented and popular students are rich,
(ro) all pale snuff-takers are unpopular,
(II) all unpopular magistrates arc abstainers from snuff,
(12) all talented poets who are active are rich;
to prove that no magistrates are snuff-takers.
To reach this conclusion by a series of ordmary syllogistic
arguments would mvolve a very long process. By Boole's
methods I have calculated that 2,048 factors are required, but
by an improved calculus of my own the result may be gamed
10 a very short time
A simpler example 1s the following .
Given that No AC 1s Band that no D which is not-Bis A,
To prove that all A 1s either not-C or not-D.
A third example might be one given by Boole.1
Given that-
(1) If A and Care absent, Eis found with B or D, but not
with both.
• Laws of Th014gl,I, p 146.
Sytnl,o.lic Logic
(2) If A and D are present and E is missing, either both
B and C will be found or will both be absent.
(3) If A is present with either B or E or both, then C or
D will be present, but not both, and conversely.
What conclusions can be drawn ?
This is said to be ' the most intricate of any given by Boole '. 1
It took two and three-quarter hours to work out by ordinary
methods, but only twenty minutes by my own calculus. The
solution Venn gives could not have taken very long.
One soon discovers that some definite rule and method is
required here as much as in mathematics, and on this point
Dodgson, in the preface to his book, rightly insists •
§ 376. Method, then, being needed, the subject really being
a particular science, any method deserves to be examined, pro-
vided always the thing is worth doing at all. Hence, pnma
f acie, there is a case for symbohc logic, though it can hardly
be said to have originated in a consciousness of the difficulty
of such problems as I have been alluding to. It was probably
felt by those who originated it that formal reasoning was like
mathematics, in its a priori character, in its necessity and
absolute accuracy, and hke algebra, in the use of abstract
symbols. The science of pure quantity had received an enormous
extension by the invention of the symbolic method of algebra,
and the thought naturally arose that something similar might
be done for formal thinking
Now when the perception of the aforesaid analogies has sug•
gested symbolism, two courses are possible. We may either
study the peculiarities of the actual problems which have arisen
in the science and consider what kmd of symbolism they seem
naturally to suggest as hkely to facilitate their solution, or we
may try to apply so far as possible the already existing symbolism
of algebra, as it stands, and thus invent a calculus on strict
algebraic analogy and then see what we can get out of 1t. This
second seems really to be the way in which symbolic logic came
mto being. The first method is clearly the sound one, for,
• Symbolic Logic, by John Venn, London (Macmillan), p 351.
[• In the original there 1s here a reference to the great Joss to philosophy
by the untunely death of Mr Adamson, Fellow of St John"s College, • a good
mathematician and a promJSmg metaphysician • )
SPECIAL LOGIC
though it is right enough to take the suggestion of symbolism
in general from algebra, it is a mistake to suppose that the
symbolism adapted to one science is likely to suit another. The
lesson which modern logic has learned and has to teach is that
the method of the particular sciences depends on their object-
matter, the various forms of the method of science are discovered
by srienttfic men themselves in the study of the special problems
peculiar to their respective sciences, and they cannot be ais-
covered in any other way.
§ 377. The presumption is therefore that if the reasonings in
a given science can be conducted by a symbolic method, the
same symbolism will not suit another. The case of analytical
(i. e. Cartesian) geometry (which is perhaps too easily misrepre-
sented) is not an exception. There geometrical relations give
rise to relations of quantity, not sham quantities, but real
quantities which can enter into equations ; they thus give rise
to true algebraic problems which algebra solves in real, not
sham, equations, with real multiplication and division. Con-
sequently, if the symbolism of algebra is transferred to the
science of formal thmkmg, we (the common logicians) cannot
help entertaimng certain anxieties. We should fear that mathe-
matical analogy, the symbolism being the same, might some-
times mislead, and a relation of logical terms be confounded
with a relation of literal quantity. Again, we should fear that
the algebraical processes would only fit partially, and that the
calculus, instead of being a potent instrument as in true algebra,
might be rather narrowed in its use ; the attempt to carry it
out consistently as a general calculus might even lead to contra-
diction and positive error. We might again expect that much
ingenuity would be expended in solving problems the difficulties
of which were due to the artificial form into which the premisses
were forced by the calculus itself. Lastly, while skilful enough
in overcoming unnecessary difficulties of its own making, the
calculus might possibly not facilitate the solution of the difficult
problems which arise naturally in formal thinking itself.
§ 378. To Judge from its contents, the main ideas of the logical
calculus seem to have been developed in some such way as this.
Formal logic from Aristotle downwards has used symbols, viz.
letters of the alphabet, like algebra, for class conceptions ;
Symbolic Logic
for instance, all A _is B. Operations with these symbols it
recognizes in symbolic form only in the case of the association of
two class conceptions to form a species. Thus AB means that
which is both A and B, and thus a narrower class than either.
This symbol AB resembles the symbol in algebra of the multi-
plication together of two quantities. These symbols, then, form
the starting-point. Equations bemg the important instrument
of algebra and its applications, an equation is sought for between
the given symbols. 'A "" B' suggests itself, and the question
arises how this should be interpreted. It is seen that the
identity of the extension of two classes could be thus repre-
sented, and this is the interpretation given ; that is to say,
A .. B means that the whole of the individuals in the class A
constitute the whole of those in the class B.
A+ B, then, would mean the united extension of A and B, or
the class formed by uniting A and B. If A' and B', then, sym-
bolize not-A and not-B respectively, we get A+ B = AB'+ AB
+ AB + A'B. Here the interpretat10n of AB + AB is not what
it would be in algebra, because if the classes A and B overlap,
the class AB is not counted twice over.
Thus AB+ AB = AB,
Similarly, A+ A = A and not 2A.
If B is part of A, the usual symbol for subtraction may be
used, so that A - B = AB'. Here certain difficulties arise if B
is not wholly contained in A. They need not, however, be
discussed here.
§ 379. The ordinary law of algebraic multiplication is said to
hold;
viz. if a+ b = :x,
ex ... c(a+b) = ca+cb
J EB
& c: b
I
for what is common to the extension of c
and :x must consist of what is common to
c and the parts a and b of x. Supposing c has nothtng in com•
mon with b, then the class cb is non-existent and so the equation
remains true because cb = o. This last is, as we shall see,
a serious assumption. It may, then, easily be verified that
the multiplication rule obtains, if for c a polynomial be intro-
duced. Thus
(a+b) (c+d) = ac+ad+bc+bd;
SPECIAL LOGIC
also that the algebraic rules about the signs + and - hold in
this sort of multiplication. Algebraic powers, however, cannot
enter since aa = a, obviously. In fact for Boole x2 = x is the
expression of the fundamental rule of thought. The operation
of division appears to a certam hm1ted extent, and such a symbol
as ", of which the symbolic logicians are rather proud, though
)'
it 1s really a snare spread for their feet.
§ 380. The symbol ab, if compared with the corresponding
algebraic symbol, has nothing to do with multiplication m the
sense of the repetition of a umt, but serves to md1cate an opera-
tion following some of the general laws which are followed by
the symbolism of multrplicat1on. In ab, a may be taken as the
symbol of an operation, viz multiplication, performed upon b as
a given quantity, but b may Just as well be a symbol of opera-
tion, and the mathematical theory of symbols of operation seeks
to make such symbols always represent the operation of multi-
plication. Thus the symbol a standing alone represents the
operation of multiplication performed on the umt of number,
1, a thus 1s eqmvalent to I xa and ab = (I xa) xb. a and
b then are always symbols of operation, that which is operated
on being the umt whatever 1t may be. Unity, then, 1s under-
stood always and not expressed with the symbols
In the symbolic logic, however, ab denotes an operation of
a upon b, which 1s the operation of takmg the part of b common
to 1t and a. On the analogy of mathematics we seek for a way
of representing a itself as an operation. What, then, must be
the class operated upon by a to produce a, the ultimate umt,
so to speak, operated on? That 1s to say, what 1s that class
such that when we take out of 1t what ts common to 1t and
any class a we get the class a itself? The answer 1s obviously
'reality'. As reality, then, is to be understood with every
symbol like ab, just as I is m algebra, the symbol I is used in
this calculus as the symbol of reality.
This may seem ingenious, but 1t 1s really unfortunate. It
would have been much better to have taken a symbol which
originally had no numerical significance to represent reality,
e. g. r ; then ab would be understood to mean abr. The negative
of r, that is the unreal or 1mposs1ble, would be represented by
Symbolic Logic
r', like any other negative class. A serious mistake would
thus have been avoided ; for, as we shall see presently, the
symbol o or zero, besides its significance as a true zero, has to
do duty in the calculus as the symbol of the impossible with
grave consequences.
[For the present we are concerned only with the normal
meaning of zero, in the logical calculus. A non-existent class
is regarded as a compartment of reality which is empty and is
represented by o. This appears to follow m a mathematical
manner from what has been already laid down, for ab denotes
the operation of taking the part of the class b common to it
and a. Thus oa ( = o) will stand for the thmgs which are both
nothmg and a, that is, for any empty class.]
§ 381. On the use of I to symbolize reality is founded the
equation fundamental to the calculus x + x' = I, wluch expresses
(or is supposed to express) the fact that everything must be
x or not-x. The equation expresses this in the form that the
whole of reality ( = 1) 1s made up of the class x and not-x,
i. e. what is not m the class :x.
S1m1larly a = ax+ax', wluch we may get directly, or derive
from the above by writing (x+x') for I thus
a= ax
= a (x+x') = ax+ax'
These equations we shall call for convenience equations of
dichotomy, and shall cntic1ze them presently.
§ 382. We will now turn back to the equation A = B. It
expresses primarily a relation between the extensions, not the
intens10ns, of A and B. That is, 1t does not mean that the
nature of A necessitates that of B and conversely, but that
the two classes comc1de. This leads, for example in Venn, to
the crudest and naivest nominalism. Now, in the case of truly
universal notions, the extension 1smfinite and there 1s absolutely
no way of 1dentifymg their extensions except through the con•
ceptions. We cannot know that the class A coincides with B,
except by knowing that the conception of A necessitates that
of B, and conversely. That 1s1 we can only know it through
the two propositions, all A is B and all B 1s A. This is, then,
not so much the interpretation of a given equation, but the
knowledge we must have before we can form the equation at
SPECIAL LOGIC
all. Similarly the proposition A= B +C implies all A is either
B or C, all B is A, and all C is A. Since, then, the relation
between the extension of two or more conceptions can only be
got at through the relation between the conceptions themselves,
as expressed m the aforesaid propositions, one may be curious
to know beforehand how far any reasoning from the equation
can be carried on without referring back to these propositions.
§ 383. It is obvious that the equation A= B will not do ior
the ordinary proposition 'a.11 A 1s B' , it only represents the
case where 'all A is B' is convertible simply, that is, it repre•
sents the two propositions 'all A is B' and 'all B is A' taken
together. Now the important problem of the calculus is to find
an equation for the ordinary proposition 'all A 1s B '. The
relation or equation between the extension of A and B 1s clearly
only A = some B. This is represented by A = v B, where v has
the special significanre of 'some' This 1s merely the pretence
of an equation, a form of equation without the reality. For an
equation something definable must be identified with something
else definable, but here a definite A is equated to an mdefinite,
which seems to contradict the idea of an equation. The symbol
v does not improve matters, especially when we find that the
calculus, for other rt>asons, 1s obliged to give it the entirely
indeterminate meaning 'some' ; it may be none, or all, or a part.
Further, A = vB does not even tell us that any A is B.
§ 384. There is, however, another form of equation for the
proposition all x 1s y, due apparently to Boole, which seems to
have the exactness necessary for an equation and to secure
another advantage. In this form of calculus the proposition all
X is Y is treated as hypothetical, not so much from a theory
that the universal affirmative categorical is necessarily hypo•
thetical (if anything is X, it is Y), but from the special needs
of the calculus itself. In algebra when we set a problem and
have to determine the value of a so-called 'unknown• x, which
suits the problem, we may be asking that certain conditions
shall be satisfied whlch cannot be, and then our calculation
shows this by representing finally the unknown x under the
form of an impossible operation. Thus we cannot say that the
variables in our equations always represent real quantities. This
logical calculus proposes 1ts problems with the same generality,
Sy,nbolic Logic
and rightly. A subject X is given as satisfying certain con-
ditions in the form of premisses, and the combination of these
may result in the conclusion that X has contradictory attributes
(say X is Y and X is Y'). We are in such a case not to pro•
nounce the premisses false, but X impossible. The important
case will be when X is compound = AB ; then the conclusion
AB is impossible yields the judgement 'no A is B '. Consequently
in a premiss all X 1s Y, we cannot say that X is possible, it
may be impossible, and so it must be read, 'X, if possible, is
Y', or 'X, whether real or unreal, 1s Y'. On this account
propositions which arc uuiversal and affirmative are said not to
be existential, that is, not to convey definite statements about
existence. They are regarded, whether rightly or not, as in
a sense ambiguous. However, it is said, the proposition all X
is Y docs involve a definite statement about existence, viz. that
there are no really existing things which are both X and not-Y,
or XY'. This 1s taken, then, as the equivalent of the proposition
all X is Y and expressed in the form there are no members in
the class XY'. This translated into equational form becomes
XY' = o. This seems at first most ingenious, for we now have
an equation of the requisite accurate and definite mathematical
form, and we need not mscrt any hypothesis about the existence
of the terms. This equation 1s possibly the most important
and fundamental feature of the calculus. I shall try to show
that it is an dlus10n, by proving -first, that the proposition which
it symbolizes, no XY' exists, though an inference from all X is
Y, is not the true eqmvalent of it ; secondly, that given the
proposition 'No XY' exists' (or XY' is impossible) it cannot be
rightly symbolized by the equation XY' = o, and that the
symbolism involves a grave error from the point of view of
a mathematical calculus, or theory of symbols of operation in
general. Finally, that it is impossible to give a true equational
form at all to the universal proposition 'all X is Y '.
§ 385. We are led to suspect some error in the fundamental
equation, if we consider a curious theorem in the doctrine of
elimination • in the calculus which depends on this equation.
Logical elimination so called means merely this. Given pro·
[• Some of this was suggested, I think, by Venn's s,,,,.,,ol,c Lo,,e, cha :iav
and xv.]
SPECIAL LOGIC
positions involving conceptions such as x, y, ands, a given element
is said to be eliminated when a proposition is found from the
data which docs not involve that element. Thus tn the syl-
logism the middle term is ehmmated. If all X is YZ, the
proposition All X 1s Y 1s true and 1s said to eliminate Z. In the
symbolic logic elimination 1s made very easy in the case of
particular propositions by the prmc1ple that such propositions
always imply the existence of their subJects, while universal$ do
not. Thus, wlulc All X ts Y cannot guarantee the existence of
any X, Some X 1s Y 1mphcs the real existence of some X and
therefore of some Y also. Thus in Some X 1s YZ we can eliminate
each element singly and each group of two thus .
some X exists,
some Y exists,
some XY exists, and so on
Now, at first sight, 1t seems odd that the merely indefinite
subject, some X, should ensure the existence of X, while the
definite, all X, cannot do this a And, 1£ the universal X 1s Y
must, for the reason stated, mean, If any X exists 1t is Y, then
for exadly the same reason the particular, Some X is Y, should
mean Some X, 1f 1t exists, is Y ; or, Some X, 1£ 1t were to exist,
would be Y. Formal proulcms lead to such an hypothetical some
jm,t as they do to an hypothetical all. Take, for instance, All
A 1s Y, all A 1s X: therefore, Some X, viz. AX, 1s Y. Here
the some X meant 1s clearly hypothetical, since A is hypothetical
It must mean: Some X, 1f 1t existed, would be Y. There must,
then, be some strong reason for a doctrine which presents such
obvious difficulties, and the fact 1s that the symbolists arc
committed to 1t as the necessary consequence of their view of
the equation XY' = o The argument 1s .
Some X is not Y is the contradictory of the proposition All
X JS y'
All X 1s Y is equivalent to No XY' exists.
Therefore Some X 1s not-Y is the contradictory of No XY'
exists. But the contradictory of No XY' exists 1s Some XY'
exists. Therefore Some X is not-Y 1s equivalent to Some XY'
[• In Dodgson's system All X is Y is considered to be equivalent to Some
X (at least) 1s Y, and No Xis Y' The resolution is, however assumed, never
justified]
Symbolic Logic
exists, that is, Some really existent Xis not-Y. For the affirma•
tive we have to use the negative universal, which in this theory
is No XY' exists ( = No Xis Y') or XY' = o. The contradictory
of No XY' exists is correctly stated; thus the argument must
turn on the equivalence of No XY' exists to All X is Y; and
so if we suspect the conclusion, we must suspect this equivalence.
Indeed we may reverse the argument and say the two proposi•
tions cannot be equivalent because their contradictories are not.
For clearly, while the contradictory of No XY' exists is Some
XY' exists, i e. Some really existent X is not Y, the contra•
dictory of All X 1s Y (understood as equivalent to Any X, 1f it
exists (or existed), is (or would be) Y) is Some X, 1f it existed,
would not be Y. Or, to put 1t m another way, All X is Y is
equivalent to All X, whether real or not, is Y, and the contra•
dictory of this must be Some X, whether real or not, is not Y.
§ 386. Agam the equivalence of the two propositions is dis·
proved by the fact that the existential meanmg which it neces•
s1tates for the particular as against the universal proposition can
be shown to involve the theory m a contradiction. It may be
premised that lhe existential propos1t1on, No XY' exists, must
be understood m the wide sense, No XY' can exist at any time;
for, otherwise, 1t would be compatible with the contradictory of
the proposition, all X 1s Y, which 1t is supposed to represent.
All A 1s B = If a thing 1s A, 1t 1s B (1)
No A is B = If a thmg 1s A, 1t 1s not B . (2)
Therefore (1), 1£ true, necessitates that (2) is untrue.
But (2), according to these logicians, = No AB exists, or No
AB is possible, . (3)
Therefore (1) necessitates the untruth of (3).
But the untruth of (3) necessitates the truth of its contra-
dictory.
And the contradictory of (3) 1s 'some AB exists'.
Hence, 'all A 1s B' necessitates the proposition 'some AB
exists', 1. e. some A exists and 1s B.
Thus the universal affirmative necessarily implies that its
subject is real, which is contrary to hypothesis This is a
sufficient reductio ad absurdum The equation, then, XY' = o,
if representmg No XY' can exist, is not the true equivalent of
All Xis Y.
SPECIAL LOGIC
f 387. We shall now inquire what is true of XY' i whether
any equation for All X is Y can be got from it ; and the meaning
and consequences of equating XY' to zero. If all X is Y, then
XY' is YY' ; that is, XY' is impossible, and has the particular
form of impossibility YY'. If we take 'XY' = o' merely to mean
'XY' is 1mposs1ble' we certainly do not take the full inference from
All X 1s Y, because we omit the particular sort of impossibility
to which 'all X is Y' leads; accordingly we cannot have 'gt>t
a true equivalent for All Xis Y. This is verified by the contra-
diction test. For, as in the case already considered, the con-
tradictory of the two propos1tlons 1s not the same. Indeed the
proposition XY' is impossible is really m the same position as
No XY can exist.
The want of equivalence 1s otherwise evident ; for, given
XY' is impossible, what follows is not that all X (whether real
or not) is Y (the true eq111valent of All X 1s Y), but the disjunctive,
Either X is unreal, or Y' is unreal, or X, 1f real, is Y.
That the full inference All XY' 1s YY', 1s a true equivalent
of AU X 1s Y, can be verified by inference, or by takmg the
contradictory Thus :
(1) Xis Y or Y', that is, is Y or XY',
but XY' is Y,
therefore all X (whether real or unreal) is Y
(2) The contradictory of 'XY' is YY" is Some XY' is not
Y'Y,
but all XY' must be Y'.
Therefore some XY' 1s not Y.
But this would be impossible 1f all X were Y, therefore some
X is not Y ; which is the contradictory of All X 1s Y.
But this does not yield an equation. We cannot put XY' ...
YY' because XY' is not coincident with every form of YY'.
The nearest we can get to an equational form is XY' = some
YY', or XY' = vYY'. Thus, mstead of improving on tlus and
gettmg a more accurate form and one which corresponds to the
determmate character of a true equation, we have only come
back to it and with no improvement, for X = vY makes
XY' = vYY' unnecessary. In view of these considerations it
1s of importance to observe that Venn, 1 after a sneering reference
1 Venn, 1. c, p. 403
to the venerable structure of the syllogism, continues : ' the
distinction between universal and particular propositions which
to it is unimportant is to us vital.'
§ 388. So far we have examined the logic which leads to the
equation XY' = o, and found that it contains serious errors.
We will now consider the mathematical side. XY' represents,
we have seen, an impossible class, and it is as such that it is
equated to zero ; the idea is that XY' bemg an impossible class
there are no members m it, and so its extension 1s o. Thus
XY' = o. Similarly, 1f A is B, AB' = o. And clearly these
equations will be very poor equations, indeed a mere shamt if
it does not follow that XY' = AB', whatever propositions XY
and AB represent. The question therefore anses, what con•
sequences have such equations? But strangely enough these
equations, though the absolutely necessary result of an equa-
tional calculus, do not seem to have been formed or considered.
The equation of 1mposs1bles as such to zero does not arise
merely from the attempt to get an equation for the universal
affirmative All X 1s Y, but is necessary everywhere to this
calculus.
The distributive law in the association of class conceptions,
or rather the limiting of one class by another, or taking the
extension common to two classes, a (b +c) = ab +ac, corre•
sponding to the distributive law of the operation of multtplica•
tion in algebra, depends entirely on the equation of impossibles
to zero.
b C b C b C
§ 389. The common part of the class a and the class formed
by putting together b and c, supposing there 1s any common
part, will certainly include either ab or ac, and it may include
both, that is, it will have a common part with b or c, or both,
but it may have no common part with one of them. It is
possible, for instance, that there may be nothing common to
a and c and, therefore, no class ac at all. Then c is a'. Supp0&e
SPECIAL LOGIC
c ,_ a'd, then ac = aa'd. But the formula for a (b +c), although
this is intended for a real class, gives always a (b +c) = ab +ac;
therefore a (b +c) =- ab +aa'd, even when ac is an impossible
class. Thus the equation can only be maintained by equating
the impossible class ac or aa' d to zero ; then and then only the
right result, a (b + c) = ab, is obtained. The same is true of all
the equational forms which attempt to represent dichotomy.
The fundamental one is x+x' = I (=all reality). Now, 1£ ~ 1s
real, x' (or not-x) includes not only the part of reality which
is not-x, but all unrealities or all 1mpossible classes Thus the
equation would falsely make reality include unrealities, and this
can only be prevented by equating the unreal part of x'
to zero.
Similarly the equation a = ax+ax', which may be regarded
as an application of the above, is given as always true But
if a is real (and even though x and x' arc restricted to realities),
one of the classes on the r1ght-hancl side of the equation may
be unreal For instance, if all a 1s x, then ax' is xx' and ax' 1s
11nposs1blc. The equation, then, 1:,, only saved by equating ax'
to zero, when we get a = ax, wh1c,h 1s true.
All 1rnpossibihties, then, are equated to zero. Thus, 1f A 1s
Band Xis Y,
AB' = o, XY' = o, AA' = o, BB' = o, XX' = o, YY' = o,
and so on.
1n this equating of the impossible to zero, two points are to
be noticed and distingmshed. First, all imposs1bilit1es are
equated to the same, which has the effect of equating them to
one another a result which equally follows 1£ they are not
equated to zero, provided they are equated to the same thing.
Secondly, each 1mposs1b1hty 1s equated to zero
§ 390 In algebra both these statements would be considered
fallacies and elementary fallacies. Familiar examples, which
illustrate the principle involved in the equation of all impossibles
to zero, are such as the following. Every person in the next
room can prove that the diagonal of the square is commensurable
with the side. This statement 1s supposed by some to be fully
justified because there are no persons in the next room. Agam,
every person who can marry a person who hved a thousand years
ago can prove the diagonal of a square to be commensurate
Symbolic; Logic;
with its side. This is justified by saying that there are no
persons in either category.
The justification is a fallacy, and it is partly on this fallacy,
we may remark incidentally, that the modern form of the
doctrine of the reduction of the categorical to the hypothetical
proposition depends.1 Moreover, the most bnlliant and striking
part of modern mathematics, the treatment of so-called imagi-
nary quantities, depends on a prmciple which makes it a fallacy.
In algebra the proof that 1mposs1bil1ties can neither be equated
to one another nor to zero 1s easily given. Probably most, if
not all, of us, when we first arrived at a result of the form
x2 +I= o, therefore x2 = -1, 1f we avoided the mistake of
putting x = - I, and saw x to be impossible because the equa-
tion makes x equal to the square root of - I, rightly said that
no quantity would sc1.ttsfy the cquat10n and then wrongly trans-
lated this mto x = o. The mistake 1s corrected by observmg
that x = o will not satisfy the given equation For, put x = o
and we get the absurdity o = I.
Again the equation of impossibles to one another is easily
disproved For suppose a and b real quantities and unequal.
If ✓ - I a = ~ b, because both are impossibles, then if we
operate on each side by the mverse operation of the root, that
1s, if we square them, we get -a = -b, and therefore a and
b are equal. Thus the equation of 1mposs1bles or imaginaries
to one another involves the equation of all real quantities to
one another.
§ 391." If at first this simple opera- v
t10n of squaring seems suspic10us,
we have a better illustration m a
more concrete form in the application
of algebra to geometry. Take a point A
0 in a straight line and, at a given dis-
tance a, draw another straight hne at
right angles to the hne From the
given pomt as centre describe a circle
of radius less than a and therefore not
cutting the straight hoe AY. If we combine the equation of
l Cf § 400.
[& Cf § II6]
R.
SPECIAL LoGtC
the circle with that of the straight line we find, for the distances
of the intersection of the two from A, two impossible quantities,
that is, reals affected with the sign ~ - If we describe
another concentric circle also not cutting AY, we get for its
intersections with AY two other impossible quantities, different
from the first in form, depending on the difference of radius.
Two different sets of impossibilities thus correspond to the
different equations of the two circles, which really means that
the 1mpo,ssibihty of one's cuttmg the hoe is different from the
impossibility of the other's cutting the line. If now we identify
the two 1mpossibilitics, we identify the equations of the two
circles and get the absurd result that all circles with the same
centre O which do not meet AY coincide with one another.
That the equation of impossibles to one another would imply
the equation of unequal realities to one another, and indeed the
equation of all realities to one another, 1s a thing we should
anticipate on quite general grounds. For an impossibility is
only the other side of a necessity ; every different necessity
gives rise to a d1fierent 1mposs1bihty And so there is nothing
mysterious m the treatment by mathematiuans of impossibilities
as definite, not as mere nothmgs merged m an mdistmgmshable
zero. Thus, if we identify different impossibilities with one
another, we shall expect to find that we have thereby identified
the corresponding necessities with one another. 1
§ 392. • Professional, and mdeed distinguished, mathemati-
cians, no mere amateurs, have invented this system of symbolic
logic, and so it may seem strange that they should have allowed
the equation of each impossible to zero ; but perhaps there were
these reasons for it. First, the equational form cannot be
maintained without it. Secondly, by the help of it, an equa-
tional system is produced which is coherent within its own
limits, Just as in algebra, if we equate the unreal roots of equa-
tions to zero, we shall find the real roots correctly enough, and
may avoid the contradiction resulting from the equation of
unreals to zero by refusing to consider unreals any further. In
this way, however, algebra would be cut down to very narrow
1
Cf §400.
C
x X
z explained. - (accordmg to mathematical an-
- - - ___ .vz alogy) repre?ents the mverse operation of xy.
It 1s explained most simply thus :
Let sy = x, then s 1s a class such that when restricted by y it
reduces to x. If, then, we write z is ~, we get this mcamng for
:Y
,,
~, that it represents any class which being restricted by y reduces
to x.
Thus, if we have given that z is ~, 1t follows that zy = x, in
y
fact we may multiply as in algebra. Observe, however, that
such an equation may be satisfied by more classes than a single
Symbolic Logic 655
given one as s, e. g. by w as in the figure. Thus from sy = x,
we cannot infer s ... ~ but that s is ~
'Y
y
,,
one of the solutions of ~ (w, e. g.,
X
bemg another). Thus, though we can z w
yw
multiply, we cannot divide. We can,
however, infer from zy = x,
that s =v ,,
~.
Now suppose the equation given
a
ex =b
Where a, b, c are real classes and x is to be determined by the
equation. Then we have bcx = a (2)
a
and X=V- (3)
bc
Suppose also the equation given
C = b' . (4)
Then a
b' X = b from (1)
and bb'x = a • from (2)
where bb' 1s an impossible class.
In tho equation x2 + I = o, or x2 = - I, though x is unreal
we have not the equation of a real quantity to an unreal, for
the square of x 1s not unreal.
( ( - 1)l)I = - I
The 1mposs1blc operation on - I, viz. ( - I )l, is removed by its
inverse ( ra,thus leaving - I where it was, that is, ac; - r. The
same is true of bb'x =a; we have not got the equation of an
impossible to a real, for (by the above)
a
X =V bb'
But if ,,
!J&
z = -, z = x+vy', z = x(y) +vy'(x').
,, ,,
classes, just as ~ 1s supposed to do. If ~ represents a class = s,
we have zy = x,
therefore, if z = 6,z · o = o.
s, then, 1s such a class that, if operated on by zero, it yields
zero. Now any class will do this Thus s may be any class.
i
The mference Venn drew from this 1s, ' stands for any logical
class whatever; that 1s, it is perfectly indefimte •. To this
Wilson of course replied that it doei, not stand doubtfully for
some or other, we do not know which, 1t stands for every one
indifferently and so for all. So he made great fun of Venn's
symbol
6,which attempts symbolically to represent a class such
that, when we take none of 1t, we yet obtain all. As usual he
tried to penetrate to the true cause of these contradictions.
They anse not because the coefficients are wrong but from
a wrong view of the coefficients themselves. The confusion
arises, he believed, from forgetting a principle in the substitution
of definite values for variables in a given function. In ,t, (xy)
we can substitute at will, 1£ x and y are independent ; but if
there is a law connecting x and y, or limiting the range of their
independence, we cannot so substitute and still retain the
,,
meaning of the function. Thus m ~, the form of the function
prescribes that all :J& is y. Then 4' (or), or q, (10), is an impossible
substitution, if 01 or 10 1s to be a class. Thus, if such a meaning
66z SPECIAL LOGIC
is to be given to the coefficient, the expansion formula cannot
be applied.
Much care was devoted by Wilson to showing that the calculus
is not in the least adapted to the solution of such difficult
formal problems as are mentioned above. On the contrary it
is painfully clumsy and long, even in the solution of fairly
simple problems. It solves problems of its own creation, but
even those can be done quicker and better without any calcu\u·s
at ali, by a method mvolvmg only Barbara and immediate
infert.nce. Wilson spent much time on the mvent1on of such
a simple method, as well as on a plulosophic toy of his own,
as he c'l.lled 1t, a fractional method , and it was characteristic
of him that he should have spent so much time trying to beat
the symuob<1ts at their own game. Hts httle book On the
Traversing of Geometrical Figures arose out of notions suggested
by these ~tudies, and so <ltd lus arduous attempts to prove
a theorem, which is connected with cltsJunctivc reasoning, the
famou,. four-colour theorem ]
PART V
TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
AND PHILOSOPHICAL CORRESPONDENCE
I
THE NATURE OF A 'THING'
82
II
THE UNIVERSn.L AND ITS DIFFERENTIATIONS
§ 406. AccORDING to the natural use of words, universal would
mean that wluch 1s 1dent1cal m a number of particulars and is
thereby d1stmgmshed from the d1vers1ty m which 1t 1s identical.
Nor 1s it merely identical but something defimte which is
1dent1cal m them I have called this distmctive character the
quality or the characteristic bcmg of the umversal. The uni•
vers.11 so understood as genus takes of its own nature specific
forms or species ; lmcanty is either rectilmcanty or curvi-
hneanty, colour 1s blue, red, &c. It 1s identical m the universals
which arc· its !>pec1cs, they ,ue nothmg outside 1t but belong to
its own nature, c1ddncss and evenness arc included m the nature
of number The aggregate of the specH's belongs to the nature
of the geuu,; and might seem to constitute its full nature, so
Aristotle sclys the genus 1c; nothmg but the species " This 1s,
however, 1mposs1blc, for the genus 1s identical m its forms and
their aggregate cannot be somct hmg 1dent1cal m each of them.
We cannot say the gcnu'l 1'l each of its specific forms, or any or
all of them together, becc1use zs m such a statement naturally
means '1s 1dcnt1cd.l with'
Agam the umvC'rsal c,mnot be except as an identity in the
particulars Of 1t& own nature 1t necessitates the particulars as
that in which 1t must be identical The particulars belong to
its own nature and arc nothmg apart from 1t. Yet here again
we cannot, any more than m the case of the umversals which
are species, identify any one of them or their aggregate with
the universal. The complete reality of the system of particulars
has d1stmgu1shablc within it the umversal and its particulariza-
tion. The complete system of particulars may be mfimte and
[•Tlus seems to refer to a tentative remark at Met 998b 28 For Anstotle's
real view see Physics, 210• 17-19, and ' Further the members of the definition
which 1s explanatory of the md1v1dual are parts of a whole Thus the genus
18 part of the speCles and m another sense the species of the genus • Mel.
10.a3b 23]
The Unive,saJ and its Differentiations 671
may not be realized all at one time, but in any particular
whatever the universal and its particularization are united.
§ 407. Thus the class is not accurately called the complete
reality of the universality, but rather the complete reality which
the nature of the universal necessitates. The saying that there
is nothing in the species but the genus is not accurate in form.
It is only true so far as the species 1s necessitated by the genus's
own nature A truer statement would be that there is nothing
m the specific universal (e. g evenness and oddness) except the
differentiation wluch belongs to the nature of the generic
umversal (e. g number)
Observe, however, that 1£ the nature of A necessitates B,
A and B are by 1mplicat10n different. A cannot be identified
with B, and it may be that B cannot be called a part of A,
though necess1tatmg B may be called a part of A's nature. For
example, though surfaC"cness necessitates volume, we cannot say
that there 1s nothmg m volume but surfaceness The latter,
however, does not offer an adequate analogy to the relation we
are considering. The necessitation through which the particular
appears as havmg its nature compnscd m that of the umversal
has no analogy , 1t 1~ a umque relat 10n between necessitatmg
and necessitated. We cannot say anythmg of the particular
(mdiv1dual) wluch is not universal, except the mere 'this' and
'that'. On the other hand, not to rest the matter on an appeal
to language (important though such an appeal is), what we
apprehend m the particulars 1s the umversal which is their
d1stmctive kmd of bemg and which is m md1v1duals of absolutely
the same umversal , besides that universal we apprehend only the
one and the other of the same kmd.
§ 408. But to return to the umty of the genus in the species.
The difference here between the species cannot be reduced to
a mere this and that. Straightness 1s a kmd of being, not a mere
this lineanty ; straightness is a form of lmeanty, but lmearity
1s not a form of straightness. They are mseparably united in
the same real individual, but not in the way m which, for
instance, surface and volume are united. These two are equally
determinate, linearity and straightness are not, the latter being
more determinate. Thus the umque idea of determination is
necessary to characterize what is meant. The genus is identical
TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
in its determinations, but not identical with them. We under•
stand this by examples and can say nothing truer or better of
the specific universals than that they are determinations of the
genus, for to say they are the forms it takes is to employ a mere
metaphor If, now, we include under determination differentia·
tion of species and part1culanzatlon in md1viduals1 the deter·
mmation of the umvcrsal 1s completed m individuals, which
themselves mvolve its determmation m species. ·
§ 409. The term nccess1tat10n 1s not adequate to express the
relat10n of the umversal to the manifold of species and of
individuals. For v.hile it 1s true that hneanty necessitates its
kmds, 1t is also true that straightness presupposes and so neces•
sitates hneanty, and through the latter necessitates curvi-
hnearity So a particular lme necessitates lmeanty and through
that all particular Imes. On the other hand, the whole bemg
of hncarity is not to be a kmd of surfaceness, though these two
necessitate one another Thus the complete reality relative to
any umversal 1<; nee css1tated either by that umversal or by any
one of its species or of its m<liv1cluals What has to be taken
mto account 1s the particular km<l of neccss1tat1on The whole
bemg of curv1lmcanty 1s, m one sense, comprised m that of
the umveri;al lmeanty, m the sense that its whole bemg 1s to
bt• a kmd of lmeanty; but, m another, 1s not, m the sense of
bemg a part of 1t 01 an clement m it , otherwise as lmeanty 1s
1dent 1cal m its two species, so must the latter be Part of,
element of, do not express the relation, whereas kmd of, species
of, differentiation of, <lo express 1t, for 1t 1s a relation sui genens.
So the whole bemg of a p.irticular hne 1s to be a particular, not
a part, of lmeanty. Again the term 'comprise' 1s itself too
general, for the bemg of lmeanty c..:m be said to be comprised
m that of surfac<'ness. Nor c.in we use include m its natural
sense, for though the genus seems to mclude the species and
the particulars, v.ha.t 1s mcluded 111 1ts nature seems necessarily
to be m 1t wherever 1t 1s, and so, 1f we said the genus 'includes'
them, we should agam have one species m another species and
one individual m another. The point 1s that the species have
not only got something identical m them but that whatever else
they have somehow belongs to this identical somethmg. Red-
ness, m fact, agrees with blueness in that in which it differs
The Universal antl its Di,fferentiations 673
from blueness. It has colourness in common with it, but it
also differs from it in colour and in nothing else. Colourness
inevitably covers the whole nature of redness and of blueness.
We must therefore examine the language in which we express
th.ts relation, to see what it is which makes us feel that somehow
the nature of the generic universal {for instance, colour) covers
and includes the whole nature of the species.
§ 4rn. In ordinary unphilosoph1cal language we say a lme
must be either straight or curved. This really expresses a con-
nexion of universals. Can we put this technically in the dis-
Junctlve form, lmeanty is l'ither straightness or curvilinearity?
Now 1f we say A is either B or C, when A is not a universal,
we mean that A is B or that A is C. This agam would be true
if A is B and not C, or C and not B, or if A is B and A is C.
But we cannot substitute linearity for A and the specific uni-
versals for Band C in these statements. We cannot, for mstance,
say lmeanty is rectllmeanty and lmeanty is curvilmeanty. The
disJunctive statement, then, is either quite wrong or at least
misleading, for 1t cannot be mterpreted as the verbal formula
of which it is an example is usually interpreted. It is, however,
true that any particular lmearity, the lmearity of any given line,
is either rectihnearity or curvilinearity, where these two terms
do not stand for universals, so the sentence means that any
particulanzat10n of linearity is a particularization of rectl•
lmeanty or of curvilinearity. Here the disjunctive has a normal
signification. But we can't say that linearity as universal
{linearity m general as the phrase goes) 1s rectdmeanty. How,
then, can we accurately express that there is nothing but
colourness m blueness, blue is all of 1t colour, there is nothing
but hneanty m rect1lineanty? A particular lmeanty (this line)
is a particular rectlhneanty and conversely. This hne, then,
has nothmg m it but lmcanty m the sense that it is entirely
a part1cular1zation of lmeanty and has 1ts whole bemg com-
prised m and constituted by that, yet not every particulariza-
tion of lmeanty 1s a part1culanzation of rectdinearity. But the
relation of the particularizat10ns depends upon the relation
between. the umversals themselves, so the real question is about
this relation. It is not enough to say the particularization of
one is a particularization of the other, for this does not show
TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
which is the generic universal, and is compatible with neither
being genus, as in the case of tnlateralness and triangularity.
§ 41 I. The relation of course is that of differentiation. The
whole nature of blueness is constituted by its be10g a species
of colourness, not m bemg colourness. Colourness as such,
viz of itself, must have for its differentiations blueness, &c.
It 1s the peculiar nature of differentiation, umque and only
10telhg1ble m examples, which makes us say that there is
nothmg hut colour 10 blueness or that colour takes the forms
of bluene,c;, redness, &c. We may solve the difficulty by
reference to the analogy of a body which preserves 1ts umty,
though 1t 1s now 10 one place, now m another. The body as
existent at different places has a variable being and yet 1s
1dent1cal Bemg somethmg here and somethmg there arc not
something <lifferent from its bcmg though associated with 1t, they
belong to its bemg Remammg completely identical the body
is thus d1ficrcnt at different times Yet by an argument similar
to the above about genus and species we could prove that if
B 1s 111 n•~ bemg here and m B's bemg there, B's bcmg here
must be m H's bcmg there, or that B m bemg there must also
be here As we h.1ve Sl'cn, its complete bemg is the complete
series of what it 1s at all different times, what 1t was, 1s, and
will Le ; winch mcludes its identical permanent being In this
1dcnt1cal bemg 1s mcluded its quality of havmg the series of
phases of variable bemg , so that, m this sense, the whole of
its variable bemg 1s comprised m the identical bcmg Suppos10g
1t to rcmam, for the sake of s1mphc1ty, unchanged m volume
and shape, 1ts identical bemg, what 1t 1s m all times and places,
1s the universal volume and shape together with the law accord10g
to which 1t moves The variable bemg 1s not the identical bemg
nor a part of 1t, yet 1s a part of the bemg of the body and 1s,
wlule not a part or constituent element of the identical bemg, still
comprised m the above sense m the identical bemg. The diverse
forms of bemg are not somethmg necessitated by the thmg's
being, as line 1s by surface (where line 1s not what surface is), but
are mcluded 10 its being ; they are true parts of 1ts being though
not of its identical bemg, wholly comprised m the bemg of the
identical thmg, for they are what 1t 1s, and there 1s nothing in
them except the bcmg of B.
The UnifJwsal and its Dijfwentiations 675
§ 412. It is important to observe that we do not identify the
thing which is identical with its complete being. For the thing
exists now but has not yet its future being, If we did this, we
should make the past and future present. Potentiality is not
able to express this relation, because that refers to the future,
and we seem to have no word for the relation of the present
actuality to the past actuality. So 1f we ask how the universal
which 1s an identity in present particulars can also be an identity
m particulars which have ceased to be and which have yet to
be, we have an exact parallel in the existence of the individual
thmg. A movmg body 1s now somethmg which, rcmammg the
same, will be hereafter m a position not yet reached, a state
which has not yet come into existence. Similarly it 1s the same
universal which 1s m these present particulars and will be in
others not yet existent.
§ 413. How, then, this umty m d1vers1ty 1s possible we under-
stand by the 1llustratlon, and we can only understand it in this
way. Usmg language parallel to that about body, we can say
that the genenc universal (colourness, lmeanty) 1s an identity in
diverse forms of bcmg (blueness, &c, straightness, &c.), so that
we arc nght to say lmcanty is rectdmcanty or curvilinearity
but not simply lmeanty 1s rcctilmeanty. The former expression
1s perm1ss1ble because the or shows what is meant We cannot
say ' lmeanty 1s rectilmeanty ', for that would express either
identity or that rectilmearity was wider than lmeanty. ' Recti-
lineanty is lmeanty ' is also unnatural. ' Rectilmearity is a form
of lmeanty ' is too metaphorical, but we may say ' is a kmd of ',
for this expresses the true relation and, though kmd may have
been in its origm metaphorical, it has ceased to be so. The
species, then, are parts of the whole bemg of the genus but not
parts or elements of its 1dentlcal being,-that 1s, what it is in
the species 1dentlcally. They are wholly comprised m the being
of the genus, for they are what 1t 1s and must be ; they are
also comprised m its identical being in the special sense that
the identical being 1s such as to necessitate these kinds of being,
these differentiations, for itself; not comprised, however, as
constituent elements of that identical being Further, the genus
universal is not to be identified with the totality of its bemg as
the species, for it is that which 1s identical m all of them ; nor
TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
is it the potentiality of its realized species but only of those not
yet realized. It is also true that there 1s nothing m the specific
universals except the being of the genus Colourness covers the
whole nature of blueness and redness , blueness differs from
redness only m colourness
§ 414. A s1m1lar ac1.-vunt 1s to be given of the mdividual. Its
bcmg 1s entirely comprised m the bemg of the umversal ; it is
a part of that whole bemg, not a part of its identical being, a11d
the sum of the md1v1duals, with the universal which 1s identical
m them, 1s the complete bemg of the umversal but not to be
idcTJ.tifteu with the identical bemg of that universal. In any
part of the whole set of particulars the bemg of the universal
1s incomplete but 1ts 1dcnt1cal bemg 1s not incomplete. This we
can only understand from mstanccs, Just as 1t was only by
inc;tances that we understood the 1dcnt1cal bemg of body in 1ts
va.rymg positions m space. It 1s important to observe what the
idea of this 1denhcal being leads to Tlus bemg, which it 1s,
is not any temporal bemg and cannot be identified with any
temporal being AE> we saw in the casr of the broken body,
tht: parts as ex1E.tcnt at various times m the past and as existent
now must have the same non-temporal character And 1t 1s the
same with the identity of the umvcrsal.
III
MODERN FALLACIES ABOUT THE UNIVERSAL
§ 415. WE will now examine certain modern fallacies which
have arisen from a failure to understand the true nature of the
umversal. And first, that particularity is itself a universal.
Universals arc d1stmgu1shed from one another by their d1s-
tmct1ve characteristics or characteristic bemg. But this, which
is their quality, also d1stmgmshes their particulars from the
particulars of other universals Besides bemg this or that
particular, besides mere particularity, two particulars of the
same umversal have no other distmction, unless the umversal 1s
diversely differentiated m them, so that they are of different
species Universals, then, cannot differ from one another in
the manner m which particulars do, 1. e. as particulars. If two
universals, Mness and Nness, be particulars of Lness, their dis-
tmchve quality is Lness and Lness only. Now 1f they are not
related as different kinds of Lness, they are 1dent1cal m quality,
viz. Lncss, and only d1ffer as this or that Lness. They are
identical m cverythmg universal m them, differ m nothmg which
1s universal. And they are also presumed to be universals. But
two universals which differ m nothmg which 1s uruvcrsal do not
differ at all They arc umversals not d1ffermg m characteristic
being and so not d1ffermg m the only way m which umversals
can differ. If we particularize Mness and Nness we shall simply
get mdividual cases of Lness, For Mness is this Lness and
Nness 1s that Lness, and the only umvcrsal to be particularized
is Lness. The class of M's could only appear as so many L's,
and the same would be true of the class of N's. Thus the
d1stmct1ve character of a universal cannot be the distinctive
character or quahty of another universal, unless that other
umversal 1s a species of itself (or the genus which mcludes
itself). If, then, Mness and Nness do not so differ but are
different only as thts Lness and that Lness, they differ in their
particularity, that is, by something which cannot be identical
TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
in different things and therefore cannot be a universal. We
may express this obvious truth by the formula ' particularity is
not a universal '.
f 416. The fallacy may be illustrated very simply by applying
it to md1v1duals Let A1, A1, A3, &c., be each an A. Then
Aness is common to Lhcm and each 1s a particular of Aness.
Now since each 1s a particular of Aness, bemg particulars of
Anes~ would appear to be a new universal of which they are
md1v1dual instances But that this new universal 1s common
to th~m is only mtelhgible as meaning that Aness is common
to them .i.s the universal of which they arc particulars. What
1s common to them, then, so far from bemg 'particularity of
Aness' reduces to Aness, and the false umversal, which 1s merely
verbal, disappears Moreover, 1f the process by which the false
umversal was obtained were continued we should clearly have
an infimtc series of such universals In fact, when we say
particularity 1s common to this particular and to certain others,
we mean that havmg a umversal common to 1t and others 1s
common to ccrtam others and to 1t
However, the umversal common to all particulars might be
said to be their bcmg particulars of some universal or other,
not necessarily the same. Now 1f we say every A 1s either
B or C, we might infer that 1t 1s common to every A to be
either B or C and so 'bemg either B or C' might be represented
verbally as a umversal common to every A. But this 1s absurd.
Each of these men is either a good man or a criminal gives
a common verbal statement for each, but 1t does not assign
anythmg m common to them, nor 1s 1t intended to do so. A is
either B or C only gives something in common to them, 1f D
1s the umverScJ.l of B and C, and then the proper statement is
that every A 1s D. Consequently the statement that each
particular 1s a particular of some universal or other and there-
fore shares in particularity does not state anything common to
particulars If, however, 1t is said that every umversal is
a species of some common universal, and we then mfer from
this that all particulars are particulars of one umversal, this 1s
exposed to the previous criticism of the representation of the
particularity of a given universal as itself a umversal.
§ 417. A similar mquiry will show that universality is not
Modem Fallacies about the Universal 679
a true universal. A universal (redness) is a definite kind of
being identical in particulars. A universal is a particular kind
of universal being, and this is what is meant by saying that
redness is a universal. It is a species of universal being, which
is the genus of all other universals, unifying them as its species,
not as a universal in particulars. A false universal can be
constructed as before and be framed in the words ' being a species
of universal bemgness '. 'Redness is a universal' 1s not equivalent
indeed to ' redness 1s a universal being ' ; redness 1s a kmd of
universal bemg, a differentiation, not a particularization of
universal being. This last sentence 1s m fact a concise refutation
of the whole fallacy
§ 418. S1mdarly speciesncss is a false universal. This would
be to say that because AXness, BXness, &c , are species of
Xness, the quality of being a species of Xness, viz (species of
Xness)-ness, is the universal of each of the species. Here the
distinctive character of the universal bemg AXness, there is
added to this the relation to Xness, viz. bemg a species of
Xness. This, then, is treated as part of the whole quality, which
is now AXness and bemg a species of Xness But the addition
is superfluous smce it is already contained in the form A added
to Xness, which precisely means a differentiation of Xness.
Blue colour means the blue species of colourness. AXness 1s
not merely a differentiation of Xness, 1t is the special differentia-
tion which is AXness. Thus its bemg as specification of Xness
is equivalent to its being as the A specification of Xness, and
this is exactly AXness In ' AXness is a species of Xness ', the
indefinite article 1s fallac1ously treated as indicating particu-
larization whereas it indicates the differentiation of a universal.
We may see this in another way. Bemg a species of Xness is
common to AXness, BXness, &c. But what 1s common to them
is Xness, as their genus. The fallacy therefore arises by sub-
stituting for the genus which is common to them, their having
the genus common to them. Xness is common to AXness, &c.,
therefore having Xness as genus common to them 1s common
to them. The form 1s artificial and merely verbal, and only
intelligible as meaning Xness 1s their common genus.
§ 419. The general nature of the fallacies which have been
examined is now evident. They arise from the assumption that
68o TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
the following statement is true, whatever A and X may be : ' If
it can be truly said that A is an X, then A is a particular of
the universal Xness.' This, however, is not true for every
meaning of A and X. In every universal, on the contrary, what
may be called the character of the universal must be distinguished
from its universality vr its community (of a special kind) with
what 1c; subordinated to 1t. The fallacies in question arise from
an unguarded generalization. In regard to ordinary universals
with a definite character common to their particulars which are
mdJVJduals, 1t can truly be said that if A 1s an X, A 1s a particular
of Xness. If now we substitute for X not the character of the
umvers.~1 but its universality (or what may be called, in a wide
sense of the word relation, the relation of the character to the
particulars), or agam the fact of its part1culanzatton or some
substitution of the rcl..1.llon of d1ffercntiat1on (specification) for
the rhar..1.cter d1fferent1ated, we get the false universals already
examined. Thus A is an X, therefore A 1s a 'particular of
Xncss '.
Now the second statement 1s itself of the same form as the
first ; 1t follows, then, that A 1s a particular of · bemg a particular
of Xness ', whence there results an mfimte regress, for we can
obv10usly continue the unreal process of substitution Agam,
smce A 1s a part1rular of Xness and A 1s a particular of ' bemg
a particular of Xncss ', we have either that 'bcmg a particular
of Xness ' 1s a species of Xness, wluch 1s unposs1ble, or Xness is
identified with 'bemg a particular of Xness ', which 1s nonsense.
Indeed Xness 1c; identified with each of an mfimte series of
universals
§ 420 It 1s important, m view of what has been said, to
formulate the different wayc; m which one universal may neces-
sitate another, for otherwise the phrase 'necessitate' may be
used as 1f it had one and only one meaning
In the first place, the relation properly understood 1s always
reciprocal One universal may so necessitate another that all
the bemg of one not only mvolves but is the being of the other.
Thus every trilateral dosed figure 1s triangular and every tri-
angular closed figure 1s trilateral. If Xness thus mvolves Yness,
every X 1s a Y and every Yan X. Here it is not quite correct to
say that every form of the one 1s a form of the other. Equilateral
ModMn Fallacies about the Universal 681
trilateralness (X1) is not identical with a form of triangularity
(Yness), but any particularization of the form trilateralness
(e.g. X 1, equiangular trilateralness) is a particularization of
the form tnangularity (e.g. Y1 , equiangular triangularity).
Thus it is not enough to say that the eXJstence of one umversal
necessitates that of the other (as the eXJstence of surface neces•
sitates that of line), but we must say that the existence of one
umversal so necessitates the existence of the other that every
particularization of the one must be a particularization of the
other. The necessitation bcmg of thts nature, all the X's are
particulars of Yness, and the members of Yness are mdividuals
and not classes such as the X class. The umversals are co-
extensive, but one 1s not the umversal of something of which
the particular of the other must be an attribute ; the universals
are not related hke hncanty and surfaceness. This is the second
kmd of necess1tat1on which we are now to consider Here Aness
necessitates Bness m such a way that the identical being of
Aness has Bness mseparable from it, in its identical being. For
example, surfaceness and linearity necessitate one another in
their identical nature, but every part1culanzat1on of surface is
not a part of lmearity m the sense above cxplamed. Aness and
Bness reciprocally condition one another, but each 1s not on
that account an 1dent1ty m all that m which the other is an
identity. All bemg of surface mvolves bemg of lme, but all
being of surface 1s not all bemg of hI\c, If we consider a particular
lme, this line is an attribute of this surface (as its boundary).
In this way the particulars x, &c (given Imes), of one, Xness
(linearity), are attributes or elements m the particulars y, &c.
(given surfaces), of the other, Yness (surfaceness), and m this
way X 1s attribute to Y.
Here the total of the particulars of Xness do not form one
particular or class of Yness, but are elements or attributes in
the particulars of Yness, each m each Thus Yness cannot have
the class of X's as its particular.
Thirdly, two umversals may necessitate one another as attri-
butes of the same subJect, for example, the weight and solidity
of a body, but neither weight nor solidity 1s an attribute of the
other. Here the particulars of neither are particulars of the
other, nor are the total of the particulars of either a particular
682 TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
of the other. The universals, then, of such subjects with attri•
butes (the subjects being heavy solid bodies) have the sams
particulars. Thus Yness {bodiness) cannot have the class of
heavinesses or the class of solidities as its particulars.
(Fourthly, of two universals one may necessitate the other as
the genus umversal necessitates the species universal. Here the
class of X's are as one a member of the class of which Y is the
quality Thus any particular X has its nature determined by
the nature of Yness, and as Yness is not identical with Xness,
thr nature of Yness must necessitate that of Xncss m the well•
understood relation of genus to species. Thus the x's are all
particulars of Yncss, and therefore Yness cannot have for a
member the class of Xncss itself Xness m fact is not a particular
member of the genus class as its own members arc members of
it, but Xnt-ss ic; a part of the genus class ; its members, not
itself, bemg members of the given class Yness] •
§ 421. Lastly we may rons1cler umversals which are presumed
to have no common gcnuc;, that is, umvcrsals wluch are them-
selves summa genera An attempt might be made to umfy them
under their common predicate umversaltty. Now we have seen
that any umvl'rc,al to be umfied must be a umversal whose
particulars are md1v1duals. If, then, umversahty be supposed
to umfy these summa genera, the particulars of umversahty must
be individuals, smcc we have seen that the particulars of the
species are particulars of the genus But the only particulars
umvcrsahty can have must be universals. We therefore reach
the rontrad1ct10n that the particulars of umversahty, which are
by hypothesis universals, arc m fact the rndividuals which com-
pose the whole of the summa genera in question. Thus uni-
versality cannot be rd.ited to universals as their genus.
Thest' considerations seem to pomt to the conclus10ns that no
universal can be a particular of another umversal, that the
quality of bemg a species (spec1esness) 1s not a true universal,
and that particularity or particularness is also not a true
umvcrsal.
la This paragraph 1s supplied for completeness, cf § 423]
IV
CLASSIFICATION OF CLASSES
[Undated.]
8
§ 468. Dichotomy seems everywhere possible, because we
can divide a class mto the members which have a certam quality
and those which have not (I shall raise the question of the
value of this presently). There seems no such general ground
for trichotomy, so as to make it applicable everywhere. But
can we find any general reason for it or principle of it where
it is applicable, and so determme certain general characteristics
which the subject-matter to which 1t applies must have ?
Suppose two species of a genus are related as 'contraries' and
are the species of a given genus furthest removed from one
another according to the same principle of order. 7 If there is
1 6b 35. • TlJ,,.or dp,9µ6t, 7• 19 seq
1 •a,A 7',) mqfn. 1 11iiJp.a.1Ji 'Tel WTII a,a.ipu&v.
1
'Tl"Xii Ha. llia.&PffW, ·•"111 &a.ipmw.
• [Dr H Goudy had sent Wilson h!S article ' Trichotomy m Roman Law ',
with a request for cnticism]
• Anstotle defines iva.vTia. as ri •A1urrw dAA~Aoi" a.,,,T.,iroTa. ,., 'Tqi a.uT+; .,..,,,,
TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
one class 'between' them and with affinities to both, we get
a tripartite divtsion as of triangles into
those which have all their sides equal (equilateral},
those which have none equal (scalene), and
those which have two sides only equal (isosceles)-the latter
species bemg intermediate between the other two. But this
does not necessarily apply when there are two 'extreme' species,
for it is not necessary that there should be only one species
intervening. E. g. we may apparently divide four-sided figures
into three:
(I) those with all sides equal,
(2) those with no sides equal, and
(3) those with some sides equal.
But the third species divides into those with
(1) 2 sides equal and the remammg two unequal,
(2) 2 s1d1..-s equal and the remammg two equal to one another
but not equal to the first two,
(3) 3 sides equal.
And the co-ordinate d1v1sion 1s therefore mto 5, there being
three species intermediate to the extreme species.
Such tripartite d1v1s1011 therefore, wluch 1s based on there
being two 'extreme' species, depends entirely on the sub1ect-
matter and is not of universal apphcat1on even to the cases
which present 'extreme' species.
§ 469. Another trichotomy which has the look of generality
11 that of which masculine, femmme, and neuter, (in our) 1 class1-
fication of species of certain animals (e. g. bees and ants), is an
example. Here the members of a genus are classified according
to the presence or absence of a qua.lity (c. g. sex}, and the case
of presence shows two species (e. g male and female) only,
which are opposed to one another. Clearly this 1s not of general
application to the cases where a class can be divided according
to the presence or absence of a quality, for it is not necessary
that the presence of the quality should give rise to two species
only, like male and female. E. g. conics are divided into those
which have a centre and those which have not. If we confine
ourselves to real curves (excluding, i. e., straight lines as limits
of conics) there is only one species without a centre, the parabola.
• MS 'or'
Trichotomy
But there are three which have a centre, the circle, the ellipse
and the hyperbola.
§ 470. Thus the possibility of trichotomy depends on the
subject-matter entirely and {I} there is no general principle of
trichotomy applicable to all subjects, like dichotomy, (2) there
1s no general reason or principle of it for all cases where it is
applicable : no general characteristics which all the subject·
matter to which 1t 1s applicable must have and which always
determine that the division must be tnpartite.
§ 471. But we may go further. In dichotomy there is
apparently a general prmCJple of d1v1sion mto two : and one
applicable to all matter. This is an illusion. If we divide
X into A and not-A, the negative (mere) designation 1s mdeter-
minate, cannot determine a class. There 's nothing to prevent
the negative not-A from having sometimes several true classes
corresponding to 1t, which arc co-ordinate with A, so that the
d1v1s1on of X mto A and not-A should really be, e.g., into A
and Band C.
The negative may have one class correspondmg, Thus number
ts either even or not-even, and not-even = odd. But this
depends agam on the sul>Jcct-mattcr The mere negative not·
even cannot cktermme a dass, that 1s due to the positive
character of number d1v1dmg itself mto even and odd, both
pos1t1ve.
The mere ncgat10n, v,1thout thus correspondmg to a pos1t1ve
designation, may seem to detcrmme a class m such an example
as the d1v1s10n of cats mto those which have tails and those
which have not. The general account of this 1s that X being
divided mto A and not-A ; XA really = B + A and X
not-A= B. Thus X not-A 1s really defined by the quality B
and X is divided mto that which 1s B and A, and that which is
B only.
Thus there is not even a general prmc1ple which would yield
a true d1chotomy or d1v1S1on of a genus into two co-ordinate
species. And there is no general principle which would yield
a dlv1s1on into any defimte number of species, whether 2 or 3 or
more. The number must depend solely on the nature of the
special sub1ect-matter.
§ 472. This brings me to Hegel, for Hegel's principle does
seem to lead to a threefold d1v1s1on, and that would appear to
722 TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
conflict with my statement above. But the truth is that Hegel's
threefold division 1s not a d1vJS1on of a genus into species at all.
The Hegelian triads, m fact, arc not an example of trichotomy.
He supposes that 1f you take a conception and then its contra-
diction, there arises a tl11rd conception m which they are united
or reconciled E. g. umty and plurality are thus combined or
reconciled m totality. Now tlus 1s not a classification of members
of a g('nu,; mto 3 mutually exclusive species One and the same
thmg &hows the umty of a plurality of parts or elements in
a totality. There 1s here no question of the d1stmct1on of
a genus mto species. So also \\1th the combmatton of Being
and Not-Being m Becoming Not only 1s Hegel not properly
then a tnchotom1st, but I doubt whether 1t 1s at all fair to
Hegel to say that he ,..,as aficcted by any merely numerical
influence or superst1t10n His method 1s not founded on any
respect for the number three or for a threefold d1v1s1on. But
his principle of the umty of eontrad1rtories, as above explained,
necessarily produces tltc&c triads of roncept1ons I am not here
defending !us prmc1plc IJut only pomting out that 1t 1s founded
on no cons1dernt10n of number as such, though 1t gives nse to
these group,; of three
§ 473 Kant would be under more suspicion than Hegel, for
each of the 4 classes mto wluch he d1v1dcs Judgements (as to
quantity, quality, relation, and modality) contains three mem-
bers. In three of these he nught be said to find a threefold
d1v1s1on (Qua11t1ty mto Umvers,tl, Particular, and Smgular;
Relation mto Categorical, Hypothetical, and D1sJunctive; and
Modality mto Problematical, Ac:;sertorical, and Apode1cttcal).
But in Quality he will only find Affirm.itive and Negative. So
one suspects his addition of the Infuut<.', whtl h 1s clearly artificial,
was due to the wish to m.ike a thr<.'cfold d1v1s1on of the class,
correspondmg to the threefold d1v1s10ns m the other three
classes. But even tlus would not be due to a respect for the
number 3 but to a respect for symmetry. When Kant had got,
very arttfic1,1lly, his 12 Categories out of his logical d1stmction
of propos1t1ons, he discovered that, m some of the 4 classes,
the 3rd Category was the union of the 1st and 2nd. He agam,
art1fic1ally and affected by symmetry, supposed this true of the
3 categories m all the four groups, though 1t clearly is not the
Trichotomy
case. It was this unity of two in a third which suggested
Hegel's principle. But while Kant does not arrive at his cate•
gones from 1t, but observes the peculiarity in them when
found, Hegel finds his system of categories by means of the
principle.
§ 47 4. 1 You think there 1s here 'the most patent disregard of
logic'. I must here join issue with you on the logical point.
Your statement as it stands would condemn a procedure which
is perfectly logical and may only appear not to be so through
a difficulty which is mamly verbal.
Suppose we have a class X, which is divided into two, A and
B, and the class B 1s divided mto two, e. g. B1 and B2
~,,,/
Central
_,,,...- ------ ::---.
Non-central
/---------------------
asymptot.il non-asymptotal
I / ,
, - ~ ~
A1 -X 1Y1 A9 •X8Y
L ~=
A21 = X1Y1 A22 X8Y8
Thuc; A1 =- X 1 Y1 is nghtly co-ordmated m the differentiation
of X with A8 = X 2Y and nghtly co-ordmated as an ultimate
d1ffcrentiatton of A, or as an inftma species with A81 and Au-
The same kind of thmg happens if X 1 mvolves the d1fferentia-
t10n of some clement or elements m Y, but not of all.
Let Y = a/J, and let A2 = X 8a 2/J, because X 1 involves the
differentiation of a mto aa
Then A2 = X 2a2/J
/ '
_.,,/ '-..._
/~ ''-..._
A21 = X2a2f3J A22 = Xaaa/3a
We may get more steps, 1£ there arc more elements in A.
Thus 1£ A = XYZ, "e may get steps corresponding to the
above classificat10n of come sect10ns For suppose that X 1
necessitates Y1 Z1 , and X 2 leaves Y undifferentiated, whde Y 2
necessitates 2 2, and Y3 lcav<..'b Z undifferentiated :
A =XYZ
-- i\l - x;vz (central conic)
A21 ~ X 2Y2Z2 (h)'pcrbola) A21 ----= X 2Y8Z {closed)
So that A1, A11, A11111 , and A111 arc co-ordinate as infimae species.
Note also that, m strict accuracy, the language used above
(pp. 723-4) is not admissible. A ought not to be represented
Trichotomy 727
as a genus with only one species (A1 which coincides with it)
and similarly for the further concrete instances. In the fu])er
symbolism A1 ( = X1Y1Z1} is a species of A ( = XVZ), just as
much as A111 ( = X 1Y 8ZaJ. It looks like a genus, only because
A,., with which it 1s co-ordinated through the division of X1, is
a genus with regard to the infimae species A11, A 1111, A 1u,
Strictly, a genus with one species is a contradiction ID terms
and it 1s only allowable 1£ it means a genus which now has only
one existing species, though 1t had others once For examp1e,
if all species of a kind of plant have died out except one. But
this case can't occur in the mathematical examples)
Note to § 462 [ Ka8&.7rtp yap (/,arn Kal ol IlvOayopflOI, TO 'll"GJI Kal nl
'11'41/Ta TO°i§' TpllTLII i':Jp,crTal. TEh(VT~ yo.p ,cal µ.lcrov ,cal cipx~ TOIi cip16p.o11
lxu TOIi Toil 'll'a11nh·, TaVTa ae n'lv Tij5' Tp1&.ao§'. 311'1 'll'apa. Tijs (/,VITECIIS
i,>..71q,,fru: i'!Jrr'll'fp voµ.ovs EKt(v71s ,cal 'll'pOS Ttlf b:yl(TTf4ar XP~p.E9a TWJI
9EWJI T,ii lip,8µ.ip TOVT'f' • • • TO crwµ.a µ.ovov Av Ef1J TWII /J,EYEB&iv Tlhnov•
µ.ovov yup ~plUTat TOi5' Tp1rr£1•. (Aristotle, de Caelo, 268" IO seq.)
'For as the followers of Pythagoras also say, the whole
and the all is determined by "threes". For, they argue, end and
middle and beginning embrace the number of the whole, and
that is the number " triad ". Accordingly we receive from
Nature, as ID a sense her laws, this number and use 1t for the
worship of the gods . . Body alone of magmtudes would
appear to be complete, for 1t alone 1s determined by three.'
St. Thomas Aq. remarks on this passage: 'Quod ergo
Aristoteles d1C1t per hunc numerum adlubmmus nos 1psos magni•
ficare Deum unum, emmentem propnetat1bus eorum quae sunt
creata, non est sic mtclhgendum quod 1pse poneret ternarium
numcrum m dmm1s Sed uult d1cerc quod ant1qm utebantur
tcrnano numero in sacrificus et orat1ombus propter quandam
ternarit numeri perfcct1onem.' S. T. I, qu xxxu, art. I, ad
pnmum. This shows that the passage had been used in con·
troversy in the thirteenth century. There 1s a curious reference
to Aristotle's supposed doctrine m the Port Royal Logic, Part III,
ch. xix, § 3 (Non causa pro causa)
(It was usual m Greece to mvoke the gods in threes, not in
pairs; thus ID the Clouds, Socrates swears by Void, Clouds, and
Tongue (424), and agam by Breath, Void, and Air (627), but
the conscientious usurer by Zeus, Hermes, and Poseidon (1234).)
Cicero cnt1c1zes Epicurus for a mistaken trichotomy, De Fin.
1i. 9. Hegel ascribes to Kant the credit of drawmg attention to
the predominance of trichotomy m the sphere of the mind.
Logic, (Encyc.) § 230. Cf. Kant, K. der Urth., Introduction, § 9
(note).]
X
CORRESPONDENCE WITH B. BOSANQUET
§ 477.
I2 Fyfield Road,
7th July, 1903.
My dear Bosanquet,
I am returning your I st six pages and am sending also some
new notes on the subJect, as I do not think you quite realized
my points. If I have got wrong, I trust you will be as frank
as you wished me to be Error m these childish and verbal
(for that 's all they are) subtleties is exasperating, for it tends
to make these abject trifles seem important-as doubtless they
seem to the writer you wot of so I shall only be too glad
to have any mistake I have made put as clcar]y and poinudJ.y
as possible. Though I don't pretend to thmk I have made any
senous error, I know one 's never sc1fc
What I feel is that these arc simply difficulties for minds that
do not realize .1.ccurately the nature of grammatical distinctions,
and 1t makes me very angry that they should masquerade as
philosophy.
There are d1fficu]t1es coming from a want of realization of the
fact, on the part of the logician, that he 1s dealing mainly with
a linguistic (grammatical) question with which one has more
sympathy-e g the whole confusion of the stock distinction
(and its treatment) of the connotation and denotation of terms.
But this stuff makes one feel why PJato and Aristotle hated
the quibbling eristic with such a holy hatred. They must have
felt it so cheap and been so vexed that it could attract attention
and be mistaken for clever thinking.
As to the papers on Royce (by the way I daresay you would
like them back. How long may I keep them? You needn't
return what I am sending you this time as I have taken a copy
of the essentials-just as you like) I would rather write later on
1h41, when you have had time to consider what I am now
sending.
Corresf,onunce with Be,na,d Bosanquet 1•9
I will just say that though not quite ready yet to take the
field upon the whole • ketten' business on which R. 's puzzle
seems to depend, I have just a little to say on the fallacies to
which distinguished mathematicians are committing themselves
in our day, which may interest you.
I feel sure we shall get on, because I am attracted by what
I venture to think the grasp of such matters as' infinite number',
&c., shown in your Logic.
Will you however m the meantime when you next write tell
me what you yourself understand by a true and a false infinity,
and what you suppose Royce to mean by them. I observe that
reflective mathematicians are begmnmg to speak of true and
false infinity: but I don't know where they get 1t from nor am
(1) altogether sure I know what they mean by 1t. It can hardly
be Hegelian (can 1V), for would Hegel's idea of the 'mfimte', as
the non-finite and ac; therefore somethmg whole and unhm1ted
by anything else and therefore properly only the whole, be
applicable at all w1thm quantity (mere) ?-and of course 1t 's only
of quantity that these mathematicians are speaking (except, as
Ca1rd points out to me, that the formula which covers the whole
infinite series might be allowed by Hegel as the truest approach
to mfimte in quantity).
May I add I like controversy with a single person? In
a general talk of several I find I am too inclined to be afraid
of bemg shown to be m any way wrong, and to fight for my
hand. But that sort of feeling hardly exists, 1£ at all, when
discussing with no 3rd person to hear, and I like the clearest
and most unsparing statement
Yours truly,
J. CooK WILSON.
§ 478. The first three pages 1 are a little difficult to deal with
because the obJection does not seem clear. It mentions some-
thing about the difference between the class of classes and
ordinary classes which 1s on the whole true but seems irrelevant
as an ob1ection. Besides you interpose a cribc1sm on it yourself
in which you abandon an important statement, so that at is not
perhaps easy to see what really remains.
1 [Note1 appended to letter of 7 vh 03]
730 TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
I venture to imagine that l see what the matter is because
something similar happened when I read a paper like that sent
to you to our small society Isn't it that you began a little
too hastily-you observed I was talking of a class the 'members'
of which were not, or not necessarily, themselves groups or
classes; whereas it is distinctive of the class of classes to have
groups unified by a common element (or notion) as \ts
members.
When I read my paper and had completed the account of the
fallacy applied to any class whatever, and its refutation, one of
my hearers at once ob1ected that the 'class of classes' had the
above d1fference from an ordinary class. I simply begged him
to observe that I of course knew the supposed characteristic of
the class of classes, and asked Jum to be content at present to
judge whether I had proved my first pomt or not, viz. that the
paradox enunciated of the class of classe~, that it was a member
of itself, c.ould be estabhshed, on the line of the paradox, of any
clasc; whatever and was not a privilege of the class of classes-
and also that I had stated its refutation
Then he admitted this (as every one else chd), and then I asked
lum to hear me out for I had provided for the class of classes.
He admitted when he had heard the whole thing to the end
that I was nght. And I really think you began JUSt as he did,
whether you ,vill end as he did is another matter
I had really written a longish piece upon membership of
a class and the special character of membership of class of
classes, wluch I spJ.red lhem and you, because it seemed to me
one could shortly and neatly refute the fallacy m the way
I proposed. If I had sent that, you would have seen I was
quite awake to your runsiderataon.
I had better state exactly what my method is in order to
show the irrelevance of the objection (or half ob1ection).
§ 479. The paradox about the class of classes 1s that being
like the classes subordinate to it, m so far as it 1s a class and
they are each a dass, it h::i.s a common element with them (being
a class) m virtue of which 1t is classed with them, i e -a member
of a class of wluch they are also members
Now I undertake to show that it 1s a mistake to suppose such
a procedure applies only to the class of classes, and therefore
Co,respondence with Bwnard Bosanquet 731
the paradox or supposed bit of metaphysics (l 1) was not due
to the wonderful subtlety of making a class of classes, but
belonged to any class, however ordinary, common, or un•
clean.
I. I proved I think rigorously that, by the method of the
paradox, [that] the paradox could be shown true of any class-
taking the quite general symbol X for any class of things which
are X.
Now on page 4 you say apparently that you doubt whether
without niuch forcing I could apply the paradox to any class.
This puzzles me extremely-unless I may suppose that in hasti•
ness you merely thought of the aforesaid difference of the class
of classes and my X class, without first going through my
demonstration. It seems to me 1£ you would look at that, you
wouldn't find the slightest forcmg about 1t. It seems easy and
simple and I certamly thmk I have shown that to any class the
paradox could be applied and you haven't anywhere mdicated
any flaw m the demonstration.
§ 480. 2. (a) I showed that, without makmg any special pro•
vision for the 'class of classes', what I said of a class in general
could be apphed immediately to the class of classes-syllo•
gistically. For that it was only necessary to make a certain
substitution. For Xness substitute simply 'being member of
a class'. I didn't begm this way, but showed independently how
the paradox was developed m the class of classes and what was
its refutation But 1t struck me, after I found the general
application of the paradox. that it was quite easy to represent
the 'class of classes' case as a particular case of it : and it was
important to do so as the full nature of the fallacy 1s the better
elucidated. Besides it helps to show that 1t is a mistake to
suppose the whole thmg a unique characteristic of the class of
classes.
(b) I gave, what I put rather shortly at the end of the paper
sent to you, a treatment of the class of classes as such. and
without bringmg 1t under the general theory as m (a).
In this way I satisfied my obJector (who is one of the acutest
people here) because I not only treated the class of classes on
it, ~wn merits-with special attention to its nature as having
,lasses for its members, which was what he wanted, but l also
1773-a Y
732 TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
gave him a new view of it whlch hadn't occurred to him (or to
any of my hearers) by showing the analogous thing in any class
whatever. I attach importance to the last, because clearly the
people who advertise the paradox imagine it due to their clever
•class of classes '.
(By the way it 1s a mistake to suppose-if anybody does-
that the class of classes is the only class which has classes for
its 'members'. I shall come to that presently.)
§ 481. Let me now return to the first part of my argument.
Perhaps I put it too shortly (a habit coming from my smattering
of mathematics) but I stated essentials, and thought it could
be easily worked out.
I will now detail 1t fully-or as fully as necessary. First we
may show that, 1f W is the class of classes, [that] it is nghtly
represented as 'the totality of things which are members of
classes', and that the general character1Stic of the class W is
rightly put as 'being member of a class'. (Of course I do not
deny that we should naturally at first put 'classness' in this
general notion, and indeed that 1s right enough, but it doesn't
suit my present purpose And the notion I have chosen 1s also
right from another pomt of view, and is the pomt of view which
suits my purpose.)
W bemg the 'class of classes'.
Let the classes subordinate to 1t be A, B, C, &c.
Now each of these classes has its own members unified by
a universal, A by 11 (say), B by fJ, C by y, &c -so that A consists
of all thmgs wluch are 11; B of all that are fJ, &c, &c.; but
for the purpose of the 'class of classes' we abstract 11, {J, y, &c.,
and regard A, B, and C, &c , &c , only as groups umfied by
some prmc1ple or another ( = dasses)
Thus the members of each group A, B, C, &c., &c., have the
common designation of being 'members of a class'.
W is the totality of the groups A, B, C, &c
. ·. W is also the totality of the members of these groups.
. ·. W is the totality of thmgs which are members of classes
and the generic conception corresponding to W is 'being a
member of a class '.
The relation of the general case to the class of claues may
QOW be shown in parallel columns :
Cor,ssf,ondence 'll1ith Bemarl Bosanquet 733
Let X be any class whatever, Let W be the 'class of clasaes '.
of which the class conception Then, as above, the class
is~- conception is 'being a mem•
ber of a class '.
X then consists of things each W then consists of things each
of which is an x. of which 1s a 'member of
a class'.
Let A, B, C, &c., be classes Let A, B, C, &c , be classes
subordinate to X. subordinate to W.
A 1s a group of things each of A is a group of things each of
'which is an x (as well as which 1s a 'member of a
being an ci-u being charac- class' (as well as being an u,
teristic of the sub-class A). u characterizmg the class A).
So B is a group of things each So B is a group of things each
of which 1s an x, &c., &c. of which is a 'member of a
class', &c., &c.
&c., &c. &c., &c.
X is the totality of the groups W is the totality of the groups
A, B, C, &c. A, B, C, &c.
. ·. X is the totality of the ·. W 1s the totality of the
members of A, B, C, &c. members of A, B, C, &c.
X then is the totality of thmgs W then 1s the totality of things
which arc each x which arc 'members of
classes'.
This latter statement is then The latter is erroneously stated
erroneously put m the form · thus.
X is a totality of things "luch W 1s a totality of things which
are x. are 'members of classes'.
The mistake of substituting the indefinite for the definite
article being made, the fallacy proceeds thus .
X being 'a group of tlungs W being a totality (or group)
which are x' 1s exactly like, of things which arc •mem-
in this way, each of the bers of classes', is thus
groups A, B, C, &c , for each exactly hke each of the
of them 1s 'a group of thmgs groups A, B, C, &c, for each
which are x '. of these 1s 'a group of things
which are members of
classes'.
It is therefore hke them a W is therefore hke them a
member of the class defined member of the class defined
by the general quality com- by the general quality com-
Y 2
134 TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
mon to A, B, C, &c., of mon to A, B, C, &c., of
•being a group of things •being a group of things
which are % S '.
1
which are members of a
class'.
But the class so denned, being But the class so denned, being
the totality of groups which the totality of groups which
are 'groups of thmgs which are •groups of things which
are x's ', 1s exactly the class are members of a class', is
X itself. exactly the class W itself.
. ·. X 1s a member of itself. . ·. W, the class of classes, is
a member of itself.
J. Coox WILSON.
' [See PS. iDlra J 1 [On a po5tcard, 9th July 15103 ]
TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
18 July 1903.
§488. I2 Fyfield Road.
My dear Bpsanquet,
In reply to your courteous expression about sending such
decided objections to my views with 'trembling, &c. ', let me
assure you that, in controversy with one other man at least,
I do like the points urged against me put as clearly as possible·
and with all their proper force. If a man from motives of con•
sideration doesn't quite express his full convictions, there is
a danger one may not fully appreciate the ob3ection, and either,
if the thing is nght, one remains in error, or more controversy
is needed to get to a right mind. It is true that a strong
expression of difference, or unqualified accusation of error, does
in the first instance rouse the fighting instinct {in its irrational
form) and that obstructs clear vision, but this has this kind of
drawback rather m conversation, where one is tempted to hit
quickly back, but even so, it is the least of the two dangers :
and in a written objection the danger 1s almost nil, and the
thing is to be absolutely clear. This 1s no affectatlon, at my
age one wants to save time wherever controversy is necessary,
and one is more aware of the limitations of one's own mind and
more anxious for help from others.
I would say this to any one who was good enough to discuss
with me. But to you I would say especially, you cannot possibly
offend me by the most downright and uncompromising state•
ment that I am m error m some particular. Because I am quite
sure that even if you detected me in a pretty bad' mistake, you
do not and would not think I was rather hopeless. I should
not feel abased, for I doubt whether any one has given such
generous commendation to some of my theories as you have,
and it has, I assure you, been a great encouragement to me
that you, especially, have so much belief in me.
I have indeed very flattering 'testimonials' from time to time
from younger men here; but then they have been my pupils,
or attended my lectures, and have got into my ways of speech
and thinking ; and besides are under obligations for mere trouble
taken with them.
But you are perhaps a trifle my senior, and are a 'Master in
Israel', and so I have been greatly delighted and helped by your
Co",sj,onlence with Bem"1'tl Bosllff(/Wt 1.P
very unstinted e:xpre•ions of agreement on certain important
matters.
I am sending you a discussion of one of your obje.ctions1 and
without any tremors. I am only making clear a point I believe
of importance and you needn't answer at all, and if you wish
to, seeing something obviously wrong, you can delay as long as
you please. We are off actually to-morrow {Sunday): perhaps1
however, I may send in another paper on another of your points.
My address will be Kurhotel, Schonwald, bei Triberg, Baden.
Your very kind letter (July 17) about Dedekind and Royce
came whde I was wnting the paper. I am so glad that what
I said was of some use.
§ 489. There seem to be two main faults in my argument from
your point of view. 1
(i) That whereas I suppose that arguing on the same principle
as 1s shown in the argument by which the paradox that
'the class of classes' 1s a member of itself is proved, it
could be shown in the same way that any class whatever
may be a member of itself . the truth 1s that my argu-
ment 1s not on the same principle.
{u) That m the argument itself there is a non sequitur, viz. the
last statement but one in the left hand parallel column,
'the class so defined as being the totality of groups
which are" groups of things which are x's" 1s exactly the
class X itself'. You say it 1s not this class at all.
It seems to me really on examination that there ,s no serious
difference after all: 1t is almost a mere question of statement.
§ 490. Let me take the first point first. Then of course we
hypothetically consider the argument in itself sound and not
affected by the second objection. We are only asking whether
it falls {if sound) under the principle of the paradox. I think
you only differ because I mean only the general and essential
principle of the argument m the paradox, while you mean
something more detailed, some closer agreement 10 detail.
perhaps.
The argument of the paradox is this :
The class of classes is a 'class',
:. it is a member of the class 'class',
• Notes appended to letter of 18.v1103.
142 TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
••. it is a member of itseli.
The first two propositions here being of the form
YisaZ,
. ·. Y is a member of the class Z.
As to the first proposition : I suppose myself to have shown
that the way 1t 1s got 1s really this :
The class of classes 1s the complex or total of all the classes;
which are themselves totals or unified manifolds. Then it is
argued really that it shares with its subordinate classes the
property of being a totality, or a unified manifold, and so
comes 1 under the general idea. That's how the first proposi-
tion 'class of classes 1s a class' 1s got, whether rightly or not
doesn't for the present purpose concern us. In the case of the
class X, assuming for the moment of course that it 1s rightly
represented as the totality of groups of y things which are x,
arguing in exactly the same way as above we should get that
X shared with its subordinate classes the property of being
a group of things which are x, and thus get by a parallel method
an exact parallel to the 1st proposition m the paradox of the
class of classes. Then the argument continues with the same
parallehsm.
The class of classes is a class, X is a group of things which
are x,
. ·. 1t 1s a member of the class . ·. X 1s a member of the class
class ' group of things which are x'
. ·. 1t 1s a member of itself for . ·. X is a member of itself, for
the class class is the class of 1t 1s the whole group of
classes. things which are x.
This 1s what I mean by saymg that I 'prove' the paradox
about the X class on the essential principle by which the para-
dox is proved for the class of classes-or, 1f you like, on the
principle which really underlies the proof of the paradox, how-
ever it may be stated. I think the above way of putting the
parallelism may very bkely satisfy you on the first point, for
I have avoided what you object to, viz. that resolution of the
class of classes (which by no means 'destroys' its character as
1 MS, • some come, •,
Cor1esf,ontk,u;e with Bernard Bosanquet 743
you think) in which one is abJe to represent its 'class conception'
as 'being a member of a class' instead of classness.
§ 491. But supposing this difficulty (No. i) to disappear, there
remains (ii), and this is the important one. Consider the class
X of which the class predicate is x, i. e. every member of the
class X is an x and so from this point of view its 'members'
are certainly not classes. I say the same class X can be repre•
sented so that its members are classes. You reply this is [is]
not true. It seems to me there is no more difference between
us than between t.wo people one of whom should say a curve
was convex, and the other should object 'no it is concave'.
Only the parallel is not accurate, for I suppose my position to
be that of the man who says it is both concave and convex.
I will make a suggestion which I think will conduce to your
appreciating the lines upon which I was thinking. You say the
class which is the totality of groups of things which are x, is
Mt X, i. e. it is not the class which (is) the totality of things
which are ,c,
Now I should suggest you should not stop at the mere nega•
tion, but ask yourself the question, if the first class (call it X')
is ,wt X, what is the positive relation between the ISt class and
X? 'X' is not X, how is X' related to X?' I imagine that if
you had asked yourself the question, you would have revised
your criticism and possibly have quite agreed with me.
Now my pomt JS this · 'The Class X as the class X means
a certain part of reality, or say a certain total of reality-it
consists of all the things which are x.
'But the very same class X, as this total of these realities,
is divided into groups A, B, and C, each of which is (a) group
of x's (a.x's, {Jx's, yx's), and so it is a total of such groups-
a total of groups each of which JS an :r group (in contrast with
which it may be called the :r-group).'
Or to put it otherwise :
'One and the same part of reality-or total of realities if you
like-is (i) a total of individuals (say) all of which are z, and
so is a manifold unified by x-ness, the members or elements of
the manifold not being classes, and (ii) it also is divided into
groups of individuals: groups A, B, C. These groups are each
unified by a kind of x-ness (az-ness, fJ:r-ness, rx-ness) within
744 TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
themselves, which make them groups and distinct groups. Now
these groups, taken as units, themselves constitute a manifold :
and they are unified by the common property of 'being a group
of z's •. Thus the totality now appears as the totality of these
groups-its members from this point of view are classes, and
the class predicate is no longer x but 'being a group of x's '.
Surely this is all right, it is but an instance of the conca\r~
and the convex-one reality with two inseparably united aspects.
Supposing you agree to this, the parallel argument [to] which
you object to can be eastly put m a form (for it 's I feel a mere
matter of statement) which would satisfy you.
I might say 'any unified manifold constituting as such a
'"class", even if it, the manifold, is presented as individuals,
• not classes, is also or consists also of a manifold of classes
'unified, &c., &c.' And then I should continue, 'If any manifold
'of individuals constituting an ordinary class is considered from
'this other point of view as the unification of a manifold of
'classes, the argument of the paradox can be applied to it in
'exact parallelism.'
§ 492. Now in truth I had taken to myself some credit for
observing two things which hadn't been observed, and hoped
(may I still hope?} to be patted on the back by you at least
for it.
(I) I think I have shown how a class of individuals is also
(not merely 'may be represented as') a class of classes
(Agamst this the 'class of classes' is simply the class of
classes, but that doesn't matter even if you don't like
that way of putting it).
(2) I have also shown how 'the class of classes' is also the
class of mdividuals defined as 'members of classes' so
that, as in the case of an ordinary class the class con•
ception is altered, when represented as a class of classes,
so in the case of the class of classes, when its members
are represented as mdividuals, its class conception
becomes as I showed m my previous paper 'being
member' of a class.
The parallel argument I first sent you, you wdl see if you
look at it again, combines this double aspect of each class. It
isn't necessar')' it should, for we can simply express the X class
.
Co"sspatknce 'llJilh Bema,d Bost11UJuel
.
1.JS
in the form corresponding to the class of classes, without any
reduction of the class of classes, and represent the parallelism
as I have done it on p. 3 of the paper. It interested me, how•
ever, to do it that way too in order to make the dass of class11
appear as a case.
§ 493. Now in conclusion I do venture to think that the
theory of the class of classes, &c., is not complete until the
double aspect of an ordinary class and of the class of classes
is recognized: and it 1s not till this is done that one realizes
the full likeness and difference between the 'class of classes' and
what we call an ordinary class. (You will note that what you
called destruction of the characteristic of the class of classes, is
to me the recognition of something essential 1 to it.)
1773.2 Aa
XII
PRIMARY AND SECONDARY QUALITIES
Lette, in criticism of a pape, on P,ima,y and.
Seconda,y Qualities
July, 1904.
§ S19. Some preliminary points.
According to the formulation of Locke {e. g.) the secondary
qualities, which are qualities of the external object, are strictly
speaking not the sensations, as heat and colour, produced in us
by the object, for these are not qualities of the object, but the
powers in the obJect to produce the sensations. Still the sensa-
tions themselves-inaccurately I think-get called secondary
qualities I observe this m the present article. It doesn't
matter, but 1t is well to remember it or it tends to confusion
in thinking.
For clearness m a discussion bke the present it is well to
confine attention to an example hke heat and to exclude colour.
For m the case of heat every one easily recognizes, without
philosophy, that he himself has a definite sensation of heat-
we know this to be a sensation inasmuch as we say we feel hot.
This is not so with colour People do not easily recognize that
colour is a sensation of their own On the contrary, the belief
that 1t is a sensation is an inference from a theory scientific or
philosophic. We all of us, both the plain and the philosophic,
think of colour as in the thing and put it there in a way we
never put our sensation of heat. Thus, too, ordinary people say
they feel hot, but never say they feel coloured, e g. feel red.
Moreover, whereas they speak of a sensation of heat, they never
speak of a 'sensation of yellow'. It is only the scientific or
philosophic who speak thuq in consequence of a theory which
they hold, and that only because they think they have proved
to themselves it is a sensation, not because they recognize it
directly as such : for it 1s not natural to do so. A connexion
with sensation becomes apparent when the colour dazzles us :
but even then we think of the colour as in the thing and of the
dazzling as its effect upon us. That colours are only seen in
On Prima,y and Secondary Qualities 76-'
the light makes no difference (and here Locke's argument is
wrong), for we simply think of their colour as a property ehey
have in the light, just as we think of floating as a property cork
has in the water.
We may therefore for the present purpose when speaking of
secondary qualities confine ourselves to the sensation of heat and
its correlative in the thing.
§ 520. Consciousness of the plain man.
I don't think you give a quite accurate representation of the
theory of the plain man's consciousness implied in the view you
are attacking. It needn't be assumed that he definitely thinks
his sensation as in the hot iron, so as, e. g., to be liable to what
is called a 'flagrant absurdity'. Rather 1t would be supposed
that in feeling a hot surface he tends to think that besides
having a sensation of burning or warmth, he is feeling something
in the thing which causes it, just as when he feels a rough
surface he not only has a special kind of sensation but recognizes
something different from 1t, viz. an uneven surface. Only that 10
the case of heat the only pos1t1ve nature he assigns to the
supposed quality felt m the thing 1s derived from his own sensa-
tion. So it might be said that by a confusion he assimilates
the character of the quality attributed to the thing to the
character of his own sensation-a confusion in which he 1s not
fully conscious of what he is really doing.
(Oddly enough, this seems to be exactly what your own theory
comes to, as I shall try to show presently, so that you don't
really differ from the theory you are attacking.)
I shouldn't mind calling this an unconscious transference of
the quality of his own sensation to the thing ; but he certainly
distinguishes from it his own feeling of being burned (and pained
possibly) or of being warmed (and pleased possibly). The quality
of his sensation thus {does) double duty; and I am prepared
to show that this is done in Bacon, and that it 1s the key to
the standing puzzle about the causa formalis or forma.
I should be quite prepared to find that some people who hold
the theory that in heat there is really nothing in the body but
a state of its primary qualities {dynamical)-especially scientific
people who think crudely on these things-have said the plain
man simply thinks the heat he feels (his sensation) is in the hot
Aa2
TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
object ; but that is merely an awkward, perhaps unintelligent,
presentation of the consequences of their theory, and the philo-
sophic view would be, I think, what I have represented.
I think it is impo1tant to notice that we have not to deal
with the plain man here as opposed to the philosopher. We are
all 'plain men' m this sense. It represents the operation of.oJlr
ordinary unreflective consciousness : and it is because we who
are reflective and philosophic have this consciousness that we
are able to deal with it. Thus it is true that the only course
we can take is to ask the plam man (m this sense) what he
means. As philosophers we mterrogate ourselves as plain men
§ 52 I. On the 'secondary quality' as a 'mere possibility'.
Unless I have mistaken your dnft, you seem to treat the
theory you are cnt1c1zing as if it implied (that) the Secondary
quality m the thing was a mere power to produce a sensation in
us, and you seem to be controvertmg that and trymg at least
to show that our 'plam consc10usncss '-' ordmary unreflectmg
thought '-considers the quality as havmg some actual nature
beyond bemg a mere power ( = mere possibility). But the
moderns who hold Locke's doctrme {and I should say, with
doubt, Locke himself) do not hold this at all. They suppose
that correspondmg to our sensat1011 of heat there is an actual,
not potential, activity of the particles themselves, a vibratory
movement-a dynamical state which is entirely comprised within
what Primary qualities mean for them. This exists whether
there 1s any sensation or not and it 1s a potentiality only with
regard to sensation. If there 1s a sensitive surface upon which
this vibratory movement can act, then it produces a sensation
of heat. Your argument certainly gives the impression that you
suppose yourself correcting a pomt m the Lockean view, and
ins1stmg on some actual or positive quality m the body said to
be hot, other than the mere possibility of producing a sensation
in us. If this is what you really mean, it is a misconception.
The thing you are trymg to establish against the theory is an
integral part of the theory itself, i.e. so far as you are merely
trymg to prove that the quality m the thmg is not merely
potentiality of sensation
It seems to me that there is not only this false issue in the
paragraph before us, but that it has helped to put you off
On P,imary and Secondary QuaUties 76'/
the scent, and to prevent you from realizing the true significance
of the 'fact' to which you appeal. I shall return to the last
point presently.
Perhaps you do not intend your contention as to the actual
and positive nature of the quality in the body to be a criticism
of the Lockean theory ; but I feel sure every reader would
suppose you did, and therefore I should suggest in re-writing to
make your meaning plain. But m any case I venture to think
that it JS your attention to this partJcular point as following
from (' shown by'} the fact to which you appeal, that has obscured
for you the main significance of that very fact.
§ 522. Sensation without representative value.
There 1s another point I should hke to clear off before coming
to grips with the main issue. You suppose that the gradual
diminution of heat sensations as the sensitive organism is with-
drawn from the hot object 1s without representative value.
Here you have overlooked the fact that, according to your own
meaning of representative value, this change has a very definite
and very important representative value. It obviously corre-
,;ponds to the objective physical fact that the heat in a body
has effects at a distance from itself, and that these effects
diminish in intensity as the distance increases: this is as
objective as the dm11nut10n of attractive force with the distance.
It shows itself not only m our sensations but m the fact that
a body gets warmer from the heat of the warming body as it
gets nearer to it
This suggests another point which you don't notice and should,
I thmk, be kept m mind m the discussion of secondary qualities.
Sometimes we feel the warmth or the cold of a body by touching
it and when we touch it, then it is easier to confuse the quality
which belongs to our sensation with a quality in the body. Bttt
how about the case where we feel warmth 'in the hand', when
the hand is advanced to a certain distance from the object?
Here we do not naturally say we feel anything in the object,
but I suppose we thmk of ourselves as feeling heat conceived
as something in the space between us and the object, and 'coming
out' from it (think, e. g., of warming the hands at a good hot
blazing fire). And in this case we clearly and definitely locate
a sensation of warmth in the hand. And here I would call your
TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
attention as a psychologist to a very striking difference between
heat as a sensation and colour (1f it is to be called a sensation) ;
though the perceiving organ is always at a distance from the
perceived coloured object, we always locate the colour in the
perceived obJect and never in the perceiving organ. In the case
of heat felt at a distance from a hot object, on the other hans),
we locate the sensation of heat in the hand (e. g) and the 'heat'
(as obJective) which we suppose ourselves to feel {through the
sensation) we do not locate in the object, though we may
connect 1t with the object.
§ 523. The theory criticized and the theory opposed to it.
The theory criticized seems properly to be this : Heat in the
hot body is only a vibratory movement of its material particles ·
and this 1s confined entirely to its' primary qualities'. Symbolize
this heat by Hm. (Heat as a mode of motion.) There is nothmg
else in the body except the po\\er of tlus Hm to produce a sensa-
tion in us. Call the sensation Hs. In the case of heat felt by
us, then, the whole reality consists of Hm, the power of Hm to
produce Hs, and of Hs.
This 1s the theory of the physicists and philosophers referred
to. (By the way, the theory began with the Greek Atom1sts,
who, though philosophers by nature, had surely rather the
scientific 1 than the phtlosoph1c spirit ) They would usually
admit that we ordinarily thmk of heat as something in the
body like our sensation, and not as a mechanical condition of
its particles (which mdecd we only know by scientific investiga-
tion). And this latter tendency of ours they regard as an illusion
though they may differ in the way in which they describe 1t.
The theory you oppose to tlus I cannot think clear, and
I doubt whether you have got yourself clear as to your own
meaning. The one certain thmg by which one has to try to
interpret you is that you deny (that) the plain man's view is
an illusion This would seem to necessitate that he is right in
thinking there is some quality in the body which, whatever else
it is, 1s neither his sensation of heat (though apparently somehow
near akin to 1t) nor the vibratory movement of the particles.
It must be different from the latter or you would agree with
the theory you criticize. This then is neither Hs nor Hm ; let
1 rn the MS •scientific• and' philosophic' are inverted.
On PrimM)' and s~t;()Mfr)I Qualities 769
us call it Hx. The distinction, however, is obscured, from your
tendency to represent the 'primary quality' theory of heat as
though it only meant a power to produce a sensation. Thus
where one would expect Hx (the secondary quality as ascribed
by the 'plain man' to the thing) to be distinguished from the
primary quality as a vibratory movement of particles, it is only
distinguished from 'their power to produce a certain sensation
in us'. One would expect you to say 'he does not merely mean
the secondary qualities as v1brat1ons of particles together with
the power of this dynamic state to produce sensations in us'.
Thus you seem committed to recognizmg Hs and Hx and Hn,
which latter 1s not Hm.
The question arises : do you really mean to recognize Hm at
all? And, 1f so, (m) what relation does it stand to Hx, since
both Hx and Hm are supposed to be in the body? This last
question is a serious one, and the fact that you haven't asked
1t seems to me to indicate that you have not fully thought out
your position. Nor on the other hand do you deny Hm.
The first criticism I should therefore pass 1s that you have
not made clear what it 1s exactly that you do hold. But,
assuming that what you don't deny you retain, the reasonable
supposition seems to be that you recognize as real and as distinct
from one another Hs, Hm, and Hx.
§ 524. Sensations as representative of secondary qualities and the
general idea of suck representation.
You begm an important section of your argument by assuming
the idea of sensations being representative.
( represent}
(They)~ express something other than themselves
Lstand for
without any cntical elucidation of the idea.
Now, I venture to thmk that the idea of such representation
in philosophy, or psychology rather, is very loose and treacherous
and, if used at all, should be preceded by a 'critique' of such
representative character, and an explanation of the exact sense
in whicll the word representative is used.
If you had undertaken such a 'critique' I think you might
have written very differently in the sequel. It seems to me
that in what follows you not only assume this idea of repre•
770 TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
sentation, but assume its application to Hs and Hx, thus
assuming the existence of Hx, the very thing which you have
to establish.
Let us consider the idea of 'represent', which you make
equivalent to 'express ', and 'stand for'. I am convinced that
we are all hable to fall mto serious confusion by an uncritii;al
use of such words. For example, I am convinced that Bradley's
theory of Judgement, and with it therefore a great deal of his
Logic, is hopelessly shipwrecked in consequence of a great con-
fusion m his mmd as to the meaning of 'significance'-' meamng'
-•sign'-' symbol', which have to do with representation. (I do
not publish my criticism of Bradley ; but this criticism I have
lately been encouraged to circulate in MS. among Oxford
students of philosophy. You are welcome to see it if you like :
though I shouldn't care for you to talk much about it-except
perhaps to me-especially as among its consequences (not
developed m my circulation copy), there is involved an uncom-
promising rejection of the general account of inference which
Bosanquet follows. For I have an uncommon regard for
Bosanquet, begotten greatly by his own generous treatment of
myself.)
In the strict meanmg of 'represent' and 'stand for' . nothmg
in the world in itself ever 'represents' or 'stands for' anytlung
else. In itself it can only be said to 'represent' itself and 'stand
for' itself ; though even this 1s an abuse of terms. Representa-
tion is our subJective act. Nothing has a meaning in itself. It
is we who 'mean'. It is we who make something represent
something else, somethmg other than itself. (This pomt I have
worked out in detail m the aforesaid cnbc1sm) Thus 1t 1s we
who decide that x shall represent the problematic quantity, and
a, b, c, &c., determmate quantities. It is we who make a weeping
willow a symbol of sorrow. There may of course be something
m the object which prompts us to give it a meanmg, e. g. the
resemblance of the weeping willow to a human figure bowed
over m the attitude of grief. But the willow m itself can neither
'mean' grief, nor 'represent' nor 'stand for' nor 'express' grief.
We do all that. The fatal thmg in Bradley is that he thinks
an 'idea' can m itself have 'meaning', be 'significant', or
'symbolical•.
On P,ima,y and Secondary Qualities 771
The thing we make representative, as opposed to mere symbol,
is, in the strict use of representative, always somehow like
the thing it represents. But there is an extended use. If the
existence of A necessitates that of B, we may, taking the
existence of A as evidence of the existence of B, speak of A as
a sign of B-i. e. a sign to us because we infer B from A; but
when we are fully conscious that this is the relation between
A and B, I thmk we stick at saymg A is 'representative' of B,
though by a confusion we may perhaps do so, when we are not
dearly aware of the true relation between A and B, or not
accurately remembering it But we should never say A
'expresses' B.
Now, in the present case, 1£ I understand you rightly, your
text seems necessarily to mean that Hs is a sensation which
'mediates our knowledge of' Hx, because Hs •represents' Hx,
or 'stands for' Hx or 'expresses' Hx. Now I would venture to
cut out at once the word •express '-a sensation cannot in any
proper sense of the word 'express' anythmg different from itself.
Let us then merely retam 'represent' and 'stand for'. How is
it we come to speak of a sensation as 'representative', for
I suppose we all tend to do 1t, not you only ? Before cnttcizmg
the application to secondary quantities, which themselves (in
the Hx form) are sub Judice, I should like to consider the case
where the existence of the quality (the primary quality) 1s
undoubted, and where we are hable to speak of 'representative'
sensations.
I think the best case to take 1s that of felt extension, for that
gives the most plausible instance, and besides I do not agree
with what you say of visual extension. Here (m felt extension)
we seem to recognize in feeling round the surfaces and edges
of a die (e. g) that we have certain feelings quite different from
the extension, and yet that it is somehow through these feelings
that we become aware of the extension. Thus we may get to
call these sensations 'representative', without any distinct
envisagemcnt of what we mean-and the word 'representative•,
instead of being an explanation, is itself a problem, and indeed
is itself due to a confusion m our ordinary thinking. Now the
very description of these sensations (tactual and the like), as
mediating our knowledge of the extension, implies that they are
772 TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
different from extension and have no extension in themselves.
They are not therefore 'representative' by reason of likeness.
How, then, are they representative? As already contended, m
no kind of way can they of themselves 'represent' anything
other than themselves. If we consider them as representative
it must be either on the ground of hkeness (excluded in th_is
instance) or because of their associatjon (m their qualitative
character and their given temporal order) with extension. We
must therefore be already acquainted with extension either to
recogmze the likeness of the representative sensations to it or
to know of the association. But this 1s 1mposs1ble 1f the media-
tion of our knowledge of extension by the sensations (together
with their order) means, as 1t usually does, that we depend
entirely on the sensations for our knowledge of extension at all.
But suppose, for the sake of argument, we know already that
a certam order and quality m our tactual sensations and (say)
'sensations of resistance' 1s caused by the fact that our fingers
are moving in contact with the surfaces of an extended obJect.
If we know this in general already, we can apply it to a particular
instance, and we might say that this order of tactual and other
sensations is 'representative' of extens10n here, the phrase being
really inaccurate (and m1sleadmg) ; our true meaning, then,
being that the so-called 'representative' sensations are known
to be associated with such and such an extension : and that
they therefore can be taken as evidence of the existence of the
extension. This waives the question as to how we could have
got our knowledge of the correlation of the sensations and
extension, and 1s merely given to show how little can be made
out of representation, m even what 1s perhaps the most favour•
able case.
As to this knowledge, 1t seems clear that we could not get it
at all if our datum was the mere sensat10ns, g1ven without any
relation to extension. If we really get both together we might
as well caJJ the extension representative of the sensatJOns as the
sensations representative of the extension.
The idea of representation, then, in fine, seems to me not
only useless in philosophy but misleading as tending to obscure
the solution of a difficult problem. In any case observe that
here the 'represented' idea (extension) is as clear to us as the
On Primary and Seconda,y Qualities 773
supposed 'representative' ideas, indeed clearer and clearly dis-
tinguished from them. Thus there is a science of the so-called
represented idea--geometry, which takes no account whatever
of the ' representative' ideas.
§ 525, Sensation (Hs) as 'representative' of a quality (Hx) in the
body.
To apply the above general considerations to the case before
us: ls Hs representative of Hx as bemg like 1t? No. for then
Hx as like a sensation in quality would itself have to be a sensa•
tion : and that, according to your own view, would be a 'flagrant
absurdity'. It would seem, then, by the above, to remain that
Hs would be something unlike Hx, but correlated with it, and
that we could only make Hs 'representative' of Hx because we
had found both associated (1. e. 1£ we allow the word 'repre-
sentative' at all). Hx, then, ought for us to have a positive
content ddiercnt-qurte different-from Hs, and clearly dlS•
tingu1shable from it : and according to your theory clearly
distinct from Hm. Clearly also there ought to be a science of
Hx. These seem to be necessary presuppositions of the only
mtelhg1ble sense in which Hs could be said to represent Hx.
§ 526. Evidence of the existence of Hx.
If Hx exists it ought, according to what seem the implications
of your representative theory, to satisfy the above conditions.
But (1) 1t seems evident that there 1s nothing which does satisfy
them. As d1stmct from our sensat10n Hs, there is nothing in
the body with any definite quality clearly d1stmguished from
Hs and from Hm, except only the power of Hm, or, 1£ you like, of
the body m general, to produce Hs : precisely the contention
of the theory you attack. If there were, there should be a science
of it, and there 1s none. In fact there ought to be a science
(empirical at least) of the relation of HJC to Hs and to Hm,
but there ts no science of its relation to either, the only science
of such relation is the science of the relation of Hm to Hs.
But (2) your own argument undes1gnedly leads straight to
the same conclusion : and here I come to the main significance
of the fact to which you appeal. 'The fact that m ascribing
secondary qualities to thmgs we normally think of the things as
if they were actually producing the sensations in an hypothetical
percipient.' This proves that if we try to find any positive
774 TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
quality of heat in the body which we may suppose ourselves to
feel (just as we feel extension m 1t), we are always thrown back
on the sensation itself for positive content, and can only give
a derivative positiveness to the property the body has of causing
it, by thinking of 1t as producing this definite quality of effect.
This means that we are able to say nothing of the body's quality
so far, except that 1t is the cause of this definite kind of sensa-
tion , though we may, by a confusion, be misled mto trans-
ferring what can only be a quality of the sensation into the
body itself.
All that you say in this connexion confirms the theory you
are attacking, and 1s indeed precisely the kind of argument which
the advocates of that theory would and do employ. They would
say that 1£ any one thmks there is a positive quality perceived
m the body (allowmg the case most favourable to you, when the
hot body 1s actually touched) other than the sensation and the
mere extension of the body, he may be challenged to assign any
positive predicate to this quality in itself ( = Hx), and it will be
found he can give none--and you have given none whatever-,
and a further proof that he JS under an JllusJon and can really
give none 1s that 1£ he tnes, he can only describe its positive
character by refcrenre to the positive character of the sensation
which 1t causes, and can never do anything else ; and this either
means that there 1s no quality assignable to the thing except
the power of producing the sensation m us, discoverable or
1mphed m our perception (and he therefore agrees with them), or
that he is confusedly transferring the quality of his sensation
to the body. Now this JS Just true of your own account, i.e. you
really say that no positive character can be found in the thmg
except by this reference to the quality of the sensation. Now
1t follows, from the above analysis of such meaning as 'repre·
sentative' can have, that the quality of a representative sensa-
t10n cannot possibly enter 'm consequence of its representative
function' into the ' essential constitution of the corresponding
secondary attributes of matter'. Just because of 'its repre-
sentative function' 1t can do nothing of the kmd, and the
statement is a mere contradiction m terms. This, I think, you
will see 1f you ask yourself now what could be intelligibly meant
by 'representative function'. In fact I hold that in this sentence
On Prima,y and Secow:la,y Qualities 775
you have exactly illustrated the unconscious transference of the
quality of the sensation into the object. I may here add that
I think this explains why some quite acute people among your
audience at Oxford were puzzled by your paper. I think they
felt they were not quite sure what you were driving at : and
some of them were inclined to suspect some confusion, if not in
your own thoughts, yet in your presentation of them.
You will see, then, that I cannot help thinking you have
proved the contradictory of what you originally intended, or at
least that your arguments are on that side and confirm the
position you meant to shake. The right formulation of the
theory seems to me what I have given above (in§ 520).
§ 527. On the relation of the supposed Hx to Hm.
As I have said, I consider it a sign that you haven't fully
cleared yourself up that you do not ever raise the important
question of the relation of Hx to Hm If Hx 1s really the
quality of the body itself which 1s correlative to our sensat10n
of heat (Hs) why 1s Hm needed ? One might expect you would
have to say that Hm is itself an illusion arising from people's
not recogmzing the existence of I Ix. If, however, m deference
to science you rctam Hm, how is 1t to be related to Hx ? Is
it the cause of Hx and Hx agam the cause of Hs ? If so, the
important thmg for science would be a theory of the relation
of Hm and Hx m the body. Thus, in any case, you would have
to propose a new science. If you reject Hm, the new science
would recognize Hx and study its causal relation to Hs. If you
do not reject Hm, you would introduce a new science to study
the relation of Hm to Hx.
But, of course, you know I should mamtam there could be no
such science, because no positive content at all can be given to
Hx. I will here add, what I have already indicated m conversa-
tion, that I am fairly sure the secret of the whole puzzle about
Bacon's 'forma' lies in the fact that he himself got into complete
confusion between Hs 1 Hx, and Hm. The real question to ask,
I am sure, is not the usual one, 'how does the "formal " cause
differ from the "efficient" cause m Bacon?' which no one has
been able to answer satisfactorily (or even to give a coherent
account of what Jonna itself means)-but we should ask what
is the relation of the forma to the simplex natura of which it
TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
is the /ormtJ. No one seems to have undertaken this inquiry.
If it is done, the result is a mass of hopeless contradictions of
statement. Some time ago I thought I detected the source of it
all in the fact that the simplex natura as conceived in the body
was precisely Hx, and the f orma of this is Hm. Bacon some-
times seems to recognize that heat in the body is only Hm, •and
besides this there is only the effect in our sensory (organism)-
a sensation-and this accounts for a certain class of passage.
But sometimes he unwittingly transfers the sensation into the
thing; thus appears the simplex natura of heat as in the thing,
which, nevertheless, derives all its positive character from the
sensation with which it is confused This accounts for another
set of passages, and the two sets are thus m irreconcilable
contradiction to one another.
As the Baconian difficulty is a recognized problem of philo-
sophy, and I believe it capable of being quite cleared up, I had
thought of givmg a public lecture on it next term. Your paper
has itself made me undertake the rethinkm~•over process which
I should have had to undertake, and so I may as well execute
my project. The lecture itself was written long ago, I should
say fourteen years ago, and I have occasionally delivered it in
my ordmary logic course. There 1s perhaps nothing in it I want
to alter, at least as far as I can see. I dare say it will interest
you to know that I have given my course on 'hypothetical
thinking' again this year, and I think I have improved it by
developing 1t and makmg 1t quite defimte m certain d1rect1ons.
§ 528. The case of the Primary Qualities.
(A) For the mam issue, which must be settled one way or
another by the preceding, it would not be necessary to go on
to what you say upon the primary qualities.
With regard to your words 'This analysis of the secondary
attributes of matter holds good in all essential respects for the
primary also', it doesn't follow, because, as I think, the analysis
is not valid for the secondary, that something like it may not be
valid for the primary ; and so I propose to consider the primary.
Moreover, I don't find I can agree with your account of sensible
extension, &c., and want to talk about it because I think your
account of the secondary has infected your view of the primary
qualities. The facts in the case of the secondary quahties seem
· On Primary and Secondary Qualities 777
to be {taking heat} that we perceive only our own sensation
{Hs) and possibly the extension of the hot body, if we touch it :
we infer a special power in the body to cause it, and we arrive
at our idea of the state of the body which has the power (Hm)
by inference and there is nothing else in reality. Hs, then,
is perceived, Hm is not perceived but inferred by a scientific
theory. Add that there is the illusion Hx, letting Hx now stand
for our tendency to transfer confusedly the quality of our
sensation (Hs) to the body.
What is there to correspond in our knowledge of extension?
Take felt extension first. There are certain tactual and muscular
sensations : call these Es ; qmte distinct from these is the exten-
sion felt and which we say we feel in the body : call this Eb.
Eb is conceived as distinct and different in its nature from Es.
Hm JI JI JI JI JI Hs.
So far the relation of Eb to Es 1s like that of Hm to Hs. But
there is a fundamental difference.
Hm is the mere result of scientific inference, it is not the
object of perception, we neither perceive it actually, nor suppose
we perceive it. Eb we certamly suppose we percei~. We say,
not we feel the tactual feelings, but we feel the extension itself.
A corroboration of this is that we arc able to describe the
extension we say we feel, as it appears to us in perception or
in what we call ' feeling ' it, we cannot possibly describe Hm
from the experience in which we have Hs.
If it is objected-we don't really perceive Eb but infer it,
and are under an dlus1on in thinking we perceive it, it may
be answered : (I) If so, how is it we do come to think we perceive
Eb, and never come to think we perceive Hm? Why can we
from mere perception describe the one and not the other ?
(2) There would still remain the fundamental difference that we
at least suppose we perceive (feel) the one and do not suppose
we feel or perceive the other. (3) Eb, or extension in a body
in general, cannot possibly be something originally unperceived
and only inferred from what is perceived : for, as shown in the
discussion of the idea of representation, if what we perceived
were only tactual, &c., sensations, without the perception in
them of any relations of extension, extension could never be
inferred from them.
TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
Thus again, while there is this correspondence that Hm is
conceived as the cause of Hs, and Eb also as the cause of our
having certain sensations (Es) in a particular order, there is this
fundamental ddferenre that our idea of Hm is only acquired by
our searching for a cause of the given Hs, but our idea of Eb
is not acquired merely from a search for a cause for Es. .
Is there anything to correspond to Hx, not as you conceive
Hx, but as an tllus1on, as I conceive it? There probably usually
1s. We not only thmk of the hardness of the extended substance
in associat10n with our feeling when we endeavour to compress
it, but confusedly transfer the quality which belongs to our
feelmg to the thmg itself.
Therefore in the case of the sensations relative to felt extension
(not seen), I should say that these sensations and their order,
though of course correlated to the extension in the body, most
certainly do not 'enter mto the constitution of it', and do not
'represent' somethmg other than themselves, i. e the extension.
As to the former phrase, the context shows that you hardly
mean it seriously yourself, for 'only so far as', &c, practically
cancels anything naturally meant by such a strong phrase as
'enter into the constitution of it', and as to the second phrase
I needn't repeat what I have said about 'representat10n '.
§ 529. To come now to visual extension.
It 1s here I specially find the 'infection' of your view of
secondary qualities. You hold here that we perceive a visual
(coloured) extension, apparently, which is as much our subJective
state as the sensation of heat, and is merely representative of the
real extension which 1s other than itself. The words m italics
seem absolutely necessary to your v1ew and to the analogy you
institute with the secondary qualities.
I confess I cannot understand how you could have persuaded
yourself that the distinctions you make in this part of your
argument were tenable, if it had not been that you were affected
by the v1ew you had developed about the secondary qualities.
Let us take first your instance of the extension (visual) perceived
with closed eyes.
This is nothing but an mstance of the following. Suppose we
are looking at a flat surface--say the wall of a room. We see
the rectangular shape of the wall when the eye is at a. sufficient
On P,iMa,Y affll Secondary Qualities 779
distance. This surface is a part of ' real ' space, of the space
'in which attraction varies', &c. As we move the eye nearer
the wall, its limits which constitute its shape get out of the
range of distinct VJsion. When the eye is near enough to
the wall we lose sight of them altogether ; when it is close to the
wall we see but a comparatively small part of it : the centre
of this distinctly, and parts at an increasing radius less dis-
tinctly, fading off mto nothing visible at all by imperceptible
gradations. And so, as in your case, we cannot say what shape
it has, but nevertheless what we see 1s a part of actual extension
and has a position in actual space, for it is on the wall Now
m the case of the closed eye-Jf you really mean we perceive
or see 'visual extension', as opposed to merely imagining-the
only ddlerence 1s that the surface has come into actual contact
with the eye, for it's nothmg but the eyelid itself which is seen
by transmitted hght, and so what we see 1s actual extension, it
certamly has a position in real space. As the case of the wall
shows, the fact that we can't tell what shape limits what we
see is no proof whatever that 1t 1s merely some subjective
extension that we see. I feel I cannot be too emphatic about
this, and I feel you have been seriously misled. You say again
it is an 'mtrms1c impossibility to express its magnitude m feet
and mchcs '. The magnitude of any part of it, on the contrary,
can just as much be expressed m feet and mches as the magnitude
of any part of the visible part of the wall, whose limits we can't
perceive on account of the nearness of the eye. The only way
m which it is impossible is irrelevant, i. e. it may be impossible
for me to use a measure so as to measure a given bJt of the
extension, but nevertheless it has a dimension expressible in
inches.
§ 530. (B) Leaving this subject for the moment, let us con-
sider the perception of a piece of coloured surface, as of a blot
of colour on a piece of white paper. This is with you 'visual
extension'; you also speak of it totulem verbis as' sensation' and
'extended sensation•. This 'visual extension' again with you
is not m the thmg (and if seriously meant to be extended
sensation, could mdeed not be} but has a 'representative func-
tion', i.e. represents something m the thing.
With you 'representative' means 'representing something
2773•2 B b
780 TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
other than itself' ; it would be important to say what ' other
than itself' exactly means, whether 'other' as one smarting pain
is other than another such pain or different as the smart is
different from the thorn which causes it-' different in kind'. You
don't expressly say, but, as I have shown above, your theory
necessitates the latter kind of difference, for 1£ Hs, which ~e{>re-
sents Hx in the body, were like Hx, what you call the flagrant
absurdity would be committed of supposing the body had a
sensation.
In several ways it may be shown that this view of the relation
is quite untenable.
For simplicity, suppose the blot to be bounded by rectilinear
edges, and to be a parallelogram.
(I) The quality of the colour-supposed to be a sensation-
is irrelevant as, e. g. green, or red, or blue : it is the extension
only that matters. This extension I describe as a parallelogram,
and say it is bounded by straight lines. By hypothesis this is
to represent something in the body different in kind from itself.
This extension in the body 1s different in kmd from anything of
the nature of a parallelogram and cannot be bounded by straight
bnes. What is that? Clearly we could say nothing whatever of
it, and you would be committed to something worse even than
'a thing m itseH', viz. to 'an attnbute m itself'. (In our con-
versation in the quadrangle, in order to reply to a remark of
mine, you committed yourself to the view that the real extension
of the thing was for aught we knew as ddierent from the visual
as 1s Hm from Hs. I build no argument on a statement m
a hasty conversation ; but 1t confirmed me in thmkmg you
had not worked out your position clearly and realized its
implications.)
But (2) we always assume that the extension in the thing is
exactly the same in kind as the visual extension, and the science
of geometry depends entirely upon this. (This 1s one of the
reasons why your criticism of Kant is invalid.} There could be
no science of the 'extension in itself' any more than of the
thing in itself. Moreover, science assumes not that the extension
of the blot that I see is like the extension in the thing, or
represents the extension, but that it is the actual extension in
the body. It is visual extension simply as real extension seen.
On PriMMY and Suontla,y Qualities 781
(I mean of course science as scfonce. If the scientific ffltJ7I was
asked, he would very likely give a ridiculous answer. They
usually do, for they are more incapable of reflecting on their
own presuppositions than the ordinary 'plain man'.)
(3) Let us analyse this 'visual extension' and inquire what
parallel it presents to the secondary qualities. If we attend to
the colour alone and distinguish Cs, Cx, Cm, then Cm as the
movement of particles of ether actuated somehow by the body
corresponds to Hm, for it is not perceived and is solely an
inference in scientific theory. But the relation of Cs to Cx is
very different from that of Hs to Hx. As already indicated,
whereas we can and do locate Hs in our sensory organ, even
though at the same time we may erroneously locate something
like it (Hx) in the body, colour is clearly and distinctly located
in the body perceived and we no more locate it in the per-
ceiving organ (the eye) than we locate there the extension of
the body itself. We have no choice: we must locate the colour
in the surface: we cannot imagine yellow save as on a surface.
Nor will all our scientific theory, that 1t is not there but our
sensation, enable us to 'locate' it in the eye or represent it
otherwise than as at a distance from the eye and on the surface.
The colour cannot be made many sense 'representative' of the
extension, simply because we can't perceive it except as
'extended', i.e. on an extended surface, nor even imagine it
without extension. Thus tf we 'perceive• colour, we must at the
same time 'perceive' extension.
§ 531. (4) But the important thing now is the extension element
in this; because it 1s as extended sensation, or visual extension,
that you make it 'YepYesentative • of something m the body-
apparent and not real, and, as it would seem, something merely
subjective.
As remarked in the discussion of the foregoing point (the
comparison of secondary qualities with extension), the percep-
tion of colour 1s impossible without the perception of extension,
not at all as an inference but as a necessary part or aspect of
the same perception, and such extension again is absolutely
unintelligible save as the extension of a SU1'fac~i. e. a real
surface. lf two colours are juxtaposed which do not shade off
imperceptibly into one another, i. e. two colours homogeneous
Bb2
TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
in themselves--as the coloured blot on white paper, we neces•
sarily perceive their common boundary as linear, that is really
the common boundary of the surfaces to which we refer the
colour. (N.B. If two sensations different from one another, other
than colour (granting 1t to be a sensation), succeed, no such idea
of a boundary arises, e. g. a taste and a smell, one toothacpe
and another pain, one sound and another.)
We 'perceive' the bm1t or boundary just as directly as we do
the colours.
The aim of this detailed analysis (in which for clearness I have
put the same thmg m different ways at the nsk of wearymg by
repetition) (1s to show) that in no sense does the perception of
what you call visual extension (as a kind of what you call
sensible extension) involve any extcns10n m sensations as sensa-
tions. When we analyse it, we find that though the extension
(is) inseparably associated with the colours, it is not assigned
to sensations but to the surfaces, a.nd to these alone, to which
the colour (1f this is to be sensation) 1s referred. It is the
coloured surfaces which are extended, the coloured sur-
faces which have a boundary. It is either a confusion or
a mere fafon de parler to speak of the colour sensation as
extended, and as a / afon de parler 1s only excusable as meaning
that the surface to which the colour is referred is extended.
Therefore, strictly speaking, in a philosophic discussion such
language should be avoided and the accurate expression sub-
stituted Accurately, then, the sensat10ns, whether tactual or of
colour, are not extended, and the idea of extension is absolutely
inapplicable to them
Now the view that visual extension (and sensible extension
in general) is merely subjective, is nothing in the thing, is an
appearance as opposed to reality; an appearance which some-
how represents a reality, which as unreal and merely subjective
has no position in real space, depends wholly upon the view
that sensations can be in themselves extended, and 1s therefore,
I am obliged to think, entirely untenable. This seems in itself
enough to me, but I will consider some of your principal state-
ments in support of your view m detail.
§ 532. (5) I should say it was impossible to develop such
a theory into details without contradiction or some verbal con•
On Primary and Secondary Qualities 783
fusion. I seem to :find contradiction in what you say of the
apparent size as given by the visual extension in contrast with
the real size.
The visual extension as consisting, according to you, of repre•
sentative sensations must, I have contended, according to you,
be different m kmd from that which it represents. You never say
this quite clearly, though it is a point on which you ought to
have pronounced defimtely, and I can't help thinking that it
was a sort of instinct which prevented you. You use, for
example, the very strong expression 'extension as a charac-
teristic of visual sensation is quite distinct from the extension
of things in space', of which the natural interpretation is that
the two things differ m kmd. But your remarks on real and
apparent size entirely contradict this The contrast of the
apparent size of a thing with its real size 'as measured m feet
and inches' means simply, e g., that it looks z inches long
whereas 1t 1s 3. This means again that the apparent length
is a line 2 inches long and the real length a Jine J inches long.
(With this kind of difference between a real and apparent
distance one is very fam1Jiar m the exercise of' judgmg distance'.)
This is only the comparison of one line with another, of two
things (two extensions) exactly the same m kmd.
Verbal confusion I seem often to find in what you say of this
curious 'sensible extension' as opposed to real extension. First
you say sensations arc extended, then you seek to take away
the paradox, by addmg an explanation of 'extension', in the
case of sensation, which takes all that 'extension' means out of
it ; (thus you say} 'they are not extended m the same sense as
corporeal things', ' bodies are extended in space', &c. But what
other sense could there be if it was extension at all? This to
my mind is as bad as saying 'our sensations are numbered and
counted, but then it is not the same kind of numbering or
counting as applies to corporeal things'. ' Bodies are extended
in space', and it is therefore implied that sensations are extended
but not in space. This to my mind is sheerest contradiction.
What is extended must be in space or it is not extended. For
instance, if it is extended as a surface (and it is really this case
we have before us), that necessarily presupposes space on both
sides of it. It will not do to meet the difficulty by allowing
784 TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
the 'extended sensation' to be in a space of its own, quite
different from and not included in 'objective space', or the
'single homogeneous infi01te space', as you describe it, for this
would involve a terrible mess which you will realize of course
well enough.
I seem to find a good deal of verbal confusion. This 'sensible
extension', notwithstanding the difference you make between it
and the ' real ' extension, you speak of as a ,nanifestation or
expression of spatial extension. Here I note the expression
'spatial extension' which would be paralleled by 'numerical
number' and implies a non-~patial extension ( = a non-extended
extension) just as the other would imply a non-numerical
number. But anyhow, what could these somewhat loose and
popular phrases 'manifestation' and 'expression' mean philo-
sophically? How could the sensible extension be the •expres•
sion' of the spatial extension which is quite different from it?
It seems connected with the fallacious use of 'representation'-
' expression' here is only to be tolerated as a metaphor, as such
it is of no use whatever as an explanation ; one has to explain
what the metaphor means. 'Mamfestabon' is used legitimately
enough m philosophy for the particular as a 'manifestation' of
the universal, but then you do not mean to relate 'spatial
extension' to 'sensible extension' as umversal to particular.
Possibly, as the context with the word 'appearance' in it sug-
gests, 'manifestation' means the manifestation of spatial exten-
sion to us in perception. But then obviously 1t must be spatial
extension 1ts very self which is before us-spatial extension
must as manifested be the object of our perception : and not
an extension 'quite different' from it. If the latter presented
itself as a 'mamfestation' of spatial extension it would be a mere
fraud : it would be only a 'manifestation' of the 'sensible
extension' and not of 'spatial', for clearly what was really mani-
fested would be simply the 'sensible extension' before us.
If you want to introduce Jones to me, 1t won't do to introduce
to me somebody 'quite different' from him ; that wouldn't be
'manifesting' ']ones to me, but that other person.
§ 533. (6) Apparent antl real sue.
The supposed difference of apparent size is what seems to
have affected you greatly in your view of the difference between
On Pritnl.W)' •ntl Sscontlary Q#tllities 185
sensible and real or spatial extension. Here again I think you
have assumed what is little better than a popular distinction
without criticism. Just as 'representative and represented' so
'real and apparent' seem to me regular trap worde, which cannot
be safely used in any particular case without a most patient
examination of their meaning and justification in the particular
instance. The distinction of real and apparent size seems to
me very slippery and to require more than usual care-all the
more so because at first it may seem familiar and not to require
any discussion at all. There are two ways of treating the theory
of 'sensible visual extension' versus 'spatial extension'. The
first and the easier for mere negative purposes is to show the
untenable consequences of adopting it. The second and harder,
but the one required to complete one's estimate of the true
facts, is to analyse what is really meant by and involved in the
conception of apparent versus real size.
(a) Assume the theory to be true. Suppose I see a chair
before me upon the lawn. The strict meaning of the theory
absolutely necessitates the view that the 'visual extension' or
the extens10n which J sec is my own 'extended sensation' (your
phrase) ; that 1t 1s not the real extension of anything, for such
extension is in space, while sensible extension (e~ hypothesi)
cannot be. The same holds of the lawn itself and of all tho
obJects (extended) which I see about the chair. These 'appear'
to me to be 'in space', tke,e seems to be empty space between
them-indeed this is absolutely necessary to and involved in my
thinking that the chair has any extension at all. (This, I trunk,
you have hardly realized.) Now the space, which indubitably
thus 'appears' to me and in which the apparent objects have
their extension, is non-real; for, if it were real, the objects
I appear to see would have their extension in real space, whereaa
by hypothesis they have not. (We thu11 come in a different
way to a previous thought.) Is it necessary to develop the
consequences of this further? May I not assume that it lea.di
to an uncompromising subjective solips1stic Idealism? (N,B.
that this space (apparent) couldn't possibly be called 'extended
sensation', and so has no place in your non-real extension.)
{b) No doubt we are accustomed to say that as an object- is
removed farther from the eye it 'looks smalls,', We believe it
TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
has not become smaller, and so people come to speak of the
variation as 'mere appearance' and so to call the size itself
which seems to vary 'apparent size' as against 'real size'.
Again the apparent variation of size is said to correspond to
a real variation of the distance from the eye, and is often said
to be 'representative' of this real variation. • •
All these phrases are most misleading and tend to pernicious
consequences m ordinary psychology In your own mvestiga-
tion I think you omitted to ask yourself at the start what could
be meant by real size. You conceal the difficulty from yourself
by describing the real size as the size measured by feet and inches.
'Thus we contrast the apparent size of a thmg ... with its real
size as measured in feet and inches.' Tlus of course suggests
two important questions :
(a) How is the apparent size measured if not by feet and
inches?-a question which doesn't seem to have occurred to you.
It must be measurable or it wouldn't be a 'size' at all, and we
couldn't speak of its becoming smaller or larger. Moreover
(part of the same question), smce the apparent size is a size
and the real size a size they must stand m a relation of measure.
So any apparent size must stand in a definite relation of magni-
tude to the real size Moreover, we can mcrcase and diminish
the apparent size ad indefinitum by removing the object far
enough or bringing it near enough to the eye. For this purpose
the magnifying glass is merely an instrument which enables us
to see the object, when brought much nearer the eye than is
consistent with clear vision without it Consequently some one
of the apparent sizes must coincide or be equal to the real size
(and be measurea in feet ana inches). There must therefore be
some distance from my eye at which the apparent size of the
object is its real s1ze. What is this distance? and how can it
be determined? Clearly this result is absurd, for there could be
no reason why one distance should have the prerogative over
another. I expect you will readily agree in the absurdity of
this necessary consequence. But it shows the untenablencss of
the ordinary distinction of apparent and real size. You come
partly into this train of thought, but you have not followed it
to its consequences, nor realized that it should have made you
revise all that you had stated previously. E. g. you say •still
On Primary and Secondary Qualities ']87
less can we select this or that apparent ex.tension and identify
it with the real. For each of them has in principle just as much
and just as little logical title to be so regarded as any of the
others.' This makes me say you will agree with me about the
foregoing absurdity; but you have not seen that the ordinary
distinction of real and apparent size, which you yourself use,
makes it necessary that there must be one of the apparent sizes
or extensions which is equal to the real.
(b) Virtually defining real size as that measured by feet and
inches, you have, as I said, disguised the difficulty. For now
the second question arises, 'What are feet and mches? ' To say
the real size of our obJect is two mches is to say its extension
is twice a given extension which 1s called an inch. But what is
the real size of this extension? What 1s the real size of the
extension which you call an inch? The question shows that we
are no 'forrarder' in the definition of real size by this reference
to feet and mchcs
The d1stmction of real size and apparent size, as above
described, I must then hold to result m hopeless contradiction.
Your theory depends very largely upon the d1stinctlon, so con-
ceived, and so for this reason agam I must think your theory
untenable.
§ 534. We must therefore undertake anew the investigation
of the facts upon which the misleading language employed above
[§ 533 (6) (b)] 1s based
We may introduce this by asking the question, 'How should
we go about to show that the real extension of a given lme was
two inches, in reply to the inquiry as to what it was, or as
agamst a conJecture that 1t was, say, an mch and a half?'
Suppose we are given a six-mch rule. We should define an
mch as the sixth part of the extension of this rule, which we
may again simply define as the rule we are holding in our hand.
We want to compare the real extension of this rule with the
real extension of the given line, e. g. by applymg the one close
to the other.
But how can this be done, since, by hypothesis, in experience
only the sensible (take here the visual) and merely apparent
extension of the given line and the sensible or apparent extension
of the ruler are given ?
788 TRNTATlVE INVESTIGATIONS
The answer would doubtless be given readily enough. 'We
simply apply the visual extension of the ruler to that of the
given line or edge, and 1f the line's visual extension coincides
with two-sixths of tbe visual extension of the ruler the real
length of the line is two-sixths of the real extension of the ruler,
i. e. two inches. If we ask 'Why?' the answer wdl be 'because
then the real extensions are in the same ratio to one another f.&S tJu
apparent extensions'. These answers, probably given with some
confidence, mvolve a pretty cod; even 1£ we omit to criticize
the application of one visual extension, as equal to one extended
sensation, to another extended sensation.
(1) This implies that the apparent extensions stand in a ratio
to one another, and so are measurable. Nor can the implication
be avoided that the apparent stand m a ratio to the real. And
from this of course 1t follows, as before, that some apparent
extension must coincide with the real extension, with the con•
sequent absurdity
(2) How can we possibly know that the real extensions
{'spatial extensions' you call them) are in the same propor•
tion as the apparent? For the former arc never objects of
our experience-by hypothesis-but only the latter, i. e. all
extension we see is visual extension This 1s an unanswerable
difficulty.
(3) The idea of the application of the visible extension of the
ruler to that of the given hne has also serious implications.
In mere visible extension we can make the visual extension
of the given hne appear to comcide with any fraction of the
ruler. It will be readily replied, 'But that is because the ruler
and object are not at the same distance from the eye, and though
we may see no space between them, they are not in contact ;
the true measure is got when they are at the same distance
from the eye.' But this refers to actual real (spatial) distance
from the eye. That we can never get at, our perception being
only of the 'sensible extension', and in such a case we can only
compare what we can perceive. Consequently we could not
know when the real distance from the eye was the same for the
ruler as for the given object.
(There is a point about the use of 'representative' which
I ought to have mentioned explicitly. I have continually been
On Pnmary and Secouary Qualities 189
presupposing it. If two things different from one another are
correlated, why, in this use of 'representative', do we make the
one (A) •representative' of the other (B) and not the latter (B)
representative of the former (A)? The one (B) is said to be
•represented ' because it is supposed not to be itself present to
our consciousness ; the representative (A) is that which is sup-
posed present to consciousness. This is vital to the distinction
of 'representative' and 'represented', and perhaps tends to be
forgotten at important points.)
Or, to put it otherwise : the apparent siies which correspond
to the real sizes, when the latter are at the same distance from
the eye, are to be compared, a.s these are in the ratio of the
real sizes. But how are we to know which apparent sizes corre-
spond to the same distance of the objects? For it is only the
apparent sizes which are present to consciousness, neither the
real sizes nor the real distances from the eye are, by hypothesis,
present to consciousness, nor indeed could they be. The question
is quite unanswerable by the theory before us. For instance,
we couldn't say they (the apparent sizes) had the same apparent
distance from the eye, for that would not only put them in
a space in general of their own (of which we have already seen
the difficulty), but smce 1t would be a distance from the eye,
this subJective space would, at the eye, have a common point
with real space-an add1tlonal absurdity-but perhaps 1t can
be dodged by the doubtful substitute of an apparent eye for
the real I Or suppose, to avoid such a difficulty about the
position of the eye, we say the visual or sensible extensions of
the ruler and the obJect, which (1. e. object and ruler) are at the
same real distance from the eye, are observed to be conterminous
(at least the tactual extensions, as there are more obvious
difficulties about supposmg we observe conterminousness in
visual extensions by eye only). This conterminousness inevitably
means prox1m1ty m a space including both the conterminous
extensions. (Besides, though this is not necessary for our
immediate purpose, there could be no test for such conter-
minousness even in the case of touch-an interval of time
between the apprehension of the sensations constituting one
tactual extension corresponding to one surface, and the appre•
henaion of those correspondmg to another, does not necessarily
79o TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
correspond to their discontinuity or non-conterminousness. This
can be proved, but we needn't stop for that now perhaps.) If
we try to do away with such space by reducing the sensible
extension, whether visual or tactual, to a sort of analogue to
a surface with no space on either side, then sensible extensions
representing surfaces of objects at very different distances from
the eye would, m such 'extension', be conterminous with one
another.
§ 535. This may serve to introduce the positive analysis of
the facts : for the explanations which are inevitably given to
account for the variation of 'apparent' magnitude, and which
cannot themselves be accounted for by the theory now criticized
or reconciled with it, are the result of a very different view of
our perception of extension and show that this view is the
ground of all our thought and perception of the spatial.
I shall try to show that it is precisely because we reason as
1f we saw the real (spatial) extension of the real obJect that we
are able to explam what are (as I hope to show) misleadingly
called 'apparent variations in its seen size', as due to a variation
of distance from the eye. That 1s1 our mental attitude pre-
supposes that we see the real extension m real space and not
some simulacrum of 1t wluch 1s not many space at all.
The explanation which would always be given of variations
of apparent magnitude while the real magnitude remains the
same is of the following kmd .
--
A...-=------------C:_
& -
B 0
[7 April 1909.
[To B. Bosanquet.] Oxford.]
§ 555. . . . The case I referred to is this.
Suppose an attribute a 1s proved of a subject S whose whole
definition 1s A1B1C1, where A1 is a d1fferentiat10n of a umversal
A. Suppose A 1s enough to necessitate a, bemg what mathe-
maticians call the 'sufficient and necessary condition' of a.
A then is the true a&efr,. If we prove a of S by deriving it
from A1 we haven't then got the true auSn. As e.g. if we
prove of an isosceles triangle that its interior angles ... two right
angles, arguing partly from the equahty of the sides. This
corresponds to Aristotle's dictum, of course, that the property
must be proved of the ,,,~ro11 ,ca8Aov e. g. of triangle (A) and
not isosceles triangle (A1). (Correct as this is, he gives no
criterion for knowing when the proof is from the wp. ,ca.(J. ; nor
would his syllogistic theory of scientific proof allow him to.)
If then we prove a. from A1, we haven't got th, true a,&n,
Cor,es,Pondfflce unth Bernard Bosanquet 821:
if we prove of the isosceles triangle (using equality of sides as
we may) that it has the given property, we don't know the real
reason, which is not that it 's an isosceles triangle, but that it 's
a triangle.
Still further are we from the a,Jn if our proof should be from
the whole definition A1B1C1•
Now it might seem that in the demonstrative sciences where
a is really proved of S that generally (i) we should prove a. from
its true cond1tion A. And as a matter of fact this is so nearly
always in Euclid. We always, with some rather unimportant
excepbons, do argue from the 11piirro11 ,ca86>.ov. But (il) supposing
it happened in some case this was not so and we derived e.g.
from A1, we should expect that we should recognize A1 as
a differentiation of A, and recognizing A we might either
(1) observe m our proof that nothing really depended upon its
different1ation mto A1, and we had only used A; or (2) could
observe that we had proved a. in the special form o.i, and see
that a depended on A, or (3), at least, recognizing A, we might
test our proof by omitting its d1fferentiabon, and try whether
we couldn't denve a. from A.
But suppose, what at first might seem an impossible hypo-
thesis, that we denved a property a of S from the whole definition
of S, not from the element A alone in S on which 1t depended ;
not knowing that it depended upon A alone ; not being able
to see in our proof that the connexion was with A alone ; and
not even recognizing A as A at all-would it not be accurate
to say, 1f such a thing were possible, that we bad proved the
fact, the 6T1, that S has a, but had not shown its reason-
..-a ~,on-we had not proved 1t from its true reason ; for indeed
we do not even know its true reason or condit1on-we neither
know its condition as its cond1tJon, nor do we know of the
existence of its condition, for its condition has not even appeared
in our proof ? Consequently though sure of the existence of the
fact we can't be said to understand it.
§ 556. I imagine that when this statement is made the first
answer in general would be that this would undoubtedly be the
state of our knowledge: i.e.
(1} that we had proved the ST& not from the &,dn ;
(2) that we don't even know the a,oT,;
TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
(3) that therefore while being sure of the fact we don't
properly understand 1t : i/ the state of things described
could occur.
But it would probably be said such a state of things cannot occur
in a true demonstration issuing in certain knowledge of
the fact.
It might seem the only thing at all corresponding would be ·
cmpmcal-experimental, inductive argument (1. e. eliminative)
where we have not eluninated the true condition, but perhaps
more than the true condition, e. g. have eliminated AB as true
condition where B 1s superfluous; or we may even suppose
a substance X to be the condition, or part of the condition,
and yet not know an element A in 1ts nature to exist, which
element is the true condition (And here too the kn0ttJledge of
the fact so far as we have it is not derived from the condition
supposed ) But now the thing does happen in exact demonstra-
tion, as we find when we advance beyond Euchd to Come
sect10ns. 1 Among the properties common to all comes as comes,
there are some, notably those connected with tangents, which
it is usual in the elementary books to prove of each come. Such
proofs start from the full defimtion of each conic and use the
full definition. The properties in question are not connected
with an element in the definition common to all conics, but
depend upon the 1(()hole definition : nor even does the element
common to all comes appear either m the defimtion itself or in
the proof.
For instance, the harmonic property of pole and polar is
proved in the case of the circle by a proof which depends upon
and uses the whole defimtion of the circle as the defimtion is
given in Euclid (I can send you references to books 1£ you hke).
Nevertheless the property proved 1s not pecuhar to the circle
and does not belong to it as circle but as 'conic section'.
But though circle is a differentiation of a universal 'conic
section', this does not appear m the aforesaid definition of
a circle at all.
. We might, out of the definition, get the genus 'plane figure
included by one line', but this will not do. It is too wide and
is not the definition of come section Thus, you observe, the
1
Cf § 104.
Correspondence with Bernard Bosanquet 823
universal on which the property depends cannot be abstracted
from the definition used : and the definition has to be used as
an inseparable unity. Moreover, this universal cannot be dis•
covered in the proof, nor can a generic character of the proof
be abstracted from the specific proof before us, which would
fit any conic section.
The student first reading the proof sees in it no reason what-
ever for supposing the property attaches to anything but the
circle. He is not the least conscious of any difference from the
ordmary procedure of Euclid which (as I have said) correctly
deduces a property from its true condition and so is not applicable
beyond the subject of which it is proved.
This, by the way, raises the question how it is we know that
the Euclid proofs are thus correct. To which I think the
answer is that in general we cannot see it from the mere form
of the proof any more than we can see that the aforesaid proof
of polar properties 1s not' correct' (m the given sense). We can
only test it by seemg whether the converse is true, for if the
property is derived from its true condition { =sufficient and
necessary condition) the converse 1s always true. Now this can
always be done m the ordmary case in Euchd and is done
explicitly, e. g. propos1t1ons 5 and 6 of Book I, propositions 47
and 48 of Book I, unless the converse is felt too obvious to
need proof. However, Euclid is a httle deficient here because
the converse of I. 32 ought to be proved. The fact that
e g. the converse 1 has to be proved m Euchd, I. 4812 shows
that the proof of I. 47 does not in itself reveal the fact that the
property is proved from its sufficient and necessary condition.
(The kmd of unimportant exception to reciprocating proofs is
Euchd, III. 2 1 which is true of the ellipse and parabola as well
as the circle.)
§ 557. In the instance then which I have quoted the student
in proving the property (1) does not prove it from its true a,orc,
(2) he does not know the true aufr,, (S) he does not know even
of the existence of the true auST, : he doesn't know the circle
is a 'conic section', (4) even an examination of the proof will
not at all reveal the generic element.
1
Viz theconvenieo/theenunc1abonof Euclid, I 47 (Pythagoras' theorem).
1
MSI47
TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
On this account it seems right to say such a proof is a proof
of the Sn-a real proof-so that we are certain of the ST,, but
it is emphatically not a proof by the &,on ; and it is right,
I think, to say that the fact is not properly 'understood' and
not properly 'explained'.
In order to bring out this better, I may draw attention to
the fact that even when the properties in question were seetl.
to be common to the vanous conic,;, 1t was some time before
a definition of the element common to the conics was obtained
from which the given tangential properties could be proved in
one proof.
'Conic section' is no help, because the cone has itself to be
defined as the surface formed as the locus of a hne which passes
through a fixed pomt, i. c the vertex of the cone and through
every pomt on a circle (an clhpse also, &c., would do). We can,
1t 1s true, then, save 1 separate proofs for each conic section, by
provmg for the circle only, and extending by 'projection' (1. c.
perspective) to the other conic sections. But we begin with the
proof from the definition of the circle and so arc no 'forrarder',
for that proof uses the whole definition of the circle.
The genenc element which has been discovered at last, wluch
forms a general dcfimtion of which every come is a species, is
this : 'A come section 1s the locus of a point which moves so
that the anharmonic rat10 of the pencil of Imes drawn from it
to four fixed pomts is constant' [figure drawn]. And from this
defimtion the pole and polar properties (of tangents) common
to all conics have been proved. You will observe that this late
product of geometry 1s not to be found as an element in the
defi.mtlon of the circle, and certamly 1s not discoverable in the
proof-such as I am referrmg to-of the tangential properties
of the circle common to 1t and other 'conic sections'.
§ 558. I may add that the case 1s different m analytical
geometry. The defimtion of the circle gives us its equation
x3 +y8 = r2 where r 1s the radius. If we form the equations
of the tangents from a point, we easily establish the properties
in question which belong to other conics also. But in this case
we can discern the generic element, for we see that the variables
have certain definite coefficients, viz. + I for each of them. The
• Vu: (apparently) escape the necessity of , .
Cor,espontknce with Be,na,tl Bosanquet 825
equation then is seen at once to be a species of the genus
a,r;I +byB • cl, where a and b may have any value and any sign
(c doesn't matter-I needn't explain why}. This is the equation
to a curve of the second degree.
This may suggest to us that it is as a curve of the second
degree that the circle has the given properties. We then see
that we can similarly generalize the equations to the tangents i
and then we find we can demonstrate the properties universally.
It was then really comparatively easy to find the generic
clement in Analytical geometry, and it is true that the special
proof suggests the generic one. But m pure geometry this was
not so-' conic section' has a verbal generality parallel to 'curve
of the second degree', but, as you have seen, isn't at all in the
same position.
§ 559. Mathematicians are, of course, aware of the necessity
of getting generic proofs of properties which belong to every
species of a genus ; but they are not, as far as I know, at all
alive to the sigmficance of the facts to which I have drawn
attention, and the kmd of curious paradox they involve which
we may put as either (1) proving the fact not from its 'reason'
and not knowing its 'reason', or (2) as somehow using the
' reason' m our proof without knowmg we are domg so 1 or even
knowing what the reason is.
Nor do I know that any logician has called attention to this,
much less discussed it. (But I must grumble that logicians in
general seem to me to have too little studied actual processes of
demonstration m the sciences ) I should say also that tho'
mathematicians know in general they should get generic proofs,
owing to the difficulty in non-analytic geometry of formulating
the common element sometimes, they will present a proof which
should be generic adulterated with specific proofs. I have before
me (Drew's Conic Sections, Appendix, prop. VI} a proof of
tangent properties which professes to be generic, and yet in one
place uses a proposition which has only been got by proving it
of each conic separately I
Of course, I am aware that there's a certain possibility of
misunderstanding if one speaks of 0.1.e reason ; but if C is the
sufficient and necessary condition of E, everything such that it
and C mutually necessitate each other is in the same position
TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
as C as a10T1, and we don't know how many such equivalents
there may be: the point remains that in the proofs I mean we
don't prove by a.ny form of true a,on.
Yours truly,
j. COOK WILSON.
Ee2
xv
DIVINE AND HUMAN CONSCIOUSNESS
[Oxford.]
IAug. 1904.
§ 564. 'There may be, &c.' 1 The proper reply 1s not that
there may be such things m themselves but that the statement
that there arc is unmtelhg1ble. At all events, if 'out of reference
to a thmkmg mmd ' means a thmg not bound by the laws of
our reason, as 1t often does, then if any one maintains the
existence of what 1s unthinkable he is professing to thmk about
the unthmkable, and so contradicts h1msclf. His statement 1s
merely verbal and no thought corresponds to it.
'The great presuppos1t1on' 1s neither a venture nor an act of
faith. A principle or theory can only be a venture or an act
of faith 1£ the contradictory of it 1s thmkable. The great pre-
supposition, however, 1s the necessary presupposition of any
attempt whatever to think the world ; and so 1t 1s merely
artificial to represent 1t as in any sense a venture or act of faith
as opposed to knowledge for 1t 1s the condition of knowledge
and thought, and therefore indisputable Now the md1sputable
cannot be a venture or an act of faith ; cf. Aristotle, cniic ltrr,
a' wo8fl1',s olia' af7"Y/µ,a & IUIO)'K)j Elva, ai' awo ,cal 601Cf&J/ IUl4)'IC'11 K7'A.1
The statement that the whole universe is a rationally coherent
unity 1s not 1dcnttcal with the statement that it exists only as
the obJcct of consc10usness. If the former does necessitate the
latter, the connexion ought to be shown and, 1£ 1t could be
successfully done, 1t would be an 1rrefragable argument m favour
of idealism.
Relations and things related are correlative and inseparable.
The popular faUacy is to suppose them separable, so that the
thing 1s something apart from all relations. The opposite fallacy
1 Notes for a letter in cr1t1C1sm of a phtlosoph1cal paper
1
that which must be and be thought to be because of its own nature
'
1s neither hypothestS nor postulate' An Po 76b 23
Dimne and Human Consciousness 83x
is to mistake the inseparableness for identity, an exaggeration
not unusual in metaphysics. I am afraid Green falls into this
fallacy. We may satisfy ourselves that any argument from the
fact that relations belong to the reality of things to the con•
clusion that a thing was only relations would inevitably apply
to each man's self, and this would reduce to a 'congeries of
relations', and that no advocate of this idealism could admit.
There is in such a theory as Green's a far more serious
difficulty m the relation of the md1vidual's self and hrs con-
sciousness to the eternal self and the eternal consciousness,
which tends to be disguised by ambiguous phrases in which the
transition from one to the other is concealed. This seems to
me the weak point of the relation of morality to the ind1v1dual
self, and also of the account of the freedom of the will in Green's
philosophy
... [he now turns to the paper under cntlc1sm.] To derive
huma.i consciousness by evolution from physical elements 1s
(said to be) a i5unpo11 r.p6TEpov [a ' hysteron proteron '] because
the material elements presuppose consc10usness as something for
which they exist This 1s only ' hysteron proteron ' 1f the human
conscioui,ness to be derived from the material elements is that
consciousness which the material elements presuppose and that
for which they exist Whence one would suppose that it is the
human consciousness for which matter exists. None but a sub-
jective 1deahst believes this. Scientific knowledge presupposes
that things, objects of my consciousness, existed before they
became objects of my consciousness. Now the miseh1ef 1s that,
though this 1s not mtendcd, the logic of the 'hysteron proteron'
argument demands 1t. Thus the consciousness which is the
condition of the material world must be the human, and according
therefore to one statement made must be eternal and infinite,
and according to another must be umversal. This certainly is
the conclusion a man readmg such an argument for the first
time would draw. He would be surprised when he came to the
protest: 'I never said my consciousness made the world.' He
would feel rather taken in and might reply : 'No, mdeed you
didn't, but everything you dul say naturally bore this inter-
pretation and, if it didn't, you should have said so at once.'
Clearly, if a d1stmction is to be made between human conscious•
832 TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
ness and the eternal universal consciousness, it ought to be most
plainly shown that the argument about human consciousness
can be grounded on that other consciousness The fact that
this 1s not done seems to me to show that . . the difficulty is
really concealed by the identity of the word consciousness in
both cases That 1s why the thing seems to me intrinsically
unsound and to profit by an ambiguity. How could we refute
a man who chose to answer in this way? 'I grant that the
material clements exist only m and for an eternal consciousness.
But your protest means they do not exist for and in human
consc10usness solely, and that they exist before a given human
consc10usness. Very well, the material evolution of human con-
sciom,ness would now mean that tlus consc10usness is developed
out of clements which at all events existed before it and do not
exist merely as obJccts for it, m it, and relative to it. Moreover,
the bram and other organs, wluch I maintain are necessary to
human consciousness, never are obJects of the human conscious-
ness which they condition. Thus my theory of the evolution
of human consciousness 1s m no wlut altered. Relative to human
consciousness these material clements rcmam as material as
anything need be. They are eternally existent matter and it
makes no ddferencc 1f they are said to have their eternal existence
m an eternal consciousness. It 1s hardly more than a verbal
change since the eternal consciousness 1s not human conscious-
ness And, m fact, 1s not the eternal consciousness so completely
other than a human consciousness that it makes precious little
difference what we do call 1t? And at least there is no
' hysteron proteron ' These difficulties are rather concealed
than answered by such representations as that ' consciousness
awakens m me', \\ here the consciousness 1s apparently the
umversal eternal consc10usness which has been pronounced like
my consciousnesc; Tlus sort of identification 1s of course
important to help out the' hysteron proteron' argument. And yet
for some purposes, as the protest (' I never said my consciousness')
shows, it is absolutely necessary not to identify the two con-
sciousnesses But consider the above phrase, 'consc10usness
awakens in me'. 1£ we here use consciousness as a universal in
the ordinary sense of a universal, this (1s) quite simple ;nd
intelbg1ble, and only means that my consciousness is a particular
Divine and Human COffsciousness 833
case of consciousness in general-such a general consciousness
only exists in each particular consciousness.
But this is not the kind of universal consciousness in which
material objects exist. For, if they are in consciousness at all,
it clearly must be in an existent consc10usness. If such a really
existent consciousness is meant by the eternal universal con-
sc10usness, such could not 'awake in me' Actual consciousness
belongs to an actual subject of consciousness, must be in it, be
its consciousness, and cannot be the consciousness of any other
subject whatever Therefore the existent eternal universal con•
sciousncss, as belonging to the eternal sub3ect, cannot be in me
or 'awake' m me or m any other person ; that would be possible
only if (I, as) sub1ect, were identical with the eternal subject.
Indeed the consciousness of no subject can be identical with
that of another. My learnmg and apprehending a theorem
cannot be the same as your learning and apprehending it.
(You yourself say) that the consc10usness which does make
the world is like my consciousncss Thus it can't be mere con-
sciousness in general, but particular and real as mme is, and
have a definite subject for it, as mine has. One might mdeed
say shortly · a consciousness like mine cannot possibly be
identical with mme, as it certainly must be 1f 1t awakes m me.
By me is meant an actual ind1v1dual subject with an actual
ind1v1dual consciousness. If this 1s thought of as a subject
existent but not yet conscious, it is impossible to represent the
consciousness of another already conscious subJect as transferred
to this subject
There tends to be an equ1vocat10n between the subject of
consciousness and consc10usness itself Consciousness is said to
'awake', which makes it not independent of time. In the same
passage 1t is made independent of time as something present to
both past and present. Now 1t 1s the subJecl which is present
to the elements of the temporal series and so independent of
time, but the subject's consciousness is an activity the phases
of which take place in time. In relation to this independence
of time there is a great difficulty for any theory. Each indi-
vidual's life has a temporal beginning and we think of the
subject himself as having a definite beginning in time. The
idealism before us is specially bound to meet the difficulty
834 TENTATIVE INVESTIGATIONS
because of what 1t says of the eternal consciousness and the
tendency in it to seem to equivocate between that and the
human consciousness.
The organic theory of society does not depend on this idealism
and can be stated w1thouL 1t. It depends solely on the meta-
physic which rccogmzes that no individual has a reality com-
plete, separate, and apart from that of others, and that the only
complete reality is the complex of individuals, &c.
Morahty (1s) not properly affected by any theory of how
consc10usncss originates, material(1st1c) or otherwise. The
intrinsic value of the moral consciousness is mdependent of any
theory of how consciousness m general arises, as the value of
a geometrical judgement is independent of any theory of the
brain processes which make thought possible. On the other
hand, the derivation of moral elements from mental elements
which contain no morality 1s dangerous to moral ideas and
affects tl1em. This should therefore be refuted.
XVI
RATIONAL GROUNDS OF BELIEF IN GOD
§ 565. THERE are 1 subjects which do not appear at first in
scientific form, art, morality, relig10n. In approaching such
subjects for the first time 1t 1s natural to begm by trying to
make proofs, or by cnt1c1zmg given proofs, of moral, religious,
or aesthetic principles, without any preliminary consideration
of the meanmg of proof or of the possible hm1tat10n of its
province. But such a process may be endless. We may con-
struct and reJect proof after proof and yet make no real progress,
because we may have presupposed, without d1stmctly recogmzmg
1t, that proof must have a certain form, a form which 1t happens
cannot fit the matter to which we are applymg it. The defect
therefore will not be in the particular proofs as such, but m the
form of proof in general, and till we recogmzc th1s we shall
labour m vain.
Or we may have somethmg in our mmds which would, whether
right or not, prevent our acceptmg any proof of whatever form.
Or 1t may and does happen that bemg already convinced of
the conclusion, moral or aesthetic, we admit a faulty proof of
it: our interest m the conclusion blmdmg us to the flaw. This
happens even m purely speculative proofs, e. g. even m mathe-
matics.
Or a proof may seem correct and yet it does not quite satisfy
us because 1t does not touch our feelmgs. Perhaps we are not
aware, in our search for scientific completeness of demonstration,
that this is the fact and, if we are at all (aware), may be afraid to
own it, because 1t seems unscientific. But the demand of our
nature remains, and we shall not be satisfied unless we raise the
question of the relations of feelings or emotion to truth.
§ 566. The attempt to vmd1cate our religious beliefs and, it
Rough notes for an address read at Canon W Sanday's Discussion Society
1
XVI (Appendix)
§ 582.
Nov. 3, 19II.
My dear Webb,
I was very surprised and pleased, and indeed touched by your
kindness m honourmg me with the present of your book. 1 What
can I do m return? Send you c1. copy of 'Traverses' 2 or of
'Interpretation of Timaeus' 3-both much at your service I My
stock 1s (alas I) so small. I can't pretend to have read yet so
far m the book as to discover your kmd and conscientious
reference to myself on p. 269. It was pointed out to me by
Williams. I rather wish I had known you thought of bringing
me in, for I should hke to have talked to you about it. It
doesn't put the thmg quite m the way or m the settmg m which
1 P,obl,ms an Ills Rslr,dions of Gotl antl Man, by C. C. J. Webb, Fellow of
[• One of the mam doctrine& of the T1mae1,s ' rel.ttes to the existence of
evil all cosmogonies "Inch attribute the world to some d1vme act1v1ty
find a difficulty here Some assume another \pmt, an evil one, though
partly subordmate to the good one , others, to avoid making an e, 11 spl.1'1tual
principle, as&ume an unmtelhgcnt matter, or m general 'iome form of Necessity
beside the Good Spmt We should suppose that Plato, 1f not monist, would
mchne to the latter and should have thought he clearly adopted 1t m the
Timaeus Thus Plato say, there .tre two cause,, i,oiis- and ,1.,,1'1"'1• each
with its own effects and therefore the ongm of the world 1s mixed , the
necessary causes are 1rrabonal and disorderly (40 e, 48 a, &c ) Again,
Plato does not represent l'oiir a'i entirely creating matter, but only as mocb•
fymg 1t God 1s never reprc-sented as makmg 1t entirely good but as only
domgh1s best with 1t (30, 47, ~3) '-Review 1n the Oxford Magazine, March 13,
1889, p 275]
POSTSCRIPT
Hh2
POSTSCRIPT
the printed pamphlets or dicta.ta. tended to stereotype a text
corrupted by the author himself, by his pupils, by the typist,
and by the printer. Moreover, the matter consists partly of
entirely new sections or paragraphs, dashed off with mature
conviction but very hurriedly in 1912 or 1913, partly of ancient
paragraphs remodelled to suit the changed pomt of view. Most
strange of all, certain parts represent word for word his own
earber lectures but have, by a slight turn, been made to ap~~r
as the arguments of some imagmary disputant and are then
confuted. New patches have thus been oddly mounted on old
garments and sections moved about with some disregard for
methodical procedure.
In the circumstances an editor's task was perplexing and
a compromise -inevitable. I have endeavoured to indicate by
my tables the mam character of the changes made. By dating,
at least approximately, the various sections or parts of sections
and by some rearrangement I have tried to remedy obvious
blemishes and at the same time to satisfy the more curious or
careful reader. To have marked every change precisely and pro-
duced a critical text would have been out of proportion to the
expense and might have distracted the reader from the general
burden of the argument, itself at times sufficiently perplexed
and mtricate. I have not endeavoured, any more than Wilson
himself did, to make the termmology consistel'l.t throughout.
This will be especially clear m Part III. Where, however, late
manuscript evidence existed I have cautiously preserved the
expression nearly exactly, though the style of it is more unstudied
and less elegant than his earlier work. Lost m the matter and
having long ceased to read, except at rare mtervals, the great
English models, he neglected too much the clearness and dis-
tinctness which cost care m compos1t10n ; his sense of form
declined and his word order of ten became German rather than
English. This last fault I have endeavoured generally to remove.
In regard to the lectures as a whole, there 1s one further cause
for a certam limitation. Wilson never broke loose from the
structure dictated by their origin. He combmed, from the first,
two original courses : one a lecture in Formal Logic, where he
followed the order of the text-books, the other an historical and
cnt1cal inquiry mto the Theory of Knowledge, principally the
POSTSCRIPT
English psychological school from Locke to Herbert Spencer.
This will explain why two different motives so constantly meet
and cross one another in this book. He is combining two
different, if cognate, inquiries, embraced in Oxford under the
traditional title Logic. A third current comes from the historical
study of Plato and Aristotle, particularly the Organon. Thus
some of the interpolated sections arose from a preoccupation at
a certain date (1908-9) with the origm and process of knowmg.
Again the first half of Part II, which was m origm an exposition
of the modern theory of Judgement, was gradually altered into
a criticism of contemporary idealistic logic, and agam Part III,
origmally a criticism, under Kant's mspirat1on, of the syllogism
as the form of mathematical demonstration, developed into
a general view of 111fcrence which was to Justify Wilson's attitude
to mathematical reasoning. Similarly the two discussions of
Conception seem hardly logical in the strict sense, turnmg
instead round a criticism of the ideology of the eighteenth
century and its modern descendants Finally, the whole discus-
sion of Induction appears m the place occupied by the treatment
of Method 111 text-books subsequent to the Port Royal logic, and
the author never had time to umfy an original criticism of Mill
with his own treatment of Inference. These arc the causes which
make the book uneven 111 texture and which have mevitably led to
some mconsistcncy. The dates will, I hope, help to explain them.
I have been asked, and the question 1s natural, whether it
can be detcrmmed what thinkers most mfluenced Wtlson's pro-
gress. In the prefatory words which I have cited above he
himself speaks of the advantages of avo1dmg publication which
may stereotype an author's views At the end, ho\\ ever, he
claims to have reached unportant opmions many years before
the date of the preface Scattered about his papers are many
notes of dates, showing his anxiety to assert mdepcndence of
the contemporary progress of philosophy. Both thmgs appear
true. From a very early date the germs of what has come to
comparative maturity in this book are present in his writings
and lectures. This 1s certamly true of his dissat1sfactton with
the idealism current m his early manhood m Oxford. It appears
also to be true that he originated h1s characteristic tenets for
himself, 1£ there can be said to be any strict origmality in the
880 POSTSCRIPT
matter. That is to say, his whole effort was directed, as we
shall see, to maintaining the objectivity of mathematics and the
mathematical sciences. He was at first content with the Kantian
solution to which he was no doubt guided by Green, and so far
as mathematical method is concerned he accepted this solution
to the end. But he was dissatisfied very early with the excessive
subjectivity-as he considered it-of Kant's general position and
his own conviction of the reality of the mathematical object was
reinforced by lus growmg conviction of the immediacy and
certamty of perceptual experience. These two things played
mto one another and V\, ere strengthened by his continuous
absorption m problems of mterpretation of Greek philosophy ; 1
he fell more and more under the mfluence of the frank objectiv1sm
of the typical Greek scientific view of the world. This also
helped to shape his doctrmc of the umversal.
If now we ask what modern mfluences, besides his reaction
from Kant, led him in tlus direction, the answer is not Lotze.
Lotze's presentatiomsm is fundamentally opposed to Wilson's
views, though with charactenstlc loyalty he did not go out of
his way to say so The mflucnce ot Lotze 1s plam m much of
his detailed work as well as 111 the fundamental conv1ct1on that
man has, m that philosopher's words, 'an immediate certainty
regarding what 1s umversally vahd, upon which all conviction
rests, a certainty which, whether called mtu1t1on or by some
other name, must be admitted to exist, though its ongm 1s and
will, 111 all likelihood, remam unexplained '. 2
The determuung mfluencc was, I thmk, that of Ueberweg,
whose Logic and /Jistory of Philosophy "ere familiar companions
of Wllson 111 lus formative penod. In the preface to the second
edition of his Logic, that philosopher recommends his work to
the reader 'as a thorough attempt to reach a relatively obJective
theory of knowledge as agamst Kant's subjective cntlc1sm '.
No doubt the tendency had long been in the air, especially m
Germany. At Gbttmgen Lotze was the successor of Herbart.
But 1t 1s Ueberweg who, m his Logic, contmually msists on
1
Apart altogether from plulosophlcal debate, we can see this, I think, 1n
hlS paper of June 1890, • On some apparent anomalies 1n the use of 1'9°.
See Transactions of O:tford, Philological Socaety, 1889-90, pp. 27-8,
1
Cf Lotze, Logic, I§ 356-7.
POSTSCRIPT 88t
a view which is, in essentials, identical with Wilson's. Ueberweg,
too, rests his theory upon the certainty of mathematiaal truth
and upon a conviction of the objectivity of our apprehensions,
Not that Wilson foJlowed him slavishly or literally, but he read
him early and adopted his method, partly historical, partly
critical, in the treatment of logical problems. Thus his general
attitude to Kant was probably affected by Ueberweg as well as
by his own English predilection for the scientific rather than
the philosophic attitude to Nature, What, however, weighed
with him more than anything else was his firm conviction of
our immediate apprehension of the truths of Euclidean geometry,
of the pure science of quantity and of mathematical physics,
especially optics and acoustics, and of their objective validity.
With this conviction went that other, that the method of
mathematics 1s not by process of mferrmg but by direct intui-
tion. These convictions explain his comparative neglect of
Descartes, Spmoza, and Le1bmz. Spmoza's method of exposi-
tion he thought fundamentally false, and he disagreed of course
with Leibmz's views of mathematical method. Thus there
remain for predommant mfluences Plato, Aristotle, and Kant,
especially the Prolegomena of the latter, with the author's con•
viction of the certamty of our direct mtuition of the truths of
mathematics as they were conceived by the Greeks.
This 1s not the place to review his philosophy, even were
I competent for the task. Excellent, if brief, summaries of
Wilson's doctrme have been given elsewhere,1 but it is best to
allow hun to speak for himself. He certamly tloes not disguise
h1s teachmg. Two clues to his thought, however, I have found
useful m studymg him. One is stated by himself m almost the
last words wh1t..h he wrote. They will be found m § 370, which
I have placed immediately after a passage of his very early
lectures to \\h1ch he was rcferrmg. His ob1ectiv1ty 1s there
declared to be the corrective of a one-sided sub1ectiv1sm from
which, under Kant's mfluence, he had started. 2
Wilson, hke his master T H. Green, 3 spent much tod over
the ordinary problem of perceptton and the theory of knowledge
1 T11st1mon1a, p lxxv.